Alienatic
Alienatic
Alienatic
net/publication/287831983
CITATIONS READS
3 2,312
3 authors, including:
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
You are not alone? A thematic analysis of accounts of paranormal experiences View project
All content following this page was uploaded by Ken Drinkwater on 21 March 2016.
Journal of Scientific Exploration (ISSN 0892-3310) is published quarterly in March, June, September, and Decem-
ber by the Society for Scientific Exploration, 151 Petaluma Blvd. So., #227, Petaluma, CA 94952 USA. Society
Members receive online Journal subscriptions with their membership. Online Library subscriptions are $135.
JOURNAL OF SCIENTIFIC EXPLORATION
A Publication of the Society for Scientific Exploration
Editorial
635 Editorial STEPHEN E. BRAUDE
Research Articles
639 Revisiting the Ganzfeld ESP Debate:
A Basic Review and Assessment BRYAN J. WILLIAMS
663 The Global Consciousness Project: EDWIN C. MAY
Identifying the Source of Psi S. JAMES P. SPOTTISWOODE
683 Reply to May and Spottiswoode on Experi-
menter Effect as the Explanation for GCP Results ROGER NELSON
690 Reply to May and Spottiswoode’s “The GCP:
Identifying the Source of Psi” PETER BANCEL
695 The Global Consciousness Project, Identifying the EDWIN C. MAY
Source of the Psi: A Response to Nelson and Bancel S. JAMES P. SPOTTISWOODE
699 Alien Visitation, Extra-Terrestrial Life, NEIL DAGNALL
and Paranormal Beliefs KENNETH DRINKWATER
ANDREW PARKER
721 Anomalous Switching of the Bi-Stable Percept
of a Necker Cube: A Preliminary Study DICK J. BIERMAN
735 Color Distribution of Light Balls in Hessdalen GERSON S. PAIVA
Lights Pheomenon CARLTON A. TAFT
Commentary
747 On Elephants and Matters Epistemological:
Reply to Etzel Cardeña’s Guest Editorial “On
Wolverines and Epistemological Totalitarianism” NEAL GROSSMAN
754 Response to Neal Grossman’s Reply
“On Elephants and Matters Epistemological” ETZEL CARDEÑA
Historical Perspective
755 Ernesto Bozzano: An Italian Spiritualist
and Psychical Researcher LUCA GASPERINI
Obituary
775 In Memory of William Corliss PATRICK HUYGHE
SSE News
867 SSE 31st Annual Conference; SSE 9th Biennial European Meeting; SSE Masthead
869 Thank You to Submission Reviewers and Book Review Authors for 2010 & 2011
871 Index of Previous Articles in JSE
885 Order forms for JSE Issues, JSE Subscriptions, and Society Membership
88938 Instructions for JSE Authors
Journal of Scientific Exploration, Vol. 25, No. 4, pp. 635–637, 2011 0892-3310/11
EDITORIAL
A s subscribers to the hard copy version of the JSE have already noticed, this
is a particularly hefty issue. I’m pleased that we’ve been able to wrap up
2011 with a gratifyingly substantive and larger than usual array of papers on a
variety of interesting and important topics. This issue contains too many papers
for me to comment on them individually. But I do want to direct your attention
to the detailed exchange over the data from the Global Consciousness Project
(GCP). This series of papers addresses not only the specific questions of how to
interpret the GCP data and what it is that the GCP is actually tracking, but also
the long-standing and more general debate among parapsychologists over the
merits of Decision Augmentation Theory (DAT), hailed by some as a more vi-
able ESP (or cognition)-based alternative to physicalistic explanations of much
of the apparent evidence for psychokinesis. Ed May and James Spottiswoode
argue first for the DAT point of view. They contend that the statistical devia-
tions reported in the GCP reflect a cognitive form of experimenter psi rather
than a force-like physical effect. Then Roger Nelson and Peter Bancel reply
separately, and from quite different perspectives. May and Spottiswoode get
the last word in this exchange. I’m personally pleased to see the details of the
debate presented so thoroughly, and I hope readers will agree that the exchange
significantly advances our understanding of the issues.
I also hope to feature additional dialogues on topics of interest to SSE
members in future issues, and I encourage readers to let me know what key
topics they would like to see debated. Of course, I can’t promise to satisfy all
(or any) suggestions. Already in my brief tenure as JSE Editor-in-Chief, I’ve
learned that I can’t always extract submissions of target articles (or replies)
from relevant researchers, no matter how pathetically or aggressively I frame
my requests. But I’ll do what I can, and I’m genuinely interested in knowing
which topics are of particular interest to our subscribers.
Since this is the holiday season and an appropriate time for reflecting on the
year that’s coming to a close, I’d like once again to acknowledge and thank my
dedicated and hardworking—in fact, overworked—team of Associate Editors
and the many reviewers on whom we all rely in vetting papers for inclusion
in the JSE. As I’ve noted before, producing this Journal poses a distinctive
challenge. Because the JSE deals with topics either shunned altogether or dealt
with shabbily by more mainstream publications, the community of qualified
readers for high-level peer review is quite small. Ideally, I’d prefer to have
a larger team of Associate Editors, in order to lighten the editorial load for
those who—perhaps inscrutably—continue to volunteer large chunks of time to
635
636 Editorial
examples, which can guide us as we look for ways to preserve our scholarly
and research legacies. Fortunately, the SSE abounds in smart and resourceful
members who, either individually or collectively, should be able to address this
recurring problem. I’d hoped that my previous Editorial would have provoked
some discussion and scheming on the matter, and I’m sorry if—for at least
some—it elicited more discouragement than enthusiasm for the challenge.
And I’m sorry too if I managed to obscure the positive message that, for the
Eisenbud/Serios material at least, we were able to find a respectable, respectful,
and indeed grateful repository, whose director very actively and energetically
promotes the collection. While it’s true (as I noted) that we must remain wary
of possible changes in attitude along with changes in personnel, I hope that this
story encourages JSE readers to explore their own mainstream connections for
protecting other research archives.
STEPHEN E. BRAUDE
638 Editorial
Journal of Scientific Exploration, Vol. 25, No. 4, pp. 639–661, 2011 0892-3310/11
RESEARCH ARTICLE
Introduction
In attempting to make a case for the existence of ostensible psychic (psi)
phenomena such as extrasensory perception (ESP), parapsychologists have
been regularly faced with the challenge from skeptics of providing a body of
notable evidence that can be reproduced under laboratory conditions. In rising
to this challenge, many parapsychologists have focused in recent years on the
data from a particular type of experiment often used to test for telepathy, and
which makes use of a sensory reduction technique known as ganzfeld.
Within the context of parapsychology, the ganzfeld (German for “total
field”) is a technique intended to help improve the reception of ESP by briefly
exposing a person to a static and uniform sensory field.1 This is done by covering
the person’s eyes with translucent eye shields (usually halved ping-pong balls
externally illuminated by a red light) and filling the person’s ears with soft static
noise played through headphones. While in this homogeneous ganzfeld “state,”
639
640 Bryan J. Williams
the person may report a dimming of the visual field and experience a diffuse
background that has been described as a “cloudy fog” (Wackermann, Pütz, &
Allefeld, 2008:1366). After several minutes, the person may begin to experience
hallucinatory-like images and/or sounds, similar to those experienced during
the hypnagogic state between wakefulness and sleep.2 Presumably, if the ESP
assumption is valid, some of the images and sounds may correspond to the ESP
target.
A typical experimental test session for telepathy using the ganzfeld
proceeds in the following manner: Two participants, one acting as the “sender”
and the other as the “receiver,”3 are isolated in separate, soundproofed rooms.
In one room, the receiver is placed in the ganzfeld state and asked to describe
any images, sounds, or impressions that come to mind while in that state. In the
other room, the sender is shown a randomly selected visual target, such as a
photograph or a video clip, and asked to concentrate on its details. After about
thirty minutes, the receiver is taken out of the ganzfeld and shown a collection
of four photos or video clips, one of which was the target that the sender was
concentrating on (the other three are decoys). The receiver is then asked to rank
the four photos/videos according to their degree of correspondence with the
images, sounds, and impressions received while in the ganzfeld. If the photo/
video that the sender was viewing is ranked as having the highest degree of
correspondence, the test session is considered a success, or a “hit.” With the
probability of a hit being 1 in 4, the hit rate expected by chance is 25% (for
further discussion of the ganzfeld and its use in ESP experiments, see, for
example, Bem & Honorton, 1994, Honorton, Berger,Varvoglis, Quant, Derr, et
al., 1990, Wackermann, Pütz, & Allefeld, 2008).4
For a period of approximately 28 years, there has been an ongoing debate
between parapsychologists and skeptics over the issue of whether or not
the ganzfeld experiment can provide the independently replicable evidence
necessary to support the empirical case for psi. This paper seeks to address
the issue in two ways. First, it provides a brief review of the substance of the
debate as it has persisted from 1982 to the present. Second, it presents a basic
assessment of a collection of 59 ganzfeld ESP studies reported in the years
following the publication of a stringent set of methodological guidelines and
recommendations for ganzfeld research developed by Ray Hyman, a cognitive
psychologist and long-time critic of parapsychology, and the late Charles
Honorton, a parapsychologist and contributor to the ganzfeld database (Hyman
& Honorton, 1986).
and Adrian Parker (Braud, Wood, & Braud, 1975, Honorton & Harper, 1974,
Parker, 1975). Between 1974 and 1981, a total of 42 ganzfeld studies had been
reported by ten different laboratories. Of these early studies, 23 (55%) produced
results that were statistically significant at the .05 level.
The debate commenced at the 25th Annual Convention of the
Parapsychological Association (PA) in August of 1982, where two preliminary
meta-analyses of the early ganzfeld database were presented.5 On the basis of
his analysis, Ray Hyman argued that the initial rate of successful replication
may have been overestimated. Noting that some of the experiments contained
slight variations on the standard ganzfeld procedure, Hyman suggested that
each variation should be counted as a separate study. By his count, there were
80 ganzfeld studies in all, 25 of which (31%) were successful. Although this
was still considered notable, Hyman further argued that the significance of the
database could be further discounted through the effects of selective reporting.
In his review of the database, Hyman found a significant tendency for
studies with a small number of test sessions to have a higher proportion of
significant positive results, suggesting to him the possibility that some studies
may have been stopped and reported early on because of their promising results
(i.e. optional stopping on a hit). In addition, Hyman claimed that there was
circumstantial evidence suggesting that some pilot or exploratory studies in
the database were being retrospectively counted as formal ones solely on the
basis of their significant outcomes. He further suggested that, in contrast to
the significant ones, studies with nonsignificant results might not have been
reported, contributing to a possible “file-drawer” effect. According to Hyman’s
argument, when the effects of selective reporting are taken into account, the
success rate of the database comes much closer to chance. Lastly, Hyman cited a
number of potential study flaws in the database relating to target randomization,
adequate security, sensory cuing, statistical errors, and the use of multiple
analyses.
Honorton responded to Hyman’s critique with his own meta-analysis
of the early ganzfeld database. To address the issue of varying conditions,
Honorton proposed that researchers should examine each study and decide for
themselves whether or not each varying ganzfeld condition should be classified
as a separate study. To adjust the results for the effects of multiple analyses,
Honorton applied a Bonferroni correction and showed that the initial success
rate would only be reduced to 45%. To further counter the multiple-analysis
argument, Honorton focused on the 28 studies that reported a hit rate, the most
common analysis measure used in the database. Of these, 12 studies (43%)
were significant at the .05 level. When combined, these 28 studies were shown
to have a Stouffer’s Z of 6.60 (p = 2.1 × 10−9). In addition to citing the PA’s
policy against selective reporting, Honorton used Rosenthal’s (1979) “file
642 Bryan J. Williams
We agree that there is an overall significant effect in this data base that cannot
be reasonably explained by selective reporting or multiple analysis. We con-
tinue to differ over the degree to which the effect constitutes evidence for psi,
but we agree that the final verdict awaits the outcome of future experiments
conducted by a broader range of investigators and according to more stringent
standards. (p. 351)
Figure 2. Results summary for the 30 ganzfeld ESP studies analyzed by Milton
and Wiseman (1999), in terms of hit rate and 95% confidence intervals.
The horizontal line at 25% indicates the hit rate expected by chance.
644 Bryan J. Williams
(Stouffer’s Z = −1.30, p = .903). The difference between the two study types
was significant (U = 190.5, p = .020). In addition, Bem, Palmer, & Broughton
(2001a) found ten other ganzfeld studies that had been reported after Milton
and Wiseman’s analysis. When these studies were combined with the 30 studies
in the Milton–Wiseman database, a significant hit rate of 30.1% was obtained
(Stouffer’s Z = 2.59, p = .0048). Graphical summaries of Bem et al.’s results are
presented in Figure 3, Figure 4, and Figure 5.
Two other recent meta-analyses have reported overall hit rates that are
significantly above the 25% expected by chance. In the first, Marilyn Schlitz
and Dean Radin (2003) found that a unified database of all ganzfeld studies
published between 1974 and 2001 had a hit rate of 32% (929 hits in 2,878
sessions, z = 8.75, p << 10−15).6
Another unified database comprising 16 early ganzfeld studies, the eleven
PRL autoganzfeld studies, and Bem et al.’s 29 “standard” ganzfeld studies was
analyzed by Jessica Utts, Michelle Norris, Eric Suess, and Wesley Johnson
(2010) in the second study. Their results indicated 709 hits in 2,124 sessions
for a hit rate of 33.4% (z = 8.92, p = 2.26 × 10−18). In addition to this frequentist
646 Bryan J. Williams
Figure 4. Results summary for the set of nine “non-standard” ganzfeld studies
contained in the database analyzed by Bem, Palmer, & Broughton
(2001b), in terms of hit rate and 95% confidence intervals.
The horizontal line at 25% indicates the hit rate expected by chance.
Figure 5. Results summary for the entire set of 40 “standard” & “non-standard”
ganzfeld studies contained in the database analyzed by Bem, Palmer,
& Broughton (2001b), in terms of hit rate and 95% confidence intervals.
The far right point interval represents the overall hit rate for all 40 studies
combined. The horizontal line at 25% indicates the hit rate expected by
chance.
Revisiting the Ganzfeld Debate 647
analysis, Utts, Norris, Suess, & Johnson (2010) performed a Bayesian analysis
on this database to illustrate how the differing levels of a priori belief regarding
the probability for ganzfeld success (modeled in terms of a beta distribution)
for three separate personal points of view (believer, skeptic, and open-minded)
were each influenced by the experimental results of the database. While the
probability distribution for the open-minded view was shifted more toward
higher probabilities of success, the distribution for the skeptic view was not
shifted much from probabilities close to chance level. The distribution for the
believer view remained within the range of higher probabilities, but was found
to have less variability.
Most recently, an analysis by Lance Storm, Patrizio Tressoldi, and Lorenzo
Di Risio (2010a) of 30 ganzfeld studies reported from 1997 to 2008 found a
hit rate of 32.2% (483 hits in 1,498 sessions, z = 6.44, p < .001).7 A graphical
summary of Storm et al.’s (2010a) results is shown in Figure 6.
More in-depth discussion of the ganzfeld debate and additional summaries
of the meta-analyses reviewed here can be found in other published reviews
by Dalkvist (2001), Palmer (2003), Radin (1997, Ch. 5, 2006, Ch. 6), Storm
(2006), and Utts (1991, 1999b).
A Basic Assessment
An issue central to the ganzfeld debate as it appeared in Psychological Bulletin
was the status of independent replication in the years following the publication
of Hyman and Honorton’s (1986) joint communiqué. At the end of their article
on the PRL autoganzfeld meta-analysis, Bem and Honorton (1994) stated
that, although they had produced significant overall results under stringent
conditions,
their ability to address the issue because of their inclusion of the early ganzfeld
database. Assuming for the moment that the early database does indeed contain
serious flaws, as argued by Hyman (1985), the argument can be made that
inclusion of this database could potentially inflate or otherwise confound the
overall results.8 Meta-analyses that used a non-unified database also offer a
positive outlook on the issue (e.g., Bem, Palmer, & Broughton, 2001a, Storm et
al., 2010a:475), although assessing the broader, long-term trend in replication
may be partially limited in these analyses by their confined periods of coverage.
For these reasons, an attempt was made to basically assess the post-communiqué
replication status of the current ganzfeld database, as well as to update and
confirm some of the results of previous meta-analyses. However, it should be
made clear that the assessment presented here was not meant to represent any
kind of formal meta-analysis, and thus that may perhaps limit interpretation of
its findings (addressed in the Discussion).
Method
To examine the current status of replication, a collection of ganzfeld studies was
compiled from the databases listed in three previously published meta-analyses
that addressed post-communiqué research (Bem, Palmer, & Broughton, 2001a,
Milton & Wiseman, 1999, Storm et al., 2010a). This resulted in 59 studies
reported in the period between 1987 and 2008 (see Appendix 1).
Formal meta-analyses of ganzfeld research have tended to use effect size
as their primary measure of effect magnitude. However, to make the assessment
results more accessible to a general interdisciplinary audience, the decision was
made here to focus on hit rate, as this is a concept that is intuitively easier
to grasp. Following the approach taken by Radin (1997), the hit rate was
obtained by determining the proportion of hits achieved over the total number
of test sessions in each study, and an associated 95% confidence interval was
calculated based on the proportion of hits and its associated standard deviation
(SD), derived from the equation (from Utts, 1999a:341):
SD = √(h)(1 – h)/N
the method of hypothesis testing described by Utts (1999a, Ch. 21) was used.
In this basic four-step method, a test statistic is used to decide between two
competing hypotheses: a null hypothesis and an alternative hypothesis. Under
the null hypothesis of no ESP, the mean hit rate in ganzfeld experiments is
expected to be around the chance rate of 25%. Under the alternative hypothesis
of ostensible ESP, the mean ganzfeld hit rate will be significantly different from
the expected chance rate of 25%. Here, the test statistic was a z-score of the form
z = (x – μ)/SD, where x is the proportion of hits observed in a given database
of ganzfeld experiments, μ is the mean proportion of hits expected under the
null hypothesis (.25), and SD is the expected standard deviation (determined
by the SD equation above, using the chance-expected proportion of hits for h).
Based on the resulting z-score, an associated probability value was obtained to
determine the degree of significance. Because the prediction in many ESP tests
(including the ganzfeld) is for an above-chance hit rate, the same prediction was
maintained here and thus all reported probability values are one-tailed.
Results
Figure 1 shows a results summary of the PRL autoganzfeld meta-analysis by
Bem and Honorton (1994), expressed in terms of hit rate and 95% confidence
intervals. As in the Bem and Honorton analysis, Study 11 (No. 302–Experienced)
was excluded from the overall hit rate because of its possible response bias. As
noted in the previous section, Bem and Honorton found a total of 106 hits in 329
sessions, for a significant overall hit rate of 32.2%. Based on Utts’ method of
hypothesis testing, this results in a z-score of 3.02 (p = .001), which is slightly
higher than, but still consistent with, the original reported finding.9
Figure 2 shows the results summary for the 30 post-communiqué ganzfeld
studies analyzed by Milton and Wiseman (1999), expressed in terms of hit
rate and 95% confidence intervals. It was noted in the previous section that
Milton and Wiseman’s analysis, as originally published, had produced a result
consistent with chance. However, a few researchers (Radin, 2006:118, Schlitz
& Radin, 2003:79, Utts cited in Storm et al., 2010a, Footnote 1) have pointed
out that if their 30-study database is analyzed in terms of hit rate, a significant
finding is obtained. An attempt was made to verify this by calculating the
proportion of hits for each study in the database and then examining the
combined hit rate.10 This resulted in 331 hits in 1,198 sessions for a hit rate of
27.6% (z = 2.08, p = .019), consistent with the estimates made by these other
researchers. It can be seen at the far right of Figure 2 that the lower bound
of the confidence interval for the combined hit rate seems to include chance
(by calculation, the lower bound is 25.07%, just marginally above chance
expectation). This suggests that, even though the result is postive, caution is
warranted in interpreting the combined result.
650 Bryan J. Williams
communiqué studies compiled from the databases of Bem et al. (2001b), Milton
and Wiseman (1999), and Storm et al. (2010a) is shown in Figure 7 in terms of a
cumulative hit rate over time and associated 95% confidence intervals (modeled
after the approach taken by Radin, 2006:120). It should be made clear that this
does not include the PRL autoganzfeld results; it is based only on ganzfeld
replication efforts independent of PRL. The graph indicates that the hit rate
begins to average out over time at about 30%, significantly above the 25%
expected by chance. Overall, there are 878 hits in 2,832 sessions for a hit rate
of 31%, which has z = 7.37, p = 8.59 × 10–14 by the Utts method. If the Dalton
(1997) study is excluded, there are 818 hits in 2,704 sessions for a hit rate of
30.3% (z = 6.36, p = 1.01 × 10–10). This suggests that, even if the early ganzfeld
and PRL autoganzfeld databases are not considered, attempts to replicate the
ganzfeld ESP effect by independent researchers are still collectively above what
would be expected by chance, with the correct target being identified about one-
third of the time on average.
Figure 8. Comparison of the overall hit rates and 95% confidence intervals
from four ganzfeld ESP meta-analyses.
The horizontal line at 25% indicates the hit rate expected by chance.
BH 94: Bem & Honorton, 1994; MW 99: Milton & Wiseman, 1999; BPB 01-A: combined result
from all studies in the Bem et al. (2001b) database; BPB 01-S & BPB 01-NS: results from the
“standard” and “non-standard” studies in Bem et al., 2001b, respectively; STDR-10: Storm et al.,
2010a; PCGANZ-ALL: combination of MW 99, BPB 01-A, and STDR-10, representing all post-
communiqué ganzfeld studies, excluding PRL.
Revisiting the Ganzfeld Debate 653
Figure 9. Comparison of the hit rates and 95% confidence intervals for 15
laboratories that have contributed to the ganzfeld ESP database.
The horizontal line at 25% indicates the hit rate expected by chance.
Above each lab is the total number of sessions contributed by that lab
to the database.
falls within the same range from one repetition of an experiment to the next”
(p. 631). This is something that can be assessed by looking at the confidence
intervals. Figure 8 shows a comparison of the hit rate confidence interval from
the Bem and Honorton (1994) PRL autoganzfeld database with the confidence
intervals of the three meta-analyses used to compile the 59-study collection
(Bem et al., 2001b, Milton & Wiseman, 1999, Storm et al., 2010a).
It can be seen that, when compared to the PRL autoganzfeld (BH 94 in
Figure 8), the three other meta-analyses each have a mean hit rate that lies
within the PRL 95% confidence interval. The same finding is evident when the
results of the three analyses are combined. When split into standard and non-
standard ganzfeld, the Bem et al. (2001b) database indicates that, as one might
predict, the mean hit rate for standard studies replicates the PRL autoganzfeld
finding, while the non-standard hit rate mean does not (although the confidence
intervals do overlap).
Looking at replication from another perspective, Figure 9 compares the
mean hit rates and confidence intervals across each of the fifteen laboratories
that have contributed to the ganzfeld database.13 While the intervals for most
of the laboratories include chance, they also have mean hit rates above what is
654 Bryan J. Williams
Discussion
The results of the basic assessment presented here are consistent with those
reported in previous meta-analyses of the ganzfeld ESP database, and seem to
indicate three main things: First, there remains a significant overall hit rate in
the series of ganzfeld studies conducted after Hyman and Honorton’s (1986)
joint communiqué.
Second, this significant finding remains apart from the results of the early
ganzfeld and PRL databases. As noted, this goes toward addressing a criticism
that could be leveled against meta-analyses that include the latter two databases
as part of a larger unified database. In addition to his finding of flaws in the
early ganzfeld database, Hyman (1994) claimed to have found subtle hints of
artifacts present in the PRL autoganzfeld database that he argues may constrain
interpretation of its results. Assuming his claims have merit, it can be argued that
inclusion of the two databases in a unified database could potentially confound
interpretation of any subsequent meta-analysis. However, in not being reliant
on either of the databases, the collection of post-communiqué studies used in
the present assessment circumvents this confound.
Third, this series of post-communiqué studies was contributed by fifteen
different laboratories, more than half of which produced a hit rate statistically
within the range of the hit rate obtained in the PRL autoganzfeld. Similarly,
the combined series shows a comparable hit rate to PRL. If the replication
issue is addressed in these terms, it would seem that, in answer to Hyman and
Honorton’s (1986:351) communiqué statement, the psi ganzfeld effect has
indeed been replicated by “a broader range of investigators” under stringent
standards.
Some consideration should be made of the potential limitations of the
present assessment. Because it was not defined in advance to be a formal meta-
analysis, the assessment had no well-defined criteria for studies to be included in
the collection used here, and no formal check of the heterogeneity of the dataset
was performed. However, it should be recognized that the studies included in the
collection came from meta-analytic databases that did have defined inclusion
criteria, and that the issue of how to properly handle a heterogeneity problem
within the ganzfeld database is still under debate (e.g., see Schmeidler & Edge,
1999:340–349, Storm, 2000). Even so, at least one formal meta-analysis that
included a test for heterogeneity has found a significant result with a trimmed,
homogeneous database (Storm et al., 2010a:475).
Revisiting the Ganzfeld Debate 655
Notes
1
The idea of how the ganzfeld might improve ESP reception is based on the assumption
that ESP is regularly overwhelmed or “drowned out” by incoming signals from the
prime sensory channels of vision and hearing. However, if these sensory channels
are reduced via the ganzfeld, then this might give the subtle ESP information a better
chance of seeping into conscious awareness.
2
The similarity between the ganzfeld state and the hypnagogic state has previously
led some researchers to suspect that the two might be related. However, the findings
reviewed by Wackermann et al. (2008) suggest that, rather than being a state of
reduced awareness like the hypnagogic state, the ganzfeld may actually be a mildly
active state, characterized in part by brain waves in the alpha range (8–12 Hz, usually
associated with a state of relaxed awareness). Some studies offer evidence to suggest
that ESP may be associated with alpha activity (see the reviews in Krippner &
Friedman, 2010), perhaps suggesting a possible connection.
3
Although the concept of telepathy traditionally assumes that the sender is
“transferring” information about the ESP target to the receiver, there is currently little
(if any) evidence to indicate that that is what is occurring. Thus, these terms are being
used here for the convenience of distinguishing between the two participants, and
should not be taken to imply that one necessarily transferred or “sent” something to
the other.
4
In addition to telepathy, a ganzfeld experiment may also be used to test for
clairvoyance; this can be done by having no sender present to view the ESP target.
Although a small number of the individual experiments in the ganzfeld database have
tested clairvoyance, the majority of them have used a telepathy design.
5
For simplicity, meta-analysis can be defined here as the statistical method of
combining the data from many separate experiments in order to examine and weigh
the evidence for a combined overall effect, rather than looking at the individual results
of each experiment alone. This type of analysis is particularly useful when evaluating
the experimental evidence for phenomena that are inherently weak or that tend to
vary across conditions, such as psi and other forms of human behavior. For useful
discussions on meta-analysis and its use in parapsychology, see Radin (1997, Chapter
4), Storm (2006), and Utts (1991, 1999b).
6
See also two books by Radin (1997:86–89, 2006:120–121) for the results of two other
unified ganzfeld meta-analyses.
7
The ganzfeld was one of the three types of ESP experiment examined in Storm et
656 Bryan J. Williams
al.’s (2010a) meta-analysis. The other two, noise reduction induced through alleged
psi-enhancing techniques (dreams, meditation, relaxation, and hypnosis) and standard
waking free response, had also shown significant overall results.
8
The issue of whether or not the early ganzfeld database does indeed contain serious
flaws remains to be one of serious controversy; it was a major point of contention in
the exchange between Milton and Wiseman (2001, 2002) and Storm and Ertel (2001,
2002) with regard to interpreting the latter’s meta-analysis, and Hyman (2010:488)
still apparently stands behind his argument of flaws (see Storm et al., 2010b:493, for a
brief counterargument and supporting references). Although some analyses have found
no significant correlation between rated study quality and effect size, one wonders
whether this would satisfy the skeptics, given the persistent controversy. Rather than
having to address it, the controversy was circumvented here by considering only the
ganzfeld studies conducted after the joint communiqué (since the focus of this paper
is on post-communiqué replication).
9
The discrepancy between the z-score obtained by the Utts method and that reported
by Bem and Honorton (1994) can be explained by the fact that the latter is associated
with the exact binomial probability for the observed number of hits compared to
chance expectation (p. 10). The same holds for the results of all the other meta-
analyses reanalyzed here.
10
In calculating the number of hits for two studies contained in the Milton–Wiseman
database, it was necessary to make approximations. For Stanford and Frank (1991),
Bem et al. (2001b:428) note that the hit rate was not reported and had to be estimated
from a z-score. The number of hits was approximated based on this hit rate and the
total number of sessions. For McDonough, Don, & Warren (1994), the approximated
number of hits was based on a composite of the hit rates obtained both by receiver
judging and by independent judging. The approximations for the two studies are noted
in the table in Appendix 1.
11
For the serial study by Parker and Westerlund (1998) and four studies summarized
by Kanthamani and Broughton (1994), Bem et al. (2001b:428) note that the hit rate
was not reported and had to be estimated from a z-score. The number of hits for these
studies was again approximated based on the estimated hit rate and the total number
of sessions. These approximations are noted in Appendix 1.
12
One of the studies (Roe & Flint, 2007) in the Storm et al. (2010a) database was
excluded because it had a hit probability of 12.5% (i.e. 1 in 8) rather than the usual
25% (1 in 4) of most other ganzfeld studies.
13
To identify these contributing laboratories, the methods sections of the individually
published studies cited in Appendix 1 were consulted in order to determine where
the ganzfeld test sessions for each study had been conducted. In some cases, this
information was also given in the study title (e.g., the Utrecht and Amsterdam series),
and/or was available in the extended Parapsychological Association Convention
abstracts for certain studies that were originally published in the annual anthology
Research in Parapsychology and later in the Journal of Parapsychology. The
numbers of sessions reported in the studies were tabulated and grouped according to
the laboratory where each study was conducted. The session numbers for all studies
conducted at a given laboratory were then summed to produce the totals for each
laboratory listed in Figure 9.
Revisiting the Ganzfeld Debate 657
Acknowledgments
The author wishes to thank Dr. Lance Storm for kindly providing a reprint of an earlier
article, and for helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper.
References
Alexander, C. H., & Broughton, R. S. (1999). CL1-ganzfeld study: A look at brain hemisphere differences
and scoring in the autoganzfeld. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological
Association 42nd Annual Convention (pp. 3–18). Durham, NC: Parapsychological Assn.
Bem, D. J., & Honorton, C. (1994). Does psi exist? Replicable evidence for an anomalous process
of information transfer. Psychological Bulletin, 115, 4–18.
Bem, D. J., Palmer, J., & Broughton, R. S. (2001a). Updating the ganzfeld database: A victim of its
own success? Journal of Parapsychology, 65, 207–218.
Bem, D. J., Palmer, J., & Broughton, R. S. (2001b). Errata. Journal of Parapsychology, 65, 427–
428.
Bierman, D. J. (1995). The Amsterdam Ganzfeld Series III and IV: Target clip emotionality, effect
sizes, and openness. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association
38th Annual Convention (pp. 27–37). Durham, NC: Parapsychological Assn.
Bierman, D. J., Bosga, D. J., Gerding, H., & Wezelman, R. (1993). Anomalous information access
in the ganzfeld: Utrecht Novice Series I and II. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The
Parapsychological Association 36th Annual Convention (pp. 192–203). Durham, NC:
Parapsychological Assn.
Braud, W. G., Wood, R., & Braud, L. W. (1975). Free-response GESP performance during an
experimental hypnagogic state induced by visual and acoustic ganzfeld techniques: A
replication and extension. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 69,
105–113.
Broughton, R. S., & Alexander, C. H. (1997). Autoganzfeld II: An attempted replication of the PRL
ganzfeld research. Journal of Parapsychology, 61, 209–226.
Dalkvist, J. (2001). The ganzfeld method: Its current status. European Journal of Parapsychology,
16, 19–22.
Dalton, K. (1994). A report on informal ganzfeld trials and comparison of receiver/sender sex
pairing: Avoiding the file drawer. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological
Association 40th Annual Convention (pp. 119–134). Durham, NC: Parapsychological Assn.
Dalton, K. (1997). Exploring the links: Creativity and psi in the ganzfeld. Proceedings of Presented
Papers: The Parapsychological Association 40th Annual Convention (pp. 119–134).
Durham, NC: Parapsychological Assn.
da Silva, F. E., Pilato, S., & Hiraoka, R. (2003). Ganzfeld vs. no Ganzfeld: An exploratory
study of the effects of Ganzfeld conditions on ESP. Proceedings of Presented Papers:
The Parapsychological Association 46th Annual Convention (pp. 31–49). Durham, NC:
Parapsychological Assn.
Goulding, A., Westerlund, J., & Parker, A. (2004). The first digital autoganzfeld study using a real-
time judging procedure. European Journal of Parapsychology, 19, 66–97.
Honorton, C. (1985). Meta-analysis of psi ganzfeld research: A response to Hyman. Journal of
Parapsychology, 49, 51–91.
Honorton, C., Berger, R. E., Varvoglis, M. P., Quant, M., Derr, P., Schechter, E. I., & Ferrari, D. C.
(1990). Psi communication in the ganzfeld: Experiments with an automated testing system
and a comparison with a meta-analysis of earlier studies. Journal of Parapsychology, 54,
99–139.
Honorton, C., & Harper, S. (1974). Psi-mediated imagery and ideation in an experimental procedure
for regulating perceptual input. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research,
68, 156–168.
658 Bryan J. Williams
Howell, D. C. (1995). Fundamental Statistics for the Behavioral Sciences (third edition). Belmont,
CA: Duxbury Press.
Hyman, R. (1985). The ganzfeld psi experiment: A critical appraisal. Journal of Parapsychology,
49, 3–49.
Hyman, R. (1994). Anomaly or artifact? Comments on Bem and Honorton. Psychological Bulletin,
115, 19–24.
Hyman, R. (2010). Meta-analysis that conceals more than it reveals: Comment on Storm et al.
(2010). Psychological Bulletin, 136, 486–490.
Hyman, R., & Honorton, C. (1986). A joint communiqué: The psi ganzfeld controversy. Journal of
Parapsychology, 50, 351–364.
Kanthamani, H., & Broughton, R. S. (1994). Institute for Parapsychology ganzfeld-ESP experiments:
The manual series. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association
37th Annual Convention (pp. 182–189). Durham, NC: Parapsychological Assn.
Kanthamani, H., & Broughton, R. S. (1996). An experiment in ganzfeld and dreams: A further
confirmation. In E. W. Cook (Ed.), Research in Parapsychology 1992 (pp. 28–31),
Lanham, MD: Scarecrow Press.
Kanthamani, H., & Khilji, A. (1990). An experiment in ganzfeld and dreams: A confirmatory
study. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association 33rd Annual
Convention (pp. 126–137). Durham, NC: Parapsychological Assn.
Kanthamani, H., Khilji, A., & Rustomji-Kerns, R. (1989). An experiment in ganzfeld and dreams
with a clairvoyance technique. In L. A. Henkel & R. E. Berger (Eds.), Research in
Parapsychology 1988 (pp. 84–88), Metuchen, NJ: Scarecrow Press.
Kanthamani, H., & Palmer, J. (1993). A ganzfeld experiment with “subliminal sending.” Journal of
Parapsychology, 57, 241–257.
Krippner, S., & Friedman, H. L. (Eds.) (2010). Mysterious Minds: The Neurobiology of Psychics,
Mediums, and Other Extraordinary People. Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger/ABC-Clio.
Lau, M. Y.-K. (2004). The PSI Phenomena: A Bayesian Approach to the Ganzfeld Procedure.
[Unpublished Master’s Thesis, University of Notre Dame, South Bend, IN]
McDonough, B. E., Don, N. S., & Warren, C. A. (1994). EEG in a ganzfeld psi task. Proceedings
of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association 37th Annual Convention (pp.
273–283). Durham, NC: Parapsychological Assn.
Milton, J. (1999). Should ganzfeld research continue to be crucial in the search for a replicable psi
effect? Part I. Discussion paper and introduction to an electronic mail discussion. Journal
of Parapsychology, 63, 309–333.
Milton, J., & Wiseman, R. (1999). Does psi exist? Lack of replication of an anomalous process of
information transfer. Psychological Bulletin, 125, 387–391.
Milton, J., & Wiseman, R. (2001). Does psi exist? Reply to Storm and Ertel (2001). Psychological
Bulletin, 127, 434–438.
Milton, J., & Wiseman, R. (2002). A response to Storm and Ertel (2002). Journal of Parapsychology,
66, 183–186.
Morris, R. L., Cunningham, S., McAlpine, S., & Taylor, R. (1993). Toward replication and extension
of autoganzfeld results. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological
Association 36th Annual Convention (pp. 177–191). Durham, NC: Parapsychological
Assn.
Morris, R. L., Dalton, K., Delanoy, D. L., & Watt, C. (1995). Comparison of the sender/no sender
condition in the ganzfeld. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological
Association 38th Annual Convention (pp. 244–259). Durham, NC: Parapsychological
Assn.
Morris, R. L., Summers, J., & Yim, S. (2003). Evidence of anomalous information transfer with
a creative population in ganzfeld stimulation. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The
Parapsychological Association 46th Annual Convention (pp. 116–131). Durham, NC:
Parapsychological Assn.
Revisiting the Ganzfeld Debate 659
Palmer, J. (2003). ESP in the ganzfeld: Analysis of a debate. Journal of Consciousness Studies,
10, 51–68.
Parker, A. (1975). Some findings relevant to the change in state hypothesis. In J. D. Morris, W. G.
Roll, & R. L. Morris (Eds.), Research in Parapsychology 1974 (pp. 40–42), Metuchen, NJ:
Scarecrow Press.
Parker, A. (2000). A review of the ganzfeld work at Gothenburg University. Journal of the Society
for Psychical Research, 64, 1–15.
Parker, A. (2010). A ganzfeld study using identical twins. Journal of the Society for Psychical
Research, 74, 118–126.
Parker, A., Frederiksen, A., & Johansson, H. (1997). Towards specifying the recipe for success in
the ganzfeld. European Journal of Parapsychology, 13, 15–27.
Parker, A., & Sjödén, B. (2008). The subliminal priming of film clips used in the ganzfeld.
Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association 51st Annual
Convention (pp. 356–359). Columbus, OH: Parapsychological Assn.
Parker, A., & Westerlund, J. (1998). Current research in giving the ganzfeld an old and new
twist. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association 41st Annual
Convention (pp. 135–142). Durham, NC: Parapsychological Assn.
Parra, A., & Villanueva, J. (2004). Are musical themes better than visual images as ESP-targets? An
experimental study using the ganzfeld technique. Australian Journal of Parapsychology,
4, 114–127.
Parra, A., & Villanueva, J. (2006). ESP under the ganzfeld, in contrast with the induction of
relaxation as a psi-conducive state. Australian Journal of Parapsychology, 6, 167–185.
Pütz, P., Gäßler, M., & Wackermann, J. (2007). An experiment with covert ganzfeld telepathy.
European Journal of Parapsychology, 22, 49–72.
Radin, D. I. (1997). The Conscious Universe: The Scientific Truth of Psychic Phenomena. San
Francisco: HarperEdge.
Radin, D. (2006). Entangled Minds: Extrasensory Experiences in a Quantum Reality. New York:
Paraview Pocket Books.
Roe, C. A., & Flint, S. (2007). A remote viewing pilot study using a ganzfeld induction technique.
Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association 50th Annual
Convention (pp. 199–202). Petaluma, CA: Parapsychological Assn.
Roe, C. A., Holt, N. J., & Simmonds, C. A. (2003). Considering the sender as a PK agent in ganzfeld
ESP studies. Journal of Parapsychology, 67, 129–145.
Roe, C. A., McKenzie, E. A., & Ali, A. N. (2001). Sender and receiver creativity scores as predictors
of performance at a ganzfeld ESP task. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 65,
107–121.
Roe, C. A., Sherwood, S. J., & Holt, N. J. (2004). Interpersonal psi: Exploring the role of the sender
in ganzfeld GESP tasks. Journal of Parapsychology, 68, 361–380.
Rosenthal, R. (1979). The “file drawer problem” and tolerance for null results. Psychological
Bulletin, 86, 638–641.
Schlitz, M., & Radin, D. (2003). Non-sensory access to information: The ganzfeld studies. In W. B.
Jonas & C. C. Crawford (Eds.), Healing, Intention and Energy Medicine: Science, Research
Methods and Clinical Implications (pp. 75–82), Edinburgh, UK: Churchill Livingstone.
Schmeidler, G. R., & Edge, H. (1999). Should ganzfeld research continue to be crucial in the search
for a replicable psi effect? Part II. Edited ganzfeld debate. Journal of Parapsychology, 63,
335–388.
Sherwood, S. J., Roe, C. A., Holt, N. J., & Wilson, S. (2005). Interpersonal psi: Exploring the role
of the experimenter and the experimental climate in a ganzfeld telepathy task. European
Journal of Parapsychology, 20, 150–172.
Simmonds-Moore, C. A., & Holt, N. J. (2007). Trait, state, and psi: A comparison of psi performance
between clusters of scorers on schizotypy in a ganzfeld and waking control condition.
Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 71, 197–215.
660 Bryan J. Williams
Smith, M. D., & Savva, L. (2008). Experimenter effects in the ganzfeld. Proceedings of Presented
Papers: The Parapsychological Association 51st Annual Convention (pp. 238–249).
Columbus, OH: Parapsychological Assn.
Stanford, R. G., & Frank, S. (1991). Prediction of ganzfeld-ESP task performance from session-based
verbal indicators of psychological function: A second study. Journal of Parapsychology,
55, 349–376.
Stevens, P. (2004). Experimental evaluation of a feedback-reinforcement model for dyadic ESP.
Journal of Parapsychology, 68, 65–92.
Storm, L. (2000). Research note: Replicable evidence of psi: A revision of Milton’s (1999) meta-
analysis of the ganzfeld databases. Journal of Parapsychology, 64, 411–416.
Storm, L. (2006). Technical Paper No. 11. Meta-analysis in parapsychology: I. The ganzfeld
domain. Australian Journal of Parapsychology, 6, 35–53.
Storm, L., & Ertel, S. (2001). Does psi exist? Comments on Milton and Wiseman’s (1999) meta-
analysis of ganzfeld research. Psychological Bulletin, 127, 424–433.
Storm, L., & Ertel, S. (2002). The ganzfeld debate continued: A response to Milton and Wiseman
(2001). Journal of Parapsychology, 66, 73–82.
Storm, L., Tressoldi, P. E., & Di Risio, L. (2010a). Meta-analysis of free-response studies, 1992–
2008: Assessing the noise reduction model in parapsychology. Psychological Bulletin, 136,
471–485.
Storm, L., Tressoldi, P. E., & Di Risio, L. (2010b). A meta-analysis with nothing to hide: Reply to
Hyman (2010). Psychological Bulletin, 136, 491–494.
Symmons, C., & Morris, R. L. (1997). Drumming at seven Hz and automated ganzfeld performance.
Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association 40th Annual
Convention (pp. 441–454). Durham, NC: Parapsychological Assn.
Utts, J. (1991). Replication and meta-analysis in parapsychology. Statistical Science, 6, 363–403.
Utts, J. M. (1999a). Seeing Through Statistics (second edition). Pacific Grove, CA: Duxbury Press.
Utts, J. (1999b). The significance of statistics in mind–matter research. Journal of Scientific
Exploration, 13, 615–638.
Utts, J., Norris, M., Suess, E., & Johnson, W. (2010). The strength of evidence versus the power
of belief: Are we all Bayesians? In C. Reading (Ed.), Data and Context in Statistics
Education: Towards an Evidence-Based Society, Voorburg, The Netherlands: International
Statistical Institute. http://www.stat.auckland.ac.nz/~iase/publications/icots8/ICOTS8_
PL2_UTTS.pdf
Wackermann, J., Pütz, P., & Allefeld, C. (2008). Ganzfeld-induced hallucinatory experience, its
phenomenology and cerebral electrophysiology. Cortex, 44, 1364–1378.
Wezelman, R., & Bierman, D. J. (1997). Process oriented ganzfeld research in Amsterdam—
Series IV B (1995): Emotionality of target material, Series V (1996) and Series VI (1997):
Judging procedure and altered states of consciousness. Proceedings of Presented Papers:
The Parapsychological Association 40th Annual Convention (pp. 477–491). Durham, NC:
Parapsychological Assn.
Wezelman, R., Gerding, J. L. F., & Verhoeven, I. (1997). Eigensender ganzfeld psi: An experiment
in practical philosophy. European Journal of Parapsychology, 13, 28–39.
Williams, C., Roe, C. A., Upchurch, I., & Lawrence, T. R. (1994). Senders and geomagnetism in
the ganzfeld. Proceedings of Presented Papers: The Parapsychological Association 37th
Annual Convention (pp. 429–438). Durham, NC: Parapsychological Assn.
Willin, M. J. (1996a). A ganzfeld experiment using musical targets. Journal of the Society for
Psychical Research, 61, 1–17.
Willin, M. J. (1996b). A ganzfeld experiment using musical targets with previous high scorers from
the general population. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 61, 103–106.
Wright, T., & Parker, A. (2003). An attempt to improve ESP scores using the real-time digital
ganzfeld technique. European Journal of Parapsychology, 18, 65–72.
Revisiting the Ganzfeld Debate 661
APPENDIX 1
The 59-Study Post-Communiqué Ganzfeld Collection
RESEARCH
EDWIN C. MAY
Laboratories for Fundamental Research, 330 Cowper Street, Palo Alto, CA 94301 USA
[email protected]
S. JAMES P. SPOTTISWOODE
9824 Charleville Blvd., Beverly Hills, CA 90212 USA
Introduction
The Global Consciousness Project was launched in 1998 in part in anticipation
of the then upcoming Y2K (i.e. date transition from the 20th to the 21st century).
It is beyond the scope of this paper to describe the historical development of
this intriguing project. Much of it can be found on the website for the project,
http://noosphere.princeton.edu; however, we will provide some of the funda-
mentals here.
663
664 Edwin C. May and S. James P. Spottiswoode
The basic idea sprang from the random number generator (RNG)1 research
which may have had its beginning with Helmut Schmidt’s seminal publica-
tion entitled “Precognition of a Quantum Process” (Schmidt, 1969). The RNG
used by Schmidt in both studies that were reported had its base in the radioac-
tive decay of the isotope Strontium-90 (i.e. often written in nuclear physics as
Sr90), which is an electron emitter mediated by the weak nuclear force. When
an electron was detected by a Geiger-Müller tube, a repeating clock that cycled
the integers 1, 2, 3, 4, 1, 2, 3, 4, . . ., etc., at one microsecond per integer was
interrupted and the resulting integer between one and four, inclusive, energized
an appropriate light on a display panel.
The participants in this study were asked to guess which of four lamps
would light after they registered their choice with a button press. After the guess
was recorded, the RNG chose which of the four lamps to light. Schmidt report-
ed significant results in both studies: Study 1: n = 63,066, z = 6.36, p =1.01 ×
10−10, effect size = 0.0253. Study 2: n = 20,000, z = 6.55, p = 1.91 × 10−11, effect
size = 0.0463.2 We note that the z-scores are relatively constant with respect to
the number of trials and the effect size scales as the square root of the ratio of
the trials. We will return to this point in the discussion section below.
The RNGs associated with the Global Consciousness Project accumulate
200 binary bits each second and report back to a central server the number of
binary ones accumulated within that second. Over time, the number of such
RNGs has grown, and as reported on the website above as of August 2009 there
are 65 of them located worldwide.
For completeness, they examined the Stouffer’s Z data for all 86,400 sec-
onds of 11 September 2001 in Eastern Daylight Time (EDT). For each Z, there
is an associated p-value, which is the integral of the normal distribution from Z
to infinity. They computed the theoretical expectation for the p-values resulting
from Zs in the range [−5.0, 5.0], and the observed values from the data of the
p-value for each Z as:
# of Zs Z g
P Value
Total # of Zs
some large tragedy/joyful event? Or when most people become aware of said
event? Are the correlative deviations of the RNGs constrained to be in real time
with the events. If not, what time window is acceptable?
It is not the intent of this paper to provide an in-depth critique of the GCP
in general nor specifically upon the details of the analytical approach; rather, it
is to demonstrate a potential source of the psi in the project.
Assumptions
In order to develop the arguments presented in this paper, the following
statements will be assumed to be true:
The network of RNGs (a.k.a. EGGs) are sound and unbiased random
number generators.
The various methods of analyses to produce z-scores are sound.
The hypothesis can change with regard to starting time and duration of
the events that are counted as part of the formal set of trials.
The summary results posted on the GCP website accurately represent
a significant effect.
Over this large a data base [PEAR’s RNG data], there arises some
quantitative statistical regularity in the PK process, epitomized by
the mean slopes of the cumulative deviations in Figs. 14 and 15 and
by the terminal values of the average deviations in Fig. 16. Traced
back to the elemental binary samples, these values imply directed
inversions from chance behavior of about one or one and a half bits
in every one thousand or, alternatively, of 0.2 or 0.3 bits per trial.
(Jahn, 1982, emphasis added)
Identifying the Source of Psi in the GCP 667
The dashed lines surrounding this line display the one standard error of the
slope. The sloping dot-dashed lines represent what the best fit line would be
under two values of the PK effect size of 0.003 for the lower one and 0.01 for
the upper one.
The elevated best fit line is significantly above the mean chance expecta-
tion for Z2 of one (z = 6.4, p = 7.77 × 10−11), and the one standard error for the
slope encompasses zero and is not significantly different from zero (t(126) =
0.173, p = 0.432).
Clearly, any asymmetric force/bit model must be rejected in that the stan-
dard error of the slope surrounds zero, the DAT prediction, and the lines repre-
senting values of the best fit under the PK hypothesis lie mostly outside the one
standard error for the fitted slope.
668 Edwin C. May and S. James P. Spottiswoode
It appears, then, that participants in these kinds of studies use their psi
ability to select out locally deviant subsequences from otherwise unperturbed
output sequences from the devices. There is a caveat to this assertion. If it turns
out that participants’ PK ability (i.e. effect size) across time and across partici-
pants dropped off as , then this DAT analysis could not distinguish between a
force-like and informational mechanism. Similarly, as we point out above, this
analysis would not be able to detect interactions that leave the mean of the par-
ent distribution exactly the same as under the null hypothesis of no psi.
Returning to Schmidt’s original study (1969), we find that the effect sizes
reported in that paper scale as , just as DAT predicts.
With regard to the results from RNGs in the Global Consciousness Project
network, there are a very limited number of possible explanations.
The horizontal black line at Z2 = 1 is mean chance expectation, and the error
bar at 48 RNGs is one standard error for the intercept at 48 RNGs for the best
fit line through the data, which is shown as a nearly horizontal line at Z2 = 1.200
± 0.058. The slope of this line is (−5.37 ± 340) × 10−5. One standard error in
the slope is shown in Figure 2 as sloping dotted lines. The one standard error
bars for the intercept are shown as the weighted mean of the number of RNGs.
An asymmetric force/bit mechanism requires a non-zero slope and the ob-
served slope is first of all negative and the slope’s one standard error easily
encompasses zero, which is required for a DAT interpretation.
A more general interpretation requires a deeper discussion. Rejecting the
force argument on the basis of a zero slope of the regression line is valid only
for forces that distort the parent distribution in asymmetrical ways; that is, all
force-like interactions that leave the mean of the parent distribution exactly
equal to zero will give rise to a zero slope in this analysis. Since it was common
in the literature and in the psi research “culture” of the 1970s and for the next
20 years or more that RNG micro-PK involved a force per bit (Jahn, 1982), our
analysis was focused on this point.
Thus we conclude that the effect from the current formal dataset for the
Global Consciousness Project appears not to include a force/bit or other kind of
asymmetric influence. That is, the network of RNGs associated with the GCP
are not physically changed asymmetrically as a result of human and or natural
events.
The original DAT formalism accounted only for direct linear forces. That
is under the PK hypothesis, the parent distribution mean shifted proportionally
to the PK effect size. This approach was reasonable in that the RNG community
collectively thought in terms of micro-PK, or a force per bit interaction. A linear
shift in the mean predicts a non-zero slope to the best-fit regression line in a
number of studies with Z2 versus number of bits resulting from a single button
push. We have come to realize that a zero slope through such data is insufficient
to reject more complex PK interactions. For example, any interaction that does
not shift the mean but changes other moments of the parent distribution would
not be detected with this analysis.
The putative interaction claimed by the GCP community arises only in
the variance of the parent distributions and thus would not lend itself to a DAT
analysis. But the RNGs in the GCP are conceptually similar to the ones used
in RNG studies (including those conducted by PEAR) in the vast literature in
which the interaction arose as a linear mean shift of the parent distribution. Why
would the GCP data be any different? Thus we call into question the GCP’s un-
derlying assumption of variance interaction. In addition, for the DAT analysis
to be invalid requires the mean shift to be nearly identically equal to zero—un-
likely to be sure.
672 Edwin C. May and S. James P. Spottiswoode
Our earlier work showed that in the non-GCP studies, there was no mean
shift of the parent distribution; rather, the sampling was biased by the operators’
precognitive ability. So we think that the DAT analysis stands for the GCP data.
Stouffer’s Z Analysis. As indicated above, the Stouffer’s Z-score for the
total dataset was 5.81. The GCP website should be further commended for in-
dicating which individual(s) brought the formal event to the GCP for analysis.
This allows for an unprecedented opportunity to determine the degree to which
any differences can be observed.
Of the 300 formal events, we found that Dr. Nelson, the founder and argu-
ably the driving force of the GCP, either singularly or among others brought
234 events to the project; whereas, all others totaled 66. The Stouffers’s Z for
the “Nelson” events was 5.91 and for the others the Stouffers’s Z was 1.26. The
Z-score for the difference is 3.29 (p = 4.97 × 10−4). Thus, there appears to be
something “special” about the events that were brought to the attention of the
GCP.
responsible for the effect. In private communication with Dr. Nelson, he sug-
gested that the reason this is true is that he knows, by means other than psi, what
events are best suited for the analysis. We find this argument to be spurious. To
realize that, say earthquakes would be an effective event while sporting events
would not, would require an independently supported model which predicted,
and hopefully explained, why these classes of event would show differing GCP
effects. No such model has been offered.
We are left then to conclude that Dr. Nelson’s DAT-like decision capacity
drives the GCP result, and it is unlikely that their statistically robust result is
due to a variation of their primary hypothesis of some global consciousness
connections to the RNG devices.
Unfortunately, this kind of psi-mediated experimenter effect is not limited
to Nelson alone. May, Paulinyi, and Vassy (2005) demonstrated in their skin
conductance study that the primary, and presumably cherished, hypothesis that
their participants’ skin conductance was reacting, in advance, to a future ran-
domly chosen startle acoustic stimulus was not supported by the data. Instead,
the results strongly suggested that the results arose because of a psi-mediated
experimenter effect enabled by DAT. Spottiswoode and May (2003) published
the protocol and pilot results of their pre-stimulus response study with acoustic
stimuli. Their still-unpublished formal results of over 5σ can be attributed di-
rectly to DAT by the experimenters.
Clearly we are not the first to notice the potential of experimenter psi in
studies. DAT just added a formal mathematical and testable method to allow
for the possibility of determining whether force-like or informational processes
better describe the observable. This kind of statistically robust experimenter
effect represents a major challenge to researchers in parapsychology. If psi-en-
abled experimenters, such as Dr. Nelson and ourselves, can achieve significant
results for their favored hypotheses by the DAT process, then discovering the
mechanism of psi through classical hypothesis testing is problematic indeed.
Notes
1
We will use this acronym for the devices rather than the popular term random event
generator which seems to us to be contrived.
2
We have recomputed the statistics and added the effect sizes based upon the reported
raw results. The z-scores agree with those reported by Schmidt as Critical Ratios.
3
It is important to emphasize that the GCP analysis uses the χ2 approach derived from
the summed Z2 scores.
4
We do not use these results to refute the significant data posted on the GCP website;
rather, we use it to show that at least in 2001 the network of RNGs appeared to func-
tion according to mean chance expectation in the aggregate.
674 Edwin C. May and S. James P. Spottiswoode
References
Bancel, P., & Nelson, R. (2008). The GCP event experiment: Design, analytical methods, results.
Journal of Scientific Exploration, 22(3), 27.
Jahn, R. G. (1982). The persistent paradox of psychic phenomena: An engineering perspective.
Proceedings of the IEEE, 70(2), 35.
May, E. C., Paulinyi, T., & Vassy, Z. (2005). Anomalous anticipatory skin conductance response to
acoustic stimuli: Experimental results and speculation upon a mechanism. The Journal of
Alternative and Complementary Medicine, 11(4), 695–702.
May, E. C., & Spottiswoode, S. P. J. (2001). Global Consciousness Project: An Independent
Analysis of the 11 September 2001 Events. Laboratories for Fundamental Research.
May, E. C., Utts, J. M., & Spottiswoode, S. J. P. (1995a). Decision augmentation theory:
Applications to the random number generator database. Journal of Scientific Exploration,
9(4), 453–488.
May, E. C., Utts, J. M., & Spottiswoode, S. J. P. (1995b). Decision augmentation theory: Toward a
model for anomalous mental phenomena. Journal of Parapsychology, 59, 195–220.
Schmidt, H. (1969). Precognition of a quantum process. Journal of Parapsychology, 33(2), 10.
Schmidt, H. (1970). PK test with electronic equipment. Journal of Parapsychology, 34(3), 7.
Spottiswoode, S. J. P., & May, E. C. (2003). Skin conductance prestimulus response: Analyses,
artifacts and a pilot study. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 17(4), 617–641.
APPENDIX 1
This table was taken direct from the Global Consciousness Project website
(http://noosphere.princeton.edu) on November 9, 2009. The preamble to this
table from the site is:
REPLY
ROGER NELSON
Global Consciousness Project
683
684 Roger Nelson
influence, though they don’t explain how this leads to the GCP. Schmidt’s test
trials were typically decisions based on 1 bit (one binary decision) and typically
the trials took a few seconds. Crucially, there was a participant with an intention
to influence that bit. There is no such participant in the GCP, and to construe
the experimenter in that role demands a convoluted argument. Nevertheless, we
encourage data-based modeling to test such notions empirically.
We also do not claim, as they assert, that global consciousness is the source
of the anomalous effects, rather, we use an operational definition of the object
of study. The hypothesis we test simply says that we expect deviations in the
data from our global network of RNGs during major world events. Formally:
the results are all reported. Whether we are looking at the time of the event or
the time when people become aware of the event isn’t relevant to the validity
of the simple hypothesis tests in the replication series. Fortunately, that ques-
tion can be empirically explored in the large GCP database, because the event
definitions typically cover a time span that includes both aspects. Similarly,
many other questions can in principle be asked of the data because we employ a
two-stage hypothesis, with a general statement that is flexible to allow explora-
tions, and formal testing via a series of rigorously defined simple hypotheses.
In practice, the event definitions are standardized based on experience, with
events in each of several categories specified using the same relative starting
point and duration.
M&S make a point of disputing an “Orwellian rewrite of history” with
regard to the use of PK or a force per bit model, but they are arguing with
someone else. The GCP does not use this language; instead, we speak in terms
of correlations. Indeed, the primary measure (the only one M&S address) is
equivalent to an average pair-wise correlation in the RNG data. As the general
hypothesis states, we are asking whether there is a deviation of this inter-node
correlation that occurs during (is correlated with) the formally selected events.
M&S wonder if the prediction is “constrained to be in real time with the events”
and of course it is. To imagine otherwise is to confuse the defined event with the
putative effect—an important distinction which, again, can be assessed in the
GCP database. For more detail on the point, see Bancel and Nelson (2008) and
Nelson and Bancel (2009).
An issue that is never discussed by M&S is the fact that all their calcula-
tions and theorizing about the sources of effects derive from a model that was
designed to address intention experiments, that is experiments where someone
is attempting to change the behavior of an RNG. However, while the GCP ex-
periment uses RNG technology, it is not about intentions to affect the behavior
of the devices. Its design is better regarded as an environmental monitor, where
the environment of interest is variations in the coherence of consciousness and
emotion across large populations. M&S might argue that the experimenter has
an intention, but it would be of a categorically different sort. As the experi-
menter of interest, I would characterize my intention in the GCP as a desire to
learn something—I’m not much interested in getting more ones or zeros. (Good
thing, too. As a participant in the PEAR REG experiments, I produced a very
small, non-significant positive effect over several years and thousands of trials.)
Moreover, the primary metric for evaluating the GCP hypothesis is not
an increase or decrease of ones and zeros, but excess correlation among the
RNGs. We predict and test for an increase in the composite spatially distributed
network variance, which is equivalent to predicting an increase (from zero)
in the average correlation between hundreds or thousands of RNG pairs. The
686 Roger Nelson
M&S model requires that the experimenter intuit or precognize the outcome
of these tests. Of course the experimenter might guess well when looking for
events that will be correlated with changes in the GCP network, but that seems
an obvious, mundane talent, assuming there are correlated changes. It can most
likely be learned, as well, with no experimenter psi required. This is a testable
proposition, and is the subject of a program we are developing to define and
teach consistent criteria for event selection which can be applied by indepen-
dent observer/analysts, including skeptics.
In the “Formal DAT Analysis” section, the authors define their procedure:
“To determine whether there is a force/bit effect in these data, we created a
scatter plot of the stated Z-score squared against the number of RNGs that were
used to compute the Z-score.” This states that the N of RNGs is used, not the
number of bits, as is usual in the DAT literature. It would have been useful for
M&S to explain the switch and show its equivalence. The quoted statement also
says they use GCP’s stated Z-scores for individual events. Thus, their proposi-
tion appears to be that the Z-score, which represents a spatially distributed vari-
ance measure (or increased pairwise correlation), is dependent on the number
of RNGs in the force per bit model, but independent of N for the DAT model.
They do not further discuss the models or their assumptions, but let’s accept
that for the moment. Taking the alternative formulation for the GCP effect since
it is easier to visualize, we can ask whether the significance of the correlation
should depend on the number of RNGs. Since increasing the number of pairs
should grow the number of correlations, leading to smaller error bars on the av-
erage correlation, the significance represented by the calculated Z-scores would
be expected to increase. Thus, the discovery of a null relationship of Z-scores
(representing the correlations) to the N of RNGs would be surprising, and in-
consistent with a physical model. We believe the data do not support the M&S
claim that the regression has zero slope.
Putting it explicitly, the bottom line drawn by M&S is premature at best:
“We are left then to conclude that Dr. Nelson’s DAT-like decision capacity
drives the GCP result, and it is unlikely that their statistically robust result is
due to a variation of their primary hypothesis of some global consciousness
connections to the RNG devices.” In a personal communication responding
to an earlier version of this paper, Peter Bancel stated that “simulations show
that it is not possible to distinguish between the models—there’s not enough
statistical power in the data.” He goes on to say that while the data may be
consistent with DAT, they are also consistent with a reasonable “force” model.
York Dobyns has tested the DAT model against data from RNG experiments
and finds it inadequate. He too points out the problem of small effects: “The
selection model assumes that the operator somehow becomes aware of the ac-
tual run outcomes and assigns intentions to suit, but I also present an argument
Reply to May and Spottiswoode on GCP 687
showing that given the small overall effect size, a standard DAT model
would produce the same statistics in the output data as the intention-
selecting model . . . ” (Dobyns, 1993, 1996, Dobyns & Nelson, 1997).
A little later in their paper, M&S recognize that their analysis doesn’t really
discriminate alternative models for the GCP data very well, but then say that
after all since the GCP does use RNGs the analysis of laboratory intention ex-
periments should still apply: “Why would the GCP data be any different? Thus
we call into question the GCP’s underlying assumption of variance interaction.”
This is a very weak argument. Perhaps M&S are confused by differing uses of
the term “variance” and perhaps their comments are directed, inappropriately,
to the variance of the individual RNGs. In any case they miss the point that,
far from being an assumption, we define the network variance as our primary
measure.
Moving to a different perspective, M&S attempt to compare the success of
Nelson vs. other predictors. They state that Nelson “brought 234 events to the
attention of the GCP,” but their count is based on the assumption that whenever
Nelson is included in the “source” column of the formal results table, he is
the source. In fact, whenever names other than Nelson are included, they can
legitimately be considered the source(s). When others suggest an event, there
is frequently a need for collaboration to establish the analysis parameters. For
example, an event will be suggested, but not the start and end times required
for a formal event specification. Because of their faulty assumption, the counts
made by M&S are wrong. In a recent categorization, May 28, 2011, I found that
a little more than half of the events had been suggested by one or more others,
sometimes including me (N = 188) and that Nelson alone had been the source
for the rest of the predictions (N = 177). Looking at the two subsets separately,
we see that Nelson’s composite Z is 5.188, agreeing pretty well with that cal-
culated by M&S on the smaller database they used, but the composite Z for the
other predictors is 3.706, not even close to the M&S calculation. The differ-
ence in composite effect size attributable to Nelson vs. others is substantial, but
not significant; the difference Z-score is 1.143. What is more important is an
obvious logical flaw in the reasoning behind this comparison of outcomes for
Nelson vs. others. Since Nelson is involved in registering, analysis, and writeup
for every event, and would presumably always have a similar interest, it is clear
ex hypothesi that this attempted comparison is artificial and invalid. It cannot
tell us whether the GCP effect is due to experimenter psi.
Beyond that, the question whether Nelson is the primary source of the ef-
fects is far more complex than M&S apparently recognize. Even if the Nelson
vs. other comparison were legitimate and the difference in composite Z were
significant, such a comparison selectively ignores other factors. In particular,
because the predictions for the GCP formal series are made a priori, they are
688 Roger Nelson
guesses. They are explicit attempts to specify, without any prior knowledge, a
period of time when the data will be found to deviate from expectation in a cer-
tain statistic. There is a history of predictions and outcomes, that is a feedback
loop that can be expected to educate the predictor as to what factors or features
of events are associated with confirmations of the predictions. Does it not seem
reasonable that Nelson, who pays more attention than anyone else to the se-
quence of successful and failed predictions, might learn something along the
way about which are the “good bets” to make? That’s pretty mundane compared
with DAT or the psychic experimenter effect postulated by M&S, but it seems
very likely to account for some considerable part of the (non-significant) advan-
tage Nelson has over other predictors. When the details are considered, there
are still other reasons why non-Nelson predictions may fail. They are often
about local and relatively small items, and many of the ones accepted for reg-
istration and analysis are about meditations, peace prayers, earth days, and the
like. I’m attuned to the ideas and ideals, and in order to learn about these events
I accept many such suggestions, but our categorization studies have shown that
they tend to have small effects.
In their discussion, M&S argue that the difference in success rate for
Nelson compared with other predictors cannot be attributed to practice and ex-
perience. “To realize that, say earthquakes would be an effective event while
sporting events would not, would require an independently supported model
which predicted, and hopefully explained, why these classes of event would
show differing GCP effects. No such model has been offered.” In fact, though it
doesn’t have the status of a formal model, categorical analysis reveals charac-
teristics which do help identify types of events that produce larger and smaller
effects (Nelson, 2008). While these are general and descriptive findings, they
are adequate to provide the sort of advantage Nelson’s predictions show, simply
as a matter of experiential learning.
I am pleased that May and Spottiswoode took the time to attempt an ex-
planation of the GCP data deviations, though it seems to me they should have
thought more deeply about various issues. They confuse or conflate various lev-
els of description, and they make unexamined assumptions. I don’t have a fun-
damental problem with an “experimenter effect” as a contributor to deviations
from expectation in psi experiments, even in the GCP data. But there are no
good reasons to think it is all or even most of the source. May and Spottiswoode
make two separate attempts to persuade us otherwise. Their DAT explanation,
even if applicable, fails because it is unable to discriminate between appropriate
models. Their attribution to Nelson as experimenter fails because their assump-
tions about who is the source of predictions is faulty. It is, however, useful to
think through these issues. They help us understand the experiment, and stimu-
late efforts to make it a better research vehicle.
Reply to May and Spottiswoode on GCP 689
References
Bancel, P., & Nelson, R. (2008). The GCP Event Experiment: Design, analytical methods, results.
Journal of Scientific Exploration, 22(3), 27.
Dobyns, Y. (1993). Selection versus influence in remote REG anomalies. Journal of Scientific
Exploration, 7(3), 259–269. Comment, RetroPsychoKinesis Project, http://www.
fourmilab.ch/rpkp/dobyns.html
Dobyns, Y. (1996). Selection versus influence revisited: New method and conclusions. Journal of
Scientific Exploration, 10(2), 253–267.
Dobyns, Y., & Nelson, R. (1997). Empirical Evidence against Decision Augmentation Theory.
Technical Note PEAR 97005, Princeton Engineering Anomalies Research, Princeton
University, School of Engineering/Applied Science.
Nelson, R. (1997). Multiple Field REG/RNG Recordings During a Global Event, Parts I & II.
http://noosphere.princeton.edu/ejap/gaiamind/1997_2a.html [Originally published in The
Electronic Journal of Parapsychology, eJAP]
Nelson, R. (2008). The Emotional Nature of Global Consciousness. Proceedings of the Bial
Foundation 7th Symposium, Behind and Beyond the Brain; Porto, Portugal; 26–29 March
2008.
Nelson, R., & Bancel, P. (2009). Response to a letter from Helmut Schmidt. Journal of Scientific
Exploration, 23(4), 510–516.
Nelson, R. & Bancel, P. (2011). Effects of mass consciousness: Changes in random data during
global events. Explore: The Journal of Science & Healing, 7(6), 373–383.
Nelson, R., Boesch, H., Boller, E., Dobyns, Y., Houtkooper, J., Lettieri, A., Radin, D., Russek, L.,
Schwartz, G., & Wesch, J. (1998). Global Resonance of Consciousness: Princess Diana
and Mother Teresa. http://noosphere.princeton.edu/ejap/diana/1998_1.html [Originally
published in The Electronic Journal of Parapsychology, eJAP]
Nelson, R., Bradish, G., Dobyns, Y., Dunne, B., & Jahn, R. (1996). FieldREG anomalies in group
situations. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 10(1), 111–141.
Nelson, R., Jahn, R., Dunne, B., Dobyns, Y., & Bradish, G. (1998). FieldREG II: Consciousness
field effects: Replications and explorations. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 12(3), 425–
454.
Journal of Scientific Exploration, Vol. 25, No. 4, pp. 690–694, 2011 0892-3310/11
REPLY
PETER BANCEL
selection procedure. In such a case, one cannot rely on the formal result to
make inferences about the RNG behavior. According to M&S, the freedom of
choice in selecting the events and their start/end times, in conjunction with psi-
mediated information about the resulting test statistics, sets up a satisfactory
explanation of the experiment. For M&S, the experimental result is merely the
consequence of fortuitous selection of naturally occurring data deviations.
M&S go a step further by using a DAT model to test their idea against
the GCP data. DAT derives from the well-known principle whereby the ratio
of signal-to-noise in a sample (i.e. the Z-score of a measurement) increases as
DF1/2 where DF (“degrees of freedom”) is the sample size. M&S distinguish
between degrees of freedom which are relevant for DAT—those which
designate an elemental instance of decision concerning what data to include in
a measurement—and irrelevant “internal” degrees of freedom which have no
inherent relevance for the decision process. In the GCP event experiment, the
elemental DAT degree of freedom is the selection of a data block representing
an event. In the DAT picture, a constant effect size, ZDAT, is attributed to each
instance of event selection. ZDAT is independent of all internal degrees of
freedom, such as the number of seconds or RNGs in the data block. It is thus
evident that any physical model which does depend on the internal degrees of
freedom can be distinguished from DAT models by testing for an association
between DFInternal and Z. If the DAT model holds, no association will be found,
whereas a physical model will yield a positive association between DFInternal
and measured values of Z. A standard way to test for association is by ordinary
least squares regression (OLS). M&S chose to do an OLS for Z2 versus N, the
number of RNGs in the network during the event. Their OLS yields a regression
slope within a standard error of zero, and they conclude that this supports a
DAT interpretation of the GCP.
This conclusion might have some weight if their regression analysis were
done correctly. Unfortunately, M&S make several errors which are fatal to their
argument. Here, I briefly sketch their errors and show that a proper test leads to
the opposite conclusion from M&S: There is a clear association between Z2 and
DFInternal and reasonably strong grounds for rejecting DAT in favor of a physical
model.
I discuss four separate errors, in order of increasing consequence. The first
two have negligible impact, but the others invalidate M&S’s calculations and
reverse the conclusions one must draw from the DAT analysis.
M&S use values for the explanatory variables, N, that are listed on the GCP
website. The website values are only approximate and should be replaced
692 Peter Bancel
with exact values which account for null data trials. In addition, it would be
preferable to calculate exact Z-scores for events 310–313, rather than use the
estimates M&S list in their table.
M&S take the Z2 as response variables. This choice yields non-normal fit
residuals which impact the reliability of the usual OLS estimators for the fit
parameter standard errors. Reliable errors for the regression slope and intercept
parameters need to be determined by simulation. A 20,000-iteration Monte
Carlo calculation (in which I use the correct values of N and Z) yields standard
errors of the slope and intercept of 0.0061 and 0.303, respectively. These are
substantially larger than the M&S values of 0.0034 and 0.058.
The most serious error M&S make is in their choice of regressor. In Bancel
and Nelson (2008), we show in considerable detail that the measured effect can
be traced to correlations between pairs of RNGs. If the RNG output is written
as z(i,t) where i labels the RNGs and t is the time in seconds, then the average
correlation, ξ, is simply
The sum is over all unique RNG pairs for each second so that DFGCP
= T(N2 − N)/2, where T is the number of seconds during the event.
The correlations ξ distribute normally (to high approximation, under the
central limit theorem), and the event Z-scores are given as Z = ξ √ DFGCP. The
appropriate regressor is thus DFGCP and not N as M&S propose. Inappropriately
selecting a DF of N introduces a large dispersion in the regressor variable,
DFGCP. This leads to a partial randomization of the regressor (see Figure 1) and
all but guarantees that the regression test will accept the DAT hypothesis.
To conclude, I show that the DAT model is rejected when a robust estimator
and the appropriate regressor are used. I employ the Theil-Sen estimator which
has a considerably higher power than OLS for the Z2 vs. DF regression. The
TSe slope estimate is taken as the median slope of all pairs of data points.
Confidence intervals can be determined by bootstrap analysis, but a hypothesis
test of the DAT model requires empirical determination of the TSe distribution
by Monte Carlo simulation. A one-tailed Monte Carlo test of DAT yields a
P-value of 0.024. Using the recommended dataset which excludes early events,
the P-value falls to 0.0053. These correspond to Z-scores of 1.98 and 2.56,
and indicate that the GCP data reject the DAT model with moderately high
confidence. Although it is beyond the scope of this Reply, one can show that
a similar procedure which tests the alternate hypothesis of a physical effect
accepts that hypothesis as being consistent with the data (in preparation by
Bancel).
In summary, M&S highlight a fundamental interpretational issue of the
GCP: whether the measured effect has its source in a physical perturbation of
the network RNGs. The issue can be addressed by testing for such structure
in the event data as would be predicted by a physical effect. The association
of Z and DFGCP is one example of this approach, and the analysis presented
here supports the GCP proposal. However, the issue is sufficiently important
that further, independent tests are needed before a convincing conclusion can
be drawn (Nelson & Bancel, 2011). A number of independent tests have been
identified, and a report is currently in preparation by Bancel.
Acknowledgements
My thanks to Roger Nelson for many useful discussions. This work is supported in part
by a grant from the Parapsychological Association. I would like to dedicate this Reply to
the memory of Helmut Schmidt and his pioneering contributions to psi research.
References
Bancel, P., & Nelson, R. (2008). The GCP Event Experiment: Design, analytical methods, results.
Journal of Scientific Exploration, 22(3), 309–333.
Nelson, R., & Bancel, P. (2011). Effects of mass consciousness: Changes in random data during
global events. Explore: The Journal of Science & Healing, 7(6), 373–383.
Journal of Scientific Exploration, Vol. 25, No. 4, pp. 695–698, 2011 0892-3310/11
RESPONSE
EDWIN C. MAY
Laboratories for Fundamental Research, 330 Cowper Street, Palo Alto, CA 94301 USA
[email protected]
S. JAMES P. SPOTTISWOODE
9824 Charleville Blvd., Beverly Hills, CA 90212 USA
[email protected]
First of all we want to express our thanks to the Journal for allowing us to
have the “last” word. We put last in quotes because the very good news about
this exchange is that the discussion will undoubtedly continue. While it might
be possible to respond point by point to Nelson and Bancel’s remarks, we
prefer to focus on serious points of disagreement. We will comment upon their
responses separately. Before we begin, it is important to recognize that while
our interpretations differ, there are large areas of overlap in our thinking.
695
696 Edwin C. May and S. James P. Spottiswoode
One lesson we have learned from our exchange is that our early thinking
on Decision Augmentation Theory (DAT) was very limited mainly because of
the RNG zeitgeist of the day of a force per bit model, as we document in our
article in this issue of this Journal. The DAT analysis shown is completely
insensitive to any forces that may be symmetrical about zero or in cases where
there is no force at all. However, the main idea behind DAT is equivalent to
experimenter psi; that is, experimenters (or agents acting like experimenters)
make psi-mediated choices to affect the outcome. Of course, this is not a new
idea (Stanford, Zenhausern, Taylor, & Dwyer, 1975).
We believe Nelson is splitting hairs with regard to their published hypothesis
with regard to the GCP when he claims “We also do not claim, as they [May &
Spottiswoode] assert, that global consciousness is the source of the anomalous
effects, rather, we use an operational definition of the object of study.” In our
rebuttal, we offer two points taken from Bancel and Nelson (2008) and the GCP
website, respectively:
To us, the paragraph from the GCP website seems to be the quintessential
definition of global consciousness.
Nelson implies that we fail to understand the GCP hypothesis (to which
we plead guilty) because we are concerned that the “time” of the event is
vague. From our perspective this project has been in a continuing state of
exploration and we think this is the case, at least in part, because addressing
whether the people who are actually involved in, say a natural disaster, or the
people worldwide who later see the disaster on television are somehow related
to the variance of the networks RNGs is the goal of the GCP project. Or even
peaks in the variance that occur before the event which requires a precognitive
description. It seems to us these considerations are not trivial.
This brings us to our major criticism of Nelson’s defense. Claiming that
the GCP is only about correlations does not absolve him of a responsibility to
Response to Nelson and Bancel Replies 697
untangle the pressing correlation issues we raised in our original paper. Without
belaboring the point, we quote from our paper:
As we all have learned in our statistics courses, correlation does not necessar-
ily imply a causal relationship between the variables. Hypothesis two above
[correlation hypothesis] also bifurcates. Either human/natural events magical-
ly happen on the average only during times of locally deviant, but expected,
excursions of the RNGs or vice versa. Even though there does not have to be
a causal relation for this correlation to arise, we are obligated to search for a
third (or more) variable(s) that give rise to the correlation. In many cases, an
external (to the primary correlative variables) variable is difficult or impos-
sible to identify.
are selected by a blind procedure and thus, by implication, are not subjected to
DAT. This is simply factually incorrect and flies in the face of most all of the psi
literature in which psi happens under double blind and sometimes even more
layers of blindness. The event selector could be a major psi contributor to the
successful outcome of the GCP.
Conclusion
If Nelson is accurate in his description of the meaning of the “Hypothesis
Source,” then clearly there is more work to be done to definitively identify the
source of the psi in the GCP. However, it is clear to us that global consciousness
however defined is not a contributor to the observables. We look forward to
working with Bancel with regard to extending our DAT analysis by incorporating
his correlational variable insight.
There is, however, one simple thing that can be done from this point forward
that would go a long way to answer the questions raised in our debate. Rather
than posting the GCP data for every second, post only, say, the even-numbered
seconds. Then data snoopers and data-mining programs can be unleashed with
impunity to isolate events that show significant correlations. Among the things
we have stipulated is the excellence of the RNG hardware, which means the
autocorrelation of non-zero lags is statistically zero. In simple language this
means that the data from second to second are independent of each other under
the null hypothesis of no effects. When the data mining produces a significant
effect on the even-numbered seconds, it must also be seen nearly exactly on the
odd-numbered seconds which now act as a formal “within session” control.2
Any causal or correlational effects should replicate on a second-by-second
basis.
Notes
1
Private communication.
2
We thank Professor Richard Broughton for first suggesting this to us.
References
Bancel, P., & Nelson, R. D. (2008). The GCP Event Experiment: Design, analytical methods,
results. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 22(3), 259–269.
Nelson, R. D., Bradish, G. J., Dobyns, Y. H., Dunne, B. J., & Jahn, R. G. (1996). FieldREG
anomalies in group situations. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 10(1), 111–141.
Stanford, R. G., Zenhausern, R., Taylor, A., & Dwyer, M. A. (1975). Psychokinesis as psi-mediated
instrumental response. Journal of American Society for Psychical Research, 69, 127–133.
Varvoglis, M. P., & McCarthy, D. (1986). Conscious-purposive focus and PK: RNG activity in
relation to awareness, task-orientation, and feedback. Journal of the American Society for
Psychical Research, 80, 1–20.
Journal of Scientific Exploration, Vol. 25, No. 4, pp. 699–720, 2011 0892-3310/11
RESEARCH
KENNETH DRINKWATER
Manchester Metropolitan University
ANDREW PARKER
Manchester Metropolitan University
Introduction
The origin, nature, and prevalence of extra-terrestrial beliefs have been relatively
under-researched within psychology (Swami, Furnham, Haubner, Stieger, &
Voracek, 2009, Swami, Pietschnig, Stieger, & Voracek, 2010b). This is surprising
because such beliefs have been recorded throughout human history (Crowe,
699
700 Neil Dagnall, Kenneth Drinkwater, & Andrew Parker
1986) and continue to prevail within modern society (Clarke, 1991, Zullino,
Verdu, Khazaal, & Borgeat, 2006). Indeed, recent work indicates that a significant
proportion of the population believe that extra-terrestrial life exists and that UFOs
are evidence of alien life (Biasco & Nunn, 2000, Chequers, Joseph, & Diduca,
1997, Gallup, 1997, Patry & Pelletier, 2001, Swami et al., 2009).
Pertinently, since the 1960s, the development of contemporary alien research
has coincided with an observed growth in extra-terrestrial beliefs (Gallup &
Newport, 1991, Genta, 2007), which has been accompanied by an increase in
reported accounts of UFO and alien-related experiences (cf., French, 2001,
French, Santomauro, Hamilton, Fox, & Thalbourne, 2008, Swami et al., 2009).
French et al. (2008) estimate that worldwide, the number of people claiming to
have conscious memories of alien abduction is likely to run into at least several
thousands. Further studies have suggested this figure may be higher, between
2% (Appelle, 1995/1996, Hopkins, Jacobs, & Westrum, 1992) and 5%–6% of
the population (Jacobs, 1992). While these figures seem unusually high, even
more conservative measures, such as consideration of reported cases, have
identified significant numbers of incidents. Notably, Bullard’s (1994) survey
of 13 investigators yielded 1,700 reports (Appelle, 1995/1996). Collectively,
these findings indicate that extra-terrestrial beliefs and experiences represent
important phenomena, which merit further study and clarification.
Historically, the study of extra-terrestrial beliefs has been hindered by the
fact that such beliefs have been frequently subsumed within measures of general
paranormal belief (e.g., the Revised Paranormal Belief Scale [R-PBS], Tobacyk,
1988). Swami et al. (2009) contend that this has occurred because extra-
terrestrial beliefs are premised upon notions and theories, which transcend the
explanatory power of mainstream science (Gray, 1991). Certainly, the scientific
community has yet to accept evidence of extra-terrestrial life as authentic and
has failed to agree on a definitive position on the existence of other life forms.
It is worth noting that the merits of including extra-terrestrial beliefs within
paranormal measures is much debated, and hence not all paranormal scales
make reference to extra-terrestrial beliefs (e.g., Australian Sheep Goat Scale,
Thalbourne, 1995a, Thalbourne & Delin, 1993).
Where extra-terrestrial beliefs have been incorporated into paranormal
belief measures, they have received a partial, limited treatment. For instance,
the R-PBS (Tobacyk, 1988) contains a three-item Extraordinary Life Form
subscale, which assesses the existence of extra-terrestrial life alongside other
extraordinary life forms (i.e. the abominable snowman of Tibet and the Loch
Ness Monster). The use of a single item to measure extra-terrestrial beliefs is
problematic because there is evidence to suggest that extra-terrestrial beliefs
are multidimensional (Dagnall, Munley, Parker, & Drinkwater, 2010a, Dagnall,
Parker, Munley, & Drinkwater, 2010, Swami et al., 2009).
Alien Visitation, Extra-Terrestrial Life, & Paranormal Beliefs 701
extra-terrestrial life beliefs are more plausible than UFO-related beliefs. Clearly,
their distinction between belief in extra-terrestrial life and UFO-related beliefs
is a useful theoretical dichotomy that requires further explanation.
Noting this, Dagnall, Munley, Parker, and Drinkwater (2010a) explored
whether alien-related beliefs (life on other planets and alien visitations) were
related to extraordinary life forms, as suggested by the R-PBS, and if such beliefs
could be considered to represent facets of paranormal belief per se (Diaz-Vilela
& Alvarez-Gonzalez, 2004). This was achieved by identifying commonly used
measures of paranormal belief (R-PBS, Paranormal Short Inventory, etc.) and
related phenomena (e.g., scales assessing belief in extra-terrestrial life and UFO-
related beliefs, Chequers et al., 1997; and Poltergeists and Hauntings, Kumar &
Pekala, 2001). The latter scales provided only a limited range of related beliefs
and consequently the authors generated additional items by exploring reports of
alien-related and haunting experiences.
The new and original scale items were combined to produce a 124-item
composite measure. This was completed by 1,481 respondents and the data
were then analyzed using exploratory factor analysis (principal components
analysis), and a nine-factor structure emerged: Hauntings, Other Life,
Superstition, Religious Belief, Alien Visitation, Extrasensory Perception (ESP),
Psychokinesis (PK), Astrology, and Witchcraft. Consistent with Chequers et
al. (1997), other life (extra-terrestrial life) and Alien Visitation (UFO-related
beliefs) were identified as separate factors; both were coherent, possessed face
validity, and demonstrated excellent internal reliability.
Dagnall, Munley, Parker, and Drinkwater (2010a) in a followup study further
explored the relationships among extra-terrestrial life, UFO-related beliefs, and
paranormal belief. They found that despite being positively correlated with
each other UFO-related beliefs were more highly correlated with paranormal
belief, as measured by the R-PBS and ASGS, than belief in extra-terrestrial life;
partial correlation, controlling for the overlap between belief in extra-terrestrial
life and UFO-related beliefs, found only the more extreme UFO-related beliefs
to be associated with paranormal belief. These findings suggest that belief in
extra-terrestrial life is multifactorial and that further research is required to
identify the structure of such beliefs.
Swami et al. (2009) conducted a study examining the structure of beliefs
about extra-terrestrial life. In order to do this they recruited 577 respondents (320
participants from Austria and 257 participants from Britain) and asked them to
complete their Extra-terrestrial Beliefs Scale (EBS). The EBS is a 37-item scale
measuring belief in evidence of extra-terrestrial life, governmental knowledge
of the existence of extra-terrestrial life, scientific search for extra-terrestrial life,
and the existence of UFOs. In addition to this, participants provided information
on sex, age, ethnicity, religion, marital status, highest educational qualification,
Alien Visitation, Extra-Terrestrial Life, & Paranormal Beliefs 703
Methods
Materials and Procedure
Participants were asked to complete: items assessing belief in extra-terrestrial
life and alien visitation (Dagnall, Munley, Parker, & Drinkwater, 2010a, Swami
et al., 2009), the Revised Paranormal Belief Scale (R-PBS, Tobacyk, 1988,
Tobacyk, 2004, Tobacyk & Milford, 1983), and the Australian Sheep–Goat Scale
(ASGS, Thalbourne, 1995a, Thalbourne & Delin, 1993). Presentation order
across questionnaires was counterbalanced to prevent order effects. The current
questionnaire measures have been previously psychometrically validated:
Belief in extra-terrestrial life and alien visitation (Dagnall, Parker,
Munley, & Drinkwater, 2010, Dagnall, Munley, Parker, & Drinkwater, 2010a,
Swami et al., 2009). Belief in extra-terrestrial life and alien visitation was
assessed via a 37-composite-item measure; 23 items from Swami et al. (2009)
and 14 items from Dagnall, Munley, Parker, & Drinkwater (2010a). The Swami
et al. (2009) items represented three factors: alien visitation and coverup (e.g.,
“The government of this country is covering up the existence of extra-terrestrial
life”), 11 questions; scientific search (e.g., “The search for extra-terrestrial life
is a serious and important scientific endeavour”), 6 questions; and general
beliefs (e.g., “Just because we have no evidence of extra-terrestrial life does not
mean that such life does not exist”), 6 questions. The Dagnall, Munley, Parker,
& Drinkwater (2010a) items represent two factors: extra-terrestrial life (e.g.,
“Somewhere in the universe there are other forms of life”), 6 questions; and
UFO-related beliefs (e.g., “Aliens are abducting human beings)”, 8 questions.
In order to facilitate direct comparison with Swami et al. (2009), all questions
employed a 7-point Likert-type scale (where 1 was disagree, 4 was neither agree
nor disagree, and 7 was agree). Previously, both item sets have been found
to be conceptually coherent and possess good to excellent internal reliability
(Cronbach’s alpha, α). Swami et al. (2009): alien visitation and coverup, α =
.90; scientific search, α = .82; and general beliefs, α = .75. Dagnall, Munley,
Parker, & Drinkwater (2010a): belief in extra-terrestrial-life, α = .91; and UFO-
related beliefs, α = .95.
Revised Paranormal Belief Scale (R-PBS) (Tobacyk, 1988, Tobacyk,
2004, Tobacyk & Milford, 1983). The R-PBS is an amended form of the
Paranormal Belief Scale developed by Tobacyk and Milford (1983) and is the
most frequently used self-report measure of paranormal belief (Irwin, 2004).
It contains 26 items assessing seven facets of paranormal belief: traditional
religious belief, psi, witchcraft, superstition, spiritualism, extraordinary life
forms, and precognition. The R-PBS can be totalled to produce overall scores,
Alien Visitation, Extra-Terrestrial Life, & Paranormal Beliefs 705
or subscores can be calculated for each of the facets. However, recent attempts
to refine/purify the scale to eliminate differential item functioning (arising from
age and gender bias) and subsequent factor analysis has identified an alternative
two-factor solution (Lange, Irwin, & Houran, 2000). This is composed of factors
assessing New Age Philosophy (NAP) and Traditional Paranormal Belief
(TPB): NAP measures belief in psi, reincarnation, altered states, and astrology
(11 items), while TPB assesses belief in concepts such as the devil, witchcraft,
and heaven and hell (5 items) (Irwin, 2004). R-PBS items are presented as
statements (e.g., “I believe in God”), and respondents record answers on a
Likert scale ranging from 1 (strongly disagree) to 7 (strongly agree). Higher
scores on the scale/sub-scale indicate higher paranormal belief.
The current paper, in line with Irwin (2004) and recent convention will
employ the two-factor solution suggested by Lange, Irwin, & Houran (2000).
This is achieved by recoding the scores; 1–7 is converted to 0–6, and the rasch
scaling procedure is used (Andrich, 1988). Rasch scaling produces scores
ranging from 6.85 to 47.72 on NAP and 11.16 to 43.24 on TPB. While the
factorial structure of the R-PBS has frequently been debated (Lawrence, 1995a,
1995b, Lawrence, Roe, & Williams, 1997, Tobacyk, 1995a, 1995b, Tobacyk
& Thomas, 1997), the scale overall has been found to be a conceptually and
psychometrically satisfactory measure (Tobacyk, 2004). Particularly, the
R-PBS has been found to possess adequate validity (Tobacyk, 1995a, 1995b,
2004) and good test–retest reliability (Tobayck, 2004).
Australian Sheep–Goat Scale (Thalbourne, 1995b, Thalbourne & Delin,
1993). The ASGS measures belief in, and alleged experience of, three core
concepts of parapsychology (life after death, psychokinesis, and extrasensory
perception). These concepts, while independent, have been found to be highly
correlated. Hence, the ASGS is generally considered to measure belief in psychic
ability (Thalbourne, 1995a, 1995b, Thalbourne & Delin, 1993, Thalbourne,
Dunbar, & Delin, 1995, Wiseman & Watt, 2006). The ASGS is composed of
18 items, and the response options are False (scored as zero), “?” (Don’t know:
scored as 1 point), and True (scored as 2 points). The scale has a range from 0
to 36, higher scores indicating higher levels of belief and experience. Recent
attempts to rasch scale the ASGS (Lange & Thalbourne, 2002) suggest that
scoring should be limited to 16 rather than 18 items. Across a range of studies
the ASGS has demonstrated good reliability and validity (Thalbourne, 1995a,
Thalbourne & Delin, 1993).
Respondents
527 respondents completed the questionnaire. Ages ranged 16–75 years, with
a mean of 25.27, a standard deviation of 10.96, and a median of 20 (lower
quartile 19 and upper quartile 27); 73% female and 27% male. Respondents
706 Neil Dagnall, Kenneth Drinkwater, & Andrew Parker
Procedure
All participants were informed that the questionnaire measure was concerned
with the measurement of belief. They were told that their responses would
be anonymous and that they should ensure that all items were completed.
Participants were instructed that there was no time limit and that they should
work through the questions at their own pace.
Results
Exploration of the Empirical Structure of the Questionnaire
In line with Swami et al. (2009) participants’ questionnaire responses were
subjected to principal components analysis (PCA) with orthogonal (varimax)
rotation. Prior to conducting PCA, the correctness of the data for factor
analysis was assessed. The data was found to be suitable for PCA: The Kaiser–
Mayer–Oklin value (.956) exceeded the recommended value of .6 (Kaiser,
1970, 1974); Bartlett’s Test of Sphericity (Bartlett, 1954) was significant (χ2
= 12797.746, df = 561, p < .001), and the correlation matrix contained many
coefficients of .3 or above. An item-loading cut-off value of .45 was selected;
Comrey and Lee (1992) suggest that item loadings above this value provide a
good measure of a factor.
The initial PCA resulted in a solution comprising six factors with
eigenvalues of greater than 1, accounting for 64% of the total variance. Parallel
analysis was conducted using the MonteCarlo PCA (Watkins, 2000). This
indicated that Factors 4, 5, and 6 should not be retained in the final analysis.
Reliability analysis, in the form of Cronbach’s alpha (α), revealed that Factor
1 (α = .95) and Factor 2 (α = .92) possessed excellent internal reliability and
Factor 3 (α = .80) good internal reliability.
Following the initial PCA and the subsequent reliability analysis, a second
PCA was undertaken. This included the three factors which produced an
acceptable internal reliability coefficient (α ≥ .7) and used a reduced set of 25
items (see Table 1).1
Alien Visitation, Extra-Terrestrial Life, & Paranormal Beliefs 707
TABLE 1
Scale Items with Mean Scores and
Standard Deviations (SD) for UK Participants
GENDER COMBINED
WOMEN MEN TOTAL
Item Mean SD Mean SD Mean SD
1 Given the size and age of the universe, it is very 4.80 1.64 5.50 1.60 4.99 1.66
likely that extra-terrestrial life must exist.
6 If Earth-like planets exist in the universe, then 4.82 1.41 4.94 1.71 4.85 1.50
it is likely that Earth-like organisms will have
evolved on those planets.
8 Intelligent extra-terrestrial life has visited 3.16 1.58 3.26 1.73 3.19 1.62
Earth.
11 The search for extra-terrestrial life is a serious 4.41 1.55 4.81 1.75 4.52 1.61
and important endeavour.
15 Just because we have no evidence of 5.51 1.55 5.70 1.58 5.56 1.56
extraterrestrial life does not mean that such life
does not exist.
18 Governments should direct more funding to the 2.98 1.66 3.36 1.69 3.08 1.67
scientific search for extra-terrestrial life.
21R The search for extra-terrestrial life is a waste of 4.18 1.77 4.61 1.83 4.30 1.79
time and money.
23R Earth is the only planet in the universe that 4.84 1.62 5.36 1.63 4.98 1.64
harbours life.
26R The search for extra-terrestrial life is a 4.38 1.58 4.52 1.80 4.42 1.64
pseudoscience (not proper science).
28 Extra-terrestrial creatures visited Earth in the 3.38 1.39 3.21 1.66 3.33 1.47
distant past or at the dawn of civilization.
38 Somewhere in the universe there are other 4.88 1.55 5.30 1.68 4.99 1.60
forms of life.
39 People have been taken on board alien 2.65 1.50 2.72 1.64 2.67 1.54
spaceships.
40R The Earth is the only planet in the universe that 4.78 1.67 5.21 1.67 4.90 1.68
supports life.
41 Aliens are abducting human beings. 2.35 1.42 2.36 1.48 2.35 1.44
42R The only intelligent life exists on earth. 4.46 1.67 4.80 1.73 4.55 1.69
43 Aliens have implanted objects into people. 2.28 1.38 2.31 1.41 2.29 1.39
44 There is life on other planets. 4.79 1.49 5.31 1.58 4.93 1.53
45 Alien spaceships regularly visit Earth. 2.57 1.52 2.57 1.56 2.57 1.53
46R There is no such thing as extra-terrestrial life. 4.68 1.74 5.22 1.75 4.83 1.76
47 Alien spaceships have crash-landed on Earth. 2.64 1.53 2.86 1.71 2.70 1.58
48 Intelligent life exists beyond our universe. 4.49 1.57 4.87 1.66 4.59 1.60
49 Alien intelligence is responsible for some UFO 3.20 1.59 3.14 1.68 3.18 1.62
sightings.
50 Extra-terrestrials have visited Earth throughout 3.25 1.69 3.22 1.75 3.24 1.71
history.
51 Unidentified Flying Objects suggest that 3.28 1.63 3.18 1.67 3.25 1.64
some kind of extra-terrestrial life form has
approached the surface of the Earth.
708 Neil Dagnall, Kenneth Drinkwater, & Andrew Parker
TABLE 2
Principal Component Loadings for Scale Items
Gender Differences
In order to allow comparisons between the three factor scores, the mean was
calculated for each factor. In order to test for gender differences on factor
scores, a multivariate analysis of covariance was conducted (MANCOVA). A
significant main effect was found for gender, F(3, 523) = 5.53, p = .001, Wilk’s
Lambda =.97, partial eta-squared = .031.2 Analysis of each alien/extra-terrestrial
belief factor revealed that: males (M = 5.22, SD = 1.18) scored higher than
females (M = 4.80, SD = 1.24) on Belief in the Existence of Extra-Terrestrial
Life, F(1, 525) = 12.08, p = .001, partial eta-squared = .022; and males (M =
4.33, SD = 1.39) scored higher than females (M = 3.99, SD = 1.30) on Search
for Extra-Terrestrial Life, F(1, 525) = 6.89, p = .009, partial eta-squared = .013.
No difference was found between males and females on Alien Visitation, F(1,
525) = .005, p > .05, partial eta-squared = .00 (see Table 3).
TABLE 3
Means, Standard Deviations, & Reliability Statistics for Factor Scores
1 Alien Visitation 2.87 1.27 .95 2.88 1.38 .96 2.88 1.30 .95
2 Existence of Extra- 4.80 1.24 .93 5.22 1.18 .90 4.92 1.24 .92
Terrestrial Life
3 Search for Extra- 3.99 1.30 .80 4.33 1.39 .79 4.08 1.33 .80
Terrestrial Life
710 Neil Dagnall, Kenneth Drinkwater, & Andrew Parker
TABLE 4
Means, Standard Deviations, and Reliability Statistics
for Paranormal Belief Measures
TABLE 5
Correlations: Alien Visitation, Extra-Terrestrial, and Paranormal Belief
1 2 3 4 5 6
1 Alien Visitation
2 Belief in ET .41**
3 Search for ET .54** .58**
4 NAP .56** .15** .25**
5 TPB .48** .07 .15** .68**
6 ASGS .49** .24** .25** .65** .53**
* p < .05; ** p < .01 (all probabilities one-tailed).
Alien Visitation, Extra-Terrestrial Life, & Paranormal Beliefs 711
TABLE 6
Differences in Correlation Magnitude between Belief in Alien/Extra-
Terrestrial Life Factors and Measures of Paranormal Belief
TABLE 7
Partial Correlations: Belief in the Existence of ET,
Search for ET, and Paranormal Belief Controlling for Alien Visitation
1 2 3 4
1 Belief in ET
2 Search for ET .47**
3 NAP −.10* −.08*
4 TPB −.16** −.15** .56**
* p < .05; **; p < 0.1 (all probabilities one-tailed).
TABLE 8
Partial Correlations: Alien Visitation, Search for ET,
and Paranormal Belief Controlling for Belief in the Existence of ET
1 2 3 4
1 Alien Visitation
2 Search for ET .40**
3 NAP .55** .19**
4 TPB .50** .14** .68**
* p < .05; ** p < 0.1 (all probabilities one-tailed).
TABLE 9
Partial Correlations: Alien Visitation, Belief in the Existence of ET,
and Paranormal Belief Controlling for Search for ET
1 2 3 4
1 Alien Visitation
2 Belief in ET .15**
3 NAP .52** .02
4 TPB .48** −.03 .67**
* p < .05; ** p < 0.1 (all probabilities one-tailed).
Alien Visitation, Extra-Terrestrial Life, & Paranormal Beliefs 713
Discussion
The nature and structure of alien/extra-terrestrial beliefs has been relatively
under-researched within psychology (Swami et al., 2009, Swami, Pietschnig,
Stieger, & Voracek, 2010b). Hence, the current paper was designed to extend
research by examining and reconciling theoretical differences between important
recent work (cf., Dagnall, Parker, Munley, & Drinkwater, 2010, Dagnall,
Munley, Parker, & Drinkwater, 2010a, and Swami et al., 2009). Particularly,
debate has arisen around the nature and number of alien/extra-terrestrial belief
factors: Dagnall, Parker, Munley, and Drinkwater (2010) and Dagnall, Munley,
Parker, and Drinkwater (2010a) forwarded two factors (Factor 1, belief in extra-
terrestrial life; and Factor 2, UFO-related beliefs), while Swami et al. (2009)
outlined three factors (Factor 1, belief that extra-terrestrial life has visited Earth
and that governmental agencies have knowledge of this fact; Factor 2; scientific
search for extra-terrestrial life; and Factor 3, general beliefs about the existence
of extra-terrestrial life). Although these studies successfully proposed alien/
extra-terrestrial factors and produced valid and reliable measures, the lack of
agreement over the number and nature of factors suggests that there is currently
no theoretical consensus, and that greater conceptual clarity is required. In this
context the current study’s intention was to disambiguate these differences and
in so doing further elucidate understanding of alien/extra-terrestrial beliefs.
To achieve this, items from the Dagnall, Parker, Munley, & Drinkwater
(2010) and Dagnall, Munley, Parker, & Drinkwater (2010a) and Swami et al.
(2009) papers were combined to produce a composite measure of alien/extra-
terrestrial belief(s). Using Principal Components Analysis (PCA), this measure
was found to be reducible to three related, but conceptually different factors:
Factor 1, Alien Visitation (e.g., “Alien spaceships regularly visit Earth”); Factor
2, Belief in the Existence of Extra-Terrestrial Life (e.g., “Somewhere in the
universe there are other forms of life”); and Factor 3, the Search for Extra-
Terrestrial Life (e.g., “Governments should direct more funding to the scientific
search for extra-terrestrial life”). The existence of three factors supports the
notion that alien/extra-terrestrial life beliefs are multifactorial (Chequers et al.,
1997, Dagnall, Parker, Munley, & Drinkwater, 2010, Dagnall, Munley, Parker,
& Drinkwater, 2010a, Swami et al., 2009) and implies that simple measures,
such as those contained within general measures of paranormal belief (e.g.,
R-PBS) are insufficient and unable to account for the complex nature of alien/
extra-terrestrial beliefs.
Importantly, support is provided for the dichotomy between alien visitation/
UFO-related beliefs and extra-terrestrial belief (Dagnall, Parker, Munley, &
Drinkwater, 2010, Dagnall, Munley, Parker, & Drinkwater, 2010a, Swami et
al., 2009, Chequers et al., 1997). Differences, however, were observed between
714 Neil Dagnall, Kenneth Drinkwater, & Andrew Parker
the factors identified in the present study and those proposed by Dagnall,
Parker, Munley, & Drinkwater (2010), Dagnall, Munley, Parker, & Drinkwater
(2010a), and Swami et al. (2009). Particularly, the Dagnall, Parker, Munley, &
Drinkwater (2010) measure was extended by the identification of an additional
factor (Search for Extra-Terrestrial Life), while the government component of
the Swami et al.’s measure (2009) (Factor 1) was found to be redundant.
Within the present study, males scored higher than females on Belief in the
Existence of Extra-Terrestrial Life (Factor 2) and Search for Extra-Terrestrial
Life (Factor 3), and no difference was found for Alien Visitation. While these
findings contradict Swami et al. (2009, 2010b), who found no sex difference,
they are consistent with previous studies, which found men more likely to
believe in extra-terrestrial life (Goode, 2000, Patry & Pelletier, 2001, Rice,
2003). Although gender differences were observed, the accompanying effect
sizes were small (Cohen, 1988), and this may explain the previously reported
inconsistent findings.
The present paper was also designed to examine the relationship between
alien/extra-terrestrial belief and paranormal belief. Previous work reports that
participants endorse the existence of life elsewhere in the universe but are
skeptical that such life has visited Earth (Dagnall, Parker, Munley, & Drinkwater,
2010, Dagnall, Munley, Parker, & Drinkwater, 2010a, Swami et al., 2009).
Noting this distinction, Swami et al. (2009) proposed a dichotomy between
paranormal-related alien/extra-terrestrial beliefs (Factor 1, belief that extra
terrestrial life has visited Earth and that government agencies have knowledge
of this fact) and more science-based beliefs (Factor 3, general beliefs about
the existence of extra terrestrial life). Dagnall, Munley, Parker, & Drinkwater
(2010a) found only the more radical UFO-related beliefs to be positively
associated with paranormal belief; alien visitation was found to correlate more
strongly with paranormal belief than the extra-terrestrial belief factors. Partial
correlations controlling for alien visitation revealed no association between the
extra-terrestrial belief factors and paranormal belief. These findings suggest
that belief in alien visitation can be viewed alongside facets of paranormal
belief, while belief in extra-terrestrial life cannot. Perhaps one interpretation of
this is that both sets of belief are dependent upon impaired/faulty reasoning and
critical evaluation (e.g., Blackmore, 1997, Bressan, 2002, Dagnall, Parker, &
Munley, 2007, Rogers, Fisk, & Wiltshire, 2010). However, in spite of this, it is
clear that belief in alien visitation or an alien presence is not always considered
to be unfounded and without evidential base (e.g., Carlotto, 1995, 1997, 2002,
DiPietro, Molenaar, & Brandenburg, 1988, Friedman, 2008, Greer, 2006, Leir,
2005, Maccabee, 2000, Sitchin, 1976, 2004, 2010).
Indeed, many researchers hold particular ideas concerning extraterrestrials
predicated upon reasoned argument and the evaluation of evidence.
Alien Visitation, Extra-Terrestrial Life, & Paranormal Beliefs 715
Consequently, what remains for further study is how the nature of alien visitation
beliefs might differ between groups of individuals depending upon how those
beliefs are derived. In some instances at least, beliefs in alien visitation or
an alien presence is the result of analytical processes that form the basis of
empirical and critical evaluation. Thus, the relationship between paranormal
beliefs and alien visitation beliefs may not be found when the latter beliefs are
based upon reasoned argument. This requires further study.
In this context one variable of particular interest is reality testing (Irwin,
2003). Reality testing has been defined as the inclination to test critically the
logical plausibility of beliefs. The importance of reality testing is derived from
the notion that pathological beliefs and delusions arise in part from the failure
to subject hypothetical explanations of sensory experience to critical testing
(Irwin, 2004, Langdon & Coltheart, 2000); problems arise because experiences
require interpretation (casual attributions) and are subject to bias (Kahneman
& Tversky, 1972, Weiner, 1986). Thus, pathological belief generation is
characterized by the failure to test the plausibility of generated explanations/
hypotheses.
Reality testing deficits have been used to explain the development
and maintenance of paranormal beliefs (Dagnall, Drinkwater, Parker, &
Munley, 2010, Irwin, 2004, 2003, Zusne & Jones, 1982). The acceptance and
maintenance of paranormal explanations over conventional alternatives arises
from the intuitive–experiential interpretation of stimuli and an absence of
analytical–rational processing (reality testing) (Irwin, 2009). Irwin and Young
(2002) argue that people with an intuitive–experiential processing style will be
predisposed toward accepting paranormal explanations because they find them
appealing and therefore do not subject them to reality testing. This notion could
be extended to include alien visitation/UFO-related beliefs.
Recent research has found that scores on cognitive–perceptual measures
(schizotypy and transliminality) affect level of paranormal belief (Dagnall,
Munley, Parker, & Drinkwater, 2010b). Particularly, participants scoring above
the median have demonstrated higher levels of endorsement across a range
of paranormal belief subscales (Hauntings, Aliens, Superstition, Other Life,
Religion, PK, ESP, Astrology, and Witchcraft) than those below the median.
In line with Swami et al. (2010b), this suggests that the individual-differences
approach may be usefully employed to clarify the underlying processes that
give rise to extra-terrestrial and alien-related beliefs.
Indeed, extra-terrestrial and alien-related beliefs have been found to be
predicted by different variables. Swami et al. (2010b) reported that extra-
terrestrial beliefs were predicted by paranormal beliefs, the unusual factor of
schizotypy, openness to experience, and education. While Swami, Chamorro-
Premuzic, and Shafi (2010a) noted that Agreeableness, Neuroticism, and
716 Neil Dagnall, Kenneth Drinkwater, & Andrew Parker
Notes
1
Within Table 1 and Table 2, reversed (item numbers with an R) denotes items that are
reversed-scored.
2
A partial eta-squared between .01 and .06 reflects a small effect size, within the .06–
.13 range a medium effect size, and .14 or higher a large effect (Cohen, 1988).
References
Andrich, D. (1988). Rasch Models for Measurement. Sage University Paper Series on Quantitative
Applications in the Social Sciences, series no. 07-068. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage Publications.
Appelle (1995/96). The abduction experience: A critical evaluation of theory and evidence. Journal
of UFO Studies, 6, 29–78.
Bartlett, M. S. (1954). A note on the multiplying factors for various chi-square approximations.
Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, 16 (Series B), 296–298.
Biasco, F., & Nunn, K. (2000). College students’ attitudes toward UFOs. College Student Journal,
34, 96–99.
Blackmore, S. J. (1997). Probability misjudgement and belief in the paranormal: A newspaper
survey. British Journal of Psychology, 88, 683–689.
Bressan, P. (2002). The connection between random sequences, everyday coincidences, and belief
in the paranormal. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 16, 17–34.
Bullard, T. E. (1994). The influence of investigators on UFO abduction reports: Results of a survey.
In Andrea Pritchard, David E. Pritchard, John E. Mack, Pam Kasey, & Claudia Yapp (Eds.),
Alien Discussions: Proceedings of the Abduction Study Conference Held at M.I.T., pp.
571–619, Cambridge, MA: North Cambridge Press.
Alien Visitation, Extra-Terrestrial Life, & Paranormal Beliefs 717
Carlotto, M. J. (1995). Digital video analysis of anomalous space objects. Journal of Scientific
Exploration, 9, 45–63.
Carlotto, M. J. (1997). Evidence in support of the hypothesis that certain objects on Mars are
artificial in origin. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 11, 123–145.
Carlotto, M. J. (2002). The Cydonia Controversy: The History, Science, and Implications of the
Discovery of Artificial Structures on Mars. Authorhouse.
Chequers, J., Joseph, S., & Diduca, D. (1997). Belief in extra-terrestrial life, UFO-related beliefs,
and schizotypal personality. Personality and Individual Differences, 23, 519–521.
Clancy, S. A., McNally, R. J., Schacter, D. L., Lenzenweger, M. F., & Pitman, R. K. (2002). Memory
distortion in people reporting abduction by aliens. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 111,
455–461.
Clarke, D. (1991). Belief in the paranormal: A New Zealand survey. Journal of the Society for
Psychical Research, 57, 412–425.
Cohen, J. (1988). Statistical Power Analysis for the Social Sciences. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence
Erlbaum.
Comrey, A. L., & Lee, H. B. (1992). A First Course in Factor Analysis (second edition). Hillsdale,
NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Crowe, M. J. (1986). The Extra-Terrestrial Life Debate, 1750–1900. Cambridge, England:
Cambridge University Press.
Dagnall, N., Drinkwater, K., Parker, A., & Munley, G. (2010). Reality testing, belief in the
paranormal, and urban legends. European Journal of Parapsychology, 25.
Dagnall, N., Munley, G., Parker, A., & Drinkwater, K. (2010a). The relationship between belief
in extra-terrestrial life, UFOs-related beliefs and paranormal belief. Society for Psychical
Research, 74, 1–14.
Dagnall, N., Munley, G., Parker, A., & Drinkwater K. (2010b). Paranormal belief, schizotypy and
transliminality. Journal of Parapsychology, 74, 117–143.
Dagnall, N., Parker, A., & Munley, G. (2007). Paranormal belief and reasoning. Personality and
Individual Differences, 43, 1406–1415.
Dagnall, N., Parker, A., Munley, G., & Drinkwater, K. (2010). Common paranormal belief
dimensions. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 24, 431–447.
Diaz-Vilela, L., & Alvarez-Gonzalez, C. (2004). Differences in paranormal beliefs across fields
of study from a Spanish adaptation of Tobacyk’s RPBS. Journal of Parapsychology, 68,
405–421.
DiPietro, V., Molenaar, G., & Brandenburg, J. (1988). Unusual Martian Surface Features (fourth
edition). Willmar, MN: Molenaar Inc. Press.
French, C. C. (2001). Alien Abductions. In R. Roberts & D. Groome (Eds.), Parapsychology: The
Science of Unusual Experience, London: Arnold, pp. 102–116.
French, C. C., Santomauro, J., Hamilton, V., Fox, R., & Thalbourne, M. A. (2008). Psychological
aspects of the alien contact experience. Cortex, 44, 1387–1395.
Friedman, S. (2008). Flying Saucers and Science: A Scientist Investigates the Mysteries of UFOs.
Franklin Lakes, NJ: New Page Books.
Gallup, G. H. (Ed.) (1997). The Gallup Poll: Public Opinion 1996. Wilmington, DE: Scholarly
Resources.
Gallup, G. H., & Newport, F. (1991). Belief in paranormal phenomena among adult Americans.
Skeptical Enquirer, 15, 137–146.
Genta, G. (2007). Lonely Minds in the Universe: The Search for Extraterrestrial Intelligence.
Berlin: Springer.
Goode, E. (2000). Paranormal Beliefs: A Sociological Introduction. Prospect Heights, IL:
Waveland Publishing.
Gray, W. D. (1991). Thinking Critically about New Age Ideas. Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
Greer, S. M. (2006). Hidden Truth: Forbidden Knowledge. Crossing Point.
718 Neil Dagnall, Kenneth Drinkwater, & Andrew Parker
Hopkins, B., Jacobs, D. M., & Westrum, R. (1992). Unusual Personal Experiences: An Analysis of
the Data from Three National Surveys Conducted by the Roper Organization. Las Vegas:
Bigelow Holding Corp.
Irwin, H. J. (2003). Reality testing and the formation of paranormal beliefs. European Journal of
Parapsychology, 18, 15–28.
Irwin, H. J. (2004). Reality testing and the formation of paranormal beliefs: A constructive
replication. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 68, 143–152.
Irwin, H. J. (2009). The Psychology of Paranormal Belief: A Researcher’s Handbook. Hatfield,
England: University of Hertfordshire Press.
Irwin, H. J., & Young, J. M. (2002). Intuitive versus reflective processes in the formation of
paranormal beliefs. European Journal of Parapsychology, 17, 45–53.
Jacobs, D. M. (1992). Secret Life: First-Hand Accounts of UFO Abductions. New York: Simon &
Schuster.
Jones, W. H., Russell, D. W., & Nickel, T. W. (1977). Belief in the Paranormal Scale: An objective
instrument to measure beliefs in magical phenomena and causes. JSAS Catalogue of
Selected Documents in Psychology, 7, 100 (Ms. No. 1577).
Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1972). Subjective probability: A judgment of representativeness.
Cognitive Psychology, 3, 430–454.
Kaiser, H. (1970). A second generation Little Jiffy. Psychometrika, 35, 401–415.
Kaiser, H. (1974). An index of factorial simplicity. Psychometrika, 39, 31–36.
Kumar, V. K., & Pekala, R. J. (2001). Relation of hypnosis-specific attitudes and behaviours to
paranormal beliefs and experiences: A technical review. In J. Houran & R. Lange (Eds.),
Hauntings and Poltergeists: Multidisciplinary Perspectives, Jefferson: NC: McFarland.
Kumar, V. K., Pekala, R. J., & Gallagher, C. (1994). The Anomalous Experiences Inventory.
Unpublished psychological test. West Chester, PA: West Chester University.
Langdon, R., & Coltheart, M. (2000). The cognitive neuropsychology of delusions. Mind &
Language, 15, 183–216.
Lange, R., Irwin, H. J., & Houran, J. (2000). Top-down purification of Tobacyk’s Revised
Paranormal Belief Scale. Personality and Individual Differences, 29, 131–156.
Lange, R., & Thalbourne, M. A. (2002). Rasch scaling paranormal belief and experience: The
structure and semantics of Thalbourne’s Australian Sheep–Goat Scale. Psychological
Reports, 91, 1065–1073.
Lawrence, T. R. (1995a). How many factors of paranormal belief are there?: A critique of the PBS.
Journal of Parapsychology, 59, 3–25.
Lawrence, T. R. (1995b). Moving on from the PBS: A final reply to Tobacyk. Journal of
Parapsychology, 59, 131–140.
Lawrence, T., Roe, C., & Williams, C. (1997). Confirming the factor structure of the Paranormal
Beliefs Scale: Big orthogonal seven or oblique five? The Journal of Parapsychology, 61,
13–27.
Leir, R. K. (2005). The Aliens and the Scalpel. Book Tree.
Maccabee, B. R. (2000). UFO FBI Connection: The Secret History of the Government’s Cover-Up.
St. Paul, MN: Llewellyn Publications.
Patry, A., & Pelletier, L. (2001). Extra-terrestrial beliefs and experiences: An application of the
theory of reasoned action. The Journal of Social Psychology, 141, 199–201.
Preece, P. F. W., & Baxter, J. H. (2000). Scepticism and gullibility: The superstitious and pseudo-
scientific beliefs of secondary school students. International Journal of Science Education,
22, 1147–1156.
Randall, T. M. (1997). Paranormal Short Inventory. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 84, 1265–
1266.
Randall, T. M., & Desrosiers, M. (1980). Measurement of supernatural belief: Sex differences and
locus of control. Journal of Personality Assessment, 44, 493–498.
Alien Visitation, Extra-Terrestrial Life, & Paranormal Beliefs 719
Rawlings, D., & MacFarlane, E. (1994). A multidimensional schizotypal traits questionnaire for
young adolescents. Personality and Individual Differences, 17, 489–496.
Rice, T. (2003). Believe it or not: Religious and other paranormal beliefs in the United States.
Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 42, 95–106.
Rogers, P., Fisk, J. E., & Wiltshire, D. (2010). Paranormal belief and the conjunctive fallacy:
Controlling the temporal relatedness and potential surprise differentials in component
events. Applied Cognitive Psychology. http://wileyonlinelibrary.com
Shostak, S. (2009). Confessions of an Alien Hunter: A Scientist’s Search for Extraterrestrial
Intelligence. National Geographic Society.
Sitchin, Z. (1976). The 12th Planet. New York: Harper.
Sitchin, Z. (2004). The Earth Chronicles Expeditions. Bear & Company.
Sitchin, Z. (2010). There Were Giants Upon the Earth: Gods, Demigods, and Human Ancestry: The
Evidence of Alien DNA (Earth Chronicles). Bear & Company.
Swami, V., Chamorro-Premuzic, T., & Shafi, M. (2010a). Psychology in outerspace: Personality,
individual difference, and demographic predictors of beliefs about extraterrestrial life.
European Psychologist 15(3), 220–228. doi:10.1027/1016-9040/a000023
Swami, V., Furnham, A., Haubner, T., Stieger, S., & Voracek, M. (2009). The truth is out there: The
structure of beliefs about extra-terrestrial life among Austrian and British respondents. The
Journal of Social Psychology, 149, 29–43.
Swami, V., Pietschnig. J., Stieger, S., & Voracek, M. (2010b). Alien Psychology: Associations
between Extraterrestrial Beliefs and Paranormal Ideation, Superstitious Beliefs,
Schizotypy, and the Big Five Personality Factors. Applied Cognitive Psychology, 25(4),
647–653. http://wileyonlinelibrary.com
Thalbourne, M. A. (1995a). Further studies of the measurement and correlates of belief in the
paranormal. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 89, 233–247.
Thalbourne, M. A. (1995b). Psychological characteristics of believers in the paranormal: A
replicative study. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 89, 153–164.
Thalbourne, M. A., & Delin, P. S. (1993). A new instrument for measuring the sheep–goat variable:
Its psychometric properties and factor structure. Journal of the Society for Psychical
Research, 59, 172–186.
Thalbourne, M. A., Dunbar, K. A., & Delin, P. S. (1995). An investigation into correlates of belief
in the paranormal. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 89, 215–231.
Tobacyk, J. J. (1988). A Revised Paranormal Belief Scale. Unpublished manuscript. Ruston, LA:
Louisiana Tech University.
Tobacyk, J. (1995a). What is the correct dimensionality of paranormal beliefs?: A reply to
Lawrence’s critique of the Paranormal Belief Scale. Journal of Parapsychology, 59, 27–46.
Tobacyk, J. (1995b). Final thoughts on issues in the measurement of paranormal beliefs. Journal of
Parapsychology, 59, 141–145.
Tobacyk, J. (2004). A revised paranormal belief scale. International Journal of Transpersonal
Studies, 23, 94–98.
Tobacyk, J., & Milford, G. (1983). Belief in paranormal phenomena: Assessment instrument
development and implications for personality functioning. Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, 44, 1029–1037.
Tobacyk, J., & Thomas, A. (1997). How the big orthogonal seven is really the oblique seven.
Journal of Parapsychology, 61, 337–334.
Vakoch, D. A. (2011). Communication with Extraterrestrial Intelligence. New York: SUNY Press.
Watkins, M. W. (2000). Monte Carlo PCA for Parallel Analysis [computer software]. State College,
PA: Ed & Psych Associates.
Weiner, B. (1986). An Attributional Theory of Motivation and Emotion. New York: Springer-Verlag.
Wiseman, R. & Watt, C. (2006). Belief in psychic ability and the misattribution hypothesis: A
qualitative review. British Journal of Psychology, 97, 323–338.
720 Neil Dagnall, Kenneth Drinkwater, & Andrew Parker
Zullino, D. F., Verdu, B., Khazaal, Y., & Borgeat, F. (2006). Delusional ideas of alien control
induced by the visit to an attraction park. German Journal of Psychiatry, 9, 57–59.
Zusne, L., & Jones, W. H. (1982). Anomalistic Psychology: A Study of Extraordinary Phenomena of
Behavior and Experience. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
Journal of Scientific Exploration, Vol. 25, No. 4, pp. 721–733, 2011 0892-3310/11
RESEARCH
Introduction
Theory
Psi phenomena can be formally defined as correlations that seem to transcend
space or time or both. For instance, there may be correlations between what
subjects choose from a set of four potential targets and the actual target about
which the subject has no information. This information may be distant in space
721
722 Dick J. Bierman
Earlier Experiments
The roots of the current research can probably be traced back to the middle
of the last century, when instruments to measure physiological processes be-
came more commonly available. A. J. Good reportedly suggested measuring
brain potentials on the surface of someone’s skull (EEG) while he sits in a
dark room and a light is flashed at random moments, to discover whether “the
EEG shows any tendency to forecast the flashes of light” (Good, 1961, cited in
Radin, 2006:163). In the 1970s, there was in fact a study conducted to explore
whether the EEG showed any tendency to forecast, not flashes of light, but the
gender of faces in pictures (Hartwell, 1978). The results showed no significant
differences in EEG for different genders, however, despite laborious (especially
at the time) and extensive analyses. At about the same time, Vassy (1978) did
report highly significant results in an experiment that was set up to measure te-
lepathy. That study is worth mentioning because its design was rather similar to
that of later presentiment studies. Vassy measured the electrical activity of the
skin (EDA) preceding an electrical shock for which the participant either was or
wasn’t warned telepathically by someone in another room. As with Hartwell’s
EEG study (Hartwell, 1978), judging and analyzing physiological measures
was cumbersome and prone to error in those days. This is perhaps why it took
a rather long time before more studies were undertaken in this direction. By the
end of the last century, Radin picked up the trail and used modern, automated
equipment in the first of a series of presentiment studies (Radin, 1997). Radin
got interesting, statistically significant, results corroborating his hypothesis.
These results were soon replicated by Bierman, and together they published a
summary of five different presentiment studies in a “mainstream” psychologi-
cal journal (Bierman & Radin, 1997). As in Vassy’s study, these early experi-
ments used mainly EDA as the dependent physiological measure of presenti-
ment; this measure seemed to produce the most reliable results.
724 Dick J. Bierman
Since then, several other physiological measures have been used as depen-
dent variables with a similar design as in Figure 1 or with a design where the
stimuli are unexpected loud sounds or light flashes to induce strong responses
like in the study by May and Spottiswoode. Variables that have been used in-
clude Evoked Potentials (Radin & Lobach, 2007), CNV (Bierman, 2006), Bold
(Bierman & Scholte, 2002, Bierman, 2007), Eye Movement (Radin & Borges,
2009), Pupil Dilation (Radin & Borges, 2009), Blinking (Radin & Borges,
2009), and HR (heart rate) (Tressoldi, Martinelli, Massaccesi, & Sartori, 2005,
McCraty, Atkinson, & Bradley, 2004a, 2004b). The results of all these stud-
ies suggest anomalous correlations, though the interpretation is far from clear
and the results are not very robust. Also a number of experiments have used
behavioral measures such as preference scores in a mere-exposure experiment
where the preference score was given before the mere exposure (Bem, 2011).
Preferences that increase as in mere exposure or decrease as in habituation can
still be seen in the framework of emotion research. Apparent retrocausal ef-
fects were also observed in a priming task where the prime was presented after
the response was given (de Boer & Bierman, 2006). This retroactive priming
study showed a clear effect of a faster response in a gender-discrimination task
when the target was followed by a congruent “prime” (which actually should be
called “post”). In this case, “emotions” apparently were not involved explicitly
or implicitly.
Research Question
In the present research, the domain of interest regarding apparent retrocausal
effects is further extended to the visual experience of a so-called “transparent”
Necker cube. When a picture of this cube is presented to subjects, their experi-
ence switches spontaneously between two viewpoints. In one perspective the
cube is experienced as observed from above, in the other it is experienced as
observed from below. We measured switching times from the “above” to the
“below” experience. Once the subject had indicated by pressing a button that
this shift had taken place, the picture of the transparent cube changed into an
opaque presentation of one of the two possible viewpoints. The choice of which
perspective was presented, “from above” or “from below”, was random. This
created two conditions. When the opaque view was “from above”, this cor-
responded to the view for which the duration was measured (congruent), the
opaque view “from below” was the incongruent condition. Arguing that in the
incongruent condition the opaque view would “retrocausally” interfere with
the “top view” for which the duration was measured, we predicted that in that
incongruent condition the duration would be shorter. Alternatively one could
argue that presenting a future congruent opaque view would stabilize retroac-
tively the experienced “top view”, thereby enhancing the switching time. The
726 Dick J. Bierman
Method
Subjects
Subjects for the pilot and confirmatory studies were recruited from the Dutch
University of Groningen student population. The second confirmatory study
used voluntary subjects from the Amsterdam area. About half of those sub-
jects in the Amsterdam study practiced yoga while the other half consisted of
matched control subjects. See Table 1 for gender counts and age information.
TABLE 1
Mean Age and Standard Deviations Split for Study and Gender
FEMALE MALE
Study N Mean sd N Mean sd
Pilot 3* 3*
Procedure
The experimental software was developed at the University of Amsterdam,
and then the same program was mailed to the University of Groningen where
the experiment was conducted by a Ph.D. student unaware of the hypotheses.
Necker Cube Switching Time Anomaly 727
Parallel to that study, a Master's student in Amsterdam ran the same experiment
in Amsterdam, also blind to the hypotheses.
Subjects were exposed to a picture of a Necker cube with a fixation point
embedded “inside” the cube (see Figure 2).
They were asked to gaze at the fixation point and wait until they expe-
rienced the cube with a “bottom view” perspective and then press the space-
bar (response 1) at the moment that this subjective experience spontaneously
changed to a “top view.” As soon as the “top view” returned to the bottom view
they pressed the spacebar again (response 2). The trial then ended by the soft-
ware changing the picture into an opaque view of the cube randomly in either
“top view” or “bottom view” (see Figure 3).
Figure 3. Example of opaque "top view" of Necker cube used for feedback.
728 Dick J. Bierman
This opaque-cube feedback remained for one second on the screen. The
time between the two responses was the duration that the “top view” was ex-
perienced. The subjects were unaware of the psi hypothesis. In the Groningen
study also the experimenter was unaware of the psi hypothesis. The experiment
was framed as a study in the category of consciousness research.
From the pilot experiment we learned that this task is not an easy one and
that subjects sometimes missed a switch or did not follow the gaze instruction.
We therefore adjusted the subject’s instructions and also added instructions for
naïve experimenters. Further, in the confirmatory studies, the subjects were
asked to indicate if they succeeded in giving the response according to instruc-
tions, otherwise the trial was not included in the analyses. For each subject, a
session consisted of 32 valid trials and lasted about six minutes.
Analysis
Data from the Groningen confirmatory experiment were mailed to the University
of Amsterdam to be analyzed. The Amsterdam experiment was analyzed sepa-
rately and later all data were pooled. Outlier trials with a perspective switch
time value larger than three standard deviations or with a switch time smaller
than 800 msec were removed. This procedure, based upon trying out several
outlier removal algorithms on the pilot data, was repeated until no further outli-
ers were present. Then the mean durations of the “top view” percept were cal-
culated for each subject and for each of the two (future) conditions. The means
were compared using SPSS 16 (Mac-version) with a two-sample t-test.
Results
Pilot
Six subjects were tested. Outliers were removed as described above. The mean
difference of 58 msec between the two (future) conditions was in the theoreti-
cally expected direction but not significant. Inspection of the preprocessed data
showed that one subject had more than nine outliers. When this subject was
removed from the analysis, the two conditions differed by 384 msec and the
t-test was marginally significant (t = 2.5, df = 4, p = 0.065 two-tailed). Two-
tailed tests were used here because we decided that in spite of the theoretical
argument that gave us an expectation for the direction of the effect, we would
use the pilot data to specify a direction to be used in the confirmatory phase
of the study. Although the p-values of the pilot study are marginal, the fact
that the effect was in the predicted direction gave us confidence to also predict
the same direction for the confirmatory studies and thereby justified the use of
one-tailed testing in those studies. It can be argued that two-tailed testing is al-
ways required when effects on both directions are of interest, and we certainly
Necker Cube Switching Time Anomaly 729
feel that this might be the case for the study of anomalous phenomena. On the
other hand, we feel that this field is in need of theory-driven research generally
predicting a direction of an effect, rather than that any anomaly be published.
It should be noted that the preprocessing procedures dealing with outli-
ers introduce some extra degrees of freedom. A subject was removed from the
study if he or she produced nine or more outliers. This value is rather arbitrary
and was chosen on the basis of optimization of the end result of the pilot study
outcome. Once these parameters were set, they were not changed again when
analyzing the confirmatory experiments.
Removal of the pilot study’s one subject who obtained a large number of
outliers also considerably improved the correlation between the two conditions.
The correlation between conditions for all six subjects was 0.77, while after
removal of the suspect subject the correlation became 0.96, adding to the im-
pression that this removed subject really was an outlier.
The results of the pilot experiment were used as a predictor for the con-
firmatory experiment. This allowed us to predict a direction for the effect. The
predicted direction was in line with the idea that the duration of the “top view”
perspective was disturbed by showing an opaque bottom view afterward. We
called this retroactive interference. We also expected on the basis of the pilot
experiment that subjects in the confirmatory experiments with nine or more
outliers would not contribute to a switching time effect.
Confirmatory Studies
The overall difference between the two conditions pooled for all 169 subjects
from the three studies was in the same direction and of the same magnitude (88
msec) as in the pilot study, but as in the pilot this effect was non-significant
(t = 1.41, df = 168, p = 0.08 one-tailed). After removal of the 16 subjects (9.5%)
who had nine or more outliers, the mean differential effect was 129 msec
(t = 1.97, df = 152, p = 0.026 one-tailed). In Table 2 the results are given for
each of the three studies separately.
The mean number of outliers per subject over all studies (including the pi-
lot) was 3.00 from the 32 trials (sd = 1.78). The mean time that each participant
spent was 12:20 (sd = 11:53).
TABLE 2
Review of Results for the Two Conditions, Top View Feedback and
Bottom View Feedback, of the Opaque Final Picture
is hardly noticed by the subjects, and above all there is no reason to assume that
this feedback induces any emotional response in the subject. Therefore it might
be concluded that this finding supports the idea that apparent retrocausal ef-
fects do occur in all events, neutral or emotional. Also, the percepts from above
and from below are conscious percepts rather than non-conscious physiological
states. Thus we might conclude that these anomalous effects might also induce
correlations between future conditions and a conscious state.
We did not formally compare stable with unstable systems, because the
Necker cube switch is by definition a phenomenon due to instability. One could
argue that when the mean switching time is small the (brain) system is even
more labile than when the mean switching times are larger. We therefore cor-
related the relative effect size for each subject with the mean switching time of
that subject. This correlation was very small and far from significant. Thus this
study does not lend support to, nor contradict, the idea that more labile systems
are more sensitive for these apparent retrocausal effects.
An alternative paranormal explanation is that the study results are an ex-
ample of an analyzer psi effect: Choosing the analysis criteria precisely in such
a way that a significant outcome arises; although a counterargument is that this
freedom of choice was constrained by adhering to the parameters that gave the
best result for the pilot series in the confirmatory studies. The analyzer effect
“explanation” has been put forward in a number of anomaly research studies.
The idea is that the analysis is also a future condition, although it is further in
the future than the feedback per trial, and a more complex task.
Another explanation that does not resort to an anomaly is that the code that
was executed for time measurement is in some way different for the two future
pictures. We tested this by simulating key-presses using an independent timer.
The mean response times for the two future pictures thus obtained did differ
by 2.4 msec (not significant). This difference is a factor of 50, smaller than the
differences obtained in this experiment.
Finally there could be a problem with data integrity. However, a copy of
the raw data stayed at Groningen University and can be compared by indepen-
dent researchers to the data that finally entered into the formal analysis.
The studies reported here are generally classified as parapsychological.
That is a misnomer. There is nothing in Psychology that prohibits these anoma-
lous effects from occurring. The term anomaly solely refers to the accepted
interpretation of physics. If anything, these studies should be classified as para-
physical. However, as was argued in the Introduction, current physical frame-
works do not really prohibit advanced phenomena. The nature and the arrow of
time is still a very open issue in physics. Therefore, the anomaly refers to the
fact that in physics advanced phenomena haven’t been observed (yet).
It is important to develop the time-symmetry model further in order to
732 Dick J. Bierman
produce testable hypotheses. Most notably, future work might focus on indi-
vidual differences and correlate these with the coherence aspect of states of
consciousness.
Acknowledgments
We wish to thank Ninja Kattenbeck and Lara Knuwer for their help as experimenters and
Jacob Joly for providing laboratory space at the University of Groningen. Eva Lobach
contributed by supervising the Master's student in Amsterdam and by commenting on
several versions of this manuscript. This work was an extension of work funded by Bial
Grant 34-04.
References
Bem, D. (2011). Feeling the future: Replicable evidence for a process of anomalous cognition.
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 100(3), 1–14.
Bierman, D. J. (2006). Empirical Research on the Radical Subjective Solution of the Measurement
Problem. Does Time Get Its Direction through Conscious Observation? In Daniel P.
Sheehan (Ed.), Frontiers of Time, American Institute of Physics Conference Proceedings,
San Diego, 20–22 June 2006, pp. 238–260.
Bierman, D. (2007). fMRI and Photo Emission Study of Presentiment: The Role of “Coherence”
in Retrocausal Processes. Final Report 34-04, Bial Foundation. http://www.uniamsterdam.
nl/D.J.Bierman/publications/2007/bial_FINAL%20REPORT_34-04_def.doc
Bierman, D. (2010). Consciousness-induced restoration of time symmetry (CIRTS). A
psychophysical theoretical perspective. Journal of Parapsychology, 24, 273–300.
Bierman, D., & Radin, D. (1997). Anomalous anticipatory response on random future conditions.
Perceptual and Motor Skills, 8(4), 689–680.
Bierman, D., & Scholte, H. (2002). Anomalous anticipatory brain activation preceding exposure
of emotional and neutral pictures. Journal of International Society of Life Information
Science, 20(2), 380–388.
Blake, R., & Logothetis, N. K. (2002). Visual competition. Neuroscience, 3, 1–11.
de Boer, R., & Bierman, D. J. (2006). The roots of paranormal belief: Divergent associations or real
paranormal experiences? Proceedings of the 49th Convention of the Parapsychological
Association, Stockholm, 4–7 August 2006, pp. 283–298.
Broughton, R. (2006). Memory, emotion and the receptive psi process. Proceedings of the 49th
Convention of the Parapsychological Association, Stockholm, 4–7 August 2006, pp. 20–
31.
Hartwell, W. (1978). Contingent negative variation as an index of precognitive information.
European Journal of Parapsychology, 2, 83–103.
Lang, P., Bradley, M., & Cuthbert, B. (1999). International Affective Picture System (IAPS):
Technical Manual and Affective Ratings. Gainesville, FL: Center for Research in
Psychophysiology, University of Florida.
Lobach, E. (2010). Somatic Components of Intuition & Psi. In Intuition and Decisionmaking, 8th
Symposium “Behind and Beyond the Brain”, 7–10 April 2010, Porto, Portugal, pp. 75–85.
Bial Foundation.
May, E. Paulinyi, T., & Vassy, Z. (2005). Anomalous anticipatory skin conductance response to
acoustic stimuli: Experimental results and speculation about a mechanism. Journal of
Alternative and Complementary Medicine, 11(4), 695–702.
Necker Cube Switching Time Anomaly 733
McCraty, R., Atkinson, M., & Bradley, R. (2004a). Electrophysiological evidence of intuition:
Part 1. The surprising role of the heart. The Journal of Alternative and Complementary
Medicine, 10, 133–143.
McCraty, R., Atkinson, M., & Bradley, R. (2004b). Electrophysiological evidence of intuition: Part
2. A system-wide process? The Journal of Alternative and Complementary Medicine, 10,
325–336.
Radin, D. (1997). Unconscious perception of future emotions. Journal of Scientific Exploration,
11(2), 163–180.
Radin, D. (2004). Electrodermal presentiments of future emotions. Journal of Scientific Exploration,
18(2), 253–273.
Radin, D. (2006). Entangled Minds. New York: Simon & Schuster.
Radin, D., & Borges, A. (2009). Intuition through time: What does the seer see? Explore, 5, 200–
211.
Radin, D., & Lobach, E. (2007). Toward an understanding of the placebo effect: Investigating a
possible retrocausal factor. Journal of Alternative and Complementary Medicine, 13(7),
733–739.
Spottiswoode, S., & May, E. (2003). Skin conductance prestimulus response: Analyses, artifact,
and pilot study. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 17(4), 617–641.
Stanford, R. G. (1990). An experimentally testable model for spontaneous psi events: A review of
related evidence and concepts from parapsychology and other sciences. In S. Krippner
(Ed.), Advances in Parapsychological Research, Volume 6, Jefferson, NC: McFarland, pp.
54–167.
Tong, F., Meng, M., & Blake, R. (2006). Neural basis of binocular rivalry. Trends in Cognitive
Sciences, 10–11, 502–511.
Tressoldi, P., Martinelli, M., Massaccesi, S., & Sartori, L. (2005). Heart rate differences between
targets and non-targets in intuitive tasks. Human Physiology, 31(6), 646–650.
Vassy, Z. (1978). Method for measuring the probability of one-bit extrasensory information transfer
between living organisms. Journal of Parapsychology, 42, 158–160.
Journal of Scientific Exploration, Vol. 25, No. 4, pp. 735–746, 2011 0892-3310/11
RESEARCH
GERSON S. PAIVA
[email protected]
CARLTON A. TAFT
[email protected]
Introduction
Several rare and unexplained light phenomena can be seen in the atmosphere.
For example, ball lightning (Paiva, Pavão, Vasconcelos, Mendes, & Silva,
2007), blue jets (Pasko & George, 2002), red sprites (Pasko, Inan, & Bell,
2000), and terrestrial gamma ray flashes (TGFs) (Paiva, Pavão, & Bastos, 2009,
Paiva, 2009). Hessdalen Lights (HL) are unexplained lights usually seen in the
valley of Hessdalen, Norway (Teodorani, 2004). They have the appearance of
a free-floating light ball with dimensions ranging from decimeters up to 30 m.
HL often show strong pulsating magnetic perturbation of about 5 Hz. They are
often accompanied by small, short-duration pulsating “spikes” in the HF and
735
736 Gerson S. Paiva and Carlton A. Taft
& Taft, 2010). Coulomb crystal is a regular structure (cubic, triangular, etc.)
formed by microparticles (dust) in the plasma of electrons and ions under certain
conditions. Several physical properties (oscillation, geometric structure, and
light spectrum) observed in Hessdalen Lights phenomenon can be explained
through the dust plasma model.
Enomoto and Hashimoto (1990) have detected the emission of charged
particles from indentation fracture of rocks. The charge generated by
hornblende andesite indentation fracture is about 1.2 × 10−11 C/s. The volume
of the fractured zone, estimated from the size of the indent, was 0.02 × 10−9 m3.
Thus, the net production rate would be ~0.6 C/m3/s. If a massive fracture occurs
during one second at ground level, over an area extending some meters, the
charge generated may be compared to the total electric charge produced by one
bolt of lightning (1 Coulomb). Charge separation on fractured surfaces produces
high electric fields on the order of 106−107 V cm−1, causing the field emission of
electrons in the atmosphere. The energy of emitted electrons may be in the keV
range. This may be sufficient to cause geoelectromagnetic disturbances.
Ogawa, Oike, and Miura (1985) showed in laboratory experiments that
rocks radiated wide-band EM waves (10 Hz–100 kHz) when they were struck
by a hammer and fractured. Very low frequency EM emission (0.01–10 Hz) was
also observed from earth rocks before and during earthquakes according to Park,
Johnson, Madden, Morgan, and Morrison (1993). Satellites showed intense EM
radiation at frequencies below 450 Hz (Serebryakova, Bilichenko, Chmyrev,
Parrot, Rauch, Lefeuvre, & Pokhotelov, 1992). These data are in accord with
the EM signals recorded by the spectrum analyzer and the magnetometer at
Hessdalen covering the band of 0.5–80 MHz (Strand, 1990). So it appears that
EM waves could have been emitted by rocks in the region where strange lights
were observed.
In this work, we present a model to explain the spatial color distribution of
luminous balls commonly observed in HL phenomenon. According to our model,
different colors of light balls in HL phenomenon are produced by accelerated
electrons due to electric fields formed by rapid fractures of piezoelectric rocks
under the ground during water freezing (i.e. during the winter). Semi-relativistic
green light balls in the HL phenomenon are produced by the light emission of
ionic oxygen transported by ionic acoustic waves (IAW) interacting with a large
white-colored light ball of HL phenomenon.
The Model
Let us consider the model of the HL cluster shown in Figure 1.
738 Gerson S. Paiva and Carlton A. Taft
Figure 1. Light balls in HL cluster: Rock fractures under the hill ground (a),
charge separation (b), high electric fields (c), acceleration of these
electrons in the atmosphere (d), electron-avalanche (e), low-intensity
blue-colored light ball (f), high-intensity red-colored light ball (g),
central white-colored light ball (h), small green light ball (i), very low
frequency electromagnetic waves (j), ion-acoustic waves (k). Rotation
(l) of the central white ball (m) ejecting its hot and cold edges, form-
ing, respectively, blue (f) and red light balls (g).
According to Figure 1, the abrupt rock fractures under the hill ground (a)
(probably produced by water expansion during freezing in the lithosphere)
results, temporarily, in charge separation (b). One possibility is that charge
separation on fractured surfaces produces high electric fields on the order of
106–107 V cm−1 (c). Free electrons with the density of 4 × 106 to 1 × 107
electrons m−3 s−1 are generated by cosmic rays and natural radiation due to
atmospheric radioactivity. The electric field generated induces charges on the
ground causing the acceleration of these electrons in the atmosphere (d). When
these electrons collide with atmospheric atoms, knocking off electrons, they
will form an electron-avalanche (e). Low-flux of high-energy (temperature)
electrons will produce a low-intensity, blue-colored light ball (f), and high-flux of
low-energy (temperature) electrons will produce a high-luminosity, red-colored
Colored Light Balls in Hessdalen Lights 739
light ball (g) in the opposite direction of the central white ball (h). Ejection of a
small green light ball (i) from a white ball is due to radiation pressure produced
by the interaction between very low frequency electromagnetic waves (j) and
atmospheric ions in the central white-colored ball through ion-acoustic waves
(IAW) (k). Centrifugal forces (l) caused by the rotation of the central white ball
(m) can eject its hot and cold poles, forming, respectively, blue and red light
balls.
IAW is a longitudinal oscillation of the ions (and the electrons) much like
acoustic waves traveling in neutral gas. The IAW velocity will be (Alexeff &
Neidigh, 1961):
e Z i k BTe i k BTi
VIAW (1)
mi
where kB is Boltzmann’s constant, ‹mi› is the mean mass of the ion, Zi is its
charge, Te is the temperature of the electrons, and Ti is the temperature of the ions.
Normally γe is taken to be unity, on the grounds that the thermal conductivity
of electrons is large enough to keep them isothermal on the time scale of ionic
acoustic waves, and γi is taken to be 3, corresponding to one-dimensional motion.
In the plasma the electrons are often much hotter than the ions, in which case the
second term in the numerator can be ignored. Thus, we have:
e Z i k BTe
VIAW ~
mi (2)
mi (O ) mi ( N )
mi
2 (3)
where mi(O+) = 2.3 × 10−16 kg is the ionic oxygen mass, and mi(N+) = 2.6 ×
10−16 kg is the ionic nitrogen mass, we have VIAW ~ 104 ms−1. This is the velocity
of the energetic wave packet of an ion acoustic wave in a dusty plasma. This
740 Gerson S. Paiva and Carlton A. Taft
value is close to the observed velocity of some ejected light balls from HL,
which is estimated as being 2 × 104 ms−1 (Teodorani, 2004).
Night vision systems revealed that the HL phenomenon produces a very
strong infrared signature even when it is very faint or invisible in the optical
range (Teodorani & Nobili, 2002). The dissociative recombination of N2+ in
excited neutral atoms can explain the infrared emission by HL phenomenon
even when it is very faint or invisible in the optical range. When VLF eject
ions in high velocity from a white ball by IAW, dissociative recombination of
N2+ [i.e. destroying molecular ions to produce excited neutral atomic species]
can occur through the reaction N2+ + e− → N + N + kinetic energy (Kasner,
1967). Dissociative recombination (DR) exhibits a high exothermicity, which
makes DR the only source of kinetically energetic atoms (>1eV) (Peterson,
Le Padellec, Danared, Dunn, Larsson, et al., 1998). These species (i.e. excited
nitrogen atoms) are disconnected by IAW because they have zero charge. Few
experimental studies of recombination have been carried out under conditions
where dissociative recombination is the predominant process (Fowler &
Atkinson, 1959). It will be the predominant electron loss process in the plasma
only in regions where the concentration ratio of atomic to molecular ions is >l04
(Biondi, 1969).
Why is the ejected ball always green-colored? Ejection of a small green
light ball from HL is due to radiation pressure produced by the interaction
between very low frequency electromagnetic waves (VLF) and atmospheric
ions (present in the central white-colored ball) through ion-acoustic
waves (IAW) (See Figure 1). Probably only O2+ ions (electronic transition
(b4Σg– → a4Πu)), with green emission lines, are predominantly transported
by IAW. Electronic bands of O2+ ions occur in auroral spectra (Chamberlain,
1961, Nicolet & Dogniaux, 1950). Electron–molecular-ion dissociative
recombination coefficient rate α as functions of electron temperature Te and
cross sections σ as a function of electron energy E have been measured by
Mehr and Biondi (1969) for N2+ and O2+ over the electron temperature interval
0.007 to 10 eV. The estimated temperature of HL is about 5,000 K (Teodorani,
2004). At this temperature, the rate coefficient of dissociative recombination
will be, respectively, α(Te)O2+ ~ 10−8 cm3 s−1, and α(Te)N2+ ~ 10−7 cm3 s−1. Thus,
the nitrogen ions will be decomposed in N2+ + e− → N + N* more rapidly than
oxygen ions in the HL plasma. Only ionic-species are transported by IAW.
Therefore, only oxygen ions will be predominantly ejected by IAW from a
central white ball in HL phenomenon forming high-velocity green-light balls
presenting a negative band of O2+ with electronic transition b4Σg− → a4Πu.
Additionally, the first positive bands of N2(1PN2, electronic transition B3Πg →
A3Σu+) make a distinct contribution to the source spectrum of red balls, while
the second positive band of N2(2PN2, electronic transition C3Πu → B3Πg) and
Colored Light Balls in Hessdalen Lights 741
the first negative band of N2+ (1NN2+, electronic transition B2Σu+ → X2Σg+) play
a minor role since they are caused by high-energy electrons—both bands are
responsible for blue-colored balls around the central white ball in HL (Wescott,
Sentman, Heavner, Hallinan, Hampton, & Osborne, 1996).
Relativistic runaway electron avalanche (RREA) is an avalanche growth of
a population of relativistic electrons driven through a material (typically air) by
an electric field. RREA has been hypothesized to be related to lightning initiation
(Gurevich & Zybin, 2005), terrestrial gamma-ray flashes (Dwyer & Smith, 2005),
and red sprites (Lehtinen, Bell, & Inan, 1999), and it is unique that it can occur
at electric fields an order of magnitude lower than the dielectric strength of the
material. When an electric field is applied to a material, free electrons will drift
slowly through the material as described by electron mobility. For low-energy
electrons, faster drift implies higher friction, so the drift speed tends to stabilize.
For electrons with energy above about 1 keV, however, higher speeds imply lower
friction. An electron with a sufficiently high energy, therefore, may be accelerated
by an electric field to even higher and higher energies, encountering less and
less friction as it accelerates. Such an electron is described as a “runaway.” Free
electrons with the density of 4 × 106 to 1 × 107 electrons m−3 s−1 are generated by
cosmic rays and natural radiation due to atmospheric radioactivity (Paiva & Taft,
2011). The electric field generated by the rock fracture or stress induces charges
on the ground that accelerate these electrons which ionize or excite N2 and
O2 molecules in the air, forming the electron avalanche by RREA. Indentation
fracture of moist andesite (under wet conditions) can produce a net negative
charge density of about 0.6 C m−3 s−1. Typical occurrence altitude of the HL
phenomenon is generally very low (a few tens of meters over the treetops), and
the vast majority of the lights were reported to be below the tops of mountains
(Bjorn, 2007). Mountainous soil has a mean dielectric constant (permittivity)
εs ~ 5 (Saveskie, 2000). Thus, the electric potential in the air on the failure will
be ΔV = q/4π εsε0 = 2.2 GV. Let us calculate the electron number produced
by the runaway electron avalanche (RREA) mechanism in HL phenomenon.
The runaway electron avalanche multiplication factor is given by Dwyer (2003,
2007):
V 2.13 106 I
N RE exp (4)
7.3 106
104 electrons. This value is 1012 times lower than that responsible for terrestrial
gamma ray flashes in high altitudes on thunderclouds (Paiva, Pavão, & Bastos,
2009). Finally, high luminosity white balls around a central white ball are formed
by a fragmentation process of Hessdalen lights–like dusty plasmas (Paiva &
Taft, 2011). According to Teodorani (2004), sudden appearance of satellite
light balls around a common nucleus can be related to the re-minimization of
the effective surface energy (with the formation of new condensation nuclei)
predicted by Turner’s ball lightning model (Turner, 2003). However, several
chemical species from rocks, such as scandium and silicon ions, were detected
in the HL spectrum, suggesting dust from the valley (Bjorn, 2007). Thus, HL
can sometimes assume the dusty plasma structure (Paiva & Taft, 2010). In this
case, fragmentation of HL in a cluster of light balls can be produced by the
interaction of low-frequency electromagnetic waves through the dust-acoustic
waves. It is known that laboratory dusty plasmas are longitudinally fragmented
by dust-acoustic waves (Barkan, Merlino, & D’Angelo, 1995). Similarly, video
images show linear fragmentation of atmospheric light balls (UFO Hessdalen
Norway, 2010, Amazing REAL looking UFO Sightings in INDIA, 2008). Dusty
acoustic waves (DAW) is a complete analog to the common ionic-acoustic
wave, where the dust particles take the role of the ions and ions and electrons
take the role of the electrons (Thompson, Barkan, D’Angelo, & Merlino, 1997),
and is an extremely low-velocity normal mode of a three-component dusty
plasma comprising electrons, ions, and massive micrometer-size charged dust
grains.
Conclusion
The appearance of “satellite spheres,” presenting different colors and intensities,
composing a cluster around a main nuclear region, is produced by the interaction
between high-energy electrons and very low frequency electromagnetic waves
and atmospheric steady plasmas. A very strong infrared signature even when
HL is very faint or invisible in the optical range is produced by the dissociative
recombination of N2+ in excited neutral atoms (i.e. with high kinetic energy)
in regions where the concentration ratio of atomic to molecular ions in the
plasma is >l04 (Biondi, 1969). Probably other related characteristics of HL
can be explained by the high-energy electrons (accelerated by the RREA
avalanche mechanism) accelerated in the atmosphere by electric fields from
fractured rocks, or by the interaction between very low frequencies (from
ground) and ions or charged dust particles in the atmospheric plasmas. Several
chemical species from rocks, such as scandium and silicon ions, were detected
in the HL spectrum (Bjorn, 2007) suggesting dust from the valley. Thus, HL
can sometimes assume the dusty plasma structure (Paiva & Taft, 2010). The
spectrum of the Hessdalen light phenomenon appears to be a continuum with
Colored Light Balls in Hessdalen Lights 743
SRT principle. For example, quantum tunneling between deuterium nuclei can
occur in HL phenomenon. In this process a particle passes through a potential
barrier that it classically could not surmount. Winter is the season of Hessdalen
Lights, when water is abundant. About one in every 6,000 water molecules
contains deuterium atoms. On the other side, experiments on board the MIR
orbital station (1991), the ISS (International Space Station) (2002), and the
Kolibri-2000 satellite (2002) at an altitude of 400 km detected neutron bursts
(one signature of nuclear fusion) in the equator regions connected with lightning
discharges (Paiva, 2009). Whether these neutrons are thermonuclear in origin
or are generated by photonuclear processes, this remains to be experimentally
determined. In the case of HL, the mechanism responsible for helium emissions
needs to be elucidated. Another possibility is that the helium comes from inside
rocks. Fractured rocks can liberate helium ions which emit light when they
recapture electrons in the atmosphere. In fact, there are rocks (for example,
uraninite) that release helium from the natural decay of uranium.
Acknowledgments
We acknowledge financial support from CNPq and Faperj (Brazil).
References
Alexeff, I., & Neidigh, R. V. (1961). Observations of ion sound waves in plasmas. Physical Review
Letters, 7, 223–225.
Amazing REAL looking UFO Sightings in INDIA Jan 26 2008 (2008/2011). http://www.youtube.com/
watch?v=pSKu2tlgoRY&feature=related
Bacioiu, I. (2011). The theoretical interpretation of some cosmic rays reaching sea-level and the
Meson Theory. Romanian Reports in Physics, 63, 161–171.
Barkan, A., Merlino, R. L., & D’Angelo, N. (1995). Laboratory observation of the dusty-acoustic
wave mode. Physics of Plasmas, 2, 3563–3565.
Biondi, M. A. (1969). Atmospheric electron–ion and ion–ion recombination processes. Canadian
Journal of Chemistry, 47, 1711–1719.
Bjorn, G. H. (2007). Optical Spectrum Analysis of the Hessdalen Phenomenon. Preliminary Report.
pp. 1–12.
Chamberlain, J. W. (1961). Physics of the Aurora and Air-Glow. New York: Academic Press.
Dwyer, J. R. (2003). A fundamental limit on electric fields in air. Geophysical Research Letters,
30, 2055.
Dwyer, J. R. (2007). Relativistic breakdown in planetary atmospheres. Physics of Plasmas, 14,
042901-042901-17.
Dwyer, J. R., & Smith, D. M. (2005). A comparison between Monte Carlo simulations of runaway
breakdown and terrestrial gamma-ray flash observations. Geophysical Research Letters,
32, L22804.
Enomoto, Y., & Hashimoto, H. (1990). Emission of charged particles from indentation fracture of
rocks. Nature, 346, 641.
Fowler, R. G., & Atkinson, W. R. (1959). Electron recombination in atomic hydrogen. Phvsical
Review, 113, 1268.
Gurevich, A. V., & Zybin, K. P. (2005). Runaway breakdown and the mysteries of lightning.
Physics Today, 58(5), 37.
Colored Light Balls in Hessdalen Lights 745
COMMENTARY
NEAL GROSSMAN
Department of Philosophy, University of Illinois at Chicago
the epistemological absolutism that pervades both the strident anti-psi and
pro-psi proponents from what I consider a healthy abeyance from fully com-
mitting to a closed position in science or in other aspects of life. (Cardeña,
p. 539)
747
748 Neal Grossman
In what follows, I shall use the expression “the data” to refer to empirical
data collected by parapsychologists and survival researchers over the past 130
years. The term “evidence” is a relational term, and is used in conjunction
with a specific hypothesis for which the data are alleged to be evidence. The
specific hypothesis for which the data are taken to be evidence in this case can
be and has been formulated in many different ways: (i) Materialism is false, (ii)
consciousness is not produced by the brain, (iii) the mind can acquire information
that is not mediated by the body’s sensory channels, (iv) the consciousness
that constitutes our self continues after the death of the body. Although we
may quibble over this, I take these to be roughly equivalent formulations of
the same underlying hypothesis. Perhaps we can agree to use William James’
formulation: The brain is a transmitter, not a producer, of consciousness.
The epistemological question here is how strong is the data as evidence
for our hypothesis, or, to shorten it, how good is the evidence? From a logical
perspective, there are three possible points of view, corresponding to the logical
quantifiers: (1) no, (2) some, and (3) all.
(1) The data does not constitute any evidence (against Materialism) at
all. This is the perspective of Materialist ideologues, who usually reach this
conclusion without examining the data, then project their conclusion onto
whatever data, if any, they examine. This is what frustrates Cardeña the most,
and I agree.
(2) The collective data constitute some evidence against Materialism, but
it is hardly conclusive, and much more research is needed. I believe that this is
the epistemological perspective of most practicing parapsychologists, including
Cardeña.
But some scientists and philosophers, who have studied the data, have
concluded that (3) the data as they now stands is sufficiently strong to conclude
that James’ hypothesis is correct. More data are of course always welcome,
but the data already obtained is evidentially sufficiently strong to assert that
Materialism is false.
Now for decades our efforts have been rightly directed against the deniers
(1) . . . those who deny that the data constitute any evidence against Materialism.
That is, those who belong to the (2)nd and (3)rd epistemological perspectives
have been so united in our efforts against the Materialist ideologues, that we
have perhaps failed to notice the major epistemological differences among
ourselves. This is the elephant in our living room.
Cardeña’s off-the-wall ridicule of me began to make some sense to me
when I tried to see how things look to someone who is committed to the (2)nd
epistemological perspective. In the next two paragraphs I will try to examine
how each perspective looks from the vantage point of the other perspective.
So let us suppose, as Cardeña does, that we believe the (2)nd perspective
On Elephants and Matters Epistemological 749
On the other side, we have the milder contempt of Grossman stating that who-
ever holds a Materialist perspective is not “a responsible investigator” and is
dogmatic and “irrational.” He also stated that those who succeed academically
do so not on the grounds of “talent, but mostly on competition, self-promotion,
and so forth.” He also implies that anyone disagreeing with his conclusion has
not accepted the primacy of love. (Cardeña, p. 544)
Cardeña’s last sentence here is so outrageous that I will not dignify it with a
reply. But let’s take a look at the first sentence. All of Cardeña’s quotes from my
work are taken from a Foreword I wrote to Chris Carter’s book, Science and the
Near-Death Experience. In the Foreword, I had quoted the following passage
from Kelly, Kelly, Crabtree, Gauld, Grosso, & Greyson (2007:421):
Given that there is a large body of empirical data that (i) is highly relevant to
this question and (ii) has convinced virtually everyone that has taken the time
to examine it that Materialism cannot explain it, I find myself agreeing with
On Elephants and Matters Epistemological 751
Those who have read Cardeña’s Guest Editorial will know that this sentence
is in complete agreement with everything Cardeña has to say regarding our
Materialist colleagues who refuse to look at the data. Yet when I say it, I am
expressing “contempt.”
Perhaps I crossed a line here by using the word love, and perhaps it was
the use of this word that, in Cardeña’s mind, triggered an association with New
Age Fluff. But my Foreword was to a book on the near-death experience, and
the concept of unconditional love plays an indispensable role to everyone who
has had an NDE. It is well-documented that one of the main difficulties, perhaps
“the” main difficulty that NDErs have, is in returning to a world that is not
organized around the principles of unconditional love that they experience in
their NDE. This “unconditional love” business is something that those of us
in the (3)rd epistemological category are obliged to take very seriously. If we
are convinced that the NDE is real (this does not apply to the inhabitants
of the (2)nd epistemological category), and if we are concerned to understand
the nature of this consciousness that we now know is a fundamental existent,
and if we wish to remain empirical in our undertakings, then it is incumbent
upon us to seriously examine the testimony of those who have experienced
consciousness in itself, independent of the body: mystics and NDErs. They all
speak to the issue of Love, and validate Ken Ring’s suggestion that the Golden
Rule is how we are supposed to live our lives.
This forces one to think about the meaning of the Golden Rule in an entirely
new way. Most of us are accustomed to regard it mainly as a precept for moral
action. . . . But in the light of these life review commentaries, the Golden Rule
is much more than that—it is actually the way it works. Familiar exhortations,
such as “Love your Brother as Yourself” from this point of view are under-
stood to mean that in the life review, you are your brother you have been urged
to love. And this is no mere intellectual conviction or even a religious credo—
it is an undeniable fact of your lived experience. (Ring, 1998:161–162)
I did not merely come to believe, but I saw that the universe is not composed
of dead matter, but is, on the contrary, a living Presence; I became conscious in
myself of eternal life. . . . I saw that all men are immortal; that the cosmic order
is such that without any peradventure all things work together for the good of
each and all; that the foundation principle of the world, of all the worlds, is
what we call love. . . . (James, 1994:435; also Tart, 2010:330)
752 Neal Grossman
the titles of their books. Their conclusions are, respectively, that consciousness
continues after the death of the body, that Materialism has been falsified by
science, that the human mind is not reducible to the brain, that the Universe is
conscious, and that consciousness exists prior to birth. These scientists did not
arrive at their conclusions by attending “New Age Fairs” or overdosing on “The
Secret type of New Age theories” (Cardeña, p. 548). No. Their conclusions
were arrived at only after a meticulous and exhaustive examination of all the
relevant empirical data, together with a detailed analysis and refutation of all
alternative hypotheses. If Cardeña does not like their conclusions, then I invite
him, and others who feel as he does, to accept the challenge, as my students did,
to go deeply into the subject matter, and to examine their arguments, and tell us
where they are mistaken in their reasoning. And if you cannot find any errors in
their argumentation, as I could not, then is it not incumbent on you, as a scientist
and rational human being, to embrace their conclusion that “consciousness can
exist independent of the brain and that Materialism is therefore empirically
false” (Grossman, cited disapprovingly in Cardeña, p. 541)?
References
Cardeña, E. (2011). On Wolverines and Epistemological Totalitarianism. Journal of Scientific
Exploration, 25(3), 539–551.
Grossman, N. (2010). Foreword to Science and the Near-Death Experience: How Consciousness
Survives Death by Chris Carter. Inner Traditions.
James, W. (1994). The Varieties of Religious Experience: A Study in Human Nature. Modern
Library.
Kelly, E. F., Kelly, E. W., Crabtree, A., Gauld, A., Grosso, M., & Greyson, B. (2007). Irreducible
Mind: Toward a Psychology for the 21st Century. Rowman & Littlefield. p. 421.
Radin, D. (1997). The Conscious Universe: The Scientific Truth of Psychic Phenomena.
HarperCollins.
Ring, K. (1998). Lessons from the Light: What We Can Learn from the Near-Death Experience.
Moment Point Press.
Tart, C. (2010). The End of Materialism: How Evidence of the Paranormal Is Bringing Science and
Spirit Together. New Harbinger Publications.
Tucker, J. (2005). Life Before Life: Children’s Memories of Previous Lives. St. Martin’s Press.
van Lommel, P. (2010). Consciousness beyond Life: The Science of the Near-Death Experience.
HarperOne.
Journal of Scientific Exploration, Vol. 25, No. 4, p. 754, 2011 0892-3310/11
RESPONSE
ETZEL CARDEÑA
Department of Psychology, Center for Research on Consciousness and Anomalous
Psychology (CERCAP), Lund University, P.O. Box 213 SE-221 00, Lund, Sweden
In his long Reply, Professor Grossman opines that my Guest Editorial is “little
more than a rant.” Although rant can be interpreted as a “wild revel,” even
without telepathic means I strongly doubt that that is what he had in mind.
Contrary to what the reader might conclude from his statements, my essay was
not at all an attack against the probable reality of psi phenomena, something that
I have supported repeatedly, nor a defense of Materialism. Instead, it criticized
epistemological totalitarianisms that endorse absolute and simplistic certainties
regarding psi or other issues and consider any disagreement with their positions
or interpretations, no matter how large or small, as lacking in reasonableness,
love, or whatever. As to the charge that I misrepresented Professor Grossman,
I provided quotations along with their source, so the reader can judge whether
I was fair or not. But more telling, I believe, is that Professor Grossman’s letter
exemplifies the problem I was describing better than I could in a limited space.
Therefore I will cede the last word to, in my view, the brightest mind we have
had in parapsychology, William James. He held that psi phenomena were real,
but instead of assuming that he completely or finally understood this issue (or
any other topic), he challenged us to develop “the habit of always seeing an
alternative” (James, 1896:4).
Reference
James, W. (1896/1978). The Teaching of Philosophy in Our Colleges. In Essays in Philosophy,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, pp. 3–6. [Original work published 1876]
Journal of Scientific Exploration, Vol. 25, No. 4, pp. 755–773, 2011 0892-3310/11
HISTORICAL PERSPECTIVE
Ernesto Bozzano:
An Italian Spiritualist and Psychical Researcher
LUCA GASPERINI
[email protected]
Introduction
Ernesto Bozzano (1862–1943) was probably the most important Italian
representative of psychical and spiritualistic studies before the 1940s, as
well as one of the few to emerge on the international scene, thanks to his
numerous publications which gained him the esteem of scientists, philosophers,
and psychical researchers. He was at the center of an intense network of
correspondence with Italian, European, and American intellectuals, receiving
an average of 200 letters a month, and was furthermore one of the few Italian
scholars to have been named an honorary member of the Society for Psychical
Research (SPR), the American Society for Psychical Research (ASPR), and the
Institut Métapsychique International (IMI). Despite the fact that the academic
historian Bruno Di Porto (1933) wrote a description of him for the Dizionario
Biografico degli Italiani (Di Porto),1 an element which testifies to his relevance,
Bozzano is completely unknown in Italy to those who do not deal with the
history of psychical research. However, this did not prevent Italian scholars
from continuing to remember him (e.g., Biondi, 1988, Inardi & Ianuzzo, 1981,
Macaluso, 1972, Orlandi, 1971) or his works from continuing to be reprinted,
even recently, in journals or by specialized publishers (e.g., Bozzano, 1948a,
755
756 Luca Gasperini
1957a, 1967a, 1972, 1975, 1982, 1998a, 2001, 2008). Still cited in France (e.g.,
Clauzure, 1983, Dumas, 1973), Bozzano does not appear in some important
historical accounts of Anglo-Saxon psychical research (e.g., Beloff, 1993,
Inglis, 1977) but does appear in the bibliographies of various authors of the
same linguistic group (e.g., Stevenson, 1977, Van de Castle, 1977). Only
beginning in 1982–1983, coinciding with the fortieth anniversary of his death,
did some historians of psychical research begin to study him in more depth
(Biondi, 1984, Iannuzzo, 1982, 1983a, 1983b, Ravaldini, 1983). From this
renewed interest, there were only two critical volumes regarding Bozzano
taken as a whole (Iannuzzo, 1983b, Ravaldini, 1993a), and some more recent
articles that examine specific aspects of his biography or works (Alvarado,
1986, 1989, 2003, 2005, 2006, 2008, Biondi, 2010, Caratelli, 1998, Cellina,
1993, Cugnaschi, 2002).
In addition, there are the first biographical articles written by his disciple
Gastone De Boni (1908–1986) (the main ones being De Boni, 1941, 1946,
1947). There are also some autobiographical articles written by Bozzano
in his old age, which are usable with reservations (Bozzano, 1924c, 1930a,
1938a, 1939). For a more in-depth study, it is however indispensable to refer
to unpublished primary sources, among which the correspondence between
Bozzano and De Boni is indispensable for reconstructing his life.2
The present article has, as its objective, a brief presentation of the life,
works, and thinking of Ernesto Bozzano.
Biographical Profile
Ernesto Bozzano was born in Genoa on January 9, 1862, the fourth son of a
lower-middle-class Genoese family, but we know very little of his childhood,
in reality of his entire life up to 1928; by his own admission, that part of his life
was without relevant biographical events, so much so that the only information
conserved regards his intellectual life. He had an early vocation for study for
which he received no support since, when he was fourteen years old, he was
taken out of school in order to begin a commercial career. Other than this brief
experience of work in his youth and a similar brief journalistic collaboration
with the Genoese daily newspaper Il Secolo XIX around 1893, of which there
is no trace, he never needed to work. Since he lived with his brother Vittorio
(1860–?), and was in part economically supported by his well-to-do brother
Adolfo (1859–?) and probably had a small income sufficient to maintain a
secluded lifestyle, Bozzano was able to dedicate all his time to studying and
writing. In fact, he managed to study by himself, dedicating himself first to
poetry and literature, then to the sciences, and finally to philosophy, his great
passion. He became a supporter of positivism and a fervent follower of the
British philosopher Herbert Spencer (1820–1903) who, in the 1880s, was
Ernesto Bozzano: Italian Spiritualist Researcher 757
memory, identity, and its own other supernormal faculties, thus ending up
with independence of the spirit from the body and subordination of the brain
to the mind. He reached this conclusion after having analyzed four categories
of phenomena. The first included the cases of sensitivity in amputees and
hemiplegics; discarding the neurological explanations, Bozzano believed he
was dealing with the initial levels of bilocation. In the second, we find the cases
in which a subject would see his own double; although accepting the possible
pathological explanation with reserve, for Bozzano these cases represented, as
a general rule, the second level of incipient bilocation, the transition between
being both inside and outside one’s own body. In the third group, he placed all
the cases in which consciousness would be completely transferred to the etheric
double which verified the sensation of seeing reality from a position external to
one’s own physical body. Finally, in the fourth group, there were the cases in
which the etheric double was seen by one or more people. Considering all the
categories cumulatively and taking the cases of this last group as crucial proof
of their intersubjectivity, Bozzano thought he had scientifically deduced some
conclusions from some facts that were evident for him but which were often
not “self-evident facts” but rather an “interpretation of the cases he considered”
(Alvarado, 2005:228). In any case, in order to understand his methods, a
quotation from his work can be useful:
If, for Bozzano, the phenomena of bilocation represented the passage from
animism to spiritism, the phenomena of transcendental music dealt with in the
monograph Musica Trascendentale (Transcendental Music) (Bozzano, 1982)
were instead of clear spiritual genesis. In this monograph, he subdivided the
phenomena into six classes, even if, dealing with animistic phenomena, he
dedicated less space to the first two (musical mediumship and transcendental
music with telepathic externalization). The classes of transcendental music of
haunting origin, of music perceived without a relationship to events dealing
with death, music at the deathbed, and music which is manifested after an event
dealing with death would instead be, cumulatively taken, reliable testimony of
spiritual intervention. In fact, from the moment that musical phenomenology was
often externalized together with apparitions of the dead person at the deathbed, in
such a way as to prove the spiritual identification of a dear deceased person who
comes to assist the dying person, because of the numerous cases in which music
Ernesto Bozzano: Italian Spiritualist Researcher 759
Scientifico Minerva about thirty years earlier (Bozzano, 1903), were the only
two experiments worth noting in the course of his research, which was otherwise
carried out almost exclusively in written analyses of books and articles. Space
does not permit the chronicling of the eloquent and detailed accounts of the
seances that Bozzano published; however, according to those who have written
about it, it seems that the scholar went to the seances, on both occasions,
already profoundly convinced of the reality of the facts to which he would have
attested, and of the authenticity of the mediums. This can be deduced by his
lack of doubts and from his critical tone against the skeptics (e.g., Bozzano,
1903:362–363) as well as from the clearly demonstrative presentation of the
events narrated, not simple events to explain to readers and to assess critically,
but compelling results of experimentation demonstrating the intervention
of disincarnate intelligence. Our affirmation is also supported by the weight
Bozzano gave to the evidence of the facts and, in particular, to psychological
control: To whoever contested the lack of verification of the mediums at the
seances of Millesimo, he responded that their psychological profile, namely
being aristocrats, cultured, and rich, meant therefore automatically that they
were not interested in committing fraud, as well as the clear evidence for
paranormal phenomenology could not but render clearly truthful all his
accounts and exempt him from subjecting the mediums to humiliating anti-
fraud verification (e.g., Bozzano, 1929a). Let us be clear, we do not want to
insinuate anything nefarious regarding the Genoese psychical researcher and
his honesty, but simply to demonstrate how his behavior could seem suspect, or
at least naïve, to many of his contemporaries.
Thanks to the wide dissemination of his writings, Bozzano managed to
begin a correspondence and friendship not only with Conan Doyle but also
with many other psychical researchers, scientists, and philosophers of that era,
such as William Crookes (1832–1919), Henry Sidgwick (1838–1900), Oliver
Lodge (1851–1940), Camille Flammarion (1842–1925), and James Hyslop
(1854–1920), with the Italian philosopher and psychologist Angelo Brofferio
(1846–1894), with Italian psychiatrists Enrico Morselli and Cesare Lombroso
(1835–1909), and also with many others (Letter from Genoa, 6 October 1942,
unpublished, in Bozzano & De Boni, 1930–1943). But he also received a lot of
letters from non-scholars who were greatly consoled by him and the doctrines
he proposed. Unfortunately, almost all his correspondence has been lost
(Ravaldini, 1993a:73–76).
But, as the Gospel says: nemo propheta in patria [never a prophet in his
own country]. In fact, in Italy, the works of Bozzano were not very well-known
outside the circle of readers of Lo or its staff; of these, positive comments on
his works came, other than from De Boni (e.g., De Boni, 1946, 1947), from
two important Italian psychical researchers, Emilio Servadio (1904–1995), who
Ernesto Bozzano: Italian Spiritualist Researcher 763
extolled the argumentative force of Bozzano (Servadio 1931, 1934), and from
Antonio Bruers (1880–1954), who was certainly more cautious regarding the
Genoese scholar in accepting the evidence of some alleged spiritualistic facts
(Bruers, 1929, 1930). The situation greatly improved when De Boni made an
agreement with the publisher L’Albero of Verona (Italy) and began publishing
the opera omnia of Bozzano5; the first volume Popoli Primitivi e Manifestazioni
Supernormali (Primitive Cultures and Supernormal Manifestations) in 1941
(Bozzano, 1941)6 was a big success and attracted the attention of a goodly
number of Italian intellectuals, above all anthropologists and religious and
oriental historians such as Giuseppe Tucci (1894–1984), Raffaele Pettazzoni
(1883–1959), and Ernesto de Martino (1908–1965), who critiqued it in
newpapers and specialized journals (e.g., de Martino, 1941, Gasperini, 2011)
and began a brief correspondence with Bozzano (unpublished correspondence).
Outside of Italy, an enthusiastic reader of Popoli Primitivi was Carl Gustav
Jung (1875–1961) (De Boni, 1949).
Bozzano died on June 24, 1943, from circulatory complications, and his
death was mentioned in Italian and French spiritualistic and psychical journals
(De Boni, 1947, Necrologie, 1946, Weissenbach, 1949).
All in all, the spiritic hypothesis is quite simple; the vast amount of the
writings and subjects that he produced to support it is, if anything, magnificent
and is Bozzano’s real contribution to psychical research. Above all, the
discourse on the autonomy of “subconscious supernormal faculties,” namely
the faculties of the incarnate spirit which is positioned in the subconscious,
is, to all effects, the reservoir for psychic phenomena. For example, the fact
that telepathy and clairvoyance emerged on rare occasions of severe physical
and psychical weakening, as the mediums and people in the state of mesmeric
sleep demonstrated, for Bozzano meant that they were completely useless in
this life since the potential senses of the incarnate spirit would become real
only when this spirit would have passed through the crisis of death (Bozzano,
1899, 1924d). For Bozzano, another strong proof in favor of the autonomy of
the bodily spirit was the evident independence of supernormal faculties from
the laws of natural selection, based on their uselessness in the struggle for life
(Bozzano, 1923c). Bozzano resolved the mind–body problem utilizing the
concept of the etheric body which envelops the incarnate spirit linking it to
the body but is also capable of breaking off, bringing with it the individual
consciousness and the integral subconscious memory contained in the etheric
brain, the true seat of thinking for which the somatic brain only serves as an
interpreter of physical sensations (Bozzano, 1930c, 1931).9
From the preceding considerations, together with the conviction that the
spirit is also present in animals, with them having the same subconscious
faculties as man (Bozzano, 1975), and the belief in the faculty of thought and
willingness to mould the subject which, according to Bozzano, appeared to
emerge from the phenomena of ideoplasty and ectoplasmy (Bozzano, 1967b,
1967c), Bozzano deduced a cosmological theory reconstructable from some
Ernesto Bozzano: Italian Spiritualist Researcher 765
Conclusion
Bozzano was deeply convinced of his Spiritistic hypothesis and therefore
spent 50 years of his life collecting his immense paranormal record of cases in
order to demonstrate them scientifically, so that no one could any longer voice
doubts about them. He built a solid reputation as a psychical researcher, but
it is evident that the image which has survived is that of a spiritualist (Fodor,
1933:36). If we keep this in mind, together with the fact that, since the 1930s,
parapsychology has moved on different tracks from those of Bozzano and
has, above all, become a discipline conducted in the English language (e.g.,
Mauskopf & McVaugh, 1980), and that in Italy this area of study is languishing,
we can form a rough idea of why the conclusions of Bozzano have not recently
been taken into consideration.
In effect, the methods of Bozzano, which Iannuzzo (1983a) defined as
observational and naturalistic and which we can also call bibliographic, must
have seemed rather simplistic to the parapsychologists of the experimental
school. In fact, he not only made exclusive use of qualitative sources but
refused to adopt the experimental method, believing that it was not worthwhile
(Ravaldini, 1993b:129), and, as was contested so many times (e.g., Di Porto,
no year, Inardi & Iannuzzo, 1981), by taking the facts reported in the literature
as immediately valid, he ended up assuming an uncritical attitude toward his
own sources.
Ernesto Bozzano: Italian Spiritualist Researcher 767
Notes
1
The Dizionario Biografico degli Italiani (acronym: DBI) is a work of highly respected
scientific value edited by the Institute of the Italian Encyclopedia, begun in 1925
and still not completed; its aim is to gather approximately 40,000 biographies having
rich bibliographies and edited by scholars, of as many illustrious Italians. Paper
publication has been interrupted, and it is now possible to consult it online at http://
www.treccani.it/Portale/ricerche/searchBiografie.html
2
His collection of letters is conserved at the Bozzano–De Boni Library Foundation in
Bologna (Italy) and includes 450 letters, of which 275 are unpublished. Those from
1928 to 1936 have been published (De Boni, 1974, 1975, 1976, 1977, 1978), and while
those from 1930 to 1936 have been published, with, however, some letters missing,
the bulk of the unpublished correspondence is from 1937 to 1943. In addition to the
published writings of Bozzano, approximately 150 binders of additional unpublished
material are conserved at the Foundation among which much other correspondence
and various collections of notes, citations, drafts of articles, and monographs never
published and even manuscripts of some of his most important publications are found.
The Foundation, which also publishes the journal Luce e Ombra and is one of the
most important Italian libraries of the history of spiritualism and psychical research,
is the only association which is involved in keeping the memory of Bozzano alive. For
further information, see http://www.bibliotecabozzanodeboni.it
3
Richet and Bozzano shared a professional friendship as is seen by their letters
which have been conserved. Thanks to these letters, we know that the French
scholar frequently sent his own publications dedicated to Bozzano, and many
times he proposed publishing a collection of all Bozzano’s works at his own
expense; furthermore, initially antispiritualistic, Richet attributed his attraction to
the spiritualistic hypothesis to reading Bozzano’s works. See Bozzano (1924a) and
unpublished letters: Richet–Bozzano, Paris, 14 May 1935, Paris, 31 May 1935, Paris,
28 June 1935.
4
Utilizing the unpublished material of the Bozzano–De Boni collection of letters,
Biondi (2009) strongly questioned the honesty of Bozzano and De Boni regarding
the events at Millesimo, quoting, in particular, their involvement in keeping secret the
Centurione Scotto fraud in the seance on July 29, 1928, and that of George Valiantine
in successive seances with the group of Millesimo, whose accounts have never been
published.
5
Although De Boni (1941), with regard to the complete edition of Bozzano’s writings,
indicated 15,000 pages in more than 50 volumes, in the end he chose 17 writings,
768 Luca Gasperini
those more theoretically important which had been updated with new material by
Bozzano between 1939 and 1943 (De Boni, 1946). Until the 1970s, De Boni did his
best to enable everybody to see the light, relying on various Italian publishing houses,
also including Editrice Luce e Ombra which was refounded by him in 1967.
6
The majority of Bozzano’s books are monographs, specific studies on a category
of metapsychical phenomena, but Popoli Primitivi is one of the few writings to
veer away from his usual theme; with this, he attempted to shed light on the entire
paranormal phenomena of the cultures which the anthropology of that era defined as
primitive, principally African peoples, but also including Indians, Aborigines, and
Maori, in order to find the occidental case records (generated not by mediums but by
yogin, shamans, and medicine men) and the solution to the question of the origin of
religions (the observation of spiritualistic facts).
7
The only vaguely systematic work, written in 1938 (the definitive and quite different
edition was published in 1967), and for this reason definable as the clear synthesis of
his 50 years of work, is Animismo o Spiritismo? Quale dei Due Spiega il Complesso
dei Fatti? (Bozzano, 1967a). The 1938 work was also translated into English as
Discarnate Influence in Human Life (Bozzano, 1938b).
8
For the formulation of this hypothesis, Bozzano was greatly inspired by the work of
Aksakof (1890) which he read in French in 1895 (Aksakof, 1895). There, in fact, we
find (I consulted the Italian translation: Aksakof, 1912) the complete formulation of
many of the points of Bozzano’s metapsychical philosophy, such as the distinction
between animistic and spiritistic phenomena, the theory according to which animistic
phenomena reside in the subconscious and are proof of the existence of an immortal
spirit free of the body, and also the importance of spiritualistic communication with
cases of identification of the deceased as the main proof in favor of survival.
9
For a more in-depth study of Bozzano (1931), also in relation to the most recent
reports of a life review in parapsychology events, see Biondi, 2010.
10
In the category of the phenomena of bilocation, Bozzano inserted a class of facts
corresponding to today’s out-of-body experiences, which, although not being
classified as such and explanations of which resorted to hypotheses of the ethereal
body and survival, had been studied for a long time. For a close examination of this
history which also deals with Bozzano from the nineteenth century until the 1980s,
see Alvarado, 1989. For a specific study of Bozzano and the phenomena of bilocation,
see Alvarado, 2005.
11
For a historical summary of these and other phenomena linked to near-death
experiences, see Alvarado, 2006. For a specific study of this monograph of Bozzano,
see Alvarado, 2008.
Acknowledgments
I wish to thank Carlos Alvarado for his suggestions.
Ernesto Bozzano: Italian Spiritualist Researcher 769
References
Aksakof, A. (1890). Animismus und Spiritismus. Versuch einer kritischen Prüfung der
mediumistischen Phänomene mit besonderer Berücksichtigung der Hypothesen der
Hallucination und des Unbewussten (2 volumes). Leipzig: Oswald Mutze.
Aksakof, A. (1895). Animisme Et Spiritisme. Essai D’Un Examen Critique Des Phenomenes
Mediumniques. Spécialement en Rapport avec les Hypothèses de la “Force Nerveuse,” de
“l’Hallucination,” et de “l’Inconsciente.” Paris: Paul Leymarie.
Aksakof, A. (1912). Animismo e Spiritismo. Saggio di un Esame Critico dei Fenomeni Medianici.
Specialmente Rispetto Alle Ipotesi della “Forza nervosa,” dell’Allucinazione,” e
dell’Incosciente.” Milan/Naples/Palermo/Rome: Utet.
Alvarado, C. S. (1986). Ernesto Bozzano. Una nota bibliografica in tre riviste straniere. Luce e
Ombra, 86, 9–11.
Alvarado, C. S. (1989). Trends in the study of out-of-body experiences: An overview of
developments since the nineteenth century. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 3, 27–42.
Alvarado, C. S. (2003). The concept of survival of bodily death and the development of
parapsychology. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 67, 65–95.
Alvarado, C. S. (2005). Ernesto Bozzano on the phenomena of bilocation. Journal of Near-Death
Studies, 23, 207–238.
Alvarado, C. S. (2006). Neglected near-death phenomena. Journal of Near-Death Studies, 24,
131–151.
Alvarado, C. S. (2008). Il volume di Ernesto Bozzano “La psiche domina la materia”. Luce e
Ombra, 108, 139–146.
Alvarado, C. S., Biondi, M., & Kramer, W. (2006). Historical notes on psychic phenomena in
specialised journals. European Journal of Parapsychology, 21, 58–87.
Beloff, J. (1993). Parapsychology. A Concise History. London: The Athlone Press.
Besterman, T. (1930). Gwendolyn Kelley Hack’s Modern Psychic Mysteries, Millesimo Castle,
Italy review. Journal of Society for Psychical Research, reprinted by Psypioneer, 5, 2009,
324–328.
Biondi, M. (1984). Pagine d’appunti di Ernesto Bozzano. Luce e Ombra, 84, 156–164.
Biondi, M. (1988). Tavoli e Medium. Storia dello Spiritismo in Italia. Rome: Gremese.
Biondi, M. (2009). The strange case of the Marquis’ transportation. Psypioneer, 5, 328–333.
Biondi, M. (2010). La life review nelle NDE secondo Ernesto Bozzano. The Missing Links, 4,
90–97.
Bozzano, E. (1899). Spiritualismo e critica scientifica. Rivista di Studi Psichici, 356–379.
Bozzano, E. (1903). Ipotesi Spiritica e Teoriche Scientifiche. Genoa: A. Donath.
Bozzano, E. (1904). Contributo allo studio dei fenomeni d’esteriorizzazione della Sensibilità e della
Motricità. Rivista di Studi Psichici, 5, 149–157.
Bozzano, E. (1922a). Considerazioni intorno al “Traité de Métapsychique” del Prof. Charles
Richet. Luce e Ombra, 22, 103–115.
Bozzano, E. (1922b). L’Hypothèse spirite et la “Cryptesthésie.” Revue Métapsychique, 4, 236–246.
Bozzano, E. (1922c). Toujours à propos de Cryptesthésie—Réponse au Professeur RICHET. Revue
Métapsychique, 6, 372–381.
Bozzano, E. (1923a). Considerazioni sull’opera “Metapsichica Moderna” del Dr. William
Mackenzie. Luce e Ombra, 22, 104–112.
Bozzano, E. (1923b). Note polemiche in risposta al Dott. William Mackenzie. Luce e Ombra, 23,
223–238.
Bozzano, E. (1923c). Facoltà supernormali subcoscienti ed evoluzione biologica delle specie. Luce
e Ombra, 23, 321–336.
Bozzano, E. (1924a). Una lettera del Prof. Charles Richet ad Ernesto Bozzano. Luce e Ombra, 24,
56–57.
Bozzano, E. (1924b). Considerazioni intorno al significato metafisico del “Moto.” Luce e Ombra,
24, 368–381.
770 Luca Gasperini
Bozzano, E. (1924c). Autobiographical sketch. Journal of the American Society for Psychical
Research, 18, 153–155.
Bozzano, E. (1924d). Cryptesthesia, animism, and spiritism. Journal of the American Society for
Psychical Research, 18, 155–169.
Bozzano, E. (1926). A Propos de l’Introduction a la Métapsychique Humaine. Réfutation du Livre
de René Sudre. Paris: Jean Meyer Editions.
Bozzano, E. (1927a). Una lettera del sen. Alessandro Chiappelli. Luce e Ombra, 27, 49–55.
Bozzano, E. (1927b). Le prime manifestazioni della “voce diretta” in Italia. Luce e Ombra, 27,
337–362.
Bozzano, E. (1927c). Breve ripresa delle esperienze di “voce diretta.” Luce e Ombra, 27, 385–408.
Bozzano, E. (1928a). Prime manifestazioni della “voce diretta” in Italia. Luce e Ombra, 28, 289–
303.
Bozzano, E. (1928b). Prime manifestazioni della “voce diretta” in Italia (ripresa delle esperienze).
Luce e Ombra, 28, 337–353.
Bozzano, E. (1928c). Prime manifestazioni della “voce diretta in Italia (ripresa delle esperienze).
Luce e Ombra, 28, 387–408.
Bozzano, E. (1928d). Prime manifestazioni della “voce diretta” in Italia (ripresa delle esperienze).
Luce e Ombra, 28, 481–495.
Bozzano, E. (1928e). Beobachtung direkter Stimmen in Millesimo. Zeitschrift für Parapsychologie,
7, 385–395.
Bozzano, E. (1929a). A proposito delle esperienze di Millesimo (risposta ai miei critici). Luce e
Ombra, 29, 49–71.
Bozzano, E. (1929b). Le Prime Manifestazioni della “Voce Diretta” in Italia. Rome: Casa Editrice
Luce e Ombra.
Bozzano, E. (1929c). Note polemiche in risposta al Prof. Rudolf Lambert. Luce e Ombra, 29,
385–404.
Bozzano, E. (1929d). The Direct Voice in Italy. Direct Experiment. Psychic Science, 307.
Bozzano, E. (1929e). Das Phänomen der “direkten Stimmen in Italien.” Zeitschrift für
Parapsychologie, 7, 369–379.
Bozzano, E. (1930a). My progress from positivist materialism to spiritualistic science. The
International Psychic Gazette, 5, 115–116.
Bozzano, E. (1930b). Risposta a un terzo attacco del Prof. Rudolf Lambert. Luce e Ombra, 30,
74–87.
Bozzano, E. (1930c). Schiarimenti e rettifiche. Luce e Ombra, 30, 258–262.
Bozzano, E. (1930d). The Millesimo Mediumship (A Reply to Prof. Lambert). Psychic Science,
135.
Bozzano, E. (1930e). Das Phänomen der “direkten Stimmen in Italien.” Zeitschrift für
Parapsychologie, 1, 24–32.
Bozzano, E. (1931). Della “Visione Panoramica” o “Memoria Sintetica” nell’Imminenza della
Morte. Perugia: Tipography Dante.
Bozzano, E. (1934). Dei Fenomeni di “Bilocazione” (second edition). Perugia: Tipography Dante.
Bozzano, E. (1936). Dei Fenomeni d’Infestazione (second edition). Perugia: Tipography Dante.
Bozzano, E. (1938a). Histoire de l’évolution spirituelle d’Ernest Bozzano. La Revue Spirite, 437–
438.
Bozzano, E. (1938b). Discarnate Influence in Human Life. London: International Institute for
Psychic Investigation and John M. Watkins.
Bozzano, E. (1939). Come divenne spiritualista un pensatore positivista. Ali del Pensiero, 1, 4–11.
Bozzano, E. (1941). Popoli Primitivie Manifestazioni Supernormali. Verona: L’Albero.
Bozzano, E. (1946a). Da Mente a Mente. Comunicazioni Medianiche fra Viventi. Verona: Europa
Editions.
Bozzano, E. (1946b). Medianità Poliglotta (Xenoglossia). Milan: Libreria Lombarda. [Original
publication date 1933]
Bozzano, E. (1947a). Dei Fenomeni di Telestesia. Verona: L’Albero.
Ernesto Bozzano: Italian Spiritualist Researcher 771
Bozzano, E. (1947b). Luci nel Futuro. I Fenomeni Premonitori (Volume 1). Verona: Europa
Editions.
Bozzano, E. (1947c). Luci nel Futuro. I Fenomeni Premonitori (Volume 2). Verona: Europa
Editions.
Bozzano, E. (1948a). Guerre e Profezie. Verona: Europa Editions.
Bozzano, E. (1948b). La Psiche Domina la Materia. Dei Fenomeni di Telecinesia in Rapporto con
Eventi di Morte. Verona: Europa Editions.
Bozzano, E. (1957a). Tornando alle origini. Jonathan Koons e la sua “camera spiritica”: 1852–
1856. Luce e Ombra, 57, 152–163.
Bozzano, E. (1957b). I precursori dello spiritismo. Luce e Ombra, 57, 219–228.
Bozzano, E. (1967a). Animismo o Spiritismo? Quale dei Due Spiega il Complesso dei Fatti?
Verona: Luce e Ombra Editions.
Bozzano, E. (1967b). Dei Fenomeni di Trasfigurazione. Verona: Luce e Ombra Editions.
Bozzano, E. (1967c). Pensiero e Volontà. Forze Plasticizzanti e Organizzanti. Verona: Luce e
Ombra Editions.
Bozzano, E. (1972). Le Visioni dei Morenti. Delle Apparizioni di Defunti al Letto di Morte. Rome:
Del Gattopardo Editions. [Original publication date 1947]
Bozzano, E. (1975). Gli Animali Hanno un’Anima? Milan: Armenia. [Original publication date
1950]
Bozzano, E. (1982). Musica Trascendentale. Rome: Mediterranean Editions. [Original publication
date 1943]
Bozzano, E. (1996). I Morti Ritornano. Per la Soluzione del Dibattito sui Casi d’Identificazione
Spiritica. Milan: Armenia. [Original publication date 1946]
Bozzano, E. (1998a). Letteratura d’Oltretomba. Rome: Il Torchio. [Original publication date 1930]
Bozzano, E. (1998b). La Crisi della Morte. Milan: Armenia. [Original publication date 1952]
Bozzano, E. (2001). I fatti di Hydesville. Luce e Ombra, 101, 175–182.
Bozzano, E. (2008). La psiche domina la materia. Luce e Ombra, 108, 147–160.
Bozzano, E., & De Boni, G. (1930–1943). Carteggio E. Bozzano–G. De Boni 1930–1943.
Unpublished.
Bruers, A. (1929). Review of “E. Bozzano: La crisi della morte nelle descrizioni dei defunti
comunicanti.” Luce e Ombra, 29, 566–570.
Bruers, A. (1930). Review of “E. Bozzano: Letteratura d’Oltretomba.” Luce e Ombra, 30, 294–295.
Caratelli, G. (1998). De Martino e Bozzano. Luce e Ombra, 98, 65–76.
Cellina, F. (1993). La “crisi della morte” di Ernesto Bozzano e le attuali esperienze di pre-morte
(NDE). Luce e Ombra, 93, 171–176.
Clauzure, G. (1983). Le secret de Psi: “l’effet Bozzano.” Renâitre 2000, 34, 196–201.
Collins, A. (1939). Discarnate Influence in Human Life. Professor Bozzano’s great work for
Spiritualism. Light, 59, 241–242.
Cugnaschi, S. (2002). Angelo Marzorati–Ernesto Bozzano: Prove “scientifiche” di una cosmologia
“sperimentale.” Luce e Ombra, 102, 83–97.
De Boni, G. (1941). Vita ed opera di Ernesto Bozzano nel cinquantenario della sua attività
metapsichica. Preface to Bozzano (1941). pp. 11–37.
De Boni, G. (1946). Prefazione. Preface to Bozzano (1946a). pp. 11–16.
De Boni, G. (1947). Prefazione. Preface to E. Bozzano (1947a). Verona: L’Albero Editions. pp.
11–15.
De Boni, G. (1949). Una visita a Carl Gustav Jung. [Reprinted in La realtà dell’Anima. Scelta di
brani della rivista Luce e Ombra 1926–1950, edited by M. Biondi and S. Ravaldini, Rome:
GSE, 1999, pp. 179–186]
De Boni, G. (1974). Carteggio E. Bozzano–G. De Boni 1928–1931. Luce e Ombra, 74, 44–112.
De Boni, G. (1975). Carteggio E. Bozzano–G. De Boni 1932–1933. Luce e Ombra, 75, 3–50.
De Boni, G. (1976). Carteggio E. Bozzano–G. De Boni 1934. Luce e Ombra, 76, 51–84.
De Boni, G. (1977). Carteggio E. Bozzano–G. De Boni 1935. Luce e Ombra, 77, 25–42.
De Boni, G. (1978). Carteggio E. Bozzano–G. De Boni 1936. Luce e Ombra, 78, 40–49.
772 Luca Gasperini
Ravaldini, S. (2000). Catalogo Generale della Biblioteca Bozzano–De Boni (2 volumes). Bologna:
Bozzano–De Boni Library.
Review of Discarnate Influence in Human Life (1938). Nature, 142, 376.
Richet, C. (1922a). Traité de Métapsychique. Paris: Félix Alcan.
Richet, C. (1922b). De la Théorie Spirite—Réponse a M. Bozzano. Revue Métapsychique, 6, 366–
371.
Richet, C. (1922c). Un dernier mot sur la Cryptesthésie–Réponse a M. E. Bozzano. Revue
Métapsychique, 6, 382–384.
Saltmarsh, H. F. (1938). Review of Discarnate Influence in Human Life. Journal of the Society for
Psychical Research, 30, 277–278.
Servadio, E. (1931). Review of “E. Bozzano: Indagini sulle manifestazioni supernormali.” Luce e
Ombra, 31, 338.
Servadio, E. (1934). In difesa dei casi d’identificazione spiritica. Luce e Ombra, 34, 56–58.
Stevenson, I. (1977). Children Who Remember Previous Lives. Charlottesville: University Press
of Virginia.
Sudre, R. (1926). Introduction a la Métapsychique Humaine. Paris: Payot.
Troubridge, U. V. (1919). Review of Dei Fenomeni d’Infestazione. Journal of the Society for
Psychical Research, 19, 107–108.
Vassallo, L. A. (1992). Gli Invisibili. Genoa: ECIG. [Original publication date 1902]
Van de Castle, R. L. (1977). Anthropology and Psychic Research. Phoenix. New Directions in the
Study of Man, 1, 27–35.
Weissenbach, R. (1949). A la Mémoire du Grand Spirite Italien: Ernest Bozzano. La Revue Spirite,
69–78.
Wilson, S. R. W. (1933). Review of Polyglot Mediumship (Xenoglossy). Journal of the Society for
Psychical Research, 28, 89–91.
Journal of Scientific Exploration, Vol. 25, No. 4, pp. 775–777, 2011 0892-3310/11
OBITUARY
775
776 Patrick Huyghe
PATRICK HUYGHE
Journal of Scientific Exploration, Vol. 25, No. 4, p. 779–780, 2011 0892-3310/11
1 – no neck;
2 – nearly fused jaws;
3 – no posterior paired appendages (pelvic fins);
4 – pronounced dorsal fin;
5 – very elongate post-vent tail region (> 1/2 body length);
6 – lateral plates encircling the body and tail region (vs. only dorso
laterally on trunk region in Hagelund’s creature);
7 – presence of a small and vertically oriented fin.
779
780 Letter to the Editor
PAUL H. LEBLOND
[email protected]
References
Hagelund, W. (1987). Whalers No More. Madeira Park, B.C.: Harbour Publishing.
LeBlond, P. H., & Bousfield, E. L. (1995). Cadborosaurus. Victoria, B.C.: Horsdal & Schubart.
Woodley, M. A., Naish, D., & McCormick, C. A. (2011). A baby sea-serpent no more: Reinterpreting
Hagelund’s juvenile “Cadborosaur” report. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 25, 497–514.
Journal of Scientific Exploration, Vol. 25, No. 4, pp. 781–787, 2011 0892-3310/11
ESSAY REVIEW
781
782 Book Reviews
in 1866, and then promptly became as now a scarce pamphlet. Sections had been
reused in The Spiritualist newspaper in 1871. It is worth noting that Wallace not
only habitually reissued material, he also revised it. To the 1875 version of the
essay, Wallace added “Notes of Personal Evidence.” The 1866 essay may be
seen as an argument for taking Spiritualism seriously.
Finally the paper “A Defence of Modern Spiritualism” (92 pages, including
an appendix of the author’s replies) had appeared in The Fortnightly Review
in 1874 and been reprinted as far afield as Boston (USA) and Dunedin (New
Zealand) before being revised for this book.
The content of the essays varied. The first essay was mainly philosophical
and logical. The second was the nearest to a general survey of Spiritualism,
including a section on its teaching. The third was chiefly a literature review.
In the first essay, Wallace discusses the philosopher David Hume whose
definitions of Miracles had been very influential, and might be said to rule
out the study of paranormal phenomena in advance.2 Hume had argued that
a uniform experience amounted to a proof that miracles did not happen,
but Wallace gives many examples of testimony to miraculous events, by no
means limited to Modern Spiritualism. Wallace also exposes the limitations
to scientific rejection a priori, without investigation, of psychic evidence, with
many examples of scientific error (e.g., “Sir Humphry Davy laughed at the idea
of London ever being lighted with gas”).
Wallace also takes issue with his contemporary, the historian William
Lecky, who had attacked the belief in miracles, and had suggested that belief in
the supernatural existed only when men were destitute of the critical spirit and
when the notion of uniform law was as yet unborn. Wallace pointed to Joseph
Glanvil as a critical mind who defended the supernatural.3
A third thinker whom Wallace challenges is the anthropologist Edward
Tylor who had asserted that psychic beliefs were an example of the survival
of savage thought.4 Many modern people, Wallace noted, can testify to the
phenomena which cause such beliefs.
Wallace concludes this first essay by repeating that he seeks only to clear
the ground of arguments supposed to disprove miracles and Spiritualism
without examination. This he has done effectively, and in a clear way that the
general reader can follow.
In the second essay, “The Scientific Aspect of the Supernatural,” Wallace
again makes some general points in defense of the miraculous, such as our
limited knowledge of the laws of nature, and the possibility of ethereal
intelligences of whose existence we are generally unaware. He calls attention to
the good quality of the witnesses who testify to modern miraculous phenomena,
and he claims:
Book Reviews 783
during the eighteen years which have passed since the revival of a belief in the
supernatural in America, not one single individual has carefully investigated
the subject without accepting the reality of the phenomena, and while thou-
sands have been converted to the belief not one adherent has been converted
back from it. (p. 49)
This book was one of Wallace’s most durable. But its main readership has
been Spiritualists, rather than psychical researchers or scientists. He wrote at
a time when the psychic field was still, to a large extent, organizationally and
ideologically undivided, except between those who accepted the phenomena
and those who did not. Within months of the book appearing, The Theosophical
Society had been formed in New York, which would develop a more critical
view of Spiritualism in the light of a revived occult tradition. The rise of
psychical research gradually emphasized the importance of the laboratory
approach, championed by Crookes, rather than the natural history of Wallace.
Notes
1
The ensuing Report on Spiritualism appeared as a book—London: Longmans,
Green, Reader & Dyer, 1871; reprinted (slightly shortened) London: J. Burns, 1873;
reprinted, London: Arno Press, 1976.
2
“A miracle is a violation of the laws of nature” and also “A miracle is a transgression
of a law of nature by a particular volition of the deity, or by the interposition of some
invisible agent.” Wallace shows that both definitions are defective.
3
Henry Sidgwick, first president of the Society for Psychical Research, read Lecky, but
was then led to take more seriously the evidence for medieval marvels. Interestingly,
Lecky seems to have facilitated the inclusion of a dream case in an early SPR survey
Phantasms of the Living (1886), being acquainted with the dreamer.
4
It is now known that Tylor was privately investigating the subject: Stocking, J., &
Book Reviews 787
LESLIE PRICE
[email protected]
Journal of Scientific Exploration, Vol. 25, No. 4, pp. 789–820, 2011 0892-3310/11
ESSAY REVIEW
Introduction
Twenty Cases Suggestive of Reincarnation (first published in 1966) is a classic
of 20th-century parapsychology that can still be read with profit.1 Along with
Children Who Remember Previous Lives (2001),2 it is an ideal introduction to
Stevenson. The latter work, intended for the educated general reader, provides
an overview of 40 years of research and includes capsule summaries of several
cases, but Twenty Cases contains detailed reports that illustrate reincarnation-
type cases much more fully.
The cases reported in Twenty Cases come from India, Ceylon (now Sri
Lanka), Lebanon, Brazil, and the United States (the Tlingit Indians of Alaska).
They were selected from about 200 personally investigated by Stevenson in
order to show the variety of features this type of case presents. The subjects
of all were young children at the time they claimed to have lived before.
Collectively these twenty cases help define “cases of the reincarnation type,” as
Stevenson came to call them, though they vary substantially in detail.
The book includes both evidentially strong and weak cases, cases among
strangers and in the same family, cases with strong behavioral features, cases
with birthmarks and congenital deformities related to the previous person,3 a
case with a change of sex between the previous person and the subject, and a
case in which the previous person died after the birth of the subject. The last
type is extremely rare. Stevenson worked for years on a volume that was to
include “anomalous date” cases, but it remained incomplete at his death in 2007
and has not been published. He also did not live to complete a planned volume
on non-tribal American cases, although he analyzed a series of 79 of them in
an article published in the Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease in 1983
(Stevenson, 1983b).
The Canadian-born Stevenson was already a tenured professor and
Chair of the Department of Psychiatry at the University of Virginia Medical
Center when he turned his attention to reincarnation-type cases. From 1960
789
790 Book Reviews
on, he enjoyed the financial support of Chester Carlson, inventor of the Xerox
process. Carlson endowed a Chair and Stevenson became Carlson Professor
of Psychiatry in 1964. In 1967, he resigned as chairman of the Department of
Psychiatry and established a Division of Parapsychology (later renamed the
Division of Personality Studies)4 within it. From then on, he devoted all of his
efforts to psychical research. Carlson continued to give annual donations, and
on his death in 1968 left a $1,000,000 bequest to the University of Virginia in
support of the work (Stevenson, 2006).
Twenty Cases was first published in 1966 in the Proceedings of the
American Society for Psychical Research, and reprinted with additional material
that included followup information on the subjects by the University Press
of Virginia in 1974 (Stevenson, 1974b). In this historical review, I describe
reincarnation studies in Anglo–American psychical research before Twenty
Cases appeared, the reception that book received, and the influence it has had. I
also assess it from the vantage of current research. If nothing else, Twenty Cases
brought a new type of spontaneous case5 to the attention of parapsychologists
and the world, although some scholars, like Almeder (1996), believe that it
(together with the works that succeeded it) accomplished much more and that it
would now be “irrational” to deny that reincarnation occurs.
her 20s, she trained herself to access this “far memory” and began dictating,
in trance, her seven novels, set in ancient Egypt, classical Greece, and
contemporary Rome, Renaissance Italy, and among American Indians in pre-
contact times (Grant, 1956, Kelsey & Grant, 1967).
Some have credited the impressive output of Pearl Curran writing as
Patience Worth to past-life memory, although Patience herself repeatedly
denied reincarnation. She identified herself as a 17th-century English woman
who had emigrated to the American colonies and been killed by Indians there.
She dictated through a Ouija board and then through automatic writing six
long novels and an array of other literary works. Most of the novels are set in
17th-century England, but one is set in Victorian England (two hundred years
after Patience is supposed to have lived) and another in Biblical-era Palestine.
Like Soul of Nyria and the far-memory novels of Joan Grant, these works are
replete with recondite period detail and language that Curran did not know or
use normally (Prince, 1927, Yost, 1916), and their source remains a mystery
(Braude, 2003).
Thanks to the Spiritism of Alan Kardec (1875), which like Theosophy
endorsed the idea, reincarnation was taken more seriously in continental Europe
than in Great Britain and the United States, and European psychical researchers
took more interest in it than did their American and British counterparts.
Albert de Rochas (1911) is well-known for his pioneering exploration of
hypnotic age regression to previous lives, but perhaps because his book has
not been translated into English it is not generally realized that the regressions
compose only a small part of the presentation. It is a wide-ranging discussion of
reincarnation that includes a review of spontaneous cases culled from a variety
of sources, including Fielding (1898). Even less well-known is a book by de
Rochas’s countryman and colleague Charles Lancelin (1922), who described
the important Italian child case of Alessandrina (Alexandrina) Samona, one of
the earliest European cases on record. This case has the interesting feature that
the rebirth was heralded in multiple ways (in dreams, séance communications,
and poltergeist raps). There are striking physical and behavioral similarities
with the previous person, and Alessandrina apparently recalled an incident from
that person’s previous life.
In 1924, R. B. S. Sunderlal reported four Indian cases in the Revue
Métapsychique.13 That same year, Gabriel Delanne (1924), a follower of Allan
Kardec, released another general study of reincarnation. In addition to survey-
ing spontaneous child cases, child prodigies, and déjà vu experiences, Delanne
examined cases of retrocognition and reviewed cases in which rebirths had
been announced in mediumistic communications. Again, because his book has
not been translated into English, it has had little influence on Anglo–American
psychical research. Other French Spiritists, such as Geléy (1920, 1930) and
Book Reviews 793
paranormal explanations, before deciding that the case is best interpreted as one
of reincarnation. The arguments are summarized and reconsidered in a chapter
at the end of the volume.
Neither in that chapter nor elsewhere does Stevenson assert that the
cases prove that reincarnation occurs—only that the best of them are highly
suggestive of it. Of the book’s reviewers, Beloff (1966) and McHarg (1969)
accepted this conclusion, with McHarg pointing out that what reincarnated
appeared to be something less than a full personality. Chari (1967) proposed
various alternative explanations, including ESP. Louisa Rhine (1966) suggested
that the cases might be the result of parents unconsciously shaping the behavior
of their children to conform to cultural expectations about reincarnation, a
position anticipated by Siwek (1953) and assumed by many later critics.
The fullest and most oft-cited expression of the psycho-cultural (or socio-
psychological) theory was made by Brody (1979) in a review of a later book by
Stevenson. Pasricha (1992), however, found that parental guidance could not
account for cases in North India, and Schouten and Stevenson (1998) tested the
possibility by comparing cases with and without written records made before
verification. On the psycho-cultural theory, cases with written records would be
expected to have many fewer verified statements than cases without them. The
test did not support this theory. Children in the group with written records made
more statements, an average of 25.5 as against an average of 18.5, a statistically
significant difference (p < 0.01), while the percentage of correct statements was
roughly the same in both groups—76.7% in the cases with written records and
78.4% in the cases without them.
Mills (1990a, 1990b) studied several Indian cases with differences of religion
(Hinduism and Buddhism) between the previous person and the subject and
wondered why religious parents would choose to impose another religious
identity on their children. We could ask a similar question about the large num-
ber of Indian cases with differences of caste. Also, many parents attempt to stop
their children from talking about their memories, believing that they will suffer
from them in some way.18 Suppression attempts are seldom successful (Steven-
son & Chadha, 1990), but if the parents are responsible for the cases, why do
they seek to quash them once they have brought them into being? Is it because
they have taken on lives of their own, so to speak? Many children insist they
have other families and demand to be taken to their previous homes, and this
must not be pleasant for their parents to hear.
The psychological and interpersonal conflicts necessary to produce
reincarnation-type cases in the psycho-cultural theory led Rhine (1966) and
Brody (1979) to call for explorations of the children’s psychologies. This has
now been done by Haraldsson and his colleagues in Sri Lanka (Haraldsson,
1995, 1997, Haraldsson, Fowler, & Periyannanpillai, 2000) and Lebanon
798 Book Reviews
(Haraldsson, 2003) and Mills (2003) in India. Children with past-life memories
are viewed by their parents as being more highly strung, more tense, more
argumentative, and more anxious and fearful than children in matched control
groups (though teachers do not report behavioral problems, and in fact the
children perform better in school than their peers). They score higher on
dissociation scales but are no more suggestible than their peers. In Lebanon,
where 80% recalled violent deaths, they seemed to suffer from a mild PTSD.
On the whole, differences between the groups appear to be attributable to
effects of the memories and do not explain them. Braude (2003), however,
wants more information on what psychological needs the memories fulfill in a
particular case. He regards the statements of Stevenson and others on this point
as superficial (as they often are), but it is not at all clear that further probing
would turn up anything of consequence.
Cultural conformance theories (of which psycho-cultural theories are a
variety) are challenged by the veridical aspects of the cases, the birthmarks
and other physical features of many, and the strong emotions and personations
exhibited by the children, forcing critics to include super-psi (as super-ESP is
now called) in their explanatory paradigms. Braude (1989, 1992, 2003) believes
that super-psi has not been properly appreciated and suggests that the children
may be accessing it in psi-conducive dissociated states (2003:24). There is little
doubt that, given sufficient ingenuity, super-psi can be stretched to cover any
eventuality, and therefore in a strict sense it cannot be ruled out, no matter how
crippling its complexity becomes. However, not everyone finds it as plausible
as Braude does. Griffin (1997) introduces what he calls retroprehensive
inclusion, essentially a new type of psi, to account for survival cases in general,
but regards even that as failing to explain the better reincarnation-type cases.
In any event, super-psi would operate within cultural confines and be
dependent upon the cultural conformance theory, so any evidence against the
latter would count also against the former.19 With this in mind, let us examine
some of the cases in the book.
Seven Cases
A Lebanese Druse boy, Imad Elawar, expressed over and over again his joy at
being able to walk. He gave many names and other details that pertained to a
man from another town who had been bedridden, probably with tuberculosis
of the spine, for two months before he died. Imad also had a pronounced fear
of large motor vehicles. The man whose life he recalled had been involved in
a bus accident and had had a cousin who had died following a truck accident.20
He had spoken French well and Imad learned that language quickly, although
no one else in his family could speak or understand it. This case was unsolved
when Stevenson reached it and he was able to record much of what Imad said
Book Reviews 799
and how he behaved before searching for and identifying the previous person,
and thus it cannot easily be attributed to cultural construction (which may be
why Angel, 1994a, 1994b, attacks Stevenson’s research methods instead, cf.
Stevenson, 1995).
An Indian boy named Ravi Shankar was born with a long, linear mark,
closely resembling the scar of a knife wound, across his neck. He spoke about
having been murdered, named the killers, and gave other details of the crime,
in which the head had been severed from the body. Ravi’s birthmark is typical
of birthmarks in reincarnation-type cases. Few are of the common types but
rather are congenital marks matching wounds and other marks on the bodies of
the deceased persons whose lives the children recall (Stevenson, 1997a). The
men Ravi named as the murderers lived in his town, and he was afraid of them
whenever he saw them. His fear remained with him as he grew older, even as
his imaged memories faded.
The case of Mallika, an Indian girl, is strikingly different. Imad was
between one and a half and two and Ravi between two and three years old
when they made their first statements, apparently spontaneously. Mallika was
four when her family moved to a new city, where they rented the ground floor
of a house. The first time she visited her landlord’s apartment, upstairs from her
own, she noticed some embroidered cushions, and said that she had made them.
She later commented on several other things in the apartment that identified
her with the landlord’s wife’s deceased sister. She exhibited some striking
behavioral similarities to this woman, but she made no statements that were not
recognitions.
Younger children, many of whom make their first statements as soon as
they begin to speak, are more likely to make them spontaneously, while subjects
of Mallika’s age or older are more likely to make them in response to something
they have seen (Matlock, 1988, 1989). It is as if the images have increasing
difficulty breaking into consciousness as the children age.21 Pratomwan Inthanu,
a Thai woman, was 20 when veridical memories of two different lives came to
her while meditating (Stevenson, 1983b). Uttara Huddar was 32 when she met
a man she believed to be the reincarnation of her past-life husband and began to
enter periodic fugue states, in which she behaved and spoke like an early 19th-
century Bangali woman called Sharada (Akolkar, 1992, Stevenson, 1984).22
Not only was Mallika relatively old (for a child subject) when she made
her recognitions, her case is a rare South Indian case, the only one among seven
Indian cases in Twenty Cases. The population of South India is largely Dravidian
or descended from Dravidian tribes, the most prominent of India’s indigenous
peoples. The Indo-European speaking Aryans arrived in North India around
1500 BC and their religion, Hinduism, adopted the belief in reincarnation from
the peoples they encountered there (Fürer-Haimendorf, 1953, Obeyesekere,
800 Book Reviews
life, intermediate between the life she recalled best and her own. She sang
the songs in Bengali, the language of East Pakistan (now Bangladesh). This
intermediate life was never confirmed, but in the 1974 second edition of Twenty
Cases, Stevenson reported that the songs had been identified as traditional
ones from the Bengal region. Although Swarnlata was unable to converse in
Bengali, as Uttara Huddar did, her singing is a form of recitative xenoglossy.
If the intermediate life was real, Swarnlata’s main memories may have been
stimulated by her environment, even though the life to which they related was
not the most recent one.
Another noteworthy Indian case in the collection is that of Jasbir, who at
the age of five suffered a serious illness and seemed to die, but revived and after
he had recuperated claimed to be a different person, named Sobha Ram. This
case is similar to the case of Lurancy Vennum, except that Lurancy’s possession
by Mary Roff lasted less than four months, whereas Sobha Ram came to
occupy Jasbir’s body permanently. In this respect, it is like the Sumitra case
(Stevenson, Pasricha, & McLean-Rice, 1989), also one of permanent possession
or “replacement reincarnation,” to coin a term.25 It is different from the Uttara
Huddar case in that Sharada was not an invading entity but was connected to
Uttara as a past-life personality whose initial emergence was triggered by a
highly emotional encounter. The revitalized Jasbir gradually came to accept his
new circumstances and developed normally in them, even accepting the name
Jasbir, which he at first resisted.
The Ceylonese case of Wijeratne is the only case in Twenty Cases to feature
a birth defect related to the previous person. Wijeratne claimed to recall the
life of a man who had killed his arranged bride when she refused to move
from her parents’ house after their civil wedding but before this was publicly
celebrated in a marriage feast. He had been tried for the crime, convicted, and
hung. Wijeratne was born with a shrunken left arm, the same arm the previous
person had used to wield the murder weapon.
Wijeratne attributed his deformity to karma, but reincarnation-type cases
provide scant evidence of karma as a moral system of rewards and punishments,
much less as conceived in this coercive, cause-and-effect way. Although
there are many Asian cases in which the social and economic situation of the
subject varies greatly from that of the previous person, there is no discernable
correlation with what is known about the previous person. Because the karmic
reason for the shifts in social status is not apparent, the assumption is that there
must be something that is not known, perhaps something from an anterior or
intermediate life, that has resulted in the present circumstances (Stevenson,
2001). Again, beliefs are adjusted to fit the cases, not the other way around, as
advocates of the cultural conformance theory would have it.
Karma is considered moral because it is derived from one’s actions (and
802 Book Reviews
sometimes one’s thoughts, intentions, etc.), good and bad. It has been taken
by many writers as a corollary of reincarnation and advanced as an ethically
appealing aspect of the belief (e.g., by Osborn, 1937, and by Johnson, 1953). But
there is nothing about reincarnation that logically entails karma, and in small-
scale or tribal societies like the Dravidian and Tlingit, reincarnation beliefs
do not include it (Matlock, 1993, Obeyesekere, 2002).26 Karma is a Sanskrit
word that originally denoted ritual action but came to be linked to reincarnation
and took on its moral coloring in Hinduism and Buddhism after they had
acquired the belief in rebirth from Indian tribal peoples (Fürer-Haimendorf,
1953, Obeyesekere, 1980, 2002). I return to this issue in my discussion of
Stevenson’s Tlingit cases, below. If not evidence of karma, Wijeratne’s case
can be explained as due to the previous person’s belief that his conduct would
have this result, and thus is another example of a person’s beliefs influencing
the reincarnation process.27
The case of Paulo Lorenz, one of two Brazilian cases28 in the book, has
several interesting features, not least of which is that Paulo recalled the life of
his deceased sister, Emilia, who had poisoned and killed herself, saying that
she wished to be reborn a boy. Paulo did not start speaking until he was three
and a half. The first thing he said was to tell another child, who was about to
put something in his mouth, that it was dangerous to do that. He identified with
Emilia, and until he was four or five refused to wear boy’s clothes. He only
accepted trousers when an old skirt of Emilia’s was used to make him a pair.
Neither Paulo nor Emilia showed any interest in cooking and both disliked
milk and had the habit of breaking corners off bread. Most importantly, both
were skilled at sewing, the only members of a family of fifteen who showed
any aptitude for it. Paulo recognized and demonstrated how to thread and use
Emilia’s sewing machine when he was younger than four years old.
Sex change is one of the features of reincarnation-type cases that varies
according to cultural expectation, being found most often in places with
traditions that allow for it, and seldom or not at all where it is believed not to
happen (Matlock, 1990b:226–227). This sometimes is held to be a telling point
in favor of the cases as cultural constructions, but it could just as well be that in
places that sex change is thought impossible, people do not consider it an option
for themselves, and so return as members of the same sex.
In the majority of sex-change cases, the subjects adjust to their new
anatomical sex, but in some cases, gender confusion persists for years (Mills,
2004, Stevenson, 1977b, Tucker & Keil, 2001). Paulo began to lose his intense
feminine traits when he was about six but was effeminate even in adulthood.
He never married and, Stevenson tells us in the second edition of Twenty
Cases, he killed himself when he was 43. Most of the other subjects in Twenty
Cases moved beyond their childhood memories and developed normally, but
Book Reviews 803
Animistic Reincarnation
We turn now to the Tlingit cases. These are divergent from the other cases in
some respects, although they share many features with them. The Tlingit are an
Alaskan Indian tribe whose reincarnation beliefs are rooted in a long Amerindian
(Jefferson, 2009, Mills & Slobodin, 1994) and global (Matlock, 1993) tradition
that includes the Dravidians and others. This is the tradition called animism, a
collection of beliefs about souls and spirits and their operation in the natural and
supernatural worlds (Tylor, 1871).29 Belief in postmortem survival is universal
in animistic societies and reincarnation beliefs are more common than might be
thought. Half of the world’s tribal peoples in cross-cultural samples have or at
one time had them (Matlock, 1993, 1995).30
In discussions of reincarnation beliefs, a contrast is often made between
Hindu and Buddhist ideas. This is an important distinction, because Buddhists
do not recognize an eternal soul but imagine rebirth propelled by attachments
to the material world (with karma playing a central role), whereas Hindus
conceive of a personal soul that continues to evolve through a succession of
lives (O’Flaherty, 1980). However, there is another contrast to be made, and
that is between reincarnation beliefs that incorporate karma and those that do
not. I believe this latter distinction to be the more basic and so group Hindu
and Buddhist beliefs together in opposition to animistic ones (Matlock, 1996).
Because reincarnation-type cases provide little evidence of karma, regardless of
the culture from which they are reported (Stevenson, 2001:251–253), they fall
under the heading of Animistic reincarnation.
Without the concept of karma,31 the Tlingit and other tribal peoples are
free to believe that they may exercise some control over the reincarnation
process, and in two of the Tlingit cases in Twenty Cases (Corliss Chortkin,
Jr., and William George, Jr.), the previous persons stated their intentions to be
reborn to the mothers of the subjects. Planned returns were expressed in the two
Brazilian cases in Twenty Cases, but they are unusual under Indic belief systems
(including Jainism and Sikhism along with Hinduism and Buddhism),32 where
karma is thought to govern the rebirth process.33 Planned returns are distinctly
animistic in implying a discarnate agency, and Stevenson (2001:39) regarded
804 Book Reviews
them as the only variety of reincarnation belief for which there is empirical
evidence.
However, the Tlingit cases are weaker evidentially than those of Southeast
Asia, and Stevenson evinced relatively little interest in them. He published
papers on the Tlingit (1966a) and neighboring Haida (1975a), but never
produced a volume of case reports about them, as he did for other cultures
(1975b, 1977a, 1980, 1983b). The weaknesses stem in part from the planned
returns, which set up the expectation of the rebirth, thereby opening the cases
to charges of parental and societal shaping in accordance to the expectation.
Another reason is that in most Tlingit cases (including all seven in Twenty Cases),
the previous person and the subject are related, so that the subject in theory
could have learned about the previous person normally or paranormally from
relatives. These cases are also often less well-developed, with fewer statements
and recognitions attributed to the subjects, than are the better Southeast Asian
cases (though rich cases may occur also among tribal peoples; see Mills, 2010).
A striking feature of the Tlingit cases in Twenty Cases is the birthmarks.
Six of the seven have birthmarks, but elsewhere in the collection they appear
only in the case of Ravi Shankar (Wijeratne’s birth defect is of a different
order). Along with planned returns, announcing dreams,34 and physical and
behavioral similarities, birthmarks are signs that allow the Tlingit to identify
a child with a particular deceased person even before he or she begins to talk
(de Laguna, 1972, Matlock, 1990a). These signs, which have become well-
known as recurrent features of reincarnation-type cases, have been reported
by ethnographers and other observers in relation to animistic reincarnation
beliefs for many years. They were noted by Tylor (1871:3–5), who assumed
that they had occurred from time immemorial and suggested that they were the
foundation of the belief in reincarnation, as seems very possible.
In small-scale tribal societies, a premium typically is placed on returning
in the same lineage or kin grouping, allowing for an almost literal “social
reproduction.” When signs suggest a child is a returning relative, he or she
may be given that person’s name and grow up to take on or to qualify to take
on that person’s rights and responsibilities and even to inherit his tangible and
intangible property (Matlock, 1990a, 1993, Mills, 1988). However, when signs
suggest that the child is the reincarnation of someone outside the kin grouping,
this also is accepted, and reincarnation thereby promotes social cohesion (Mills
& Champion, 1996). In the much more populous Indic societies, the pattern
is reversed, with the majority of cases occurring between non-relatives, often
strangers. This is because, as Obeyesekere puts it, “karma theory produces
dislocation and the dispersal of kin” in rebirth (2002:344). It does so by de-
emphasizing personal relationships and ascribing rebirth to an impersonal
moral force.
Book Reviews 805
I suggest that personal agency always plays a role, but different sets of
expectations (on the part of the previous persons), generated by different
cultural ideals (discarnate agency vs. karma), produce the different outcomes
(same-family cases in animistic societies vs. non-relative and stranger cases
in Indic societies). Beliefs about the reincarnation process influence the cases
from the inside, as it were, carried by dying persons into their postmortem state.
Discarnate actors are involved in selecting their new births, unconsciously if not
consciously.35 This accords with animistic thinking and is what I call Animistic
reincarnation.
Keil (1996) called cases in which the child makes no or very few
statements “silent” and “near-silent” cases. His data suggest that these account
for a relatively small percentage of cases among the Turkish Alevi, whereas
the impression one receives from the ethnographic literature is that silent and
near-silent cases are in the majority in tribal societies. The less well-developed
tribal cases are like cases from Europe and non-tribal North America (Harrison
& Harrison, 1991, Jacobson, 1974, Osborn, 1937, Rivas, 2003, 2004, Stemman,
2005, Stevenson, 1960, 2003, Tucker, 2005) in being notably underdeveloped
and often unsolved. Moreover, solved cases similar to those from other places,
have been reported from Europe and non-tribal North America (Cockell, 1994,
Leininger & Leininger, 2009, Stevenson, 1960, 1983a, 1983b, 2003, Tucker,
2005). There is no correlation between the strength of reincarnation beliefs and
the strength or even the appearance of cases. Both strong and weak cases may
occur where the belief is weak or absent as well as where it is strongly present,
and cases where the belief is strongly present are not always strong as we saw in
the instance of South India36 and see again with the cases from tribal societies.
We must therefore seek explanations for these cases in terms of something other
than the belief in reincarnation.37
The same year the revised edition of Twenty Cases appeared, Stevenson
introduced the idea of a psychophore to explain how reincarnation might operate.
He described the psychophore as an “intermediate ‘non-physical’ body which
acts as the carrier of . . . attributes between one life and another” (1974a:406).
He returned to this idea in Children Who Remember Previous Lives, where he
speculated at greater length about processes (2001:233–254). The psychophore
would not simply convey characteristics, but would have will and intention at
its disposal. It might exercise some initiative, such as waiting for a body of the
desired sex to be available, if it did not operate on the developing zygote directly.
The psychophore sounds very much like an astral body—perhaps a “minded”
astral body, to borrow a term from Wheatley (1979)—and it harmonizes well
with my concept of Animistic reincarnation.38
If reincarnation happens for some, does it happen for all? Griffin assumes
that the only people who have reincarnated are those who remember having
806 Book Reviews
lived before (1997:186), but silent cases suggest that reincarnation may occur
without imaged memories, and it is possible that a person might reincarnate
without having any indication of it whatsoever. And if we all reincarnate, we
may all have past-life memories accessible to us. They may enter consciousness
on occasion, and perhaps be retrievable under hypnosis, trance, and other
dissociative states, as we find with adults such as Pratomwan Inthanu and
Uttara Huddar. They may also lie in the background of fictional productions
such as those of Pearl Curran and Joan Grant. I believe the assumption that we
all reincarnate handles the data better than the assumption that only some of
us do, but as Stevenson observed (2001:216), we may never be certain on this
point.
Stevenson’s Legacy
Twenty Cases depicted reincarnation very differently than had been imagined
before Stevenson’s 1960 paper, and it more than confirmed the findings
and fulfilled the promise of that paper. All the major recurrent features of
reincarnation-type cases appear in the book.39 Indeed, it is remarkable how
well it lays out the parameters of this type of case. Subsequent work has
added details but has not changed our understanding in any substantial way.
Moreover, as I have shown, the twenty cases collectively provide the basis of a
theoretical conception of reincarnation in terms of an Animistic as opposed to
an Indic model, a way of thinking about reincarnation radically different from
that assumed before 1960.
Twenty Cases did much to pull reincarnation studies out of the realm of
speculation and to provide it a scientific footing. However, Stevenson’s fellow
parapsychologists were slow to recognize its significance, and the larger world
of science, to which Stevenson appealed constantly, has yet to come to grips
with it (Edelstein, 2008). Attitudes may be changing, however. Astronomer and
science writer Carl Sagan, a skeptic about most things parapsychological, wrote
in his last book that he regarded reincarnation-type cases to be one of the few
promising areas of research in the field (Sagan, 1997:302).
One reason for Stevenson’s early difficulty in parapsychology was
his adherence to the old SPR style of field investigation at a time when the
gravitational center of the discipline had moved from spontaneous cases and
survival questions to laboratory studies of ESP under the influence of J. B. Rhine
(Alvarado & Zingrone, 2008). Stevenson was out of step with the majority of
his colleagues, especially in the United States. It was widely believed that he
was the only researcher turning up reincarnation-type cases, something easily
disproved (Matlock, 1990b). Similar cases had been reported by many people
over many years, and other investigators, such as Brazilian parapsychologist
Hernani Andrade, were finding them also. However, because Andrade published
Book Reviews 807
in Portuguese (e.g., 1988), he was and still is not as well-known in the English-
speaking world as he should be (but see Playfair, 1975, 2006, and Andrade,
Rossi, Playfair, & Lima, 2010, for English-language summaries of his cases.)
Of those Stevenson trained to assist him in the field, Satwant Pasricha
has made the most significant contributions, but she is not the only one. K.
S. Rawat has recently co-authored an article and a book with newcomer Titus
Rivas (Rawat & Rivas, 2005, 2007). Stevenson’s research has attracted others
as well. Anthropologist Antonia Mills was acquainted with the reincarnation
beliefs of the Indians of British Columbia when she met Stevenson in 1984
and became interested in cases (Mills, 1994). Stevenson underwrote her work
with the Gitksan and Beaver, reported in 1988, as well as her first field trips to
India, in 1987 and 1988, in an attempt to “replicate” his findings (Mills, 1989).
Later, she joined Erlendur Haraldsson and Jürgen Keil in a larger replication of
Stevenson’s research (Mills, Haraldsson, & Keil, 1994).40
As readers of this Journal know, Pasricha, Mills, Haraldsson, and Keil
have continued to report reincarnation-type cases and have carried the research
in new directions. Haraldsson (1995, 2000, 2003) has studied the psychology
of the child subjects, Mills (2001, 2006, 2010) is demonstrating the power of
combining anthropological and parapsychological approaches, and Keil (1996,
2010) is drawing attention to unusual and problematical cases. Meanwhile,
Tucker (2005) has been working with non-tribal American cases, Rivas (2000,
2003, 2004) has reported cases from The Netherlands, and an increasing
number of original accounts are appearing in popular publications (Bowman,
1997, 2001, Cockell, 1994, Harrison & Harrison, 1991, Leininger & Leininger,
2009). Important new voices are also emerging on the side of commentary
and critique (Edelman & Bernet, 2007, Moura Visoni, 2010, Nahm & Hassler,
2011). Stevenson’s passing has not brought an end to serious reincarnation
studies, as some may have expected.
I have focused on the professional reception of Twenty Cases because
that is where Stevenson placed his emphasis, but I cannot altogether ignore
the popular sphere, for it is there that the book has had its greatest impact. By
1990, Twenty Cases had been translated into seven languages and sold some
50,000 copies (Stevenson, 1990), astonishing for a university press offering.
It is difficult to find a book on reincarnation published after 1966 that does not
refer to it. Many popular books summarize its cases and conclusions, making
them more accessible to a wide audience. Angel identifies it as “one of the most
influential sources of empirical evidence for reincarnation” (1994a:481) and
says that his students in the philosophy of religion routinely cite authors who
have been persuaded by it.
As of 1990, Stevenson’s research had received little attention from
academia (see Matlock, 1990b). Since that date, it has been addressed by several
808 Book Reviews
philosophers, who have raised the level of discourse on the subject considerably.
Angel (1994b) limits himself to the case of Imad Elawar, but Almeder (1992),
Becker (1993), Paterson (1995), Edwards (1996), Griffin (1997), Braude
(2003), Grosso (2004), and Lund (2009) treat Stevenson’s work generally.
Edwards, a humanist, ridicules much of the data. Almeder, as already noted, is
convinced. The others fall somewhere in between. Most contrast reincarnation
with super-psi and psycho-cultural explanations. Griffin, Becker, Lund, Paterson,
and Grosso lean toward reincarnation, but Braude favors super-psi.
Stevenson had high hopes for Reincarnation and Biology, his massive
two-volume examination of birthmarks and birth defects (1997a, 1997b).
This “medical monograph” includes detailed reports of 225 cases, together
with supporting photographs and citations from autopsy reports, and he was
very disheartened when it was met with silence. Edelstein (2008) suggests
that this non-reaction was due in part to Stevenson having done little to show
how reincarnation could be integrated with biology. His psychophore concept
was not well-enough articulated to serve the purpose. I agree with this, but I
think there may be other large obstacles also. One is Stevenson’s steadfastly
parapsychological presentation. He was very much a psychical researcher of
the old school and was not good at communicating with scientists of other
disciplines, despite his many publications in mainstream journals. Another part
of the problem may lie with the word reincarnation.
Do the cases Stevenson studied suggest or support reincarnation? Not if we
define it in the Indic sense, as involving karma. If we want to say that these cases
suggest reincarnation, we must be clear that we mean Animistic reincarnation,
and we would do well to point out that the evidence we have suggests that it
occurs most often in the same community or region and that there typically are
very few years between lives.41 There is no hint in the spontaneous cases of
past lives centuries before in distant foreign lands, as was commonly envisaged
before 1960. Nor is there much evidence of past lives spent as animals, as is
allowed under Hinduism and Buddhism (and in some societies with animistic
beliefs). In other words, we must distinguish an empirically based, scientific
understanding of reincarnation from a religious or occult one. We may also
want to follow McTaggart’s lead and come up with a new name for the process.
Stevenson’s most important legacy arguably lies in making reincarnation
a problem for science, not merely religion and philosophy, but we must now
take the next steps. It is good to show that reincarnation is logically coherent
and that it makes better sense of the data than other theories do, but until we
can demonstrate its relation to established concepts in biology and psychology,
we will not have advanced much beyond where we were in 1960, as far as
the majority of scientists are concerned.42 Moreover, although I think that
current data point in the direction of reincarnation, we must be cautious in our
Book Reviews 809
conclusions, since it may turn out that our present ideas are not quite right and
that another solution, which we cannot yet see, is the correct one. Regardless,
reincarnation-type cases without a doubt present a problem for science, one that
we will always be indebted to Stevenson and Twenty Cases for having brought
to our attention.
Acknowledgments
I owe many thanks to Antonia Mills for email discussions of the theoretical issues
addressed in this paper, which helped me to clarify both my ideas and their expression.
I would like to thank her also for reading the paper in draft and making many useful
editorial suggestions. Carlos Alvarado read it at a late stage and also made useful
suggestions. Finally, I want to thank Nivedita Nadkarni, M.D., a Resident in Psychiatry at
the University of Virginia, for helping me to understand Hindu concepts of reincarnation
and karma.
Notes
1
Twenty Cases remains in press in its 1980 paperback edition.
2
The 2001 publication is a updated edition of the book of the same title published in
1987.
3
Stevenson referred to the person of the previous life as the “previous personality,” but
persons and personalities are not at all the same thing. The individuals concerned were
more than personalities, and I prefer the term “previous person” (Matlock, 1990b).
4
The current name is Division of Perceptual Studies.
5
I use the term “spontaneous case” as it used in parapsychology, to denote paranormal
experiences. Spontaneous past-life memories resemble what psychologists call in-
voluntary memories and flashbulb memories, except that many have behavioral and
physical components.
6
Super-ESP is ESP of a nature and range not otherwise observed.
7
There was, however, more evidence than Myers realized. The earliest recorded rein-
carnation-type cases presently known are Chinese cases dating from the 3rd to the 10th
centuries AD (De Groot, 1901:143–145, and Paton, 1921:26–27, per Gauld, 2008:33,
Note 7). Nineteenth-century cases are described by Wortabet (1860:308–309n; retold
by Oliphant, 1880:322–323), Hearn (1897:267–290), and Fielding (1898:335–353).
Signs of the sort now recognized to be recurrent features of cases appear in the reports
of travelers, missionaries, and government functionaries from the 17th through the
19th centuries (Tylor, 1871:3–5). Besterman (1930) cites 19th-century examples from
sub-Saharan Africa, and Matlock and Mills (1994) have several 19th-century refer-
ences for North American native societies.
8
Many Spiritualists were opposed to reincarnation because they thought that it was
contradicted by mediumistic communication and because mediums were said not to
hear about it from deceased communicators. This was not the case in continental
Europe, where Kardec’s Spiritism and, later, Steiner’s Anthroposophy were popular
(see Note 9), leading to tensions between adherents of the different spiritualist schools
(see Alvarado, 2003:83–84, for examples of the Victorian Spiritualist attitude toward
Spiritism).
810 Book Reviews
9
Other occult systems, including Spiritism (Kardec, 1875), Anthroposophy (Steiner,
1914), and Rosicrucianism (Heindel, 1909), also taught reincarnation, but Theosophy
was by far the most prominent in the earlier part of the 20th century in the United
States and Great Britain. On reincarnation and 19th-century Spiritism in France, see a
recent book by Sharp (2006).
10
Rogo (1985:17–18) suggested that the SPR’s lack of interest in reincarnation may
have stemmed from their dislike of the Theosophist Helena Blavatsky, whom they had
investigated and found a fraud (Hodgson, Netherclift, & Sidgwick, 1885). Another
factor may have been doubts raised by the different positions taken by Spiritualism
and Spiritism (Sudre, 1930).
11
Xenoglossy is the correct use of an unlearned language. It may be either recitative
(use of words or expressions only without the ability to converse) or responsive (use
of language in an interactive way, showing the ability to understand as well as speak).
12
This author has generally been cited in psychical research as Campbell-Praed (e.g.,
by Rogo, 1985, and Stevenson, 1960), probably because Shirley (1936) hyphenated
the name. However, the name is not hyphenated on the title pages of her books and
appears as Praed in the catalog of the Library of Congress, the authority followed by
most libraries.
13
Sunderlal submitted this paper first to the ASPR Journal, but the editors thought it
possibly a hoax because similar cases were unknown to them (documents in the ASPR
archives).
14
The case of Shanti Devi began to develop in the early 1930s and led to a formal
investigation in the middle of that decade (Gupta, Sharma, & Mathur, 1936). Shanti
retained her memories into adulthood, which permitted other investigators to interview
her as well (Bose, 1952, Lönnerstrand, 1998, Rawat, 1997). Today it is one of the
best-known Indian child cases but this was not so in the period before 1960. Ducasse
(1961) appears to have been the first after Shirley (1936) to comment on it in English.
Tenhaeff (1958) dealt with it, but in Dutch, and an English translation of his book was
not published until 1972.
15
Objections were raised earlier by Pringle-Pattison (1922), whose concept of reincar-
nation was informed mainly by Hindu and Buddhist teachings. Siwek’s treatment is,
so far as I know, the first skeptical one to deal extensively with memory claims.
16
Indeed, Ducasse doubted the regressions of de Rochas (1911) not only because they
were not veridical but because the lives ostensibly recalled were located in France
rather than in distant locales (Ducasse, 1961:274).
17
However, Ayer made the same point a few years earlier (1956:193–194), so this pas-
sage may be no more than a coincidence of timing.
18
Stevenson has found this idea in various parts of the world, among the Alaskan Tlingit
and Nigerian Igbo as well as throughout South Asia (2001:96).
19
I do not have space to consider other ESP models, such as Murphy’s application
of Carington’s psychon theory (Murphy, 1973), Roll’s long body (1982), or Keil’s
thought bundles (2010), but as none transcend culture, the same general consider-
ations apply to them also. See Matlock (1990b) on the earlier theories and Nahm and
Hassler (2011) on Keil.
20
Stevenson learned about another man who as a child claimed to remember the life of
the cousin who had been killed in the truck accident. Because both he and Imad spoke
about the same accident, albeit from different points of view, this case has been por-
Book Reviews 811
trayed as one of “merged and divided” rebirth by Roll (1977, 1982) and Rogo (1985).
There would seem little basis for this reading (Matlock, 1992). Apart from the truck
accident, the memories of the two subjects were entirely distinct.
21
Adult spontaneous past-life memory cases have received relatively little attention.
In adults, apparent memories (much less-developed and less often veridical than in
young children) tend to arise in dreams, trances, and other altered states (Jacobson,
1974, Lenz, 1979, Osborn, 1937, Pasricha, 1990:109–112, Rogo, 1985, 1991).
22
This case is commonly known by the name of the previous person, Sharada. It has
been analyzed as one of possession rather than reincarnation by Griffin (1997) and
Braude (2003), but both Stevenson (1984) and Akolkar (1992), who investigated it,
treat it as one of reincarnation. The key is appreciating that Uttara was relatively old
at case onset. She was practiced in meditation and this may have played an important
role in the way her memories presented (Matlock, 1988).
23
The median intermission was four months among the Haida of Alaska. The longest
median intermission of ten societies compared was 141 months in a series of 25 non-
tribal U.S. cases (Stevenson, 1986:212).
24
I am suggesting something more than the idea that thoughts at the point of death have
an influence on the new birth, as one finds in Tibetan and other forms of Buddhism. I
mean long-held, firmly established beliefs that may be largely unconscious and may
persist after death in the “mind” of a discarnate actor who brings about his or her own
reincarnation.
25
Only a few other cases of this sort have been reported (Barrington, Mulacz, & Rivas,
2005, Pasricha, 1990:104–109, Stevenson, 1983b:171–190). However, although rare,
the phenomenon is common enough in India to be recognized by a special name in
Hindu religious thought—parakaya pravesh, which refers to the entry of a wandering
soul into a physical body, replacing the soul with which the body was born (Nivedita
Nadkarni, personal communication). Parakaya pravesh generally is glossed as “pos-
session” in English, though this obscures the fact that it covers both temporary and
permanent forms of possession.
26
Karma is also missing from ancient Greek and other reincarnation concepts, as
Obeyesekere (2002) shows in some detail. It is found only in the Indic religions and
occult systems such as Theosophy that are derived from them.
27
It is interesting that Wijeratne did not have a birthmark related to the hanging. I
suggest that he did not because the previous person was more concerned (perhaps
preoccupied) with the murder he had committed. I do not think that birthmarks are
automatically produced but rather that they are conditioned by the previous person’s
focus of attention and emotional attachments. This hypothesis allows us to explain
why not all death wounds produce birthmarks and why some represent marks made to
the body after death, as well as why some represent wounds or marks from earlier in
life (Stevenson, 1997a, 2001).
28
Despite opposition from the Catholic Church, reincarnation is widely accepted in Bra-
zil, with beliefs derived from the West African culture of former slaves, reinforced by
the Spiritism of Allan Kardec.
29
The animistic worldview is fundamentally empirical. Tylor (1871), who introduced
animism, argued that concepts of the soul and its survival of death were suggested by
observations and experiences such as paranormal dreams, apparitions, and what we
now call out-of-body and near-death experiences. Tylor believed that the soul was
812 Book Reviews
then generalized to lower animals and in some situations to plants and to natural force
and even to words and names, although these last are by no means universal features
of animism as it appears in the ethnographic record (Matlock, 1993, 1995).
30
Animistic peoples do not necessarily see a conflict between ancestral spirits and rein-
carnation. In a cross-cultural study (Matlock, 1995), I found a statistically significant
relationship (p =.003) between beliefs in reincarnation and active ancestral spirits,
those thought to interact with the living in some way. In another study, I found a sig-
nificant relationship (p =.035) between beliefs in reincarnation and the fragmentation
of the soul upon death (Matlock, 1993:128–129). Typically, the soul is thought to split
three ways upon death, one part staying with the corpse, another part going on to the
land of the dead, and a third part reincarnating.
31
In the introduction to the Tlingit cases in Twenty Cases, Stevenson described what he
thought were indications of karma in Tlingit beliefs and speculated that these were
influenced by contact with Buddhism. However, the examples he gives of karma are
of no more than a belief in the continuity of identity from one life to another and have
no reference to the moral qualities of actions with which karma is concerned. He does
not repeat this assertion on other occasions.
32
This classification of Hindu with Buddhist, Jain, and Sikh beliefs as Indic is problem-
atical because in Hinduism, unlike in the other religions, there has long been debate
about whether karma is the result of individual action alone or whether it is imple-
mented or adjusted by God (O’Flaherty, 1980). In modern Hinduism, God is involved
in the mediation of karma to such an extent that modern Hinduism is better assigned
to a Theistic category (Nivedita Nadkarni, personal communication). In Theistic re-
incarnation, God determines how a new birth is assigned. Other examples of Theistic
reincarnation beliefs are the Druse and Alevi (see Stevenson, 2001:38).
33
Obeyesekere (2002) compares planned returns in animistic societies to the “rebirth
wishes” that often are a part of Buddhist merit-making rituals. The latter may
include desires to be reborn to certain people, especially in the same family, but
Obeyesekere—I think correctly—reads these as survivals of earlier animistic beliefs
because they are fundamentally at odds with karma (2002:344).
34
Announcing dreams are dreams in which a deceased person appears and “announces”
his or her intention to be reborn, usually to a certain woman.
35
This brings us to the “selection problem” (the problem of how the new parents are
selected), but I do not have space here to go further into the issue. For a longer dis-
cussion, see Stevenson (2001:236–244), and see also the literature on intermission
memories (Rawat & Rivas, 2005, Sharma & Tucker, 2005, Story, 1975:191–199).
36
Chari (1967) observed that there are few cases not only in South India, but in most
of North India also. It appears that reincarnation-type cases occur more frequently in
some places than others. The reasons for this variation would seem to have little to do
with belief but are not yet understood.
37
This conclusion would be stronger if it were more than impressionistic. Tucker’s
(2000) Strength of Case Scale could be used to rate the strength of cases, which could
then be compared to the strength of reincarnation beliefs in different cultures, if this
could be assessed in some way.
38
Many religious traditions and occult systems have similar concepts, but Stevenson
introduced his neologism, which means “soul bearing,” to avoid their connotations
(2001:309). Elsewhere he suggested that the psychophore might be composed of mor-
Book Reviews 813
JAMES G. MATLOCK
[email protected]
References
Akolkar, V. V. (1992). Search for Sharada: Summary of a case and its investigation. Journal of the
American Society for Psychical Research, 86, 209–247.
Almeder, R. (1992). Death and Personal Survival. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield.
Almeder, R. (1996). Almeder’s reply to Wheatley and Braude. Journal of Scientific Exploration,
10, 529–533.
Alvarado, C. A. (2003). The concept of survival of bodily death and the development of
parapsychology. Journal of the Society for Psychical Research, 67, 65–95.
Alvarado, C. A., & Zingrone, N. L. (2008). Ian Stevenson and the modern study of spontaneous
ESP experiences. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 22, 44–53.
Andrade, H. G. (1988). Reencarnação no Brasil. Matão: O Clarim.
Andrade, H. G., Rossi, E., Playfair, G. L., & Lima, R. (2010). Science & Spirit. London: Roundtable.
Angel, L. (1994a). Empirical evidence of reincarnation? Examining Stevenson’s “most impressive”
case. Skeptical Inquirer, 18, 481–487.
Angel, L. (1994b). Enlightenment East and West. Albany: State University of New York Press.
Ayer, A. J. (1956). The Problem of Knowledge. Hammondsworth, Middlesex, UK: Penguin.
Ayer, A. J. (1963). The Concept of a Person and Other Essays. London: Macmillan.
Barrett, W. F. (1917). On the Threshold of the Unseen. London: K. Paul, Trench, Trübner.
Barrington, M. R., Mulacz, P., & Rivas, T. (2005). The case of Iris Farczády—A stolen life. Journal
of the Society for Psychical Research, 69, 49–77.
Becker, C. (1993). Paranormal Experience and the Survival of Death. Albany: SUNY Press.
814 Book Reviews
Ducasse, C. J. (1960). How the case of The Search for Bridey Murphy stands today. Journal of the
American Society for Psychical Research, 54, 3–22.
Ducasse, C. J. (1961). A Critical Examination of the Belief in a Life after Death. Springfield, IL:
Charles C. Thomas.
Edelman, J., & Bernet, W. (2007). Setting criteria for ideal reincarnation research. Journal of
Consciousness Studies, 14, 92–101.
Edelstein, S. J. (2008). The quest for acceptance. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 22, 95–99.
Edwards, P. (1996). Reincarnation: A Critical Examination. Amherst, NY: Prometheus Books.
Fielding, H. (1898). The Soul of a People. London: Bentley and Son.
Flammarion, C. (1923). Death and Its Mystery: After Death; Manifestations and Apparitions of the
Dead; the Soul after Death. London: T. Fisher Unwin.
Flournoy, T. (1900). From India to the Planet Mars. New York: Harper & Brothers.
Fürer-Haimendorf, C. von (1953). The after-life in Indian tribal belief. Journal of the Royal
Anthropological Institute, 83, 37–49.
Gauld, A. (1961). The “super-ESP” hypothesis. Proceedings of the Society for Psychical Research,
53, 226–246.
Gauld, A. (1968). The Founders of Psychical Research. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
Gauld, A. (2008). Reflections on the life and work of Ian Stevenson. Journal of Scientific
Exploration, 22, 18–35.
Geléy, G. (1920). From the Unconscious to the Conscious. London: William Collins.
Geléy, G. (1930). Reincarnation. London: Rider.
Grant, J. (1937). Winged Pharaoh. London: A. Barker.
Grant, J. (1956). Far Memory. New York: Harper.
Griffin, D. R. (1997). Parapsychology, Philosophy, and Spirituality: A Postmodern Exploration.
Albany: State University of New York Press.
Grosso, M. (2004). Experiencing the Next World Now. New York: Paraview Pocket Books.
Gupta, L. D., Sharma, N. R., & Mathur, T. C. (1936). An Inquiry into the Case of Shanti Devi. New
Delhi: International Aryan League.
Haraldsson, E. (1995). Personality and abilities of children claiming previous-life memories.
Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 183, 445–451.
Haraldsson, E. (1997). Psychological comparison between ordinary children and those who claim
previous-life memories. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 11, 323–335.
Haraldsson, E. (2003). Children who speak of a past life experience: Is there a psychological
explanation? Psychology and Psychotherapy, 76, 55–67.
Haraldsson, E., Fowler, P. C., & Periyannanpillai, V. (2000). Psychological characteristics of
children who speak of a previous life: A further field study in Sri Lanka. Transcultural
Psychiatry, 37, 525–544.
Harrison, P., & Harrison, M. (1991). The Children That Time Forgot. Emsworth, England: Kenneth
Mason.
Hart, H. (1959). The Enigma of Survival: The Case for and Against an After Life. Springfield, IL:
Charles C. Thomas.
Hearn, L. (1897). Gleanings in Buddha-Fields. Boston: Houghton, Mifflin.
Heindel, Max (1909). The Rosicrucian Cosmo-Conception; or, Christian Occult Science. Seattle:
Rosicrucian Fellowship.
Hill, J. A. (1929). Some reincarnationist automatic scripts. Proceedings of the Society for Psychical
Research, 38, 375–387.
Hodgson, R., Netherclift, F. G., & Sidgwick, Mrs. H. (1885). Report of the committee appointed
to investigate phenomena connected with the Theosophical Society. Proceedings of the
Society for Psychical Research, 3, 201–400.
Hulme, A. J. H., & Wood, F. H. (1936). Ancient Egypt Speaks: A Miracle of “Tongues”. London:
Rider.
816 Book Reviews
Hyslop, J. H. (1906). Borderland of Psychical Research. Boston: Small, Maynard & Co.
Hyslop, J. H. (1919). Contact with the Other World. New York: Century.
Jacobson, N. (1974). Life without Death? On Parapsychology, Mysticism and the Question of
Survival. New York: Delacorte Press.
Jefferson, W. (2009). Reincarnation Beliefs of North American Indians. Summertown, TN: Native
Voices.
Johnson, R. C. (1953). The Imprisoned Splendor. New York: Harper & Bros.
Kardec, A. (1875). Spiritualist Philosophy: The Spirits’ Book. London: Trübner & Co.
Keil, [H. H.] J. (1996). Cases of the reincarnation type: An evaluation of some indirect evidence
with examples of “silent” cases. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 10, 467–485.
Keil, [H. H.] J. (2010). Questions of the reincarnation type. Journal of Scientific Exploration, 24,
79–99.
Keil, H. H. J., & Tucker, J. (2005). Children who claim to remember previous lives: Cases with
written records made before the previous personality was identified. Journal of Scientific
Exploration, 19, 91–101.
Kelsey, D., & Grant, J. (1967). Many Lifetimes. Garden City, New York: Doubleday.
Lancelin, C. (1922). La Vie Posthume. Paris: Henri Durville.
Leininger, B., & Leininger, A. (2009). Soul Survivor: The Reincarnation of a World War II Fighter
Pilot. New York: Grand Central Publishing.
Lenz, F. (1979). Lifetimes: True Accounts of Reincarnation. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.
Lodge, O. (1907). The Substance of Faith Allied with Science. New York and London: Harper &
Bros.
Lönnerstrand, S. (1998). I Have Lived Before: The True Story of the Reincarnation of Shanti Devi.
Huntsville, AR: Ozark Mountain Publishers.
Lund, D. H. (2009). Persons, Souls and Death: A Philosophical Investigation of an Afterlife.
Jefferson, NC: McFarland.
Matlock, J. G. (1988). The decline of past life memory with subject’s age in spontaneous
reincarnation cases. In M. L. Albertson, D. S. Ward, & K. P. Freeman (Eds.), Paranormal
Research, Ft. Collins, CO: Rocky Mountain Research Institute, pp. 388–401.
Matlock, J. G. (1989). Age and stimulus in past life memory cases: A study of published cases.
Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 83, 303–316.
Matlock, J. G. (1990a). Of names and signs: Reincarnation, inheritance and social structure on the
Northwest Coast. Anthropology of Consciousness, 1(2), 9–18.
Matlock, J. G. (1990b). Past life memory case studies. In S. Krippner (Ed.), Advances in
Parapsychological Research, 6, Jefferson, NC: McFarland, pp. 184–267.
Matlock, J. G. (1992). Interpreting the case of Imad Elawar. Journal of Religion and Psychical
Research, 15, 91–98.
Matlock, J. G. (1993). A Cross-Cultural Study of Reincarnation Ideologies and Their Social
Correlates. [Unpublished M.A. thesis, Hunter College, New York: City University of New
York.]
Matlock, J. G. (1995). Death symbolism in matrilineal societies: A replication study. Cross-Cultural
Research, 29, 158–177.
Matlock, J. G. (1996). Reincarnation. In D. Levinson & M. Ember (Eds.), Encyclopedia of Cultural
Anthropology, Volume 3, New York: Henry Holt, pp. 1086–1089.
Matlock, J. G., & Mills, A. (1994). A trait index to North American Indian and Inuit reincarnation
beliefs. In A. Mills & R. Sobodin (Eds.), Amerindian Rebirth, Toronto: University of
Toronto Press, pp. 299–356.
McHarg, J. F. (1969). Review of Twenty Cases Suggestive of Reincarnation by I. Stevenson. British
Journal of Medical Psychology, 42, 84–86.
McTaggart, J. M. E. (1906). Some Dogmas of Religion. London: Edwin Arnold.
Mills, A. (1988). A comparison of Witsuwit’en cases of the reincarnation type with Gitksan and
Book Reviews 817
O’Flaherty, W. D. (Ed.) (1980). Karma and Rebirth in Classical Indian Traditions. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Oliphant, L. (1880). The Land of Gilead. Edinburgh and London: Blackwood.
Osborn, A. (1937). The Superphysical. London: Nicholson & Watson.
Pasricha, S. K. (1990). Claims of Reincarnation: An Empirical Study of Cases in India. New Delhi:
Harman Publishing House.
Pasricha, S. [K.] (1992). Are reincarnation type cases shaped by parental guidance? An empirical
study concerning the limits of parents’ influence on children. Journal of Scientific
Exploration, 6, 167–180.
Pasricha, S. K. (2001). Cases of the reincarnation type in South India: Why so few reports? Journal
of Scientific Exploration, 15, 211–221.
Paterson, R. W. K. (1995). Philosophy and the Belief in a Life after Death. New York: St. Martin’s
Press.
Paton, L. B. (1921). Spiritism and the Cult of the Dead in Antiquity. London: Hodder & Stoughton.
Playfair, G. [L.] (1975). The Flying Cow: Research into Paranormal Phenomena in the World’s
Most Psychic Country. London: Souvenir Press.
Playfair, G. L. (2006). New Clothes for Old Souls: Worldwide Evidence for Reincarnation. London:
Druze Heritage Foundation.
Praed, Mrs. C. (1931). Soul of Nyria. London: Rider.
Prince, W. F. (1927). The Case of Patience Worth. Boston: Boston Society for Psychic Research.
Pringle-Pattison, A. S. (1922). The Idea of Immortality: The Gifford Lectures. Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Rawat, K. S. (1997). The case of Shanti Devi. Venture Inward (March/April 1997), 18–21.
Rawat, K. S., & Rivas, T. (2005). The life beyond: Through the eyes of children who claim to
remember previous lives. Journal of Religion and Psychical Research, 28, 126–136.
Rawat, K. S. & Rivas, T. (2007). Reincarnation: The Scientific Evidence Is Building. Vancouver:
Writers.
Rhine, L. R. (1966). Review of Twenty Cases Suggestive of Reincarnation by I. Stevenson. Journal
of Parapsychology, 30, 263–272.
Rivas, T. (2000). Parapsychologisch Onderzoek naar Reïncarnatie en Leven na de Dood. Deventer,
The Netherlands: Ankh-Hermes.
Rivas, T. (2003). Three new cases of the reincarnation type in The Netherlands. Journal of Scientific
Exploration, 17, 527–532.
Rivas, T. (2004). Six cases of the reincarnation type in The Netherlands. Paranormal Review, 29
(January), 17–21.
de Rochas, A. (1911). Les Vies Successives, Documents pour l’Étude de Cette Question. Paris:
Bibliothèque Chacornac.
Rogo, D. S. (1985). The Search for Yesterday: A Critical Examination of the Evidence for
Reincarnation. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
Rogo, D. S. (1991). State of consciousness factors in reincarnation cases. In A. Berger & J. Berger
(Eds.), Reincarnation: Fact or Fable?, London: Aquarian Press, pp. 15–30.
Roll, W. G. (1977). Where Is Said Bouhamsy? Theta, 5(3), 1–4.
Roll, W. G. (1982). The changing perspective on life after death. In S. Krippner (Ed.), Advances in
Parapsychological Research, 3, New York: Plenum Press, pp. 147–291.
Sagan, C. (1997). The Demon-Haunted World. New York: Random House.
Schouten, S., & Stevenson, I. (1998). Does the socio-psychological hypothesis explain cases of the
reincarnation type? Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 186, 504–506.
Sharma, P., & Tucker, J. (2005). Cases of the reincarnation type with memories of the intermission
between lives. Journal of Near-Death Studies, 23, 101–118.
Sharp, L. L. (2006). Secular Spirituality: Reincarnation and Spiritism in Nineteenth-Century
France. Lanham, MD: Lexington Books.
Book Reviews 819
Sheldrake, R. (1981). A New Science of Life: The Hypothesis of Formative Causation. London:
Blond & Briggs.
Sheldrake, R. (2009). Morphic Resonance: The Nature of Formative Causation (fourth U.S. revised
edition). Rochester, VT: Park Street Press.
Shirley, R. (1936). The Problem of Rebirth: An Enquiry into the Basis of the Reincarnationist
Hypothesis. London: Rider.
Siwek, P. (1953). The Enigma of the Hereafter: The Re-incarnation of Souls. New York:
Philosophical Library.
Steiner, R. (1914). An Outline of Occult Science. Chicago: Rand, McNally.
Stemman, R. (2005). One Soul, Many Lives: First-Hand Stories of Reincarnation and the Striking
Evidence of Past Lives. Berkeley, CA: Ulysses Press.
Stevens, E. W. (1887). The Watseka Wonder. Chicago: Religio-Philosophical Publishing House.
Stevenson, I. (1960). The evidence for survival from claimed memories of former incarnations. Part
I. Review of the data. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research, 54, 51–71.
Stevenson, I. (1961–1962). Comments on “Parapsychology and ‘reincarnation’” by Professor C. T.
K. Chari. Indian Journal of Parapsychology, 3(2), 22–26.
Stevenson, I. (1966a). Cultural patterns in cases suggestive of reincarnation among the Tlingit
Indians of southeastern Alaska. Journal of the American Society for Psychical Research,
60, 229–243.
Stevenson, I. (1966b). Twenty cases suggestive of reincarnation. Proceedings of the American
Society for Psychical Research, 26, 1–362.
Stevenson, I. (1974a). Some questions related to cases of the reincarnation type. Journal of the
American Society for Psychical Research, 68, 395–416.
Stevenson, I. (1974b). Twenty Cases Suggestive of Reincarnation (second edition, revised).
Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia.
Stevenson, I. (1975a). Cases of the Reincarnation Type. I: Ten Cases in India. Charlottesville:
University Press of Virginia.
Stevenson, I. (1975b). The belief and cases related to reincarnation among the Haida. Journal of
Anthropological Research, 31, 364–375.
Stevenson, I. (1977a). Cases of the Reincarnation Type. II: Ten Cases in Sri Lanka. Charlottesville:
University Press of Virginia.
Stevenson, I. (1977b). The Southeast Asian interpretation of gender dysphoria: An illustrative case
report. Journal of Nervous and Mental Disease, 165, 201–208.
Stevenson, I. (1980). Cases of the Reincarnation Type. III: Twelve Cases in Lebanon and Turkey.
Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia.
Stevenson I. (1983a). American children who claim to remember previous lives. Journal of Nervous
and Mental Disease, 171, 742–748.
Stevenson, I. (1983b). Cases of the Reincarnation Type. IV: Twelve Cases in Thailand and Burma.
Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia.
Stevenson, I. (1984). Unlearned Language: New Studies in Xenoglossy. Charlottesville: University
Press of Virginia.
Stevenson, I. (1986). Characteristics of cases of the reincarnation type among the Igbo of Nigeria.
Journal of Asian and African Studies, 21, 204–216.
Stevenson, I. (1990). Some of My Journeys in Medicine (Flora Levy Lecture in the Humanities,
1989). Lafayette: The University of Southwestern Louisiana. http://www.medicine.
virginia.edu/clinical/departments/psychiatry/sections/cspp/dops/publicationslinks/some-
of-my-journeys-in-medicine.pdf.
Stevenson, I. (1995). Empirical evidence for reincarnation? A response to Leonard Angel. Skeptical
Inquirer, 19, 50–51.
Stevenson, I. (1997a). Reincarnation and Biology: A Contribution to the Etiology of Birthmarks
and Birth Defects. Volume 1: Birthmarks. Westport, CT: Praeger.
820 Book Reviews
BOOK REVIEWS
821
822 Book Reviews
this holistic science would have to stand in mutually respectful and construc-
tive complementarity to one another if the composite discipline were to fulfill
itself and its role in society.
Dare I give one more “whew”? In this section they explore whether quantum
metaphors have sufficient power to help us understand their data; whether it is
more productive to think of the apparent correlations between the conscious
mind and tangible output in a more circuitous route involving unconscious
processes (their M5 model); the place of filters in the communication between
consciousness and its Source. Finally, they anticipate the intellectual pushback
in the reader reacting to their paradigm-busting presentation. Are the data
wrong? Are they real but not important? Should we consider this outside of
scientific inquiry? Should we keep working to get back to our safe deterministic
models? Should we change the rules of science? Jahn and Dunne, in a masterly
essay, recommend the latter. Let’s “Change the Rules!”
The final section, Consolidation and Closure, is as promised, and presents
itself as the most speculative of the sections. As they pose the question of how
to distill both their empirical data and theoretical propositions, Jahn and Dunne
really let out all of the stops. Again, in their own words:
Again, not to give away the punch line, they suggest that traditional science
has been focused on the famous equivalence of matter and energy, but they
have left information out of their equations. To them, the most facile conceptual
language to describe their results is information: in the case of REGs, insertion
into the random binary strings; in the case of remote perception, extraction from
a global array of possible targets. And returning to the science of the subjective,
they implore us to somehow balance the more objective measurements of
information quantification with the more subjective sense of personal meaning.
Indeed, more attention to such subjective states as “intention,” “resonance,”
“unconscious processing,” and more are called for. Imagine “a functionally
proactive subjective consciousness . . . added to the arsenal of scientific concepts
and tools . . .” Game changer.
This is a beautiful book. I recommend reading it slowly, thoroughly, and
reflectively. The prose is rich and is actually aesthetically pleasing. I found
Book Reviews 825
WILLIAM F. BENGSTON
St. Joseph’s College
President, Society for Scientific Exploration
What might physician and professor of geriatric medicine Raymond Tallis and
actor John Rhys-Davies have in common? In Peter Jackson’s epic film The
Lord of the Rings, Rhys-Davies (as Gimli the dwarf) wields an axe with such
consummate skill as to challenge, intimidate, and lend a hand in the defeat
of the evil orcs of Mordor; while in Aping Mankind Tallis (as philosopher
and scientist) with a finely-honed axe of logic takes on perhaps equally
formidable foes: those Cognitive Scientists possessed by Neuromania (p. 26)
and Evolutionary Biologists obsessed by Darwinitis (p. 40) (called respectively
Neuromaniacs and Darwinitics).
An inapt comparison? Orcs are degenerate mutations from a once-benign
race, who would destroy or enslave all humankind, while Evolutionary Biologists
and Cognitive Scientists are, certainly, benign professionals enriching the store
of knowledge for the benefit of all. Yet as Tallis makes abundantly clear, many
Cognitive Scientists believe that the mind is the brain, the brain is a computer,
and since a computer has no self and does not exist in a world of intentionality,
human beings have no selves and do not exist in a world of intentionality
(p. 101).1 Some biologists and psychologists, influenced by the twin premises
that the brain is a product of evolution and that the mind is a computer–brain,
826 Book Reviews
The human brain is a machine which alone accounts for all our actions, our
most private thoughts, our beliefs. . . . All our actions are products of the activ-
ity of our brains. (p. 50)
In referring to private thoughts and beliefs, this does not go far enough;
a significant theme in neuroscientific circles is eliminative materialism, which
argues that thoughts are merely the flow of physical energies within the
computer–brain, and beliefs are illusions of a “folk psychology” eventually to
be replaced by a new conceptual framework provided by neuroscience.3 And
since the self is an illusion, the idea of any thought being private is also in error,
since there is nothing for a thought to be private to. The brain is a machine which
has no thoughts and no beliefs. And “you” are “your” brain (but there is no you).
Book Reviews 827
What I am now going to relate is the history of the next two centuries. I shall
describe what will happen, what must necessarily happen: the triumph of Ni-
hilism. . . . What does Nihilism mean? That the highest values are losing their
value. There is no bourne. There is no answer to the question: To what pur-
pose? . . . Thorough Nihilism is the conviction that life is absurd. (Nietzsche,
1910, Preface and p. 8)
Seen from the perspective provided by Tallis, one may wonder whether this
prediction is well on its way toward fulfillment. Surely it is cavalier, with the
presumed authority of science, to divest the world of meaning by intentionally
denying the existence of intentionality. But whether the dire result feared by
Tallis is avoidable or inevitable would seem to depend on the question of
whether the identification of humanity with animality and of the mind with a
computer–brain is founded on truth or scientistic confusion.5
Love is not like a response to a simple stimulus such as a picture. It is not even a
single enduring state, like being cold. It encompasses many things, including: not
feeling in love at that moment; hunger; indifference; delight, wanting to be kind;
wanting to impress; worrying over the logistics of meetings; lust; awe; surprise;
joy; guilt; anger; jealousy; imagining conversations or events; speculating what
the loved one is doing when one is not there; and so on. . . . The more you think
about the idea that human life can be parcelled out into discrete functions that
are allocated to their own bits of the brain, the more absurd it seems. (pp. 75–80)
The stable ideal meanings which are the fruit of nature are forbidden . . . from
dropping seeds in nature to its further fructification. (Dewey, 1958:58)
Book Reviews 831
As I read him, this is the central point of Tallis’s deeply felt concern:
Instead of running away from the world of common sense and calling it
pejorative names such as folk psychology, science should always, no matter
how abstract its theory becomes, return to that world and give back with interest
what it has taken. The startling degree to which the neuro- and evolutionary-
pseudosciences manage to impoverish the world is starkly highlighted in a
summary Tallis gives in Chapter 9 (p. 337).
Misplaced Anti-Animality
Tallis to this point has presented a richly detailed and convincingly argued
position, and he does this in a highly readable style. But now we come to a less
satisfactory discussion. Tallis still must put Evolutionary Biology in its place.
Here he commits a large-scale blunder. In order to reject the idea that all human
behavior is explained by reference to animal instinct driven exclusively by the
mechanism of natural selection, he finds himself having to advocate a yawning
gulf between animal life and human experience. The form his argument takes
is to mount a wholesale denigration of animal existence. Human behavior is
fundamentally different (p. 233). He comes close to concatenating animals with
insentient matter (p. 232). Animal vision is “programmed response” while that
of humans is “the gaze which looks out and sees” (p. 171). Animal life, in
contrast to the human shared world, is rather a world of “bumped-into objects
and forces,” seeming to suggest that animals are little different from billiard
balls. Animal emotions are exhausted by the “rapid heart rate and increased
respiratory rate of a beast being prepared for fighting, fleeing, feeding, or
copulating” (p. 233). It is, he says, bad biology to assimilate animal emotions
to human feelings. He does not appear to realize that it is also bad biology to
assimilate animal behavior to that of billiard balls.
Animals as he sees them also do not live in any dimension of time. While
human experience has temporal depth (p. 250), the behavior of animals such as
crows caching food for future use does not indicate any sense of future need
but is rather a mechanical hard-wired activity with no relation to a felt need
or the existence of a future (p. 134). In such a view, an animal chasing a prey,
for example, is not pursuing a goal within a temporal dimension, but is merely
reacting mechanically from one instant to the next, with all the composite
instances being separate billiard-ball reactions to separate stimuli. There is
no telic quality (possibly rudimentary intentionality) to animal behavior, this
despite the testimony of biologists such as Edmund Sinnott, who speaks of the
“persistent directiveness or goal-seeking that is the essential feature of behavior
and thus finally the basis of all mental activity” (Sinnott, 1955:52).
Sinnott is not a DT. He does not reduce human behavior to that of animals.
But he posits a continuity in the development of consciousness from animal to
832 Book Reviews
human life. Such continuity works both ways: There is something of the animal
in the human, but there is also something of the human in the animal. Tallis is
exaggeratedly wary of admitting continuity as it might apply to consciousness
because he mistakenly feels that to admit any incremental or significant
developmental flow from animal to human is to give in to the DTs. We shall
see however that although Tallis repeatedly gives the (sometimes excessively
brutal) impression that nonhuman animals have nothing like a conscious
existence, he cannot hold firmly to this position, and it causes him trouble when
he arrives at his concluding attempts at a remedial theory.
The hand . . . made the human animal, our hominid ancestor, uniquely aware
of its own actively engaged body. This awoke the dim intuition that I am this
body. (p. 212)
So the key, the turning point, is the “awakening” of a dim intuition. But
how can an intuitionless being have an intuition? “Intuition” belongs to the
language of mind; an intuition can occur only to a self—even if it is “dim” and
is occurring to a limited kind of self. Otherwise “dim intuition” is just a couple
of words explaining nothing. And calling this intuition dim admits of degrees.
Something was there, some kind of self-consciousness, as a necessary condition
for the having of any intuition whatsoever. And if we grant the possibility of a
“dim intuition” there is no way to avoid the possibility of a dim anticipation or
a dim sense of having a goal: a dim, but nevertheless extant, temporal depth.
834 Book Reviews
What he has stumbled upon, driven by the force of his own reasoning,
is a theoretical position similar to that of thinkers such as Pierre Teilhard (de
Chardin), another profoundly relevant and much-neglected philosopher who is
also not within the sphere of Tallis’s references.
My point here is not to argue for the validity of Teilhard’s view, which
is nonetheless vastly more accommodating than Tallis’s attempt to slip
consciousness in where he has previously fought to deny it. The point is that
Tallis cannot get out of his dilemma without admitting a prior development of
degrees of consciousness within the evolutionary process, thereby arriving at a
position close to that of Teilhard.
The real contrast, then, seems to me to be between the closed world empty
of consciousness and deprived of selfhood as envisioned by the NMs and DTs
sitting huddled with the others in Plato’s cave, or an open world of continuity
within which human consciousness is a part of nature simply because in
one degree or another, the spawning of consciousness is an entirely natural
phenomenon and extends somehow to the roots of matter.8 If the latter is one’s
choice, and if that choice means a revolution in our understanding of matter
and of a healthier relation between science and humanity, so be it. It should be
a conclusion with which, however reluctantly, Tallis must agree.
Notes
1
Intentionality refers essentially to the sphere of meaning, as evidenced in what are
called propositional attitudes such as hopes, desires, fears, and, more broadly, beliefs,
which are directed at objects . . . or clusters of possibilities that are felt to be other than
the subject (p. 101).
2
These capitalized abbreviations are my own. Since the terms in full have a rhetorical
purpose but nevertheless do refer to specific theoretical attitudes, the more or less
neutral abbreviations are preferable.
3
For a description and criticism of these views, see Will Wilkenson, Churchland
Debunked, Commonsense Psychology Vindicated. http://enlightenment.supersaturated.
com/essays/text/willwilkinson/churchlanddebunked.html
4
Tallis gives a more incisive discussion of this concern in his small volume Why the
Book Reviews 835
Mind Is Not a Computer, pointing out how scientistic ideas contributed to oppression
of the Jews in Germany and the Kulaks in Soviet Russia (Tallis, 2004:26).
5
Scientism is “the mistaken belief that the natural sciences . . . can or will give a
complete description and explanation of everything” (p. 13).
6
Tallis’ view of a World here is reminiscent of John Dewey’s concept of “Experience”
as a fundamental category of being and the obligation of science to enrich, rather
than diminish, it. Dewey’s philosophical work has emerged from undeserved
obscurity recently as a major influence in critiques of the mind–brain identity theory
(Noë, 2009, Chemero, 2009, Rockwell, 2007).
7
An example of this fallacy outside the realm of neuroscience: “From a quantum world
view, we and the things around us are mostly empty space. The way we experience
ourselves . . . is really just a ‘figment of our imaginations shaped by our senses.’”
This from ASU Regents’ Professor David Ferry reported at http://www.physorg.com/
news197266420.html, July 2, 2010.
8
Considering matter as an expression of energy, Teilhard proposed a revision of the
concept of energy. This involved his hypothesis of the existence of a radial energy,
which is the energy leading to organization, specifically the functional organization
of matter around a center which he called the within of things (Teilhard, 1961:63ff.).
The question of the relation of this concept to standard physics has been discussed at
length in O’Manique (1969).
STAN V. MCDANIEL
Professor of Philosophy Emeritus
Sonoma State University
References
Chemero, A. (2009). Radical Embodied Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, A Bradford
Book.
Churchland, P. S.(1986). Neurophilosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Dewey, J. (1958). Experience and Nature. New York: Dover Publications. [Reprint of the 1929
edition]
Nietzsche, F. (1910). The Will to Power (Volume I of The Complete Works, edited by Oscar Levy).
Edinburgh: T. N. Foulis.
Noë, A. (2009). Out of Our Heads. Hill & Wang.
O’Manique, J. (1969). Energy in Evolution. New York: Humanities Press.
Rockwell, W. T. (2007). Neither Brain Nor Ghost: A Non-Dualist Alternative to the Mind–Brain
Identity Theory. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, A Bradford Book. [Paperback edition of the
2005 publication]
Sinnott, E. J. (1955). Biology of the Spirit. Compass Books C 17.
Tallis, R. (2004). Why the Mind Is Not a Computer. Charlottesville, VA: Imprint Academic.
Teilhard de Chardin, P. (1961). The Phenomenon of Man. Harper Torchbooks TB383. [Original
publication in French, 1955]
Zeki, S., & Goodenough, O. (2006). Law and the Brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
836 Book Reviews
In this accessible book, Allan Combs takes on the daunting task of addressing
the subject matter of consciousness. The title, Consciousness Explained Better,
alludes to the title of Daniel Dennett’s book Consciousness Explained, in which
Dennett gives a reductionist account of consciousness. But the title of Combs’s
book is misleading in that his book consists of a description of the structures
of experience and not an explanation of consciousness, nor of experience or
its structures. However, for those who are unfamiliar with a developmental
approach to the structures of experience, this book is a good introduction.
Combs starts by taking the reader back to William James’s “world of pure
experience,” conceptually prior to the splitting of experience into subjective
and objective distinctions. His main thesis is that the actual events that occur
for us depend upon the structures through which our experience is lived. These
structures form a developmental sequence from Jean Piaget’s sensorimotor
period through his formal operational thinking and then, linking with Ken
Wilber’s cosmology, to various levels of transpersonal mentation culminating
in “nondual awareness” (p. 84), which Combs characterizes as the “Ever-
present ordinary mind; the direct experience of the nondual ground” (p. 100).
For Combs, these stages not only take place within the individual development
of people, but can also be seen as giving rise to historical time periods in which
they were first expressed. For this, Combs brings in the work of Jean Gebser
and provides examples from science and art to illustrate that contention. With
reference to the writing of Sri Aurobindo, Combs pays particular attention to
the first developmental stage after formal operational thinking, that of “Integral
or Vision Logic” (p. 100), where “multiple perspectives” (p. 144) can be
held simultaneously. Combs wants this to be more than just “a laundry list
of characteristics” and considers the relationship of integral consciousness to
“enlightenment” (p. 144).
The main strength of this book, to my mind, is the adoption of such a broad
approach to its subject matter that it forces us to reconsider the usual framework
within which consciousness is discussed. In particular, according to Combs,
Combs leans toward a “perennialist view,” and, in the end, asserts that there
are “universal dimensions of consciousness that mark us as human beings” (p.
144).
Although Combs’s account is largely descriptive, I think that he has
discerned the crux of the solution to the problem with consciousness when he
elucidates the nature of experience before its evolutionary split into subjective
and objective aspects and after its recombination into the nondual state of
being for those for whom such transcendent events have occurred. In doing
so, Combs’s work can reset the course of consciousness studies onto a more
productive track. And I would very much like to see him, along with other
researchers, develop these ideas in such a way as to explicate the nature of
experience and the reasons for its manifestations.
IMANTS BARUŠS
Department of Psychology
King’s University College at The University of Western Ontario
[email protected]
838 Book Reviews
Veteran anthropologist Alice Kehoe has written a small volume using the
Kensington Runestone controversy as a cautionary case study illustrating the
need for a multidisciplinary approach in assessing antiquities, their contexts,
and their implications. In the process, she reveals her own positive conclusions
regarding one particular object, which inadequately informed professionals
have routinely relegated to the official dustbin for infamous fakes and hoaxes.
The Kensington stone is a yard-long, shaped slab of greywacke on whose
surface appears an incised inscription in Scandinavian runic characters and
language. The inscription includes a declared carving date of 1362. In her first
chapter, Kehoe discusses the initial reports of the finding of the stone, clasped
in the roots of a modest-sized aspen tree that was being winched out of the
ground on the farm of one Olof Ohman, near Kensington, Minnesota, in 1898.
The stone and copies of its text came to be circulated to regional universities as
well as in Scandinavia, with inconclusive results. In 1907, avocational historian
Hjalmar Holand examined the object, became convinced of its authenticity, and
promoted its study, involving, among others, the Minnesota Historical Society.
The Historical Society submitted the text to Scandinavian linguists, all of
whom pronounced the inscription to be a modern fake. This conclusion was
based partly on the perceived improbability of fourteenth-century Scandinavians
being in Minnesota, partly on the flimsily based suspicion that Ohman had
faked the stone to promote Swedish pride, and partly on the linguistic and
paleographic bases of words, runes, and usages seeming to be anachronistic,
without attestation in other fourteenth-century documents.
In 1909, Minnesota’s most eminent geologist examined the stone, noted
significant patination in the runic incisions, and declared that in his opinion the
object was genuinely old. However, in view of the linguistic objections, the
Historical Society declined to conclude for or against authenticity.
Over the decades, the debate went on. Various Scandinavian-language
specialists—notably UCLA’s Erik Wahlgren in 1958—studied the text and the
runes rather cursorily and affirmed fakery, and this conclusion became mainline
belief. A pro-Runestone book by Romance-languages philologist Robert A.
Hall, Jr., published in 1982, was rather technical, and it impressed some linguists
but few, if, any, professional archaeologists or historians. The same may be
said for the work of American avocational runologist Richard Nielsen, who
speaks Danish as well as English. He has demonstrated that essentially all of the
840 Book Reviews
Savants cannot normally give insight into how they perform their skill and
are uncontaminated by learned algorithms. It just comes to them. They just
see it. With maturity, the occasionally offered insights are suspect, possibly
contaminated by the acquisition of concepts concerning their particular skill.
Yet, I have labelled one savant, Daniel Tammet, a Rosetta stone. (Snyder,
2011:3400)
following complex instructions. Yet with the crucial help of friends, Daniel was
even able to master what even ordinary people can find daunting: traveling on
the London underground. Also vital seems to have been the support of parents
and others in enabling him to spend a year doing voluntary service in Lithuania.
This experience was evidently crucial to the building of his self-confidence
and to the furthering of his fascination for languages. Shortly afterward, the
advent of computers and the Internet enabled his world of social relationship to
be greatly extended and eventually led to a lasting love relationship. The final
confirmation of the consistent parental support given to Daniel, came with his
parents’ acceptance of his declaration of being gay (which he had realized from
the age of eleven).
The book gives some insight into the feat which first brought Daniel
to the attention of the mass media: his success at winning the British and
European record for reciting pi. Daniel recited 22,514 digits in the course of
more than five hours. This was not as spontaneous as might appear from the
videorecording but required three months of practice. What is most distinctive
in his various numerical performances is the recall of digits in the form of
touchable landscapes. It is this aspect of synesthetic experience which is the
truly remarkable. The synesthetic ability is augmented by his extraordinary
memory span which has been established at 10–12 digits (compared to the
normal range of 5–7 digits).
The attention given to his success at winning this record led to the BBC
film, a documentary that included a journey to meet the real “rain man,” the
recently deceased Kim Peek. As part of the program, Daniel was willing to
take part in research to which he clearly has a positive attitude. While not all
researchers might prove worthy of this confidence, BBC’s choice of Vilayanur
Ramachandran and his assistants at the Center for Brain and Cognition proved
to be an appropriate one. It was with interest concerning the fruits of this
cooperation that I turned to the sequel book.
The title of this, Embracing the Wide Sky, is inspired from an Emily
Dickinson poem and serves to emphasize one of Daniel’s personal insights in
life. Despite his intellectual prowess, he is able to reach a state of consciousness
transcending this, and this transcendence means for him that he has a Christian
religious belief. The book begins as a primer of contemporary findings in
cognitive and neuropsychology before focusing on what Daniel Tammet has
learned from his own experience and from his now considerable knowledge of
the neuroscience literature.
One of the ready explanations for savant ability is what he calls “the
drudge theory,” by which he means that the spectacular performances are
due to repetitious and even obsessional hard work in the use of rote memory.
Clearly in most cases hard work is a prerequisite. Daniel Tammet succeeded
Book Reviews 845
have had for learning such complex skills. The above books are now a very
important contribution to this literature. Given that Daniel Tammet has access
to this reservoir of semantic relationships that we are not normally conscious
of and seldom use, it is just possible that he is far more unique than we have
realized. We can be thankful that he has such a positive and generous attitude
to research.
There is only one quip which I am almost reluctant to mention given
Daniel’s confessed obsessive attention to detail. The books show how well read
he is, but Born on a Blue Day lacks references and Embracing the Wide Sky
lacks many of those quoted in the text.
ADRIAN PARKER
Department of Psychology, University of Gothenburg
References
Chandler, K. (2004). People who remember things they never have learned. Australian Journal of
Parapsychology, 4(1), 2–31.
Snyder, A. (2009). Explaining and inducing savant skills: Privileged access lower-level, less-
processed information. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London,
Biological Sciences, 364, 1399–1405.
Snyder, A. (2011). Accepting information normally beyond conscious awareness by non-invasive
brain stimulation: Opening the doors to perception and memory. Proceedings of Towards a
Science of Consciousness; 3–11 May 2011; Stockholm.
Treffert, D. (2000). Extraordinary People: Understanding Savant Syndrome. Lincoln, NE:
iUniverse.com.
Treffert, D., & Wallace, G. (2002). Islands of Genius. Scientific American, June, 68–75.
Drawing upon more than four decades of professional and personal experience
in the arena, James Fadiman has written a practical, informed, and entertaining
handbook for people who desire to embark on an encounter with LSD, mescaline,
peyote, psilocybin mushrooms, or the dozens of other natural and synthetic
substances that fall under the psychedelic umbrella. Similar guidebooks have
been written over the years, but none of them approach the authority, credibility,
or utility of The Psychedelic Explorer’s Guide.
Fadiman is a faculty member of the Institute of Transpersonal Psychology,
a graduate school that he helped to found in 1975. He possesses considerable
gravitas on this topic, having conducted research with psychedelics when
Book Reviews 849
STANLEY KRIPPNER
Saybrook University, San Franciso, CA
References
Krippner, S. (1970). Letter. Drug deceptions. Science, 168, 654–655.
Masters, R. E. L., & Houston, J. (1966). The Varieties of Psychedelic Experience. New York: Holt,
Rinehart, and Winston.
Ufology is a historical enterprise deep down in its heart. For all their scientific
aspirations, ufologists spend most of their time collecting and collating cases,
looking for connections over time, searching for patterns of meaning amid a
welter of details—in short, the very sort of thing historians do to chronicle
the lives of Roman emperors or events of the Civil War. One key date is June
24, 1947, and anyone familiar with UFOs recognizes it as the day when the
852 Book Reviews
“first” flying saucers appeared; but no sooner had Kenneth Arnold reported his
sighting than reports of antecedents called the uniqueness of this event into
question. The Arnold incident holds benchmark importance, a beginning of the
modern era when saucers began to fly thick and fast as they quickly established
themselves as a cultural fixture and a mystery to reckon with, but historical
awareness sets this event in a wider perspective: Arnold did not see the first
UFO, just one more in an unbroken line that stretches back to the 19th century
in some opinions; in others, to antiquity or even remote prehistory.
Early cases entered into UFO discourse almost from the start. In a sense this
prior history was ready and waiting for the flying saucers to arrive through the
writings of American author Charles Fort, who spent much of his life combing
newspapers and scientific publications of the 19th and early 20th centuries for
reports of strange phenomena damned to exclusion by official science. His four
books and the still-active Fortean Society provided the new phenomenon with
a robust lineage of suggestive observations. A segment on old sightings became
standard in most UFO books of the 1950s. Ufologists have embraced old reports
as stout supports for the extraterrestrial hypothesis, since skeptics’ arguments
that airplanes or satellites are responsible for many UFO reports hardly apply
in ages when no man-made flying machine had yet left the ground. Proponents
took a vested interest in finding modern UFOs flying over Roman legions and
crusader castles, because if such reports existed, they had to describe alien
vehicles. By simple elimination, no other explanation would work.
If ufologists have good reason to value history, they have not necessarily
shown a very discriminating knowledge of it. The examples in the 1950s
literature were haphazard and, when derived from sources other than Fort, often
inaccurate, distorted, even rewritten to confirm a proponent’s wishes. By the
1960s and 1970s historical research divided between two contrasting pathways:
One led to systematic explorations of the phantom airship waves of the 1890s
and early 1900s, and to Jacques Vallee’s seminal Passport to Magonia (1969),
which related UFO experiences to fairy and demonic lore with the suggestion
that some broader mystery might underlie a multitude of anomalous phenomena.
Along the other path, “ancient astronauts” theories ran rampant as every ancient
myth and monument became evidence for alien visitation and intervention in
human history. Hoaxes and wild speculations multiplied to the discredit of
ufology and to the confusion of whatever message the historic reports carried
for the UFO mystery as a whole.
Now at last a book has come along that intends to set the study of historical
UFOs on a sound footing. Wonders in the Sky is authored by Jacques Vallee, one
of the most respected names in UFO research, and Chris Aubeck, who has made
a distinguished name for himself among serious historical researchers over the
past eight years. In 2003 Aubeck organized the Magoniax project to link a
Book Reviews 853
rose above the hills, illuminating them before it sank again and repeating this
behavior twice more before vanishing. My favorite case is the Robozero Marvel
of 1663, when residents of a Russian village watched a ball of fire with the
diameter of a 14-story building pass back and forth overhead three times before
hovering close over the surface of a lake for 45 minutes then finally flying away.
If the nature of the objects in this chapter remains open to contention, their
puzzling and uncharacteristic qualities are undeniable.
A second extensive section, titled Myths, Legends, and Chariots of the
Gods, provides the authors with an opportunity to discuss some questionable
stories taken as evidence for extraterrestrial visitation in the UFO literature. The
entries include hoaxes like the “Dropa Stones,” supposedly artifacts left by a
group of aliens marooned on earth thousands of years ago, or the “silver shields”
that flew over Alexander the Great’s army though only in the imagination of
some modern writer. Other instances exemplify an abundance of speculation
applied to texts, so that the vimanas of ancient Indian epics become spaceships
or the Star of Bethlehem acquires an extraterrestrial identity. Meteors, auroras,
halos, and other conventional phenomena clearly explain some appearances
that amazed witnesses in the past. Common folk beliefs contribute to stories of
ships in the sky and to accounts that associate lights and entities with fairies,
though traditional beliefs do not necessarily exhaust the strangeness of some
reports. By treating these reports in a separate section, the authors can satisfy
readers’ curiosity about claims often associated with UFOs and at the same time
distinguish the doubtful evidence from the sound.
The book consists mainly of cases, but it also provides orientation,
connecting material, and some basic analysis. Considerable care goes into
explaining the sources used and the criteria for selecting cases. A preference
for the most original sources available—the medieval chronicles or scientific
journals or the literature of prodigies and wonders like the 1557 Prodigiorum ac
Ostentorum Chronicon of Conrad Lycosthenes—sets this collection apart from
the usual derivative materials found in the UFO literature and on the Internet.
The inherent strangeness of the case rather than interpretations imposed on it or
suggested by current agendas qualifies an account for inclusion, so that even as
tempting a report as a flying shield does not automatically mean a flying saucer,
but only that an ancient historian drew a conventional comparison to describe a
meteor. Scattered through the extensive chronicle of cases are pauses to update
readers on the historical context of the reports, such as changes in religious
beliefs, social conditions, and technological developments that contributed to
the shape, dissemination, and interest in prodigious occurrences at a given time.
Issues of interpretation do not arise in this book. The authors are satisfied
to establish the existence of unknown aerial appearances and not jump to the
conclusion that alien visitation or any other particular cause was responsible. At
Book Reviews 855
the same time they do not leave readers entirely adrift. In a Foreword by David
Hufford, this noted scholar of anomalies reminds readers that beliefs often
originate in experience, and a study of claims about strange phenomena stands
to profit from an experience-centered approach. The authors’ Introduction cites
four conclusions—that unknown phenomena have appeared throughout history,
that interpretations change from epoch to epoch, that these phenomena have
had an influence on human civilization, and that historical cases teach lessons
applicable to modern aerial manifestations. A final chapter returns to these
conclusions and summarizes the case files to argue that similar phenomena
have recurred down the centuries all over the world, while the phenomenology
of past events anticipates the reported experiences of UFO witnesses today.
Human interests and explanations vary according to time and place but the
underlying appearances show a consistency worthy of further study. These
measured and cautious proposals grow out of the historical materials as fully
justified and free of the jarring leaps of faith so common in relating UFOs to
their supposed antecedents.
This admirable study fulfills its goals and leaves little cause for complaint.
Some of the case summaries would benefit from more complete information.
Historical records of aerial anomalies are often frustrating in their brevity,
while equally frustrating copyright restrictions hinder direct quotations and
raise barriers that are especially onerous for such a wide-ranging project as
this one. Still, a case like no. 473 appears almost devoid of details to indicate
why it was included at all, even though it is familiar from Charles Fort and
intriguing only because of the omitted descriptions. Other cases almost
certainly have conventional explanations, like no. 482, wherein an astronomer
watched the slow progression of a red “bolide” over Marseille in 1871. While
the object certainly was not meteoric in its actions, its characteristics well suit
the behavior of a fire balloon. While high standards govern the selection of
cases and secondary sources are usually reputable, the authors draw on the UFO
literature now and then. These lapses allow inclusion of Japanese and Chinese
reports not otherwise available, but in rare instances the sources are doubtful, at
least in details, yet included anyway (e.g., case no. 49 and case no. 188).
The authors are well aware that the written record tells a cultural truth
that is not always the same thing as historical truth. Prodigies became tools of
propaganda in the Reformation era, with some entries in the Mirabilis Annus
collection so slanted toward the Puritan cause in 1660s England that royalist
authorities sought to apprehend the author. Newspapers in the 19th century
shamelessly resorted to bogus stories of extraordinary events to provide a form of
journalistic entertainment known as “nature faking.” These pitfalls are familiar
enough, but the literature of signs and wonders twists and turns in a labyrinth of
motives and customs wherein no amount of caution is ever quite enough. The
856 Book Reviews
garrulous monk William of Newburgh seems never to have met a strange story
he didn’t like, but he simply represents one of the most visible examples of a
credulous medieval writer. Others have idiosyncrasies of their own and even
the most disciplined sometimes waive their sound judgment where anomalies
are concerned. The written accounts cannot be taken entirely at face value and
as a result cases cited in Wonders in the Sky provide an “enriched” sample of
unknowns rather than a “pure” sample.
Another possible source of error is the stereotypical elements of some
accounts. A “saints’ lives” literature stands by itself but also infiltrates many
mainstream medieval chronicles with recurrent motifs of luminous phenomena
accompanying the birth, death, and miraculous activities of saints. These
obligatory elements serve more to validate the sanctity of a historical personage
in a biographical genre than to record literal history. Folkloric motifs intrude
in some accounts, one example perhaps being the fiery object that followed
travelers in 1394. This account bears similarities to the will-o’the-wisp or the
fairy lantern that leads wayfarers astray, and even if the experience was real the
description may have taken its shape from popular belief.
The brevity of the book’s forays into the historical and intellectual contexts
of its subject matter calls for expansion, as does the database itself and analysis
of the findings. But these jobs are work for another day. What we have in
hand is a book worthy of celebration in itself. The authors replace the faith
and phonies too often characteristic of historical UFO research with a solid
basis, both an extensive collection of genuinely interesting anomalies from
original or creditable international sources, and the provision of a framework
for understanding these reports and for building on this foundation in the future.
Whatever opinion the reader may hold about the nature of these accounts, the
factual matter of the case, the fundamental cause for wonder, stands out with
unprecedented clarity and sets bounds on the speculative impulse. We can thank
the authors for this important step toward the truth, whatever form it ultimately
takes, and look forward to further scholarship at the same high standards.
THOMAS E. BULLARD
[email protected]
Book Reviews 857
References
Biondi, M. (1984). Pagine d’appunti di Ernesto Bozzano. Luce e Ombra, 84, 156–164.
Caratelli, G. (2011). Preface. Dizionario Enciclopedico delle Classificazioni Analitiche. Bologna.
Volume 1, VII–VIII.
Ravaldini, S. (2011). Preface. Dizionario Enciclopedico delle Classificazioni Analitiche. Bologna.
Volume 1, III–V.
Book Reviews 859
institution (Smith, 1994). The stability of society seems here to depend on ritual
rapport with the dead. Anything that prevents that ritual rapport must corrode
basic social bonds.
This leads to the second premise essential for understanding. What in fact
was deeply antithetical to traditional Vietnam burial customs? Answer: The
Vietnam War. For proper ritual burial you have to have a body. Without an intact
body—a head or a limb won’t do—the li cannot be performed. The Vietnamese
believe that rite-deprived souls cannot handle their fate on their own in the next
world. Facing what is perceived as insurmountable frustration of their support,
they become angry ghosts. But before we sketch a picture of the angry ghost
and the kind of havoc it is alleged to inflict on Gustafsson’s informants, we
need to comprehend the enormity of the war’s cost, part of which seems to have
involved denizens of the “other world” as well as living survivors. On page 125
we find that the American losers of this war still managed to inflict the following
on the Vietnamese people: more than 5 million dead; 300,000 missing; 300,000
orphans; 64,000 injured, and 40,000 killed by landmines and unexploded
ordnance, since the end of the war in 1975; nor should we omit the 250,000
boat people who died during attempts to escape nor the 10 million refugees,
said to be a conservative number. The number of key importance to the angry
ghost question is the 300,000 missing but no-doubt-dead bodies. According to
the belief system, that means 300,000 angry ghosts are out there wandering
about looking for ways to vent their fury. Suppose the invisible afterworld
corridors do indeed swarm with such agents of ill will—truly horrifying is the
belief that there is no hope of relief for them, no prospect of ever escaping from
this anarchic psychic inferno. The author keeps hammering home this picture
of hopelessness; it’s a hellishly narrow place to be trapped in, dependent on
the kindness and remembrance of the living, forever trying to be noticed, if
necessary by means of cruel and spiteful actions.
The author provides an Appendix (I), titled “Table of Suffering” (pp.
147–167), summarizing what she learned from her 190 victims of otherworldly
aggression. They cover all types, genders, ages. Besides basic facts about the
informants, we learn of their symptoms, their diagnoses, and their treatments. The
book also covers individual cases in greater detail. The possession experience
presents a roster of symptoms. The drift of them suggest the displacement of
the normal personality and something else forcing its way in, and in no gentle
or kindly manner. Some symptoms are mainly physical and may indicate the
resistance and discomfort in being displaced; for example, pains, tremors,
shaking, convulsions, skin disorders, listlessness, and unexplained illnesses.
(The author repeatedly underscores the failure of physicians to account for
most of these symptoms.) Other symptoms show the outline of the invading
personality itself: voices, obsessive thoughts, inability to concentrate, amnesia,
Book Reviews 861
aiming to produce proof in the manner of a parapsychologist, but I felt she was
quietly persuaded that the touted ghosts were objectively real. I first heard her
on public radio describe the case of an American who upon returning to Vietnam
for a visit had symptoms of possession; the American, normally very even-
tempered, began to have nightmares and shouted in his sleep furious outbursts in
perfectly grammatical Vietnamese. His girlfriend was witness to these displays,
and vouched for their grammatic excellence. This story would pack a wallop if
the American knew no Vietnamese; but he had moved to Vietnam and did have
a working knowledge of the language. What was impressive to witnesses was
the fluency and idiomatic style of his execrations.
There is a broad argument meant to support, or at least suggest, the
hypothesis that ghostly survival is the best explanation of the symptoms
experienced by the author’s informants. If the ritual recognition of the angry
ghosts is effective, the symptoms do ease off or completely vanish; in short,
it looks as if the ghosts are responding to the ritual treatment. The trouble is
that the links in the chain of the argument are too fuzzy. We have at best a very
sketchy medical knowledge of the symptoms. There is another crucial question.
How did the angry ghost get identified as the culprit? Here again we’re in what
looks like a cloudy realm to the outside observer. And finally, the doubter might
think: Couldn’t all the beneficial effects from the treatments be explained by a
powerful placebo effect and a highly active and culturally primed imagination?
Perhaps the angry ghosts are really the guilty unconscious of the survivors
punishing themselves and trying to make amends. In short, counterexplanations
could be advanced to explain the angry ghost phenomenon; but they’re not
likely to persuade victims.
In my opinion, this very well-written and courageous book merits our
attention for at least two reasons. First, it points to an area of research that
may be of interest to investigators of postmortem survival. As it turns out,
much survival evidence is found to relate to violent situations and mortal crisis:
most obviously, near-death experiences; also many reincarnation memories,
behaviors, and bodily marks; and many hauntings that involve violent death
and violent emotion. The hauntings and possessions of angry, aggressive
ghosts reported by Dr. Gustafsson may be included here, exacerbated by body-
vaporizing warfare, and the special problems that result from lack of proper
burial. If there is a transition to a next world, the how of the transition must
make a difference. The ideal Vietnamese death is peaceful and harmonious with
the surviving family. The purpose of this harmonious death is to establish a link
with the invisible world and be led by the wisdom and virtual godlikeness of
benevolent ancestors. On the other hand, being instantly blown to smithereens
by a bomb might indeed, as the Vietnamese believe, transform a human soul
into a permanent agent of festering ill will.
Book Reviews 863
The second valuable point is that War and Shadows enlarges our
understanding of the scope of human suffering. On any interpretation of the
material recounted, war is costly in ways most of us can barely conceive. In
the undoubtedly profitable business of war, the profound hell of hatred and
misery that we create, not just for survivors but for possible afterdeath victims,
is something we need to reckon with as part of the collateral damage.
MICHAEL GROSSO
Division of Perceptual Studies, University of Virginia
Charlottesville, VA 22902
[email protected]
Reference
Smith, H. (1994). The Illustrated Guide to the World’s Religions. Harper SanFrancisco. p. 120.
Thanks to Amazon and Google, old books don’t die. They’re available online
in near perpetuity. Some end up like those lonely paperbacks left behind on the
bookshelf of a summer beach rental—worth but a bored afternoon when it’s
raining outside. Others are worth saving and savoring.
Martin Ebon’s book, written in 1972, is the latter. It’s a keeper. A professional
writer, Ebon served as managing editor of Eileen Garrett’s International Journal
of Parapsychology and as a consultant to ESP studies pioneer Dr. J. B. Rhine,
deeply exposing him to their body of work. But he honed his wordsmithing as
a book editor with the New American Library and Playboy Press. Ebon deploys
erudite writing: intelligent, sophisticated, with historical references, and
touches of humor to drive home his key point—biographers of famous persons
routinely sanitize their subjects’ lives, glossing over or removing entirely any
references to their psychic experiences or beliefs.
Ebon’s richly woven tapestry of illustrious scientists, authors, politicians,
and philosophers who wrestled with the unknown is extensive and delicious:
864 Book Reviews
Articles of Interest
MARK RODEGHIER
Center for UFO Studies
SSE News 867
871
872 Index of Previous Articles in JSE
12:3 Estimates of Optical Power Output in Six Cases of Unexplained Aerial Objects J. Vallee
Analyses in Ten Cases of Unexplained Aerial Objects with Material Samples J. Vallee
Do Near-Death Experiences Provide Evidence for Survival of Human Personality E. Cook et al.
Anomalous Statistical Influence Depends on Details of Random Process M. Ibison
FieldREG II: Consciousness Field Effects: Replications and Explorations R. D. Nelson et al.
Biological Effects of Very Low Frequency (VLF) Atmospherics in Humans A. Schienle et al.
12:4 The Timing of Conscious Experience: Causality-Violating F. A. Wolf
Double-Slit Diffraction Experiment of Investigate Consciousness Anomalies M. Ibison/S. Jeffers
Techno-Dowsing: A Physiological Response System to Improve Psi Training P. Stevens
Physical Measurement of Episodes of Focused Group Energy W. Rowe
Experimental Studies of Telepathic Group Communication of Emotions J. Dalkvist/
Westerlund
Strategies for Dissenting Scientists B. Martin
13:1 Significance Levels for the Assessment of Anomalous Phenomena R. A. J. Matthews
Retrotransposons as Engines of Human Bodily Transformation C. A. Kelleher
A Rescaled Range Analysis of Random Events F. Pallikari/E. Boller
Subtle Domain Connections to the Physical Domain Aspect of Reality W. A. Tiller
Parapsychology in Intelligence: A Personal Review and Conclusions K. A. Kress
Dreaming Consciousness: More Than a Bit Player in the Mind/Body Problem M. Ullman
13:2 The Effect of ‘‘Healing with Intent’’ on Pepsin Enzyme Activity T. Bunnell
Electronic Device-Mediated pH Changes in Water W. Dibble/W. Tiller
Variations on the Foundations of Dirac’s Quantum Physics J. Edmonds
Do Cases of the Reincarnation Type Show Similar Features over Many Years? J. Keil/I. Stevenson
Optical Power Output of an Unidentifi ed High Altitude Light Source B. Maccabee
Registration of Actual and Intended Eye Gaze: Correlation with Spiritual Beliefs G. Schwartz/
L. Russek
Real Communication? Report on a SORRAT Letter-Writing Experiment I. Grattan-Guinness
What are the Irreducible Components of the Scientific Enterprise? I. Stevenson
Anomalies in the History of Relativity I. McCausland
Magic of Signs: A Nonlocal Interpretation of Homeopathy H. Walach
13:3 Second Sight and Family History: Pedigree and Segregation Analyses S. Cohn
Mound Configurations on the Martian Cydonia Plain H. Crater/
S. McDaniel
Geomorphology of Selected Massifs on the Plains of Cydonia, Mars D. Pieri
Atmosphere or UFO? A Response to the 1997 SSE Review Panel Report B. Maccabee
An Unusual Case of Stigmatization M. Margnelli
Methuselah: Oldest Myth. or Oldest Man? L. McKague
Analysis of Technically Inventive Dream-Like Mental Imagery B. Towe/
Randall-May
Exploring the Limits of Direct Mental Influence: Two Studies C. Watt et al.
13:4 Experimental Systems in Mind–Matter Research R. Morris
Basic Elements and Problems of Probability Theory H. Primas
The Significance of Statistics in Mind–Matter Research R. Utts
Introductory Remarks on Large Deviations Statistics Amann/
Atmanspacher
p-adic Information Spaces. Small Probabilities and Anomalous Phenomena A. Khrennikov
Towards an Understanding of the Nature of Racial Prejudice Hoyle/
Wickramasinghe
Clyde Tombaugh, Mars and UFOs M. Swords
14:1 Investigating Deviations from Dynamical Randomness with Scaling Indices Atmanspacher et al.
Valentich Disappearence: New Evidence and New Conclusion R. Haines/P.
Norman
Protection of Mice from Tularemia with Ultra-Low Agitated Dilutions W. Jonas/D. Dillner
876 Index of Previous Articles in JSE
The Correlation of the Gradient of Shannon Entropy and Anomalous Cognition Spottiswoode/Faith
Contributions to Variance in REG Experiments: ANOVA Models R. Nelson et al.
Publication Bias: The ‘‘File-Drawer’’ Problem in Scientific Inference J. Scargle
Remote Viewing in a Group Setting R. Targ/J. Katra
14:2 Overview of Several Theoretical Models on PEAR Data Y. Dobyns
The Ordering of Random Events by Emotional Expression R. Blasband
Energy, Fitness and Information-Augmented EMFs in Drosophila melanogaster M. Kohane/
W. Tiller
A Dog That Seems To Know When His Owner Is Coming Home R. Sheldrake/
P. Smart
What Can Elementary Particles Tell Us about the World in Which We Live? R. Bryan
Modern Physics and Subtle Realms: Not Mutually Exclusive R. Klauber
14:3 Plate Tectonics: A Paradigm Under Threat D. Pratt
The Effect of the ‘‘Laying On of Hands’’ on Transplanted Breast Cancer in Mice Bengston/Krinsley
Stability of Assessments of Paranormal Connections in Reincarnation Type Cases I. Stevenson/J. Keil
ArtREG: A Random Event Experiment Utilizing Picture-Preference Feedback R. G. Jahn et al.
Can Population Growth Rule Out Reincarnation? D. Bishai
The Mars Effect Is Genuine S. Ertel/K. Irving
Bulky Mars Effect Hard To Hide S. Ertel
What Has Science Come to? H. Arp
14:4 Mind/Machine Interaction Consortium: PortREG Replication Experiments Jahn/Mischo/
Vaitl et al.
Unusual Play in Young Children Who Claim to Remember Previous Lives I. Stevenson
A Scale to Measure the Strength of Children’s Claims of Previous Lives J. B. Tucker
Reanalysis of the 1965 Hefl in UFO Photos Druffel/Wood/
Kelson
Should You Take Aspirin To Prevent Heart Attack? J. M. Kauffman
15:1 The Biomedical Significance of Homocysteine K. McCully
20th and 21st Century Science: Reflections and Projections R. G. Jahn
To Be Or Not To Be! A ‘Paraphysics’ for the New Millennium J. E. Beichler
Science of the Future in Light of Alterations of Consciousness I. Barušs
Composition Analysis of the Brazil Magnesium P. A. Sturrock
Does Recurrent ISP Involve More Than Congnitive Neuroscience? J.-C. Terrillon/
S. Marques
Bonham
15:2 The Scole Investigation: Critical Analysis of Paranormal Physical Phenomena M. Keen
Bio-photons and Bio-communication R. VanWijk
Scalar Waves: Theory and Experiments K. Meyl
Commentary: On Existence of K. Meyl’s Scalar Waves G. W. Bruhn
Cases of the Reincarnation Type in South India: Why So Few Reports? S. K. Pasricha
Mind, Matter, and Diversity of Stable Isotopes J. P. Pui/A. A.
Berezin
Are the Apparitions of Medjugorge Real? J. P. Pandarakalam
Where Do We File ‘Flying Saucers’? Archivist and Uncertainty Principle H. Evans
The Bakken: A Library and Museum of Electricity in Life D. Stillings
15:3 A Modular Model of Mind/Matter Manifestations (M5) R. G. Jahn/B. J.
Dunne
The Speed of Thought: Complex Space–Time Metric and Psychic Phenomenon E. A. Rauscher/
R. Targ
Failure to Replicate Electronic Voice Phenomenon I. Barušs
Experimental Study on Precognition Vasilescu/Vasilescu
Unexplained Temporal Coincidence of Crystallization Constain/Davies
15:4 The Challenge of Consciousness R. G. Jahn
Index of Previous Articles in JSE 877
ENCLOSED
Signature
Associate Member ($75/year with online Journal; $135 includes print Journal): Anyone who
supports the goals of the Society is welcome. No application material is required.
Student Member ($35/year includes online Journal; $95/year includes print Journal): Send
proof of enrollment in an accredited educational institution.
Full Member ($95/year for online Journal; $155/year includes Print Journal): Full
Members may vote in SSE elections, hold office in SSE, and present papers at
annual conferences. Full Members are scientists or other scholars who have
an established reputation in their field of study. Most Full Members have: a)
doctoral degree or equivalent; b) appointment at a university, college, or other
research institution; and c) a record of publication in the traditional scholarly
literature. Application material required: 1) Your curriculum vitae; 2) Bibliography
of your publications; 2) Supporting statement by a Full SSE member; or the
name of Full SSE member we may contact for support of your application. Send
application materials to SSE Secretary Mark Urban-Lurain, [email protected]
Emeritus Member ($75/year with online Journal; $135/year includes print Journal): Full
Members who are now retired persons may apply for Emeritus Status. Please
send birth year, retirement year, and institution/company retired from.
All SSE members receive: online quarterly Journal of Scientific Exploration (JSE),
EdgeScience online magazine, The Explorer online newsletter, notices of
conferences, access to SSE online services, searchable recent Journal articles
from 2008–2011 on the JSE site by member password, and for all 25 years of
previous articles on the SSE site. For new benefits, see Institute for Scientific
Exploration, instituteforscientificexploration.org
Instructions to Authors
(Revised March 2010)
All correspondence and submissions should be directed to:
JSE Managing Editor, 151 Petaluma Blvd. So., #227, Petaluma CA 94952 USA, EricksonEditorial@gmail.
com, (1) 415/435-1604, fax (1) 707/559-5030
Please submit all manuscripts at http://journalofscientificexploration.org/index.php/jse/login (please note
that “www” is NOT used in this address). This website provides directions for author registration and
online submission of manuscripts. Full author’s instructions are posted on the Society for Scientific Explo-
ration’s website, at http://www.scientificexploration.org/jse/author_instr.php for submission of items for
publication in the Journal of Scientific Exploration. Before you submit a paper, please familiarize yourself
with the Journal by reading articles from a recent issue. (Back issues can be ordered from SSE Treasurer
John Reed at [email protected], or by using the order form in the back of this issue.) Electronic files
of text, tables, and figures at resolution of a minimum of 300 dpi (TIF preferred) will be required for
online submission. You will also need to attest to a statement online that the article has not been previ-
ously published or posted on the Internet and that it is not currently submitted elsewhere for publication.
AIMS AND SCOPE: The Journal of Scientific Exploration publishes material consistent with the Soci-
ety’s mission: to provide a professional forum for critical discussion of topics that are for various reasons
ignored or studied inadequately within mainstream science, and to promote improved understanding
of social and intellectual factors that limit the scope of scientific inquiry. Topics of interest cover a wide
spectrum, ranging from apparent anomalies in well-established disciplines to paradoxical phenomena
that seem to belong to no established discipline, as well as philosophical issues about the connections
among disciplines. The Journal publishes research articles, review articles, essays, commentaries, guest
editorials, historical perspectives, obituaries, book reviews, and letters or commentaries pertaining to
previously published material.
REFEREEING: Manuscripts will be sent to one or more referees at the discretion of the Editor-in-Chief.
Reviewers are given the option of providing an anonymous report or a signed report.
In established disciplines, concordance with accepted disciplinary paradigms is the chief guide in
evaluating material for scholarly publication. On many of the matters of interest to the Society for Sci-
entific Exploration, however, consensus does not prevail. Therefore the Journal of Scientific Exploration
necessarily publishes claimed observations and proffered explanations that will seem more speculative
or less plausible than those appearing in some mainstream disciplinary journals. Nevertheless, those ob-
servations and explanations must conform to rigorous standards of observational techniques and logical
argument.
If publication is deemed warranted but there remain points of disagreement between authors and
referee(s), the reviewer(s) may be given the option of having their opinion(s) published along with the
article, subject to the Editor-in-Chief ’s judgment as to length, wording, and the like. The publication
of such critical reviews is intended to encourage debate and discussion of controversial issues, since such
debate and discussion offer the only path toward eventual resolution and consensus.
LETTERS TO THE EDITOR intended for publication should be clearly identified as such. They
should be directed strictly to the point at issue, as concisely as possible, and will be published, possibly in
edited form, at the discretion of the Editor-in-Chief.
PROOFS AND AUTHOR COPIES: After reviewing the copyedited manuscript, corresponding au-
thors will receive typeset PDF page proofs for review. Print copies of the published Journal will be sent
to all named authors.
COPYRIGHT: Authors retain copyright to their writings. However, when an article has been submitted
to the Journal of Scientific Exploration for consideration, the Journal holds first serial (periodical) publica-
tion rights. Additionally, after acceptance and publication, the Society has the right to post the article on
the Internet and to make it available via electronic as well as print subscription. The material must not
appear anywhere else (including on an Internet website) until it has been published by the Journal (or
rejected for publication). After publication in the Journal, authors may use the material as they wish but
should make appropriate reference to the prior publication in the Journal. For example: “Reprinted from
[or From] “[title of article]”, Journal of Scientific Exploration, vol. [xx], no. [xx], pp. [xx], published by the
Society for Scientific Exploration, http://www.scientificexploration.org.”
DISCLAIMER: While every effort is made by the Publisher, Editors, and Editorial Board to see that
no inaccurate or misleading data, opinion, or statement appears in this Journal, they wish to point out
that the data and opinions appearing in the articles and announcements herein are the sole responsibility
of the contributor concerned. The Publisher, Editors, Editorial Board, and their respective employees,
officers, and agents accept no responsibility or liability for the consequences of any such inaccurate or
misleading data, opinion, or statement.