Alf Ross
Alf Ross
Alf Ross
Aulis Aarnio
Professor, Dr.
The Tampere Club, Finland
Alf Ross (1899 – 1979) was, without a doubt, one of the greatest European legal
thinkers of the 20th century. He was like a tall oak, in the shadow of which only a
standing with Axel Hägerström, whose philosophy also provided Ross with his
first intellectual home. In this spirit, Ross took a strong stand on the normative
nature of morality (and valuations) in his writings of the early 1930’s. According to
duty.Because of this background, we have good reason to connect Alf Ross with
Still, to understand Ross and his contemporaries, we must remember that Ross
also wrote in the pragmatic tradition beginning in Denmark from Oerstedt and
was carried on in the works of, for instance, Ussing and Vinding Kruse. When
seen like this, Alf Ross was a deeply Nordic thinker, and connecting him to, for
complete distortion of the background of his learning and his basic legal scientific
commitments.
As regards Alf Ross and his thoughts on the doctrinal study of law are
2
concerned, we must be careful to separate his “two persons”. The first, is the
analytical Alf Ross, whose findings were in Nordic countries elaborated by the
so-called analytical school of the doctrinal study of law. The second “person”,
under closer scrutiny here, is the (legal) realist Alf Ross. This side of Ross’
What Alf Ross was interested in as a realist was the nature of the scientific
(at least in principle) be true or false in the same way as those of science in
“The leading idea of this work is to carry, in the field of law, the empirical
principles to their ultimate conclusions. From this idea springs the methodological
demand that the study of law must follow the traditional patterns of observation
and verification which animate all modern empirical science; and the analytical
demand that the fundamental legal notions must be interpreted as conceptions of
social reality, the behavior of man in society, and as nothing else”.
Alf Ross was not a realist only due to the influence of Axel Hägerström, even
though Hägerström’s shadow was cast on the young Ross. Actually, Alf Ross’
path to Hägerström went through Hans Kelsen. Ross’ book ”Theorie der
thoughts, even to the point that Ross´s countryman Vinding Kruse, among
others, criticized him for being too Kelsenian. It is apparently this very criticism
that led to Ross finishing his dissertation in Uppsala under the guidance of
Hägerström.
3
This is also how Ross was drawn to the camp of Scandinavian realism, even
though he did this in a characteristic way. It is also interesting to note that in the
introduction to the work Theorie der Rechtsquellen (The Theory of the Sources of
Law) Ross actually disassociates himself from the central arguments of his book
and, at the same time, from the whole Kelsenian thinking. The introduction is
thus something of a pathway from the young Ross to a more mature character.
The most significant and influential work Ross published on the theory of the
doctrinal study of law is ”On Law and Justice” (Om ret og retfaerdighed).
to these inaccuracies in Ross’ favor, so this theme will not be discussed at any
greater length in this context. However, in this contribution the original text has
”On Law and Justice” is no longer a pure example of the Uppsala school. Its
author has also seen the phase of logical empiricism and the so-called Vienna
circle, which is why the work must be evaluated against the scientific background
of its time. Before we get better acquainted with the realist-Ross of this phase,
The words ”legal theory” refer literally to theory about law. When interpreted like
this, legal theory can be (1) theory about legal systematics, that is, the structures
norms, and concepts), (2) theory about the application of law (adjudication), (3)
thery on legislation, or (4) theory about legal research (the doctrinal study of law).
4
Ross often talked about legal philosophy instead of legal theory. This concept
should not be taken verbatim. In current terms, Ross’ thought was purely about
legal theory, not about a part or area of general philosophy. Seen from this point
of view, legal philosophy could be, for example, philosophy about the origin of
law, its foundation, its social role or other basic questions like this. This is only to
refer to the conversation about whether philosophy is a science and about the
In this, he is similar to the later Ludwig Wittgenstein who emphasized that for him
from unnecessary problems. In the same spirit, Alf Ross writes: Not legal
was a child of his age. As Ross himself mentioned, logical empiricism, still very
much dominant at the time of ” On Law and Justice” set as its programmatic
statement the thesis: The task of philosophy is the logical analysis of the
language of science. Therefore, ”On Law and Justice” strives for the analysis of
the scientific nature (status) of the legal statements presented in the doctrinal
study of law.
5
Alf Ross´ realism is literally legal realism. Everything he writes about law is
written through the doctrinal study of law. As we are about to see, this attitude is
a source of both Alf Ross’ strengths and weaknesses. Let us first take a look at
of a few starting points. Ross’ main target since his early works was natural law.
whereas the thoughts of the later Ross are more related to philosophical
positivism. Both of these attitudes meant a polemical attitude against natural law.
Therefore, one possible way to read ”On Law and Justice ” is choosing the
theory for scientific the doctrinal study of law. What follows from this is an attempt
to define what science is followed by the evaluation of whether, and with which
qualifications, the doctrinal study of law fits this definition. If it does not, it is
is no surprise when taking into account the strong position of the movement in
the years following World War II. In this setting, we can count, for instance,
According to logical empiricism, relevant scientific arguments are either (1) based
on perceptions or can at least (2) be returned to them. Ross concurs with this
6
statement:
logically derived from proposs that express direct experiences. Only in this way,
proposition does not fulfill this requirement, it does not belong to science even
feelings. Thus, only empirical propositions could belong to Ross’ scientific world-
view.
This can be called the empiricism hypothesis. On the other hand, also
belong to science. Let us call this the logicality hypothesis. Scientific theories are
As a legal realist, Alf Ross saw the law produced by the legislative act is not valid
in any other way but formally. This formally valid law only becomes valid law
(geldende ret) once it is realized in society. Ross writes: “I reject the idea of a
specific a priori validity which raises the law above the world of facts, and
7
reinterpret validity in terms of social facts”. From this viewpoint, the problem is in
Danish professor in civil law, Knud Illum, contemporary and colleague of Ross,
emphasized that law is valid if and only if the citizens have experienced it as
valid. According to Illum, the “legal conviction” of the people is the measure for
validity. In this context. To a certain extent, Ross accepted this view. Peoples’
conceptions (borgernes retsakter) define the content of legal life (retslivet) in its
broad sense. Otherwise, Ross didn’t accept Illum’s view .For Ross, people´s
Like American realism (pragmatic instrumentalism) he took off from the point
that only the law applied by officials is ”living”, or valid. Thus, the legal
phenomena as the counterpart of the norms must be the decisions of the courts,
and the validity of norms can therefore sought solely in the judicial application of
the law, and not in the law in action among private individuals.
One dimension of this idea is based on law always being the use of coercive
force. The machinery of officials realizes the use of coercion, as the judges
define which deed fulfills the threat of sanction. In Rossian terms, law, coercion
Nevertheless, Ross rejected the idea that law’s coercive nature means the
8
upholding of legal norm with the support of coercion. In the adjudication the
judge uses power but this does not meant that the validity of law depends on
power and coercion. Power is not something “behind” law although law is, in
A key to Ross’ concept of the doctrinal study of law can be found in his theory on
the validity of norms. I shall illustrate this idea with certain ideas introduced by G.
H. von Wright on the same subject, since they are even better suited for
analyzing the basic concepts about validity than the analyzes made by Ross. von
Wright writes that it is not often natural to talk about the existence of a (legal)
norm. Instead, we can state that there exists a duty to do something. What, in
this case, does it mean that individual i has the duty to do, let us say, O?
According to von Wright, this means the same as: i belongs to group C of which
unpleasant from the viewpoint of a member of group C, for example, some “bad”
caused by R is, from C’s viewpoint, greater than the benefit or advantage gained
from not doing O. If individual i has, in these circumstances, the duty to do O, the
norm N “Every C has to do O” is valid. A norm like this can be called a primary
norm. Its “target” is precisely the behavior of the citizen (C) and its validity
The legal order also includes norms that oblige officials (A) to put into effect
obey the norm N. It is this secondary norm that guarantees the realization of the
sanctions set in the primary norm. The validity of the secondary norm thus
implicates the validity of the primary norm, but not the other way around, which is
why the validity of the secondary norm presumes the existence of a “Hartian” rule
Let us now return to the Rossian view about legal validity. Ross, like many other
legal theoreticians, used as his example the game of chess. He asked: What
does it mean that a certain rule of chess is, during the game, a valid chess norm?
The answer to that question opens the nature of a (chess) game as a normative
phenomenon. Once this example is moved into law, we can outline an answer to
the classic problem: What is law? In Ross’ opinion, the validity of a chess norm
can be analyzed only by separating the external and internal viewpoint. Ross
himself did not use exactly these terms, later presented, for instance, by H. L. A.
Hart, but he had by all accounts adopted the same view. Actually, it may be so
that in jurisprudence Alf Ross would earn the “paternity” of this distinction
chess from the outside tries to understand the players’ moves, he must connect
10
this activity to certain rules. The player acts in the way he does because he has
to, since if he does not, he will be excluded from the game. The game is
conceptually defined by the rules. The same goes for any other game. External
Ludwig Wittgenstein defended exactly the same idea. Without an internal point of
we cannot know anything about rules that are completely strange to us. The
same hold true as far as the chess game is concerned. The rules of game make
the player´s actions intelligible to someone on the outside. The rules express an
explanatory scheme.
From the internal point of view, the rule is no longer an interpretative scheme. As
distinct from the outsiders, the player does not try to understand his own or the
other player’s actions. He simply plays and tries to do it in accordance with the
All this means that legal rules have a dual function, the external and the internal
11
ones, depending on the point of view one takes. In this regard, the legal norms
to accept certain judicial rules of recognition (as well as rules of amendment and
As regards the doctrinal study of law Ross establishes as his point of reference
the sentence:
A similar argument could naturally be made about any other possible statute in
any other national law. The assertion A is, according to Ross, a typical legal
sense? Ross reminds first, that a legal norm, just like a chess rule, forms an inter
ideology adopted by the majority of judges. Rules are followed because they are
He thought that a rule, which is experienced as legally binding provides the judge
with a model for behaviour. The model motivates the judge as does the rule of
the chess game as far as the player is concerned. The rule which serves as an
interpretation or explanation scheme for an outsider, is for the judge the basis of
12
motivation.
The motivation to follow the rule is not based on need-calculations or other such
a person who experiences that ideology as a kind of social pressure. This makes
The judicial ideology is not well articulated, but assumed as a kind of ”silent
validity, similar to the Hartian rule of recognition. That rule of recognition makes
very seldom it explicit which norm is valid at a given time. The same holds true
as regards the judicial ideology. It is a complex totality with the result that
different judges may have and also actually have different conceptions on the
validity of norms. Nonetheless, it does not make the judicial ideology as a rule of
Ross is careful not to confuse what is with what ought to be, and he thus in no
way belittles the strength of Hume’s guillotine. One cannot draw something that
ought to be from something that is. Hence, the judges are not supposed to draw
normative (ideological) consequences from the their actual work. Ross only
emphasizes that what is truly felt as binding must be internalized. The same
problem was pondered by G. H. von Wright in his theory of action. For him, one
behavior is enough.
However, Ross was more interested in the method of the doctrinal study of law
than the deep structure of law. Therefore the core of his theory concerns exactly
the question: What is the assertion ”A = (D) is valid (Danish) law ” about? This
question is a crucial one as regards the scientific status of the doctrinal study of
law. In the simplest possible terms, Ross’ answer is: The assertion A is a
The doctrinal study of law never looks at the past, to history, but at the future,
and therefore the legal research should never be interested in the court´s past
behavior de facto. This is the case despite the fact that it has to base its
The focus of the doctrinal study of law is always on the judge´s commitment to
follow a certain norm. This is another matter than “the activity of courts” since
the court is, according to Ross, an institution, and it is inaccurate to say that the
institution ”commits to a shared ideology”. In the Rossian theory the judge and
Ross does not make a rigid difference between the predictions of the doctrinal
study of law and legal-political estimations (sentential ferenda). This is due to the
14
fact that future social events are never strictly determined. Each prediction might
also affect the future, shaping it. To a certain degree, the prediction might thus
also be self-fulfilling.
of law is as follows:
The prediction A1 can be taken as accurate (anses for sand) if and only if there
are good reasons to estimate that the prediction will be realized in the activity of
the judge. Still, it must be emphasized that the “truth-value” of sentence A1 does
not depend on whether, for example, the evidence of the fact can be estimated
well enough in an actual case. The predictive nature of sentence A1 does not
depend on procedural evidence, but on the prognosis whether a certain norm will
be included in the judges´s reasoning or not, that is, whether a norm will be
The prediction concerns always the normative ideology internalized by the judge.
The norm is valid in a certain legal order if and only if it is a part of that judicial
ideology. Further, the assertion A1 about the validity of a norm is true if and only
In one sense, Ross’ thoughts prove to be quite problematic. He thinks that the
validity of norm N. From this it follows that norm N can never be either valid or
(nearly) 1 – 0. Ross himself points out, that the validity depends on the varying
judges. i
(erfaringsmateriale), the prediction is based on. Ross calls this material legal-
law. As this is the case, there appear problems in two different dimensions. First,
kind of material. Legal source -material (or judicial ideology) does not often give
”arguability”, that is, about how well founded justification of the future activity of
doctrinal study of law – unlike the predictions of science, for example – are based
on data, the ontological status of which is problematic. This can be seen as one
before, these data are ontologically difficult in the same way as the “existence” of
language. They are partly dependant on the subject and his interests.
the difference to the ”perceptions” that support legal predictions is clear. As the
interpreter of his “perceptions”, one engaged in the doctrinal study of law also
belongs to the community that has produced the interpreted data in the first
place. This person evaluates the data from an internal viewpoint, and is not an
meter. A lawyer has already learned the language where and in relation to which
This can be called epistemic internal viewpoint. In a sense, it is a key both to the
approaches of the scholar and the judge toward law, for example, toward
sources of law and their way of use. Without an adequately shared epistemic
viewpoint the scholar and the judge will not reach an agreement on the content of
law, and in extreme situations might not even understand the language the other
uses. This adequate and shared viewpoint also separates the scholar and the
judge from an epistemic external viewpoint, which is represented by, for instance,
On the other hand, the scholar and the judge have an organizationally different
jurisdiction. He is the applier of coercive force, why the position of the judge can
A genuine prediction always aims at the future even though it is based on past
facts. This raises a problem: What, in the end, is the target of the prediction?
(1) The prediction is targeted toward the end result of the case at hand (e.g.. the
Supreme Court will affirm the consequence X)
(3) The scholar tries to anticipate the (public) arguments the court announces to
18
(4) The scholar predicts the norm the decision (probably, credibly etc.) is based
on, even though the norm is not written out.
Taking into account Ross’ view of the doctrinal study of law, the alternatives (1) –
(3) can be ruled out. If the prediction would solely concern the end result of a
certain case, it would not fulfill the basic requirements of the doctrinal study of
law. Contrary to the task of an attorney or other advisors involved with certain
cases, the task of legal research is not to anticipate the results of singular
decisions.
As regards the alternative (2), it is difficult even to talk about a prediction. Making
more promising. The fact that we have some way of anticipating the arguments
used by the court does not necessarily tell us what the content of valid law is. As
Ross remarks on many occasions – like a true realist – arguments can also be
nothing more but a façade. The decision may be justified with entirely different
arguments than with those used de facto by the judge, or they may mean
something entirely else. In some cases, the decision may be made even without
a single rational argument. On the other hand, we can never find out what the
judge really thinks, for we only receive the arguments, having thus to manage
only with the facade. Ross did not think this enough deeply, since even the realist
19
doctrinal study of law does not predict mere “facades”, it reaches to something
The answer is bound to the alternative (4), combined with alternative (1). For
Ross, the genuine prediction concerns the premises used by the judge, that is,
the judicial ideology.. He points out, that if we are able to predict the legal
premises of the case, we also succeed to predict the conclusions. In this way,
Ross places the judicial ideology in the centre of his prediction theory. The
prediction attempts to reach the (de facto) effective normative ideology or that
The prediction does not concern the individual arguments used by the court, but
whether or not the norm belongs to the normative ideology accepted by the
judge. He follows that very norm due to the fact that he has internalized the
normative ideology in an uncompelled way. For this reason, the norm forms a
foundation of the judge and his knowledge of the facts are what define the
decision he makes. This is why it is important for the predictive doctrinal study of
law to know which (normative) motivational foundation the judge commits to.132 In
Here, the doctrine of the sources of law forms an essential part of the normative
the sources of law, which are the essential constituent of valid law. The
1
20
regulate the final decision but gives a guideline or a standard according to which
the judge is able to orientate further in order to find, in the end, the decisive
directive. Into this normative ideology belong not only the norms of law but also
behavior, but selects as its target the ideology that guides the behavior. Here
also takes distance from vulgar court realism. Still, the theory of prediction faces
First the usefulness of the prediction theory can be questioned. A judge is not
interested at all in knowing the prediction about his own actions. His interest
concerns the way he should act, that is, what is the content of the binding
normative basis in his case. There is, however, an even more serious deficiency
in the prediction theory. It does not make possible the critique of the court’s
activity.
adjudication, and to give constructive feedback to the courts. The social task of
the doctrinal study of law is partly normative, and accepting this normative task it
necessarily becomes critical toward the judicial practice. The doctrinal study of
21
typical situations. The doctrinal study of law that is solely predictive is only a
Ross rejected this critique. For him, the prediction theory does not make the
doctrinal study of law a slave to practice (slave af praksis). His answer is firmly
attached to his original theoretical hypotheses. Ross says that predictions “live”
constantly. When there is new information about the judge’s actions, the
prediction is adjusted. The prediction A1 in case Y is not probable if it, all things
considered and including the former decision X, is probable that case Y will not
be decided like X. The predictive doctrinal study of law is thus all the time
dynamic. It takes into account all the new information concerning the changes of
the normative ideology. Still, there is left an open question: What knowledge is
of law is based on empirical research dealing with the behavior of judges. This is
why the doctrine of the sources of law is not, according to Ross, normative as to
its nature. Instead, the doctrine is descriptive and presents the content of judicial
However, let us remember what Wittgenstein said: One must know something
before asking the name. This holds true also as regards the predictions. In order
22
to predict the future behavior of the judges, one must already have some idea of
the judicial ideology prevailing in the court as well as of its role in judge´s
decision-making procedure. Yet, this is not enough. For a prediction one needs
also information about the effective normative ideology. This is where Ross gets
formed in practice?
Interviewing the judges is out of the question. It produces something like the
legitimation of what the judges feel to be the right way to act rather than
questions, man tries to give a best possible image of himself, and judges are only
human beings.
There remains only one possibility. The prediction must based on what one
knows about the judges thinking in general. The scholar has to presume that the
judges’ thoughts about the content of law are similar to the thoughts of other
lawyers, including the scholar himself. The predictor must have the same
epistemic internal viewpoint as the judges. Without this, the scholar has no way
This means, that the scholar has to be ”inside” the same normative world as the
judge, that is, he has to internalize the same sources of information – and vice
versa. The question is not only about the scholar somehow “finding” the
23
descriptive sources of law. He also interprets, understands and puts then into the
order of preference. The scholar gives the sources of law a content he assumes
law. According to this principle, the scholar and the judge have to use (nearly)
the same
To put it in a nutshell, the scholar necessarily has to assume that the judge has
“anticipating” the future activity of the courts than to use the source material
The Rossian prediction theory does not take this dilemma seriously. That is why
his theory leads to mere pseudo-predictions. The scholar might have, of course,
exactly on the same source material as the non-predictive doctrinal study of law.
predictions. As far as their content is concerned, they are nothing else but a
It seems to me, that Ross was aware of the problems inherent in pseudo-
predictions even though he did not draw the necessary conclusions from these
difficulties. He even noted that the predictions of the doctrinal study of law are
general. When a prediction is made public, it tends quite often to bring about
because both the “predictor” and his target are intertwined with the same societal
All this means, that Alf Ross could not consistently hold to his empiricist thesis.
of his prediction theory is the notion of judicial ideology, which in its turn is a
normative phenomenon. As Ross was quick to deny that the task of the doctrinal
psychology, there was actually nothing more left than the acceptance of a non-
as idealistic, why Alf Ross was a positivist by words, not by deeds. Instead of
approach. He defined the validity of law on the grounds of the judge’s internal
sources of law. This is why the Rossian doctrinal study of law cannot be only
description or explanation of the judge´s behavior, not even its prediction. The
25
doctrinal study of law is the rational reconstruction of how the judge as well as