INTERMEDIA
INTERMEDIA
Lecture Notes
Sérgio O. Parreiras
Spring, 2015
Decision Theory: Lotteries
x1 x2 ... xn
p2
p1 pn
ℓ
The Certain Lottery, Expectation and Variance
δx = ((x), (1)) .
Var[ℓ1 ] =p1 · (x1 − E[ℓ1 ])2 + p2 · (x2 − E[ℓ1 ])2 + . . . pn · (xn − E[ℓ1 ])2 =
∑
n
= pi · (xi − E[ℓ1 ])2 .
i=1
Composition of Lotteries
x1
x2
ℓ
y1
Composition of Lotteries
x1
p
ℓ1
α x2
1−p
ℓ
1−α q
ℓ2 y1
1−q y2
Composition of Lotteries
x1
α·
p
p) x2
α · (1 −
ℓ (1 − α)
·q
(1 − y1
α)
· (1
−q
)
y2
Preferences Over Lotteries
if and only if
∑
n ∑m
u(xk ) · pk > u(yk ) · qk .
k=1 k=1
Expected Utility
We write:
U (ℓ1 ) = u(x1 ) · p1 + . . . + u(xn ) · pn
We write:
We write:
Recapitulating so far:
1. We made assumptions about the agents’ preferences over
lotteries so we can represent his/her preferences by an expected
utility.
2. The agent will choose the lottery that delivers the highest
expected utility.
∑
n
U (X , p, ω0 ) = u(ω0 + xs ) · ps
s=1
Recapitulating so far:
1. We made assumptions about the agents’ preferences over
lotteries so we can represent his/her preferences by an expected
utility.
2. The agent will choose the lottery that delivers the highest
expected utility.
∑
n
U (X , p, ω0 ) = u(ω0 + xs ) · ps
s=1
Recapitulating so far:
1. We made assumptions about the agents’ preferences over
lotteries so we can represent his/her preferences by an expected
utility.
2. The agent will choose the lottery that delivers the highest
expected utility.
∑
n
U (X , p, ω0 ) = u(ω0 + xs ) · ps
s=1
Recapitulating so far:
1. We made assumptions about the agents’ preferences over
lotteries so we can represent his/her preferences by an expected
utility.
2. The agent will choose the lottery that delivers the highest
expected utility.
∑
n
U (X , p, ω0 ) = u(ω0 + xs ) · ps
s=1
Recapitulating so far:
1. We made assumptions about the agents’ preferences over
lotteries so we can represent his/her preferences by an expected
utility.
2. The agent will choose the lottery that delivers the highest
expected utility.
∑
n
U (X , p, ω0 ) = u(ω0 + xs ) · ps
s=1
Recapitulating so far:
1. We made assumptions about the agents’ preferences over
lotteries so we can represent his/her preferences by an expected
utility.
2. The agent will choose the lottery that delivers the highest
expected utility.
∑
n
U (X , p, ω0 ) = u(ω0 + xs ) · ps
s=1
√
Lottery A, initial wealth ω = 0 and u(x) = x.
√
$1000 1000
1
2 √ √
t=0 1000 0
2 + 2
1
2
√
$0 0
Decision/Probability Tree
√
Lottery B, initial wealth ω = 0 and u(x) = x
√
$500 500
1
2
√
t=0 500
1
2
√
$500 500
Decision/Probability Tree
√
$1000 + 8 1008
1
2 √ √
t=0 1008 8
2 + 2
1
2
√
$0 + 8 8
Decision/Probability Tree
√
$508 508
1
2
√
t=0 508
1
2
√
$508 508
Decision/Probability Tree
Two coins example, u(x) = − exp(−x).
E[U (X )] =
8 − 1 + 10
1
2
− exp(−17)
4 +
t=1 8−1+5
1
− exp(−12)
1 2
2 4 +
≻
Extracting u from ⪰
≻
Extracting u from ⪰
≺
A Behavioral Look at Choice
Anchoring
Availability
Representativeness
Optimism and over confidence
Gains and losses
Status Quo Bias
Framming
Risk Aversion
We have
1 1
U (ℓ1 ) = u(150 − 50) · + u(150 + 50) · and
2 2
U (δ150 ) = u(150) · 1.
Risk Aversion
We have
1 1
U (ℓ1 ) = u(150 − 50) · + u(150 + 50) · and
2 2
U (δ150 ) = u(150) · 1.
Risk Aversion
We have
1 1
U (ℓ1 ) = u(150 − 50) · + u(150 + 50) · and
2 2
U (δ150 ) = u(150) · 1.
Risk Aversion
We have
1 1
U (ℓ1 ) = u(150 − 50) · + u(150 + 50) · and
2 2
U (δ150 ) = u(150) · 1.
Risk Aversion
[ ]
u(200) − u(150) u(150) − u(100) 50
U (ℓ1 ) − U (δ150 ) = − ·
50 50 2
u(200)
u(100)
x
100 150 200
E[ℓ1 ]
Risk Aversion
u(200) − u(150) u(150) − u(100) 50
U (ℓ1 ) − U (δ150 ) =
− ·
2
| 50
{z } | 50
{z }
≃ Mu(150) ≃ Mu(100)
u(200)
U (ℓ1 )
u(100)
x
100 150 200
E[ℓ1 ]
Risk Aversion
u(200) − u(150) u(150) − u(100) 50
U (ℓ1 ) − U (δ150 ) =
− ·
2
| 50
{z } | 50
{z }
≃ Mu(150) ≃ Mu(100)
u(200)
U (ℓ1 )
u(100)
x
100 150 200
E[ℓ1 ]
Risk Aversion
u(200) − u(150) u(150) − u(100) 50
U (ℓ1 ) − U (δ150 ) =
− ·
2
| 50
{z } | 50
{z }
≃ Mu(150) ≃ Mu(100)
u(200)
U (ℓ1 )
u(100)
x
100 150 200
E[ℓ1 ]
Risk Aversion
u(200) − u(150) u(150) − u(100) 50
U (ℓ1 ) − U (δ150 ) =
− ·
2
| 50
{z } | 50
{z }
≃ Mu(150) ≃ Mu(100)
u(200)
U (ℓ1 )
u(100)
x
100 150 200
E[ℓ1 ]
Expected Utility Theory
Attitudes Towards Risk
Definition
The Arrow-Pratt absolute measure of risk-aversion of an agent
with VN-M utility u at wealth level w is:
−u ′′ (w)
ρu (w) = .
u ′ (w)
Definition
The Arrow-Pratt absolute measure of risk-aversion of an agent
with VN-M utility u at wealth level w is:
−u ′′ (w)
ρu (w) = .
u ′ (w)
Definition
The relative absolute measure of risk-aversion of an agent with
VN-M utility u at wealth level w is:
−u ′′ (w) w
ru (w) = .
u ′ (w)
Mathematics Review
Partial Derivatives
For each of the composite functions below tell us, what are the
corresponding f and g and compute h ′ .
√
1 h(x) = 2x.
2 h(x) = − exp(−ρ · x)
1
3 h(x) = (4 + x σ ) σ .
f (x + h) − f (x) ≃ f ′ (x) · h
f (x + h) − f (x) ≃ f ′ (x) · h
f (x + h) − f (x) ≃ f ′ (x) · h
= MUx · ∆x + MUy · ∆y
Mathematical Review
Interior Solutions
Definition: f is concave if and only if, for all α ∈ [0, 1], and
any two points x, y ∈ Rk , we have
f (α x + (1 − α) y) ≥ α f (x) + (1 − α) f (y).
Then,
∂
f (x, g(x))
′ ∂x
g (x) = −
∂
f (x, g(x)).
∂y
Math. Review
The implicit Function Theorem
d ∂ ∂ ∂ ∂
f (x, g(x)) = f (x, g(x)) · x+ f (x, g(x)) · g(x)
dx ∂x ∂x ∂y ∂x
∂ ∂
= f (x, g(x)) + f (x, g(x)) · g ′ (x) ⇒
∂x ∂y
∂
f (x, g(x))
g ′ (x) = − ∂x .
∂
f (x, g(x))
∂y
Key concepts:
1 Present Value
2 Arbitrage
3 Intertemporal Marginal Rate of Substitution - MRIS
Learning Goals:
1 Be able to compute PV .
2 Solve for the optimal consumption bundle.
3 Be able to justify the PV by arbitrage arguments.
Intertemporal Consumption
Key concepts:
1 Present Value
2 Arbitrage
3 Intertemporal Marginal Rate of Substitution - MRIS
Learning Goals:
1 Be able to compute PV .
2 Solve for the optimal consumption bundle.
3 Be able to justify the PV by arbitrage arguments.
Intertemporal Consumption
Key concepts:
1 Present Value
2 Arbitrage
3 Intertemporal Marginal Rate of Substitution - MRIS
Learning Goals:
1 Be able to compute PV .
2 Solve for the optimal consumption bundle.
3 Be able to justify the PV by arbitrage arguments.
Intertemporal Consumption
Key concepts:
1 Present Value
2 Arbitrage
3 Intertemporal Marginal Rate of Substitution - MRIS
Learning Goals:
1 Be able to compute PV .
2 Solve for the optimal consumption bundle.
3 Be able to justify the PV by arbitrage arguments.
Intertemporal Consumption
Key concepts:
1 Present Value
2 Arbitrage
3 Intertemporal Marginal Rate of Substitution - MRIS
Learning Goals:
1 Be able to compute PV .
2 Solve for the optimal consumption bundle.
3 Be able to justify the PV by arbitrage arguments.
Intertemporal Consumption
Key concepts:
1 Present Value
2 Arbitrage
3 Intertemporal Marginal Rate of Substitution - MRIS
Learning Goals:
1 Be able to compute PV .
2 Solve for the optimal consumption bundle.
3 Be able to justify the PV by arbitrage arguments.
Intertemporal Consumption
Key concepts:
1 Present Value
2 Arbitrage
3 Intertemporal Marginal Rate of Substitution - MRIS
Learning Goals:
1 Be able to compute PV .
2 Solve for the optimal consumption bundle.
3 Be able to justify the PV by arbitrage arguments.
Intertemporal Model (no uncertainty)
t = 0, 1, . . . , T periods.
one good at each period, ct consumption at period t
πt = 1 is the spot price for all t (pay at the "spot")
pt is the forward price (contingent price) (pay today)
t=0
p0 = π0
p1
t=1 t=2 t t=T
p2 π1 π2 πt πT
..
.
pT
Definition: A forward contract is a non-standardized contract
between two parties to buy or to sell an asset at a specified
future time at a price agreed upon today.
Intertemporal Model (no uncertainty)
t = 0, 1, . . . , T periods.
one good at each period, ct consumption at period t
πt = 1 is the spot price for all t (pay at the "spot")
pt is the forward price (contingent price) (pay today)
t=0
p0 = π0
p1
t=1 t=2 t t=T
p2 π1 π2 πt πT
..
.
pT
Definition: A forward contract is a non-standardized contract
between two parties to buy or to sell an asset at a specified
future time at a price agreed upon today.
Intertemporal Model (no uncertainty)
t = 0, 1, . . . , T periods.
one good at each period, ct consumption at period t
πt = 1 is the spot price for all t (pay at the "spot")
pt is the forward price (contingent price) (pay today)
t=0
p0 = π0
p1
t=1 t=2 t t=T
p2 π1 π2 πt πT
..
.
pT
Definition: A forward contract is a non-standardized contract
between two parties to buy or to sell an asset at a specified
future time at a price agreed upon today.
Intertemporal Model (no uncertainty)
t = 0, 1, . . . , T periods.
one good at each period, ct consumption at period t
πt = 1 is the spot price for all t (pay at the "spot")
pt is the forward price (contingent price) (pay today)
t=0
p0 = π0
p1
t=1 t=2 t t=T
p2 π1 π2 πt πT
..
.
pT
Definition: A forward contract is a non-standardized contract
between two parties to buy or to sell an asset at a specified
future time at a price agreed upon today.
Intertemporal Model (no uncertainty)
t = 0, 1, . . . , T periods.
one good at each period, ct consumption at period t
πt = 1 is the spot price for all t (pay at the "spot")
pt is the forward price (contingent price) (pay today)
t=0
p0 = π0
p1
t=1 t=2 t t=T
p2 π1 π2 πt πT
..
.
pT
Definition: A forward contract is a non-standardized contract
between two parties to buy or to sell an asset at a specified
future time at a price agreed upon today.
Intertemporal Model (no uncertainty)
t = 0, 1, . . . , T periods.
one good at each period, ct consumption at period t
πt = 1 is the spot price for all t (pay at the "spot")
pt is the forward price (contingent price) (pay today)
t=0
p0 = π0
p1
t=1 t=2 t t=T
p2 π1 π2 πt πT
..
.
pT
Definition: A forward contract is a non-standardized contract
between two parties to buy or to sell an asset at a specified
future time at a price agreed upon today.
Intertemporal Model (no uncertainty)
πt
pt = .
(1 + ı)t
It cash-flow in period t
ı interest rate period t to t + 1 (constant)
It cash-flow in period t
ı interest rate period t to t + 1 (constant)
(1 + ı)Y0 + Y1
Y1
c0
Y0 Y1
0 Y0 +
1+ı
Inter-temporal Consumption
2-Period (T = 2) Consumer Problem
c1 max U (c0 , c1 )
c1 , c2
subject to
c0 + 1
≤ Y0 + (1+ı)
(1+ı) c1
1
Y1
(1 + bı)Y0 + Y1
c0 ≥ 0 and c1 ≥ 0
(1 + ı)Y0 + Y1 ı ↗ bı
Y1
c0
Y0 Y1
0 Y1 Y0 +
Y0 + 1+ı
1 + bı
Inter-temporal Consumption
2-Period (T = 2) Consumer Problem
c1 max U (c0 , c1 )
c1 , c2
subject to
c0 + 1
≤ Y0 + (1+ı)
(1+ı) c1
1
Y1
c0 ≥ 0 and c1 ≥ 0
(1 + ı)Y0 + Y1 ı ↘ eı
Y1
(1 + eı)Y0 + Y1
c0
Y0 Y1
0 Y0 +
1+ı
Y1
Y0 +
1 + eı
The idea of arbitrage
The A’s front office realized right away, of course, that they
couldn’t replace Jason Giambi with another first baseman just
like him. There wasn’t another first baseman just like him and
if there were they couldn’t have afforded him and in any case
that’s not how they thought about the holes they had to fill.
"The important thing is not to recreate the individual," Billy
Beane would later say. "The important thing is to recreate the
aggregate." He couldn’t and wouldn’t find another Jason
Giambi; but he could find the pieces of Giambi he could least
afford to be without, and buy them for a tiny fraction of the
cost of Giambi himself. – Moneyball by Micheal Lewis, p. 103
The idea of arbitrage
continuation
The A’s front office had broken down Giambi into his obvious
offensive statistics: walks, singles, doubles, home runs along
with his less obvious ones: pitches seen per plate appearance,
walk to strikeout ratio and asked: which can we afford to
replace? And they realized that they could afford, in a
roundabout way, to replace his most critical offensive trait, his
on-base percentage, along with several less obvious ones. The
previous season Giambi’s on-base percentage had been .477, the
highest in the American League by 50 points. (Seattle’s Edgar
Martinez had been second at .423; the average American
League on-base percentage was .334.) There was no one player
who got on base half the time he came to bat that the A’s could
afford; – Moneyball by Micheal Lewis, p. 103
The idea of arbitrage
continuation
on the other hand, Jason Giambi wasn’t the only player in the
Oakland A’s lineup who needed replacing. Johnny Damon
(onbase percentage .324) was gone from center field, and the
designated hitter Olmedo Saenz (.291) was headed for the
bench. The average on-base percentage of those three players
(.364) was what Billy and Paul had set out to replace. They
went looking for three players who could play, between them,
first base, outfield, and DH, and who shared an ability to get on
base at a rate thirty points higher than the average big league
player. – Moneyball by Micheal Lewis, p. 103
Understanding Present Value
Arbitrage
MU0
MRIS ≡ =1+ı
MU1
1
c0 + c1 = PV(Y0 , Y1 )
(1 + ı)
Note: the strike price is not the price of the option (in practice,
the price of the option is called premium).
A Call Option Example
continuation
$ − 26.5 + 28 = 1.5
2
3
t=0
1
3
$0
A Call Option Example
continuation
2
3 2u(37.5−P) u(36−P)
t=0 3 + 3
1
3
36 − P
u(36 − P)
t=1
A Call Option Example
continuation
2u(37.5 − P) u(36 − P)
U (buy) = + .
3 3
1 u(x) = x =⇒ Pmax = 1.
2 u(x) = x 2 =⇒ Pmax = 1.0069. Making the DM indifferent,
√ − 74P + P = 0 so
we get 73.5 2
74− 742 −4(73.5)
P= 2 ≃ 1.0069.
√
3 u(x) = √ x =⇒ Pmax = 0.9965. Making the DM indifferent,
√
we get 2 36 − P + 32 + 36 − P = 3 · 6. The "trick" is to
√
√ y = 36 − P and remove the square root in
call
2 y 2 − 32 + y = 18 to get a quadratic equation in y. We
solve it for y and set P = 36 − y 2 .
A Call Option Example
continuation
wealth when
state H happens
Portfolio selection
continuation...
wealth when
state L happens
Portfolio selection
continuation...
U ′ (α) = 0 or equivalently,
(1 + ı)Y0 + Y1
Indiference curve with utility ū
U (c0 , c1 ) = 4 c0
Y0 Y1
0 Y0 +
1+ı
Intertemporal Choice (recap.)
(1 + ı)Y0 + Y1
Indiference curve with utility ū
U (c0 , c1 ) = 5
c0
Y0 Y1
0 Y0 +
1+ı
Intertemporal Choice (recap.)
(1 + ı)Y0 + Y1
Indiference curve with utility ū
U (c0 , c1 ) = 6
c0
Y0 Y1
0 Y0 +
1+ı
Intertemporal Choice (recap.)
(1 + ı)Y0 + Y1
Indiference curve with utility ū
U (c0 , c1 ) = 5.9
c0
Y0 Y1
0 Y0 +
1+ı
General Equilibrium
0
c0B
endowment
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
endowment
c0A
0
A’s endowment of c0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
endowment
c0A
0
B’s endowment of c0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
B’s endowment of c0
0
c0B
endowment
c0A
0
A’s endowment of c0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
B’s endowment of c0
0
c0B
B’s
en-
dow-
ment
of c1
A’s
en-
dow-
ment
endowment
of c1
c0A
0
A’s endowment of c0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
B’s endowment of c0
0
c0B
B’s
en-
dow-
ment
of c1
A’s
en-
dow-
ment
of c1
c0A
0
A’s endowment of c0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
B’s endowment of c0
0
c0B
B’s
en-
dow-
ment
of c1
A’s
en-
dow-
ment
of c1
c0A
0
A’s endowment of c0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
util
ity
bet of
ter A
end tha
ow n
me
nt
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
util
ity
bet of
ter B
end tha
ow n
me
nt
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
both
are
r
bette
off
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
efficient
alloca-
tions
both
are
r
bette
off
= MRSB
MRSA
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
efficiency:
efficient
indiff.
alloca-
curves are
tions
tangent
= MRSB
MRSA
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
efficiency:
efficient
indiff.
alloca-
curves are
tions
tangent
= MRSB
MRSA
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
efficiency:
efficient
indiff.
alloca-
curves are
tions
tangent
= MRSB
MRSA
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
efficient
alloca-
= MRS B
MRS A tions
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
efficient
alloca-
tions
S
= MR B
MRS A
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
efficient
alloca-
tions
S
= MR B
MRS A
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
efficient
alloca-
tions
S
= MR B
MRS A
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
efficient
alloca-
tions
S
= MR B
MRS A
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
efficient
alloca-
tions
S
= MR B
MRS A
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
efficient
alloca-
tions
S
= MR B
MRS A
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
efficient
alloca-
tions
S
= MR B
MRS A
c0A
0
c1B
c1A General Equilibrium
0
c0B
efficient
alloca-
tions
S
= MR B
MRS A
c0A
0
c1B
General Equilibrium: Time and Uncertainty
Arrow-Debreu goods
Assume that:
K ∈ {umbrella,parasol},
K ∈ {Hillsborough,Chicago},
T ∈ {today,tomorrow}, and
S ∈ {sun,rain}.
1 Weather Markets
2 A weather contract
3 Events Markets
Complete Markets
1 Weather Markets
2 A weather contract
3 Events Markets
Complete Markets
1 Weather Markets
2 A weather contract
3 Events Markets
Complete Markets
1 Weather Markets
2 A weather contract
3 Events Markets
General Equilibrium
5pX + 6pY pX 6
=4⇒ =
3pX pY 7
GE: comparing the economies of examples 1 & 2
t=1 t=2
s=0 s=0
p
t=0
1−p
t=1 t=2
s=1 s=0
GE: Example 4
Production
√ √
ES [UD (c)] = (1 − p) · c1 + p · c2
The are 5 goods in this economy:
1 consumption contigent on t = 0, c0
2 consumption contingent on t = 1 and s = 0, c1,0 .
3 consumption contingent on t = 1 and s = 1, c1,1 .
4 consumption contingent on t = 2 and s = 0, c2,0 .
5 consumption contingent on t = 2 and s = 1, c2,1 .
With this notation, expected utility becomes
√ √
(1 − p) · c1,1 + p · c2,0 .
GE: Example 4
Production
FOC
(1 − p)
√
2 c1,1 p1,1
MRS(1,1),(2,0) = p =
√ p2,0
2 c2,0
πS′ = p1,0 qS + p1,1 qS − p0 qS ⇒ p1,0 + p1,1 − p0 = 0.
c0 + qS + qL = 1,
c1,0 = qS ,
c1,1 = qS ,
c2,0 = RqL ,
c2,1 = RqL .
The Consumer Problem under Complete Markets
Two States and One Good
max
cL ,cH
πL u(cL ) + πH u(cH ).
st.
pL cL +pH cH ≤pL YL +pH YH
max
c ,c
U (cL , cH ).
L H
st.
pL cL +pH cH ≤pL YL +pH YH
max
cL ,cH ,zL ,zH
U (cL , cH ).
st.
qL zL +qH zH ≤0
p̂L cL ≤p̂L YL +zL
p̂H cH ≤p̂H YH +zH
Financial Market Eq. with Arrow Securities
max
cL ,cH ,zL ,zH
U (cL , cH ).
st.
qL zL +qH zH ≤0
p̂L cL ≤p̂L YL +zL
p̂H cH ≤p̂H YH +zH
where:
qs is the price of one unit of the security s.
zs is the amount of securities s the consumer buys
(negative if he or she sells).
The consumer problem under uncertainty
with Arrow securities
max
cL ,cH
πL u(cL ) + πH u(cH ). (CP - Arrow securities)
st.
qL zL +qH zH ≤0
p̂L cL ≤p̂L YL +zL
p̂H cH ≤p̂H YH +zH
Let’s assume:
two consumers (A and B)
complete markets (with Arrow-securities we will obtain
identical results).
total endowment constant across states,
⇔ cLA < cH
A
But this is a contradiction !
Portfolio Choice
Let’s assume:
Three dates (0, 1 and 2) and one consumer.
Investment occurs at dates 0 and 1.
Consumption occurs at dates 1 or 2.
With prob. π1 consumption takes place only at date 1.
With prob. π2 = 1 − π1 consumption takes place at date 2.
Safe (short asset) investment of x yields x at next date.
Risky (long asset) investment of x at date 0 yields R x at
date 2 where R > 1. The long asset is illiquid at date 1.
Initial wealth: W0 = 1.
The fraction of wealth in short asset is β.
Dates: = t = 0, 1, 2.
Consumer with utility u(c) = log(c).
Safe (short asset): investment of x yields x at next date.
Risky (long asset): invest. x at t = 0 yields 4 x at t = 2.
Long asset is illiquid at t = 1.
Initial wealth: W0 = 10.
Investment at t = 0, 1.
Consumption at t = 1, 2 but not both.
1
With prob. 2 consumption takes place only at date 1.
The fraction of wealth in short asset is β.
1 1
max log (β 10) + log (β 10 + (1 − β)40)
β 2 2
st.
0≤β≤1
Liquidity Shocks
An Example
1 1
max log (β 10) + log (β 10 + (1 − β)40)
β 2 2
st.
0≤β≤1
10 10 − 40
+ =0 (FOC)
2 (β 10) 2 (β 10 + (1 − β)40)
2
β=
3
Liquidity
with risk-pooling
Two agents, i = 1, 2.
Initial individual wealth, W0i = ω.
Short asset with rate of return r, 1 ≤ r < R.
Long asset with rate of return R.
β fraction of wealth invest in short-asset.
π prob. of liquidity shock (independent across agents).
d amount of short-asset promised to an agent who had a
liquidity shock if the other agent did not suffer a liquidity
shock.
Liquidity
with risk-pooling (continuation)
If agents do not pool their resources, each agent choose its own
β to maximize:
( )
max πu (r β ω) + (1 − π)u r 2 β ω + (1 − β)R ω
β
st.
0≤β≤1
(INDIVIDUAL)
Without pooling:
State Probability Agent 1’s consumption
All suffer the shock π2 rβω
Only 1 suffers π(1 − π) rβω
Only 2 suffers (1 − π)π r 2 β ω + R (1 − β) ω
None suffers (1 − π)2 r 2 β ω + R (1 − β) ω
With pooling:
State Probability Agent 1’s consumption
All suffer the shock π2 βω
Only 1 suffers π(1 − π) d
Only 2 suffers (1 − π)π r (r β 2 ω − d) + R (1 − β)2 ω
None suffers (1 − π)2 r 2 β ω + R (1 − β)ω
Liquidity
with risk-pooling (continuation)
Let’s assume:
Three dates (0, 1 and 2).
Infinitely many consumers i ∈ [0, 1], each one with Wi = 1 and
same preferences ui = u.
Investment opportunities and consumption are as before.
Probabilities of liquidity shocks are independent.
π1 prob. of a ‘bad’ liquidity shock or fraction of consumers who
suffer a ‘bad’ shock.
Company decides on investment decision for the pool of consumers,
it promises c1 to early consumers and c2 to late consumers.
Company faces no risk (Law of Large Numbers), its plans are
feasible if π1 c1 = β and π2 c2 = (1 − π1 )c2 = (1 − β)R.
where [x] is the floor function, it gives the largest integer below x.
Law of Large Numbers
eliminating uncertainty thru averages, side comment
The model is similar the the ones we saw before. But now there
is uncertainty regarding the fraction of the population who
suffers a liquidity shock: it could be high or low, λH (in state H
that happens with prob. π) or λL (in state L that happens with
prob. 1 − π) .
Dates: t = 0, 1, 2. States: s = H , L.
At date 0: consumers make deposit decisions and banks
offer deposit contracts and then make portfolio decisions
(how much to invest in the short-asset and how much to
invest in the long-asset).
At the start of date 1: all learn what is the current state
and mkts. open for trade.
At t = 1 there are two markets: the good market (where c2
Asset Markets and Liquidity
Model Set-Up (cont.)
Ps = R · p s
ps ≤ 1
Asset Markets and Liquidity Simplified Model
NOT COVERED Chapter 4- No Banks,
Let’s assume for now that consumers do their own investment: y in the
short-asset and x in the long asset, x + y = 1.
π · λH · u(c1H ) + π · (1 − λH ) · u(c2H )+
(1 − π) · λL · u(c1L ) + (1 − π) · (1 − λL ) · u(c2L )
Asset Markets and Liquidity Simplified Model
NOT COVERED Chapter 4- No Banks
π · λH · u(c1H ) + π · (1 − λH ) · u(c2H )+
(1 − π) · λL · u(c1L ) + (1 − π) · (1 − λL ) · u(c2L )
Asset Markets and Liquidity Model
Chapter 5 - Banks,
If no bank ever defaults in period 1, then given (PH , PL ), all banks are
maximizing the same function (the expected utility of a depositor). An
important consequence of this fact is that:
All banks will choose the same deposit contract (d, y).
Asset Markets and Liquidity, Chapter 5
No Default Scenario
y > λ s · d ⇒ Ps = R
y ≤ λ s · d ⇒ Ps ≤ R
Behavior in the asset market
continuation
Because (in the no default case) banks are choose the same
strategy (d, y). No banks can ever be short of cash at state s
because if one bank has to liquidate (forced to sell) some of the
long asset, then all banks will be selling (and none will be
buying) so the price would fall to Ps = 0. But if the price of the
long-asset is zero in any state, then in period t = 0, any bank
should invest all in the short-asset and buy an infinite amount
of the long-asset in period t = 1 in the state where Ps = 0. But
all banks doing this cannot be part of an equilibrium...
Behavior in the asset market
no default, continuation
( )
y y
U( , y) =(π · λH + (1 − π) · λL ) · u +
λH λH
( )
y + (1 − y)PH − λH λyH
+ π · (1 − λH ) · u +
(1 − λH ) · pH
( )
y + (1 − y)R − λL λyH
+ (1 − π) · (1 − λL ) · u
(1 − λL ) · 1
The Optimal Deposit Contract
no default, continuation
∂ ∂ y ∂
We now solve d
dy U = U· + U = 0 for y ...
∂d ∂y λH ∂y
Asset Markets again!
no default, continuation
( )
U B (d B , y B ) =(π · λH + (1 − π) · λL ) · u d B +
( B )
y + (1 − y B )PH − λH d
+ π · (1 − λH ) · u +
(1 − λH ) · PH /R
( B )
y + (1 − y B )PH − λL d
+ (1 − π) · (1 − λL ) · u
(1 − λL ) · PL /R
( )
U A (d A , y A ) =(1 − π) · λL · u d A +
( )
+ π · u y A + (1 − y A )PH +
( A )
y + (1 − y A )PL − λL d A
+ (1 − π) · (1 − λL ) · u
(1 − λL ) · PL /R
Asset Markets and Liquidity, Chapter 5
Default Scenario
where C = c1 + c2 .
If ps < 1 banks are not willing to carry cash from date 1 into
date 2.
Asset Markets and Liquidity, Chapter 5
Default Scenario