Siegel 1989
Siegel 1989
Siegel 1989
ABSTRACT. This paper considers two philosophical problems and their relation to
science education. The first involves the rationality of science; it is argued here that the
traditional view, according to which science is rational because of its adherence to (a
non-standard conception of) scientific method, successfully answers one central question
concerning science's rationality. The second involves the aims of education; here it is
argued that a fundamental educational aim is the fostering of rationality, or its
educational cognate, critical thinking. The ramifications of these two philosophical
theses for science education are then considered, and a science education which takes
reasons in science as its fundamental feature is sketched.
I N T R O D U C T I O N : SCIENCE, R A T I O N A L I T Y , AND
SCIENCE EDUCATION
quite unable to recognize evidence for what it is; and whose personal
careerist motivations give the lie to the idea that the scientist yearns
only, or even mainly, for the truth. Under the weight of this new
image, many philosophers and others have questioned the notion that
science is the apex of rationality, and that the scientist is the per-
sonification of rationality par excellence. And if science and scientists
are as uncritical, and as unguided by reasons and evidence, as the new
image suggests, then how, and to what end, shall science education be
envisioned.'?
In this paper I consider two classic philosophical problems. Both
concern rationality, and both have ramifications for science education.
The first is the problem of the rationality of science. This is, arguably,
the most fundamental problem in the philosophy of science; in any
case it has occupied center stage in philosophy of science for the last
several decades. The many challenges to the traditional understanding
of that rationality - according to which, as the opening motto from
Russell suggests, science is preeminently rational, in virtue of its
adherence to scientific method - have left many philosophers denying
that science is rational, or securing that rationality in some other way
than by appeal to its method. In the first section of this paper, I offer
an analysis which upholds the traditional conception. That is, I argue
that science is properly thought of as preeminently rational, and it is
properly so thought because of its embrace of scientific method
(although my characterization of scientific method is itself un-
orthodox).
In the second section I turn from philosophy of science to philoso-
phy of education and our second classic philosophical problem. In the
philosophy of education, the most fundamental problem concerns the
aims of education. Here I shall argue that education should take as a
basic aim the fostering of rationality; and that rationality, or its
educational cognate, critical thinking, should be taken to be a fun-
damental educational ideal. Calling the critical thinker one who is
'appropriately moved by reasons', I shall in this section develop this
conception of education, and point out its close relationship to the
conception of the rationality of science offered in the previous section.
Finally, in the third section I shall turn to science education. Here I
shall argue that embracing the traditional conception of the rationality
of science, and embracing rationality or critical thinking as a fun-
damental educational ideal, both have important ramifications for
THE RATIONALITY OF SCIENCE 11
B. Scientific Method
It is method rather than doctrine that defines the community of science, and it is the
stability of method in pursuit of truth that holds the community together throughout
doctrinal change. (Schettler 1974, p. 75) 4
14 HARVEY SIEGEL
2. RA'FIONALITY/CR1TICAL THINKING AS AN
EDUCATIONAL IDEAL
• . . the attitudes we seek to foster in the critical reasoning course might be summed up
under the label 'love of reason'. We not only want our students to be able to reason
well; we want them actually to do it, and so we want them to be eager to do it and to
enjoy it - to think it important. We want it to assume an important place in their lives. 22
The pedagogical principle of the proliferation of theories could be stated in this way:
Students should learn to work with many theories a s working hypotheses in a given
domain of inquiry, even if commitment in the strong sense [i.e., as true or probably true]
to an incompatible theory is justified in the domain.
The rationale for the proliferation of theories approach is this: The more theories one
is used to working within a given domain, the less likely it is that one will be blinded by
one's commitments.., to any one of t h e m . . . (Martin 1972, p. 126)
NOTES
* This paper is mainly drawn from other publications. The first section is taken from my
(1985); the second from (1988), Chapter 2; and the third from (1988), Chapter 6. Since
what appears here are truncated versions of those discussions, I urge interested readers
to look to those other works for fuller treatments of the issues here discussed.
i See Siegel (1983) for criticism of this view.
2 See Siegel (1980a) for criticism.
3 See Siegel (1985, pp. 518-22) for criticism of this means-end conception of the
rationality of science.
4 It is not clear from the context if Scheflter is here asserting this thesis himself, or
rather reporting the Pragmatists' commitment to it.
5 See Siegel (1985, pp. 526-28) for further discussion of SM.
6 This paragraph owes much to discussion with Norman GiUespie. Two additional
points need to be made here. First, I am not suggesting that what counts as evidence in
science is in some essential way different from evidence in other areas of inquiry. I
remain, for the purposes of this paper, agnostic on this question. For this is the question
which Q2 asks. As will presently become clear, the characterization of SM offered here
is to be regarded as an answer to Q1, not Q2. Off the record, I would speculate that the
various areas of inquiry are marked off from each other not by means of alternative sorts
of evidence but by complex evolutionary histories of problems, language, etc. See, in
this regard, Toulmin (1972). Second, one may wonder (as one of the referees does) why
SM should be taken as a commitment to evidence, rather than (say) a commitment to
truth. Full consideration of the point would require far more space than is available
here. But, briefly, it seems clear that science cannot achieve truth except, if at all, by
way of evidence, so that, methodologically speaking, evidence is prior to truth;
moreover, recognizing the familiar fallibilist point regarding the possibility of future
evidence and the fact that scientific views change with the uncovering of evidence
requires that current available evidence, rather than truth, be the locus of scientific
belief and inquiry. But there is obviously much more to say on the matter than I have
said here.
7 Even Kuhn seems to agree here. See his (1970), p. 159.
s See Siegel (1985, pp. 526--28).
9 See Siegel (1985, pp. 518-22).
1o Ibid., (pp. 522; 534, Note 21).
la Ibid., pp. 523, 534.
12 See also Popper's remarks on the 'attitude of reasonableness', in (1962, p. 225).
~3 In Siegel (1988), from which the present discussion is taken.
14 Throughout I should be taken to mean that the critical thinker accepts the convicting
force of good reasons, i.e., of reasons which actually have convicting force and which
warrant conviction. I have not added 'good' before each occurrence of 'reason', because
I take it to be implied by 'appropriate' in 'appropriately moved by reasons'. To be
appropriately moved is to be moved to just the extent that the reasons in question
THE RATIONALITY OF SCIENCE 37
something to be striven for, and developed to varying degrees, over time, not something
to be accomplished once and for all. I am grateful here to discussion with Robert Floden
and Dennis Rohatyn.
25 Assuming here that acts of thinking are acts, the present point is simply that acts of
thinking are not the only sort of acts there are.
26 In the philosophy of action a distinction is frequently drawn between what are called
the 'internalist' and 'externalist' perspectives. The rationality of an action can be
appraised externally, by inquiring as to whether there are (were) good reasons for
performing the action; or internally, by inquiring as to whether the agent has (had) good
reasons for performing the action, and acts (acted) for those reasons. Full consideration
of this matter would take us far afield. It is clear, however, that critical thinking is to be
understood in an internalist way, insofar as the critical thinker acts in accordance with
reasons she has. An excellent and thorough discussion of the internalist/externalist
literature and its relevance to education may be found in Emily Robertson's (1984). I
am grateful to Robertson for correspondence and conversation on these and related
matters.
27 See Passmore (1967, pp. 1951t).
28 Of course achieving the ideal - being a critical thinker - is a matter of degree.
Taking critical thinking as an ideal means fostering the features of critical thinking to
the greatest extent possible. But there is no magic point or threshold at which the
non-critical thinker turns into a critical thinker. Presumably most people have the
capacity to be at least minimally critical, and presumably no one is perfectly critical.
Critical thinking must be taken as an ideal which we strive for, and approximate to
varying degrees. I am thankful for discussion with Robert Floden, Emily Robertson, and
Dennis Rohatyn on this point.
29 Siegel (1988, Chap. 2).
30 I hasten to note that in this Section I have not defended the view that critical
thinking is a fundamental educational ideal. I have only tried to articulate the 'reasons'
conception of critical thinking. For further articulation, especially regarding the dis-
tinction between the probative force and the normative impact of reasons, see my
(1989b). For the defense of the view that critical thinking is a fundamental educational
ideal, see Siegel (1988, Chap. 3).
31 See Martin (1972, Chap. 1).
32 See Schemer (1973, p. 75 and Chap. 3, esp. pp. 35-36), for related discussion; also
Schemer (1973b). See also Martin (1972), whose discussion both exemplifies and argues
for the virtues of a science education informed by philosophy of science.
33 See Martin's discussion of pseudoscience in the science curriculum in his (1972, pp.
40--42). My own favorite example of pseudoscience, for purposes of contrast with
genuine science, is that of 'scientific' creationism. See my (1981) and (1984a). An
excellent discussion may also be found in Moshman (1985). A provocative alternative
view, which denies the science/pseudoscience distinction but nevertheless upholds
standards of good science, is advanced in Kitcher (1985).
34 Siegel (1988, Chap. 6). The rest of the present section is taken from this source. In
this chapter I discuss alternative approaches to science education in considerable detail;
the interested reader may wish to consult the chapter for a more complete and
systematic presentation.
THE RATIONALITY OF S C I E N C E 39
REFERENCES
Binkley, R. W.: 1980, 'Can the Ability to Reason Well Be Thought?', in J. A. Blair and
R. Johnson (eds.), Informal Logic: The First International Symposium, Edgepress,
Inverness, California, pp. 79-92.
Dewey, J.: 1916, Democracy and Education, The Free Press, Macmillan, New York.
Ennis, R. H.: 1979, 'Research in Philosophy of Science Bearing on Science Education',
in P. D. Asquith and H. E. Kyburg, Jr. (eds.), Current Research in Philosophy of
Science, Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, Michigan, pp. 138-70.
Green, T. F.: 1972, 'Indoctrination and Beliefs', in I. A. Snook (ed.), Concepts of
Indoctrination, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, pp. 25-46.
Hempel, C.: 1979, 'Scientific Rationality: Analytic vs. Pragmatic Perspectives', in T. G.
Geraets (ed.), pp. 45-66.
Holton, G.: 1975, 'Science, Science Teaching, and Rationality', in S. Hook, P. Kurtz
and M. Todorovich (eds.), The Philosophy of the Curriculum, Prometheus Books, New
York, pp. 101-18.
Kitcher, P.: 1985, 'Good Science, Bad Science, Dreadful Science, and Pseudoscience',
Journal of College Science Teaching 14, 168-73.
Kuhn, T. S.: 1970, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed., enlarged, University
of Chicago Press, Chicago.
Martin, M.: 1972, Concepts of Science Education, Scott Foresman, Glenview, Illinois.
Moshman, D.: 1985, 'A Role for Creationism in Science Education', Journal of College
Science Teaching 15, 106-09.
Nagel, E.: 1975, 'In Defense of Scientific Knowledge', in S. Hook, P. Kurtz and M.
Todorovich (eds.), The Philosophy of the Curriculum, Prometheus Books, New York,
pp. 119-26.
Newton-Smith, W. H.: 1981, The Rationality of Science, Routledge and Kegan Paul,
London.
40 HARVEY SIEGEL
Passmore, J.: 1967, 'On Teaching To Be Critical', in R. S. Peters (ed.), The Concept o[
Education, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, pp. 192-211.
Paul, R.: 1984, 'Critical Thinking: Fundamental to Education for a Free Society',
Educational Leadership, pp. 4-14.
Peters, R. S.: 1966, 'Reason and Habit: The Paradox of Moral Education', in I. Scheffler
(ed.), Philosophy and Education, 2nd ed., Allyn and Bacon, Boston, pp. 245--62.
Peters, R. S.: 1973, Reason and Compassion, Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.
Phillips, D. C.: 1985, 'Can Scientific Method Be Taught?', Journal of College Science
Teaching 15, 95-101.
Popper, K. R.: 1962, The Open Society and Its Enemies, Vol. 2, Princeton University
Press, Princeton, New Jersey.
Popper, K. R.: 1970, 'Normal Science and Its Dangers', in I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave
(eds.), Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, Cambridge University Press, Cam-
bridge, pp. 51-58.
Putnam, H.: 1981, Reason, Truth and History, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Robertson, E. E.: 1984, 'Practical Reasons, Authority, and Education', in R. Roemer
(ed.), Philosophy of Education 1983: Proceedings of the Thirty-Ninth Annual Meeting
of the Philosophy of Education Society, Philosophy of Education Society, Normal,
Illinois, pp. 61-75.
Russell, B.: 1945, A History of Western Philosophy, Simon and Schuster, New York.
Scheflter, I.: 1960, The Language of Education, Charles C. Thomas, Springfield, Illinois.
Scheflter, I.: 1965, Conditions of Knowledge, Scott Foresman, Chicago, Illinois.
Scheitter, I.: 1973, Reason and Teaching, Bobbs-Merrill, New York, first published in
1973 by Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.
Scheffler, I.: 1973a, 'Philosophical Models of Teaching', in I. Schettter, Reason and
Teaching, pp. 67-81.
Scheffler, I.: 1973b, 'Philosophies of and the Curriculum', in J. F. Doyle (ed.), Educa-
tional Judgments, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London.
Scheffler, I.: 1974, Four Pragmatists, Humanities Press, New York.
Scheifter, I.: 1982, 'In Praise of the Cognitive Emotions', reprinted as Appendix B
in I. Scheffter, Science and Subjectivity, 2nd ed., enlarged, Hackett, Indianopolis,
Indiana, pp. 139-57; originally published in Teachers College Record 79, 171-86.
Schwab, J. J.: 1962, The Teaching of Science as Enquiry, Harvard University Press,
Cambridge, Massachusetts.
Scriven, M.: 1975, 'Cognitive Moral Education', Phi Delta Kappan 57, 689-94.
Siegel, H.: 1980, 'Discovery, Justification and the Naturalizing of Epistemology',
Philosophy of Science 47, 297-321.
Siegel, H.: 1980a, 'Objectivity, Rationality, Incommensurability, and More', British
Journal for the Philosophy of Science 31, 359-75.
Siegel, H.: 1981, 'Creationism, Evolution, and Education: The California Fiasco', Phi
Delta Kappan 63, 95-101.
Siegel, H.: 1983, 'Truth, Problem Solving and the Rationality of Science', Studies in
History and Philosophy of Science 14, 89-112.
Siegel, H.: 1984, "Goodmanian Relativism', The Monist 67, 359-375.
Siegel, H.: 1984a, 'The Response to Creationism', Educational Studies 15, 349--64.
Siegel, H.: 1985, 'What Is the Question Concerning the Rationality of Science?',
Philosophy of Science 52, 517-37.
T H E R A T I O N A L I T Y OF S C I E N C E 41
Department of Philosophy
University of Miami
Coral Gables, FL 33124
U.S.A.