On Deconstructing Narratology - Seymour Chatman
On Deconstructing Narratology - Seymour Chatman
On Deconstructing Narratology - Seymour Chatman
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Penn State University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Style
This content downloaded from 142.3.100.128 on Sun, 03 Jul 2016 07:40:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Seymour Chatman
On Deconstructing Narratology
This content downloaded from 142.3.100.128 on Sun, 03 Jul 2016 07:40:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
10 Seymour Chatman
precision? Why continue the effort to reduce semantic slippage by coining and
redefining terms? The narratologist, like the theorist of any subject, is con-
cerned to minimize terminological confusion. Should she or he disown the
simple assumption that a technical term can be defined to mean precisely so-
and-so? And that if dissent arises, it is meaningful to argue the term's suita-
bility?
Without denying the value of deconstructive analysis of literary texts, we
should not, I believe, give up the project of improving theoretical distinctions
and terms. As deconstructors themselves have argued, far from invalidating
the structuralist project, deconstruction presupposes structuralist efforts to un-
derstand the complex codes amidst which we live and cannot itself exist apart
from them:
Without that specific tension between "practice" and "promise" exemplified in structuralist
thought, Derrida could hardly have broached the questions that animate his own writing.
Deconstruction is a constant and vigilant reminder of what structuralism must be if it is
to avoid the traps laid down by its seductive concepts of method.2
This content downloaded from 142.3.100.128 on Sun, 03 Jul 2016 07:40:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
On Deconstructing Narratology 1 1
I am not, of course, suggesting that narcologists believe that the events of a Balzac story
actually took place or that Balzac conceived the events first and then embodied them in
narrative discourse. I am claiming that narcological analysis of a text requires one to treat
the discourse as a representation of events which are conceived of as independent of any
particular narrative perspective or presentation and which are thought of as having the
properties of real events. (Pursuit of Signs 171)
So his is a logical priority: "The analyst must assume that the events reported
have a true order, for only then can he or she describe the narrative presentation
as a modification or effacement of the order of events." (The order of the
discourse, of course, may also simply parallel that of the story. Presumably
this "zero-case" is presupposed by Culler's formulation.)
But, Culler goes on to argue, beside the traditional priority given to story
as some "natural" sequence of events, there coexists a quite opposite and
indeed irreconcilable priority. Events, he maintains, may be the effects, not
the causes of the discourse. In other words, discourse may be prior and story
anterior: "Positing the priority of events to the discourse which reports or
presents them, narratology establishes a hierarchy which the functioning of
narratives often subverts by presenting events not as givens but as the products
of discursive forces or requirements ( Pursuit of Signs 172). He gives these
various names: "the demands of signification," "the logic of signification,"
"meaning" ( tout court), "theme," "narrative coherence," "the ethical and re-
ferential dimension of the narrative," "the ethical import," "the point," "the
evaluation," the "implicit argument that is common to narrative," the need
to make the story "truly tellable" (so as to avoid the reader's potential mocking
question "so what?") and the like.
He offers several illustrations of this reversal. Let us just consider that
of the Oedipus myth. On the one hand, Culler writes, there is the sequence of
events as normally perceived:
This content downloaded from 142.3.100.128 on Sun, 03 Jul 2016 07:40:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
12 Seymour Chatman
But, Culler reminds us, the only eyewitness to the murder claimed that
it was a group of robbers- several, not one- who killed Laius, so there remains
the possibility, urged by Jocasta, that Oedipus is innocent. Yet Oedipus rejects
this argument and accepts his guilt without even questioning the eyewitness
about what he saw.
Oedipus himself and all his readers are convinced of his guilt but our conviction does not
come from the revelation of the deed. Instead of a revealed prior deed determining meaning,
we could say that it is meaning, the convergence of meaning in the narrative discourse,
that leads us to posit this deed as its appropriate manifestation. . . .
[Oedipus's] conclusion is based not on new evidence concerning a past deed but on the
force of meaning, the interweaving of prophesies and the demands of narrative coherence.
The convergence of discursive forces makes it essential that he become the murderer of
Laius, and he yields to this force of meaning. Instead of saying, therefore, that there is a
sequence of past events that are given and which the play reveals with certain detours, we
can say that the crucial event is the product of demands of signification. Here meaning is
not the effect of a prior event but its cause. ( Pursuit of Signs 1 74)
Indeed, Culler argues, if this were not the case- if, say, Oedipus had demanded
more evidence or convinced himself that " 'the fact that he's my father doesn't
mean that I killed him' "-Oedipus could neither "acquire the necessary tragic
stature" nor even be said to suffer from an Oedipus complex. From this and
other examples- Daniel Deronda, Freud's story of the Wolfman, Labov's black
vernacular tales- Culler concludes
that every narrative operates according to this double logic, presenting its plot as a sequence
of events which is prior to and independent of the given perspective on these events, and,
at the same time, suggesting by its implicit claims to significance that these events are
justified by their appropriateness to a thematic structure. (Pursuit of Signs 178)
This content downloaded from 142.3.100.128 on Sun, 03 Jul 2016 07:40:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
On Deconstructing Narratology 13
Once we are well into the play, we know that Oedipus must be found guilty, otherwise the
play will not work at all; and the logic to which we are responding is not simply an esthetic
logic that affects readers of literary works. Oedipus, too, feels the force of this logic.7
Surely he does, and the play is magnified by that consciousness. But there is
no evidence that the play would not function at the simple narrative level if
he did not. Narrative qua narrative can hardly be said to deconstruct just
because a character knows or has a premonition that the past was other than
he had previously imagined. The narrative would still "work," however inferior
its literary merit. A character's knowledge cannot "cause" prior events. Only
the implied author has that power. Only the implied author is the overseer of
the relations between story and discourse. By definition.
Culler's two logics do not operate within the same conceptual universe.
He lumps together crucially different activities, one presupposed by narrative
structure as such and one by a critical interpretation of a given narrative. The
view of plot as a sequence of events logically prior to their presentation is
simply a working convention of the class of texts we call narratives. After-the-
fact decisions about meaning, appropriateness to theme, and the like are not
part of that convention but are separate evaluative activities that we can per-
form on any text- not only narratives, but arguments, expositions, and de-
scriptions as well. Such evaluative activity is part of literary criticism as it is
traditionally conceived. But a character's performance of such an evaluation
simply constitutes one more event in the plot. The search for larger meanings
may legitimately be called "discursive," but it cannot be called "discoursive"
without depriving that term of any precision it might have gained in narra-
tology.
Culler must make this equation if he is to find the ubiquitous specter of
self-deconstruction. Narrative- the entire code, the very structure of narrative
as a type of text- is fated eternally, like any mere text, to deconstruct itself.
Even the notion of causation is subject to this bold claim:
Causation involves a narrative structure in which we posit first the presence of a cause and
then the production of an effect. Indeed, the very notion of plot, as E. M. Forster taught
us, is based on causation: "the king died, then the queen died" is not a narrative, although
This content downloaded from 142.3.100.128 on Sun, 03 Jul 2016 07:40:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
14 Seymour Chatman
"the king died, then the queen died of grief' is. . . . This, one might say, is the fabula of
the causal narrative: first, there is cause; then, there is effect; first a mosquito bites one's
arm, then one feels pain. But, says Nietzsche, this sequence is not given; it is constructed
by a rhetorical operation. What happens may be, for example, that we feel a pain and then
look around for some factor we can treat as the cause. The "real" causal sequence may be:
first pain, then mosquito. It is the effect that causes us to produce a cause; a tropological
operation then reorders the sequence pain-mosquito as mosquito-pain. This latter sequence
is the product of discursive forces, but we treat it as a given, as the true order.
(Pursuit of Signs 183)
With all due respect to Nietszche, the reasoning seems a bit questionable.
Remember that originally we were only asked to accept logical, not actual,
temporal priority. To say that in narrative, events are "prior" to their expres-
sion is not the same as to say that they literally exist before that expression
takes place. From the theoretical point of view, narratology is resolutely syn-
chronic. It does not assume that either telling or told "precede" each other:
they are coexistent, cotemporal parts of the model. But in Culler's sentence,
words like "first" and "then" seem to shift the ground of discussion from logic
to chronologic. Mosquitoes bite, and then we feel the consequences. Our per-
ception neither precedes the event nor causes the mosquito to bite in the first
place, as might be implied by the mysterious "tropological operation" that
"reorders the sequence pain-mosquito as mosquito-pain." Culler's sentence,
"The 'real' causal sequence may be: first pain, then mosquito," omits, in its
excessive succinctness, some crucial elements: the experience of pain prompts
the search for the cause of the pain; the search, in turn, does not "cause" the
original source of the pain but rather leads to the discovery of that original
source. Discovering is not causing. The discovery of the pain cannot but follow
upon the pain itself. The hyphens connecting "pain-mosquito" and "mosquito-
pain" conceal more than they reveal. However goes the narrative order, whether
the telling is congruent with the told:
the cause can never be other than the mosquito's bite and the effect never
other than "his" pain. "He" did not "produce" the mosquito-as-cause in any
sense of "cause" useful to narratology. A narrative can present the story of an
inquiry in to a series of events, but that does not "cause" the events in the
way that event A of a story is said to be the cause of event B. Remember, too,
that the "he" who is bitten is a character (that is, in the story), whereas the
narrator, who provides the information that a mosquito was responsible, is
This content downloaded from 142.3.100.128 on Sun, 03 Jul 2016 07:40:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
On Deconstructing Narratology 1 5
not in the story but out in the discourse. By a parallel logic it was not Oedipus
(only a character in the story and subject to its laws) who "caused" the murder
of his father "by bowing to the demands of narrative coherence and deeming
the act to have taken place" ( Pursuit of Signs 174) but rather the implied
author who caused these events to befall this character, so configuring them
and their discoursive representation that Oedipus should first unknowingly
murder his father and then accept his guilt without making any further inquiry
into the facts of the matter. Whatever Culler, and Nietzsche behind him, might
mean by the "non-givenness" of the causal sequence, or by its "metonymical"
character, causality is no mere rhetorical operation. Nor, from the purely nar-
ratological perspective, an easily reversible one.
Like those from Oedipus Rex and Daniel Deronda, Culler's mosquito
example seems to confuse psychological and logical orderings of events. Prud-
ence suggests that we keep these separate. From the logical point of view,
causality always entails sequence or temporal following- by definition.8 Culler
blurs the logical condition of causality with the possibility of someone's (Oed-
ipus's, the audience's) discovering the causal sequence. But that discovery can
only be after the fact. When we discover a causal sequence, the order of our
discovery, whether it proceeds from cause to effect or vice versa, is irrelevant
to the logical structure of the sequence, which presumes for narratives (except
fantasies and the like) the ordinary laws of nature. The order of logical en-
tailment bears no necessary relation to the psychological experience, the dis-
covery procedure, if you will, of what caused the events. One may, of course,
anticipate the effect before the cause occurs, as when we see the mosquito
alight on our arm before it has yet bitten. Here a discovery does precede the
event, but it is not the discovery of pain but simply of the mosquito's presence.
Or one may first feel the pain, then deduce the cause. But it is obviously not
the case (except in fantasy) that the order of causality can itself be reversed.
Again, the pain did not cause the mosquito to bite the arm.
In short, Culler's use of the word "cause" is not felicitous from the nar-
ratological point of view. Narratology takes it as axiomatic that event A causes
or has some other, contingent relation with B. To say that event B "causes"
A in the sense that the story would not otherwise have a "point" or "meaning"
does not seem to me a narratological observation. It is, rather, literary-critical,
an evaluation performed by reader or critic as he or she situates the digested
text in the universe of meanings and values. Readers must agree, if they are
to read a narrative at all, that event A precedes event B in the story. But they
may differ about what the point of that precedence is. To ignore the distinction
is precisely to reintroduce interpretation into narratology and thus into poetics
in general.9 Narratology may indeed be deconstructible; it may even need to
be deconstructed. But one would hope for a logically more secure demonstra-
tion which pinpointed problems in our current narratological suppositions
without undermining important and hard-earned distinctions on questionable
This content downloaded from 142.3.100.128 on Sun, 03 Jul 2016 07:40:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
16 Seymour Chatman
Notes
3 The best argument for dissociating literary theory and interpretation is Culler's
"Beyond Interpretation," the first chapter of The Pursuit of Signs. "Structuralism,"
argues Culler, continues to be
a relation between events, processes, or entities in the same time series, such that (a) when
one occurs, the other necessarily follows (sufficient condition), (b) when the latter occurs,
the former must have preceded (necessary condition), (c) both conditions a and b prevail
(necessary and sufficient condition), (d) when one occurs under certain conditions, the other
necessarily follows (contributory, but not sufficient, condition). . . .
Further,
When an entity, event, or process is said to follow from another, it may be meant that it
must succeed but can be neither contemporaneous with nor prior to the other, that it must
This content downloaded from 142.3.100.128 on Sun, 03 Jul 2016 07:40:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
On Deconstructing Narratology 17
either succeed or be contemporaneous with and dependent upon but cannot precede the
other, or that one is dependent upon the other but they either are not in the same time
series or one is in no time series at all.
Works Cited
Chatman, Seymour. "Characters and Narrators: Filter, Center, Slant, and Interest-Fo-
cus." Poetics Today 7 (1986): 189-204.
Culler, Jonathan. "Fabula and Sjuzhet in the Analysis of Narrative: Some American
Discussions." Poetics Today 1 (1980): 27-37.
This content downloaded from 142.3.100.128 on Sun, 03 Jul 2016 07:40:12 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms