Creatio Ex Nihilo Recovered: David B. Burrell, C.S.C
Creatio Ex Nihilo Recovered: David B. Burrell, C.S.C
Creatio Ex Nihilo Recovered: David B. Burrell, C.S.C
2
For current reflections from these traditions, see Carlo Cogliati, Janet M. Soskice, and
William R. Stoeger, eds., Creation and the God of Abraham (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2010).
universe in a creator, that creator can hardly be free. The argument will have
to assume some form of emanation modelled on logical deduction, whereby
the initial premise cannot adequately be distinguished from what emanates
from it. So the source cannot be the free creator espoused by Jews, Christians,
and Muslims for their respective revelations. Fortunately, Josef Pieper’s insis-
tence that “the hidden element in the philosophy of St. Thomas is creation,” by
which he meant free creation as offered in revelation, leads us away from
preoccupation with purely “philosophical” approaches to a dialectical inter-
change between faith and reason. This directs us to realize the centrality of
revelation to Aquinas as well as to his Muslim and Jewish interlocutors,
Avicenna and Moses Maimonides.3
3
For a narrative sketch of the interaction among these signal medieval protagonists, see my
Knowing the Unknowable God: Ibn-Sina, Maimonides, Aquinas (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre
Dame Press, 1986), as well as Freedom and Creation in Three Traditions (Notre Dame, IN: University
of Notre Dame Press, 1993).
4
ST, I, 44,1.
5
ST, I, 3, 4.
6
ST, I, 44, 1, ad. 2.
7
Sara Grant, Towards an Alternative Theology: Confessions of a Non-dualist Christian (Notre
Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2001).
8
See Robert Sokolowski, God of Faith and Reason (Washington, DC: Catholic University of
America Press, 1995); from a cognate perspective, Kathryn Tanner develops a sense of transcen-
dence that is expressly “non-contrastive”, illustrating that suggestive category though the
history of some key questions in philosophical theology, in her God and Creation in Christian
Theology (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1988).
9
ST, I, 45, 1.
the term “emanation” to articulate it. For once the scheme has been gutted,
that sui generis descriptor should serve to divert us from imaging the creator
over-against the universe, as an entity exercising causal efficacy on anything-
that-is in a manner parallel to causation within the universe. While the all-
important “distinction” preserves God’s freedom in creating, which the
emanation scheme invariably finesses, we must nevertheless be wary of pic-
turing that distinction in a fashion which assimilates the creator to another
item within the universe. Harm Goris has shown how close attention to the
uniqueness of the creator/creature relation, with its attendant corollary of
participation as a way of articulating this sui generis causal relation, can
neutralize many of the conundrums which can continue to fascinate philoso-
phers of religion.10
10
Harm Goris, Free Creatures of an Eternal God (Leuven: Peeters, 1996).
11
Robert J. Dobie, Logos and Revelation: Ibn Arabi, Meister Eckhart, and Mystical Hermeneutics
(Washington DC: Catholic University America Press, 2010).
gravity returned east from Andalusia, while a fresh set of protagonists sought
ways to relate revelation with reason rather than contrasting one to another.12
That would explain why students of philosophy in the west might not rec-
ognize Ibn ‘Arabi as a philosopher, habituated as they have become to the
story that al-Ghazali’s critique of Averroës effectively terminated any hope of
philosophical inquiry in Islam. That judgment reflects modernist assess-
ments of properly philosophical inquiry, however, rather than attending to
the contours of philosophical theology in the wider Muslim world, compris-
ing Shi’ite as well as Sunni perspectives. On a reading more sensitive to its
original context, al-Ghazali’s critique represents a dialectical moment in
Islamic philosophical inquiry rather than ending it, much as recent scholar-
ship finds Averroës to be less a “rationalist” than one seeking ways to recon-
cile faith with reason.13 A trio of eastern thinkers form the vanguard of this
“second phase” of Islamic philosophy, introducing a properly philosophical
theology: Suhrawardi, Ibn ‘Arabi, and Mulla Sadra.14 The secondary sources
cited converge to help readers discover the philosophical acumen of Ibn
‘Arabi. Often dubbed a “mystic” (or even a “pantheist”), his work is better
appreciated when read as a sustained attempt to articulate what Robert
Sokolowski has identified as the crucial “distinction” between creator and
creatures in a universe founded on free creation.
Now we begin to suspect why Dobie sought to compare Ibn ‘Arabi with
Meister Eckhart, who has been saddled with similar incomprehension. Yet
applying the Sokolowski test allows us to capture Eckhart’s intent as well: to
show how a focus on Aquinas’ masterful account of creation as “the emana-
tion of all of being from the universal cause of being”—existence itself [ipsum
esse]—culminates in a “distinction” which eludes proper articulation, since
creator and creatures can never be “two” as two creatures are. Let us take
their respective treatments of existence, which Aquinas introduces as the only
“feature” common to creatures and creator, precisely because it cannot prop-
erly be a feature: “only in so far as things are beings can they be similar to God,
as the first and universal principle of all existence [esse] (ST 1.4.3), yet ineradi-
cably dissimilar once we recognize that “God alone is being essentially, while
all other beings are so by participation” (1.4.3.3). In employing the Platonic
12
See my “Islamic Philosophical Theology and the West,” Islamochristiana, Vol.33 (2007), pp.
75–90, amplified in “Journey to Mulla Sadra: Islamic Philosophy II,” Journal of Islamic Studies,
Vol. 3 (2010), pp. 44–64.
13
Avital Wohlman: Al-Ghazali, Averroes and the Interpretation of the Qur’an: Common Sense and
Philosophy in Islam (London: Routledge, 2009).
14
For leads to them, see Oliver Leaman and Sayyed Hossain Nasr, eds., History of Islamic
Philosophy (New York, NY: Routledge, 1996). For Ibn ‘Arabi, the most comprehensive treatment
can be found William Chittick’s trilogy: The Sufi Path of Knowledge: Ibn al-‘Arabı̄’s Metaphysics of
Imagination (1989); The Self-Disclosure of God: Principles of Ibn al-‘Arabı̄’s Cosmology (1997); and
Imaginal Worlds: Ibn al-‘Arabı̄ and the Problem of Religious Diversity (1995); but see also Salman
Bashier, Ibn al-‘Arabi’s Barzakh: Concept of the Limit and the Relationship between God and the World
(2004)—all Albany NY: State University of New York Press.
This shows why Sokolowski identifies “the distinction” as lying “at the
intersection of faith and reason.”
Let us explore another of Dobie’s four areas, that of revelation. Here
especially the very differences will prove illuminating. Ibn ‘Arabi’s great
commentator, Dawud al-Qaysari, notes how, in effect:
“divine book of revelation” (p. 40). . . . It is in the Qur’an that the voyage
is made that leads man back to his original status, to his divine similitude
(p. 54). . . . The goal is the complete assimilation of the self to the Word of
God as revealed in the Qur’an (p. 55).
Fascinating for both its similarity and its difference is the way “the birth of
the Son in the soul . . .” is central to Eckhart’s interpretation of scripture:
all interpretive activity aims at cracking the “outer shell” of the text to
reveal its “hidden marrow,” which is precisely the process of inner birth.
Eckhart thus argues that the Christian life is not one of mere rational
assent to the divine Word of Scripture but an actual giving birth to this
Word in the innermost ground of the soul, which then bears fruit in a life
of detached freedom and love (p. 59).
for Eckhart, it is to have the Word of Scripture reborn in the very ground
of a fallen and corrupted soul so that the soul may become a true Noble-
man [edele Mensch]; for Ibn ‘Arabi, it is to understand the inner meaning
of the Law or sharî’a that restores the Muslim to the state of perfect
vice-regency as the Universal Man [al-insân al-kâmîl], which is itself a
return to the pure, original nature of humanity [fitra] in which the human
being was a perfect mirror of God’s essential attributes (p. 88).
15
See my Analogy and Philosophical Language (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1973).
16
Robert Barron, Thomas Aquinas: Spiritual Master (New York, NY: Crossroad, 1996); Olivier-
Thomas Venard, O.P., Littérature et Théologie: Une saison en enfer (Genève: Ad Solem, 2002).
between creatures and the creator. And if Aquinas exemplifies the dialectic
between faith and reason in appropriating Hellenic philosophy in a manner
informed by faith, John of the Cross will amplify Aquinas’ suggestive
remarks about faith itself to show how it alone can be the proper way by
which human beings can activate that sui generis relation which is their very
“being to the creator”.
First to John of the Cross, who is disarmingly forthright in enunciating the
goal of the dynamic of faith which activates that grounding relation as: “the
union and transformation of the [person] in God”.17 The power leading to
that goal is ″faith alone, which is the only proximate and proportionate means
to union with God″ (Ascent 2.9.1). He is at pains to distinguish this intentional
union from the “union between God and creatures [which] always exists [by
which] God sustains every soul and dwells in it substantially. . . . By it He
conserves their being so that if the union would end they would immediately
be annihilated and cease to exist” (Ascent 2.5.3). In this way, John will
presume the unique metaphysical relation of all creatures to their source,
which Meister Eckhart elaborates from Aquinas’ grounding “distinction”,
while identifying it as a union in persons of faith—indeed, an “essential or
substantial union”. This grounding fact attends all creatures, hence it is
natural and found in everything (though displayed differently in animate
from inanimate, and in animate, differing from animals to humans, though
among humans it can still be found in “the greatest sinner in the world”),
while the intentional union is supernatural and can only be found “where
there is a likeness of love [such that] God’s will and the [person’s] are in
conformity” (Ascent 2.5.3). What eliminates any prospect of “heteronomy”
between those two wills is precisely this “non-reciprocal relation of depen-
dence” (Sara Grant) as the very being of all creatures.
But let us attend first to the internal connection between faith and union
which John confidently asserts. What makes this sound so startling is our
propensity to confine such talk to “mystics” while reducing faith to belief:
holding certain propositions to be true. Yet John is simply elaborating some
key assertions of Aquinas to cut through the debates which by his time had
come to polarize intellect and will in the act of faith. His assertions in the
Living Flame of Love are bold:
This flame of love is the Spirit of the Bridegroom, which is the Holy Spirit.
. . . Such is the activity of the Holy Spirit in the soul transformed in love:
the interior acts He produces shoot up flames for they are acts of
inflamed love, in which the will of the soul united with that flame, made
one with it, loves most sublimely. . . . Thus in this state the soul cannot
make acts because the Holy Spirit makes them all and moves it towards
17
John of the Cross, Collected Works, translated by Kieran Kavanaugh and Otilio Rodriguez
(Washington DC: Institute for Carmelite Studies, 1991), Ascent of Mount Carmel, 2.5.3.
them. As a result all the acts of the soul are divine, since the movement
toward these acts and their execution stems from God. Hence it seems to
a person that every time this flame shoots up, making him love with
delight and divine quality, it is giving him eternal life, since it raises him
up to the activity of God in God (pp. 580–581).18
crude and false picture [which many have in thinking that] the maker,
the form, and the end in creatures along with God are two makers or
efficient causes, two forms, two ends. That is crude, first, because no
being can be counted alongside God. Existence and being, existence and
nothing, and also a form and what informs it make up no number.
18
John of the Cross, Collected Works: Living Flame of Love.
19
Meister Eckhart: Teacher and Preacher, edited Bernard McGinn, (New York, NY: Paulist Press,
1986) pp. 178–179.
Existence is more intimate than any form [cf. ST 1a q8 a1] and is not a
source of number. Second, because every being, every maker, every
form, and every end that is conceived of outside or beyond existence, or
that is numbered along with existence, is nothing—it is neither a being,
nor a maker, nor a form, nor an end. This is because existence, that is,
God, is within every being, every form and end, and conversely every
being, form, and end is in existence itself. Indeed, every maker works
through its existence, form informs through its existence, and every end
moves through its existence—through nothing else (Teacher, p. 210).
These sample texts can suggest why western theologians might be wary of
Meister Eckhart, since his rhetoric raises the spectre of “pantheism”. Yet we
can also see him underscoring the sui generis relation implicit in free creation
as Aquinas elaborates it metaphysically, and as Sara Grant helps us to appre-
ciate. A serendipitous corroboration of the intimate relation between the
processions in the triune God and the emanation of all things from that same
God—a final way of marking and celebrating the unique relation between
creatures and creator—can already be found in a 1957 study by Per Erik
Persson, published in English in 1970: Sacra doctrina: Reason and Revelation in
Aquinas.20 Building on the primacy of existing in Aquinas’ account of creation,
he links the ensuing special relation with the unprecedented presence of the
triune God in Christ to all of creation:
20
Per Erik Persson, Sacra doctrina: Reason and Revelation in Aquinas (Philadelphia, PA: Fortress
Press/Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1970).
21
For a prime example of such recovery, see Gilles Emery, O.P., The Trinity: An Introduction to
Catholic Doctrine on the Trinity, translated by Francesca Murphy (Washington DC: Catholic
University of America Press, 2011).
22
See Joseph Godfrey, Trust of People, Words, and God: A Route for Philosophy of Religion (Notre
Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2012).
23
Brian Davies, Thomas Aquinas on God and Evil (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011).
24
I am indebted to my longtime student and friend, Mary Budde Ragan, for this summary of
Davies.
25
Marilyn McCord Adams, Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God (Ithaca NY: Cornell
Unviersity Press, 1999).
26
See my “Theology and Philosophy” in Gareth Jones, ed., Blackwell Companion to Modern
Theology (Oxford: Blackwell, 2004), pp. 34–46.
make that “scriptural turn,” they will also be led to deconstruct some other
ways of proceeding to which philosophers had become accustomed. That
represents the patent subtext of McCord Adams’ reflections, as well as the
avowed goal of our reflection here.
Paul Griffiths invokes participation to exhibit a growing tendency among
philosophers of religion, in his Intellectual Appetite, to acknowledge the
operative sense faith can give us of ourselves.27
Thinking and speaking of creation as the gift of being from nothing, and
of creatures as recipients of and participants in that gift, suggest some
things to say about what it is for creatures to . . . perform the act of
knowing. By definition, this act must establish a relation between knower
and known, and this relation will inevitably be . . . a relation between one
participant in God and another [since] knower and known share a fun-
damental likeness and intimacy because each participates in God (p. 129).
27
Paul J. Griffiths, Intellectual Appetite: A Theological Grammar (Washington DC: Catholic
University of America Press, 2009).
These illustrations are offered to help us taste how the prose this work
exhibits is itself an icon of the intimacy associated with a conception of
knowing which has deliberately replaced a modern fascination with represen-
tation with a classical predilection for participation. And that move is executed
by an exacting analysis of what it means to be gift, enabling us to approach
gingerly and modestly the daunting task of speaking of the universe as gift.
For that is what creatio ex nihilo challenges us to learn how to do.
Thinking analogously about God’s being is more difficult than any other
intellectual enterprise: we grope, we fail, and our failures are magnified
by our unwillingness to recognize the depth and scope of what we do not
know and of the errors in whose truth we have confidence (p. 69)
Philosophers of religion, take note: this extended essay reads like a medita-
tion of one who has come to appreciate the limits of academic study of
religion, and would initiate others into the set of attitudes and practices
which can nurture wonder and even intimacy with God. What more fitting
summary of the way attention to creatio ex nihilo can invite transformations in
philosophical approaches to God and to the cosmos?