0% found this document useful (0 votes)
291 views8 pages

Stoic Physics

Stoic physics is the natural philosophy of ancient Stoic philosophers used to explain the universe. They believed the universe is made of one divine essence called pneuma that provides form and motion. It develops and destroys in endless cycles. The human soul comes from this divine essence and knowledge comes from reasoning about sense impressions.

Uploaded by

Al Oy
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
291 views8 pages

Stoic Physics

Stoic physics is the natural philosophy of ancient Stoic philosophers used to explain the universe. They believed the universe is made of one divine essence called pneuma that provides form and motion. It develops and destroys in endless cycles. The human soul comes from this divine essence and knowledge comes from reasoning about sense impressions.

Uploaded by

Al Oy
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 8

Stoic physics

Stoic physics is the natural philosophy adopted by the Stoic philosophers of


ancient Greece and Rome used to explain the natural processes at work in the
universe. To the Stoics, the universe is a single pantheistic god, but one which is
also a material substance. The primitive substance of the universe is a divine
essence (pneuma) which is the basis of everything which exists. This pneuma,
which is the active part or reason (logos) of God, provides form and motion to
matter, and is the origin of the elements, life, and human rationality. From their
physics, the Stoics explained the development, and ultimately, the destruction of
the universe in a never-ending cycle (palingenesis). The human soul is an
emanation from the divine reason which permeates the universe, and knowledge
is gained by the mind from sense impressions and subjecting them to reason.

In Stoic physics, the Earth and the


universe are all part of a single
Contents whole.

Central tenets
Monism
Materialism
Dynamism
Universe
Formation
Ending and rebirth
God
Fate
Divination
Mixture
Tension
Soul
Sensation
See also
Notes
Citations
References

Central tenets
In pursuing their physics the Stoics wanted to create a picture of the world which would be completely coherent.[1] Stoic physics
can be described in terms of (a) monism, (b) materialism, and (c) dynamism.[2]

Monism
Stoicism was a pantheistic philosophy.[3] The universe is active, life-giving, rational and creative.[4] It is a self-supporting entity,
containing within it all that it needs, and all parts depending on mutual exchange with each other.[5] Different parts of this unified
structure are able to interact and have an affinity with each other (sympatheia).[6] The Stoics explained everything from natural
events to human conduct as manifestations of an all-pervading reason (logos).[1] Thus they identified the universe with God,[3]
and the diversity of the world is explained through the transformations and products of God as the rational principle of the
universe.[7]

Materialism
Philosophers since the time of Plato had asked whether abstract qualities of the soul, such as justice and wisdom, have an
independent existence.[8] In particular, could something that was not visible and tangible be said to exist. The Stoics' answer to
this dilemma was to assert that everything, including wisdom, justice, etc., are corporeal.[9] Plato had defined being as "that
which has the power to act or be acted upon,"[10] and for the Stoics this meant that all action proceeds by bodily contact; every
form of causation is reduced to the efficient cause, which implies the communication of motion from one body to another.[2] Only
Body exists.[11] The Stoics did recognise the presence of incorporeal things such as void, place and time,[11] but although real
they could not exist and were said to "subsist".[12] Stoicism was thus fully materialistic; the answers to metaphysics are to be
sought in physics; particularly the problem of the causes of things for which the Platonic Theory of Forms and the Peripatetic
"constitutive form" had been put forth as solutions.[2]

Dynamism
A dualistic feature of the Stoic system are the two principles, the active and the passive: everything which exists is capable of
acting and being acted upon.[2] The active principle is God acting as the rational principle (logos), and which has a higher status
than the passive matter (ousia).[3] In their earlier writings the Stoics characterised the rational principle as a creative fire,[7]
although later accounts stress the idea of pneuma as the active substance.[a] The universe is thus filled with an all-pervading
pneuma which allows for the cohesion of matter and permits contact between all parts of the universe.[13] The pneuma is
everywhere coextensive with matter, pervading and permeating it, and, together with it, occupying and filling space.[14]

The Epicureans had placed the form and movement of matter in the chance movements of primitive atoms.[2] In the Stoic system
material substance has a continuous structure,[15] held together by tension (tonos) as the essential attribute of body.[2] This
tension is a property of the pneuma, and physical bodies are held together by the pneuma which is in a continual state of
motion.[16] The various pneuma currents combining in this way give objects their stable, physical properties (hexis).[16] A thing
is no longer, as Plato maintained, hot or hard or bright by partaking in abstract heat or hardness or brightness, but by containing
within its own substance the material of these pneuma currents in various degrees of tension.[14] This can be compared to
Aristotle's essential form: in both systems the active principle, "the cause of all that matter becomes," is that which accounts for
the existence of a given concrete thing, but in the Stoic system, the principle is itself material.[14]

As to the relation between the active and the passive principles there was no clear difference.[14] Although the Stoics talked about
the active and passive as two separate types of body, it is likely they saw them as merely two aspects of the single material
cosmos.[17] Pneuma, from this perspective, is not a special substance intermingled with passive matter, but rather it could be said
that the material world has pneumatic qualities.[17] The whole universe is a single cohesive unit.[18] The reason of things – that
which accounts for them – is not some external end to which they are tending; it is something acting within them, "a spirit deeply
interfused," germinating and developing from within.[14]

Universe
Like Aristotle, the Stoics conceived of the universe as being finite with the Earth
at the centre and the moon, sun, planets, and fixed stars surrounding it.[19]
Similarly, they rejected the possibility of any void (i.e. vacuum) within the
cosmos since that would destroy the coherence of the universe and the sympathy
of its parts.[20] However, unlike Aristotle, the Stoics saw the universe as an
island embedded in an infinite void.[13] The universe has its own hexis which
holds it together and protects it and the surrounding void cannot affect it.[21] The
universe can, however, vary in volume, allowing it to expand and contract in
volume through its cycles.[20]

Formation
The pneuma of the Stoics is the primitive substance which existed before the
universe. It is the everlasting presupposition of particular things; the totality of
all existence; out of it the whole visible universe proceeds, eventually to be
consumed by it. It is the creative force (God) which develops and shapes the In Stoic physics, the universe begins
and ends in a divine artisan-fire.
universal order (cosmos). God is everything that exists.[14]

In the original state, the pneuma-God and the universe are absolutely identical;
but even then tension, the essential attribute of matter, is at work.[14] In the primitive pneuma there resides the utmost heat and
tension, within which there is a pressure, an expansive and dispersive tendency. Motion backwards and forwards once set up
cools the glowing mass of fiery vapour and weakens the tension.[14] Thus follows the first differentiation of primitive substance –
the separation of force from matter, the emanation of the world from God. The seminal Logos which, in virtue of its tension,
slumbered in pneuma, now proceeds upon its creative task.[14] The cycle of its transformations and successive condensations
constitutes the life of the universe.[14] The universe and all its parts are only different embodiments and stages in the change of
primitive being which Heraclitus had called "a progress up and down".[22]

Out of it is separated elemental fire, the fire which we know, which burns and destroys; and this condenses into air; a further step
in the downward path produces water and earth from the solidification of air.[23] At every stage the degree of tension is
slackened, and the resulting element approaches more and more to "inert" matter.[14] But, just as one element does not wholly
transform into another (e.g. only a part of air is transmuted into water or earth), so the pneuma itself does not wholly transform
into the elements.[14] From the elements the one substance is transformed into the multitude of individual things in the orderly
universe, which is itself a living thing or being, and the pneuma pervading it, and conditioning life and growth everywhere, is its
soul.[14]

Ending and rebirth


The process of differentiation is not eternal; it continues only until the time of the restoration of all things. For the universe will in
turn decay, and the tension which has been relaxed will again be tightened. Things will gradually resolve into elements, and the
elements into the primary substance, to be consummated in a general conflagration (ekpyrôsis) when once more the world will be
absorbed in God.[14] This ekpyrôsis is not so much a catastrophic event, but rather the period of the cosmic cycle when the
preponderance of the fiery element once again reaches its maximum.[24] All matter is consumed becoming completely fiery and
wholly soul-like.[25] God, at this point, can be regarded as completely existing in itself.[26]

In due order a new cycle of the universe begins (palingenesis), reproducing the previous universe, and so on forever.[27]
Therefore, the same events play out again repeated endlessly.[28] Since the universe always unfolds according to the best possible
reason, any succeeding world is likely to be identical to the previous one.[29]
God
The Stoics often identified the universe and God with Zeus,[30] as the ruler and
upholder, and at the same time the law, of the universe.[31] The Stoic God is not
a transcendent omniscient being standing outside nature, but rather it is
immanent—the divine element is immersed in nature itself.[30] God orders the
universe for the good,[32] and every element of the world contains a portion of
the divine element that accounts for its behaviour.[30]

However, the universe is good only in as far as it contains the optimal rationality
and virtue.[33] The contents of the world may be appropriate and well-fitted, but
they are morally indifferent.[33] The goodness of the Stoic God lies in its rational
and virtuous selection of the indifferent things of the world.[33] Thus pain,
suffering, and tragedy occur, even while the universe unfolds according to the
rational good.[34] World events are God events; they unfold according to the best
possible reason,[33] and they are knowable by reason.[35] The good for humans
lies in the understanding and acceptance of this combined with actions directed
towards the good.[36]

The Stoics attempted to incorporate traditional polytheism into their Zeno of Citium, founder of the Stoic
philosophy.[31] Not only was the primitive substance God, the one supreme school

being, but divinity could be ascribed to the manifestations—to the heavenly


bodies, to the forces of nature, even to deified persons; and thus the world was
peopled with divine agencies.[31] Prayers are of little avail in a rationally ordered cosmos, and surviving examples of Stoic
prayers appear to be more like types of self-meditation than appeals for divine intervention.[37]

Fate
To the Stoics nothing passes unexplained; there is a reason (Logos) for everything in nature.[2] Because of the Stoics commitment
to the unity and cohesion of the cosmos and its all-encompassing reason, they fully embraced determinism.[38] However instead
of a single chain of causal events, there is instead a many-dimensional network of events interacting within the framework of
fate.[39] Out of this swarm of causes, the course of events is fully realised.[39] Humans appear to have free will because personal
actions participate in the determined chain of events independently of external conditions.[40] This "soft-determinism" allows
humans to be responsible for their own actions, alleviating the apparent arbitrariness of fate.[40][41]

Divination
Divination was an essential element of Greek religion, and the Stoics attempted to reconcile it with their own rational doctrine of
strict causation.[31] Since the pneuma of the world-soul pervades the whole universe, this allows human souls to be influenced by
divine souls.[42] Omens and portents, Chrysippus explained, are the natural symptoms of certain occurrences. There must be
countless indications of the course of providence, for the most part unobserved, the meaning of only a few having become known
to humanity.[31] To those who argued that divination was superfluous as all events are foreordained, he replied that both
divination and our behaviour under the warnings which it affords are included in the chain of causation.[31]

Mixture
To fully characterize the physical world, the Stoics developed a theory of mixing in which they recognised three types of
mixture.[43] The first type was a purely mechanical mixture such as mixing barley and wheat grains together: the individual
components maintain their own properties, and they can be separated again.[43] The second type was a fusion, whereby a new
substance is created leading to the loss of the properties of the individual components, this roughly corresponds to the modern
concept of a chemical change.[43] The third type was a commingling, or total blending: there is complete interpenetration of the
components down to the infinitesimal, but each component maintains its own properties.[44] In this third type of mixture a new
substance is created, but since it still has the qualities of the two original substances, it is possible to extract them again.[45] In the
words of Chrysippus: "there is nothing to prevent one drop of wine from mixing with the whole ocean".[44] Ancient critics often
regarded this type of mixing as paradoxical since it apparently implied that each constituent substance be the receptacle of each
other.[46] However to the Stoics, the pneuma is like a force, a continuous field interpenetrating matter and spreading through all
of space.[47]

Tension
Every character and property of a particular thing is determined solely by the tension in it of pneuma, and pneuma, though present
in all things, varies indefinitely in quantity and intensity.[48]

In the lowest degree of tension the pneuma dwelling in inorganic bodies holds bodies together (whether animate
or inanimate) providing cohesion (hexis).[49] This is the type of pneuma present in stone or metal as a retaining
principle.[48]

In the next degree of tension the pneuma provides nature or growth (physis) to living things.[49] This is the
highest level in which it is found in plants.[48]

In a higher degree of tension the pneuma produces soul (psyche) to all animals, providing them with sensation
and impulse.[49]

In humans can be found the pneuma in its highest form as the rational soul (logike psyche).[49]
A certain warmth, akin to the vital heat of organic being, seems to be found in inorganic nature: vapours from the earth, hot
springs, sparks from the flint, were claimed as the last remnant of pneuma not yet utterly slackened and cold.[48] They appealed
also to the speed and expansion of gaseous bodies, to whirlwinds and inflated balloons.[48]

Soul
In the rational creatures pneuma is manifested in the highest degree of purity and intensity as an emanation from the world-
soul.[48] Humans have souls because the universe has a soul,[50] and human rationality is the same as God's rationality.[3] The
pneuma that is soul pervades the entire human body.[49]

The soul is corporeal, else it would have no real existence, would be incapable of extension in three dimensions (i.e. to diffuse all
over the body), incapable of holding the body together, herein presenting a sharp contrast to the Epicurean tenet that it is the body
which confines and shelters the atoms of soul.[48] This corporeal soul is reason, mind, and ruling principle; in virtue of its divine
origin Cleanthes can say to Zeus, "We too are thy offspring," and Seneca can calmly insist that, if man and God are not on perfect
equality, the superiority rests rather on our side.[51] What God is for the world, the soul is for humans. The cosmos is a single
whole, its variety being referred to varying stages of condensation in pneuma.[48] So, too, the human soul must possess absolute
simplicity, its varying functions being conditioned by the degrees of its tension. There are no separate "parts" of the soul, as
previous thinkers imagined.[48]

With this psychology is intimately connected the Stoic theory of knowledge. From the unity of soul it follows that all mental
processes – sensation, assent, impulse – proceed from reason, the ruling part; the one rational soul alone has sensations, assents to
judgments, is impelled towards objects of desire just as much as it thinks or reasons.[48] Not that all these powers at once reach
full maturity. The soul at first is empty of content; in the embryo it has not developed beyond the nutritive principle of a plant; at
birth the "ruling part" is a blank tablet, although ready prepared to receive writing.[48] The source of knowledge is experience and
discursive thought, which manipulates the materials of sense. Our ideas are copied from stored-up sensations.[48]

Just as a relaxation in tension brings about the dissolution of the universe; so in the body, a relaxation of tension, accounts for
sleep, decay, and death for the human body. After death the disembodied soul can only maintain its separate existence, even for a
limited time, by mounting to that region of the universe which is akin to its nature. It was a moot point whether all souls so
survive, as Cleanthes thought, or the souls of the wise and good alone, which was the opinion of Chrysippus; in any case, sooner
or later individual souls are merged in the soul of the universe, from which they originated.[48]

Sensation
The Stoics explained perception as a transmission of the perceived quality of an
object, by means of the sense organ, into the percipient's mind.[52] The quality
transmitted appears as a disturbance or impression upon the corporeal surface of
that "thinking thing," the soul.[52] In the example of sight, a conical pencil of
rays diverges from the pupil of the eye, so that its base covers the object seen. A
presentation is conveyed, by an air-current, from the sense organ, here the eye, to
the mind, i.e. the soul's "ruling part." The presentation, besides attesting its own
existence, gives further information of its object – such as colour or size.[52]
Zeno and Cleanthes compared this presentation to the impression which a seal
bears upon wax, while Chrysippus determined it more vaguely as a hidden
modification or mode of mind.[52] But the mind is no mere passive recipient of
impressions: the mind assents or dissents.[52] The contents of experience are not
all true or valid: hallucination is possible; here the Stoics agreed with the
Epicureans.[52] It is necessary, therefore, that assent should not be given
indiscriminately; we must determine a criterion of truth, a special formal test Chrysippus of Soli
whereby reason may recognize the merely plausible and hold fast the true.[52]

The earlier Stoics made right reason the standard of truth.[53] Zeno compared sensation to the outstretched hand, flat and open;
bending the fingers was assent; the clenched fist was "simple apprehension," the mental grasp of an object; knowledge was the
clenched fist tightly held in the other hand.[54] But this criterion was open to the persistent attacks of Epicureans and Academics,
who made clear (1) that reason is dependent upon, if not derived from, sense, and (2) that the utterances of reason lack
consistency.[52] Chrysippus, therefore, did much to develop Stoic logic,[55] and more clearly defined and safeguarded his
predecessors' position.[52]

See also
Block universe
Eternal return
Holism
Natural law
Stoic categories
Vitalism
World soul

Notes
a. ^ The concept of pneuma (as a "vital breath") was prominent in the Hellenistic medical schools. Its precise relationship to the
"creative fire" (pyr technikon) of the Stoics is uncertain. Some ancient sources state that pneuma was a combination of elemental
fire and air. However in Stoic writings it behaves much like the active principle, and they may have adopted pneuma as a straight
swap for the creative fire.[56]

Citations
1. Long 1996, p. 45
2. Hicks 1911, p. 943
3. Algra 2003, p. 167
4. White 2003, p. 129
5. Sambursky 1959, p. 114
6. Sambursky 1959, p. 41
7. Long 1996, p. 46
8. Sellars 2006, pp. 81-2 Cf. Plato, Sophist, 246C ff.
9. Sellars 2006, p. 82
10. Plato, Sophist, 247D
11. White 2003, p. 128
12. Sellars 2006, p. 84
13. Sambursky 1959, p. 1
14. Hicks 1911, p. 944
15. White 2003, p. 149
16. Sambursky 1959, p. 31
17. Sellars 2006, p. 90
18. Sambursky 1959, p. 5
19. Sambursky 1959, p. 108
20. Sambursky 1959, p. 110
21. Sambursky 1959, p. 113
22. Heraclitus, DK B60
23. Sellars 2006, p. 98
24. Sambursky 1959, p. 106
25. Sambursky 1959, pp. 107-8
26. White 2003, p. 137
27. White 2003, p. 142
28. Sellars 2006, p. 99
29. White 2003, p. 143
30. Frede 2003, pp. 201-2
31. Hicks 1911, p. 947
32. Algra 2003, p. 172
33. Brennan 2003, p. 288
34. Jacquette 1995, pp. 429-30
35. Jacquette 1995, p. 415
36. Jacquette 1995, p. 430
37. Algra 2003, p. 175
38. White 2003, p. 139
39. Sambursky 1959, p. 77
40. Sambursky 1959, p. 65
41. White 2003, p. 144
42. Sambursky 1959, p. 66
43. Sambursky 1959, p. 12
44. Sambursky 1959, p. 13
45. Sellars 2006, p. 89
46. White 2003, p. 148
47. Sambursky 1959, p. 36
48. Hicks 1911, p. 945
49. Sellars 2006, p. 105
50. Sellars 2006, p. 106
51. Seneca, Epistles, liii. 11–12
52. Hicks 1911, p. 946
53. Diogenes Laërtius, vii. 54
54. Cicero, Academica, ii. 4
55. Sellars 2006, p. 56
56. White 2003, pp. 134-6

References
Algra, Keimpe (2003), "Stoic Theology", in Inwood, Brad (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics,
Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0521779855
Brennan, Tad (2003), "Stoic Moral Psychology", in Inwood, Brad (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics,
Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0521779855
Frede, Dorothea (2003), "Stoic Determinism", in Inwood, Brad (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics,
Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0521779855
Hicks, Robert Drew (1911), "Stoics" (https://en.wikisource.org/wiki/1911_Encyclopædia_Britannica/Stoics), in
Chisholm, Hugh (ed.), The Encyclopædia Britannica, 25, Cambridge University Press
Jacquette, Dale (1995-12-01). "Zeno of Citium on the divinity of the cosmos". Studies in Religion/Sciences
Religieuses. 24 (4): 415–431. doi:10.1177/000842989502400402 (https://doi.org/10.1177%2F000842989502400
402).
Long, A. A. (1996), "Heraclitus and Stoicism", Stoic Studies, University of California Press, ISBN 0520229746
Sambursky, Samuel (1959), Physics of the Stoics, Routledge
Sellars, John (2006), Ancient Philosophies: Stoicism, Acumen, ISBN 978-1-84465-053-8
White, Michael J. (2003), "Stoic Natural Philosophy (Physics and Cosmology)", in Inwood, Brad (ed.), The
Cambridge Companion to the Stoics, Cambridge University Press, ISBN 0521779855

Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Stoic_physics&oldid=888492632"

This page was last edited on 19 March 2019, at 14:45 (UTC).

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. By using
this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia
Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.

You might also like