Silk Semantics Assignment Variables
Silk Semantics Assignment Variables
Abstract†
* Draft available at goo.gl/kFVhw3. Thanks to the audience and commentators Dilip Ninan and
Brian Rabern at a 2018 Pacific APA symposium session, and to Ivano Caponigro, Salvatore Florio,
Daniel Rothschild, and Ede Zimmermann for discussion.
†
Short version: A very long formal footnote to Stalnaker 1988.
of possibilities. Interrogative sentences denote a set of possible answers, con-
ceived as sets of possibilities. Additional shifting data are compositionally
derived, e.g. concerning “interrogative flip,” information-sensitivity, indexical
shift, and donkey anaphora. Applications to weak crossover and weak vs.
strong quantifiers are considered. The account affords a uniform composi-
tional semantics for ‘if’-clauses in diverse conditional constructions (adjoined
to NP/VP/IP/CP, with/without a main clause modal or ‘then’), and for indi-
vidual correlative clauses adjoined to DP/IP/CP. The result is a unified ap-
proach to the syntax/semantics of interrogatives, conditionals, and relativiza-
tion. The semantics avoids introducing added interpretive principles or com-
position rules such as for quantification, binding, movement (e.g., Predicate
Abstraction, Predicate Modification, Event Identification, Trace Conversion).
The semantics is fully compositional.
Contents (short)
1 Introduction 1
Part I 19
2 Basics 19
3 Syntax and semantics: Standardizing quantification 26
4 Attitude ascriptions 39
5 Recap. Next steps 63
Part II 65
6 Relative clauses (I) 65
7 Quantifiers (I) 97
8 Noun phrases 148
Part III 238
9 Conditionals 238
10 Interrogatives 280
11 Taking stock 317
Appendix Formal overview: Syntax, Semantics, Metasemantics 319
References 333
ii
Contents (detailed)
1 Introduction 1
1.1 Parameters and operators: A (Ptolemaic?) road not taken . . . . . . 8
Part I 19
2 Basics 19
2.1 Formal overview . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19
2.2 Preliminary derivation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23
4 Attitude ascriptions 39
4.1 Attitude ascription . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39
4.2 De re/de dicto, Specific/non-specific . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 41
4.3 Quantified modal attitude ascription . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 44
4.3.1 Standardizing quantification . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 46
4.3.2 Assignment modification . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 47
4.3.3 Epistemic modals: Locality and binding . . . . . . . . . . . . 49
4.4 Pierre and friends . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51
Part II 65
iii
6.3 Recap. Features and bugs . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 93
7 Quantifiers (I) 97
7.1 “Specificity” (I) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 97
7.2 Genitives and non-relative restrictive modification . . . . . . . . . . 110
7.3 Bound pronouns . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 131
7.4 Weak crossover, inverse linking, genitive binding . . . . . . . . . . . 138
9 Conditionals 238
9.1 Local and global readings . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 238
9.2 ‘If’-clauses as plural definite descriptions of assignments . . . . . . . 240
9.3 Adnominal conditionals . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 246
9.4 Sentence-final ‘if’-clauses . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 251
9.5 Sentence-initial ‘if’-clauses . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 253
9.6 Modalized conditionals: Restricting and shifting . . . . . . . . . . . 258
9.6.1 Direct restriction . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 258
9.6.2 Double modal and information-sensitive readings . . . . . . 260
9.7 Correlatives and proforms: Individual and conditional . . . . . . . . 265
9.7.1 Individual correlatives and proforms . . . . . . . . . . . . . 267
9.7.2 Conditional correlatives and ‘then’ . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 275
iv
10 Interrogatives 280
10.1 Local and global readings in questions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 280
10.2 Syntax, semantics, metasemantics . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 282
10.3 wh questions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 286
10.3.1 Recap: Choice functions and choice-function variables . . . 297
10.3.2 Aside: Weak crossover revisited . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 300
10.4 “Interrogative flip” . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 303
10.5 Conditional questions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 305
10.5.1 Relevance conditional questions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 306
10.5.2 Correlative questions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 308
10.5.3 Hypothetical conditional questions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 310
10.6 Recap: Standardizing quantification. Unifying relativization, condi-
tionals, questions . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 315
References 333
v
This manuscript develops a framework for compositional semantics, and begins
illustrating its fruitfulness by applying it to certain core linguistic data. The key
move is to posit variables for assignment functions in the syntax; semantic values
are treated systematically in terms of functions from assignments, now included in
the model. The core data involve a spectrum of linguistic “shifting” phenomena,
such as with quantifiers, intensionality, and context-sensitivity under modals and
attitude verbs. Extensions to questions, conditionals, relative clauses, and various
types of pronominal anaphora such as donkey anaphora are provided. The proposed
assignment-variable-based theory affords a standardization of quantification across
domains (individuals, worlds, assignments), and a unified approach to shifting phe-
nomena in natural language.
1 Introduction
An overview of the account’s theoretical context and key features is as follows.
Following Stalnaker (1970), Kamp (1971), Lewis (1980), and Kaplan (1989),
a standard move in formal semantics is to treat expressions as interpreted with
respect to two general parameters: to a first approximation, a context c which takes
expressions to intensions, and circumstance (index) i which takes intensions to ex-
tensions. To handle quantification and free/bound pronouns, the context parameter
may be treated as an assignment function gc , mapping typed numerical indices ⟨n, τ ⟩
(abbreviated: nτ ) to items in the model.1 Nuances aside, the interpretation function
returns Truth for a sentence such as S = ‘It7 laughed’, JSKgc ,i = 1, iff such-and-such
individual relevant in c, gc (7e), laughed in the circumstance i, where 7 is an arbitrary
index for the free pronoun (type e for individuals):
1
as pronouns referring to times. Compositional details aside, and bracketing tense
and aspect, the interpretation function, now J⋅Kgc , may return a semantic value for
S as in (1.2) (type s for worlds; world-variable left free).
(1.3) [Context: It’s presupposed that Sue, the woman being demonstrated in the
discourse context c1 , never smoked.]
Tom believes that [that woman]c1 has quitc2 smoking.
a. ≈ Tom believes that Sue used to smoke and no longer smokes
(cf. Swanson 2011: ex. 31)
(1.4) Phoebe believes itc2 is longer than itc1 is. (cf. Stalnaker 1988: 158–159)
2
(1.5) [Talking about Bert:] Alice believes that hec1 is richc1 /c2 .
a. ≈ Alice believes that Bert is sc1 /sc2 -wealthy
(cf. Silk 2016a: 165–166, 2017: 1787–1788)
3
(1.8) Alice thinks it might be raining.
a. ≉Alice thinks g(i) is compatible with its raining, where g(i) represents
the information accepted in the discourse context
(local reading obligatory)
4
(1.11) [je mee-Tii okhane dãRie ache] Sei /∗oi lOmba.
which girl there.deict stand be ∗
that.anaph/ that.deict tall
(lit. ‘Which girl is standing over there, that is tall’)
‘The girl who is standing over there is tall.’
(Bagchi 1994: ex. 3; Bangla (Indo-Aryan))
Yet most context-sensitive expressions fall somewhere in the middle regarding their
tendencies for local/global readings — e.g., with gradable adjectives and degree
standards, additives and implications of alternatives, quantifiers and domain re-
strictions, perspectival expressions and perspectives, etc. (Silk 2014a, 2016a).
Mechanisms for capturing the varieties of shifting phenomena have grown in-
creasingly complex in current “context-index”-style frameworks (see §1.1). Adding
5
assignment variables to the object-language is far from trivial. Yet I’ll show how
an account with assignment variables can compositionally derive a spectrum of
linguistic shifting phenomena using independently motivated syntactic/semantic
resources and a standardization of quantification across domains. Key features are
as follows: the proposed account
Though detailed theory comparison would be premature at this stage, features such
as these should make the project of interest to ongoing work on topics such as
quantification, modality, and context-sensitivity.
An overview of the paper is as follows: §2 introduces principal elements of the
basic syntax/semantics. §3 motives a more complex clausal architecture by examin-
ing how an assignment-variable-based theory can be integrated into independently
motivated treatments of the syntax-semantics interface. The resulting account cap-
tures intensionality and local/global interpretations of context-sensitive expressions
via general mechanisms of movement and variable binding, and it affords an elegant
standardization of quantification. A definition for a generalized binder index, which
attaches directly to moved expressions, is provided; the semantics is fully com-
positional. §4 illustrates compositional derivations of various examples involving
quantifiers, attitude ascriptions, and modals using the syntax/semantics from §3.
6
Speculative applications to classic puzzles of names in attitude ascriptions are briefly
considered. Working through these examples will afford opportunities for exam-
ining issues regarding quantification in the metalanguage, binding with pronouns
vs. traces, and (non-)conventionalized locality/globality principles for constraining
readings. An improved formalization of assignment modification captures binding
relations in derivations with long-distance binding. §5 recaps the main develop-
ments thus far.
§§6–10 explore how the foregoing assignment-variable-based framework may
be extended to other complex constructions, such as relative clauses and various
types of noun phrases (§§6–8), conditionals (§9), and interrogatives (§10). Nomi-
nal quantifiers are treated as introducing quantification over assignments, binding
relative pronouns in headed relative constructions as well as other types of pronouns
such as donkey pronouns (§§6–7). The assignment-variable-based account of quan-
tifiers is integrated in a general layered n syntax/semantics for noun phrases (§8).
‘If’-clauses are treated as free relatives, interpreted as plural definite descriptions
of assignments (possibilities) (§9). Interrogative sentences denote a set of possi-
ble answers, with answers conceived as sets of assignments (possibilities) (§10).
Derivations of various types of local/global readings in relative clauses, conditionals,
and questions are provided, such as involving binding phenomena with pronouns
and donkey anaphora, weak vs. strong quantifiers, indexical shift, information-
sensitivity, and “interrogative flip.” A speculative event semantics for verb phrases
in light of the proposed parallel layered n/v analyses of noun/verb phrases is briefly
considered.
Certain features of the treatments of noun phrases, relativization, conditionals,
and questions in these sections are of general interest, independent of the particular
assignment-variable-based implementation — e.g., an analysis of various types of
apparent binding out of DPs such as with donkey pronouns, genitive binding, inverse
linking; a distinction between trace-binding and pronoun-binding, with applications
to weak crossover; a general layered n syntax/semantics for quantificational and
non-quantificational noun phrases; formal diagnoses of various contrasts between
(so-called) weak vs. strong quantifiers, such as regarding “specificity,” “discourse-
linking,” modal independence, and compatibility with existential ‘there’; alternative
compositional semantics for head-raising and matching analyses of relative clauses;
a uniform compositional semantics for ‘if’-clauses in post-nominal, sentence-final,
and sentence-initial positions, with or without a main-clause modal or ‘then’, and
with declarative or interrogative main clauses; a uniform compositional seman-
tics for individual correlative clauses adjoined to the main clause or to a correlate
proform; compositional treatments of relativization and interrogatives which avoid
7
additional composition rules or interpretive principles (Predicate Abstraction, Pred-
icate Modification, Event Identification, Trace Conversion); a unified analysis of
wh-words, relative determiners, and certain indefinites; and a unified approach to
the syntax/semantics of conditional, correlative, and interrogative clauses.
The specific account to be developed of course isn’t the only way of implement-
ing a syntax/semantics with object-language assignment variables. There will be
various choice points, many of them unforced, along the way. I leave additional
applications, development of alternative implementations, and comparisons with
existing frameworks for future research.
A preliminary methodological remark: The project in this paper isn’t to provide
a possibility proof; the question isn’t whether it is possible to construct a formal
syntax/semantics with object-language assignment-variables. I would be surprised
if it wasn’t. The project is to investigate the prospects for a specific type of syn-
tax/semantics of natural language so as to provide a concrete basis for overall theory
comparison. Some of the data will be new, though in many cases the aim will be
to provide a new take on old facts — to integrate data from diverse literatures in
new ways, and systematize phenomena independently familiar yet often not jointly
considered in theorizing. The goal is a more coherent theory of linguistic shifting
phenomena with improved empirical coverage and explanatory power. Sustained
investigation into a variety of linguistic phenomena is thus required. One must
ensure that particular choice points and analyses generalize across the spectrum
of examples, and can be systematized into an overall account that plausibly rivals
accounts in more traditional frameworks; the devil is in the details (lambdas, trees).
It will be critical to motivate particular syntactic implementations and apply the
account to diverse expressions and constructions. I ask for the reader’s patience
along the way. I hope the preliminary developments in this paper may illustrate
the fruitfulness of an assignment-variable-based framework for linguistic theorizing
and provide a more adequate basis for future theory comparison.
8
to develop the accounts in depth, or to show that no alternative (whether developed
along the following lines or otherwise) can succeed. The aim is simply to highlight
certain prima facie costs so as to further motivate the paper’s central constructive
project. Readers satisfied with the motivations in §1 may wish to proceed to page 16.
The string in (1.15) permits a range of readings depending on context.4
(1.15) Everyone thinks that Zoe dreamt a friend of mine was rich.
• ‘a friend of mine’, Specific/Non-specific:
– Non-specific: the witness for the DP may vary across the quantificational
subject’s belief-worlds
– Specific: the witness for the DP is constant across the quantificational
subject’s belief-worlds; the belief is about a particular individual
• ‘a friend of mine’, De re/De dicto:
– De dicto: the witness for the DP is a friend of mine in the local evaluation
world; the belief is about individuals conceived as being friends of mine
– De re: the witness for the DP is a friend of mine in the actual world; the
belief is about actual-world friends of mine
• ‘everyone’, ‘a friend of mine’, domain restriction:
– Global: the domain of quantification is determined by the discourse
– Local: the domain of quantification is determined by a local attitude/information
state (e.g., where the relevant subjects differ on which friends ought to
be considered in questions about richness (do my animal friends count?
do my toddler friends count?))
• positive form relative gradable adjective ‘rich’, standard of richness:
– Global: the standard for richness — how rich one must be to count as
rich — is determined by the discourse context (each subject’s attitude
is about whether such-and-such individuals are dc -wealthy, where dc is
the contextually presupposed standard for richness)
– Intermediate: the standard for richness is determined by the quantifica-
tional subject’s beliefs (each subject o’s attitude is about whether such-
and-such individuals are do -wealthy, where do is the standard for rich-
ness accepted by o)
4
See Fodor 1970, von Fintel & Heim 2011 on distinguishing the specific/non-specific dis-
tinction from the de re/de dicto distinction (more in §§4.2, 6.2). See Barker 2002, Silk 2016a
on local/global readings of relative gradable adjectives (more in §10). See Silk 2014a, 2016a on
local/global readings of quantifier domain restrictions. Terminology varies among authors.
9
– Local: the standard for richness is determined relative to the local epis-
temic possibility (the subjects may fail to accept particular standards
for richness, and each subject o’s attitude is about whether such-and-
such individuals are deo -wealthy, where deo is the standard for richness
regarded as live by o)
For instance, suppose we are millionaires and we agree that one must be a million-
aire to count as rich. Rita is one of my friends, and we are considering Alice’s, Bert’s,
and Chip’s beliefs about a dream that Zoe had about her income. I know that each
of them thinks that Zoe dreamt that Rita was a millionaire. Though I may know
nothing about Alice’s, Bert’s, or Chip’s standards for richness, or their beliefs about
the standards operative in Zoe’s dream, I can describe their states of mind using
(1.15), as reflected in (1.16). (I use the superscript/subscript indices informally to
indicate certain of the intuitive binder/bindee relations.)
Alternatively, suppose Alice, Bert, and Chip each think that Zoe had a dream about
some or other of the Sharks, who, it turns out, are friends of mine. I know that each
of Alice, Bert, and Chip accept a particular though different standard for richness.
The string in (1.15) can be used to describe their states of mind in this scenario as
well, as reflected in (1.17).
10
unshifted so as to capture how the beliefs are about actual-world friends of mine.
Treating worlds as parameters of evaluation that are shifted by intensional operators
obscures how the DP’s predicate can be anchored to the actual world while scoping
under the modal/attitude verb (though see von Fintel & Heim 2011). Introducing
world variables in the syntax (cf. (1.2)), and treating modal quantifiers over worlds
parallel to determiner quantifiers over individuals, avoids the problem. Non-specific
de re readings are captured via long-distance binding of the embedded DP’s world
variable, as reflected in (1.18) and (1.19).5 (I use ‘⋋’ to distinguish the assumed
object-language binder index.)
11
operators (Stephenson 2007a, Yalcin 2007, Hacquard 2010, MacFarlane 2014;
cf. “nonindexicalism” in the sense of MacFarlane 2009). To a first approximation:6
(1.21) characterizes Al’s beliefs as being compatible with some actual friend of mine
being the winner, as derived in (1.22). The attitude verb obligatorily shifts the
informational coordinate in the index to the subject’s belief state.
The above sort of semantics may work well for expressions for which local
readings are conventionalized. Yet the approach is awkward for expressions permit-
ting both local and global readings — that is, the vast majority of context-sensitive
expressions.7 Take the standard-sensitivity associated with positive form relative
gradable adjectives. Since ‘rich’ can receive non-shifted readings in certain contexts,
it won’t do to treat e.g. ‘rich’ as directly dependent on a posited standard coordinate
d in the index, analogous to the semantics for ‘might’ in (1.22). So suppose we treat
‘rich’ as having an argument place filled either by a contextually provided standard-
pronoun, representing global readings, or an element stipulated as referring to the
standard coordinate of the index, representing local readings. A simplified seman-
tics is as follows, where DOX∗x,w is now a set of world-standard pairs compatible
with x’s belief state in w, and ‘o is d-wealthy’ abbreviates that o’s degree of wealth
is at least d.8
12
a. … [S′ Rita is rich-w4 -D]]
b. … [S′′ Rita is rich-w4 -d3 ]]
(1.24) JrichKg;s,d = λws .λdd .λxe . x is d-wealthy in w
JDKg;s,d = d
′ ′
Jthink-wi ϕKg;s,d = λxe . ∀⟨w′ , d′ ⟩ ∈ s∗ ∶ JϕKg;s ,d (w′ ) = 1,
where s∗ = DOX∗x,g(is) and s′ = {w ∣ ∃d′′ ∶ ⟨w, d′′ ⟩ ∈ DOX∗x,g(is) }
JS′ Kg;s,d = 1 iff Rita is d-wealthy in g(4s)
JS′′ Kg;s,d = 1 iff Rita is g(3d)-wealthy in g(4s)
Local: (1.23a) is true in c iff (roughly) for all worlds w′ and standards d′
compatible with Al’s belief state in wc , Rita is d′ -wealthy in w′
Global: (1.23b) is true in c iff (roughly) for all worlds w′ and standards d′
compatible with Al’s belief state in wc , Rita is gc (3d)-wealthy in w′
Analogous moves can be made for other expressions optionally taking local or global
readings, as in (1.25)–(1.26) for quantifiers and domain variables (von Fintel
1994, Stanley & Szabó 2000, Stanley 2002). (For simplicity I treat the added
parameter G in the index as a set of individuals, and I leave ‘can-vote’ unanalyzed.)
13
ing the interpretation of paradigm indexicals such as ‘I’ (e.g., Santorio 2012) —
one might wonder if a simpler theoretical apparatus and treatment of shifted/non-
shifted readings is available.
On a more empirical level, it isn’t evident that the approach will generalize to
more complex examples. For instance, (1.25) represented the index coordinate for
shiftable quantifier domain restrictions simply as a set of individuals. This represen-
tation would need to be complicated to account for different restrictions associated
with different quantified expressions. The parameter might be represented instead
as a function from NP-meanings to domain restrictions, roughly as in (1.27), where
∗
JGKg;G ,... = G∗ is type ⟨et, et⟩ and cat/dog is the set of cats/dogs (ignoring intension-
ality). Intuitively, G∗ (cat) represents a set of individuals relevant when considering
cats, G∗ (dog) represents a set of individuals relevant when considering dogs, etc.
(1.27) Jevery dog G ⋋1 every cat G likes t1 Kg; G ,... = 1 iff for every y s.t. y is a dog
∗
Yet examples such as (1.28) involving multiple occurrences of the same quantified
expression, where each occurrence receives a different shifted restriction, remain
problematic (cf. e.g. Stanley 2005).
(1.28) [Context: A panel survey is being carried out to discern sentiments about the
University’s practices in distributing a certain award. The panel members —
Alice, Bert, and Chloe — have different views on who should be allowed
to be nominated for the award, and who should be allowed to vote in
deciding the winner. Alice thinks that the award should be reserved for
undergraduates, and that only graduate students and faculty should be
allowed to vote for the winner; and she thinks that the award procedure
in fact proceeds accordingly. Bert thinks that the award should be open to
graduate students too, and that undergrads, grads, and faculty should all
be allowed to vote; and he thinks that the award procedure in fact proceeds
accordingly. Chloe thinks the award should be open to all members of the
University, but she thinks that faculty are (wrongfully) excluded from being
nominated. When asked about how well the University is doing regarding
sentiments about the fairness of the award practices, you report:]
Quite well. Most people think that everyone can vote for everyone.
One strategy for addressing these concerns is to abandon the notion of an in-
dex parameter, and treat expressions such as modals/attitude verbs as assignment-
shifters (cf. Cumming 2008, Santorio 2010, 2012, Ninan 2012). Previous ac-
14
counts have focused on indexical shift with individual pronouns. Suppose we gen-
eralize the approach to shifting with other types of context-sensitive expressions.
Just as the attitudes and circumstances of interlocutors in a concrete discourse are
assumed to be representable by an abstract “contextually determined assignment”
which determines values for pronouns, quantifier domain restrictions, degree stan-
dards, etc. (e.g. Heim & Kratzer 1998, Heim 2008), so too, we can assume, for
concrete attitude states more generally. Adapting the semantics in Santorio 2010,
suppose we relativize the interpretation function to an ordinary assignment g as
well as an assignment a shifted by certain modals/attitude verbs. The syntactic
indices in a’s domain can be distinguished accordingly, marked as [+a]. Expressions
optionally receiving local/global readings may take variables of both types; other
context-sensitive expressions may lexically specify a particular type of variable. To
a first approximation, simplified derivations for the alternative readings of (1.23)
and for (1.28) might proceed as follows.9
Such an approach may capture alternative readings where the relevant expres-
sions receive their interpretation from the discourse or embedding attitude (modal,
etc.). Yet neither operator-based account outline above captures intermediate read-
ings such as (1.17), reproduced in (1.31), where the interpretation of an expression
9
Metasemantic principles could be given regarding the relation between the assignments g and a,
what particular indices represent, and what it is for an assignment to be compatible with an attitude
state. For the moment I ignore such issues; we will return to them in §§3, 4.
15
is determined non-locally but with respect to an environment distinct from the
discourse context.
On the intermediate reading in question, the supplied standard for how rich one
must be to count as rich is the standard accepted by the quantificational subject. Yet
identifying the richness-standard variable d??? in (1.32) as di would represent the
global reading, where the standard is supplied by the basic contextually determined
assignment g. And identifying the variable as di[+a] would represent the local reading
shifted by ‘dream’, where the standard is supplied by the assignment representing
the possibility compatible with Zoe’s dream state.
Such examples can be multiplied. Consider (1.33) on the intermediate reading
of ‘every adult’, where the relevant domain restriction represents the set of individ-
uals considered relevant by x in matters of voting rights, for each bigot x (ignoring
domain restrictions for ‘every bigot’ and ‘most people’).
(1.33) ‘Every bigot thinks most people think every adult can vote’
a. every bigotc thinkskc [most peoplek thinknk [every adultn Pk can-voten ]]
b. Intended reading: Al, Betty, and Chuck are the bigots, who are prejudiced
in favor of their groups GA , GB , GC , respectively. Al thinks that most
people think that all the GA s (individuals in GA ) can vote; Betty thinks
that most people think that all the GB s can vote; Chuck thinks that most
people think that all the GC s can vote.
This says that every bigot x is optimistic about most people’s beliefs about whether
anyone is improperly excluded (by x’s lights) from being legally permitted to vote.
To recap: Certain prominent phenomena that have led theorists to posit syntac-
16
tic world variables and object-language quantification over worlds can be observed
with features associated with various context-sensitive expressions. This raises a
challenge for any account providing distinct treatments of world- and individual-
quantification/shifting, on the one hand, and quantification/shifting with context-
sensitive expressions more generally. One response would be to further complicate
the syntax/semantics and attempt to capture the spectrum of local/non-local read-
ings within an operator-based framework (see von Fintel & Heim 2011 for general
discussion and possible strategies). I suggest that we put such epicycles to the side.
The present project pursues a fundamental reorientation in theorizing about
context and “shiftiness” in natural language. The traditional approach takes unshifted
readings for context-sensitive expressions as paradigmatic. Here is Kaplan: “What
is common to [indexical words] is that the referent is dependent on the context of
use and that the meaning of the word provides a rule which determines the referent
in terms of certain aspects of the context” (1989: 490; cf. Fillmore 1971/1997,
Kratzer 1998a, Rullmann 2004). Though such an approach might seem initially
plausible for English expressions such as (say) ‘I’ or ‘here’, it is puzzling from the
perspective of the broader spectrum of linguistic shifting phenomena — hence the
plethora of mechanisms for intensionality, quantification, and context-sensitivity,
and epicycles for capturing local readings across context-sensitive expressions. In-
deed Kaplan goes so far as to treat strings with referential readings and strings with
bound-variable readings as uses of homonyms (1989: 489–490). Lest one scoff, note
that Kratzer’s (1998a, 2009) “minimal pronoun” account of apparent bound-variable
(“fake indexical”) uses of 1st and 2nd person pronouns is a homonym account.10
10
Further, whereas local fake indexicals are treated as minimal pronouns (mere indices) inter-
preted via an ordinary λ-binder ((i)), long-distance fake indexicals are treated as fully-specified
pronouns interpreted via distinctive context-shifting λ-binders ((ii)), syncategorematically defined
as in (iii). The “true” and “fake” indexical uses of the string ‘you’ in (i-a) are homonyms; the local
and long-distance fake indexical uses of ‘you’ in (i-a) and (ii-a), respectively, are homonyms; and the
binder indices in (i-b) and (ii-b) have distinct interpretation rules.
(i) a. Only you got a question that you understood.
b. Only [2nd] [⋋2 got a question that ∅2 understood]
(ii) a. You are the only one who knows somebody who understands your paper.
b. [2nd] … [⋋[2nd] know somebody who understands [2nd]’s paper]
(iii) J⋋n αKg,c = λx.JαKg ,c , where g′ is like g, except possibly that g′ (n) = x
′
17
(1.34) a. Only I got a question that I understood.
b. [Only [1st]] ⋋1 got a question that ∅1 understood.
(1.35) J[1st]Kg,c = speaker(c)
J∅n Kg,c = g(n) (Kratzer 1998a: 94–95)
What classical theories ostensibly gain when it comes to prototypical global read-
ings, they lose when it comes to the spectrum of tendencies for local/global read-
ings across context-sensitive expressions. The notion of a crosslinguistic class of
specialized anaphoric pronouns — pronouns conventionally excluded from receiving
their interpretation from the discourse context (§1) — is a borderline conceptual
impossibility from a classical perspective.
It is time to rethink the foundational assumptions about shifting and context-
sensitivity motivating the traditional formalism. Our understanding of the rich-
ness of contextual dependencies in natural language — e.g., indexicality, intension-
ality, logophoricity, perspective, projection, local context, assignment shift — has
come a long way since e.g. Kaplan’s (in)famous ban on “monsters.” The project
in what follows is to develop a theory which takes the opposite approach. Shifta-
bility for context-sensitive expressions is the default; unshiftability and obligatory
shifting on the poles of the spectrum are what call for special explanation. The
proposed assignment-variable-based syntax/semantics provides unified analyses of
shifted/non-shifted readings among context-sensitive expressions, and a fully com-
positional standardization of quantification across domains (see §1). I encourage
the development of alternative overall theories with which the following assignment-
variable-based account may be compared.
18
Part I
2 Basics
2.1 Formal overview: Semantic values, models, domains, assignments, composition
I begin with core elements of the basic syntax/semantics.
Rather than having a traditional interpretation function (J Kg )g∈G parameterized
by assignments (worlds, etc.), we have an unrelativized interpretation function
J K , which assigns expressions semantic values in terms of sets of assignments in the
model. (I’ll ignore tense/aspect and times/events.)
(2.1) Models M:
– E: set of entities
– T: set of truth-values, {0, 1}
– W: set of worlds
– G: set of assignments
19
given that functions are sets of ordered pairs, having a case where ⟨k, S⟩ ∈ g ∧ g ∈ S,
for some set of assignments S, would violate standard set-theoretic bans on ∈-chains.
Let the set of assignments G in the model be a set of ordinary assignments h —
functions from typed numerical indices ⟨n, τ ⟩, for any non-assignment type τ , to
elements of the model. For instance, h(⟨4, e⟩) returns an entity o ∈ E, say Fluffy;
h(⟨4, et⟩) returns (the characteristic function of) a set of entities in E, say {Fluffy, Fido};
and so on. Ordinary assignments h ∈ G are undefined for indices for assignments
or functions involving assignments. I let the domain of assignments Dg be a set of
assignments whose domain also includes indices ⟨n, a⟩ for assignments — i.e., where
dom(g) = dom(h) ∪ {⟨n, a⟩ ∶ n ∈ N}, and range(g) = range(h) ∪ G. For instance, for
some g ∈ Dg , g(⟨2, a⟩) is an ordinary assignment h ∈ G; g(⟨2, e⟩) is an entity o ∈ E,
say Fido; and so on. (For purposes of the present exposition, I refer to ordinary
assignments h ∈ G as “assignmentsM ” (for assignments in the Model), and to the
richer assignments g ∈ Dg as “assignmentsD ” (for assignments in the Domain). When
the distinction is irrelevant I ignore the subscripting; context should disambiguate.
For readability I often abbreviate indices ⟨i, α⟩ with iα.)
Our system avoids the worries mentioned above regarding non-wellfoundedness
and ∈-chains. Since assignmentsD gg return elements in the model, there is no case
of an assignment being in its own codomain. For h ∈ G, h(ia) is undefined; and
for g ∈ Dg , g(ia) = hj ≠ g. Since there are no high type assignment indices in the
domain of assignments in Dg (or G), expressions such as h(iat), g(iat), g(ia)(iat),
etc. are undefined. Such a restriction in assignments’ domains is motivated by our
posited theoretical role for assignment-variables as an object-language mechanism
for tracking the interpretation of context-sensitive expressions; yet the assumption
that there are no pronouns for sets of assignments is ultimately an empirical one.
So, our semantic types are as follows, where the set of assignmentsM G and do-
main of assignmentsD Dg are defined as above — i.e. where the inputs of assignmentsM
h ∈ G are (non-assignment-)indices ⟨n, τ ⟩ for τ ≠ g, a, ⟨. . . g/a . . . ⟩, and the inputs
of assignmentsD g ∈ Dg are indices ⟨n, σ⟩ for σ ≠ g, ⟨. . . g/a . . . ⟩. (Although the for-
malization of assignments excludes pronouns for functions involving assignments,
there may be other expressions of type ⟨a, t⟩, etc.; more on this below.)11
20
– Ds = WDg
– Da = GDg
– Dαβ = DDβ
α
For the degenerate case where γβ is of basic type β ∈ {e, s, t, a}, ↓ γ is a function
from an assignmentD gg to the item in the model that is the image under γ of g.
For instance, for x ∈ De , (↓ x)(g) is the individual (nullary function) o ∈ E such
that o = x(g), i.e. (↓ x)(g) = x(g). For P ∈ D⟨e,t⟩ , (↓ P)(g) is the function f ∶ E → T
such that for any xe , P(x)(g) = f((↓ x)(g)) = f(x(g)); and so on. The denotations
of viσ of complex types σ = ⟨σn , ⟨. . . , σ0 ⟩ ⋯ ⟩ can be defined accordingly as func-
tions Jviσ K ∈ Daσ such that, for any gg , aa , γσnn , . . . , γσ1 1 , Jviσ K(a)(γ n ) . . . (γ 1 )(g) =
a(g)(iσ)((↓ γ n )(g)) . . . ((↓ γ 1 )(g)). For instance, a pronoun for a set of worlds
[p2 g1 ] denotes a function Jp2 K(Jg1 K) ∈ Dst such that for any ws , gg , g(1a)(2st)((↓ w)(g)) =
12
I use bold and single quotes for object-language expressions; I’ll also use bold for highlighting
key points. I use gi for assignment variables, wi for world variables, oi for individual variables. I
continue to use h for “ordinary” assignmentsM in G in the model, and g for assignmentsD in Dg .
21
g(1a)(2st)(w(g)); a choice-function pronoun [F1 g1 ] denotes a function JF1 K(Jg1 K) ∈
D⟨⟨e,t⟩,e⟩ such that for any P⟨e,t⟩ , gg , g(1a)(1ete)((↓ P)(g)) is a selected o ∈ E in
(the characteristic set of) (↓ P)(g), where (↓ P)(g) is the function f ∶ E → T such
that f(x(g)) = f(x)(g) for any xe ; and so on. I treat the semantic values of traces
equivalently yet lacking the initial type a argument — e.g., Jt1e K = λgg .g(1e). For
complex type σ = ⟨σn , ⟨. . . , σ0 ⟩ ⋯ ⟩, trace t, and pronoun-variable v (variables of
basic types could be understood degenerately where n = 0 and σ 0 ∈ {e, s, t, a}):13
13
For expository purposes I use traces in representing displacement (cf. Chomsky 1981), though
the framework is also compatible with a minimalist syntax that rejects traces as theoretical primitives.
For instance, remnants of movement may be understood as copies of the moved expression, as in a
copy theory of movement (Chomsky 1993, 1995, Sauerland 1998, Fox 2000, 2002, Hornstein
2001, Nunes 2004; see Takahashi 2010 for a comparative overview). Unless indicated otherwise,
we can assume that non-semantically-driven movement is undone at LF, and any copies not necessary
for semantic composition are uninterpreted. In movement for type reasons, i.e. Quantifier Raising
QR (May 1977, 1985), the lower copy might be interpreted via an LF-interface rule replacing the
copy with a coindexed variable; more simply, one can treat all parts of the lower copy as being
deleted except for its numerical/type features (cf. Kratzer 2004), as in (i)–(ii) (using ‘∧ ’ to indicate
binder features, and strikethrough for deletion in the semantic component).
(i) QR (alternative): Copy α⟨i,σ⟩ from A, and Merge with A.
(ii) a. ⋮
everyone[∧ ⟨5, e⟩]
[S Alice beat everyone[∧ ⟨5, e⟩]
[S everyone[∧ ⟨5, e⟩] [S Alice beat everyone[∧ ⟨5, e⟩] ]]
b. [S everyone[∧ ⟨5, e⟩] [S Alice beat everyone[∧ ⟨5, e⟩] ]]
LF ≈ [S everyone[∧ ⟨5, e⟩] [S Alice beat [⟨5, e⟩] ]]
The precise formulation of such principles may be adapted for alternative views on the theoretical
status of indices. The general framework is compatible with treating chain relations as represented
in the narrow syntax or as captured in the interfaces (e.g., indices could be understood as explicitly
represented in lexical item tokens in a lexical array (or a device for identifying complex syntactic
objects individuated in terms of such indices), or as representing the syntactic relations on which
(co)indexing in the interfaces supervenes; see also Collins & Stabler 2016, Larson 2016 for
discussion). (The accounts of relativization and interrogatives in §§6–10 will avoid introducing
additional rules for interpreting structures derived from movement, such as Predicate Abstraction
(Heim & Kratzer 1998) or Trace Conversion (Fox 2000, 2002, 2003; cf. Sauerland 2004,
Johnson 2012, Moulton 2015).) For presentational purposes I provide both interpretation rules
in (2.4)–(2.5), though the account isn’t committed to a fundamental distinction between traces and
pronoun-variables. All variables might be interpreted as in (2.4), and the definition of QR (or lower
copy replacement) could be adapted so that remnants of movement are sister to an identity function
on assignments. Yet a simpler option is afforded by our treatment of indices as features. The rules
in (2.4)–(2.5) amount to saying that J K returns the values in (iii) for numerical/type feature sets:
22
(2.4) Jviσ K = λaa .λγσnn . . . λγσ1 1 .λgg . a(g)(iσ)((↓ γ n )(g)) . . . ((↓ γ 1 )(g))
a. For α ∈ {e, s, t}, Jviα K = λaa .λgg . a(g)(iα) b. Jgi K = λgg . g(ia)
(2.5) Jtiσ K = λγσnn . . . λγσ1 1 .λgg . g(iσ)((↓ γ n )(g)) . . . ((↓ γ 1 )(g))
a. For β ∈ {e, s, t, a}, Jtiβ K = λgg . g(iβ)
(Note that variables g for assignments are type a (functions Dg → G); there are no
denotations of type g. In what follows I use ‘pronoun’ both in the present techni-
cal sense for a pronoun-variable + assignment-variable [viσ gk ] complex, and infor-
mally for pronounced forms such as ‘it’, ‘she’, etc.; context should disambiguate.)
23
(2.6) Everything loves it.
S∶t
T⟨1,a⟩ ∶ ⟨t, t⟩ S1 ∶ t
⟨e, et⟩ e
24
S is true in c iff JSK(gc ) = 1
iff ∀xe ∶ x(gc [g−c /1a]) loves g−c (1e) in g−c (1s)
First, pronouns are sister to assignment variables, which determine their interpre-
tation. I assume that sentences have a topmost assignment-binder T⟨i,a⟩ , which
effectively maps variables sister to assignment variables coindexed with T⟨i,a⟩ to the
values provided by the input assignment. This anchors intuitively free pronouns to
the discourse context via the definition of truth-in-a-context (Percus 2000, von Fin-
tel & Heim 2011). In more complex examples, alternative local/global readings
will be reflected in different coindexings on assignment variables. A result of §3
will be a derivation of binder expressions, like T⟨i,a⟩ , from an independently defined
generalized (cross-categorial, type-flexible) binder-index ⟨i,σ⟩ .
A more complex clausal architecture will be provided in §3. The world argument
of a clause’s main predicate will be supplied by a world-trace, rather than by a
world+assignment-variable complex. For the moment, given the present simpler
syntax, one may assume that in the intended interpretation the first-positioned
world g(1s) represents the world of the possibility represented by g.
Importantly, the outputs of assignments are items in the model. What is loved
according to (2.6) isn’t a function y ∈ De but an individual o ∈ E, say Fluffy. Likewise,
although the metalanguage quantification is over functions x ∶ Dg → E, the items
in terms of which the condition is stated are images of the given assignment g under
x, i.e. individuals o ∈ E in the model. The universal quantification over xe includes
functions mapping g to object o1 ∈ E, functions mapping g to o2 ∈ E, etc. The
metalanguage quantificational condition ∀xe ∶ . . . in (2.6) is satisfied iff regardless
of which such function we look at, its value o ∈ E loves the contextually relevant
individual (=Fluffy): if there was an oi ∈ E that didn’t love Fluffy, then any function
xi ∈ De mapping gc to oi would be such that xi (gc ) doesn’t love gc (1e) (=Fluffy),
falsifying the condition; and if there was a function xj ∈ De whose value given gc
doesn’t love gc (1e), then there would be an oj ∈ De , namely xj (gc ), that doesn’t
love Fluffy (=gc (1e)). In this way the universal quantification over functions x ∈ De
makes a claim about every object o ∈ E in the set of entities (cf. Kobele 2010).
So, the semantics derives that S is true in c iff in the world of c everything loves
the individual o ∈ E represented by 1.
25
3 Syntax and semantics: Standardizing quantification
Adding assignment-variables to the object language raises non-trivial issues for the
syntax and lexical/compositional semantics. This section shows how a theory with
assignment-variables can be integrated into independently motivated treatments
of the syntax/semantics interface. The revised account captures phenomena of
intensionality and (non-)shifted interpretations of context-sensitive expressions via
general mechanisms of movement and variable binding, and affords an elegant
standardization of quantification in the syntax and semantics (§1).
The particular treatments of the syntax and lexical/compositional semantics
in the remainder of the paper are of course not the only way of developing an
assignment-variable-based theory. I will spare the reader all my other failed at-
tempts. I welcome the development of alternatives with which the account may be
compared.15
3.1 Preamble
A worry with any framework positing object-language variables for worlds/times/etc.
is that they have the potential to overgenerate readings. The worry might seem espe-
cially pressing for a theory with assignment variables. Absent additional constraints,
nothing would seem to exclude a structure/interpretation such as (3.1), where the
embedded pronoun receives a local reading, being sister to an assignment variable
coindexed with ‘think’, and the embedded world variable receives a global reading,
being sister to an assignment variable coindexed with the topmost assignment-binder.
15
I want to flag that the general assignment-variable framework (§2) doesn’t itself require a
project of standardizing quantification. One could build assignment-binding properties directly into
the entries for modals, attitude verbs, etc., as in the Hintikka-style lexical entry in (i) (letting
Dox(o, u) be a set of assignments (possibilities) compatible with o’s beliefs in u).
(i) Jthink⟨i,a⟩ K = λws .λTt .λxe .λgg . ∀aa ∶ a(g) ∈ Dox(x(g), w(g)) → T(g[a(g)/ia])
On this line, expressions such as ‘think’ receive an interpretation only in combination with a binder-
index feature; neither is given an independent lexical entry. Such an approach contrasts with the
standard approach to determiner quantifiers (e.g. (2.6)), where binding of particular variables results
from combining a binder-index with the quantifier, as triggered by movement. Methodologically it is
worth examining the prospects for an approach which unifies the treatments of the various shifting
phenomena. So I put options such as (i) aside.
26
(3.1) Alice thinks it cried.
a.
T⟨1,a⟩
Alice
thinks⟨2,a⟩ w1 g1 it4 g2
⟨s, ⟨t, ⟨e, t⟩⟩⟩ cried
w1 g1
b. ≈ for every h representing a possibility compatible with Alice’s beliefs in
the actual world (=gc (1s)), the individual o ∈ E represented with 4 by h
(=h(4e)) cried in the actual world
27
general relation seems available with ‘it’; addressees don’t generally know what the
speaker may be presupposing about what some attitude subject takes as relevantly
salient. Given the paucity of descriptive content of ‘it’, shifted readings under at-
titude verbs, modals, etc. would seem generally unretrievable. For theories using
unshiftable (or selectively shiftable) context/assignment parameters on the interpre-
tation function, such stories may be understood at the “presemantic”/metasemantic
level of what formal objects correctly represent the shifting possibilities for a given
string, or of explaining what makes it the case that a given string corresponds to
a lexical item receiving its interpretation from such-and-such parameter; for a the-
ory positing object-language assignment-variables, at (say) the syntactic or lexical
semantic level of why there is a conventionalized locality/globality principle for a
given expression. All types of theories must ultimately provide an explanation of
the contrasting tendencies — and in some cases conventionalized constraints — for
local/global readings among expressions, both in English and crosslinguistically.
Where one does is a matter of bookkeeping (cf. Silk 2016a, 2017).
Of course not all ways of carving up the explanatory terrain are empirically or
theoretically on a par — hence the present project. The classical approach takes
unshiftability for context-sensitive expressions as the default. In light of the spec-
trum of tendencies for local/global readings, I suggest we take the opposite tack.
Individual-, world-, and assignment-shifting are given a uniform general analysis.
Optionality with respect to local vs. global readings is the default; unshiftability and
obligatory shifting on the poles of the spectrum are what call for special explanation
(more on which in due course). We will see that proceeding in this way, and in-
troducing assignment variables into the syntax/semantics, affords diverse empirical
and theoretical advantages. In semantics as in tailoring (so I’m told), it is often
easier to start big and take in.
Preamble (=rant) over; the proof of the pudding is in the lambdas and whatnot,
so let us proceed.
Some limitations and patterns in available readings may be derived conversa-
tionally; not all LFs may be equally likely in representing speakers’ intentions in
uttering a given string across concrete discourses. Yet some constraints on readings
are certainly grammaticalized. In this section I would like to focus primarily on
one constraint on readings, to begin reining in the system’s flexibility: the con-
straint on embedded world-variables. As Percus 2000 observes, the world ar-
gument of a clause’s main predicate must be bound by the closest world-binder.
In the present framework, the aim is to derive that the main predicate’s world
argument receives an obligatory local reading, and to do so in a way that allows other
28
embedded variables to receive global readings linked to the discourse context. This
section develops the preliminary §2-account to capture these points. The revised
account derives the binding of specific variables from basic lexical entries and a
generalized binder-index (§§1–2). (We will revisit obligatory local/global readings
of certain other types of pronouns/variables in §§4.3, 8.5, 8.7.)
T⟨1,a⟩ ∶ ⟨t, t⟩ S′ ∶ t
S′′ ∶ t
everything⟨2,e⟩ ∶ ⟨t, t⟩
it1 g1
t2e
loves
w1 g1
Preliminary type-specific denotation for the binder-index:
J⟨i,e⟩ K = λQ⟨et,t⟩ .λTt .λgg . Q(λxe .λg′′g .T(g[x(g′′ )/⟨i, e⟩]))(g)
29
JS′′ K = JlovesK(Jw1 K(Jg1 K)) (Jt2e K) (Jit1 K(Jg1 K))
= λgg .g(1a)(1e) loves g(2e) in g(1a)(1s)
Roughly, the binder-index combines with the quantifier so that the quantifier’s scope
argument becomes the set of individuals that make the proposition JS′′ K true when
returned as value for 2e (n. 16).
A natural hypothesis is to treat a parallel mechanism as at play with world-
and assignment-quantification. I suggest that we treat the relevant items as moving
because of a type mismatch. Specifically, I treat complementizers (e.g. declarative
‘that’) as base-generated at the position of the main predicate’s world argument;
as a higher-type quantifier over worlds, it moves, leaving a world-trace. I treat
modals and attitude verbs as base-generated at the position of a posited assignment
argument of the C head; as a higher-type quantifier over assignments, it moves,
leaving an assignment-trace:17
(3.3)
⟨i,a⟩
Z0 CP/C
C0
⟨j,s⟩
⋮
C tia V tjs
30
There are precedents for treating the syntax/semantics interface in the proposed
way. Hacquard 2006, 2010 proposes an analogous move for Aspect, treating
Aspect as a quantifier over events and moving from the verb’s event-argument po-
sition (see also Moulton 2015). von Stechow 2008, following Heim 2001, treats
attitude verbs as quantifiers over worlds and moving from inside the complement
(cf. von Fintel & Iatridou 2009). Similar semantic effects of head movement
have been defended in Lechner 2006, Bruening 2010, Szabolcsi 2011. As we
will see in §§6–7, a prominent approach in syntax is to treat quantifiers as mov-
ing from within the nominal/clausal complement (Campbell 1996, Matthewson
1998, Ihsane & Puskás 2001, Giusti 2002, Luján 2004). Heim 2012 treats the
question operator as moving from an internal argument of the interrogative comple-
mentizer as a quantifier over propositions (§10). On a more general level, in light of
crosslinguistic phenomena with nominal tense Lecarme (1996, 1999b, 2004) offers
parallel syntax for clauses and noun phrases in terms of verbal/nominal T-chains:
the main (verbal/nominal) predicate’s event argument ei is assumed to be bound
by a higher operator OPi in agreement with T(ense)i (where OPi /Ti may themselves
bear morphosyntactic relations with C/D), as in (3.4).
Lecarme doesn’t address what generates the assumed operator or establishes the
(obligatory) binding relation between OPi and ei , what the operator’s specific seman-
tics is, or how the assumed agreement relations among OPi , Ti , ei figure in a compo-
sitional derivation of the (temporal, modal) interpretation of the verbal/nominal
predicate.18 Though I will bracket projections such as for Tense, the proposed
syntax/semantics in this paper can be understood as deriving the relevant operators
and chain relations in a specific compositional semantics — e.g., linking the main
18
Likewise for the other authors mentioned above, whose primary focus also isn’t on the specific
compositional semantics. Lecarme (1999b) writes: With clauses, the “relationship” between the
predicate’s variable ei and operator OPi in Spec,C is “mediated by the R(eference)-time” (e.g.,
S(peech) time); Opi “determines the value of C, which contains the R(eference)-time”; and the
[±past] tenses in Ti “tell us whether the time of an event E is before / after / simultaneous with
a given R-time. If R = S, tense locates the [event] before the ‘now’ of the utterance.” With nominals,
the “operator in Spec,D binds the variable e-position. This accounts for the context-dependency of
[strong, presuppositional] determiners: DPs are temporally restricted by the context, a local process.”
I don’t know what exactly Lecarme has in mind here regarding the specific compositional semantics.
31
predicate, complementizer, and an embedding modal via type-driven movement, as
schematized in (3.3). (Compositional semantic details will follow in due course.
§§6–8 will extend the movement-based approach to the syntax/semantics interface
to quantificational noun phrases, affording parallel treatments of nominal and ver-
bal predication, reference, quantification. Extensions to clauses with other types of
complementizers (e.g., in conditionals, interrogatives) are explored in §§9–10.)
The proposed treatment of the complementizer as the source of intensionality
could be refined accordingly in light of more detailed understandings of the clausal
architecture. For instance, the complementizer could be analyzed as raising for
type reasons from an internal world-argument of (say) Aspect, which, following
Hacquard, raises as a quantifier over events from the event argument of the main
predicate, as in (3.5), letting v be a type for events.
(3.5) ⋮
CP
⟨1,s⟩
C0 ⋮
AspP
C t1a
⟨1,v⟩
Asp0 VP
32
3.3 Complementizers: World-binding
Modifying the clausal architecture as suggested in §3.2 has direct implications for the
lexical/compositional semantics. Start with the complementizer. The preliminary
§2-implementation adopted a metasemantic constraint that the first world-position
of gc , gc (1s), pick out the world of c. Even if we don’t require this, there will be some
position or other in an assignment that represents the world of the possibility that the
assignment represents (§2). Accordingly, it can be useful to define a metalanguage
function @ ∶ G → W that maps an assignment h to the world of the possibility
represented by h. I offer (3.6) as a lexical entry for (possibly unpronounced) ‘that’.
(3.6) JthatK = λaa .λp⟨s,t⟩ .λgg . ∀ws = [λg′g .@(a(g′ ))]∶ p(w)(g)
(3.7) CP
[C0 ]⟨1,s⟩ IP
⋮
that tia
rained t1s
Roughly put, (3.7) denotes the proposition that it rained in the world identical to
the world of the given possibility, @(a(g)). As we will derive below, the modal
element base-generated in the complementizer’s assignment-argument position will
determine the local modal domain. Note that the verb’s world argument is now a
trace, directly bound by the complementizer.
33
over a such that a(g) is in the set of accessible possibilities; and with ‘think’ it’s over
a such that a(g) is compatible with the subject’s state of mind:
The meaning for the modal verb in (3.9) can be understood as adapting a famil-
iar Kratzer-style semantics, treating modals as quantifying over a set of contextually
relevant possibilities (Kratzer 1977, 1981). For simplicity I use a basic accessi-
bility relation r (“modal background”), which maps the world argument to a set
of assignments. The alternative entries in (3.9) correspond to alternative possible
argument structures. The (a)-option represents an argument structure where the
modal takes its world argument separately; the (b)-option represents an argument
structure where the world and modal-background pronouns combine, yielding a
world-indexed set of possibilities that combines with the modal (cf. von Fintel &
Heim 2011). To fix ideas I will assume the latter option, in (3.9b).20 As usual,
the meaning for ‘think’ in (3.10) lexically specifies the set of possibilities being
quantified over. As we will see in the compositional derivations in §4, the set of
worlds at which a clause is evaluated is ultimately determined by the assignment-
quantification introduced by the modal. For example, with ‘think’, the complement
is evaluated at a multiplicity of worlds (assuming one isn’t maximally opinionated),
i.e. the worlds w(g) identical to worlds @(a(g)) of assignments representing pos-
sibilities compatible with the subject’s state of mind. With T, the main clause is
evaluated at a singleton set, {@ (a(g))} = {@ (g− )}, i.e. ultimately the world of the
assignment representing the discourse context.
Recall that assignments are understood theoretically as representing possibil-
ities, where “possible ways things might be” may include what world is actual,
foci of attention, objects’ relative saliences, etc. It is important to distinguish the
compositional semantics, which takes as given an abstract representation such as
an assignment, from the metasemantics of what makes it the case that (say) an
20
As we will see in §§6–9, proceeding this way will provide an elegant way of characterizing the
semantics of modal and determiner quantifiers. I revisit the argument structure for attitude verbs
in §8.1.
34
assignment or set of assignments represents a particular concrete content-bearing
state, such as a discourse situation, body of information, or state of mind. As is
common, for purposes of developing the formal syntax and semantics I will put
the latter metasemantic issues to the side. The task of addressing such issues is
common to any overall theory which utilizes a notion of the “assignment of the
context” gc , or an “assignment determined by” “the physical and psychological cir-
cumstances” (Heim & Kratzer 1998: 243; cf., e.g., Percus & Sauerland 2003,
Schlenker 2003, Hacquard 2006, Cumming 2008, Santorio 2010, 2012, Ninan
2012, Silk 2018). (Work on indexical shift and concept generators may provide
additional (gramatical/lexical/metasemantic) resources for reining in the system’s
flexibility (§3.1). For instance, one might require, say, that in the intended inter-
pretation the first-positioned individual in an assignment representing an epistemic
possibility determined by gc be an epistemic counterpart of the first-positioned indi-
vidual in gc , who is the speaker of c — or, generalizing, that the syntactic indexing
determined by the concrete discourse be such that, for any relevant index ⟨i, σ⟩,
a(g)(iσ) represents an epistemic counterpart of gc (iσ). More pedantically, one
might require that if a concrete discourse c determines that a particular syntactic
indexing ⟨i, σ⟩ and abstract assignment gc would represent an intention to pick out
such-and-such item s in the model with a token use of an expression α in c, then for
any assignment h representing an epistemic possibility (possibility compatible with
so-and-so’s state of mind, etc.), h(iσ) is an epistemic (doxastic, etc.) counterpart of
gc (iσ) = s.)
3.5 Generalized binder-index
Previous definitions of object language binder indices have been limited to DPs in
the binding of individual variables (e.g., Kobele 2010, Kennedy 2014). The above
treatments of the syntax/semantics afford a means of standardizing quantification
and defining a generalized binder-index, applying to quantificational expressions of
various types. I propose (3.11) — where χτ is a variable for the type of what is being
quantified over, σ is the type of the mother node (i.e. the result of combining the
binding expression with its scope argument), and γσ1 1 . . . γσnn are variables for any
intermediate arguments.
35
⟨i,e⟩
(3.12) J[everything] K = J⟨i,e⟩ K(JeverythingK)
= λTt .λgg . ∀xe ∶ T(g[x(g)/ie])
(3.13) J[that tja ]⟨i,s⟩ K = J⟨i,s⟩ K(Jthat tja K)
= λTt .λgg . ∀ws = λg′g .@(g′ (ja))∶ T(g[w(g)/is])
(3.14) J[think tjs ]⟨i,a⟩ K = J⟨i,a⟩ K(Jthink tjs K)
= λTt .λxe .λgg . ∀aa ∶ a(g) is compatible with x(g)’s state of mind in
g(js) → T(g[a(g)/ia])
36
movement operations in QR may proceed by Merge: The expression α merges with
the binder index in its base position, yielding α⟨i,σ⟩ , remerged later in the deriva-
tion. Though our general framework needn’t be committed to a particular theory
of syntactic structure building or the interfaces, a natural way of understanding
the syntactic contribution of the generalized binder-index is as providing a “trigger”
feature (Collins & Stabler 2016), which would be checked by the application
of Merge in generating the post-movement structure.21 The lower copy may be
replaced with a coindexed variable viσ directly, as in a trace theory, or via a general
post-syntactic replacement/deletion rule in the semantic component (see n. 13).
The generalized binder index would thus be what triggers QR syntactically, and
allows for combination via function application semantically. The result is a syntax
and compositional semantics of type-driven movement in terms of ordinary feature-
driven Merge and function application.22
21
In a model such as that in Groat & O'neil 1996, type-driven overt vs. covert movements
(e.g., with attitude verbs vs. object-position determiner quantifiers) would be distinguished in terms
of whether phonological features are moved to the head of the chain. In a theory with local
morphophonological spell-out, covert instances of QR would take place after spell-out (cf. Fox &
Nissenbaum 1999, Nissenbaum 2001, Cecchetto 2004, Tanaka 2015; more on this in §8.5).
22
Contrast the present sort of simplified derivation for a basic case of QR in (i) with the trace-
theoretic, copy-theoretic, and multidominant alternatives in (ii)–(iv) (cf. n. 13). (For concreteness
in (i) I use ‘∧ ’ to indicate the binder feature and derive the variable in the lower position via deletion;
see n. 13. Fox’s Trace Conversion in (iii) converts the lower copy of a quantificational DP to a definite
description by replacing the D head (here ‘every’) with ‘the’ and inserting an identity predicate
in the complement (here yielding [[boy][=o5 ]] from [boy]). I return to comparisons with Trace
Conversion in §6. Regarding (iv), in a multidominant syntax remerged syntactic objects are literally
in both positions — hence Johnson’s (2012) need to generate the quantifier (here ∀) in the higher
position, independent of the NP assumed to be its complement. (Johnson assumes that, by some
morphosyntactic principles, the syntactically displaced ∀ and ‘the’ get pronounced as ‘every’.) I don’t
know how such an approach would generalize across varieties of type-driven movement.)
(i) Merge + Function Application
∧
a. [every boy] [⟨5, e⟩]
⋮
∧
[S Alice beat [every boy] [⟨5, e⟩] ]
∧ ∧
[S [every boy] [⟨5, e⟩] [S Alice beat [every boy] [⟨5, e⟩] ]] (by Merge)
∧ ∧
[S [every boy] [⟨5, e⟩] [S Alice beat [every boy] [⟨5, e⟩] ]]
b. LF: [S [every boy]⟨5,e⟩ [S Alice beat [⟨5, e⟩] ]]
c. ≈ for every boy o, Alice beat o (by FA)
(ii) Traces + QR + Predicate Abstraction (PA) (Heim & Kratzer 1998)
a. [every boy]
⋮
SS: [Alice beat [every boy]5 ] (by Merge)
37
The next section shows how the lexical entries and derived binder denotations in
this section capture the requisite binding relationships in sentences’ quantifications
over individuals/worlds/assignments.
(iv) Multidominance + Decomposed scattered ‘every’ + Agree + PA∗ (cf. Johnson 2012)
a. [DP [the∗ pro5 ] boy]
⋮
[Alice beat [DP [the∗ pro5 ] [NP boy]]]
[Alice beat [DP [the∗ pro5 ] NP]] [QP ∀ NP] (by Merge)
● NP: identical token = [NP boy], sister to both Q0 and D0 (multidominance)
b. LF: [[Alice beat [DP [the∗ pro5 ] NP]] [QP5 ∀ NP]] (by Merge, Agreement∗ )
∗
● Stipulated Agreement : QPi must have the same index as the index sister to D0 in
[D0 D0 proi ] that is sister to the lower occurrence of the NP sister to Q
c. ≈ for every boy o, Alice beat o, provided o is a boy (by PA∗ , FA)
● Jthe∗ K = λxλP ∶ P(x) = 1 . x
38
4 Examples: Attitude ascriptions
4.1 Attitude Ascription: Intensionality, local/global readings
Start with a simple attitude ascription such as (4.1) with a “free” (global) reading
of an embedded pronoun. (I use ‘Cd ’ for an unpronounced declarative comple-
mentizer, JCd K = JthatK , assumed to head the main clause (cf. Chomsky 1995,
Lecarme 1999a, Franco 2013). For readability I abbreviate ‘o’s state of mind in
u’ with ‘SOMo,u ’; I suppress certain irrelevant assignment modifications, indicated
with ‘≈’; I leave intermediate calculations to the reader.)23
T⟨1,a⟩ CPm
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a VP
he1 g1
⟨2,a⟩ CPn
thinks t1s
⟨2,s⟩
39
≈ λxe .λgg . ∀aa ∶ a(g) is compatible with SOMx(g), g(1s) →
g(1a)(2e) cried in @(a(g))
JCPm K = J[Cd t1a ]⟨1,s⟩ K(JVPK(λg′g .g′ (1a)(1e)))
≈ λgg . ∀w′s = λg′g .@(g′ (1a))∶
∀aa ∶ a(g) is compatible with SOMg(1a)(1e), w′ (g) →
g(1a)(2e) cried in @(a(g))
≈ λgg . ∀aa ∶ a(g) is compatible with SOMg(1a)(1e), @(g(1a)) →
g(1a)(2e) cried in @(a(g))
JSK = JT⟨1,a⟩ K(JCPm K) = λgg . ∀a′a = λg′′g .g′′− ∶ JCPm K(g[a′ (g)/1a])
≈ λgg . ∀a′a = λg′′g .g′′− ∶ ∀aa ∶ a(g) is compatible with SOMa′ (g)(1e), @(a′ (g)) →
a′ (g)(2e) cried in @(a(g))
≈ λgg . ∀aa ∶ a(g) is compatible with SOMg−(1e), @(g−) →
g−(2e) cried in @(a(g))
Roughly put: (4.1) is true in c, JSK(gc ) = 1, iff gc (2e) cried in the world of every
possibility compatible with gc (1e)’s state of mind in @(gc ). (For readability I will
often omit the superscript in ‘g−c ’, though it should be understood (§2.2).)
Parallel to the movement of the quantifier in (3.2), movement of the comple-
mentizer from the world-argument position of the clause’s main predicate leaves a
trace (t1s , t2s ), and the binder-index attaches to the moved expression. The type-
driven movement of the embedding modal element determines the local modal
domain. This captures Percus’s point (§3.1): Percus’s point is diagnosed as an
obligatory local reading of the world argument of the clause’s main predicate; it is
captured via general mechanisms of movement.
The embedded world argument is obligatorily shifted to the embedding pred-
icate ‘think’, being supplied directly by a trace left from movement of the clause’s
complementizer; however, the embedded pronoun can still receive a non-shifted
reading, receiving its interpretation from an assignment-variable. The intuitively
free, or global reading, of ‘it’ is reflected in its being sister to an assignment-variable
coindexed with the topmost assignment-binder, anchoring its interpretation to the
discourse context (via g[a′ (g)/1a](1a)(2e) = a′ (g)(2e) = g(2e)).24
24
The talk of intuitively free/bound readings of pronouns can be formalized more precisely. An
intuitively “free” reading of a pronoun, represented syntactically via a pronoun-+assignment-variable
complex [viσ gj ], is reflected in an LF where (a) the nearest c-commanding assignment-binder, if any,
is T⟨j,a⟩ , and (b) there is no ⟨i,σ⟩ -binder c-commanded by the topmost world-/assignment-binders that
c-commands it.
40
As with individual-quantification (§2.2), although the items quantified over by
the complementizer/modal are functions in Ds /Dg , the conditions are conditions on
worlds/assignments in the model. This reflects a philosophical point from Stalnaker
(1988, 2014), in his emphasis on understanding shifted “contexts” as derived, in the
sense of being determined by the discourse. Which features of the subject’s state of
mind are relevant for interpreting embedded material can depend on context. The
formalism represents this in treating the condition placed by the attitude verb as a
condition on ways a of mapping the discourse assignment g to an assignment a(g)
representing a possibility compatible with the subject’s state of mind.
Likewise, the “…cried in @(a(g))” in the last line shouldn’t mislead. The pro-
posed meanings for ‘think’ and Cd /‘that’ restrict the quantification to functions w
mapping g to worlds w(g) = @(a(g)) of the possibilities compatible with the sub-
ject’s state of mind. The attitude ascription requires that the relevant individual
cried in any such world @(a(g)) ∈ W compatible with the subject’s state of mind.
41
Ja [FoM [wi gj ]]K = λQ⟨e,t⟩ .λgg . ∃xe ∶ x(g) is a friend of mine in g(ja)(is) ∧ Q(x)(g)
T⟨1,a⟩
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a Alice
⟨2,a⟩ CP
thinks t1s
⟨2,s⟩
that t2a DP
t2s won
a
FoM
w2 g2
42
(4.6) De re, Specific:
≈ there is some particular individual who is a friend of mine such that Alice
thinks (s)he won
S
T⟨1,a⟩
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a
DP⟨1,e⟩
a Alice
FoM
w1 g1 ⟨2,a⟩ CP
As observed in Fodor 1970, DPs such as ‘a friend of mine’ in (4.2) can also have a
so-called non-specific de re reading — informally, a reading ascribing a belief that is
“de re” in the sense that it’s about actual-world friends-of-mine, yet “non-specific”
in the sense that it isn’t about any particular individual. Fodor’s non-specific de re
readings can be captured via structures involving long-distance binding of the predi-
cate’s world-pronoun:
43
(4.7) De re, Non-specific:
≈ there is some group of individuals who are friends of mine (say, the Sharks)
such that Alice thinks some or other of them won
S
T⟨1,a⟩
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a Alice
⟨2,a⟩ CP
thinks t1s
⟨2,s⟩
that t2a DP
t2s won
a
FoM
w1 g1
Like other accounts with covert world-variables, the present account has a resource
for capturing Fodor’s “third reading” in terms of long-distance/local binding. What
is particular to the present account is how the binding is implemented — via coin-
dexing involving the world-variable’s sister assignment-variable — and what gives
rise to the potential, or lack thereof, for the alternative readings with different pred-
icate positions. Intensionality is diagnosed as local context-sensitivity of embedded
world-variables, and it is captured via general mechanisms for capturing (possibly
obligatory) local interpretation. Distinctions among readings are diagnosed in terms
of movement and the general phenomenon of optional local/global readings of
pronouns, here world-pronouns. Constraints on possible readings are explained in
terms of the treatment of pronouns vs. traces.27
44
help illustrate a range of features of the account, as concerning free/bound pro-
nouns, modality, and local/global readings with context-sensitive expressions. (To
improve readability I will continue to omit explicit reference to the quantification
over w ∈ Ds when the modal domain has been derived. As above I suppress irrelevant
assignment modifications, indicated with ‘≈’. Certain equivalences from assignment
modification are highlighted for comment below. I use ‘r’ for type ⟨s, at⟩.)28
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a [everything]⟨1,e⟩
t1e VP
⟨2,a⟩ CPm
thinks t1s
⟨2,s⟩ ModP
that t2a
⟨3,a⟩ CPm
might
r1 g2 t2s ⟨3,s⟩
Cd t3a [something]⟨2,e⟩
o1 g1 t2e
t3s love
28
Here and throughout I represent the non-finite clausal complement of the modal at LF as CP,
and use Cd again for the implicit C. (See Bhatt 2006 on modally interpreted non-finite CPs more
generally; cf. Kayne 1994, Mavrogiorgos 2010. I don’t assume that all non-finite clauses need be
CPs.) For space purposes further intermediate calculations are again left to the reader:
JCPn K ≈ λgg . ∃xe ∶ g[w(g)/3s][x(g)/2e](1a)(1e) loves x(g[w(g)/3s]) in @(g(3a))
J[r1 g2 ]K = Jr1 K(Jg2 K)
= [λa′a .[λws .[λaa .[λgg . a′ (g)(1r)(w(g))(a(g))]]]](λgg .g(2a))
= [λws .[λaa .[λgg . g(2a)(1r)(w(g))(a(g))]]]
45
JSK ≈ λgg . ∀a′′a = λgg .g− ∶
∀ye ∀aa ∶ a(g) is compatible with SOMy(g), @(a′′ (g)) →
(∃a′a ∶ a(g)(1r)(@(a(g)))(a′ (g)) ∧
∃xe ∶ g[a′′ (g)/1a][y(g)/1e](1a)(1e) loves x(g) in @(a′ (g)))
= λ gg . . . . ∃xe ∶ g[a′′ (g[y(g)/1e])/1a](1a)(1e) loves x(g) in @(a′ (g))
= λ gg . . . . ∃xe ∶ a′′ (g[y(g)/1e])(1e) loves x(g) in @(a′ (g))
= λ gg . . . . ∃xe ∶ g[y(g)/1e]− (1e) loves x(g) in @(a′ (g))
= λgg . ∀ye ∀aa ∶ a(g) is compatible with SOMy(g), @(g−) →
(∃a′a ∶ a(g)(1r)(@(a(g)))(a′ (g)) ∧ ∃xe ∶ y(g) loves x(g) in @(a′ (g)))
Roughly put: (4.8) is true iff for every individual o, for every possibility h compatible
with o’s beliefs, there is some possibility h′ accessible from h such that there is some
individual o′ whom o loves in the world of h′ .
46
says to interpret o1 with respect to the input assignment modified to take ⟨1, e⟩ to (in
this case) y(g). Although embedded under several assignment-shifters, the pronoun
can be linked to the main-clause quantifier via its assignment-variable g1 coindexed
with the topmost assignment-binder.
Analogous points hold with the modal’s epistemic modal-background pronoun
[r1 g2 ]. The variable r1 is interpreted with respect to (takes as argument) the as-
signment variable g2 coindexed with the assignment-binder attaching to the attitude
verb. Just as a concrete discourse may be represented via an abstract assignment
that assigns a set of epistemic possibilities to a certain syntactic index, say 1r, so
too with a subject’s concrete state of mind (§3.4). The shifted modal background
a(g)(1r) represents a doxastic counterpart of the (epistemic) modal background
gc (1r) that would be determined by the discourse, and the set of accessible possi-
bilities is determined by the possibilities a(g) compatible with the subject’s state of
mind. The generalized semantics for variables/traces (§2.1) derives how, although
the modal quantifies over functions a′ ∶ Dg → G, the value returned by a(g)(1r) is
a function from worlds u ∈ W to a set of assignments (possibilities) h′ ∈ G, and the
quantified condition is a condition on a possibility h′ ∈ G in this set a(g)(1r)(u)
(n. 28). (I return to issues about local/bound readings of modal-background pro-
nouns below.)
47
G of the) original assignment g, i.e g−(1e), but what is returned by g as modified by
the initial modification, i.e. g[y(g)/1e](1e) = y(g). What we need — and as yet fail
to have — is a way of ensuring a sort of dynamic updating in repeated assignment
modifications, so that references to “g” in later modifications refer to the assignments
as modified in earlier steps.29
To capture this, I propose that we treat assignment modifiers as operators on
assignments, and repeated modifications as proceeding via function composition.
These definitions derive the crucial equivalence step in (4.8), reproduced in (4.10);
the modifier [a′′ (g)/1a] is correctly treated as mapping m = g[y(g)/1e] to an as-
signment m′ that is just like m except that it maps 1a to its image under a′′ .30
29
The only place I’ve seen this issue addressed is Sternefeld 1998: 16–17. Sternefeld cheats in
the way mentioned in the main text.
30
For readability I abbreviate the right conjunct in (4.9a) as m(jσ, ≠ iτ ) = g(jσ, ≠ iτ ); I use large
parentheses to enclose descriptions of assignments when prefixed to an argument, e.g. (ιg ∶ ...)(1s):
(i) [a′′ (g)/1a] = λgg . ιm∶ m(1a) = a′′ (g) ∧ m(jσ, ≠ 1a) = g(jσ, ≠ 1a)
[y(g)/1e] = λgg . ιm∶ m(1e) = y(g) ∧ m(jσ, ≠ 1e) = g(jσ, ≠ 1e)
g[a′′ (g)/1a][y(g)/1e]
= ([a′′ (g)/1a] ○ [y(g)/1e])(g)
= [λg′g . [a′′ (g)/1a]([y(g)/1e](g′ ))](g)
= [λg′g . [λg′′g . ιm∶ m(1a) = a′′ (g′′ ) ∧ m(jσ, ≠ 1a) = g′′ (jσ, ≠ 1a)]
48
(4.10) g[a′′ (g)/1a][y(g)/1e](1a)(1e) = g[a′′ (g[y(g)/1e])/1a](1a)(1e)
g[...g...][⋯] = g[...g[⋯]...]
The remainder of the derivation proceeds straightforwardly: Given 1a, the resulting
assignment g[a′′ (g[y(g)/1e])/1a] returns a′′ (g[y(g)/1e]). Since a′′ = λgg .g− , this
reduces to g[y(g)/1e]− , which, given 1e, returns y(g), capturing the bound reading
of the pronoun by the quantifier, as desired.
(4.11) Alice: Bert thinks that [every contestant]i thinks shei might be the winner.
(cf. Stephenson 2007b: 22–23)
49
ings. Such explanations would be understood at the “presemantic” level of what
LFs are (not) determined by token utterances. For certain types of epistemic uses of
modals a locality principle might be given which excludes LFs in which the modal-
background pronoun’s assignment-variable isn’t coindexed with the closest c-com-
manding assignment-binder.32 Such a principle would be no more ad hoc than a
globality principle excluding LFs in which the relevant assignment-variable is bound
by an element other than T, such as for (say) English gendered pronouns or lan-
guages with conventionalized referential pronouns, as in (4.12)–(4.13) (cf. Déchaine
& Wiltschko’s (2002) class of “pro-DPs”; see also §1).
50
are conventionally compatible with both shifted and non-shifted readings. The
proposed assignment-variable framework affords a unified analysis of the context-
sensitivity of the different classes of expressions, along with a principled basis for
distinguishing and theoretically representing patterns of shifted/non-shifted read-
ings.34
(4.14) Pierre doesn’t realize that Londonci is Londonck . (Swanson 2011: ex. 34)
Though Stalnaker and Swanson don’t offer specific formal implementations, re-
cent work provides various mechanisms, such as variables for “guises” or “concept
generators,” for capturing how the interpretation of certain referential expressions
can shift in embedded clauses (cf. Uriagereka 1998, Percus & Sauerland 2003,
Cumming 2008, Santorio 2010, Ninan 2012, Charlow & Sharvit 2014). Such
machinery could of course be layered into the general assignment-variable frame-
work developed thus far. Since the terrain here is already well-trod, it may be more
interesting to consider an approach that hasn’t quite been considered as such. I
leave it to the reader to make relevant adjustments depending on their preferred
broader views on the syntax and semantics of names.
Consider a predicativist-style account in which a name ‘N’, qua lexical item,
denotes the property of being called N (cf. Burge 1973, Geurts 1997, Elbourne
2005, Fara 2015).35 In sentences such as (4.15) the name is in a predicate position,
complement to an overt determiner quantifier. In ordinary bare singular uses pred-
34
We will examine other types of constraints on readings of pronouns/variables in §§7–8.
35
Cf. Beaver 2001, Cumming 2008 for analyses of names as definites or variables, respectively.
For treatments of names as constants, see Kripke 1980, Salmon 1986, Soames 2002. See Fara
2011 on the importance of the “called N” vs. “called ‘N’ ” distinction.
51
icativists posit that the name the complement of an implicit determiner, reflected
in (4.16). In languages such as Italian the determiner may be more generally pro-
nounced, as in (4.17)–(4.18); deleting the overt D-element and leaving the name
in its NP position renders the sentence ungrammatical.36
(4.15) a. Some Alfreds are crazy; some are sane. (Burge 1973: 429)
b. There are at least two Tylers with philosophy degrees from Princeton.
(Fara 2015: ex. 8)
(4.16) Alfred is crazy.
a. [ DP ∅D [ NP Alfred]] is crazy
b. ≈ “the relevant individual called Alfred is crazy”
(4.17) a. La Callas ha cantato.
the Callas(fem) has sang
‘Callas sang.’
b. *Callas ha cantato.
Callas(fem) has sang (Longobardi 1994: ex. 25; Italian)
(4.18) a. Il mio/∗ Mio Gianni ha finalmente telefonato.
the my John has finally called
‘My John has finally called.’
b. [ DP the [ AgrP my [ NP John]]] has finally called
(Longobardi 1994: ex. 28, Bernstein 2001: exs. 11-12; Italian)
52
(4.20) [ DP F1 g1 [ NP Alfred w1 g1 ]]
JAlfredK = λws .λxe .λgg . x(g) is called Alfred in w(g)
JF1 g1 K = λPet .λgg . g(1a)(1cf)((↓ P)(g))
JDPK = λgg . g(1a)(1cf)([λgg .the function f s.t. ∀ye ∶ f(y(g)) iff y(g) is called
Alfred in g(1a)(1s)](g))
≈ λgg . g(1a)(1cf)(Alfredg(1a)(1s) )
53
our metalanguage @ operator while also assuming that the first-positioned world 1s
represents the world of the possibility represented by the assignment, i.e. h(1s) =
@(h), for any h ∈ G.
Turning to attitude ascriptions, first consider (4.22), adapted from an example
from Jennifer Saul (1998: 366), on a global reading of ‘Bob Dylan’.
(4.22) [Context: We’re talking about people’s views on Bob Dylan’s singing abil-
ities. I know that Glenda, one of his childhood friends, knows him only
under the name ‘Robert Zimmerman’. Since you know him only under the
name ‘Bob Dylan’, I say:]
Glenda thinks Bob Dylan has a beautiful voice. (Saul 1998: cf. ex. 7)
I can felicitously use ‘Bob Dylan’ to characterize Glenda’s belief, even though she
wouldn’t “put it that way,” since what matters for our purposes is Glenda’s belief
about the individual whom we associate with ‘Bob Dylan’ (cf. Silk 2016a: §§4.2, 4.4;
2017: §3.3). A simplified LF and derivation for the specific global reading of ‘Bob
Dylan’ in (4.22) is as follows (treat ‘Bob-Dylan’ and ‘sings-beautifully’ as unanalyzed
predicates).
(4.23) S
T⟨1,a⟩
⟨1,s⟩
VP
Cd t1a she1 g1
⟨2,a⟩ CP
thinks t1s
⟨2,s⟩
Cd t2a
F1 g1
BD w1 -g2 sings-beautifully t2s
54
The choice-function pronoun [F1cf g1 ] is linked to the topmost assignment-binder
T⟨1,a⟩ , anchoring its interpretation to the discourse assignment gc . The contextually
determined value gc (1cf) selects the particular relevant individual o ∈ E called Bob
Dylan in the world of the discourse (gc (1s) = @(gc )). The attitude ascription is
true iff for every possibility h compatible with Glenda’s (=gc (1e)’s) state of mind,
the selected individual o = gc (1cf)(BDgc (1s) ) — the individual with whom we in the
discourse context associate the name — has a beautiful voice in @(h). Whether o is
called Bob Dylan in @(h) is irrelevant.
As those with anti-Millian intuitions may be keen to point out, (4.22) may also
have a reading on which it seems false. To bring out such a reading, consider the
alternative context in (4.24).
(4.24) [Context: Gwen attends an afternoon reunion where she hears her child-
hood friend going by the name ‘Robert Zimmerman’ sing a dedication song.
Feeling nostalgic she says ‘I love Robert; he always sang so beautifully’.
Later that evening she attends a concert of a man named ‘Bob Dylan’. She
can’t stand big public events and says ‘This is awful; this Bob Dylan guy
has a terrible voice’. Since Bob Dylan is excellent at keeping his star sta-
tus concealed to his childhood friends, Gwen doesn’t realize that the man
singing at the concert is her childhood friend who also sang at the reunion.
We’re talking about how factors such as kinship, environment, etc. can affect
people’s perceptions; you say:]
a. Gwen thinks Robert Zimmerman has a beautiful voice.
b. Gwen thinks Bob Dylan has a terrible voice.
In such a context your uses of (4.24a)–(4.24b) may both have readings on which
they seem true. One way of representing such uses is as follows (mutatis mutandis
for (4.24a)):
55
(4.25) S
T⟨1,a⟩
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a VP
she2 g1
⟨2,a⟩ CP
thinks t1s
⟨2,s⟩
Cd t2a
F2 g1 sings-terribly t2s
BD w1 -g2
Each of Gwen’s (=gc (2e)’s) belief-worlds includes two epistemic counterparts of the
actual individual BD/RZ — a childhood friend going by the name ‘Robert Zimmer-
man’ who sings beautifully, and a distinct celebrity going by the name ‘Bob Dylan’
who sings terribly. In the context in (4.24) the contextually determined value for the
choice-function pronoun, here gc (2cf), selects for any world u (=a(g)(1s) = @(a(g))
compatible with Gwen’s beliefs and set of individuals S = {o′ ∶ o′ is called Bob Dylan in u},
the individual o who is the singer-counterpart in u of BD/RZ. The attitude ascrip-
tion is true insofar as every such selected individual o (=gc (2cf)(BDa(g)(1s) )) sings
terribly in every such world u.
The above assignment-variable analysis captures how the embedded choice-
function pronoun receives its interpretation from the discourse context, while the
world-pronoun of the name-qua-predicate receives a local reading shifted by the atti-
tude verb: The discourse context determines the basis for selecting the relevant indi-
vidual o ∈ S in each of Gwen’s belief-worlds u, while each such set S is determined on
the basis of Gwen’s beliefs. Whereas the contextually relevant choice function in the
context in (4.22) selects BD/RZ from any set including him, as represented in (4.23),
the contextually relevant choice function in the context in (4.24) selects, from any
set of Bob Dylans in Gwen’s belief-worlds, a particular epistemic counterpart o of
BD/RZ, namely the singer-counterpart. In each possibility compatible with Gwen’s
56
beliefs the selected individual is called Bob Dylan. In the terminology from §4.2 the
use of the name is represented as having a specific de dicto reading — “specific”
in the sense that every such o is identical to one another (or at least metaphysical
counterparts of one another (Lewis 1986)), and “de dicto” in the sense that the
selected terrible singer is conceptualized as being called Bob Dylan. Indeed (4.24b)
could be used to characterize Gwen’s state of mind even if the “Bob Dylan” craze was
an elaborate hoax and there is in fact no such individual. Ordinary uses of names
may thus constitute a systematic case of the specific de dicto. Santorio 2013 argues
that capturing such readings in the case of indefinite DPs requires overhauling the
semantics for descriptions; some have even expressed doubt about the possibility of
specific de dicto readings (e.g., von Fintel & Heim 2011). No such innovations or
skepticism need be required. The readings in contexts such as (4.24) follow from an
off-the-shelf predicativist semantics with choice functions, implemented in a general
assignment-variable-based framework.
Finally, recall the “Puzzling Pierre” (Kripke 1979) example in (4.14) in which
two uses of ‘London’ receive different interpretations under the attitude verb. In
Kripke’s case, Pierre is a native French speaker who hears wonderful things about a
beautiful distant city named Londres. Later, he happens to move to an unattractive
part of London, and learns that it is named ‘London’; finding it ugly, he says ‘London
isn’t pretty’. Not realizing that the city he currently lives in is the same city as the city
he heard about while in France, he continues to accept the French sentence Londres
est jolie. Hence:
Pierre’s state of mind is such that each of his belief-worlds includes a city called
Londres which is pretty, and another dreary city called London where he lives. There
are various formalizations that would derive how a use of ‘London is London’ in
(4.26) in the given context may fail to characterize Pierre’s state of mind.
For the sake of argument let’s assume an “is-of-identity” reading for ‘is’. A sample
LF and semantic value is in (4.27).
57
(4.27) S
T⟨1,a⟩
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a he3 g1
⟨2,a⟩ CP
thinks t1s
⟨2,s⟩
Cd t2a
Roughly put, this says that the attitude ascription in (4.26) is true, on the relevant
reading, iff for every possibility h compatible with Pierre’s (=gc (3e)’s) state of mind,
the city o1 = F(London@(gc ) ) selected from among the things actually called London
is identical to the city o2 = F′ (London@(h) ) selected among the things called London
in Pierre’s belief-worlds @(h) (=a(g)(1s)).
The first occurrence of ‘London’ is represented as receiving a local reading,
picking out the city called London as Pierre conceives it; the second occurrence
of ‘London’ is represented as receiving a global reading, picking out the actual
city of London — though perhaps not so-called in Pierre’s belief-worlds. In the sec-
ond occurrence, the contextually determined value for the choice-function pronoun
[F3cf g1 ], gc (3cf), selects the present capital city of England from any set which
includes it; hence F(Londongc (1s) ) = o1 = London, an entity that includes areas
believed pretty by Pierre. In contrast, the world-pronoun in the first occurrence
of ‘London’ receives a local reading. The contextually determined choice-function
gc (2cf) selects the dreary city o2 where he lives from any set of things called London
in Pierre’s belief-worlds. Hence the belief ascribed isn’t necessarily true; indeed
(4.27) is correctly derived as false: the selected objects o1 , o2 are non-identical in
(some if not all of) Pierre’s belief-worlds @(h). Among other things, the entirety
of o2 is ugly and named ‘London’ throughout the worlds @(h); not so for o1 , which
includes areas that are pretty and named ‘Londres’. The analysis in (4.27) captures
58
how the complement of the attitude verb can express a contingent proposition that
fails to characterize Pierre’s state of mind.
The assignment-variable account outlined in this section maintains features mo-
tivating various types of semantics for names. First, with predicativists, we give a
uniform semantics for names qua lexical items in predicative and bare singular uses.
In both environments the name ‘N’ denotes the property of being called N.
Second, like many non-Millian accounts, the account captures the context-sensitivity
of uses of names without treating names as systematically ambiguous. The uses of
the string ‘F-r-e-d-d-o’ in (4.21) are uses of the same lexical item. The different
interpretations are derived from the contextually determined values for the choice-
function pronouns; the first use of ‘Freddo’ is interpreted with respect to a choice
function selecting Freddo the character, the second use with respect to a choice
function selecting Freddo the cookie.
Third, the semantics is compatible with certain uses of names being “rigid desig-
nators,” in the sense (roughly) of being used to designate the same individual across
worlds. For instance, in a bare singular use of ‘N’ context may determine a value for
the choice-function pronoun, F, that is defined only for sets including a particular
individual o, and selects o given every such set:
(4.29) [Context: Bert has been receiving daily unsigned letters ostensibly from a
secret admirer. Bert doesn’t know who they’re from, and even wonders
whether they’re all from the same individual. We, who deliver the letters,
deliver them without the envelopes, which we see are in each case addressed
from ‘Ernie’. We see Bert walking excitedly to the mailbox; you say:]
Bert thinks Ernie sent him another letter.
Your use of ‘Ernie’ in (4.29) is appropriate even if (it’s presupposed that) it’s not the
case that there is some particular individual o ∈ E who sends Bert a letter across
Bert’s belief-worlds.
With variabilist accounts, we capture various types of “shifted” readings in em-
bedded contexts. Classic puzzles of names in attitude ascriptions are assimilated to
phenomena with local/global readings of context-sensitive expressions. The range
59
of readings are derived from independently motivated resources from the litera-
ture — choice-function pronouns and predicativism — and our general assignment-
variable syntax and semantics. Additional mechanisms specific to names or intu-
itively referential expressions (e.g., substitutional quantification, guises, etc.) aren’t
required.38
Our assignment-variable-based framework formally implements the Stalnake-
rian (1988) idea that “multiple contexts” can be available for interpretation within
a single embedded clause (§1). Devices such as names can be used both to char-
acterize an individual’s “psychological semantic representation of a word” (Partee
1979: 11), and also “to pick out individuals in the basic context, and… express
propositions that alter the derived context” representing a subject’s state of mind
(Stalnaker 1988: 158–159). These dual functions, conspiring in classic puzzle
cases such as in (4.22)–(4.25), come together vividly in “Puzzling Pierre” exam-
ples such as (4.14)/(4.27). It isn’t evident how to capture such examples in an
operator-based variabilist semantics, where names are analyzed as simple variables
(e.g. Cumming 2008), without treating the names as ambiguous. By contrast, the
lexical item ‘London’ in (4.27) is treated as having the same semantic value in both
occurrences. The spectrum of shifted/unshifted readings are derived via interactions
between how individuals are selected (local/global readings of the choice-function
pronoun) and which individuals are candidates for selection (local/global readings
of the name-qua-predicate’s world pronoun).
Many variabilist and predicativist accounts of names are motivated by appeal-
ing to various types of non-purely-referential uses. Any overall account must also
be able to say something about the apparent differences in shiftability of names
in comparison with other context-sensitive expressions such as pronouns, definite
descriptions, etc., as in e.g. (4.30)–(4.31) (cf. Schlenker 2005).
60
d. Every guitarist thinks he plays the fastest.
≈ “every musician x thinks x plays the fastest”
(4.31) a. Only Alfred did Alfred’s homework.
≠ “only Alfred = o is such that [λx.x did x’s homework](o) = 1”
b. Only you did your homework.
≈ “only you = o are such that [λx.x did x’s homework](o) = 1”
This isn’t the place to provide a general binding theory for names. For present pur-
poses suffice it to say that binding phenomena with names are far from straightfor-
ward. For instance, unlike languages such as English, copy reflexive languages read-
ily use names with bound-variable readings, as in (4.32)–(4.33) (see also Lasnik
1989, Mortensen 2003, Boeckx et al. 2007).
Suppose then that in response to a wave of familial scorn ((4.35)), several Donalds
change their ways and begin telling others they are called Ronald. Characterizing
their families’ and partners’ states of mind, one might say (4.35), and later (4.36).
(4.35) ?Every family with a Donald thinks Donald should grow up.
(4.36) ?Every partner of a Donald thinks Donald is called Ronald.
≈ “every x such that x is the partner of some y called Donald thinks y is
called Ronald”
61
existing variabilist or predicativist accounts.39 The extra structure afforded by the
choice-function implementation in this section would provide a natural account; a
first-pass LF for (4.34) may be as follows (assuming that in the intended interpreta-
tion the index 2cf represents roughly a “bestness” choice function):
(4.37) [ S T⟨1,a⟩ … [[ DP every Donald-w1 -g1 ] [[thinks t1s ]⟨2,a⟩ … [ IP [ DP F2 -g2 Donald-
w1 -g1/2 ] …]]]] (preliminary)
The bound shifted reading of the embedded ‘Donald’ in (4.37) is represented pre-
cisely analogously to the bound shifted reading of the embedded epistemic ‘might’
in (4.8). I leave further refinements in light of binding phenomena with names
crosslinguistically, and comparisons with alternative (assignment-variable-based)
variabilist and predicativist analyses, for future work.40 (Hereafter I put the compli-
cations in this section with names aside; unless otherwise noted I will treat names
as constants.)
39
Examples combining predicative and bare singular uses of names would raise challenges for
variabilist accounts; examples such as (4.36) would raise a distinctive challenge for predicativist
semantics analyzing names along the lines of “being called N.”
40
If the reader finds (4.35)–(4.36) to bear an uncanny resemblance to donkey sentences: indeed.
A revised account is given below. I reconsider issues with pronoun binding and donkey anaphora in
§§6.2, 7.3, 7.4, 8.8 (also §§9.7, 10.3).
62
5 Recap. Next steps
Let’s take stock. Independent linguistic phenomena have led various theorists to
introduce assignments into the model, and to posit variables in the syntax for (e.g.)
worlds, times, and elements interpreting referential expressions. This paper begins
developing a linguistic theory which posits object-language variables for assignment
functions — variables for the sort of item responsible for interpreting quantifiers
and context-sensitive language generally — and treats compositional semantic val-
ues systematically in terms of sets of assignments. Principal features of the account
are that it standardizes quantification across domains (e.g. individuals, worlds, as-
signments); and it systematizes a range of linguistic shifting phenomena, as with
quantifiers, intensionality, and local/global readings of context-sensitive expressions.
A particular version of an assignment-variable-based account has been devel-
oped. The syntax and lexical/compositional semantics delineate the sources of
intensionality and assignment-shifting: world-quantification/binding arises from
the complementizer, which moves from the world-argument position of the clause’s
main predicate; assignment-quantification/binding arises from modals (broadly con-
strued), which move from the assignment-argument position of the C head. Bind-
ing with individuals/worlds/assignments is derived uniformly from a generalized
binder-index resulting from type-driven movement. This binder-index attaches di-
rectly to moved expressions. The account avoids quantification-specific compo-
sition rules or added parameters of interpretation. A distinction between trace-
binding and pronoun-binding — something arguably desirable for independent rea-
sons (Büring 2004, 2005) — falls out directly (more on which in §7). An improved
formalization of assignment modification was provided, which helps capture bind-
ing relations in examples with repeated modifications.
Philosophically, the account can be understood as providing a precise formal im-
plementation of Stalnaker’s “multiple context” approach to attitude ascriptions. The
syntax/semantics affords a unified analysis of the context-sensitivity of pronouns,
epistemic modals, etc., in the spirit of contextualist theories. Yet it improves in
compositionally deriving certain distinctive shifting phenomena (e.g. with epistemic
modals), and providing a framework for theorizing about expressions’ different
tendencies for local/global readings. Further (grammatical, lexical, metasemantic,
conversational) constraints on readings call for more thorough investigation (more
on which throughout the following sections).
§§2–4 applied the assignment-variable-based framework and particular treat-
ment of the syntax/semantics interface to certain phenomena with quantifiers, at-
titude verbs, and modal verbs. The remainder of the manuscript examines how
63
the account may be extended to other types of constructions. I focus primarily on
local/global readings in relative clauses, noun phrases, conditionals, and questions.
Extending an assignment-variable-based account to a particular expression or
construction isn’t as straightforward as taking one’s favorite style of analysis and
adding assignment-variables to interpret any other variables or context-sensitive
elements. The treatments of intensionality and modals in §3 relied on particular
assumptions about the syntax and semantics to motivate a basis for introducing
the relevant world- and assignment-binders, traces, and variables. Whatever style
of analysis one assumes for a given further expression, one needs to ensure that
any binder indices and sources of shifting phenomena can be derived from features
of the syntax/semantics that are independently attested and continuous with the
theory developed thus far — e.g., base-generating complementizers in the world
argument position of the clause’s main predicate, and base-generating assignment-
shifters, such as certain semantically modal expressions, in a relevant assignment-
argument position. §6 draws on prominent head-raising analyses of relative clauses
to develop an assignment-variable approach to restrictive relative clauses and don-
key anaphora: nominal quantifiers are treated as introducing quantification over
assignments, binding pronouns such as relative pronouns and donkey pronouns.
§7 examines how an assignment-quantificational syntax/semantics for quantifier
phrases can help capture various further phenomena with quantifiers and pronoun
binding; §8 further develops the account in a more general assignment-variable-
based syntax/semantics for different types of noun phrases. An alternative matching
account of relative clauses is provided (§8.7), which improves on the §6-account. Ex-
tensions to events in light of the proposed parallel layered n/v analyses of noun/verb
phrases are briefly explored (§8.9). §9 turns to local/global readings in condi-
tionals, drawing on developments on ‘if’-clauses as free relatives, now construed
as definite descriptions of possibilities, i.e. assignments. The approach to certain
types of pronominal anaphora from §§6–7 is applied to proforms in correlatives and
‘then’ conditionals. §10 examines local/global readings in interrogative sentences,
drawing on developments from Heim of an approach to questions as sets of possible
answers, with answers now construed as sets of assignments. The proposed syn-
tax/semantics afford uniform analyses of wh-words, indefinites, and relative words
as choice-function pronouns, and of interrogative sentences, ‘if’-clauses, and non-
modal correlative clauses; and they capture a spectrum of shifting phenomena with
‘if’-clauses in sentence-initial, sentence-internal, and sentence-final positions (ad-
joined to NP/VP/IP/CP), with individual correlative clauses adjoined to DP/IP/CP,
and with conditionals with modalized/non-modalized and declarative/interrogative
main clauses.
64
Part II
6 Relative clauses (I)
The following sections examine applications of the assignment-variable framework
to various types of non-declarative clauses and linguistic anaphora. I begin with
relative clauses. §6.1 motivates an account of determiner quantifiers in headed
relative clauses as introducing quantification over assignments. §6.2 applies the
treatment of relative clauses from §6.1 to several types of donkey anaphora. §§7–8
explore ways of extending the approach to the syntax/semantics from this section
to other types of noun phrases, restrictive modification, and pronoun binding; a
revised analysis of headed relative clauses is also provided. Features of the proposed
assignment-variable-based account include:
(I use ‘relative clause’ for expressions such as the bracketed material, ‘relative phrase’
for the combination of the relative word and nominal (‘which baby’), and ‘nominal
head’ for the nominal in the relative phrase (‘baby’). This informal usage doesn’t
presuppose particular views on the syntactic category or semantic type of the matrix
determiner’s restrictor argument, the relation between relative words and interrog-
ative wh words, or the semantic type of relative words such as ‘which’.)
65
which laughed’ in (6.1a) as restricting the domain of ‘every’ to the set of babies
o such that o laughed. How to derive this intuitive interpretation in the syntax
and compositional semantics is controversial. A familiar idea, following e.g. Heim
& Kratzer 1998, is that the relative word triggers Predicate Abstraction, and the
nominal head and relative clause combine by Predicate Modification:
66
I will suggest that an assignment-variable-based compositional semantics can pro-
vide a basis for an improved head-raising analysis of relative clauses. An alternative
“matching” analysis (Lees 1960, Sauerland 1998, 2003) is developed in §8.7.
67
combine with whatever fills the gap position, e.g. yielding type t denotation for
the IP, and (ii) that the relative clause CP is predicate-type so that it can combine
with the matrix determiner.
The principal attempt to address this compositional semantic challenge for head-
raising analyses comes from Bhatt 2002, which resorts to non-compositional op-
erations for interpreting traces (qua copies of movement; n. 13) and effects of
reconstruction (for parallel moves see Elbourne 2005, Moulton 2015). On Bhatt’s
analysis, the relative phrase ‘rel NP’ reconstructs to be interpreted in the gap posi-
tion in IP, and a mechanism of Trace Conversion from Fox (2000, 2002) converts
the relative phrase to a definite description ≈ “the NP identical to xi .” The variable
xi is bound by a binder-index in the position of the highest copy of the relative
phrase, where the binder-index is assumed to remain above the IP even though the
relative phrase, whose movement triggered the insertion of the binder, is deleted.
Formally, the derivation proceeds from a full chain such as (6.5a) to (6.5b), in which
deleting the non-lowest copies is assumed to leave a binder index in the position of
the highest copy, and then from (6.5b) to (6.5c) by Trace Conversion, in which the
relative phrase is replaced by a variable-bound definite description.
(6.6) a. every [[which baby]1 1 Alice thinks [[which baby]1 1 that Bert likes [which baby]1 ]]
68
b. every [1 Alice thinks [1 that Bert likes [which baby]1 ]]
c. every [1 Alice thinks [1 that Bert likes [the [[baby] [=o1 ]]]]]
(6.9) a. Chloe said that if hisk teacher is out sick, every boyk will be happy.
b. Chloe said that every boyk will be happy if hisk teacher is out sick.
An apparently simple Copy operation in the syntax of movement yields “copy and
delete along with any binder indices, unless at the base, in which case reinterpret
69
via Trace Conversion, and unless a relative phrase with no higher copies, in which
case delete but retain the binder index” at the syntax/semantics interface.
One way of alleviating at least some of these distinctions would be to treat
the relative phrase as only partially reconstructing (cf. Chomsky 1995, Moulton
2015). Compare (6.11) in which the intermediate copies are erased at LF (indi-
cated by the strikethrough), the relative word is interpreted in the highest copy,
the (pied-piped) complement NP is interpreted in the gap position, and the lowest
copy is converted such that ‘the’ is inserted into the empty D position and a variable
coindexed with the relative DP is inserted in the identity predicate sister to the NP.
Following Heim & Kratzer 1998 the binder-index triggers Predicate Abstraction,
which binds the coindexed variable inside the gap position, and the relative word
can be treated as denoting the identity function λPet .P. The relative clause denotes
(roughly) [λx . Alice thinks Bert likes the baby identical to x].
The LF in (6.11e) yields an intuitively correct denotation for the relative clause.
Consider the needed array of assumptions: (a) Deleted copies are syntactically
represented and semantically interpreted differently in different positions — e.g.,
the highest copy of ‘baby’ and the intermediate copy of the relative phrase are
erased at LF, whereas the deleted lowest copy of ‘which’ is replaced at LF with an
interpreted definite determiner. (b) Inserted sister to the NP in the lowest copy
is an identity predicate ‘= o1 ’, where the variable ‘o1 ’ internal to the gap-position
DP is coindexed with that very DP — i.e., with the DP originally represented with
the relative phrase [which baby]1 , the movement of which created a coindexed λ-
binder. (c) The inserted identity predicate (type ⟨e, t⟩) combines with the nominal
‘baby’ (type ⟨e, t⟩) via a rule of Predicate Modification. (d) The λ-abstraction at
the top of the relative clause is derived syncategorematically via an added Predicate
Abstraction rule; the node consisting of the binder-index isn’t given a denotation.
Further, note that there is no constituent for the relative phrase ‘which baby’ in
70
the final representation of the relative clause; ‘which baby’ doesn’t itself receive a
semantic value.
The above operations formalize what needs to be explained — roughly put, how
the relative clause CP ‘wh-NP Crel IP’ comes to have a property-type ⟨e, t⟩ denotation,
where the gap element of the IP is interpreted as coreferential with the NP-individual
intuitively abstracted over. Other things equal it would be preferable to provide a
semantics for the head-raising analysis without needing to invoke additional (non-
compositional) syntactic and semantic mechanisms such as these.43,44
The goal is to compositionally derive an interpretation of the relative clause from
the lexical semantics of the relative word and relative complementizer, function
application, and binding relations arising from type-driven movement. An attractive
strategy is to treat the syntax/semantics of DPs in headed relative constructions
43
The above discussion followed Bhatt 2002 (following Fox 2000, 2002) in treating operations
such as Trace Conversion are syntactic rules. The points carry over straightforwardly to implemen-
tations of Trace Conversion as a semantic rule. Adapting a suggestion in Fox 2003, one might treat
the narrow syntax as delivering (i-a), which is converted to (i-b) by copy deletion, and interpreted
straightway via the sort of semantic rule in (ii). The interpretation of the sister of ‘every’ in (i-b) may
be derived roughly as in (iii) (again assuming scattered copy deletion, and letting the relative ‘wh’
denote the identity function).
(i) a. every [CPrel [which baby]1 Alice thinks [[which baby]1 that Bert likes [which baby]1 ]]
b. every [CPrel [DP which]1 Alice thinks that Bert likes [DP baby]1 ]
(ii) Trace Conversion (semantic)
Let α be a structure of the form: DPi [β …DPi …]. JαK = JDPK(λx.Jβx′ /i K), where
a. βx′ /i is the structure derived from replacing the (possibly empty) head of every i-indexed
constituent in β with thex , where
b. Jthex K = λPet .JtheK(λy.y = x ∧ P(y) = 1) (cf. Fox 2003: ex. 52)
(iii) JCPrel K = (λQet .Q)(λx.J[. . . Bert likes [DP baby]1 ]′x/1 K)
= λx . J. . . Bert likes [thex baby]K
= λx . . . . Bert likes JtheK(λy.y = x ∧ JbabyK(y) = 1)
≈ λx . Alice thinks Bert likes the unique baby identical to x
The formalization of Trace Conversion in (ii) simply encodes the series of syntactic operations
considered in the main text in a compositional semantic rule. The effect is no more explanatory
for purposes of compositional semantics.
44
Compare Safir 1999, which analyzes certain lower copies like pronouns, and Sportiche
2006, which analyzes the lower copies as demonstratives. Safir appeals to Fiengo & May’s (1994)
mechanism of “vehicle change” to motivate treating copies of names and definite descriptions as
“evaluated as pronouns with respect to interpretive principles” (Safir 1999: 587); however, crucial
to Safir’s general account is that quantified expressions, which include relative clause heads, “do not
permit their variables to undergo vehicle change” (1999: 615). Given their purposes, neither Safir
nor Sportiche provide derivations for their posited interpretations in the compositional semantics.
71
parallel to the syntax/semantics of assignment-quantifiers such as modals from §3.
Research into parallels between nominals and clauses has a rich history in diverse
areas of syntax and semantics. As noted in §3.2, DP-internal operator-movement
from the complement of D has independent precedents in syntactic work on quan-
tificational/definite DPs (Campbell 1996, Matthewson 1998, Lecarme 1999b,
Ihsane & Puskás 2001, Giusti 2002, Luján 2004, Larson 2014). So, we can try
saying, just as modal quantifiers raise for type reasons from inside their clausal com-
plement, determiner quantifiers raise for type reasons from inside the relative clause
complement in headed restrictive relative clauses, (cf. Luján 2004). An assignment-
variable-based syntax/semantics for relativization along the lines pursued here may
thus provide yet another instance of the linguistic parallels between individual and
modal domains.45
There are various ways of implementing the approach in the compositional
semantics. Choice points include (i) the relation between relative words and in-
terrogative wh words; (ii) the position of the relative phrase at LF; (iii) the inter-
actions among the relative complementizer, relative phrase, and (possibly gappy)
IP in deriving a suitable argument for the matrix determiner. For purposes of com-
Compare also Caponigro 2003 on semantics for various types of free relatives. Caponigro treats
relative determiners in free relatives as raising from the IP gap position to Spec,C, leaving a λ-binder
in C; the [C λi IP] node is interpreted via a non-compositional abstraction rule. Caponigro is careful
to restrict his analysis to free relatives. It isn’t immediately evident how it would apply to headed
relatives (or to wh-interrogatives, though Caponigro assumes that free relatives are introduced
with wh-words). I am not aware of other analyses of QR/wh-movement which treat the λ-binder
as occupying a head position, such as that for the complementizer C. That aside, an analogous
Caponigro-style treatment of headed relatives would need to assume that in headed relatives with an
overt complementizer (e.g. ‘baby that Bert likes’), the complementizer gets fully deleted prior to wh-
movement. Yet such an assumption would raise issues for (wh) interrogative clauses, which require
the presence of the substantive interrogative complementizer throughout the derivation (e.g., to
trigger wh movement and satisfy selection requirements of question-embedding expressions (§10)).
45
For discussion with further examples of DP-internal movement, see Tellier 1991, Longobardi
1994, 2001, Campbell 1996, Alexiadou & Wilder 1998b, den Dikken 1998, Matthewson 1998,
Bhattacharya 1999a,b, Bernstein 2001, 2008, Boeckx 2001, Ihsane & Puskás 2001, Giusti
2002, Luján 2004, Hiraiwa 2005, Laenzlinger 2005, Larson 2014, Ilkhanipour 2016. For
general discussion on syntactic parallels in nominal/verbal extended projections and interpretive
parallels across domains (individual, spatial, temporal, modal), see also Chomsky 1970, Partee
1984b, Fukui & Speas 1986, Abney 1987, Szabolcsi 1987, 1994, Guéron & Hoekstra 1995,
Webelhuth 1995, Bittner & Hale 1996, Lecarme 1996, 1999b, 2004, 2008, Siloni 1997, Stone
1997, Kratzer 1998a, Cardinaletti & Starke 1999, Pesetsky & Torrego 2001, Rijkhoff 2002,
2008, Koopman 2003, 2005, Aboh 2004, Bhat 2004, Svenonius 2004, Grimshaw 2005, Ticio
2005, Alexiadou et al. 2007, Aikhenvald 2008, Megerdoomian 2008, Wiltschko 2014; also
n. 2, §§7.2, 8.
72
parison, the remainder of this section explores how our assignment-variable-based
framework can help provide an improved compositional semantics for head-raising
analyses of relative clauses. As we will see, there are reasons to think that the
resulting account cannot be right for the general case. However, the following
preliminary discussion will be instructive in illustrating resources for developing
the assignment-variable-based syntax/semantics from §3. An alternative matching
analysis is given in §8.7 in the context of a more general syntax/semantics for noun
phrases.
The core components of the account of (headed restrictive) relative clauses in
this section are as follows. Regarding (i), I will suggest a unified analysis of relative
pronouns, wh-words, and (at least some) indefinites as choice-function pronouns
(more on interrogative wh words in §10.3). Regarding (ii), one option is to treat the
relative phrase [whrel NP] as originating Spec of Crel (Sternefeld 2001, Gračanin-
Yuksek 2008). So, for (iii), just as the declarative complementizer raises for type
reasons from the clause’s verbal head, Crel in an individual relative clause raises
for type reasons from the nominal gap position. And just as modal quantifiers raise
from an internal argument of the matrix complementizer, the matrix determiner can
be analyzed as raising from an internal argument of the relative complementizer.
A simplified LF is as follows (using ‘wh’ for relative words, ignoring worlds, and
treating names as constants (§4.4); I address the question marks shortly).
every⟨i,?⟩ CPrel
C
baby
wh g?
⟨j,e⟩ IP
Free relatives in argument positions might be treated analogously (though see Caponigro
2003, Gračanin-Yuksek 2008). Adapting Comp accounts of free relatives (Groos
& van Riemsdijk 1981), the relative phrase in (6.13) is in a specifier position and
what raises from C0rel is a definite-like element, which picks out the (possibly plural)
73
individual in the relevant domain (=[Pet g]) that satisfies the property denoted by
the relative clause (cf. e.g. Jacobson 1995, Rullmann 1995, Dayal 1996, Grosu
& Landman 1998, Caponigro 2003, 2012; for simplicity assume ‘what’ ≈ ‘which
relevant thing(s)’).46
46
The definite-like element, though implicit in English, is overt in various languages, as in (i).
Like other definites, free relatives are generally incompatible with existential ‘there’ sentences (more
on which in §8.4).
(i) [le [ba’ax k-in tsikbal-t-ik-∅ te’ex]-a’
det what hab-erg.1s chat-trans-ind-abs.3s 2.pl-cl
‘this (thing) which I’m telling you about’ (Gutiérrez-Bravo 2012: ex. 10; Yucatec Maya)
(ii) a. *There is what Alice likes. (ok only with locative ‘there’)
b. There is something/∗the book Alice likes.
An interesting precedent for the analyses in (6.12)–(6.13) is Rullmann 1995: 149–150; in Rull-
mann’s (iii), the relative complementizer also binds a variable occupying the gap position and
the relative word is in Spec,C. (Rullmann stipulates that the empty complementizer is parsed as
a lambda abstractor and coindexed with the variable assumed to occupy the gap position. Rullmann
treats the relative word as itself the maximality operator; the account isn’t applied to restrictive
(non-maximalizing) relatives.)
(iii) [ CP what [ C ei [ IP John ordered ti ]]] (Rullmann 1995: 150)
Caponigro (2003) also treats DP-like standard free relatives as denoting a maximal entity, but treats
the free relatives as CPs with the covert pluralization operator in an adjoined position (as opposed to
treating the free relatives as DPs with the operator as a covert D head). The approach in (6.13) could
be adapted accordingly. As we will see, the analyses of relative and wh words proposed below and in
§10, respectively, maintain a uniform semantics for relative and wh words, and are thus compatible
with Caponigro’s (2003) proposal to identify interrogative wh-words and the relative words in free
relatives. See Caponigro 2003, Gračanin-Yuksek 2008 on various respects in which free relatives
pattern with wh-interrogatives in contrast to headed relatives crosslinguistically.
74
(6.13) Free relative as DP: D∅ CPrel (preliminary)
a. ‘(Bert likes) what Alice likes’
b. DP
⟨i,?⟩
ιo CPrel
C
wh g? P g
⟨j,e⟩ IP
75
(6.16) Bert might think some stalker is out to get him.
a. Intermediate reading: ≈ it’s possible that there is some particular stalker
o such that Bert thinks o is out to get him (might > indef > think)
(6.17) Every baby cried because a (certain) toy of mine scared them.
(every > indef > because)
(6.18) Every professor rewarded every student who read a/some book he had
recommended. (every prof > indef > every student)
(Abusch 1994: ex. 10; Kratzer 1998b: ex. 16)
(6.19b) isn’t true simply if most farmer-shovel pairs ⟨x, y⟩ are such that x uses y, or
if most shovel-owning farmers use some stolen shovel or other; the truth of (6.19b)
requires that most farmers x use some shovel owned by x. The quantificational
force and content of the donkey pronoun varies with the subject and value for the
indefinite in the quantifier’s restriction.
The interpretation of certain indefinites and expressions linguistically dependent
on them can shift, not only in “shifty” contexts such as conditionals and attitude
ascriptions, but also under ordinary quantifiers. A hypothesis is that just as modal
quantifiers can shift the interpretations of pronouns, so too, at least in some cases,
with determiner quantifiers. This section develops a syntax/semantics of determiner
quantifiers as involving quantification over assignments. §6.2, as well as §§7.3,
7.4, 8.8, apply the account to several types of pronominal anaphora. I leave appli-
cations to specific indefinites and other types of linguistic and discourse anaphora
for future work.
I suggest that we treat determiner quantifiers in headed relative clauses as quan-
tifying over assignments, and raising for type reasons from an internal assignment-
argument of the relative complementizer. Intuitively put, a DP such as ‘every baby
which Alice likes’ quantifies over those individuals which could be chosen from
76
among the babies and would correctly answer the question of what Alice likes. I
offer the following lexical entry for the relative complementizer Crel :47
(6.20) JCrel K = λaa .λPet .λye .λxe .λgg . x(g) = y(g) ∧ P(x)(g)
77
‘The man who you saw yesterday went home.’
(Peterson 1974: 74; Mooré (Niger-Congo))
48
In the general definition of the binder-index: with every, τ = a, σ = ⟨⟨a, et⟩, t⟩, σ1 = e; with
DP: D CPrel , τ = a, σ = t, σ1 = e. I assume that the relative word must have the same assignment-
variable as the local relative complementizer, as due to agreement (Williams 1980, Chung 1998,
Kratzer 2009; we will revisit this in §§8.7–8.8). As with other determiners, there may be reasons
for incorporating domain variables to further restrict the domains of relative words. In (6.23) the
domain variable may be treated as sister to ‘baby’ or as an additional argument of ‘which’, restricting
the domain of the choice-function pronoun to a set of contextually relevant babies; see n. 26. For
simplicity I continue to ignore such further structure.
78
(6.23) ‘Every baby which she likes laughed’
S
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a
DP⟨2,a⟩
t1s laughed
every⟨2,a⟩ CPrel
DP∗
⟨2,e⟩
wh2 g2 baby
w1 g1 Crel t2a she1 g1
t2e
likes
w1 g1
79
some choice function or other from among the babies and are liked by gc (1e). The
sentence (6.23) is true iff every such individual laughed.
For instance, suppose there are four individuals o1-4 ; only o1-3 are babies; only
o1-2 are liked by gc (1e); and only o1 laughed. And suppose that h1 (2cf) selects o1
among the babies; h2 (2cf) selects o2 ; and h3 (3cf) selects o3 . So, for individual o2
and assignment h2 , the restrictor condition is satisfied: o2 = h2 (2cf)(babygc (1s) ), and
gc (1e) likes o2 . Yet o2 didn’t laugh. Hence (6.23) is false.
The above syntax/semantics compositionally derives the intuitive interpretation
delivered by familiar semantics with Predicate Abstraction and intersective mod-
ification, and does so without positing additional composition rules or principles
for interpreting reconstructed phrases (e.g. Trace Conversion). The syntax is co-
opted from prominent head-raising and D-complement analyses of headed rela-
tives. The compositional semantics parallels the treatments of type-driven bind-
ing/quantification with verbal quantifiers from §§3–4: Just as a declarative clause
predicates a property of a world identical to a world in a domain determined by an
embedding modal, a relative clause predicates a property of an individual identical
to an individual in a domain determined by an embedding determiner quantifier.
Complementizers in matrix clauses raise from VP as quantifiers over worlds, captur-
ing the obligatory local reading of the main predicate’s world argument; analogously
the relative complementizer raises from the gap position in the relative clause, cap-
turing the obligatory link between the gap and the nominal head. Semantically
modal elements raise from inside their complement clause as quantifiers over as-
signments, determining the relevant modal domain; analogously the determiner
quantifier ‘every’ in (6.23) raises from inside its complement CPrel , determining the
relevant domain of individuals. The basic type-⟨aet, ⟨aet, t⟩⟩ semantics for deter-
miner quantifiers parallels the basic type-⟨at, ⟨at, t⟩⟩ of modal quantifiers from §3.
The syntax/semantics of quantificational DP: D CP is a nominal counterpart of the
syntax/semantics of modals in the domain of individuals (§6.1.2).
It is standard in syntax to treat features on a head X as projecting to the XP.
Given the treatment of binder-indices as features on expressions, the assignment
binder-index on ‘every’ projects to the DP. In what follows I will suggest that this as-
signment binder affords a resource for capturing shifted interpretations of pronouns
and various phenomena with donkey anaphora.
80
(6.24) ‘Every baby which got a toy liked it’
a. [S …[[DP every⟨2,a⟩ [CPrel wh2 g2 baby [[Crel t2a ]⟨2,e⟩ [t2e got ???-toy]]]] liked ??? ]]
As is familiar, the donkey pronoun ‘it’ isn’t c-commanded by its apparent linguistic
antecedent, the indefinite ‘a toy’. Simply representing ‘it’ with some individual
pronoun [it3 gi ] doesn’t capture the intuitive anaphoric49 interpretation: coindexing
the assignment-variable with the topmost assignment-binder yields a claim about
gc (3e), and coindexing it with every⟨2,a⟩ yields a claim about gc (2a)(3e). Ap-
proaches to donkey anaphora are diverse. One might layer resources from one’s
preferred theory into an assignment-variable-based framework — e.g., adding uns-
elective binders and revising the treatment of indefinites (Kamp 1981, Heim 1982),
or treating donkey pronouns as E-type descriptions and introducing mechanisms for
recovering the relevant descriptive content (Heim 1990, Büring 2004, Elbourne
2005). However, it is worth exploring whether the assignment-quantification with
determiners could be exploited for developing an account of apparent non-c-com-
mand anaphora such as donkey anaphora.
A common approach in both dynamic and non-dynamic theories is to treat indefi-
nites as introducing a (new) variable, as for an individual (Kamp 1981, Heim 1982)
or choice function (Reinhart 1997, Kratzer 1998b). Following our treatment
of relative words, suppose we represent the relevant uses of indefinites such as ‘a’
likewise as choice-function pronouns. To a first approximation, I suggest repre-
senting donkey pronouns in sentences such as (6.24) as copies of their linguistic
antecedent.50 There are various ways of implementing this idea. One option —
the option I wish to pursue here — is to represent the anaphoric pronoun (n. 49)
as a copy of the interpreted material of the antecedent (refinements to follow). A
donkey pronoun such as ‘it’ in (6.24) is spelled out at LF with a coindexed choice-
49
Here and throughout I use ‘anaphora’ and its kin informally for phenomena in which an
expression seems to receive its interpretation directly from the linguistic context. For familiarity I use
‘anaphor’/‘anaphoric pronoun’ broadly to cover uses of pronouns with intuitively bound readings,
though sometimes to the exclusion of anaphors proper; context should disambiguate. My usage
doesn’t presuppose that pronouns with “anaphoric” or “intuitively bound” readings are to be analyzed
as syntactically or semantically bound by their felt linguistic antecedents. I briefly consider anaphors
proper, such as reflexives, and ordinary bound readings of pronouns in §7.3. I focus exclusively on
intra-sentential linguistic anaphora.
50
We will reexamine the internal/external syntax and semantics for choice-functional uses of
indefinites and donkey pronouns in §8.8.3. I don’t assume that all indefinites are to be analyzed
uniformly as choice-function pronouns; see e.g. Kratzer 1998b for an ambiguity account positing
choice-function/quantificational analyses of specific/nonspecific indefinites, respectively; cf. Fodor
& Sag 1982.
81
function pronoun and elided nominal complement, as in (6.25). (Hereafter, unless
indicated otherwise I use the strikethrough for material that is interpreted at LF
but unpronounced. I will sometimes use ‘oi ’ as short for ‘oicf ’ with choice-function
variables.)51
51
The present approach might be understood as an assignment-variable analogue of the NP-dele-
tion E-type theory in Elbourne 2001, 2005, 2013 (though see below; cf. Cooper 1979, Heim &
Kratzer 1998, Büring 2005); see Postal 1969, Wiltschko 1998, Radford 1997, Déchaine
& Wiltschko 2002, Panagiotidis 2002, Baltin 2012, Patel-Grosz & Grosz 2017 for broader
“X+elided-complement” analyses of certain pro-forms crosslinguistically. I focus exclusively on
instances of donkey anaphora where the pronoun has a linguistic antecedent. I leave open how
the account may be extended to “paycheck” pronouns, as in (i), where the pronoun’s covarying
interpretation is contextually determined.
(i) [Context: A new faculty member picks up her first paycheck from her mailbox. Waving it in the
air, she says to a colleague:]
Do most faculty members deposit it in the Credit Union? (Jacobson 2000: 89n.12)
I don’t assume that all pronouns or anaphoric expressions need be analyzed in this way. For
instance, depending on one’s views on the relation between referential and anaphoric/bound pro-
nouns, free readings could be represented with simplex individual-type pronouns [oe g], or with
choice-function pronouns coindexed with T and a (possibly trivial) property-type pronoun (≈“which
(relevant) thing”). For unified theories of pronouns, see e.g. Heim & Kratzer 1998, Panagiotidis
2002, Elbourne 2005, 2013; for contrasting approaches, see Aoun & Hornstein 1992, Noguchi
1997, Hornstein 2001, 2007, Bhat 2004, Déchaine & Wiltschko 2002, 2017b, Kratzer 2009.
Likewise I leave open the specific syntactic category of the relevant English pronouns; the account
needn’t be committed to treating choice-function pronoun elements as uniformly in D positions (see
Déchaine & Wiltschko 2002, 2015, 2017a,b, Alexiadou et al. 2007, Baltin 2012, Patel-Grosz
& Grosz 2017 for overviews on potential structural differences among pronouns crosslinguistically;
also n. 78). Given our purposes I ignore internal projections such as for φ-features. The analysis is
compatible with there being differences in φ-features in certain examples, as in (ii). Such examples
may be assimilated to independent phenomena in which a pronoun’s φ-features are apparently
uninterpreted (e.g. due to Feature Deletion or Feature Transmission), as with “fake indexicals” such
as in (iii) (cf. von Stechow 2003, Rullmann 2003, Hornstein 2007, Heim 2008, Kratzer 2009,
Sudo 2012, Déchaine & Wiltschko 2015, Wiltschko 2016).
(ii) Every freshman who met a senior hoped that they would become friends.
(iii) a. I’m the only one around here who will admit that I could be wrong. (Partee 1989a: fn. 3)
b. Only you remember our first appointment. (Kratzer 2009: ex. 87)
82
(6.25) ‘Every baby which got a toy liked it’
S
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a
DP⟨2,a⟩ VP
every⟨2,a⟩ CPrel
liked t1s
it3 g2
toy-w1 -g1
⟨2,e⟩
wh2 g2
baby-w1 -g1
Crel t2a t2e
got-w1 -g1
a3 g2
toy-w1 -g1
CPrel denotes a singleton set of individuals that are selected by some particular
choice function and got a toy selected by some particular choice function. The de-
terminer’s assignment-binder binds the assignment-variables in the choice-function
pronouns representing the indefinite ‘a toy’ and relative phrase ‘which baby’. Roughly,
the DP ‘every baby which got a toy’ universally quantifies over those individuals
o ∈ E and choice functions F, F′ such that F (=a(g)(2cf)) selects o from among
the babies, F′ (=a(g)(3cf)) selects some o′ (=a(g)(3cf)(toygc (1s) )) from among the
toys, and o got o′ — babies o that got some toy or other o′ . The sentence is true
iff for every such o, o liked o′ . The apparent anaphoric connection between ‘a toy’
and ‘it’ is captured by (i) the syntactic identification of the donkey pronoun with
83
its antecedent [a3 -g2 toy-w1 -g1 ], and (ii) the assignment-binding introduced by the
determiner quantifier.
Treating instances of donkey anaphora as copies of their linguistic antecedent
affords a straightforward implementation of the prominent idea that “there is a
pairing of indefinite antecedents with donkey-pronouns that is purely syntactic (as
expected under the unselective binding approach, but not available under the E-type
approach)” (von Fintel 1994: 176, drawing on Kratzer 1995; emphasis mine;
cf. e.g. Heim 1990, Ward et al. 1991, Elbourne 2005, Patel-Grosz & Grosz
2010). However, the proposed treatment of certain anaphoric pronouns as “copies”
of their linguistic antecedents shouldn’t be conflated with copies in the sense of the
copy theory of movement (see n. 13). Copies of movement are treated as identical to
the moved expression (or at least identical with respect to φ-features, [wh] features,
Case, etc.; cf. also Nunes 2004, van Koppen 2007). In contrast, the anaphoric
expressions in question, on the present proposal, need only be equivalent to their
antecedents with respect to features interpreted at LF (n. 51). The pronouns needn’t
be identical to their antecedents with respect to other features relevant for non-
semantic (purely syntactic, phonological) reasons. It is a substantive question, for
a given type of anaphoric expression, whether the anaphoric “copy,” in the present
usage, is the result of some syntactic Copy operation. (More on these issues below
and in §§7.4, 9.7, 10.3.)
If the LF representations of donkey pronouns were syntactically complex in
the proposed way, one might expect to find evidence for this complexity in other
languages (n. 51). First, indirect evidence may come from independently attested
structure in pronouns used as donkey pronouns. For instance, in languages with
nominal tense such as Somali, tense morphology may appear on any common noun,
as in (6.26) (Lecarme 1996, 2004, Nordlinger & Sadler 2004, Adamou 2011;
cf. Aikhenvald 2008). Interestingly, whereas (e.g.) indefinite nominals and even
certain syntactically marked definites are tenseless in Somali, individual pronouns
may be marked for tense — not only in referential uses, as in (6.27), but also in
bound uses and donkey sentences, as in (6.28). As with other nominals, the tense
on a pronoun can be independent of clausal tense.
84
(6.27) a. Isá-gíi baa hádal-kíi qaatáy, oo yiri:
he-emph.past decl talk-def.past take.past and said
‘He began to speak, and said:’ (Lecarme 2008: ex. 10a)
b. Isa-ga waxaa arkay Axmed.
him-emph.nonpast decl saw.past Axmed
‘Axmed saw him.’ (Özyıldız & Ivan 2017: ex. 6)
(6.28) a. Qof walba oo hali leh iya-dai wuu garacaa.
person every rel she-camel has her-emph.nonpast decl beats
‘Everyone who has a cameli beats iti .’ (Özyıldız & Ivan 2017: ex. 18a)
b. Nini hád-díi uu seexdó oo sóo toosó, waa isá-gíii
man time-def.past he sleeps and dir wakes-up decl him-emph.past
ún.
only
‘If a mani goes to sleep and then wakes up, hei is only himself (i.e. the
same as he was before).’ (Lecarme 2008: ex. 19a)
Somali tense-related DPs have full TP complements (Lecarme 2008, 2012). Exam-
ples such as (6.28) suggest that such structure can apply to donkey pronouns, e.g.
roughly as in (6.29).
85
b. los buenos
they good
‘the good ones’
c. lo que agrada
it that pleases
‘that which pleases’ (Luján 2004: exs. 2, 4; Spanish)
(6.32) a. Hvis en mann eier et esel, slår han det.
if a man owns a donkey beats he it
b. Si un hombre tiene un burro, lo trata mal.
if a man has a donkey it.acc treats badly
86
forms, pro-NPs are generally incompatible with bound-variable readings (Déchaine
& Wiltschko 2002):53
What distinguishes ‘it’ from han, det, etc. is whether it has a selectional property of
disallowing an overtly modified complement (e.g., CPrel or a multi-segmented NP).55
Though see Yashima 2015 on the specific binding-theoretic properties of Japanese kare.
53
As is common, I use φP as a cover term for the relevant intermediate functional projection(s)
54
87
More direct crosslinguistic support for the proposed analysis of donkey pronouns
as (internally complex) copies of their linguistic antecedents may come from the
morphosyntax of the donkey-anaphoric expressions themselves. Notably, in certain
Chinese and Hmong donkey sentences the anaphoric expression must be a complete
copy of its (non-c-commanding) antecedent, as in (6.39)–(6.40) with the indefinites
shei and (tug) twg.
Interestingly, overtly prenominal uses of English ‘it’ are even attested in toddler
speech, as in the naturally occurring example in (6.41a).
Following Radford, uses such as (6.41) reflect a developmental stage where the
child hasn’t yet learned that the particular word ‘it’ in English selects for a phoneti-
cally unrealized complement (unlike, say, ‘we’; see below).56 One might imagine a
precocious counterpart of McNeill’s toddler saying ‘Everyone who has a ladder likes
it ladder’, parallel to (6.39)–(6.40).
Second, although Déchaine & Wiltschko’s (2002) class of pro-DPs generally re-
sist bound readings, some are compatible with overtly realizing the morphosyntactically
complex DP, as in (6.42a) with the pronoun thú-tl’ò, in (6.42b) with English ‘we’,
and in (6.43) with the pronoun yi. Wiltschko 1998 argues on independent grounds
c. *them good
[ φP them [ NP good N]]
56
Suggestively, Radford even glosses the toddler’s use of ‘it’ in (6.41) as analogous to an adult
speaker’s use of a specificity determiner such as ‘the’ (1997: 155; see n. 52).
88
that German d-pronouns are also syntactically complex DPs with an elided nomi-
nal complement (see also Schwarz 2009, Patel-Grosz & Grosz 2017). Notably,
though d-pronouns are generally unacceptable with bound variable readings, they
may be used as donkey pronouns, as in (6.45). Class pronouns in languages such
as Bùlì exhibit no restrictions in bound or anaphoric readings, yet they also occur
freely with full nominals, as in (6.44) with wá (cf. also Postal 1969, Pesetsky 1978,
Collins 1993, Radford 1997).
On the flip side, in Hindi donkey sentences the anaphoric expression can be
overtly realized as a copy of the antecedent nominal, as in (6.46) in which the bare
gadheKO ‘donkey’ is anaphorically linked to the non-c-commanding indefinite koii
gadhaa ‘some donkey’.
89
(6.46) har aadmii jis ke paas koii gadhaai hotaa hai gadheKOi maartaa hai.
every man rel with some donkey has donkey beats
‘Every man who has a donkey beats it.’ (Srivastav 1991: ex. 45a; Hindi)
Such examples can be represented parallel to their English counterparts at LF, as re-
flected schematically in (6.47) for (6.46) (ignoring worlds and using English glosses).
(6.48) Every child who got a toy will bring that toy for show-and-tell.
As noted above, many languages use the same format for demonstratives and pro-
nouns such as third-person pronouns (n. 52). Yet it won’t do to respond by simply
positing a covert demonstrative. Compare (6.46), in which the bare nominal can
function as the anaphoric expression, with (6.49), in which removing the demon-
strative renders the sentence ungrammatical.
90
to the lack of an overt demonstrative. (6.50), in which the correlate is implicit, is
acceptable (Srivastav 1991, Bhatt 2003; cf. Lipták 2012 on Hungarian).
(6.51) JmostK = λP+⟨a,et⟩ .λQ+⟨a,et⟩ .λgg . #o[∃aa ∶ P+(a)(λgg .o)(g) ∧ Q+(a)(λgg .o)(g)]
÷ #o′ [∃a′a ∶ P+(a′ )(λgg .o′ )(g)] > 1/2
● #o[ . . . o . . . ] ∶= the cardinality of the set of atoms o s.t. . . . o . . .
(6.52) a. ‘Most babies which got a toy liked it’
b. ≈ λgg . #o[∃aa ∶ o = a(g)(2cf)(babiesg−(1s) ) ∧ o got a(g)(3cf)(toyg−(1s) )
in g−(1s) ∧ o liked a(g)(3cf)(toyg−(1s) ) in @(g−)]
÷ #o′ [∃a′a ∶ o′ = a′ (g)(2cf)(babiesg−(1s) ) ∧ o′ got a′ (g)(3cf)(toyg−(1s) )
in g−(1s)] > 1/2
58
Following Link 1983, E is structured to include (plural) sums of atomic individuals. (An atomic
individual is an individual whose only atomic part is itself. Note that atoms are included in babiesu
(Krifka 1989).) We will return to number in §§8.1–8.2.
91
The entry for ‘most’ in (6.51) says, roughly, that the number of atomic individuals
that satisfy the restrictor and scope arguments is greater than the number of atomic
individuals that satisfy the restrictor but not the scope. Suppose there are three
babies b1-3 ; b1 got four toys and liked them; and neither b2 nor b3 liked the unique
toy they got. So, b2 /b3 satisfy the restriction that there are choice functions which
select them from among the babies and select a toy they got; however, b2 /b3 fail to
satisfy the scope condition since they don’t like the selected toy, i.e. a(g)(3cf)(toy).
The semantics avoids giving symmetric construals of asymmetric readings.
The semantics for ‘every’ in (6.22) derives a so-called “universal reading” for
donkey sentences: The derived truth condition in (6.25) is falsified if there is a
baby o′ and choice function F′ such that o′ got F′ (toy), and o′ didn’t like F′ (toy).
Although many theories predict only universal readings for donkey sentences (Kamp
1981, Heim 1982, Groenendijk & Stockhof 1991, Elbourne 2005), it has been
observed that some donkey sentences have existential readings. (6.53b) is intu-
itively true as long as every person who has a dime will put some dime that she has
in the meter.
(6.53) a. Yesterday, every person who had a credit card paid his bill with it.
(R. Cooper)
b. Every person who has a dime will put it in the meter.
(Pelletier and Schubert 1989)
c. Every person who submitted a paper had it rejected once.
(Chierchia 1995: ex. 3)
One way of capturing existential readings is to weaken the semantics of the quanti-
fier. Consider the following alternative entry for ‘every’ and semantic value for (6.25):
The semantics in (6.54) requires that, for every individual satisfying the restriction,
there is some assignment that verifies both the restriction and scope. The derived
semantic value for (6.25) represents the existential reading: (6.55) says, roughly,
92
that for any o ∈ E for which there are choice functions F, F′ such that o = F(baby)
and o got F′ (toy), there is a choice function F′′ that selects a toy that o got and
liked. There is universal quantification over the subject-babies o, but existential
quantification in the scope over toys liked by o — more precisely, over assignments
which determine choice functions that select a toy o liked from among the toys o
received. The condition “P+(a′ )(x)(g)” in (6.54) ensures that the choice function
F′′ relative to which the individuals o satisfy the scope condition — that o likes
F′′(toy) — selects a toy received by o. (6.24) is still correctly predicted false in a
scenario where a baby liked some toys or other but hated all the toys it received.
It is controversial whether some donkey sentences conventionally have both
existential and universal readings. I leave open whether all universal readings can be
derived conversationally, or positing some sort of ambiguity is ultimately necessary
(see Kanazawa 1994, Chierchia 1995, King 2004, Brasoveanu 2007). Here-
after, unless indicated otherwise, I will simplify by assuming “universal reading”
entries such as (6.22).
93
Although the account captures the core linguistic shifting data in this section, there
are reasons to be dissatisfied. There are reasons to think that any account which
represents the relative complementizer as originating in the “gap” position cannot be
correct for the general case of headed restrictive relative clauses crosslinguistically.
There is compelling syntactic and semantic evidence that, in at least some cases,
it’s the relative phrase that originates in the nominal gap position. Notably, in
languages with circumnominal relative clauses, the relative phrase is pronounced in
this position, as in (6.56) (de Vries 2002, Hiraiwa 2005, 2017). Although leaving
Spec,Crel empty is ungrammatical in (6.57b), elements other than the relative phrase
can satisfy Crel ’s EPP properties, as in (6.57a) (Hiraiwa 2005). Relative phrases in
DP-like free relatives can also appear inside the relative clause, as in (6.58)
(6.56) [[CPrel Atia n da’ [bua seka] da’a zaam] la] bɔi mɛ.
Atia c buy.perf goat rel market yesterday d lose.perf prt
(lit. ‘The [Atia bought which goat at the market yesterday] got lost.’)
‘The goat that Atia bought at the market yesterday got lost.’
(Hiraiwa et al. 2017: 5; Gurenɛ (Niger-Congo))
(6.57) a. Atim ale da mango-kuui la
Atim c bought mango-rel dem
‘the mango that Atim bought’
b. ∗ale/∗ate/∗∅ Atim da mango-kuui la
c Atim bought mango-rel dem
(Hiraiwa 2005: 297; Bùlì (Niger-Congo))
(6.58) [[CPrel Mary [taku] ka� � e] ki] ophewathų.
Mary something make the I.buy
‘I bought what Mary made.’ (Williamson 1987: 188; Lakhota (Siouan))
It is hard to see how relative clauses such as these could be derived if the relative
phrase originated in Spec,Crel (or outside CPrel , as in head-external analyses). In
(6.56)/(6.57a) the relative clause subject is apparently pronounced in this position.
Even in English there are semantic reasons for thinking that the relative phrase
can have a representation in the gap position. Consider (6.59) (the indices are used
informally to indicate the interpretation of the predicate’s world argument).
(6.59) Callie wants to hug every unicorni which Timmy thinksi he found.
Roughly put, (6.59) says that Callie wants to hug every o such that for every pos-
sibility h compatible with Timmy’s beliefs, o is a unicorn in h and Timmy found o
in h. (6.59) needn’t imply that there are actually unicorns. Details aside, it is hard
94
to see how the world argument for ‘unicorn’ could be linked to ‘thinks’ if the relative
phrase ‘which unicorn’ originates in Spec,Crel above the attitude verb, as in (6.60).
⟨2,e⟩
(6.60) [every [ CPrel wh unicorn-w??? [C0rel [ IP Timmy thinks [he found t2e ]]]]]
Alternative local and intermediate readings of the nominal head’s world argument
are also possible. In (6.61) the world argument of ‘monster’ is intuitively associated
with the lower intensional verb in the relative clause. (6.61) says, roughly, that
Timmy gets nightmares from every o such that for every possibility h compatible
with Alice’s beliefs and every possibility h′ compatible with what Timmy fears in
h, o is a monster in h′ . In (6.62) the world argument of ‘monster’ is intuitively
associated with the higher attitude verb ‘thinks’ in the relative clause.
(6.63) a. [everyj [ CPrel … [ IP Timmy thinksi she found [wh unicorni ]j ]]]
b. [everyj [ CPrel … [ IP Alice thinksk [Timmy is afraidi of [wh monsteri ]j ]]]]
c. [everyj [ CPrel … [ IP Timmy thinksi [his mother is afraidk of [wh monsteri ]j ]]]]
Intensional gap readings (as we might call them) raise a challenge for any account
in which the head NP isn’t represented in the gap position.
One needn’t assume that restrictive relative clauses in all languages are formed
from the same underlying structure (Carlson 1977, Åfarli 1994, Sauerland 1998,
Bhatt 2002, Grosu 2002, Hastings 2004, Gračanin-Yuksek 2008, Kalivoda &
Zyman 2015; contrast Cinque 2013, 2015, Sportiche 2017). The analysis in this
section might be correct for certain types of relative clauses. (Indeed the analyses
of correlative clauses, free relative ‘if’-clauses, and interrogative clauses in §§9–10
will be modeled after the application to free relatives from §6.1.2.) Yet it is worth
investigating how we might develop a compositional semantics applicable to both
95
circumnominal and overtly head-external relativization strategies. The next section
offers an alternative account of headed relative clauses integrated in a more gen-
eral assignment-variable-based syntax/semantics for noun phrases. The proposed
“matching” analysis (Lees 1960, Sauerland 2003) in §8.7 maintains the features
of the head-raising account and treatment of donkey pronouns in this section, while
giving the relative phrase an IPrel -internal representation. The account applies to
head-internal and head-external relative clauses in other languages, and captures
the further linguistic shifting data from intensional gap readings. Before returning to
relative clauses, it will be useful to have on the table a more detailed understanding
of the internal syntax/semantics of noun phrases more generally. The next section
begins by extending the assignment-quantificational approach to determiner quanti-
fiers in headed relative constructions to quantifiers with non-relative complements.
96
7 Quantifiers (I)
The semantics in §6 treats nominal quantifiers in headed relative clauses as rais-
ing from an assignment-argument position internal to the relative clause. The as-
signment binder-index resulting from the type-driven movement of the quantifier
helped capture the link between the relative phrase and gap position in the relative
clause, and certain anaphoric dependencies between the determiner’s restrictor and
scope. This section examines how a generalized assignment-quantificational syn-
tax/semantics for noun phrases can help capture various further phenomena with
complex quantifier phrases and pronoun binding — in particular, phenomena con-
cerning specificity (§7.1), restrictive modification (§7.2), anaphoric noun phrases (§7.3),
and weak crossover (§7.4). §8 further develops the accounts in a more detailed,
general analysis of the syntax and compositional semantics of noun phrases. The
proposed assignment-variable-based account of noun phrases affords a unified syn-
tax/semantics for quantifier words with relativized and non-relativized complements,
with applications to “free R” (modifier) and “inherent R” (argument) readings of
prenominal and postnominal genitives (§§7.2, 8.2, 8.7–8.9); it extends the account
of donkey anaphora to apparent binding out of DPs with inverse linking and genitive
binding, and uses of donkey pronouns in intensional contexts (§§7.4, 8.8); and it
provides formal diagnoses of differences between “weak” vs. “strong” quantifiers,
such as in presuppositionality, modal independence, and compatibility with exis-
tential ‘there’ constructions (§8). An alternative analysis of headed relative clauses,
which addresses the concerns in §6.3, is layered directly into the general syntax and
semantics for noun phrases (§8.7).
I want to flag that certain parts of §§7–8 will be a bit more syntactically oriented
than the other sections. While this may be of general interest, independent of the
assignment-variable-based framework, the syntactic speculations aren’t merely tan-
gential. It is critical for developing our syntax/semantics with assignment variables
that any binder indices and sources of linguistic shifting be derived from inde-
pendently motivated syntactic structures. Otherwise the proposed compositional
derivations will be little more than an ad hoc technical exercise. We will see that a
generalized assignment-quantificational syntax/semantics for quantifier phrases can
be motivated by crosslinguistic data on expressions of quantification, and integrated
in syntactic work on different types of noun phrases.
97
in relative constructions relates the syntax/semantics when combining with non-
relativized complements and simple noun phrases, as in (7.1).
Headed relative constructions aren’t the only case of determiners taking clausal
complements crosslinguistically (cf. Kayne 1994, Uriagereka 1998, Caponigro
2002, de Vries 2002, Koopman 2003, 2005, Larson 2003, Hiraiwa 2005, Law
2011, Hankamer & Mikkelsen 2012, Himmelmann 2016). In some languages
the determiners in headed relative constructions can be used with factive clauses or
root clauses:
(7.3) a. naa bu la
cow cl dem
‘that cow’
b. Amoak nya [[ CP Atim ale sua naa buui] la].
Amoak saw Atim c own cow rel] dem].
‘Amoak saw the cow that Atim owned.’
c. [[ CP Atim ale dɛ mango-kú] la] tɛ Amoak po pienti.
Atim C ate mango-D dem gave Amoak stomach whiten
‘That Atim ate the mango pleased Amoak.’
d. [[ CP Atim nagi Amoak] la].
Atim hit Amoak dem
‘Atim hit Amoak, as I said.’
(Hiraiwa 2005: 31, Hiraiwa et al. 2017: 5–6; Bùlì (Niger-Congo))
98
2012) and Chang (2012) explicitly treat DPs as taking tensed TP complements,
yielding a structure for DPs analogous to that for sentences (see §3.2); the time-
dependence of noun phrases is captured not in D itself but in DP-internal T(ense)
(see also Hiraiwa 2005, Ilkhanipour 2016). As we have seen, the assignment(s)
relevant for interpreting the clause’s main predicate can differ from the assign-
ment(s) for interpreting other predicates as well. Following Kayne 1994, general-
ized D+CP analyses of DPs have been defended by e.g. Campbell (1996), Koopman
(2003, 2005), and Luján (2004) (in non-relative/reduced-relative complements the
CP may be or contain a small clause, lacking Tense). In Campbell’s and Luján’s
accounts, the main operator is even analyzed as moving from within the complement
of the determiner, as in (7.4) (cf. also Alexiadou & Wilder 1998a, Matthewson
1998, Ihsane & Puskás 2001, Giusti 2002, Alexiadou 2003, Laenzlinger 2005,
Larson 2014).
The focus in the above-cited accounts is on matters of syntax rather than compo-
sitional semantics. Though some of the authors gesture at interpretive and discourse
effects of the posited DP-internal movements, semantic entries and derivations aren’t
provided. The generalized assignment-quantificational syntax/semantics for quan-
tificational DPs pursued here can be understood as deriving the relevant move-
ment operations and DP-internal/-external binding relations in a specific compo-
sitional semantics via type-driven movement. The type-⟨aet, ⟨aet, t⟩⟩ implemen-
tation with determiner quantifiers is an instance of the general approach to the
syntax/semantics throughout the paper: Just as modals with clausal complements
are treated as verbal quantifiers raising from the assignment argument of (e.g.) Cd ,
which raises from the world argument of the clause’s main predicate (§§3–4), deter-
miners such as ‘every’ with clausal complements are treated as nominal quantifiers
raising from the assignment argument of (e.g.) Crel , which raises from the individual
gap position (DPs with reduced complements to follow). A generalized assignment-
variable-based syntax/semantics for individual quantification/binding may thus be
understood as contributing to the long tradition of linguistic work on parallels be-
tween nominal and verbal categories, and individual and modal domains (n. 45).
Treating determiner quantifiers as in general taking complements with struc-
ture analogous to that of a restrictive relative clause doesn’t require identifying
the complements as full CPs or representing all cases of restrictive modification as
modification by a (possibly reduced) syntactic relative clause. For instance, in the
99
D+CP structure for (7.1) in (7.5), the constituent [Fcf -g baby] needn’t be identified
as a relative (or [+wh]) phrase (again ignoring worlds).
(7.5) a. [every⟨2,a⟩ [ CP F2cf -g2 baby [ C [ C0⟨i,e⟩ C t2a ] [ IP tie [P1et g1 ]]]]]
b. J(7.1)K ≈ λgg . ∀xe ∀aa ∶ (x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(baby) ∧ g−(1et)(x(g)))
→ x(g) laughed
The complement of the quantifier needn’t even be a CP/SC. Compare (7.6) where
the relevant structure is integrated in an extended nominal projection (cf. Campbell
1996, Siloni 1997, Matthewson 1998, Bhattacharya 1999b, Zamparelli 2000,
Iatridou et al. 2001, Adger 2003, Aboh 2004, Svenonius 2004, Hiraiwa 2005,
Bhatt 2006, Megerdoomian 2008, Donati & Cecchetto 2015):
In the LFs in (7.6) the quantifier raises for type reasons from the main nominal
constituent. The YP specifier of the nominal XP projection in (7.6a) may be under-
stood as a placeholder for other restrictive modifiers in the extended NP layer (more
on which shortly; Cinque 1995, Alexiadou 2001a, Giusti 2002, Lecarme 2004,
Alexiadou et al. 2007). (Hereafter I often refer to analyses such as those in (7.6)
jointly as “D+XP” analyses.)59
In our examples with headed restrictive relative clauses there was an overt basis
for positing the constituent with the choice-function pronoun: the relative phrase.
Positing such a constituent in quantifier phrases with non-relative complements, as
in (7.5)–(7.6), may seem surprising. The remainder of the section examines how
a generalized assignment-quantificational syntax/semantics for determiner quanti-
fiers can help capture further linguistic shifting data. But first it is worth pausing to
consider independent morphosyntactic/semantic evidence for the relevant structure
in quantifier phrases more generally. This subsection focuses primarily on evidence
for a choice-function element in the complement of the quantifier; §7.2 suggests
that data with genitive constructions may favor an implementation for non-rela-
59
For the moment I continue to label quantifiers such as ‘every’ as D; we will examine the nature
of the relevant extended projections of the head noun below and in §§7.2, 8. In both (7.6a)–(7.6b),
since the quantifier raises directly from the nominal constituent, there is no need for an additional
agreement mechanism (§§6.1.3, 10.3). It would be interesting to examine potential parallels of the
alternative D+XP/CP treatments of the syntax/semantics interface in the verbal domain, such as
with modals taking verbal vs. clausal complements.
100
tivized quantifier phrases such as (7.6a), with a reduced XP complement, over a
fully generalized D+CP analysis.
First, generalizing our syntax/semantics along the lines in (7.5)–(7.6) may give
precise expression to common ideas about the “specificity” (Enç 1991) of quantifi-
cational DPs. Here is Enç (emphases mine; Enç’s NP corresponds to our DP).
Lecarme draws on Enç’s notion of specificity in her accounts of nominal tense and the
distribution of nominal tense morphemes in Somali. What marks the distinction be-
tween strong/presuppositional vs. weak/cardinal noun phrases (e.g. ‘every/most N’
vs. ‘many/three N’), according to Lecarme, is the “referentiality” of the D(eterminer)
category (cf. e.g. Chomsky 2007: 25, Hartmann 2008: 111, 131, 139). The inher-
ent “definiteness” of D (Lyons 1999, Déchaine & Wiltschko 2002, Paul et al.
2015) is treated by Déchaine & Wiltschko as capturing differences in binding possi-
bilities among pronouns (emphases mine):
101
“[I]ndexicality is a necessary feature of… D-pronouns, and has a par-
ticular structural locus, namely the D-position.”
“D, the locus of indexicality, is responsible for assigning reference.”
“Consequently, fake indexicals are analyzed as instantiating φ rather
than D.” (Déchaine & Wiltschko 2015: 24; 2017b: 68, 80n.10)
“This view [locates] DP’s specific/anaphoric reference and discourse
function directly in its head Determiner… Accordingly, determiners
may be described as discourse-linking functions.” (Luján 2004: 130)
It isn’t always manifest to what extent authors take the above notions (index-
icality, presuppositionality, specificity, familiarity, definiteness, deixis, D-linking,
strength) to be relevantly related (cf. Matthewson 1998, Cardinaletti & Starke
1999). Plainly understood, the appeal to notions such as referentiality or defi-
niteness can seem puzzling. One wouldn’t typically expect to find quantificational
determiners in a list of indexicals. On the face of it, quantifiers can also be bound,
as in (7.8). The weak/cardinal noun phrases in (7.9) would seem to be interpreted
with respect to “relevant sets of individuals” as much as ‘every man’ in Enç’s (7.7).
(7.9a) can be true even if Alice is satisfied with general cookie production; pointing
out in (7.9b) that lots of rival players were congratulating one another in other
games likely won’t earn one points with the tournament referee.
(7.8) In every music school, most guitar students wanted to play like the head
instructor. (cf. Heim 1991, von Fintel 1998b)
(7.9) a. Alice gave Timmy a brownie because she doubted there were many cookies.
b. I regret to inform you that your teams didn’t meet the required standards
for sportsmanship: The referee didn’t observe three players congratulate
three players, and so you won’t be advancing to the next round.
102
or indexicality.60 Indeed Giusti (1992, 1997, 2002) has argued that the “definite”
article — “probably… the only category which occupies the head D position, un-
controversially and crosslinguistically” (Progovac 1998: 165–166) — is generally
used for grammatical reasons and needn’t have any semantic contribution, such as
specificity, referentiality, or notional definiteness (also e.g. Danon 2001, Hallman
2016; we will return to these issues below and throughout §8).
The syntax/semantics in this section affords a locus for the putative specificity,
in Enç’s (1991) sense, of “true” (Lecarme 2008: 204) quantificational DPs. DPs
such as ‘every baby’ in (7.5)–(7.6) “presuppose existence” (Enç 1991: 11) insofar
as the choice-function pronoun sister to the main NP is undefined for empty sets of
individuals. A lexical entry for C/Crel such as in (7.11a) would make the connections
with presuppositionality even more explicit (more on which in §10); if there are
no babies, the semantic value of the quantifier’s restrictor argument in (7.12) is
undefined for any value for y. An analogous preliminary entry for the X head is in
(7.11b), as compared to (7.10) (more on which shortly).
103
ficity determiner or determiner-like functional head as having an additional internal
argument (e.g. situation) which figures in determining the relevant domain, as in
(7.13), has precedents in various syntactic theories (cf. von Fintel 1994, Büring
2004, Elbourne 2005, 2013, Schwarz 2009, Patel-Grosz & Grosz 2017). As
noted above, some accounts even treat the main operator as moving to its inter-
preted position from inside the complement of D (see (7.4), also §§3.2, 6.1).
The choice-function pronoun posited in the extended NP layer in [Fcf -g NP] — and
the movement of the determiner/quantifier from the internal (assignment) argu-
ment of Fcf in (7.6) — may be understood in parallel to such moves.
Although some accounts which posit an additional DP-internal element iden-
tify it as a (weak) definite article or a deictic demonstrative,61 such identifications
should be regarded with caution. Our identifying the choice-function pronoun in
quantificational DPs with (say) a definite determiner would be no more warranted
for the general case than our identifying it with an implicit relative/wh word on the
basis of our examples with headed relative clauses.
The choice-function-based analyses developed here, and in greater detail in §8,
may provide a common basis for certain notions of “specificity” from the literature
with quantificational and non-quantificational DPs. Adopting the choice-function-
based analysis of names from §4.4, and extending the §6.2-analysis of donkey pro-
nouns, may help capture connections with treatments of definiteness/D-linking with
names and certain types of pronouns (cf. Sharvit 1999, Boeckx & Grohmann
2004, Lecarme 2008, Patel-Grosz & Grosz 2017). Alternative structural features
or additional constraints may be associated with different types of expressions —
e.g., a feature or implicit functional head restricting to choice functions defined only
for sets of individuals in the world of the discourse, or choice functions whose do-
main/range is restricted to individuals included in a particular discourse-determined
domain. Such lexical or construction-specific differences may yield a more refined
typology of the various effects.
To take one example, whereas the existence presupposition is captured in the
interaction between the choice-function pronoun and nominal head, the connection
to a contextually relevant set of individuals may be captured as a species of implicit
domain restriction (n. 26). The (possibly skolemized) domain variable in (7.5),
61
E.g.: “Since both types of pronouns denote individuals, the most plausible assumption is that
both contain a definite determiner” (Patel-Grosz & Grosz 2017: 272). See below.
104
reproduced in (7.14), functions analogously to the restriction in a headed relative,
and restricts the quantification to a topical subdomain of babies. The lexical entry
for X from (7.10) derives the equivalent interpretation.62
(7.15) [Context (cf. (1.14)): Alice thinks there are magical trolls. She thinks that
some groups of them aren’t legally permitted to vote (e.g., baby trolls), but
that no group with a moral right to vote is legally excluded from voting.]
a. Alice thinks every troll can vote.
b. ≈ Alice thinks there are trolls and that every troll in the groups she
considers relevant in matters of voting rights is legally permitted to vote
(local D-linking)
(A more precise analysis of the internal syntax and compositional semantics will
be given in §8. I return to weak quantifiers and differences among (expressions
represented here with) choice-function pronouns below and in §§8, 10.3.)
The previous discussion examined how positing our choice-function-based con-
stituent in quantificational DPs can be motivated by independent work on notions
of specificity (broadly construed). There is also direct morphological and mor-
phosyntactic evidence for the extra structure. It is crosslinguistically common for
quantifier words to be diachronically related to or composed from a relative/wh
form or determiner/demonstrative — e.g., German jeder ‘every’ as je ‘ever’ + der
‘that’/‘the’/‘which’, Romanian fiecare ‘every’ as fie ‘be’ + care ‘which’. As noted
above, choice-function pronouns will be exploited in our analyses of relative/wh
words and certain demonstrative proforms; synchronic and diachronic connections
between definite articles and demonstratives, and among demonstrative, relative,
62
We will return to overt modifiers in §7.2. For purposes of the semantics we can leave open
the specific position in the XP area of the implicit domain pronoun in structures such as (7.14b)
(e.g., Spec,X or adjoined to X or XP).
105
and interrogative forms, are crosslinguistically robust (Haspelmath 1995, Diessel
1999, Lyons 1999, Heine & Kuteva 2002, de Vries 2002, Bhat 2004, Thurgood
& LaPolla 2017; n. 52). In many languages quantified expressions are overtly
realized via a quantifier word and a distinct determiner phrase (Löbel 1989, Giusti
1991, 1992, 1997, Santelmann 1993, Dimitrova-Vulchanova & Giusti 1996,
Lecarme 1996, 2004, Matthewson 1998, 2008, 2013, Zamparelli 2000, Hiraiwa
2005, Julien 2005, Hanitramalala & Ileana 2012, Keenan & Paperno 2012,
Cardinaletti & Giusti 2017). The additional determiner is obligatory in (7.16)–
(7.20).63
106
‘All (the) students succeeded.’ (Lecarme 1999b: ex. 35b; Somali)
107
alized in different ways in different constructions, both across languages and within
a particular language. For instance, in the headed relative clauses in §§6.1–6.2 the
choice-function pronoun is realized via a [wh] relative word; in English quantifier
phrases such as ‘every baby’ it is implicit; in St’át’imcets quantifier phrases it is real-
ized via an overt determiner; in Somali quantifier phrases it is realized via a syntacti-
cally marked definite (see also §10.3). Even in the case of Somali, syntactic Definite
features needn’t correlate with semantic/pragmatic definiteness, as Lecarme (1996,
1999b) is careful to point out (see also Giusti 1997, 2002, Bhattacharya 1999a,b,
Danon 2001, Schwarz 2009). Similarly, though Etxeberria & Giannakidou
(2010) treat St’át’imcets determiners as definite, Matthewson (1999, 2013) ar-
gues that they can fail to exhibit notional definiteness phenomena (uniqueness,
maximality, familiarity); likewise for the relevant determiners in Skwuwú7mesh
(Squamish) Salish quantified expressions, which Gillon (2013) argues are un-
marked for definiteness/indefiniteness. As we have seen, expressions represented
with choice-function pronouns needn’t be syntactically/semantically definite or even
have intuitively specific readings (§§6.1.3, 6.2.2; cf. §8.8.3).
Likewise, for simplicity I have assumed that quantifier words (in languages
such as English) project a determiner phrase; yet the approach is compatible with
treating them as occupying a distinct Quantifier category — say, analogous to how
a modal might be treated as heading ModP. For instance, first, Chomsky 2007 and
Bruening 2009 give syntactic arguments for reviving the idea that the head of the
noun phrase is a nominal, rather than a functional determiner per the DP hypothesis
(see also Satık 2017). Though specific positive proposals aren’t given, Chomsky and
Bruening briefly consider integrating the relevant functional elements in (“little”) nP
shells; in Chomsky’s version, definite/specific nominals are treated as n∗Ps with a
DP complement, roughly as in (7.23) (cf. Bruening 2009: 33). The present account
may afford a natural way of developing such an approach. Our X is essentially a
light nominal n∗, parallel to v∗ in a verb phrase (cf. Kratzer 1996, Bhattacharya
1999b, Rackowski 2002, Adger 2003, Alexiadou 2003, Lecarme 2004, 2008,
Alexiadou et al. 2006, Pylkkänen 2008, Harley 2009, 2013, Megerdoomian
2009, D'Alessandro et al. 2017, Wood & Marantz 2017; more on this below).
In quantificational expressions (broadly construed), the choice-function pronoun
would be treated as occupying the lower D; the quantificational element raises to
Spec,n∗ ((7.24a)), or heads its own projection QP with an n∗P complement ((7.24b)).
The quantifier ‘every’ in (7.24b) raises from the internal assignment-argument po-
sition of D, parallel to how modal elements raise from the internal assignment-
argument position of C. Treating the quantifier as having an internal (implicit, pos-
sibly skolemized) domain restriction argument (=P in (7.24)) would bring the par-
108
allels with modals even closer, as in the adapted version of the LF from (7.6a)
in (7.24b).
Implementing the syntax in this way may thus provide a compositional semantic
framework for an nP analysis of noun phrases and a broader account of structural
parallels in nominal and verbal domains. Indeed the aim of §8 will be to further
develop our syntax/semantics in precisely this way.
Alternatively, the argument of the quantifier might be analyzed as a syntactic
DP, as in the adapted version of the LF from (7.6b) in (7.25) (cf. n. 75; see Löbel
1989, Giusti 1991, 1997, Giusti & Leko 1995, Matthewson 1998, 2001, 2013,
Zamparelli 2000, Alexiadou et al. 2007, Cardinaletti & Giusti 2017).
109
The project of generalizing our assignment-quantificational account of quantifier
phrases with choice functions from §§6.1–6.2 can be motivated independently of a
specific Q DP syntax (more on the nominal XP projection in §7.2).
To recap: This section has examine independent precedents in syntax for the
elements in the proposed generalized assignment-quantificational account of quan-
tifier phrases — notably, (i) the additional internal structure in the complement of
the quantifier, (ii) a specificity-like element F in the extended functional projection
of the NP; (iii) an internal argument of the F head, which figures in determining
the relevant domain; and (iv) movement of the main operator from within the
complement. Although accounts differ in their particular implementations and theo-
retical interpretations of the different elements, the convergence with such different
empirical phenomena in view is striking. Such precedents further motivate the gen-
eralized treatment of quantifier phrases pursued here. On the flip side, the present
assignment-variable-based implementation may provide new applications and lines
of inquiry on the internal structure of nominals/quantifiers and interactions among
the syntax, semantics, and theories of discourse.
110
rule such as Predicate Modification isn’t required (Partee 1995a, Heim & Kratzer
1998).65
111
a. [every⟨2,a⟩ [ CP F2cf -g2 baby … [ IP tie girl]]]]
b. [every⟨2,a⟩ [ XP girl [X [F2cf -t2a baby]]]]
c. JCPK = JXPK = λye .λgg . y(g) = g(2a)(2cf)(baby) ∧ y(g) is a girl
d. ≈ λgg . ∀xe ∀aa ∶ (x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(baby) ∧ x(g) is a girl) → x(g) laughed
The approaches to restrictive modification in (7.14) afford a structural basis for the
contrast in readings — namely, in whether the possessor+relation is represented in
the head NP, with the relevant relation supplied by the overt noun, as in inherent R
readings; or in a position for restrictive modifiers, with the relevant relation supplied
by an implicit pronoun, as in free R readings. In various language families the pres-
ence of the further relation in free R readings is overtly marked, as in (7.29)–(7.30).
In the free R readings in (7.30c)/(7.30d) the additional possessive affix appears
on the possessor noun, in addition to the usual genitive suffix on the head noun
(cf. (7.30a)/(7.30b)). In some cases the additional element used in free R readings
66
I will use ‘genitive (DP)’ for the complex phrase X’s Y. I use ‘possessor’ for X, though the
relevant relation needn’t be possession narrowly construed (more on which shortly). I sometimes use
‘structural possessor/possessee’ or scare quotes to highlight this point. I use ‘genitive morpheme’ for
functional heads such as ’s heading the genitive construction; this usage is neutral on the morpheme’s
specific category (more on which presently).
112
is historically derived from a relational noun (e.g., ‘hand’, ‘home’) or preposition
(cf. (7.30e)), or an element expressing other thematic relations.67
(7.29) a. qatu-ku
head-1sg.gen
‘my head’
67
See e.g. Dixon 1980: ch. 10, 2010: ch. 16, Lichtenberk 1985, 2002, Chappell & McGregor
1989, Heine et al. 1991: §6.1, Koptjevskaja-Tamm 1996, 2001, Heine 1997: chs. 2–3, Song 1997,
Aikhenvald 2000, 2013, Heine & Kuteva 2002: 55, 104, 167, 175, 245–246, 296–297, Sato 2009,
Frajzyngier 2013, Sabbagh 2016, van Rijn 2017. For instance, in (i) the first occurrence of la- is
used to express a general possession relation, the second occurrence to express a benefactive relation;
the free R marker a in (ii-b) introduces the agentive subject (more on this in §8.9). In languages with
multiple free R markers, different markers may be subspecialized for different sorts of relations, as
with the spectrum of possessive relation markers in Oceanic languages, e.g. in (iii). (Such elements
aren’t ordinary noun classifiers which specify the kind or other properties of the possessor/possessee
(see Lichtenberk 1983, 1985, 2009a,b, Aikhenvald 2000: chs. 3, 5). Their “crucial property” is
rather that “their use is determined … by the nature of the real-world relation between the possessed
and the possessor”; they “specif[y] more closely the type of the relation [between the possessed and
the possessor],” e.g. that the former “is food for” the latter, as in (iii-c), even (iii-d) (Lichtenberk
1983: 148, 157, 161, 2009a: 268, 286).)
(i) Sohn el mole-lah [ik la-l Sepe ah] [la-l Sru].
John 3sg.sbj buy-asp fish possfr -3sg.poss Sepe det possfr -3sg.poss Sru
‘John has bought Sepe’s fish for Sru.’ (Song 1997: 33; Kusaiean (Austronesian))
(ii) a. nga kur� [a Mere]
art dog possfr Mere
‘Mere’s dogs’
b. ka whakamau [a Mere] i te taura.
t/a fasten possfr Mere acc art rope
‘Mere is fastening the rope’
(Harlow 2007: 166, Chung 1973: 652, Maori (Austronesian))
(iii) a. sina-gu
mother-my
‘my mother’
b. e-gu udo
possfr -my taro
‘my taro’
c. a-gu udo
possfr.edib -my taro
‘my taro (to eat)’
d. [Context: a man who contracts to eat parts of a motor-car in a sideshow says:]
a-gu motoka
possfr.edib -my car
‘my car (to eat)’ (Lynch 1973: 71, 87, 99n.18; Suau (Austronesian))
113
b. no-ku qatu
possfr -1sg.gen head
‘my head (e.g. pig’s head)’
(Hyslop 2001: 170, 183; Lolovoli (Austronesian))
(7.30) a. (ŋaḷi-na) ŋaḷa-jaya-ŋga
f.nom-dis f.nom-daughter-2sg.gen
‘(she’s) your daughter’
b. ḷandi jurgjurg-ṇawu
tree leaf-3sg.m.gen
‘leaves of a tree’
c. ṇu-ṇyaŋ-gu ṇa-muyg-ṇuṇya (ŋan-ḍaḷag)
possfr +2pl m.nom-dog-2pl.gen 3sg/1sg-bite.pastpunc
‘your dog (bit me)’
d. ṇa-bugbuŋ-gu baṇam-ṇawu
m.possfr -old.man camp-3sg.m.gen
‘the old man’s camp’
e. ṇa-bugbuŋ-gu baṇam-gaḷama ga-ŋa-yag
m.dat-old.man camp-all pres.realis-1sg-go
‘I am going to the camp for the old man.’
(Merlan 1982: 5, 66-67, 74, 102, 105; Mangarayi, Australia)
Suppose first that we treat the genitive morpheme ’s as the head determiner
and as having the same assignment-quantificational semantics as ‘the’, taking a CP
complement (we will reconsider these assumptions shortly). Preliminary LFs are
in (7.32)–(7.33). (For the moment I will ignore intensionality (an internal world-
argument) with the relation pronoun in free R readings (see §8.9); I use ‘Ri ’/‘R’ in
pronouns/indices for type ⟨e, et⟩.)68
These patterns, in which the forms used in free R readings are at least as morphologically com-
plex/marked as the corresponding forms used in inherent R readings, are crosslinguistically robust.
For studies on particular languages or language families, see e.g. Mosel 1984: §2.4, Lichtenberk
1985, 2009a, Claudi & Heine 1989, Koptjevskaja-Tamm 1996, Song 1997, Stolz et al. 2008,
Aikhenvald 2012: §5.3, Helmbrecht 2016: §4; for general inventories see also Seiler 1983a,
Haiman 1985: 130–136, Nichols 1988: 564–566, 579, 1992: 117–118, Chappell & McGregor
1989, 1996b, Heine 1997: chs. 2–3, Koptjevskaja-Tamm 2001, Dixon 2010: 286–290, 308–309,
Aikhenvald 2013, Haspelmath 2017, van Rijn 2017. (Of course not all markers of free R readings
need be realizations of the relation pronoun. In some cases the additional morphological content
may simply be a genitive morpheme, which is unpronounced in inherent R constructions.)
68
As expected, free R possessives with saturated relational nouns are also attested, as in (i)
(cf. Lichtenberk 2009b: 396–397):
114
(7.31) JtheK = λP+⟨a,et⟩ .λQ+⟨a,et⟩ .λgg . ∃xe ∃aa ∶ P+(a)(x)(g) ∧ ∀ye ∶ (P+(a)(y)(g) → y(g) = x(g))
∧ Q+(a)(x)(g)
= λP+⟨a,et⟩ .λQ+⟨a,et⟩ .λgg . ∃xe ∃aa ∶ (x(g) = the o such that (↓ P+)(a(g))(o))
∧ Q+(a)(x)(g)
≈ λP+⟨a,et⟩ .λQ+⟨a,et⟩ .λgg . [ιx(g)∃a∶ P+(a)(x)(g)] Q+(a)(x)(g)
(to be revised)
(7.32) D+CP “free R” (modifier) genitive LF
a. Bert’s TV is broken.
b. [ DP⟨2,a⟩ ’s⟨2,a⟩ [ CP F2cf -g2 TV [[ C⟨1,e⟩ C t2a ] t1e R1 -g1 Bert]]]
c. ≈ λgg . [ιx(g)∃aa ∶ x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(TV) ∧ g−(1R)(Bert)(x(g))] x(g) is broken
d. ≈ “the unique o such that there is a choice function that selects o from
among the TVs, and o bears the relevant relation R (=gc (1R)) to Bert,
is broken”
(7.33) D+CP “inherent R” (argument) genitive LF
a. Bert’s hand is broken.
b. [ DP⟨2,a⟩ ’s⟨2,a⟩ [ CP F2cf -g2 [hand Bert] [[ C⟨1,e⟩ C t2a ] t1e P1et -g1 ]]]
c. ≈ λgg . [ιxe (g)∃aa ∶ x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(hand-of-Bert) ∧ g−(1et)(x(g))]
x(g) is broken
d. ≈ “the unique o such that there is a choice function that selects o from
115
among the hands of Bert, and o is in the relevant set of entities (=gc (1et)),
is broken”
The domain pronoun [P1et g1 ] in (7.33) captures how the inherent R reading can
be felicitous even if Bert has more than one hand (cf. Jespersen 1924: 110–111).
Assuming that the supplied value for the pronoun restricts the domain to a set that
includes only one of Bert’s hands, the uniqueness condition is satisfied. Likewise
for the felicitous use of ‘Alice’s brother’ in (7.34), even if Alice has older brothers;
and for the free and inherent R readings of ‘Bert’s hand’ in (7.35), even if Bert is
ambidextrous and he and the other medical students have been keeping individual
inventories of their cadavers:
(7.34) [Context: Alice has two older brothers away at college, and one younger
brother. She wants to go to the movies with her friends, but since her
parents are away, she has to take her younger brother with them. Later
one of their other friends who couldn’t make it to the movie asks how it
was. You say:]
Be glad you didn’t come. Alice’s brother was pestering us the whole time.
(7.35) [Context: We’re medical students practicing on cadavers.]
a. Free R: Bert’s hand is broken. It’s obvious, but I bet he’ll miss it and get
the diagnosis wrong.
b. Inherent R: Bert’s hand is broken. There’s no way he’s going to be able
to pass the practice exam with his cast on.
The relevant value for the relation pronoun in (7.35a) associates Bert with the
cadaver hand he is currently practicing on.69
The analyses in (7.32)–(7.33) maintain a uniform overall syntax for the genitive
69
Additional contextual domain restrictions with free R readings might also be represented via
an additional domain-pronoun modifier in the edge of the XP, as discussed in n. 65. I will ignore
any such additional structure in what follows. Iterated possessor modifiers are also possible, as in
stacked free R genitives such as (i)–(ii).
(i) il-kotba [ta’ Pietru] [ta’ l-awtur favorit [tieghi]]
def-books possfr Peter possfr def-author favorite my
‘Peter’s books by my favorite author’ (Koptjevskaja-Tamm 1996: 266; Maltese)
(ii) [le-ghu] [ghaja ai-a] kaipu
possfr -1sg.gen pig 3sg.gen-possfr.pass punch
‘my punch to a pig (my hitting a pig)’ (lit. ‘my a-pig’s punch’)
(cf. Sato 2009: ex. 30, Lichtenberk 2009b: 397; Kove (Austronesian))
116
construction, and a uniform semantics for the genitive morpheme ’s. The intu-
itive contrast between free vs. inherent R readings of prenominal genitives needn’t
require positing a lexical ambiguity in the genitive morpheme, type-shifting, or
coercion (as in e.g. Partee 1983, Jensen & Vikner 1994, Vikner & Jensen 2002,
Partee & Borschev 2003; cf. n. 68). The distinction between “possessors” as
arguments vs. restrictive modifiers can be captured in terms of general features of
the proposed structure for DPs.
The D+CP implementation in (7.32)–(7.33) captures the specificity of prenom-
inal genitives in the semantics of the genitive morpheme, treated as the head deter-
miner. Such an analysis is awkward for predicative uses and uses where the genitive
is the argument of a determiner, such as with the postnominal genitives in (7.36).
In some languages an overt determiner can co-occur with prenominal genitives as
well ((7.37)–(7.38)).
117
with -ŋu or (7.40) with ge;70 the revised entry for ’s in (7.41) directly implements
such a function (cf. n. 65). (I use ‘ιo ’ for the implicit determiner in English prenom-
inal genitives, where Jιo K = JtheK from (7.31); for now I continue to ignore inten-
sionality.)
118
The derived semantic values in (7.42c)/(7.43c) for the prenominal genitives are
equivalent to those in (7.32)/(7.33). No additional resources are required in the
compositional semantics of postnominal genitives.71
Like many other pronouns, the implicit relation pronoun R in free R readings
may receive local (shifted) readings. Suppose Bert and Ernie are former roommates,
and there is a dispute about who is to be responsible for which of their two pet
ducks, Ducky and Fluffy. Bert was the original owner of Fluffy, and Ernie was the
original owner of Ducky; but Bert’s lifestyle is more conducive to Ducky’s general
welfare, and Ernie’s lifestyle is more conducive to Fluffy’s general welfare (perhaps
Ducky dislikes the water). Suppose we all agree that the rightful owner is the one
who would be in the best interest of the pet (Bert and Ernie aren’t party to our
conversation). Talking about Chip, we can felicitously say (7.44) with a global
reading of R in ‘Ernie’s duck’, even if we know Chip isn’t acquainted with Ernie
and may have no idea about Ducky’s relation to Ernie. The value for the relation
pronoun determined by the discourse assignment maps ⟨Ernie, Fluffy⟩ to True, and
⟨Ernie, y⟩, for all other ducks y, to False.
119
Alternatively, suppose we are talking about Bert and how wants to keep Fluffy for
himself. We might say (7.45a) or (7.45b), even if Bert’s belief is about a particular
individual and his desire isn’t for the Indiscernibility of Identicals to be false. If Bert
has been confused in his biology, incorrectly thinking Fluffy to be (say) a loon, the
world-pronoun associated with ‘duck’ in the genitive DP may receive a global reading
though R receives a local reading under the attitude verb, reflected in (7.45c) Sup-
pose Ernie is more altruistic, preferring to yield Ducky to Bert, yet mistaking Ducky
(though not Fluffy) for a loon. We might characterize the unfortunate state of affairs
with the quantified attitude ascription in (7.46). The relevant bound reading can
be derived analogously to the quantified modal attitude ascription from §4.3:
120
(7.46) Everyone thinksk Bert’sk duck@ is a loonk .
S
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩ S
Cd t1a
VP
every⟨2,a⟩ XP
⟨3,a⟩ CP
DPgen VP
⟨4,a⟩
ιo is a loon t2s
R1 -g3 Bert ’s
F2cf t4a
duck w1 -g1
This says, roughly, that for every relevant o — every o ∈ gc (1et) selectable among the
persons — for every possibility h compatible with o’s state of mind, the o′ such that o′
bears h(1R) to Bert and o′ is identical to some actual duck or other (=a(g)(2cf)(duckgc (1s) )),
is a loon in @(h). The domain pronoun [P1et g1 ] restricts the quantification to the
contextually relevant individuals, say gc (1et) = {Bert, Ernie}. In the embedded
genitive DP ‘Bert’s duck’ under the attitude verb, the relation-pronoun [R1 g3 ] re-
121
ceives a local reading. Roughly put, the shifted value for the pronoun, h(1R), is
the relation relating (e.g.) Bert to individuals which the quantificational subject
regards as properly being in Bert’s charge (pedantically, the subject’s epistemic
counterpart of the function that would be determined by the discourse assignment
gc (1R) (§§3.4, 4.3.3, 4.4)). For every possibility h′ compatible with Bert’s state of
mind, Fluffy ∈ h′ (1R)(Bert); and for every possibility h′′ compatible with Ernie’s
state of mind, Ducky ∈ h′′ (1R)(Bert). By contrast, the world-pronoun [w1 g1 ] re-
ceives a global reading, requiring that the relevant selected individual is a duck
in the world of the discourse. The truth of (7.46) requires that Fluffy and Ducky
are each potentially selectable from among the actual ducks, and that Bert thinks
Fluffy is a loon and Ernie thinks Ducky is a loon. Hence the quantified attitude
ascription on the relevant reading — with a shifted reading of the relation-pronoun
and unshifted reading of the world-pronoun in the genitive DP embedded under the
attitude verb — is correctly derived to be true.
As the reader may have noticed, the semantics for the genitive morpheme in
(7.41) is equivalent to the semantics for X in (7.10). An attractive hypothesis is that
the posited nominal XP projection just is the projection headed by the genitive mor-
pheme in genitive constructions. Above we noted various diachronic and synchronic
connections between quantificational DPs and specificity. The crosslinguistic con-
nections with genitives may provide additional support for the D+XP analysis. As
discussed in §7.1, in various languages individual quantification is expressed via a
structural genitive (e.g. (7.19)–(7.20)). Our X head arguably corresponds to the
head posited for assigning genitive Case to quantifier complements in certain Slavic
languages, as in (7.47) for Serbian (cf. e.g. Franks & Pereltsvaig 2004, Bošković
2006, Hartmann & Milićević 2008).
In light of her extensive work on nominal tense in genitives, Lecarme even concludes
that “genitive constructions universally involve a form of quantification” (2004: 17;
122
cf. Postma 1997, Borschev et al. 2008, Hartmann & Milićević 2009, Peters &
Westerståhl 2013).72
72
Lecarme notes that in genitives with quantifiers and kinship and body-part nouns, tense
morphemes cannot appear on the head nominal, as occurs in other genitives. Analogous patterns
are observed in certain other languages with nominal tense, as reflected in (i)–(ii).
(i) a. [ardáy-dii kúlli-g-ood] wáy gudbeen.
students-det+past whole-det+poss.3pl decl.3pl succeeded
‘All (the) students succeeded.’
b. ardáy-da macállin-k-ood-ii wúu baxay.
students-det teacher-det-poss.3p-past decl.3ms left
‘The students’ teacher left.’ (Lecarme 1999b: exs. 35b, 28b; Somali)
(ii) a. [’moj-et bu’bajko] ’beše mih’tar
my-def.past father was mihtar
‘My father was mihtar (in charge of the community’s relations with outsiders).’
b. la’ni [de’ti-te mi] ’beha ja’vaʃ
last.year children-def.past 1sg.dat were.3pl quiet
‘Last year, my students were easy going.’ (Adamou 2011: exs. 14c, 8a; Pomak (Slavic))
For genitives such as in (i-b) with non-relational nouns, Lecarme posits an independent “syntactic
rule that serves to delete the [+past] tense morpheme on a locally dependent DP” (1999b: 12). For
quantified phrases and kinship/body-part nouns Lecarme suggests distinct semantic explanations:
“Universal quantifiers in natural language quantify over contextually given sets of individuals… [T]he
genitive complement refers to the ‘familiar’ set… Such examples, then, provide further evidence
that nominal tense is linked to the notion of specificity (1999b: 15–16). Kinship/body-part nouns
“are not compatible with tense features, even in the syntactic contexts where they are normally
required,” on the ground that they “lack autonomous reference” and express essentially “atemporal
relations” (1996: 9; also 1999b, 2004). One might wonder why relations such as being a part of,
being a sister of, being a hand of, etc. would necessarily be conceptualized as failing to hold at a
time (cf. von Prince 2016: 83). Independent worries aside, such informal semantic explanations
are surprising given Lecarme’s emphasis on the “purely structural meaning” (2004: 15) of genitive
case. The contrasting analyses for free/inherent R genitives in the main text may afford a “purely
structural” (Lecarme 2004) basis for the relevant distribution of tense morphemes without requiring
questionable semantic or metaphysical assumptions about the (a)temporality of certain relations or
fundamental appeals to notions of “alienable” vs. “inalienable” possession (cf. Seiler 1983a, Nichols
1988, 1992: §4.1, Chappell & McGregor 1996b, Heine 1997: §3.4, Koptjevskaja-Tamm 2001:
§§3–4, van Rijn 2017). Data such as (iii) in Pomak, corresponding to (7.35), provides preliminary
evidence that the distribution of tense features correlates with the distinction between free R and
inherent R readings. The body-part noun in the free R reading in (iii-a) bears interpretable tense
features. (Thanks to Evangelia Adamou.)
(iii) [Context: we’re medical students practicing on cadavers (=(7.35))]
a. ören’ciete ra’kota
student-def.past hand-def.past
‘the student’s hand (was broken)’ (free R reading, ≈ (7.35a): tense on head noun)
b. ören’civata ’roka
student-def.past hand
123
The genitive morpheme ’s, on this line, is an overt (semantically equivalent,
+EPP) analogue of the implicit X in (7.6a)/(7.14b)/(7.26b), licensing (indeed mor-
phosyntactically requiring) the overt specifier characteristic to genitives. The nom-
inal X category in the DP might be understood as analogous to (say) v∗ in a clause.
As Partee & Borschev put it in the case of genitives, “an argument genitive is
most like a direct object, an ‘internal argument’… A ‘possessor’ genitive, on the
other hand, is most subject-like, agent-like, less like an internal argument, more
independent” (2003: 100; cf. Seiler 1983b, Haiman 1985: 130–136, Nichols
1988, 1992: 116–122, Heine 1997: §3.4, Alexiadou 2003, Myler 2016: §2.1.2,
van Rijn 2017: 99, 163). In various language families, this distinction is reflected
in the morphology. Structural possessors in inherent R readings are typically in-
troduced like nominal complements generally, as in (7.48) (unmarked) or (7.50)
(following the transitivizing suffix). The possessors of free-R-marked possessives
such as in (7.49)/(7.51), in contrast, are “constructed in exactly the same way
as” “the agent of nominalised active verbs” (Mosel 1984: 35–36). The contrasting
readings of ‘my story’ in (7.50a)–(7.51a) are reflected in constructions introducing
the possessor on the model of an object (cf. (7.50b)) vs. an agentive subject of the
deverbal (cf. (7.51b)). In (7.52), only in the free R reading can the possessor
be introduced with the transitive-subject marker ((7.52b) vs. (7.52c)) (see also
Chung 1973, Seiler 1983a,b, Lichtenberk 1985, 2009a,b, Chappell & McGre-
‘the student’s hand (was broken)’ (inherent R reading, ≈ (7.35b): tense on possessor)
(Evangelia Adamou, p.c.; Pomak (Slavic))
It is worth exploring whether the alternative structures in (e.g.) (7.42)–(7.43) might provide insight
into the distribution of tense morphemes in different nominal tense languages. (For instance, very
roughly, for purposes of illustration: Following Lecarme (2004, 2008), suppose that in Somali N
undergoes syntactic N-to-D movement, which yields the overt N-D order; and that uninterpretable
tense on D is valued under a local relation with interpretable tense features on T (the D-T connection),
say via Agree (Chomsky 2000, 2001). In inherent R readings such as (i-a) the possessor DP (‘the
students) originates as an argument of the relational noun, and raises successive cyclically from
Spec,N to its pronounced position in Spec,D — i.e., yielding [DP DPposs [D [D0 N0 +D0 ] …]]. Given
that interpretable tense may only be realized once per DP in Somali, the tense feature in T is deleted
via Feature Deletion (von Stechow 2003) by the c-commanding tensed possessor DP. In free R
readings such as (i-b), by contrast, the possessor DP originates inside a ZP modifier, which raises from
Spec,X to Spec,D — i.e., yielding [DP [ZP DPposs Z0 ] [D [D0 N0 +D0 ] …]]. At no point in the derivation
is the tensed possessor DP in a position to mark the main tense feature in T for deletion. The D-
proposs -T order in prenominal genitives such as (i-b) can be captured via postsyntactic Lowering
(in the sense of Embick & Noyer 2001) of T0 — i.e., whereby T0 right-adjoins to the X0 head of
its XP complement, which hosts the clitic possessive pronoun. The proposs +T complex cliticizes to
D, yielding the observed Poss N-D-proposs -T order, with tense morphology on the complex with the
nominal head (‘teacher’).)
124
gor 1989, Koptjevskaja-Tamm 1996, Palmer 2008, Sato 2009, Dixon 2010:
ch. 16, Aikhenvald 2013, von Prince 2016, Haspelmath 2017, van Rijn 2017;
cf. n. 67).
(7.48) a. tura-na
brother-3sg
‘his brother’
b. a nilul upi ra nian
art asking for art food
‘the asking for food’
c. ta-na
to-3sg
‘to him’
(7.49) a. ka-na pal
poss-3sg house
‘his house’
b. a vinavana ka-i ra tutana
art going possfr -mrk art man
‘the going of the man’
(Mosel 1984: 29–32, 36, 39; Tolai (Austronesian))
(7.50) a. nounage ín Titoga
story trans Titoga
‘Titoga’s story (i.e. the story about Titoga)’
b. i-ak-am-ɨgn-ín uus aan
1excl-concurr-cont-afraid-trans man that
‘I am afraid of that man.’
(7.51) a. nounage taha Titoga
story possfr Titoga
‘Titoga’s story (i.e. the one he told)’
b. n-arɨk-aan taha-mar le nauanu uk
nomz-stay-nomz possfr -1excl.pl loc village this
‘our staying in this village’
(Lynch 1978: 31, 86, 111; Lenakel (Austronesian))
(7.52) a. Deveni na Vagi e-ia.
Deveni trans.sbj Vagi 3sg.sbj.nonfut-see
‘Deveni saw Vagi.’
b. thau na vanua
I trans.sbj village
125
‘my village’
c. *thau na ama(-ku)
I trans.sbj father-my
d. (thau) ama-ku
I father-my
‘my father’ (Lynch 1973: 71, 74, 86; Aroma (Austronesian))
The LFs in (7.42)–(7.43) reflect these ideas. In inherent R readings the structural
“possessor” originates as the object argument of the (possibly coerced) relational
noun; in free R readings the possessor originates in Spec,X and is related to the
selected individual by the possession-like relation supplied by the relation pronoun.
As in the verbal case, one may expect different features to be associated with
different X heads. For instance, first, there may be differences with respect to syn-
tactic features, as we have seen with Case and EPP properties. In (7.14)/(7.53a) X is
implicit, and the semantic “possessor” is in effect the plural individual representing
the contextually relevant subdomain. Likewise for explicit partitives, as reflected
in (7.53b). The definite article spells out the choice-function pronoun, and a Case-
assigning element may be overt. Differences in number features and semantic def-
initeness aside, the analysis in (7.53b) is equivalent to (7.14b)–(7.14c)/(7.53a).73
An analysis of the partitive falls out of the general D+XP structure for presupposi-
tional quantifier phrases; special semantic operations such as type shifting (Ladusaw
1982, Giannakidou 2004) needn’t be required. In some languages partitives can
also be realized with a genitive construction, as in (7.54) (cf. e.g. Harris & Camp-
bell 1995: 55–56, 339–341).
126
c. bàdə́mm ir-á-tàrè
all head-gen-3pl
‘all of them’ (Frajzyngier 2012: 138; Wandala (Chadic))
d. macallimíntii qaar-k-óod baa la xeray.
professors-det+past part-det+poss.3pl decl one put-in-jail
‘Some of the professors have been put in jail.’
(Lecarme 1999b: ex. 35d; Somali)
On the flip side, in addition to the prenominal strategy in (7.54d), genitives in So-
mali can also be realized via a “construct state” construction, as in (7.56) (cf. (7.19)/(7.54b)).
Somali genitives/partitives of the (7.56)-form require linear adjacency without prepo-
sition or case; however, the article on the head noun is obligatory (Lecarme 1996,
1999b, 2004).
127
sives such as (7.57). Although the range of relations under the heading of “posses-
sion” can be broad, it is more constrained than the range of relations potentially
associated with genitives generally (see Seiler 1983a, Nichols 1988, Chappell &
McGregor 1989, 1996b, Taylor 1989, Nikiforidou 1991, Barker 1995: ch. 2,
Langacker 1995, Koptjevskaja-Tamm 1996, 2004, Heine 1997, Marantz 1997,
Partee & Borschev 2003, Storto 2003, Lee-Schoenfeld 2006, Badulescu &
Moldovan 2008, Payne 2009, Dixon 2010: ch. 16, Lichtenberk et al. 2011,
Aikhenvald 2013).
128
basis for the posited additional layer of structure in ordinary (non-genitive, non-
relative) quantificational DPs such as in (7.6)/(7.14)/(7.26). The structure we
have arrived at for nominals, though motivated on largely semantic grounds, par-
allels implementations of syntactic symmetries in noun and verb phrases. As we
have seen, the account is compatible with different ways of filling out the spe-
cific syntactic details. In (7.24) we briefly considered a Q+n∗P/n∗ implementa-
tion, as part of a possible general nP analysis of noun phrases (Chomsky 2007).
Two additional noteworthy connections are the layered DP syntax developed in
Bhattacharya 1999a,b and Hiraiwa 2005. Notably, Bhattacharya and Hiraiwa
identify distinct heads for Case/agreement and a specificity element under the de-
terminer (see §7.1), as reflected in (7.58); the former corresponds to our X, and the
latter is explicitly identified as a position for certain specific indefinites, elements
treated here with choice-function pronouns (Bhattacharya 1999a, 1999b: 85–98,
Hiraiwa 2005: 201, 213–214; cf. also Zamparelli 2000, Megerdoomian 2008,
2009, Himmelmann 2016). Bhattacharya’s and Hiraiwa’s nominal shell under the
determiner is essentially the same XP structure posited in this section for genitives
(i) a. ardayád soomaalí ah/∗ ahayd [CPrel oo telefóon kúu soo dirtay]
student Somali is/∗ was.past and telephone you-to towards sent.past
‘A Somali student who phoned you’
b. ardayád-dii soomaalí-da ahayd [CPrel oo telefóon kúu soo dirtay]
student-def.past Somali-def was.past and telephone you-to towards sent.past
‘The Somali student who phoned you’
(Lecarme 2004: ex. 20; structure markings in original)
The tense domain of the head noun includes adjectival/nominal modifiers but not the relative clause
(Lecarme 1996, 1999b, 2004). Such properties of tense agreement, overtly marked in Somali,
arguably extend to worlds as well: A “mixed” de re/de dicto reading is perhaps more easily available
with the embedded restrictive relative in (iii) than with the modifier in (ii).
(ii) Bert thinks every freshman girl is smart.
a. De dicto ≈ there are no freshman girls but Bert thinks there are; he thinks all of them are
smart (e.g., Bert thinks the actual sophomore boys are the freshman girls)
b. De re ≈ for G the set of freshmen and G′ the set of girls: Bert thinks every o ∈ G ∩ G′ is smart
(compatible with Bert thinking some of the o’s are sophomores or boys)
c. #Mixed ≈ for G the set of actual freshmen: Bert thinks every o′ ∈ G such that o′ is a girl
is smart (compatible with some of the Gs being boys, and Bert thinking some of them are
sophomores)
(iii) [Context: Stan doesn’t realize that the Smiths are Russian spies. He thinks they live across the
street from him, but the house is actually a Russian safe house.]
??Mixed ≈ Stan thinksi every spy@ who livesi across the street from him is a loyal American.
We will return to possibilities for modally independent readings for different types of noun phrases
in §§8.5–8.9.
129
((7.43)–(7.42)) and the complements of quantifier phrases ((7.6a)): the (implicit)
choice-function pronoun instantiates F2 , and X corresponds to F1 . (I use neutral
category labels F1 , F2 for consistency.)
(7.58) … D [ F1 P F1 [ F2 P F2 nP]]
(cf. Bhattacharya 1999b, Hiraiwa 2005; labels adapted)
Though I have been ignoring events and categories such as v, Asp, T, perhaps a more
refined syntax for the verbal domain could afford a parallel assignment-variable-
based treatment of the semantics (more on which in §8.9; cf. §3.2, nn. 45, 119, 128).
Let’s recap. This section has examined several ways of extending the assignment-
quantificational treatment of determiner quantifiers from §§6.1–6.2 to quantifier
phrases with non-relative complements. I argued that a generalized D+CP/XP ac-
count is motivated by diachronic, morphological, syntactic, and semantic connec-
tions between individual quantifier phrases and expressions often associated with
notions of “specificity” (broadly construed); and helps capture a range of inde-
pendent linguistic phenomena, including implicit domain restriction, non-relative
restrictive modification, the distinction between free R (modifier) and inherent R
readings of genitives. Although the assignment-quantificational semantics is com-
patible with alternative analyses of the internal syntax, I speculated that a D+XP
implementation for non-relative quantificational DPs may have advantages over a
D+CP implementation. The posited nominal XP projection is independently mo-
tivated by accounts of genitive constructions and parallels in the verbal domain.
The D+XP analyses in (7.42)–(7.43) yield a common structure in the interpreta-
tion of prenominal and postnominal genitives, and capture the distinction between
free R and inherent R readings in terms of a more general treatment of restrictive
modification, as in (7.26b) (also nn. 65, 75). Such syntactic and semantic features
may be of broader theoretical interest independent of the particular assignment-
variable implementation developed here. It is worth examining to what extent
the proposals might be adapted to other types of quantificational, genitive, and
specific/non-specific expressions, and in English and in other languages. The issues
regarding the internal syntax, and comparisons among different notions associated
with “specificity” warrant more careful independent investigation. (We will return
to these issues below and in greater detail throughout §8.)
The syntactic speculations in this section, though not essential to the overall
account, haven’t been a mere detour; they highlight an important methodological
point (cf. §§1, 3.1, 5). Critical to any compositional semantic theory is that the
semantic derivations proceed from plausible syntactic structures. The independent
130
features of the D+CP and D+XP (Q+DP, Q+n∗P) analyses provide further moti-
vation for the LFs used in capturing the linguistic shifting data which constitute
the project’s primary focus. The remainder of the section applies our generalized
assignment-variable syntax/semantics of quantifier phrases to several additional
phenomena with pronominal anaphora and binding.
(7.59) Pronoun-binding via A-movement (cf. Heim & Kratzer 1998: 262-264)
a. Every cat likes its owner.
LF ≈ [ S every cat [2 [ S t2 likes the-owner-of-o2 ]]]
b. Every cat thinks that it is smarter than its owner.
LF ≈ [ S every cat [2 [ S t2 thinks [ S it2 is smarter than the-owner-of-it2 ]]]]
(7.60) a. [[ DP⟨2,a⟩ every⟨2,a⟩ [ XP … F2cf -g2 cat] [ VP likes [the-owner-of-it2 -g2 cat]]]
b. JSK ≈ λgg . ∀xe ∀aa ∶ x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(cat) ∧ . . .
→ x(g) likes the-owner-of-a(g)(2cf)(cat)
Additional support for such an approach may come from languages in which a bound
pronoun can be overtly realized as a copy of its antecedent, as in (7.61).
76
Following Heim & Kratzer’s account of movement, the binder index occupies its own node.
They posit that the embedded subject pronoun also QRs; I ignore this additional movement.
131
(7.61) a. Aajarni khit waa puak rua chob aajarni .
teacher think that all we like teacher
‘The teacheri thinks we like himi .’ (Lee 2003; Thai)
b. A w-nalààa’z bxuuhahzi g-uhcnèe Lia Paamm bxuuhahzi
already remembered priest helped Pam priest
‘The priesti remembered that Pam helped himi .’ (Lee 2003; Zapotec)
132
the more richly articulated internal structure, in contrast to the reduced syntax of
the bound pronoun.78
A treatment of bound pronouns along these lines may shed light on contrasts
with other types of pronouns. Consider reflexives. A prominent implementation
among movement theories of reflexivization is to analyze the reflexive as a pro-
nounced copy of movement (Lidz & Idsardi 1998, Hornstein 2001, 2007, Boeckx
et al. 2007, Bošković & Nunes 2007, Drummond et al. 2011; cf. Lebeaux 1983,
78
There are of course independent differences in the degree of internal syntactic complexity
among different types of pronouns and (non-)quantificational DPs across languages (Giusti 1991,
1992, 2002, Cardinaletti & Starke 1999, Zamparelli 2000, Bernstein 2001, Matthewson
2001, 2013, Déchaine & Wiltschko 2002, 2015, 2017b, Aboh 2004, Bhat 2004, Lecarme 2004,
2012, Borer 2005a, Julien 2005, Watanabe 2006, Alexiadou et al. 2007, Tănase-Dogaru 2007,
von Fintel & Matthewson 2008, Leu 2008, Ghomeshi et al. 2009, ?, Mavrogiorgos 2010, Gil
et al. 2013, Gillon 2013, Paul et al. 2015, Grosz & Patel-Grosz 2016, Patel-Grosz & Grosz
2017, Himmelmann 2016, Sabbagh 2016, Cardinaletti & Giusti 2017; see also n. 51). We
have already observed as much in the distinction between D CP quantifier phrases and indefinites
which take an NP complement. Likewise capturing the anaphoric potential of bound pronouns and
donkey pronouns in the above ways is compatible with there being other syntactic differences among
them (§§6.2.1, 8.8). For instance, given our purposes I have left open how exactly the non-movement
copies (informally understood) enter the syntactic derivation — e.g., whether they are the product
of some sequence of syntactic operations involving Copy, or the lexical material is duplicated in the
numeration. Different types of anaphoric pronouns and expressions may differ in this respect, both
crosslinguistically and within a particular language. On one approach (Nunes 2004, Bošković &
Nunes 2007, Kandybowicz 2007), multiple Copies (products of Copy) can be pronounced only if
some Copy can be morpho-phonologically fused with another element, thereby avoiding a violation
of the Linear Correspondence Axiom (Kayne 1994); roughly put, if multiple identical Copies are
pronounced, the lexical items in the numeration won’t be able to be consistently linearized, since
some items are assigned to more than one position (contrast e.g. Kandybowicz 2008, Nasu 2010
for non-fusion-based approaches). So, insofar as complex elements are less susceptible to morpho-
phonological reanalyzation, structures with multiple pronounced Copies are generally excluded at
PF. Interestingly, whereas morphologically complex bound pronoun copies are (to my knowledge)
unattested (see also (7.61)–(7.62) above), individual correlates in correlative constructions can be
overtly realized as syntactically and morphologically complex (§9.7); complex donkey-anaphoric
expressions are also possible in some languages ((6.40), below; cf. (6.45)).
(i) a. *Ob tug dlevi yeej tum ob tug dlevi .
two clf dog always bite two clf dog
‘The two dogs bite themselves/each other.’ (Mortensen 2003; Hmong complex reflexive)
b. Tug twgi pum (proj ) los tug twgi yeej nyam (proj ).
clf which see top clf which always like
‘Whoever sees him will surely like him.’ (Mortensen 2003; Hmong donkey sentence)
c. [jo (larkii) kharii hai] vo laRkii lambii hai.
rel (girl) standing is dem girl tall is
‘Which girl is standing, that girl is tall.’ (Srivastav 1991; Hindi complex correlate)
133
Chomsky 1993, Kratzer 2009). A sentence such as (7.63a) is represented roughly
as in (7.63b). In languages such as English the lower copy is converted to a re-
flexive pronoun in the morpho-phonological components. In explicit copy reflex-
ive languages the lower copy can be pronounced itself (Lasnik 1989, Lee 2003,
Mortensen 2003, Boeckx et al. 2007).
One way of reflecting these contrasts might be to distinguish the representations of bound pronouns
(like reflexives) as products of a Copy operation. It would be interesting to examine whether
there may be crosslinguistic differences in this respect, and to what extent such differences may
come apart from differences such as in e.g. morphology and possibilities for morpho-phonological
reanalysis, zero anaphora, anaphoric devices, etc. (We will return to these issues and comparisons
with correlatives in §§9–10; for broader general discussion see also Hornstein 2001, Elbourne
2005, Corver & Nunes 2007, Kratzer 2009, Leung 2009.)
79
Hereafter I will omit the qualification limiting to dedicated local-domain forms/devices, but it
should be understood (see e.g. Zribi-Hertz 2008, Déchaine & Wiltschko 2017b).
134
additional structure in the quantifier phrases, intermediate copies, and any semantic
contribution of the ‘-self’ morpheme.)80
In (7.66) the higher complete copy is pronounced and interpreted, and the lower
copy is reduced prior to LF (indicated by the strikethrough).81 The reflexive pronoun
in (7.66) is the overt realization of an identical (here reduced) copy of movement
in an A-chain (specifically, a chain spanning multiple θ-positions). As with bound
pronoun examples such as (7.59)–(7.60), the account captures the bound reading
of the reflexive without requiring non-type-driven movement of the antecedent, a
special abstraction principle, or an ad hoc binder index (Heim & Kratzer 1998,
Büring 2005, Kratzer 2009).
One argument for movement analyses of reflexives is that they afford a means
of deriving Principle A, that dedicated reflexive forms have local antecedents; the
local relation with the antecedent is derived from the local nature of the kind of
A-movement. A live issue is whether Principle B — that bound pronouns have a non-
local antecedent, that bound pronouns be free in the domain in which reflexives are
bound (cf. (7.67)) — may also be explained in more fundamental terms.82
80
In a trace theory, the attachment of the binder-index feature would be built into the definition
of QR. Alternatively, if the object DP enters the derivation with its individual binder-index feature,
an LF where the lower copy is replaced by t2a could be filtered out for type reasons, or which variable
the lower copy is replaced by could be determined by which binder-index feature is unchecked in
that position, here determining replacement with the individual-variable (see nn. 13, 22). We will
return to object-position quantifiers in §7.4.
81
Contrast e.g. Hornstein 2001, 2007, Boeckx et al. 2007, Bošković & Nunes 2007, in which
the chain link phonetically realized as the reflexive pronoun is treated as a complete copy.
82
Cf. e.g. Richards 1996, Hornstein 2001, Reuland 2001, Drummond et al. 2011, Déchaine
& Wiltschko 2015, 2017b. See Reuland & Koster 1991 for an overview on non-complementary
distributions of reflexives and bound pronouns (long-distance reflexives, locally bound pronouns)
crosslinguistically (n. 79). Cf. Schlenker 2005, Cecchetto & Donati 2010 on Condition C.
135
(7.67) a. Percyi likes himselfi /∗ himi .
b. Percyi thinks Penny likes himi /∗ himselfi .
As Hornstein puts it, “Why should anaphors, whose properties follow from the
theory of movement, block the the presence of pronouns, whose distribution and
interpretive properties follow from the theory of binding? The big fact [that bound
pronouns are in complementary distribution with reflexives] is rendered capricious,
a colossal grammatical accident” (2007: 354). In response Hornstein (2001, 2007)
argues that what explains the complementarity of reflexives and bound pronouns is
an economy principle which favors the use of reflexives, qua copies of movement:
“what makes for economy in such cases is Movement. In particular, if a derivation
can converge without the use of pronouns, it must so converge. In short, Move
trumps Pronominalize… [Pronouns are] what the system uses when movement
fails” (2007: 383). So, the thought goes, the use of a bound pronoun is avail-
able in (7.67) when, and only when, ‘Percy’ cannot be linked to its lower copy via
(A-)movement.
Movement-based theories of construal have been supported by diverse crosslin-
guistic examples in which the use of pronouns — not simply bound pronouns —
anticorrelates with the possibility of movement rather than with the use of reflexives
as such. A critical issue for derivational economy accounts such as Hornstein’s is
whether the core economy assumption — e.g., that syntactic derivations resorting to
movement are preferred as more economical than derivations resorting to pronoun
use — can be sufficiently motivated to bear the relevant explanatory weight. It is
well established that various types of even local A-/A-movements incur non-trivial
processing costs (Felser 2015, Wurmbrand 2018). It may seem surprising that the
relevant local movement operations (even understood in terms of copying) would
be systematically less costly than inserting a bundle of (possibly uninterpreted)
φ-features.83
Economy-based movement accounts aren’t silent on this issue (e.g. Hornstein
2001). This isn’t the place to critically assess movement analyses of reflexivization or
particular explanations of binding-theoretic principles such as Hornstein’s. Suffice
it to say that a generalized assignment-variable analysis, such as considered above,
may provide a basis for an economy-based account of the distribution of reflexives
83
See Richards 1999 for developments of a syntactic theory that assumes a general preference
for Move over Merge. In order to treat the alternative versions of sentences such as in (7.67) as
competing, Hornstein must assume that the reflexive and bound pronouns are “semantically inert”
and hence that their φ-features are uninterpreted — not only in “fake indexical” examples but in
general, contrary to standard theories (see n. 51).
136
and pronouns. Unlike bound pronouns, on the above line, reflexives are systemat-
ically represented from identical copies of movement. The relevant economy prin-
ciple needn’t be construed fundamentally as “Avoid Pronouns” (Chomsky 1981),
or “Move (=Copy-and-Merge) trumps Pronominalize” (Hornstein 2001, 2007),
but, suggestively, “Copy-and-Merge trumps Find and (at least for the most part)
Repeat” — or, less syntactically put, “Using a form marked as a local identical copy of
movement trumps using a form variably interpreted as non-anaphoric or a possibly
non-identical copy of some possibly non-commanding local or non-local antecedent
or other.” An account along these lines might not treat the starred and unstarred
versions of (7.67) as strictly “competing” in the sense relevant in Chomsky 1993.
Yet one needn’t assume that all syntactic principles are fundamentally explained
by purely non-lexical properties (cf. Reinhart 1983a,b, 2006, Richards 1996,
Grimshaw 1997, Barbosa et al. 1998, Fox 2000, Reuland 2001, Schlenker
2005, Broekhuis 2008, Zribi-Hertz 2008).84
The extensions in this section to other types of pronominal anaphora have been
speculative. There are interesting crosslinguistic differences among bound pronouns
and reflexives — e.g., in their relative distributions, internal and external syntax, and
binding-theoretic properties (Déchaine & Wiltschko 2002, 2015, 2017b, Bhat
2004, Zribi-Hertz 2008; see nn. 51, 78, §10.3.1). Investigation of other more ar-
ticulated structures for certain types of pronouns, and comparisons with movement
analyses of other anaphoric expressions may provide fruitful avenues to explore
(e.g., resumptive pronouns or doubled clitic pronouns, cf. Cinque 1977, Pesetsky
1998, Boeckx 2003, Mavrogiorgos 2010, Rouveret 2011; see Kayne 2002 for a
general movement theory of pronouns). We will return to these issues throughout
the following sections.
84
Movement analyses provide one approach to capturing how certain reflexives get their status
as specialized local-domain forms/devices, and thereby block the use of less specialized forms
(Williams 1997; nn. 79, 82). Déchaine & Wiltschko (2015, 2017b) treat the obligatory local
binding with morphemes such as ‘self’ as “forced by” the signal of “inalienable possession” associated
with body-part nouns (see also Vergnaud & Zubizarreta 1992, Bhat 2004). Though it is true that
reflexives are often formed using body-part nouns crosslinguistically, a challenge is to explain why
the “inalienable possession” couldn’t be associated with some non-local subject, as indeed it is in some
languages (e.g., Chinese zìji ‘self’). Such accounts also leave open what (possibly covert) features
force the local binding in other types of reflexive forms (e.g., French se ‘3.refl’). See Drummond
et al. 2011 for a critical overview of other movement- and non-movement-based economy accounts
of reflexivization as blocking pronoun binding.
137
7.4 Donkey crossings: Weak crossover, inverse linking, genitive binding
Our discussion in these sections has focused on examples with subject-position quan-
tifiers. A critical issue concerns examples with QR’d quantifier phrases. In (7.68) the
determiner ‘every’ raises from CPrel as a quantifier over assignments to take its type
⟨e, t⟩ restrictor argument, and the object-position DP QRs, binding an individual-
trace (again ignoring worlds).85
{⟨2,a⟩,⟨2,e⟩}
DP
Alice likes t2e
every⟨2,a⟩ CPrel
⟨1,e⟩
wh2 -g2 baby
t1e laughed
Crel t2a
In principle one could treat the determiner’s scope argument in such examples fun-
damentally as type ⟨e, t⟩. Yet such a move has an air of “multiplying senses beyond
necessity.” One would also need to stipulate that the assignment binder-index
feature on D doesn’t project to the DP. A more attractive approach is to maintain
the uniform type ⟨aet, ⟨aet, t⟩⟩ for ‘every’. As in the subject-position examples, the
assignment binder-index feature on D projects to the DP, and an individual binder-
index attaches to the QR’d DP, as reflected in the feature set on the DP in (7.68).
However, a prima facie worry may come from crossover.
Following Reinhart (1983a) a prominent generalization of weak crossover is
that an expression β can bind a pronoun only if β is in an A-position (argument
position) that c-commands the pronoun at LF. This generalization allows trace-
85
If Kennedy’s (2014) approach to Antecedent Contained Deletion is right, there may be reasons
for requiring coindexing between the individual binder features on the quantificational DP and its
relative complement CPrel , e.g. via agreement. I will ignore such a requirement in what follows.
138
binding but excludes pronoun-binding from A-positions (non-argument positions),
such as positions derived from QR or wh-movement, as in (7.69)–(7.70).
Reinhart’s generalization has also been applied to donkey pronouns in cases of “don-
key crossover” (Haïk 1984, Reinhart 1987, Büring 2004), reflected in (7.71)–(7.72).
The object DP ‘every farmer who beat a donkey’ in (7.72) can bind its trace but,
unlike the subject DP in (7.71), it cannot provide an antecedent for the donkey
pronoun ‘it’.
Absent additional constraints, nothing would seem to exclude the rough LF and
semantic value for (7.72) in (7.73). This represents the unattested bound reading
where the interpretation of the donkey pronoun covaries with the raised DP. (I will
simplify by ignoring the internal structure in C0rel = [C0 Crel t2a ]; I continue to ignore
worlds.)
One could treat Reinhart’s generalization as a basic principle in the grammar.86 LFs
such as (7.73a) would be excluded because they violate Reinhart’s generalization:
86
Cf. Safir’s (2004) Quantifier Dependency Condition, which essentially reformulates Reinhart’s
generalization that pronouns can only be bound from A-positions.
139
the assignment-variable in the pronoun [it3cf g2 ] (underlined in (7.73a)) is bound
by the assignment-binder from the A-position DP.
It would be theoretically preferable to derive generalizations such as Reinhart’s
from more basic features of the syntax/semantics. A more explanatory approach
might be to allow expressions to have multiple binder-indices, but include a con-
straint that no expression may bind distinct variables, in some relevant sense of
binding — call it “s-binding.” A first approximation is as follows. (I will often be
sloppy about distinguishing expressions/variables (qua types) from occurrences.)
An explanation of donkey crossover falls out directly: The raised object DP in (7.73a)
has the set of binder-index features {⟨2,a⟩,⟨3,e⟩} . Like all movement, QR leaves a
coindexed trace. On the unattested reading, the assignment binder-index binds the
assignment-variable in [it3 g2 ] and the individual binder-index binding the trace t3e .
This violates the constraint in (7.74). The donkey pronoun cannot be bound by the
raised DP because the DP’s binding capacities are exhausted from binding the trace
derived from QR. Hence a string such as in (7.73) can have an acceptable reading
but only with an intuitively free reading of ‘its’. No analogous constraint excludes
an intuitively bound reading of ‘its’ in (7.71) where the DP is in an A-position: the
subject DP doesn’t bind a trace and is free to bind the donkey pronoun.
Adopting a general type-⟨aet, ⟨aet, t⟩⟩ syntax/semantics of determiner quanti-
fiers provides a means of generalizing the above approach to weak crossover to
examples with non-relative complements, as reflected schematically in (7.75).
140
The foregoing approach carries over to other recalcitrant cases of apparent bind-
ing out of DPs (see esp. Büring 2004). The remainder of the section considers two
such cases: genitive binding and inverse linking.
Consider donkey-style anaphora and crossover with genitives:
In (7.76) the embedded DP ‘every boy’ can provide an antecedent for ‘him’ even
though it doesn’t c-command the pronoun at LF. In (7.77) the pronoun can be linked
either to the embedded DP ‘every boy’s sister’ or to the DP ‘every boy’ embedded in
it. Yet the interpretation of the pronoun cannot vary when the main genitive DP
QRs in (7.78).
For present purposes we can put aside many controversial issues about the
syntax of different types of genitive constructions, in English and crosslinguistically.
For concreteness let’s assume the D+XP implementation of “free R” readings of
prenominal genitives X’s Y from (7.42) — where the relevant relation is supplied
by an implicit pronoun R, the “possessor” X+relation R originate as modifiers in the
nominal XP headed by the genitive morpheme, and the XP is the complement of an
implicit definite-like determiner (cf. Partee 1983), as reflected in (7.79) (n. 66).
(I continue to ignore intensionality (an internal world-argument) with the relation
pronoun, and use ‘Ri ’/‘R’ in pronouns/indices of type ⟨e, et⟩.)
In (7.76) the quantificational possessor ‘every boy’ must QR for type reasons (cf. e.g.
May 1985). Thus far our compositional semantics has proceeded solely via function
application; however, adapting the treatment of inverse linking in Kobele 2010,
suppose that we allow a role for function composition in deriving the semantic val-
ues of certain adjunction structures, such as complex DPs formed from DP-internal
141
QR/movement.87 Combining DP∗ of type ⟨et, t⟩ and the raised DP∗∗ of type ⟨t, t⟩ by
function composition yields the complex subject DP of generalized quantifier type
⟨et, t⟩, as shown in (7.80). The assignment binder-index feature projected to the DP
binds the donkey pronoun, again represented as a copy of the antecedent choice-
function pronoun and NP (here internal to the complex quantificational DP∗∗ ). (For
simplicity assume that the implicit domain restriction in DP∗∗ is trivial, where the
property pronoun is contextually identified with E.)88
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a
DP{...⟨2,a⟩... } ∶ ⟨et, t⟩ VP
142
≈ λPet .λgg . ∀xe ∀aa ∶ x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(boyg(1a)(1s) ) →
[ιy(g)∃a′a ∶ y(g) = a′ (g)(3cf)(catg(1a)(1s) ) ∧ g(1a)(1R)(x(g))(y(g))]
P(y)(g[x(g)/2e][a(g)/2a][a′ (g)/3a])
JSK ≈ λgg . ∀xe ∃aa ∶ x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(boyg−(1s) ) →
[ιye (g)∃a′a ∶ y(g) = a′ (g)(3cf)(catg−(1s) ) ∧ g(1R)(x(g))(y(g))]
y(g) likes a(g)(2cf)(boyg−(1s) ) in @(g−)
This says, roughly, that for every o ∈ E such that there is a choice function that selects
o from among the boys, the unique o′ ∈ E such that o′ is selected by some choice
function from among the cats and bears the relevant relation gc (1R) (“is owned by,”
“is a pet of”) o, is such that o′ likes o — i.e., for every o in the set of boys, the unique
o′ among the cats which bears gc (1R) to o likes o.
The above account of weak crossover/“donkey crossover” carries over to “gen-
itive crossover” violations such as (7.78). (I use ’s both for the morpheme in the
genitive phrase and in the spell-out of the possessive pronoun.)
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a
DP{⟨4,e⟩,⟨2,a⟩... }
The object-position quantifier ‘every boy’s cat’ has a set of binder-index features
including an individual binder-index resulting from QR, and an assignment binder-
143
index projecting from DP∗∗ . The individual binder-index binds the DP’s coindexed
trace t4e . In order for the interpretation of the pronoun to covary with the DP,
the assignment binder-index must bind the assignment-variable in [him2 g2 ]. This
violates the binding constraint in (7.74) which excludes a single expression from
binding distinct variables.
Inverse linking readings, as in (7.82), raise well-known challenges for compo-
sitional semantics. The embedded DP ‘every parent’ in (7.82) is a constituent of the
subject DP (e.g. May 1985, Heim & Kratzer 1998). So, first, ‘every parent’ must
be able to combine with its sister ‘some child of t’ to form the subject DP. Second,
the interpretation of ‘her’ covaries with the quantificational subject even though
the pronoun isn’t c-commanded by ‘every parent’. Third, as with donkey pronouns,
pronouns in inverse linking examples exhibit weak crossover effects:
The raised ‘every parent’ can bind its trace in (7.82a)–(7.82b); but it can provide a
linguistic antecedent for the pronoun only in (7.82a) when embedded in the subject
DP, and not in (7.82b) when embedded in the QR’d object DP.
The compositional semantics proceeds analogously to examples with complex
genitives, as reflected in (7.83). DP∗∗ and D∗ of types of types ⟨t, t⟩ and ⟨et, t⟩,
respectively, combine by function composition to yield the main DP of type ⟨et, t⟩.
The assignment binder-index feature projected from DP∗∗ to the DP binds the don-
key pronoun. (As previously, assume that the property-type pronouns in Spec,X are
contextually identified with E.)
144
(7.83) Some friend of every baby hugged her.
S
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a
DP {...⟨2,a⟩... } ∶ ⟨et, t⟩ VP
loves t1s
DP∗∗{⟨2,e⟩,⟨2,a⟩} ∶ ⟨t, t⟩ DP∗⟨3,a⟩ ∶ ⟨et, t⟩
her2 -g2 baby-w1 -g1
every⟨2,a⟩ XP some⟨3,a⟩ XP
⋮
The derived semantic value captures the inverse linking reading: (7.83) says that
for every o ∈ E selectable from among the babies, there is an o′ ∈ E selected by some
choice function from among o’s friends such that o′ loves o — i.e., for every baby o,
there is an o′ among the friends of o such that o′ loves o.
The above account of weak crossover carries over to “inverse crossover” cases
such as (7.82b)/(7.84):
145
(7.84) *Her cati likes some friend of every childi .
≉ “for every child o, there is some friend of o that is liked by o’s cat”
S
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a
DP{⟨4,e⟩,⟨2,a⟩... }
DP⟨4,a⟩
DP∗∗{⟨2,e⟩,⟨2,a⟩} DP∗⟨3,a⟩ ∶ ⟨et, t⟩ t4e
likes t1s
⟨4,a⟩
ιo XP
every⟨2,a⟩ XP some⟨3,a⟩ XP
⋮
The QR’d object DP binds its coindexed trace t4e . Given the constraint that an
expression cannot semantically bind distinct variables, g2 in the representation of
‘her’ cannot be bound by the DP, and the intuitively bound reading is excluded.
Let’s recap. This section has speculated about how the assignment-quantificational
approach to donkey anaphora from §6.2 might be extended to other recalcitrant
phenomena with pronominal anaphora — e.g., regarding weak crossover effects
and apparent binding out of DPs with inverse linking and genitive binding. The
D+XP syntax for inverse linking and genitives captures how expressions such as
‘some child of every parent’ and ‘every boy’s cat’ form constituent DPs (contrast
Hornstein 1995). The intuitively bound readings of pronouns in the DPs’ scope
follow from (i) the treatment of anaphoric pronouns as copies of their linguistic
antecedents, (ii) the generalized assignment-quantificational syntax/semantics for
determiner quantifiers, and (iii) the use of function composition in the composi-
tional semantics of (e.g.) complex DPs formed from DP-internal movement. I sug-
gested potentially explaining weak crossover data such as Reinhart’s generalization
via a general principle that no expression can bind distinct variables. Since a moved
expression must bind its trace, the assignment-variable in a subject pronoun cannot
146
be bound by a QR’d object DP — in examples with simple DPs ((7.75b)), donkey
sentences ((7.72)–(7.73)), inverse linking ((7.82b)/(7.84)), and genitive binding
((7.78)/(7.81)) alike. There is no analogous obstacle to bound readings when the
DP is in subject position — hence Reinhart’s generalization that bound pronouns,
unlike traces, must be bound from A-positions.89
A worry with many accounts of (donkey) crossover is that they end up for-
malizing what needs to be explained — the distinction between trace-binding and
pronoun-binding. Contrasts such as in (7.71)–(7.72) may be captured via stipula-
tions on admissible indexings (e.g. Haïk 1984, Safir 1984, Reinhart 1987), or
ad hoc syntactic/semantic distinctions between traces and pronouns (e.g. Büring
2004, Safir 2004, Elbourne 2005). For instance, Büring 2004 — arguably the
most extensively developed account — introduces distinct syntactic categories for
traces and pronouns (including, crucially, individual-variables in E-type representa-
tions), distinct binding operators and domains for assignments corresponding to the
two categories, and distinct principles regarding admissible LFs for traces/pronouns
and their respective binding operators. At minimum the present assignment-variable-
based framework offers independent grounds for formally distinguishing pronouns
and traces (§§2, 4.3). Pronouns [viτ gj ] include an assignment-variable from which
the element receives its interpretation; no assignment-variable is included in the
representation of a trace tiτ since the binder-index attaching to the moved expres-
sion binds the variable directly. This independent distinction may be exploited in
an account of weak crossover. No additional binder operators or constraints on
admissible indexings are required. Assignment functions and the generalized binder
index make no distinction between traces and pronouns as such.
I hope the preliminary discussion in this section may provide a basis for a more
explanatory treatment of weak crossover. The prospects for the specific assignment-
variable-based approaches in this section to determiner quantification, relativiza-
tion, and trace-/pronoun-binding remain to be seen. Ellipsis, “sloppy identity” read-
ings, and discourse anaphora may offer fruitful additional applications to explore.
89
Yes, the last inference was too quick. The above discussion applied specifically to DPs with
assignment binder-indices. Nothing has been said about weak crossover effects with wh interrog-
atives, as in (7.70). There are independently attested contrasts between wh-chains and QR-chains
regarding the interpretation of traces/pronouns (e.g. Safir 1999, Cecchetto 2004). How to extend
the approach to weak crossover in this section will depend on one’s views on the syntactic/semantic
status of wh movement, reconstruction, pied piping, etc. A more general binding theory is certainly
needed. I return to wh interrogatives in §10.3.
147
8 Noun phrases
Our discussion in §§6–7 focused primarily on strong quantifiers such as ‘every’. In
§7.1 we saw how the proposed choice-function based analysis can help capture
certain effects associated with “specificity” (Enç 1991), such as existence presup-
positions and contextual domain restrictions. Not all quantifier words exhibit these
effects, in general or in particular uses; and some words exhibit some effects but
not others. A critical question is how the proposed assignment-quantificational
syntax/semantics of strong quantifiers relates to the syntax/semantics for other
types of (non-)quantified noun phrases, such as weak quantifiers and indefinites —
to a first approximation, those compatible with existential ‘there’ sentences, as in
(8.1) (‘sm’ for unstressed ‘some’).90 In some languages the difference between
90
All examples with ‘there’ sentences will be with existential ‘there’, not locative or presentational
‘there’ (cf. (i)). See McNally 1997, 1998, Zamparelli 1998, 2000, Francez 2007 on uses of
strong quantifiers with kind/amount nominals (cf. Carlson 1977, Grosu 2002, Beaver et al.
2005, Hartmann 2008, Hallman 2016 for relevant discussion). There is substantial variation in
acceptability with different quantifiers, noun phrases, and modifiers, cf. (ii)–(x):
(i) a. There was/wasn’t a book on the table.
b. There was/∗wasn’t a certain book on the table.
c. There appeared/∗didn’t appear a ghost.
(ii) a. There is every/??each kind of ice cream (on sale/available/in the store).
b. There are all/??most kinds of ice cream (on sale/available/in the store).
(iii) a. There was every flavor/#tub of ice cream (on sale/available/in the store).
b. There were all flavors/#tubs of ice cream (on sale/available/in the store).
(iv) There are ??all/#most of the kinds of ice cream (on sale/available/in the store).
(v) a.#There was every/each kind of ice cream being eaten (/put on the shelf).
b. There were all/#most kinds of ice cream being eaten (/put on the shelf).
(vi) a. There was everything we wanted on the menu.
b.#There all/most things we wanted on the menu.
c. There were ??all/?#most of the things we wanted on the menu.
(vii) a. There is every/#all/#most reason to believe that Alice will win.
b.#There are all/most reasons to believe that Alice will win.
(viii) a. There is ?every/#all/#most chance that Alice will win.
b. There is ??every/#all/#most probability/possibility that Alice will win.
c. #There are all/most chances/probabilities/possibilities that Alice will win.
(ix) a. There was every [kind of pie and flavor of ice cream] at the party.
b. There were all [kinds of pie and flavors of ice cream] at the party.
c. There were cars of [all styles and most colors] on display.
(x) a. ?There are most kinds of movies available on every channel. (every > most)
b. Most kinds of movies are available on every channel. (every > most, most > every)
148
presuppositional and nonpresuppositional uses ((8.1)–(8.2)) can be lexicalized or
otherwise marked, as in (8.3)–(8.4) in Turkish (cf. Enç 1991, Zamparelli 2000,
Kelepir 2001).
149
(‘three’) and articles (‘the’). I inevitably use ‘quantifier’ multiply for quantified ex-
pressions, quantifier words/strings as types, and for particular tokens. Crucially, my
usage doesn’t presuppose that the item has the syntax or semantics of a generalized
quantifier, either in general or in particular occurrences.)
(8.5) nP
n NumP
Num N
As usual, NumP is an independent projection for number and certain uses of numer-
als and non-definite determiners; it provides the locus of cardinal and “specified
quantity” interpretations, e.g. distinguishing ‘a/two/several book(s)’ from a mass
noun such as ‘water’ (Ritter 1991, Bernstein 2001, ?, Borer 2005a, Tănase-
Dogaru 2007, Megerdoomian 2008).91 n is a light noun parallel to v in a verb
phrase (e.g. ‘do’). Following Marantz 1997 it is common to treat “little” n and v
as present for purposes such as distinguishing nominal and verbal environments.
In some languages the nominalizers and verbalizers with lexical roots are mor-
phologically overt, as in (8.6)–(8.7) (Nishayama 1998, Heine & Kuteva 2002,
Rackowski 2002, Levinson 2007, Pylkkänen 2008, Harley 2009, 2013, Julien
2015, D'Alessandro et al. 2017).
150
(ii) [ vP [ v /ɑ/] √barg] (cf. Julien 2015: 6)
(8.7) a. Santos kari-te.
Santos house-v0
‘Santos is building a house.’
b. Aman kari-te-wa.
there house-v0 -pass
‘Houses are being built there.’
(Harley 2013: 42–43, 53; Hiaki (Uto-Aztecan))
I propose that we treat n0 and v0 as the locus of world variables.92 The ar-
gument structure for verbs can be adapted accordingly so that the verb combines
first with its object(s)/complement — e.g. treating ‘like’ as type ⟨e, ⟨s, et⟩⟩, ‘think’
as type ⟨at, ⟨s, et⟩⟩, etc. ((8.9)) — yielding the VP complement of v0 . In clauses
such as the complement of ‘think’ in (8.8a), the world variable in v0 of the main
predicate is determined by the type-driven movement of the complementizer. A
simple predicative sentence may be represented roughly as in (8.8b).93 Number
features can be treated semantically as modifiers (cf. Ionin & Matushansky 2006)
92
We will examine constraints on world variables in the nP area and substantive lexical entries for
certain n0 /v0 heads in §§8.5–8.9. Adapting ideas from the “supercategorial theory” in Hiraiwa 2005,
n and v might be treated as different manifestations of a single “supercategory,” call it ‘w’ (cf. n. 94).
(Compare Bowers’s (2001) Pr(ed) category, which takes as its complement the maximal projection
of any lexical category (VP, NP), and is present even with non-relational nouns/verbs (hence distinct
from n∗/v∗); however, other roles posited for Pr, such as projecting an external argument, correspond
to v∗ (cf. (8.7b)).) I leave open where classifiers and other φ-features may be located.
93
For now I continue to ignore v∗ for introducing external arguments, I ignore any additional
semantic contribution that ‘be’ may make in sentences such as (8.8b), and I put aside issues regarding
the category of the copula in different languages (see Partee 1986a, den Dikken 1995, 1998,
Harley 1995, Rothstein 1997, Dixon 2002, Folli & Harley 2007, Mikkelsen 2011, Moro
2017); we will return to these issues in §8.9. For instance, ‘be’ could be analyzed as a main verb V or
as phonetically realizing v, as in (i). In (ii) lea ‘be’ is realized with the verbal marker /ɑ/ from (8.6).
Sabbagh 2009 argues that both v and V have morphological content in certain Tagalog existential
sentences ((iii)).
(i) a. [ vP [ v be] nP/n∗P]
b. [ vP [ v be] [ VP e nP/n∗P]]
c. [ vP v [ VP be nP/n∗P]]
(ii) Mu bohtal lea guoros.
my(n) bottle is(v) empty (Julien 2005: 318; North Sámi (Uralic))
(iii) a. May-roon sa bahay na manok.
exist.there loc house lk chicken
‘There’s a chicken in the house.’
b. [vP may [VP roon …]] (Sabbagh 2009: exs. 4c, 21; Tagalog (Austronesian))
151
of type ⟨⟨s, et⟩, ⟨s, et⟩⟩, as in (8.10). (An atomic individual o is an individual with
no proper parts, i.e. no o′ such that o′ ⊏ o, where ‘a ⊑ b’ says that a is a (possibly
improper) part of b (Link 1983). I use ‘count’ for whatever the relevant properties
are for being in a plural or count denotation, where ‘count(o)’ implies at least that
o has atomic parts; hence ‘atom(o)’ implies ‘count(o)’.)
(8.8) a. [ vP tis [ VP think⟨2,a⟩ [ CP [Cd t2a ]⟨2,s⟩ [Percy [ vP t2s [ VP likes Colin]]]]]]
b. [ S T⟨1,a⟩ [ CP [Cd t1a ]⟨1,s⟩ [Fluffy [t1s [a-[sg] cat]]]]] (preliminary)
(8.9) a. JlikeK = λxe .λws .λye .λgg . y(g) likes x(g) in w(g)
b. JthinkK = λA⟨a,t⟩ .λws .λxe .λgg . ∀aa ∶ a(g) is compatible with x(g)’s state
of mind in w(g) → A(a)(g)
(8.10) a. J[sg]K = λP⟨s,et⟩ .λws .λye .λgg ∶ atom(y(g)) . P(w)(y)(g)
b. J[pl]K = λP⟨s,et⟩ .λws .λye .λgg ∶ count(y(g)) . P(w)(y)(g)
I will ignore issues regarding the base position of direct objects (e.g., Comp of V, or Spec of an
intermediate functional head such as Asp(ect); see Verkuyl 1993, Bowers 2002, Borer 2005b,
Hiraiwa 2005). In the definition of the binder index (§3.5), now for ‘think’: τ = a, σ = ⟨s, et⟩.
94
The present layered analyses of noun/verb phrases build on developments (focusing primarily
on the verbal case) in delineating categories for N/V (the root or head noun/verb), n/v (a functional
projection identifying nominal/verbal environments), and n∗/v∗ (a functional projection closing off
complete noun/verb phrases) (Rackowski 2002, Lecarme 2004, 2008, Alexiadou et al. 2006,
Levinson 2007, Megerdoomian 2008, Pylkkänen 2008, Harley 2009, 2013, 2017, Julien 2015,
D'Alessandro et al. 2017, Wood & Marantz 2017; cf. (8.6)–(8.7)). Phasal properties of n∗, v∗
are examined in §8.5. I will continue to use (bold) X for the implicit lexical item, now identifying
n∗ as the general category. (I leave open whether v∗ is to be equated with Voice (Kratzer 1996;
see Ramchand 2017 for critical discussion). We will examine the semantics of verbalizing elements
in an event semantics briefly in §8.9.) See §§7.1–7.2 on comparisons between our F and functional
heads posited in previous literature for certain specificity elements; cf. n. 111. We will consider an
alternative F position under n in §§8.7–8.9. I represent at least some quantifier words as projecting
a QP, but, as discussed in §7.1, this is inessential; we will return to this.
152
(8.11) Layered n structure for noun phrases (preliminary)
QP
Q n∗P
n∗ FP
F nP
n NumP
Num N
(8.12) There are no friends of Bert’s in the audience (??because he doesn’t have
any friends).
(8.13) Alice found no/few mistakes of the author’s…
a. So she’s going to get fired.
b.??So the author must have been super careful.
153
X’s’ is generally marked (other things equal) in comparison to ‘There are Qwk Ns
(ZP)’ or ‘There are Qwk N’s of X’s ZP’.
One could imagine saying (8.18b) as a way of allaying a child’s fears before bed
while accommodating an assumption that there are monsters in one’s charge. The
presuppositional effects of the genitive complements are prima facie puzzling. There
is nothing incoherent with truth conditions such as, say, that ¬∃o[friend(Bert)(o)],
or that ¬∃o[won(o)(Alice) ∧ medal(o)]. The condition that ¬∃o[mistake(o) ∧
wrote(o)(the-author) ∧ found(o)(Alice)] could be satisfied because the author
made no mistakes.
There is an important correlation between the possibility of nonpresuppositional
readings and the structure of the complement. We saw in §7.1 that it is common to
treat (definite) D as the locus of “specificity” phenomena such as existence presup-
positions, D-linking. Data such as (8.17) suggest that the key element is rather the
position occupied by a genitive morpheme (§7.2), regardless of whether it appears
with a definite determiner (implicit with prenominal genitives) or strong quantifier.
To a first approximation, the relevance of an overt genitive in (8.12)–(8.18) is that it
motivates an interpretation in which the quantifier is interpreted above n∗ — above
the position occupied by ’s and implicitly realized by X in non-genitive quantifier
phrases (§§7.1–7.2). The contrasts in (8.16)–(8.18) are analogous in this respect to
contrasts with overt partitives in existential ‘there’ sentences with/without a coda,
as in (8.19) (see also Hoeksema 1996a).
154
structural specificity position above n — and select an individual from the given
world. And presuppositional uses of quantifiers raise from the internal assignment
position to a position above n∗. The presuppositional readings of weak quantifiers
in (8.21) with a postnominal genitive (cf. (7.42)–(7.43)) and (8.22) with (non-re-
duced) ‘some’ may be derived parallel to (8.20) with ‘every’ (scope ¬ > ∀).95 In
(8.20) the choice-function pronoun takes the world-indexed nP as argument, and
thus selects an entity that is a mistake in the world of the discourse (=gc (1s)). So, as
in §7.1, the quantification presupposes that there are mistakes in the manuscript —
hence the infelicity of continuations implying that there weren’t any mistakes.
(8.20) The editor didn’t find every mistake. (#…because there weren’t any)
a. [ S T⟨1,a⟩ [ CP [Cd t1a ]⟨1,s⟩ -n’t
95
Unless otherwise indicated I will ignore the specific contributions of number features from
(8.10). Note that our assignment-quantificational syntax/semantics for presuppositional uses is
compatible with quantifiers taking singular or plural noun phrases. For instance, what differentiates
(i) and (ii) is whether the possible witnesses for the quantifier include pluralities of babies. In (i) the
quantification is over individuals selectable among the set of atomic babies denoted by the singular
nP (=babyu , i.e. the set of o such that o is an atom and o is a baby); in (ii), where the nP is plural, the
choice function selects from a set that includes pluralities (=babiesu , i.e. the closure of babyu under
sum formation).
(i) a. Some/No baby laughed.
b. … [ nP w1 -g1 [sg]-baby] …
c. ≈ λgg . (¬)∃xe ∃aa ∶ x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(babyg−(1s) ) ∧ g−(1et)(x(g)) ∧ x(g) laughed in @(g−)
(ii) a. Some/No babies laughed.
b. … [ nP w1 -g1 [pl]-baby] …
c. ≈ λgg . (¬)∃xe ∃aa ∶ x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(babiesg−(1s) ) ∧ g−(1et)(x(g))∧ x(g) laughed in @(g−)
Interesting issues in crosslinguistic work on the syntax and semantics of quantifiers include differ-
ences between quantifier words that obligatorily take singular vs. plural complements, differences in
distributivity, and differences between partitive complements with definite plural vs. singular noun
phrases, as in (iii)–(v). (where the relevant reading of ‘different N’ in (iv) is the bound, non-deictic
reading). I won’t consider such issues here.
(iii) a. Every {baby is, ∗babies are} cute.
b. All {babies are, ∗baby is} cute.
(iv) a. Every/Each baby got a different toy.
b. Each of the babies got a different toy.
c. *All/Three/Most babies got a different toy. (cf. Beghelli & Stowell 1997: ex. 20)
(v) a. All/Most of the babies are dirty.
b. All/Most of the baby is dirty.
c. *All/Most baby is dirty.
155
[[ QP{⟨2,a⟩,⟨2,e⟩} every⟨2,a⟩ [ n∗P P1et -g1 X [ FP F2cf -t2a [ nP w1 -g1 mistake]]]]
the-editor (v∗) [ vP t1s (did) find t2e ]]]]
b. JnPK = λxe .λgg . x(g) is a mistake in g(1a)(1s)
JSK ≈ λgg . ¬(∀xe ∀aa ∶ (x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(mistakeg−(1s) ) ∧ g−(1et)(x(g))) →
the-editor found x(g) in @(g−))
(8.21) No friend of Bert’s is in the audience.
a. [ S T⟨1,a⟩ [ CP [Cd t1a ]⟨1,s⟩
[[no⟨2,a⟩ [P1et -g1 [ n∗ ’s [ FP F2cf -t2a [ nP w1 g1 [friend Bert]]]]]]
(v∗) [ vP t1s (is) in-the-audience]]]]
b. JSK ≈ λgg . ¬∃xe ∃aa ∶ (x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(friend-of-Bg−(1s) ) ∧ g−(1et)(x(g)))
∧ x(g) is in-the-audience in @(g−)
(8.22) Some (#sm) people are jackasses. (Milsark 1977: 54–55)
a. [ S T⟨1,a⟩ [ CP [Cd t1a]⟨1,s⟩
[[some⟨2,a⟩ [P1et -g1 [ n∗ X [ FP F2cf -t2a [ nP w1 -g1 people]]]]]
(v∗) [ vP t1s (are) jackasses]]]]
b. JSK ≈ λgg . ∃xe ∃aa ∶ x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(peopleg−(1s) ) ∧ g−(1et)(x(g))
∧ x(g) are jackasses in @(g−)
As Milsark puts it, “the only sense of some which can be understood felicitously in
[(8.22)] is the… ‘some’ sense…, that some members of the human race, as opposed,
presumably, to others, are jackasses. Substitution of destressed sm and its reading of
an indefinite number of people, nothing more, yields nonsense” (1977: 55). Indeed,
as in (8.20), the choice-function pronoun selects a (plural) person in the actual
world, and the domain pronoun in Spec,n∗ restricts the quantification to people in
the contextually relevant domain (=gc (1et)). The quantifier existentially quantifies
over those individuals o who are potentially selectable among actual people and in
the given domain. The sentence is true iff some such o are jackasses.
I suggest that what distinguishes nonpresuppositional uses of weak quantifiers
(indefinites, etc.) is that they are interpreted below n in NumP, the position asso-
ciated with number and specified quantity. A key feature of nonpresuppositional
quantifiers is that their meanings can be given in cardinal terms ((8.23)). Treating
number words as type ⟨⟨s, et⟩, ⟨s, et⟩⟩, yielding type ⟨e, t⟩ denotations for the relevant
156
nPs, coheres with common ideas in syntax about the predicative status of weak
quantifiers.96 A derivation for a predicative use is in (8.24) (see nn. 91, 93).
The entry in (8.23) treats ‘three’ as taking a property P and returning the property
true of (plural) individuals with at least three P-atoms. The sentence is true iff the
cardinality of the set of atomic individuals o such that o is a woman and o is in the
group of winners is 3, i.e. iff there are three women among the winners.
The denotations in predicative vs. non-predicative environments can be sys-
tematically related via a general lexical rule for number words or an analogous
general type shifting mechanism (Partee 1986b, 1989b). A first approximation is in
(8.26)–(8.27), adapting a Partee-style ⟨e, t⟩-to-⟨et, t⟩ type shift for a plural domain.
To simplify the definitions, (8.25) defines a metalanguage operator max, which
(roughly put) maps a set of individuals to the singleton set of its maximal element,
if any.
(8.25) For any xe , Fet , gg : max(F(x))(g) ∶= F(x)(g) ∧ ∀x′e ∶ F(x′ )(g) → x′ (g) ⊑ x(g)
(8.26) Type shift option (σ ): For any F′et ,
sigma(F′ ) = λFet .λgg . ∀z∶ (F(z)(g) ∧ ∀z′e ∶ F(z′ )(g) → z′ (g) ⊑ z(g)) → F′ (z)(g)
= λFet .λgg . ∀ze ∶ max(F(z))(g) → F′ (z)(g)
96
See Partee 1986b, Higginbotham 1987, Hudson 1989, Giusti 1991, 1992, 1997, Diesing
1992, Mandelbaum 1994, Cinque 1995, Giusti & Leko 1995, Dimitrova-Vulchanova & Giusti
1996, Zamparelli 2000, Carlson 2003, Landman 2003; see also Bartsch 1973, Verkuyl 1993,
Ionin & Matushansky 2006 on numerals as modifiers. Hereafter I will often leave the number
features implicit; see n. 91.
157
(8.27) Lexical rule option: For Num Jδ# K ∈ D⟨⟨s,et⟩,⟨s,et⟩⟩ ,
JδK = λP⟨s,et⟩ .λws .λFet .λgg . ∀ze ∶ (F(z)(g) ∧ ∀z′e ∶ F(z′ )(g) → z′ (g) ⊑ z(g))
→ Jδ# K(P)(w)(z)(g)
= λP⟨s,et⟩ .λws .λFet .λgg . ∀ze ∶ max(F(z))(g) → Jδ# K(P)(w)(z)(g)
In both options, the upshot at the level of the nP is a mapping from a set of indi-
viduals S′ to the set of sets whose maximal element is in S′ . Contrast (8.20) with
‘every’ with the derivations of (8.28) in (8.29)–(8.30) with (nonpresuppositional)
‘no’/‘three’. (In (8.29), for clarity I represent the type shift with an element in
Spec,n, though there are plausibly syntactic and semantic reasons for treating it
as a semantic type-shifter that applies on demand; see Partee 1986a,b, Chierchia
1998, Landman 2003. In the lexical rule option in (8.30), LFs with the basic δ#
entry would be filtered out for type reasons. I won’t distinguish singular and plural
predicates; we can understand our metalanguage in such a way that a condition
such as (e.g.) that o laughed is satisfied iff every atomic part of o laughed.)
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a nP⟨2,e⟩
Bert vP
(σ )
w1 g1
NumP t1s found t2e
no# unicorns
158
sigma(JNumPK(Jw1 g1 K)) = λFet .λgg . ∀ze ∶ max(F(z))(g) →
#x(g)[x(g) is a unicorn in g(1a)(1s) ∧ x(g) ⊑ z(g)] = 0
JSK ≈ λgg . ∀ze ∶ max(λgg .Bert found z(g) in @(g−))(g) →
#x(g)[x(g) is a unicorn in g−(1s) ∧ x(g) ⊑ z(g)] = 0
≈ λgg . ∀ze ∶ (Bert found z(g) in @(g−)
∧ ∀ye ∶ Bert found y(g) in @(g−) → y(g) ⊑ z(g)) →
#x(g)[x(g) is a unicorn in g−(1s) ∧ x(g) ⊑ z(g)] = 0
(8.30) Non-presuppositional quantifier (lexical rule option; (8.27))
‘Sofia didn’t find three mistakes’ (=(8.28b))
a. [ S T⟨1,a⟩ [ CP [Cd t1a ]⟨1,s⟩ -n’t [[ nP⟨2,e⟩ w1 g1 [ NumP three mistakes]]
Sofia (v∗) [ vP t1s (did) find t2e ]]]]
b. JSK ≈ λgg . ¬(∀ze ∶ max(λgg .Sofia found z(g) in @(g−))(g) →
#x(g)[x(g) is a mistake in g−(1s) ∧ x(g) ⊑ z(g)] ≥ 3)
In (8.29) the NumP ‘no unicorns’ denotes the property of having no unicorn as a part,
which is shifted by sigma to a generalized quantifier at the level of the nP. Roughly
put, the sentence is true iff for any o, if Bert found o and o includes everything
Bert found as a part, then the number of o′ such that o′ is a unicorn and o′ is a
part of o is zero — i.e., iff there is no o′ such that o′ is a unicorn among the things,
if any, that Bert found. The derived truth condition can be satisfied even if there
are no unicorns; indeed (8.29) is guaranteed to be true on the intended reading
if there are no unicorns. Similarly, (8.30) is true iff it’s not the case that for any
o, if o corresponds to the maximal set of things that Sofia found, then the number
of things that are mistakes and part of o is at least three — i.e., iff there are fewer
than three o′ such that o′ is a mistake and o′ is included among what, if anything,
Sofia found. These truth conditions can be satisfied even if there are no unicorns
or no mistakes, respectively; (8.29)–(8.30) on the intended readings would be true.
Note that the rules in (8.26)–(8.27) also capture the coherence of sentences such
as (8.31). If Bert didn’t find anything, the restrictor set is the empty set and the
universal quantification is vacuously satisfied.97
159
b. ≈ λgg .∀ze ∶ Bert found z(g) in @(g−) ∧ . . . →
#x(g)[x(g) is a thing in g−(1s) ∧ x(g) ⊑ z(g)] = 0
160
linking readings to be generally unavailable with nonpresuppositional uses. This
prediction can be delicate to test since most quantifier words and numerals can be
used presuppositionally, but examples with unstressed ‘sm’ may provide preliminary
support. Contrast (7.76)/(7.82a) with the (a)-examples in (8.34)–(8.35).
(8.34) [“My cat doesn’t like me because no cats like their owners.” / “No, it’s you; …]
a.#sm boysi ’ cats like themi .
b. Some/SOME boysi ’ cats like themi .
c. Most boysi ’ cats likes themi .
(8.35) [“My students don’t like me because no teachers are popular with their
students.” / “No, it’s you; …]
a.#Most students of sm teachersi like themi .
b. Most students of some/SOME teachersi like themi .
c. Some students of most teachersi like themi .
Note that the anomalousness of (8.34a)/(8.35a) on the intended readings isn’t due
to some general incompatibility between ‘sm’ and (noun-phrase-internal) posses-
sor/object positions. Examples such as (8.37) can be felicitous with either stressed
or unstressed ‘some’.
(We will return to the syntax/semantics of donkey pronouns in light of the analyses
of noun phrases in this section in §8.8.3.)
161
(8.38): (i) Num (or Spec,Num), which modifies the head noun by specifying number
or cardinality, mapping a property P to the property of having nδ P-individuals as
atomic parts; (ii) little n, analogous to little v in a verb phrase, which may supply the
world-variable for the nP; (iii) F, which provides the locus for specific readings and
existence implications, by selecting an individual from the (possibly singleton) set
denoted by the NumP in the world supplied by little n; (iv) n∗, which provides the
locus of domain restriction; and (v) “true” quantifiers, which raise for type reasons
from inside the noun phrase, and provide the locus of proportional readings and
assignment-quantification.
162
(8.39) a. Kɔ́kú xɔ̀ távò lɔ́ lɛ́.
Koku bought table spfc[+def] pl
‘Koku bought the specific tables.’
b. Kɔ́kú xɔ̀ távò ɖé lɛ́.
Koku bought table spfc[–def] pl
‘Koku bought some specific tables.’
c. *Kɔ́kú xɔ̀ távò ɖé lɔ́ lɛ́.
Koku buy.perf table spfc[–def] spfc[+def] pl
(Aboh 2004: 76–77; Gungbe (Niger-Congo))
English quantifier phrases such as ‘every baby’ are “presuppositional” in the sense of
implying the existence of babies and a contextually relevant domain. Yet whereas
the contextual domain restriction with anaphoric ‘both’ (‘both babies’) or an ex-
plicit partitive is to a set of previously introduced individuals in the context, no
such “familiarity” presupposition need be associated with ‘every baby’. Additional
implications may of course be associated with particular expressions or occurrences,
though I don’t assume that syntactic or semantic definiteness is criterial of any of
the relevant positions.98
Likewise the structure in (8.11) may apply to languages without articles or
(definite) determiners. Certain quantifier words or choice-function elements might
be treated as instantiating a D(eterminer) position, yet the account is compatible
with alternative categories for quantifier phrases (§7.1). We may expect differences
within and across languages — say, with different quantifier words instantiating D,
a Q(uantifier) category, or a Top(ic) position, and some projecting while others not,
as in e.g. (8.40).
What is essential are the general functional heads n, n∗, criterial of noun phrases;
a position for specificity elements such as certain specific indefinites (relative/wh
words, etc.); and a position for number.
Although an FP may pick out an individual in the world supplied by the nP, not
all uses of expressions with at least the structure of an FP need have intuitively spe-
98
We will return to issues regarding choice-function elements within the nP in §§8.7–8.9.
163
cific readings or imply existence in the world of the discourse. Higher assignment-
binders internal or external to the noun phrase may generate local readings of a
choice-function pronoun, domain pronoun, or world pronoun (§§1, 7.1, 8.8.3).
In §§8.7.2, 8.8.3 we will see how local readings in choice-functional expressions
can generate nonspecific interpretations in intensional contexts. Specific indefinites
which are used as relative words, such as in various Gur languages, needn’t have
‘certain’-like readings when bound by the higher operator in a relative clause (§6.1;
Hiraiwa 2005). In (non-cardinal) quantifier phrases the selected individual varies
with the assignment-quantification introduced by the quantifier. I don’t see a useful
sense in which a postnominal genitive such as ‘cat of Alice’s’ in ‘some cat of Alice’s
or other’, or non-partitive quantifier phrases such as ‘every cat’ or ‘no one’, are
specific. (For this reason in what follows I will avoid Enç-style talk of “specificity,”
and reserve ‘specific’ for characterizing readings about a specific individual or group
of individuals.)
164
borne out. I am not aware of languages with quantifier words for ‘all’, ‘most’, etc.
that can be used nonpresuppositionally.99
What relevantly distinguishes quantifier words such as ‘no’, ‘many’, etc. is that
they can also be associated with denotations of the form in (8.23) and given the syn-
tax/semantics of a modifier in NumP. As we have seen, uses of δ# in such environ-
ments aren’t associated with “contextually given sets” (Enç 1991: 11) and needn’t
carry existential implications. Although their abstract semantics renders them com-
patible with both cardinal/modifier uses and quantificational uses, we should expect
there to be languages with words for some, many, etc. which lexically specify a
particular type of use. That is, we should expect there to be quantifier words for
such concepts which only have the type ⟨⟨s, et⟩, ⟨s, et⟩⟩ cardinal denotation — hence
can only be modifiers in structures of the form in (8.24)/(8.29)–(8.29) and be used
nonpresuppositionally — or only have the type ⟨⟨a, et⟩, ⟨⟨a, et⟩, t⟩⟩ quantificational
denotation — hence can only be assignment quantifiers in structures of the form in
(8.20)–(8.22) and be used presuppositionally. This prediction is also borne out.
As we saw in (8.22) from Milsark, unstressed ‘sm’ is of the former kind; ‘sm’ can
receive only the nonpresuppositional “reading of an indefinite number of people,”
hence its “nonsense” in (8.22) (Milsark 1977: 55). On the account in this section,
whereas ‘some’ can be interpreted as (8.41a), as in the Q+n∗P structure in (8.22),
‘sm’ is associated exclusively with the cardinal modifier entry, as reflected in (8.42)
(assuming the sigma type-shift option). (The particular modificational entry for
unstressed ‘some’ needn’t concern us here. ‘sm N’ doesn’t in general yield a count
99
I think it is sometimes underappreciated just how surprising this crosslinguistic tendency (if
not generalization) is. Enç’s response is representative (§7.1; Enç’s NP corresponds to our DP):
Why should universally quantifying NPs be specific? … It has often been noted that
universal quantifiers in natural languages quantify over contextually given sets…
If universal quantification is over contextually relevant sets of individuals, it follows
that NPs that quantify universally are specific… The characterization of universally
quantifying NPs as specific guarantees [that they presuppose existence].
(Enç 1991: 11; emphasis added)
There are reasons to be dissatisfied here. It might be one thing if all quantifier words were always
used presuppositionally with existence implications; but they aren’t. Prima facie, ‘no’ quantifications
would also seem to quantify over “contextually given sets”; yet ‘no’ patterns with positive existentials
in allowing nonpresuppositional uses. It would be striking if no language lexicalized a nonpresuppo-
sitional universal quantifier every∗/all∗ (≈ ‘all if any’) for which uses such as (i) would be felicitous.
(i) a. I have no idea whether there are aliens, but if many/all∗ aliens attack us, it will be a bad day.
b. Intended: ≈ “…if many/all aliens, if there are any, attack us …”
The general absence of such quantifiers follows from the proposed general structure of noun phrases
and syntax/semantics of quantifier words.
165
meaning in the manner suggested by (8.41b) (e.g. ‘sm water’); but for present
purposes I treat the modificational entry for ‘sm’ along the lines of the schema for
δ# in (8.23).)
“Nonsense” indeed.
On the flip side, quantifier words which correspond to paradigmatic “weak”
quantifiers in English, yet can only be used with existence implications, are attested
in various languages. In (8.3) from Enç 1991, we saw how Turkish bazɨ ‘some’ con-
trasts with English ‘some’ in being incompatible with existential ‘there’ constructions.
Faller & Hastings (2008) show that wakin in Cuzco Quechua functions essentially
as a strong quantifier; it cannot be used in existential ‘there’ sentences, in predicative
environments, or nonpresuppositionally, as in e.g. (8.43). Matthewson (1998,
2009) observes similar phenomena with St’át’imcets nukw, as in (8.44).
The words for some in such languages can be treated as the counterpart of ‘sm’ in
(8.42): ‘sm’ lexically specifies the modifier entry in (8.41b); expressions such as
166
wakin lexically specify an assignment-quantificational relational/proportional entry
such as (8.41a). The predicative use in (8.44) is ungrammatical since nukw lacks the
type-⟨set, set⟩ entry that would allow it to combine with type-⟨s, et⟩ ‘children’. (8.43)
with wakin can only be represented with a Q+n∗P structure such as (8.47), leading
to the (anomalous) presuppositional interpretation parallel to (8.20)–(8.22).
167
(8.48) a. *Wakin(/Askha/∗Llapan) llama-kuna chakra-pi ka-n.
some(/many/all) llama-pl field-loc be-3
‘There are some llamas in the field.’
(Faller & Hastings 2008: 283; Cuzco Quechua)
b. *Bahçe-de bazɨ(/ birkaç) çocuk-lar var.
ok
168
b. vP ∉ J K
The “key factor” excluding existential sentences such as those in (8.1)/(8.48) isn’t
presuppositionality per se but the structure of the noun phrase. The problem of
quantifier words in existential ‘there’ sentences is fundamentally a problem not of
logic (Keenan 1987, 2003), syntax (Safir 1985, Law 2011), or presupposition, but
of compositional semantics.
A sample derivation for a felicitous existential ‘There be Q N’ sentence is in
(8.50) (to be revised in §8.9). Suppose, following work by Partee & Borschev and
Francez, that existential ‘there’ sentences include a (possibly locational) pronoun
representing a relevant domain (Borschev & Partee 2002, Partee & Borschev
2007, Francez 2007, 2009, 2010; also Hartmann 2008, McCloskey 2014, Irwin
2018). The type-⟨e, t⟩ main predicate combines with the plural/locational pronoun
(cf. (8.8b), (8.24), n. 93).100
100
We will consider existential sentences with codas and revisit the syntax/semantics of nominal
pivots, the copula, and contextual domain element in §8.9 (see also nn. 90, 93). (In ‘There be YP
(ZP)’, the nominal YP is often called the “pivot,” and the ZP, if present, the “coda.”) See Francez
2007, 2009, 2010 for possible additional implicit structure in the element(s) determining the relevant
domain restriction. Given our purposes I bracket questions about the relation between the interpreted
plural/locational pronoun and overt grammatical subjects such as existential ‘there’ (see Hazout
2004, Hartmann 2008: §§2.2, 3.2, Tortora 2014: ch. 2 on comparisons between existential and
verbal ‘there’ sentences; cf. Moro 1997: 278n.14, Cresti & Tortora 2000: 71); and I ignore any
potential complications from distinguishing sorted variables for locations (see e.g. Kracht 2002).
Interestingly, whereas standard English exploits the otherwise-locative marker ‘there’, Appalachian
English uses the plural pronoun ‘they’ for the grammatical subject in existential sentences:
(i) They is something bad wrong with her.
(Montgomery & Hall 2004: lxii; Appalachian English)
Distinguishing the grammatical subject and the type-e pronoun may afford an analysis of existential
constructions in languages that use both an expletive subject and locative marker, as in (ii) with
French il y a. Another potential candidate might be the German locative da in existential construc-
tions with sein ‘be’ ((iii)). In existentials such as (iv) with a coda, the coda phrase is available to
serve as the V2-licenser, yielding the sein da order (the verb moved to C); in bare existentials such
as (iii)/(vii), V2 is licensed by da, yielding the da sein order. So, unlike es, which cannot follow
the tensed verb in existentials with ‘be’ ((iv)), da isn’t merely a syntactic expletive merged in Spec,C
to license V2 (Czinglar 2000, 2002, Hartmann 2008). As may be expected, in V-final clauses
da follows the complementizer and precedes middle-field elements such as the nominal pivot ((v)).
Existentials with ‘be’ in which da and the expletive es co-occur are also possible ((vi)); es is obligatorily
merged in Spec,C, and da remains in situ. Semantically, Hartmann (2008) reports that although
da’s locative meaning is largely bleached in existential sentences (cf. (vii)), da still makes a semantic
contribution. Unlike in languages such as French, an alternative impersonal existential construction
(es gibt) is available, and da retains a broadly locational flavor. (Thanks to Maja Spener and Merten
Reglitz for assistance with the data.)
169
(8.50) ‘There are three pillows’
a. [ S T⟨1,a⟩ [[Cd t1a ]⟨1,s⟩ [ vP o3e g1 [t1s [three# pillows]]]]]
170
b. JSK ≈ λgg . #x(g)[x(g) is a pillow in @(g−) ∧ x(g) ⊑ g−(3e)] ≥ 3
(preliminary)
Roughly put, the existential ‘there’ sentence in (8.50) with ‘three’ is true iff the
number of pillows in the relevant domain — pillows that are part of (the plural-
ity/location) gc (3e) — is at least three.
As is evident, there is nothing distinctly “existential” about so-called existen-
tial ‘there’ sentences on the above analysis (cf. Creissels 2014). (be) Q N is given
the syntax/semantics of a main predicate; the property expressed is predicated of
the pronoun which represents the relevant domain. The derived truth-condition in
(8.50) is equivalent to the intuitive quantificational condition that there is an o such
that o is a pillow ∧ . . . Yet there is no (implicit or explicit) existential quantification,
no “existence predicate,” no implication of property-instantiation, etc. (contrast e.g.
Milsark 1974, McNally 1997, 1998, 2009, Chung & Ladusaw 2004, Hartmann
2008, Sabbagh 2009, Law 2011, McCloskey 2014, Irwin 2018). This is for the
better. No innovations are required for existential ‘there’ sentences with nominals
expressing downward entailing (‘no/few Ns’) or non-monotone (‘exactly three Ns’)
quantificational concepts. The compositional semantics of (8.51) with ‘no’ is the
same as that of (8.50) with ‘three’.101
Roughly put, (8.51) is true iff the number of individuals o such that o is a pillow in
@(gc ) and o is part of the plurality gc (2e) representing the relevant domain is zero.
In (8.51) the relevant domain is contextually restricted — hence the coherence of
continuations such as ‘so we should go buy some’. Compare (8.52) where the rele-
vant domain gc (4e) corresponds to the domain of entities E. The derived semantic
value is contextually equivalent to the condition that no o′ ∈ E is a unicorn in @(gc ).
E might even be empty (cf. ‘There are no unicorns, because nothing exists’, possibly
true, never truly uttered).
101
Contrast the common talk of the “existential predicate” and “existential proposition”
(e.g. McNally 1997, 2011, 2016, Francez 2007, McCloskey 2014, Irwin 2018). E.g.: “the
assertion of an existential sentence has the effect of introducing an additional discourse referent
instantiating the argument of the existential predicate”; an existential “construction … does little
more than allow speakers to introduce a new individual into the discourse” (McNally 1997: 6, 2016:
212; cf. Kimball 1973: 265, Ward & Birner 1995, Payne 2009: 120, a.m.o.). (See Creissels 2014:
§2 for a helpful corrective.)
171
(8.52) There are no unicorns.
a. [ S T⟨1,a⟩ [[Cd t1a ]⟨1,s⟩ [ vP o4e g1 [t1s [no# unicorns]]]]]
b. JSK ≈ λgg . #x(g)[x(g) is a unicorn in @(g−) ∧ x(g) ⊑ g−(4e)] = 0
The derived semantic values for existential ‘There be no N’ sentences imply existence
of Ns no more than the semantic values for nonpresuppositional uses such as (8.29).
The account of nonpresuppositional uses proposed in this section treats the
type-⟨⟨s, et⟩, ⟨s, et⟩⟩ modifier δ# as basic, and derives the non-predicative meaning
for the nP from a general lexical rule or semantic type shift, as in (8.26)–(8.27).
Although type shifts are sometimes assumed to be universal, Partee herself was
careful not to make such an assumption (cf. Partee 1986b: 208). A natural question
is whether there are languages which lack the type-shifting operations in (8.26)–
(8.27). In such languages uses of quantifier words in non-predicative environments
would have exclusively non-cardinal readings. Interestingly, Matthewson reports
that quantifier words in St’át’imcets have obligatory cardinal readings in predicative
uses, and obligatory proportional readings in non-predicative uses, as reflected in
(8.53) (Matthewson 1998).
172
only available structure for (8.53b) is the structure with the complete n∗P, i.e. the
structure with the quantificational proportional entry for ‘many’, as in (8.55).102
Recall that our account distinguishes the existence implications derived with Q+n∗P
quantifier phrases generally from intuitively “specific” interpretations and semantic
definiteness. As discussed above, the determiner (here choice-function pronoun)
in St’át’imcets needn’t be notionally definite in the sense of presupposing that the
selected individuals in the relevant domain have been previously introduced in the
discourse (Matthewson 1998, 2009, 2013). However, given that St’át’imcets quan-
tifier words in non-predicative uses can only appear in complete Q+n∗P quantifier
phrases, our account does predict that all non-predicative uses will carry an existence
102
See Matthewson 1998: 353–358 on the specific proportional conditions associated with
quantificational cw7it; see Partee 1989b on proportional ‘many’ in English. In Tagalog, nonpre-
suppositional quantifiers cannot function as subjects in active transitive sentences, as reflected in
(i) with kaunti ‘few’; yet other types of argument-position uses are possible, as in the antipassive
construction in (ii).
(i) a. [kaunti]pred ang tao-ng uminon ng kape.
few sbj person-lnk agr.asp.drink nonsbj coffee
lit. ‘The people who drank coffee were few’ (‘Few people drank coffee’)
b. Uminom ng kape [ang bawa’t/∗kaunti-ng tao].
agr.asp.drink nonsbj coffee sbj each/∗few-lnk person
‘Each person/Few people drank coffee.’ (Sabbagh 2009: 707; Tagalog (Austronesian))
(ii) Nakakita ako roon ng marami-ng tao
perf.intr.see 1sg.sbj there nonsbj many-lnk person
‘I saw many people there’ (Sabbagh 2016: 655; Tagalog (Austronesian))
It would be interesting to check whether proportional readings of e.g. kaunti/maraming ‘few’/‘many’
in Tagalog are also unavailable in subject uses such as (i-b). If so, Tagalog would contrast with
St’át’imcets in lacking associated proportional/non-proportional entries for quantifier words/strings
expressing few, many, etc.
173
implication; as in examples such as (8.20), the (obligatory) determiner qua choice-
function pronoun in F above the nP selects an individual in the given world. Indeed
Matthewson 1998 glosses the enclitic portion …a of the determiner as encoding
“assertion of existence.”
Although Musan, following Enç (1981, 1987), focused primarily on tense and possi-
bilities for independent temporal interpretations, she notes that contrasts analogous
174
to those in (8.56)–(8.57) may be observed with worlds (Musan 1995: 219–220).103
Examples such as (8.58)–(8.59) support Musan’s generalization. (8.58), unlike
(8.59), is compatible with the non-sadistic (modally independent) reading — the
reading in which the world of the noun phrase is independent of the world of the
clause’s main predicate. In (8.60) Alice has a superior tactical strategy; Bert is
confused.
In (8.60a) the world relevant for interpreting ‘everyone on offense’ is the world of
103
Lecarme (1996, 1999b, 2004, 2008) shows that in nominal tense languages such as Somali
these interpretive possibilities are reflected in the morphology (§§7.1–7.2); indefinite noun phrases
in Somali are incompatible with interpreted tense morphemes, which would supply an independent
temporal interpretation. In some languages modally independent readings of noun phrases can also
be overtly marked, as in (i-b).
(i) a. [mee tabori -mete -mone jokana] clearing joro
3nonsg home.f far.past.nonwit.f rep.f real clearing(f) sit(du.sbj)
ni-kimi-ne-ke
aux-two-contin.f-decl.f
‘The two clearings of their reported past villages are there.’
b. [oko jibotee-ne] o-katomi-ne
1sg.poss spouse-irr.f 1sg.ag-fight.with-contin.f
‘I fight with (and kill) one who could have been my wife.’
(Dixon 2004: exs. 10.67–10.68; Jarawara (Arawan))
175
the discourse; Alice is saying that the team would play better if all of the players
actually playing on offense played defense instead. (8.60b) can only be interpreted
as saying that the relevant better worlds u are worlds in which some offensive players
in u are on defense in u; the world for ‘players on offense’ can only be the world of
the counterfactual possibility.
Like the distribution of (non)presuppositional readings, the distribution of modally
(temporally) (in)dependent noun phrases cannot be characterized simply at the
level of quantifier words/strings. The distinction between modally dependent and
modally independent interpretations isn’t equivalent to, say, the distinction between
weak and strong quantifiers. Whereas (8.61a) can receive the coherent reading
corresponding to Alice’s utterance in (8.60a), (8.61b) with the existential ‘there’
construction is incoherent.
What relevantly distinguishes (8.61b) (and (8.60b)) is that the existential ‘there’
construction forces the nonpresuppositional reading — on the analysis in this sec-
tion, the reading in which the quantifier word is in NumP and the noun phrase is
an nP. Examples such as (8.58)–(8.61) thus suggest that the possibility of receiving
a modally independent reading depends on having at least the structure of an FP
(cf. §6.1.3). The distinction between uses of quantifier words that can have modally
independent interpretations vs. those that cannot corresponds to the distinction
between structurally non-defective and defective noun phrases.
§4.2 applied our assignment-variable syntax/semantics to classic de re vs. de dicto
ambiguities in attitude ascriptions. The distinction between de re vs. de dicto read-
ings was diagnosed as a distinction between global vs. local readings of world-
pronouns, i.e. world-pronouns bound by T vs. the local assignment binder-index.
However, we can now see that not all embedded noun phrases can receive de re
(unshifted) readings in this sense. The world variables with nPs have obligatory
local (de dicto) readings. One strategy might be to revise our syntax/semantics
so that nPs lack a world-pronoun and receive their world-argument directly from
the main predicate; in an n∗P the world argument might be supplied by one of the
higher functional elements such as n∗. However, such an approach would require
treating verbal elements as systematically ambiguous with respect to the types of
their individual arguments — namely, depending on whether the argument is or is
not world-dependent; verbs can combine with both nPs and (Q+)n∗Ps. The treat-
176
ment of the relevant type-shifting operations for non-predicative uses of nPs would
also need to be revised to cohere with the revised entries for verbs.
A more promising approach is to explain the world-dependency of nPs as the
result of a purely syntactic process. The relevant generalization is that the world-
variable (if any) occupying n in an nP must be coindexed with the world-variable in
the closest v (cf. Rizzi 1990). No such constraint applies if the nP is embedded in a
larger noun phrase, i.e. if n doesn’t head the maximal projection of the noun. Given
that indices are features, the generalization amounts to the claim that the (subscript)
index-feature in n must agree with the (subscript) index-feature in the closest v
unless n is “blocked off” (in some sense to be made precise) by an intervening head,
such as n∗. These generalizations can be derived from the general architecture of
the current theory and agreement mechanisms in contemporary syntax.
For purposes of illustration consider a general phase-based framework, follow-
ing Chomsky (2000, 2001, 2008), in which syntactic derivations take place in small
chunks, phases, which provide the window for syntactic operations, such as fea-
ture matching/transmission (also e.g. Cecchetto 2004, Hiraiwa 2005, Kratzer
2009). Phases are characterized by various types of syntactic, semantic, and mor-
phophonological independence. In the clausal case the phases have been argued to
be (at least) v∗P and CP. Putting aside issues regarding possibilities for modal/temporal
independence, it is evident that any nominal phases are above nP. Arguments from
the literature for treating DP as a phase, such as regarding island constraints, may be
reframed as applying to the spread of functional projections above nP (see e.g. Adger
2003: ch. 10, Svenonius 2004, Hiraiwa 2005, Lee-Schoenfeld 2007; cf. Chomsky
2007: 26). Extraction is degraded from the specific indefinites, definites, and pre-
suppositional quantifier phrases in (8.62).
(8.62) a. Who did Alice say you saw a/sm/more than three picture(s) of?
b.*?Who did Alice say you saw the/a certain of?
c. *Who did Alice say you saw Bert’s/most picture(s) of?
(cf. Diesing 1992: 97–98)
As we saw in §6.1.3, specific indefinites can also receive world-independent (de re)
readings.104 The apparent gradation in unacceptability in (8.62b)–(8.62c) may
104
As Diesing puts it: “Thus, the ‘specificity’ effect is not due to a contrast between the definite and
indefinite determiners, or even between strong and weak determiners. Although extraction from an
NP with a strong determiner is generally bad, the acceptability of extraction from an NP with a weak
determiner hinges on their being no presuppositional reading available (or required) in the given
context” (Diesing 1992: 98).
177
support positing multiple nominal phases (cf. Kluender 1992, Svenonius 2004,
Kazuhiro 2010, Jiménez-Fernández 2012, Haegeman et al. 2014). Adjudicating
among such options needn’t concern us here; but for present purposes let’s assume
that at least FP is a phase.
(The relevant minimal nominal phase could also be treated as n∗P, where the
apparent phasal status of FP noun phrases such as specific indefinites is due to an
n∗P shell, i.e. [ n∗P n∗ [ FP F nP]]. The embedding n∗ would play its usual syntactic
functions, e.g. marking the FP as a noun phrase; nP is attracted to Spec,F, and
F raises to n∗ in the narrow syntax. Yet, unlike in genitive constructions, quan-
tifier phrases, etc., the n∗ head would be semantically empty (thus maintaining
the contrast between specific indefinites of type e and n∗Ps of type ⟨e, t⟩ in e.g.
postnominal genitives). Such an analysis would make the parallels between noun
phrases and verb phrases even more transparent: nP/vP are defective noun/verb
phrases, and n∗P/v∗P are nominal/verbal phases (cf. Chomsky 2007: 25–26). Given
our purposes I will ignore such potential semantically vacuous structure, and I will
speak of FP in [F nP] noun phrases as a nominal phase. The talk of “FP noun
phrases” and “FP phases” in what follows can be understood as short for [ n∗P n∗
[ FP F nP]] structures with a semantically vacuous n∗. We will return to these issues
in §§8.7–8.9.)
The modal dependence of nPs on the closest v, and modal independence of noun
phrases larger than nP, can be derived from feature transmission and the locality of
phases. There are various ways of formalizing the relevant syntactic notions that
would fit the bill. The definitions in (8.63)–(8.64) will suffice for our purposes
(see e.g. Chomsky 2000, 2001, 2007, Richards 2007, Heim 2008, Kratzer 2009,
Gallego 2010).
The Phase Impenetrability Condition encodes the idea that the complement of a
phase is only accessible to syntactic operations such as agreement from positions
inside the phase. Feature Checking (FC) says, roughly, that world-index features
178
in a verbal domain agree, where “verbal domains” are understood broadly as those
headed by elements with world features.105
The possibility for modally independent readings with FPs (n∗Ps, QPs) follows
straightway from PIC. The world-pronoun in n is inside the complement of the
nominal phase and thus inaccessible to feature-matching operations outside it, as
reflected in (8.65) (where H is the relevant nominal phase head in (8.65), and the
grayed-out nP complement indicates inaccessibility at a higher phase ZP, such as
v∗P or CP).
(8.65) [ ZP Z … [ HP H … [nP [n wk gj ] …
So, n can — and for compositional semantic purposes, must — enter the syntactic
derivation as a world-pronoun [wk gj ] with its own set of index-features. The world-
pronoun might end up being interpreted as identical to the local v, i.e. the world-
variable of the clause’s main predicate. Yet since the nominal phase head renders
n invisible from the positions of higher verbal functional heads, no coindexing or
interpretive equivalence is required.
Turning to nPs, there are two relevant positions to consider. If the nP originates
inside the vP, the agreement in world-index features is ensured by v in the v∗P phase
via Feature Checking (FC), as illustrated in (8.66) (where underlining indicates the
results of FC). The world-variable in n is c-commanded by v; and, since n and v are
in the same v∗P phase, n is visible for syntactic operations to v; hence the feature
sets agree by FC yielding the coindexed variables representing the feature-set with
[i], [s].
179
definition of PIC, the nP in the edge (specifier) of the v∗P phase is visible from
the local C position and accessible to operations such as FC. So, the world-variable
in n is in the domain of the local C; since n is in Spec,v∗, n is visible for syntactic
operations from C; and C has feature s; hence, by FC, the feature sets agree, yielding
the coindexed variable with the feature-set with [i], [s], as in (8.67) (the grayed-out
vP complement of v∗ again indicating inaccessibility at the CP phase).
⟨i,s⟩
(8.67) [ CP C0 … [ v∗P [ nP n0is … ] [v∗ vP]]]
In either case, since feature checking applies only at the phase-level, n’s index cannot
be determined via agreement with a v or C in a higher clause, as reflected in (8.68)
(order of the embedded n and v irrelevant).
⟨i,s⟩
(8.68) [ v∗P … v0ks … [CP C0 … n0is … v0is … ]]
The locality of phases ensures that the world-variable in n is coindexed with the
closest v.
An agreement-based account of modally dependent readings of nPs along these
lines is compatible with alternative theories of agreement. Understanding agree-
ment in terms of feature-matching might be most natural, yet theories with feature
copying or feature merging/unification (Barlow 1992, Kratzer 2009) are also
possible. Although feature agreement construed as unification is in principle neutral
with respect to the direction of feature transmission, our compositional semantics
severely constrains the possible n’s that can enter the syntactic derivation in nP noun
phrases. Insofar as the complementizer raises for type reasons from v, v will be a
fully specified variable, say tis , and thus won’t be able to receive index features from
n. If n enters the derivation with a feature-set including [d], for some number d ≠ i
or type d ≠ s, then at minimum n won’t be interpretable after FC since variables with
multiple numerical or type indices aren’t interpretable (§2). The only possibilities
in our current system are (i) for n to enter the structure with a matching feature-set,
n0is ; (ii) for n to be empty (ignoring other elements such as category features); and
perhaps, depending on how exactly numerical and type features are delineated,
(iii) for n to enter the structure minimally specified for type, n0s . In case (i), FC
amounts to checking. In case (iii) (if possible), n receives v or C’s numerical index
and becomes an interpretable variable syntactically/semantically bound by C. And
in case (ii), n lacks a world feature and thus isn’t recognised as a target for FC.106
106
Case (ii) might be understood as applying to examples such as (8.8b), (8.24), (8.50)–(8.52)
where the nominal provides the clause’s main predicate, as reflected in (i). Alternatively, the
complementizer might be treated as raising directly from n0 , as in (ii).
180
A derivation with a modally dependent nP in an attitude ascription is in (8.69).
The boxes indicate the result of agreement from FC in the lower CP phase. (I
continue to ignore v∗ for purposes of the semantics; I assume the simplified cardinal
entry for ‘sm’ from (8.41b); and I leave ‘friends-of-mine’ unanalyzed.)
⟨i,s⟩
(i) C0 … [ vP v0is [ nP n∅ NumP]]
⟨i,s⟩
(ii) C0 … [ vP v [ nP [ n0 tis ] NumP]]
In (ii) the predicate nominal is “nominal” in having the category of the root determined by n (and
having interpretable φ-features), and “predicative” in having its world-features determined directly
by the (type-driven) movement of the complementizer. The sort of upward φ-feature propagation to
the verbal/clausal domain discussed in Hazout 2004 follows straightway (see also nn. 92, 93).)
In either configuration, note that the overt movement of the complementizer from inside the
vP is consistent with the phase-based model. Following Chomsky (e.g. 2001: 13–14), the com-
plement of a phase becomes inaccessible to further syntactic operations when the next higher
phase is assembled. Hence a vP undergoes spell-out only after the complementizer raises and is
⟨i ,s ⟩
(re)merged to the structure, forming the CP, [ CP C0 … [ v∗P v∗ … tis … ]]. (We will reconsider
world-agreement with other types of predicative uses and with relative clauses in §§8.7–8.9. In-
terestingly, the above sorts of v+nP analyses of predicate nominals are effectively a mirror image
of the n+vP analysis of nominal ‘of-ing’ nominalizations in Harley 2009: 337. Comparisons with
other types of nominalizations may provide interesting avenues to explore (cf. also Marantz 1997,
Alexiadou 2001b, Hiraiwa 2005).)
181
(8.69) ‘Bert thinks sm friends of mine smoke.’
S
T⟨1,a⟩
⟨1,s⟩
Bert
Cd t1a
t1s
thinks⟨2,a⟩ CP
⟨2,s⟩ v∗P
Cd t2a
nP
(v∗) vP
(σ ) t2s smoke
u2s NumP
sm F-o-M
This says, roughly, that for all possibilities h compatible with Bert’s state of mind,
the number of o that are friends of mine in @(h) and included among the smokers
in @(h) is at least one. The embedded subject nP ‘sm friends-of-mind’ is in the
edge position of the lower v∗P phase. The n0 with feature [s] is thus visible from
the position of the embedding complementizer and accessible for operations such
as FC. The nominal predicate’s world-variable is coindexed with C’s binder-index
182
by agreement, and so, by extension, with the world-trace left from the type-driven
movement of the complementizer from v of the clause’s main predicate.107
The account of modally (in)dependent readings of noun phrases in this section
highlights a crucial feature of our general syntactic/semantic architecture from §3.
The above account offers a purely syntactic basis for the obligatory local (modally
dependent) readings of certain uses of noun phrases, those with the structure of
an nP. One might wonder whether the obligatory local reading of the clause’s main
predicate might be captured by the same sort of general agreement mechanism,
and thus whether we could do away with the type-driven movement of the com-
plementizer. The answer is “no.” In clauses with complete verb phrases, v∗P, the
verb’s world-argument position inside the vP is invisible from the position of the
complementizer or an embedding modal, as reflected in (8.70). Regardless of how
exactly the compositional semantics would proceed, the world variable wi inside the
complement of the v∗P phase is inaccessible for feature agreement with the higher
C or mod.
107
The LF and derived truth conditions in (8.69) represent a “nonspecific de dicto” reading in the
sense of §4.2; (8.69) ascribes to Bert a belief that I have friends and some or other of them smoke.
Since ‘think’ isn’t a scope island (unlike ‘if’ in (8.58)–(8.61)), one might expect the noun phrase to
be able to take wide scope with respect to the attitude verb. In such a case, the nP’s world variable
is coindexed with the matrix complementizer by FC in the higher CP phase; the attitude ascription
would be true iff the number of actual friends of mine o′ such that, for all possibilities h′ compatible
with Bert’s state of mind, o′ is included among the smokers in @(h′ ), is at least one. In §4.2 we saw
that certain noun phrases, such as those with indefinite ‘a’, can also receive so-called “nonspecific
de re” readings — readings in which the noun phrase takes narrow scope and its world argument
receives a global reading, as in (4.7), reproduced below:
(i) Alice thinks a friend of mine will win.
● nonspecific de re ≈ “there is some group of individuals who are friends of mine (say, the
Sharks) such that Alice thinks some or other of them will win”
Unlike noun phrases with ‘a’, noun phrases with ‘sm’ are exclusively nPs. So, we should expect
nonspecific de re readings to be generally unavailable with ‘sm’ and other nonpresuppositional uses
of weak quantifiers. This seems to be borne out. Nonspecific de re readings in (8.58)–(8.61) (where
nonspecificity is forced by the scope island) are apparently unavailable. Examples such as (ii) with
attitude ascriptions are similarly strained.
(ii) [Context: There’s a group of friends of mine, the Sharks, and Bert thinks some or other of them
are after him, but he doesn’t know who. Bert doesn’t think I have any friends.]
#Bert thinks there are sm friends of mine after him.
The embedded nP’s world argument is coindexed with the local complementizer by agreement. The
contrast in possibilities for nonspecific de re readings falls out of the general account of possibilities
for modally independent readings (non-local readings of world arguments) with nPs vs. n∗Ps.
183
(8.70) mod [ CP C … [ v∗P … [vP … wi … ]]]
184
with relative clause complements might be extended to other types of quantified
expressions. In §§7.1–7.2 I suggested that the proposed D+XP syntax may provide
a common basis for certain notions of specificity from the literature. This section
has examined the internal syntax and compositional semantics more carefully with
an aim of developing a more general assignment-variable-based account of noun
phrases. The proposed account coheres with current work in syntax on parallels
between noun phrases and verb phrases; it provides precise derivations for var-
ious properties often going under headings of “specificity” and the weak/strong
quantifier distinction — e.g., existence implications, contextual domain restriction,
notional definiteness, compatibility with predicative uses and existential ‘there’ sen-
tences, and modal independence; and it captures various data involving local/global
readings with different types of quantificational expressions, in English and in cer-
tain other languages. I hope that these features may provide a fruitful contribution
to broader crosslinguistic work on the syntax and compositional semantics of noun
phrases and quantifier words.
Key features of the account are as follows. Contrasts between broadly non-
presuppositional and presuppositional uses are captured in terms of the structural
complexity of the noun phrase. First, noun and verb phrases are given a parallel
basic structure. The light noun/verb n/v provides the locus of world variables.
nP noun phrases represent nonpresuppositional readings and provide the nominal
analogue of “defective” vPs. The syntax/semantics of [n NumP] noun phrases is fun-
damentally predicative. Cardinal readings of numerals and certain quantifier words
are represented as modifiers in NumP, yielding a property-type denotation (perhaps
analogous to how aspectual heads may modify the verb in a verb phrase). In predi-
cate nominals the world argument is supplied by the world-trace from the movement
of the complementizer, (cf. (8.8b), (8.24), (8.50)–(8.52), (8.135), n. 106; more
on this in §8.9). In non-predicative uses the world-variable in n is determined by
agreement with the local v in the v∗P phase or with the local C in the CP phase. In
both cases the world argument for the noun phrase is derived to be identical with
the world argument of the clause’s main predicate (cf. (8.66)–(8.69)). The modal
dependence of nonpresuppositional noun phrases — the obligatory local reading of
the nominal predicate’s world argument — follows from the proposed nP analysis,
the general clausal architecture from §3, and independent syntactic mechanisms
(e.g., feature transmission, PIC).
What distinguishes presuppositional uses of noun phrases is that the nP is in-
tegrated in a larger structure. We delineated three relevant heads above nP (per-
haps among others; cf. (8.40)): F, for elements such as specific indefinites, certain
uses of relative/wh words, and implicit choice-function elements, perhaps along
185
with certain uses of definite articles and other determiners (§7.1); n∗, for elements
such as the genitive morpheme and certain (possibly implicit) case-assigning ele-
ments (§7.2); and Q, for certain uses of quantifier words. Various “specificity”-
related phenomena are derived from characteristic properties of positions in the
larger structure.
The modal independence of specific indefinites, definites, and presuppositional
uses of quantifier words — the possibility for non-local readings of the nominal’s
world argument — is an instance of the general syntactic/semantic independence of
the nominal phase (see §8.5). Since the world-argument position in n is inaccessible
for agreement operations with an outside verbal head, the world argument may —
and, for compositional semantic reasons, typically must — be supplied by a world-
pronoun. The interpretation of the world-pronoun may or may not be identified
with the world of the clause’s main predicate. So, de re (global) readings of nominal
predicates embedded under a modal are predicted to be available only with noun
phrases having at least the structure of [(n∗) FP] (cf. §4.2).
The analysis delineates the sources of specific readings, existence implications,
and notional definiteness. Insofar as the F head selects an individual from the set
denoted by the nP, [FP F nP] structures are characteristically associated with specific
readings and existence implications (cf. (8.20)–(8.22)). In larger noun phrases
the quantification introduced by a higher element may lead to readings that aren’t
intuitively specific, in the sense of being about a particular individual. In embedded
contexts such as attitude ascriptions, the existence implication may be relative to
a local domain (cf. §§1, 7.1, 8.8.3). The n∗ head, analogous to v∗ in complete
verb phrases, may provide a source of contextual domain restriction (cf. (8.22),
§§7.1–7.2). Importantly, such elements in the FP or n∗P needn’t be associated with
semantic definiteness. Absent additional semantic definiteness features or lexical
constraints, the relevant individual or set of individuals denoted by an FP or n∗P
may or may not be “familiar,” in the sense of having been previously introduced
in the discourse (§§7.1, 8.3). Further consideration of how notional definiteness
phenomena may be implemented with different expressions and uses is called for.
Finally, “true” quantifiers — nominal elements with a quantificational seman-
tics — provide the locus of proportional readings and assignment quantification.
As in the previous sections, the quantifier word is base-generated in a relevant inter-
nal assignment-argument position, such as in F0 , and raises as the maximal element
of the nominal layer. I suggested that the distinction between “weak” vs. “strong”
quantifiers corresponds to a distinction between quantifier words that can vs. cannot
function as modifiers in NumP. Strong quantifiers across languages are predicted
to be those which express inherently relational quantificational concepts, such as
186
‘all’, ‘each’, ‘most’. Their abstract semantics and the general syntactic architecture
predict that they can only be used in QPs, and thus that they will be invariably exhibit
properties such as presuppositionality, proportional readings, independence, etc.
What relevantly distinguishes weak quantifiers is that they express quantificational
concepts that they can be associated with cardinal modifier entries such as (8.23);
insofar as they can function as number modifiers, they can be used in the sorts of nP
structures which give rise to predicative and nonpresuppositional uses. Although
their abstract semantics may be compatible with modifier and quantificational en-
tries, languages may have forms which are only associated with a particular entry —
e.g., forms expressing some that are exclusively number modifiers, and thus can
only be used in (predicative) nPs with nonpresuppositional, cardinal, dependent
readings; or forms expressing some that are exclusively quantificational, and thus
can only be used in QPs with presuppositional, proportional readings (cf. (8.41)–
(8.49)). Some languages may lack the lexical or semantic type shift for nPs ((8.26)–
(8.27)), leading to systematic correlations between predicative/non-predicative en-
vironments and cardinal/proportional readings ((8.53)–(8.55)). Although I treated
the quantifier words as heading QPs, an alternative is to treat them as adjoining
to n∗P; delineating other categories for elements above n∗ may also be called for
(cf. (8.40); see also §10.3). It might not be surprising if the distinction between
quantifier words that are necessarily quantificational (i.e., inherently or lexically
specified strong quantifiers) and those that aren’t was grammaticalized in certain
languages. Phenomena such as compatibility with different types of existential
sentences call for more careful investigation (more on which in §8.9).
A central feature of our assignment-variable-based account is that it helps cap-
ture various types of local and global readings of broadly context-dependent ex-
pressions. Yet just as important for an overall theory is to provide explanations
for why certain readings may be systematically not available. We have seen that
different mechanisms may apply in different cases. For instance, for the obligatory
local reading of the world argument of a clause’s main predicate, §3 offered a move-
ment-based explanation (cf. §8.1): the complementizer is base-generated in the
world-argument position (now identified as little v) and moves for type reasons as a
quantifier over worlds; and the interpretation of the world variable is determined by
an embedding modal element, which raises as a quantifier over assignments from
an internal argument in C0 . Obligatory local/global readings of particular expres-
sions may be determined by lexical constraints — e.g., that a relevant pronoun’s
assignment-variable be bound by the local or topmost assignment-binder (§4.3.3).
For some expressions, such as perhaps epistemic modals, the relevant lexical con-
straints might be explainable in terms of the truth-conditional content and general
187
features of contexts of use (cf. Blutner 2004, Leckie 2013, Silk 2016a, 2017);
for other expressions, the constraints may be language-specific and idiosyncratic
(cf. §8.4). Third, in §8.5 I suggested that the modal/temporal dependence of non-
presuppositional noun phrases (Musan 1995) — the obligatory local readings of
world arguments in nPs — may have a purely syntactic explanation. Appealing to
multiple explanatory mechanisms in these ways shouldn’t be regarded as a defect.
Indeed we should expect the different parts of the theory — narrow syntax, lexical
and compositional semantics, pragmatics — to (conventionally) constrain interpre-
tation in different ways. A linguistic theory with assignment variables can provide
compositional derivations of the varieties of local and global readings, while offering
principled bases for reining in the flexibility of the system.
8.7 A revised analysis of relative clauses: Internal heads and intensional gaps
Now that our more general assignment-variable-based analysis of noun phrases is on
the table, let’s revisit the issues raised for the account of restrictive relative clauses
from §6. The analysis in §6.1 treats the relative phrase as originating in Spec,Crel ,
and the relative complementizer as moving from the gap position as a quantifier over
individuals. Yet §6.3 raised critical syntactic and semantic issues for any account
along these lines. In particular, it is hard to see how a syntax/semantics in which the
relative phrase originates external to the relative IP could apply to languages with
circumnominal relative constructions, or capture intensional gap readings, in which
the nominal predicate’s world argument receives a non-global reading under an
IPrel -internal element, as in (6.56) and (6.59)–(6.63), reproduced in (8.71)–(8.72).
(8.71) a. [CPrel Atia n da’ [bua seka] da’a zaam] la bɔi mɛ.
Atia c buy.perf goat rel market yesterday d lose.perf prt
(lit. ‘The [Atia bought which goat at the market yesterday] got lost.’)
‘The goat that Atia bought at the market yesterday got lost.’
(Hiraiwa et al. 2017: 5; Gurenɛ (Niger-Congo))
b. [Mary [taku/∅] ka� � e] ki ophewathų.
Mary something make the I.buy
(lit. ‘I bought the [Mary made (something)]’)
‘I bought what Mary made.’
(Williamson 1987: 188–189n.4; Lakhota (Siouan))
(8.72) Callie wants to hug every unicorni which Timmy thinksi he found __.
188
§6 developed an improved assignment-variable-based compositional semantics
for head-raising analyses. The remainder of this section outlines an alternative
“matching” analysis that maintains the features of the §6-account and avoids the
bugs. Matching analyses agree with head-raising analyses that the relative phrase
originates inside the relative clause; however, matching analyses posit that the
nominal head also has an independent representation external to CPrel (Lees 1960,
Carlson 1977, Sauerland 1998, 2003, 2004, Bhatt 2002; see also Cinque 2013,
2015 for comparisons with raising analyses). Although one of the “internal” and
“external” heads is in general deleted in the phonological component, both are
semantically interpreted. The following matching account captures the data from
§6.2 with donkey sentences, as well as shifting phenomena with intensional gap
readings and further crosslinguistic data with circumnominals. The treatment of
restrictive relative clauses is layered directly into the general syntax/semantics for
noun phrases developed in this section.
(8.73) a.*?Who did you say there are sm/many/three pictures of which Alice likes?
b. There are sm/many/three pictures of Bert which Alice likes.
c. Who did you say there are sm/many/three pictures of (in the newspaper)?
(8.74) ‘cats of Alice’s’
[ n∗P [R-g Alice] [ n∗ ’s [Fcf -tia cats]]]
(8.75) “Matching” structure (schematic)
[ n∗P [ CPrel … [Fcf -tia (n) NumP] …] [n∗ [Fcf -tia (n) NumP]]]
(8.76) ‘cats which are owned by Alice’
≈ [ n∗P [ CPrel … whcf -tia cats are owned by Alice] [ n∗ n∗ [Fcf -tia cats]]]
189
A matching structure for relative clauses falls out of our general approach to modi-
fication and the syntax/semantics of noun phrases.109
In languages with double-headed circumnominal relative constructions (Dryer
2005, Heath 2008, Cinque 2013: ch. 17, 2017), the structure in (8.75) may be
equivalent to the pronounced form, as in (8.77b)–(8.78). In Kombai (8.77) the
connective marker -o in double-headed relatives is the same marker used with gen-
itives, as well as other types of prenominal modifiers. In Jamsay (8.78) the particle
mediating the relative clause and external head is a possessive morpheme (cf. Dixon
1969, 1972, Matisoff 1972, Gil 2013, Nikolaeva & Spencer 2013, Thurgood
& LaPolla 2017). The relative clause functions analogously to the structural “pos-
sessor” in free R genitives, delimiting the relevant domain (see n. 70, §§7.2, 8.2).
(8.77) a. momof-o lã
uncle-conn wife
‘uncle’s wife’
b. [doü adiyano-n-o doü] deyalukhe
sago give.3pl.nonfut-tr-conn sago finished.adj
‘the sago that they gave’
(de Vries 1993: 77–78; Kombai (Trans–New Guinea))
(8.78) [[ ìjɛ̀ è íjɛ́ bèrɛ̂ː] mà ìjɛ́]
position 2pl stand can.impf-ppl.nonhum poss position
‘the position (/situation) where you stand’
(Heath 2008: 481; Jamsay (Niger-Congo))
190
first approximation, the relative phrase inside the relative clause can be formed as
a copy of the [Fcf -g n Num N] complement of n∗ (see Sauerland 2004, Cinque
2013: ch. 17 for potential complications). In light of data such as (8.71) with
circumnominals, the relative phrase is now treated as originating in the gap position
inside the relative clause. The remainder of the relative clause can be constructed
largely like main clauses. The relative clause’s main predicate can be interpreted
independently of a matrix modal (or tense) (cf. n. 75).
One option would be to treat the main predicate’s world argument as supplied by a
world-pronoun (as in §6) and treat the relative complementizer as generated in its
interpreted position. Alternatively, the relative complementizer might be analyzed
like other types of complementizers as raising from little v as a quantifier over
worlds; however, the complementizer’s internal assignment argument would be
supplied by an assignment variable representing the relevant local/global reading of
the main predicate. Examples such as (8.80)–(8.81) may provide (theory-internal)
evidence against the former option. (8.80b) is sad; (8.80a) is disturbing.
(8.80) a. In the sixties, few children who sm senatorsi/∗k bulliedi were invited to
their birthday parties.
b. In the sixties, few children who most senators bullied were invited to
their birthday parties.
(8.81) [Context: Bert doesn’t think there are spies, but we know better.]
Bert thinks that if people who most/#sm spies are friends with come to the
party, it will be fun.
191
So, for uniformity with our analyses of other types of clauses, let’s assume the
implementation reflected in (8.82a). What distinguishes individual relative clauses
in nominals from matrix clauses and subordinate clauses in verbal environments is
that the modal domain isn’t determined by type-driven movement of an embedding
modal assignment-quantifier; the relevant embedding element is the assignment-
quantifier determining the individual domain (more on which below). A revised
structure for the n∗P is in (8.83).
In this way, noun phrases with headed relative clauses are given the structure
of any other n∗P. There are various approaches one might take regarding the com-
positional semantics. Presumably the relative IP is type t, as usual. If we assume
for simplicity that any modifiers in specifier positions are type ⟨e, t⟩ (see n. 65), one
straightforward option would be to give Crel the same semantics as Cd but with an
additional (vacuous) individual argument. A preliminary derivation is in (8.84).
(I will continue to ignore v∗ for introducing external individual arguments, and
I leave open which of the internal/external heads represents the head ultimately
deleted in the phonological component.)
192
(8.84) ‘Every cat which meowed jumped.’
S
T⟨1,a⟩
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a
vP
CPrel
X FP
⟨2,s⟩
nP
F2cf t2a
Crel g1 FP vP
w1 -g1 cat
t2s meowed
nP
wh2cf t2a
w1 -g1 cat
JCrel K = λaa .λpst .λxe .λgg . ∀ws = λg′g .@(a(g′ )), p(w)(g)
JCPrel K ≈ λxe .λgg . g(2a)(2cf)(catg(1a)(1s) ) meowed in @(g(1a))
Jn∗PK ≈ λxe .λgg . x(g) = g(2a)(2cf)(catg(1a)(1s) ) ∧ g(2a)(2cf)(catg(1a)(1s) )
meowed in @(g(1a))
JSK ≈ λgg . ∀x∀a∶ (x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(catg−(1s) ) ∧ a(g)(2cf)(catg−(1s) )
meowed in @(g−)) → x(g) jumped in @(g−)
In contrast to the head-raising account from §6, the present matching account af-
fords a unified syntax/semantics for quantifier words with relativized and non-rel-
ativized complements: as in §§7.1–7.4, the matrix quantifier in (8.83) raises from
the internal assignment argument of the choice-function pronoun and takes a nom-
193
inal complement.110 The assignment-variable g1 in C0rel is bound by the topmost
assignment-binder, which anchors the interpretation of the relative clause’s main
predicate ‘meowed’ to the world of the discourse. Roughly put, the matrix quan-
tifier quantifies over those individuals o for which there is some choice function F
such that F selects o from among the actual cats (=catgc (1s) ), and F(catgc (1s) ) (=o)
meowed. Insofar as the relative phrase in the “gap position” is formed as a copy of
the external FP, both conditions are derived as conditions on the same individual
o = F(catgc (1s) ). The sentence is true iff every such o jumped.
The account of donkey anaphora from §6.2 carries over to the above matching
analysis. The donkey pronoun in (6.24), reproduced in (8.85), is represented as a
copy of its linguistic antecedent; the assignment-binding introduced by the quanti-
fier captures the apparent anaphoric connection (n. 109). (I continue to assume the
“universal donkey” entry for the quantifier (§§6.2.1–6.2.2).)
194
[ n∗P [ CPrel [Crel g1 ]⟨2,s⟩ [[ FP wh2 -t2a w1 -g1 -baby] [ vP t2s got a3 -g2 toy-w1 -g1 ]]]
[X [ FP wh2 -t2a w1 -g1 -baby]]]]
[ vP t1s liked it3 -g2 toy-w1 -g1 ]]]]
b. JSK ≈ λgg . ∀xe ∀aa ∶ (x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(babyg−(1s) ) ∧ a(g)(2cf)(babyg−(1s) )
got a(g)(3cf)(toyg− (1s) ) in @(g−)) →
x(g) liked a(g)(3cf)(toyg− (1s) ) in @(g−)
The derived truth condition is equivalent to that derived with the head-raising anal-
ysis in §6.2.1.
195
(8.86) Callie thinks that the monsteri which Timmy thinksi Alice found ate Fluffy.
S
T⟨1,a⟩
⟨1,s⟩
Callie
Cd t1a
t1s
thinks⟨2,a⟩ CP
⟨2,s⟩
that t2a
vP
the⟨4,a⟩ n∗P
t2s ate Fluffy
CPrel
X FP
⟨4,s⟩
Timmy
Crel g2 F2cf t4a
t4s
w1 -g??? monster
thinks⟨3,a⟩ CP
⟨3,s⟩
Alice
Cd t3a
t3s
found FP
wh2 t4a
w1 -g??? monster
Informally, (8.86) ascribes to Callie a belief that the thing o which is a monster and
found by Alice in Timmy’s belief-worlds ate Fluffy. The worry is that no represen-
tation of the internal/external world-pronouns seems to capture the target read-
ings implying that (Callie thinks that) Timmy believes in monsters. Identifying the
196
world-pronoun with [w1 g1 ], bound by the topmost assignment-binder, represents
the global (de re) reading that implies the existence of monsters. Identifying the
world-pronoun with [w1 g2 ], bound by the higher attitude verb, fails to capture
Timmy’s belief that the individual is a monster; the individual which Callie thinks ate
Fluffy would be an individual that is a monster in Callie’s belief-worlds, though not
necessarily in Timmy’s. Representing the world-pronoun as [w1 g3 ] would correctly
link the interpretation of the internal nominal head ‘monster’ to Timmy’s belief-
worlds; however, the external head wouldn’t be bound since the attitude verb is
inside the relative IP.
The challenge is to capture the local reading of the internal head under the IP-
internal attitude verb, while still determining the domain of quantification via the
external head. Let’s start by revisiting the internal structure of the relative phrase.
In §6 we noted that it is crosslinguistically common for relative and wh words to be
morphologically related to indefinites (e.g. de Vries 2002, Bhat 2004). Thus far
we have been representing the relative phrase parallel to specific indefinites, with
an independently supplied world-pronoun. However, just as there are indefinite
elements in nP and n∗P noun phrases, so too, we might expect, for relative or wh
elements.
Suppose, as a first step, that the relative phrase in intensional gap readings is an
nP. Let’s assume as a working hypothesis that the world-variable (if any) is supplied
after any modification of the noun as the highest element in the nP — schematically,
[nP w wh-g Num N]. For present purposes we can leave open what specific position
the intensional choice-function element occupies above Num. One option would be
to posit an alternative F (focus?) position under n, as reflected in (8.87).111
111
Cf. e.g. Harley 2009, 2013, 2017, Ramchand 2017 on functional projections FP between (our)
v and v∗, and between v and V. Alternatively Fcf∗ might be treated in Spec,Num or adjoined to NumP.
In circumnominals such as (i) the number word occurs between the noun and relative morpheme.
(i) a. Amok ale da [mango-ta ŋa-nu tii] diem la
Amok c bought mango-pl cl.pl-five rel yesterday dem
‘the five mangos that Amok bought yesterday’ (Hiraiwa 2005: 221; Bùlì)
b. A [mongo-ri ata na] Dakoraa nang da
d mango-pl three rel Dakoraa c buy
‘the three mangoes that Dakoraa bought’ (Hiraiwa et al. 2017: 20; Dàgáárè)
197
(8.87) ⋮
n∗P
n∗ (FP)
(F) nP
Fcf g n (FP)
(F) NumP
Fcf∗ g
Choice-function elements under n can be analyzed as (what we might call) inten-
sional choice function pronouns Fcf∗ — pronouns for functions F∗ ∶ [W → [E → T]] → EW
from properties P to individual concepts o∗ that manifest P. One might posit a
principle such as (8.88) requiring that F∗(P)(u) ∈ P(u), for any u (cf. Ojeda 1993,
Chierchia 1998); the value F∗ of an intensional choice-function pronoun, on this
line, maps a property P to a (possibly non-atomic) part of the maximal P(u)-individual.
(We will revisit the status of such a constraint shortly.)112
Treating the relative phrase as an nP has non-trivial implications for the inter-
pretation of the world argument. Since nP isn’t a nominal phase, the account in
§8.5 predicts that its world-variable is determined by feature transmission FC with
the local verbal head ((8.63)–(8.64)). First, the resulting structure for the relative
112
Intensional choice functions in the sense of (8.88) might be compared to Chierchia’s (1998)
∩
operator, as reflected in (i). For a property P, or function from worlds u to sets of individuals
P(u), ∩ P (if defined) is the function from worlds u to the maximal P(u)-individual, i.e. the individual
concept λu.ιP(u).
(i) For any world u ∈ W and property P ∶ W → E → T in the domain of ∩ :
F∗(P)(u) ⊑ (∩ P)(u)
where ∩ P ∶= λu.ιP(u)
In Chierchia’s account of nominalization, applying ∩ to the property denotation of a bare noun
shifts it to a kind-level denotation — represented as an individual concept — which can serve as
an individual argument (see also Partee 1986a,b, Chierchia 1988, Ojeda 1993). An intensional
choice function pronoun is, in effect, a choice-functional lexicalization of ∩ , generalized to apply to
properties with/without corresponding kinds. Chierchia treats the individual concepts representing
kinds as type e; for our purposes intensional choice functions can be typed as ⟨⟨s, et⟩, se⟩.
198
clause CPrel is as follows (again ignoring v∗ and using underlining to indicate the
result of FC).
⟨3,a⟩
(8.89) [ CPrel [Crel g2 ]⟨4,s⟩ Timmy [thinks t4s ]
[ CP [Cd t3a ]⟨3,s⟩ Alice [ vP t3s found [ nP u3s wh2cf∗-t4a monster]]]]
Insofar as the relative phrase is interpreted in its base position, the world argument
is supplied by a [+s] variable that agrees with the local c-commanding v in the
v∗P phase. By FC this yields a variable of type s with numerical index feature 3 —
i.e., a world-variable bound by the local complementizer under ‘Timmy thinks …’
The internal head’s world argument is thus anchored by agreement to the attitude
state representing Timmy’s beliefs.
The external head originates as the complement of n∗. One approach might be
to treat the world argument as determined by FC via some movement to the edge
of QP, as reflected in (8.90). The world-variable in the external head would be
determined as u2s , anchored to the local modal domain representing Callie’s beliefs.
⟨2,s⟩
(8.90) (… Callie thinks …) C0I … [ QP … [ n u2s ] … Q …]
However, we needn’t assume that the external nP’s world argument must be de-
termined via movement/agreement. A critical question is whether, in examples
with intensional gap readings, the world argument of the external head can itself
receive a modally independent interpretation. Examples such as (8.91) may provide
preliminary support. Callie’s utterance makes a claim about a certain actual monster
o, and implies that things would be better if o wasn’t a monster. Yet the belief
ascribed to Timmy is still de dicto and nonspecific.
(8.91) [Context: Callie believes in monsters. She thinks that Timmy thinks Alice
found some monster or other, but that he doesn’t know which. Callie says:]
It would be better if the monster which Timmy thinks Alice found wasn’t a
monster.
Treating the external head’s world argument as being independently supplied al-
lows for such interpretations. The world-pronoun supplying the external nP’s world
argument would be bound by a non-local assignment-binder.
To fix ideas I assume the latter analysis, where the world argument of the
external head is supplied by a world-pronoun. The resulting revised LF and semantic
value for (8.86) is as follows:
199
(8.92) S
T⟨1,a⟩
⟨1,s⟩
Callie
Cd t1a
t1s
thinks⟨2,a⟩ CP
⟨2,s⟩
that t2a
vP
∗
the⟨4,a⟩ nP
t2s ate Fluffy
CPrel
X nP1
⟨4,s⟩
Timmy w1 g2
Crel g2
t4s F2cf∗-t4a monster
thinks⟨3,a⟩ CP
⟨3,s⟩
Alice
Cd t3a
t3s
found nP2
u3s
wh2cf∗-t4a monster
∗
JF2cf∗-t4a monsterK = λws .λgg . g(4a)(2cf )(monster)(w(g))
JCPrel K = ∀aa ∶ a(g) is compatible with SOMTimmy,@(g(2a)) →
∗
Alice found g(4a)(2cf )(monster)(@(a(g))) in @(a(g))
200
JSK ≈ λgg . ∀aa ∶ a(g) is compatible with SOMCallie,@(g−) →
([ιx(g)∃a′a ∶ x(g) = a′ (g)(2cf∗)(monster)(a(g)(1s))
∧ ∀a′′a ∶ a′′ (g) is compatible with SOMTimmy,@(a(g)) →
∗
Alice found a′ (g)(2cf )(monster)(@(a′′ (g))) in @(a′′ (g))]
x(g) ate Fluffy in @(a(g)))
Roughly put, this says that (8.86) is true iff for all possibilities h compatible with
Callie’s state of mind, the o such that, for some individual concept of a monster
F∗(monster), [o is identical to the manifestation of F∗(monster) in @(h), and for
all possibilities h′′ compatible with Timmy’s state of mind in @(h), Alice found the
manifestation of F∗(monster) in @(h′′ )], ate Fluffy in @(h).
Rather than selecting a particular individual in a given world, [F2cf∗-t4a monster]
in the representations of the internal and external heads selects an individual con-
cept: an individual concept of a monster, F∗(monster) = o∗. What world is supplied
depends on the position of the nP. The world argument for the internal head —
the head inside the relative clause CPrel — is supplied by the world-variable u3s
anchored to Timmy’s belief-worlds; o∗(@(h)) ∈ monster@(h) , for any possibility h
compatible with Timmy’s state of mind. The resulting semantic value for CPrel
requires that, for any such h, Alice found such-and-such individual o∗(@(h)) se-
lectable among the monsters in @(h). The local (intensional, de dicto) reading of
the relative phrase follows from the general feature transmission mechanisms from
§8.5.
Although the relative phrase denotes an individual concept, the account avoids
ascribing to Callie a belief that Fluffy was eaten by an individual concept. While
there may be intensional verbs that take property-/individual-concept objects, ‘find’
and ‘eat’ aren’t among them. Likewise, though the internal nP2 picks out an individ-
ual in Timmy’s belief-worlds, the derived truth conditions don’t imply a commitment
to transworld eating. The world argument for the external head is supplied by the
world-pronoun [w1 g2 ] anchored to Callie’s belief-worlds. nP1 picks out the mani-
festation of F∗(monster) = o∗ in the world @(h) of the given possibility h compatible
with Callie’s state of mind. The entities which ate Fluffy and Alice found are ordinary
concrete individuals.
Though the internal and external heads receive different world arguments, the
denotation of the n∗P can still capture the intuitive quantificational domain. For-
mally, an individual concept is a function from worlds to individuals. We can
suppose that, in the intended interpretation, the sorts of functions F∗ potentially rep-
resented by cf∗ indices map properties P to relevant “transworld” lines — functions
201
from worlds u to individuals F∗(P)(u) such that the manifestations of F∗ at the
worlds in F∗(P)’s domain are relevant counterparts of one another (i.e., for any
u, v on which F∗(P) is defined, F∗(P)(u) is a relevant counterpart of F∗(P)(v);
cf. e.g. Ojeda 1993). So, for each of Callie’s belief-worlds @(h), the definite noun
phrase picks out the unique individual o ∈ E such that (i) o manifests some individual
concept o∗ of a monster, o = o∗(@(h)); and (ii) Alice found the relevant counterpart
of o in each of Timmy’s belief-worlds @(h′′ ), i.e. the manifestation of o∗ in @(h′′ ),
o∗(@(h′′ )). (8.92) says that the attitude ascription is true, on the intended reading,
iff for each such @(h), that o = o∗(@(h)) — the manifestation of the individual
concept o∗ in @(h) — ate Fluffy in @(h).
The above account allows for the possibility that the internal and external heads
with [ nP n FP] relative phrases may receive different world arguments. Such an
account is compatible with a matching analysis which treats one of the heads as
deleted under (semantic or syntactic) identity, even an account which constructs
the internal relative phrase via a syntactic copy operation. For instance, the copy
operation could be treated as applying to the constituent constructed upon merg-
ing the choice-function pronoun — following (8.87), the FP. The n heads in inter-
nal/external nPs would thus be free to enter the derivation with alternative world
variables or pronouns (subject to other syntactic and interpretive constraints).
There may be reasons to avoid treating the condition in (8.88) as a general re-
quirement on the ⟨set, se⟩ denotations of relative words in [nP n FP] relative phrases.
Consider (8.93).
(8.93) The monsteri which you thinki you saw was a shadow.
The intensional gap reading of (8.93) needn’t imply a commitment to monsters. In-
deed (8.93) would generally be interpreted as saying that the object which you think
you saw wasn’t a monster, as you believe, but a shadow. The predicted structure
and semantic value would presumably be as in (8.94) (leaving ‘be-a-shadow’ as an
unanalyzed predicate, again using ‘cf∗’ in indices for type ⟨set, se⟩).
⟨2,a⟩
(8.94) a. [ S T⟨1,a⟩ [ CP [Cd t1a ]⟨1,s⟩ [[the⟨3,a⟩ [ n∗P [ CPrel [Crel g1 ]⟨2,s⟩ you2e -g1 t2s think
[ CP [Cd t2a ]⟨3,s⟩ you2e -g1 t3s saw [ nP u3s wh2cf∗-t3a monster]]]
[X [ nP u1s F2cf∗-t3a monster]]]]
[ vP t1s -was-a-shadow]]]]
∗
b. JSK ≈ λgg . [ιx(g)∃a∶ x(g) = a(g)(2cf )(monster)(@(g−))
202
∧ ∀a′ ∶ a′ (g) is compatible with SOMg−(2e),@(g−) →
g−(2e) saw a(g)(2cf∗)(monster)(@(a′ (g))) in @(a′ (g))]
x(g) was a shadow in @(g−)
Dropping the assumption that assignments a(g) necessarily map ⟨set, se⟩/cf∗ indices
to intensional choice functions captures the intended reading. The subject noun
∗
phrase picks out the o such that, for some individual concept o∗ = a(g)(2cf )(monster),
o is the manifestation of o∗ in the actual world, i.e. o = o∗(@(gc )), and, for all possi-
bilities h compatible with your state of mind, you (=gc (2e)) saw the counterpart of
o in @(h), i.e. o∗(@(h)) = a(g)(2cf∗)(monster)(@(h)). Though the manifestations
of o∗ throughout your belief-worlds @(h) may be monsters, o∗(@(h)) ∈ monster@(h) ,
the “world-line” of the individual concept o∗ may include worlds in which the man-
ifestation of o∗ isn’t a monster but a (monster-looking) shadow. The sentence is
true iff the actual world @(gc ) is such a world, i.e. iff the relevant counterpart
o∗(@(gc )) in @(gc ) of the monsters o∗(@(h)) you saw in your belief-worlds @(h)
was a shadow in @(gc ). For interpretive reasons ⟨set, se⟩/cf∗ indices will typically
represent intensional choice functions satisfying the condition in (8.88). Compare
(8.93) with the anomalous (8.95).
(8.95) ??The monster which you think you saw hit Bert.
8.8 Extensions?
In closing I would like to mention several potential further applications of the match-
ing analysis and approach to intensional gap readings from §8.7. §8.9 briefly con-
siders how the parallel layered n/v analyses of noun/verb phrases in this section
might be further developed in the semantics of verb phrases vP/v∗P; a speculative
assignment-variable-based event semantics is introduced as a basis for future re-
search.
203
(8.96) The prize went to a woman (/sm/several/three women) who got a perfect
score.
(8.99) The prize went to a woman who got a perfect score. Two others also got
perfect scores, but they were disqualified for cheating.
Positing an implicit operator leads one to expect that there might be crosslin-
guistic variation in its presence or specific content. For instance, one might wonder
whether languages might have an implicit definite counterpart of ∃r . In §9 we will
see crosslinguistic and syntactic/semantic evidence for precisely such an element in
204
‘if’-clauses and correlatives of individuals. ‘If’-clauses and correlative clauses will be
analyzed essentially as maximalizing free relatives of possibilities (assignments).
Or suppose an element such as ∃r was unavailable for a relative construction
in a given language. Such a relative construction would be invariably headed by
a (possibly implicit) presuppositional quantifier, and incompatible with nonpresup-
positional readings. Interestingly, this is precisely what is observed with so-called
“maximalizing” relatives (Grosu & Landman 1998, Grosu 2002, 2012). Unlike
their English counterparts, the maximalizing relatives in (8.100) are incompatible
with continuations implying a non-maximal interpretation.
The relative in (8.100a), for instance, is interpreted as ‘the two horses that the man
bought’. In some languages the definite element is overt (Hiraiwa 2005, Hiraiwa
et al. 2017). Maximalizing relatives might be represented as in (8.102), using
‘3-mangoesu ’ for the set of individuals o such that #o′ [o′ is a mango in u ∧ o′ ⊑ o] ≥ 3,
i.e. individuals having three mangoes as atomic parts. (The metalanguage ‘ι’ is again
a plural maximality operator, reflected in (8.101); cf. Link 1983.)
(8.101) Jιo K = λPaet .λQaet .λgg . ∃xe ∃aa ∶ (P(a)(x)(g) ∧ ∀ye ∶ P(a)(y)(g) → y(g) ⊑ x(g))
∧ Q(a)(x)(g)
= λPaet .λQaet .λgg . ∃xe ∃aa ∶ x(g) = the maximal o s.t. (↓ P)(a(g))(o)
∧ Q(a)(x)(g)
≈ λPaet .λQaet .λgg . [ιx(g)∃a∶ P(a)(x)(g)] Q(a)(x)(g)
(8.102) “Maximalizing” headed relative clause
a. ‘(Alice ate) three mangoes which Ken bought’ (cf. (8.100b))
⟨2,a⟩
b. [ S … [ιo [ n∗P [ CPrel [Crel g1 ]⟨2,s⟩
[Ken [ vP t2s bought [wh2 -t2a w1 -g1 three# -mangoes]]]]
[X [wh2 -t2a w1 -g1 three# -mangoes]]]]…]
205
c. JSK ≈ λgg . [ιx(g)∃a∶ x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(3-mangoesg−(1s) )
∧ Ken bought a(g)(2cf)(3-mangoesg−(1s) ) in @(g−)]
Alice ate x(g) in @(g−)
206
‘(the person) who scolded me’
(Huang 2008: 761–762; Ronghong Qiang)
(8.104) Matching “light-headed” free relative (cf. (8.103))
a. ‘(Bert likes) who Alice likes’
b. [def⟨2,a⟩ [ n∗P [ CPrel [Crel g1 ]⟨2,s⟩ [Alice [ vP t2s likes [wh2 -t2a w1 -g1 -person]]]]
[X [wh2 -t2a w1 -g1 -person]]]]
c. J(8.104b)K ≈ λgg . ιx(g)∃a∶ x(g) = a(g)(2cf)(persong(1a)(1s) )
∧ Alice likes a(g)(2cf)(persong(1a)(1s) ) in @(g(1a))
207
resumptive pronouns. Doron 1982 observes that resumptive pronouns in languages
such as Hebrew are incompatible with certain sorts of intensional readings (see also
e.g. Sells 1987, Suñer 1998, Sharvit 1999, Boeckx 2003, Bianchi 2011). The
“highly preferred reading” (Sharvit 1999: 593) of (8.105b) with the resumptive
pronoun is the reading implying the existence of a salient woman who is the object
of Dani’s seeking (cf. Sells 1987: 287–288). (8.105b) lacks the otherwise available
“concept interpretation” (Sells 1987) of (8.105a) on which Dani is merely “looking
for a woman with certain properties” — e.g. a woman to lead his team — “but does
not know who such a woman might be” (Sells 1987: 288).114
Suppose that resumptive pronouns are pronounced realizations of the (lowest copy
of the) relative phrase with an elided head noun (cf. §6.2). If resumptive pronouns
in (e.g.) Hebrew have at least the structure of [F nP], using a resumptive pronoun
will be incompatible with the sorts of structures representing intensional gap read-
ings. In examples such as those in this section, the relative phrase would be (at
least) an [F nP] with a world-pronoun bound by an assignment-binder above the
relative clause, as in (8.106) (again ignoring any copy of the relative phrase in
Spec,Crel , and ignoring any semantically vacuous n∗ head in the representation of
the resumptive pronoun (see §8.5)). Or if intensional verbs such as ‘seek’ in (8.105)
may optionally take intensional objects such as individual concepts, the richer struc-
ture would be excluded — or at least “highly [dis]preferred” (Sharvit 1999) — for
114
Sells 1987 characterizes the distinction in readings as a distinction between specific vs.
nonspecific readings — e.g., in (8.105), readings which do/don’t imply that there is a particular
woman o such that Dani is looking for o (1987: 288). Sharvit 1999 characterizes the distinction as
a distinction between de re vs. de dicto readings — e.g., readings which do/don’t imply the existence
of a (salient) woman (1999: 593). (Doron 1982 labels the distinction as de re/de dicto, but glosses
examples in terms specificity/nonspecificity (1982: 305). Bianchi 2011 uses the distinctions inter-
changeably (2011: 320).) Further data would be needed to tease apart precisely which distinction
is operative (§§4.2, 8.8.3), and which type of reading is generally associated with the resumptive
pronoun. Sharvit illustrates connections between resumptive pronouns and D-linking, but a formal
analysis isn’t provided. I return briefly to D-linking with interrogative wh phrases in §10.3. Thanks
to Anya Saliy and Amit Ginbar for feedback on the Hebrew data.
208
general economy reasons against vacuous functional structure (cf. Cardinaletti &
Starke 1999, Katzir 2011, Patel-Grosz & Grosz 2017); the denotations for the
nP and FP in (8.107) are equivalent.
(8.108) Every star who has a secret admirer thinks he is stalking her.
(King 2004: ex. 18)
King (2004) argues that such examples are problematic for main approaches to don-
key pronouns such as DRT and dynamic theories. Insofar as these approaches treat
donkey pronouns as semantically bound variables, they predict a specific reading for
‘he’, i.e. a reading which attributes to each relevant star a belief about a particular
individual. However, the attitude ascription can also receive a nonspecific reading
which “can be true even though the women in question don’t know who their secret
admirers are” (2004: 105).
Imagine, à la Dretske, that a trickster sent each zoo-owning epistemologist a
letter accompanying the latest delivery of animals to the effect that some or other
of the zebra-looking animals was a cleverly painted mule. Consider the following
LF and derived semantic value for (8.109) on a nonspecific reading, where which
mule did the ruining may vary across the subject’s doxastic alternatives. (I represent
the relative phrase as having a full [F nP] structure, and treat the relative clause is
209
merged left of n∗, though nothing hangs on this. For simplicity I continue to use the
“universal donkey” reading entry for ‘every’ from §6.2.2.)
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a
QP⟨2,a⟩
t1s
every⟨2,a⟩ n∗P thinks⟨3,a⟩
⟨3,s⟩
CPrel Cd t3a
nP
X t3s ruined-ep
⟨4,s⟩ F2cf -t2a w1 -g1 epist u3s
Crel g1 painted-mule
it3cf∗ g2a
t4s
wh2cf -t2a w1 -g1 epist got nP
u4s
painted-mule
a3cf∗ g2a
Roughly put, this says that (8.109) is true, on the relevant reading, iff for any o ∈ E
∗
and individual concept of a painted mule h(3cf )(painted-mule) = o∗ such that o is
selectable among the epistemologists and o got the manifestation of o∗ in @(gc ), in
each of o’s belief-worlds @(h′ ) the manifestation of o∗ in @(h′ ) ruined epistemology.
210
The donkey pronoun ‘it’ is again represented as a copy of its linguistic antecedent —
here the intensional choice-function pronoun [a3cf∗-g2 painted-mule], which selects
an individual concept of a painted mule. The world-variable in the indefinite is
anchored to the discourse context. In effect, the quantifier phrase quantifies over in-
dividuals o, o′ ∈ E such that o is selectable among the epistemologists, o′ is the mani-
festation in the actual world of an individual concept o∗ of a painted mule, and o got
o′ . The world-variable in the donkey pronoun, in contrast, is anchored (by FC) to the
local attitude state. For each of the quantificational subject o’s belief-worlds @(h′ ),
the individual(s) o∗(@(h′ )) ∈ E which ruined epistemology is a relevant counterpart
of the individual(s) o∗(@(gc )) ∈ E which o received (§8.7.2). The relevant counter-
part of o∗(@(gc )) might be the same across the subject’s belief-worlds; but as far
as the formal semantics is concerned, it need not be. The particular individual that
manifests the individual concept o∗ may vary across the worlds @(h′ ). The intu-
itively nonspecific reading of the donkey pronoun follows from the §6.2-account of
donkey pronouns as copies of their linguistic antecedents, and the syntax/semantics
for nPs developed throughout this section.
Specific readings of attitude ascriptions such as (8.108)–(8.109) can be repre-
sented with ordinary [F nP] choice-functional phrases for the indefinite and donkey
pronoun, e.g. [F3cf -g2 w1 -g1 painted-mule]. The scope condition would require
that the particular individual(s) selected among the actual painted mules ruined
epistemology in every possibility compatible with the subject’s state of mind.
King’s (2004) “Context-Dependent Quantifier” (CDQ) account also treats don-
key pronouns as representing material from the linguistic context. Donkey pronouns
are analyzed as quantifiers which inherit their force and restriction from their lin-
guistic antecedent and other features of the sentence. Yet there are issues with King’s
account, in general and regarding examples with donkey pronouns in intensional
contexts. First, King diagnoses specific vs. nonspecific readings of donkey pronouns
in examples such as (8.108) in terms of differences in scope: insofar as the pronoun is
quantificational, it may take varying scopes with respect to attitude verbs. This diag-
nosis is problematic. Donkey pronouns can receive alternative specific/nonspecific
readings even when embedded in scope islands such as ‘if’-clauses, as in (8.110).
(8.110) Every star who has a secret admireri thinks that if hei is a stalker, hei is
evil.
In contrast, the account in this section diagnoses the distinction between specific
vs. nonspecific readings of donkey pronouns under attitude verbs in terms of the
structure of the noun phrase.
211
Second, King characterizes the nonspecific reading of (8.108) as follows:
King’s gloss in the underlined portion is misleading. We saw in §4.2 that the de re/de dicto
distinction cannot be assimilated to the specific/general distinction. The fact that the
subject’s beliefs are nonspecific — the beliefs aren’t about a particular individual —
doesn’t imply that the beliefs are de dicto, in the sense that the subject represents the
stalkers in question as secret admirers. Examples such as (8.111)–(8.112) reinforce
the possibility of a nonspecific non-de dicto reading of the donkey pronoun.
The stars in (8.111) don’t represent their actual-world (secret) admirers as admirers
but as pranksters; yet they still don’t know who the individuals are, “and so have
no beliefs about particular persons.” The quantified attitude ascription in (8.112)
can be true even if the boys don’t think that their coins are nickels. Absent addi-
tional mechanisms for capturing non-de dicto readings with narrow scope quanti-
fiers, simply saying that the donkey pronoun “has the same quantificational force as
its antecedent” (King 2004: 105) fails to capture readings in which the pronoun’s
intuitive descriptive content isn’t satisfied throughout the local attitude state.
The sort of [nP n FP] analysis in (8.109) allows for nonspecific non-de dicto read-
ings of “intensional donkey pronouns” such as (8.111)–(8.112). For instance, the
indefinite and its copy in the representation of the donkey pronoun [Fcf∗ g admirer]
select an individual concept of a secret admirer, F∗(admirer) = o∗. In a context
where a principle such as (8.88) is relaxed, the “world-line” of o∗ may include worlds
u in the subject’s belief-worlds in which the manifestation of o∗, o∗(u), isn’t an ad-
mirer but (say) a prankster; the relevant counterpart of the given admirer o∗(@(gc ))
212
may be a prankster in the subject’s belief worlds. The treatment of nonspecific non-
de dicto readings of donkey pronouns is, in effect, the mirror image of the treatment
of intensional gap readings such as (8.93)–(8.94). In the intensional gap reading in
(8.93)–(8.94) with ‘which monster’, the relevant individual concept is manifested
by a monster throughout the subject’s belief-worlds and by a (non-monster) shadow
in the actual world; in the nonspecific non-de dicto reading of ‘he’ in (8.112), the
relevant individual concept is manifested by a secret admirer in the actual world
and by different (non-admirer) pranksters throughout the subject’s belief-worlds.
Third, King’s account must ensure that the donkey pronoun-quantifier’s restric-
tion isn’t identified with the restriction of its linguistic antecedent, but is rather
“determined by the predicative material in the sentence in which the antecedent occurs”
(2004: 106; emphasis added). For instance, the restriction in (8.113a) must be
recovered from ‘donkey’ and some combination with ‘farmer’ and ‘owns’, so that
‘it’ quantifies over donkeys owned by the quantificational subject; (8.113a) isn’t
equivalent to (8.113b).
In work applying the account to discourse anaphora, King identifies the restriction
of the anaphoric pronoun with “the intersection of the denotation of its antecedent’s
N-bar constituent, the denotation of the set term the antecedent attaches to, and the
denotation of any predicative material occurring in a sentence intervening between
S and the antecedent which contains a cdq [i.e. anaphoric pronoun] with the same
antecedent” (1994: 224). It isn’t immediately obvious how to implement this idea
in the case of donkey sentences. There is no syntactic constituent in (8.113a)
corresponding to the intuitive restriction ‘is owned by x’ or ‘is a donkey owned by x’.
The relation in more complex examples can be even more indirect:
(8.114) Every farmer who beats a donkey that loves a donkey hates it.
The syntax/semantics developed in the foregoing sections avoids such issues. In-
stances of donkey anaphora are represented syntactically as copies of their linguistic
antecedents. The semantic restriction in interpreting the donkey pronoun is cap-
tured by the assignment-quantification introduced by the matrix quantifier, which
requires that the assignment verifying the scope argument verifies the restrictor
argument.
213
8.9 Appendix: Verb phrases and events.
Existential sentences revisited: Predication and possession
The compositional semantics for noun phrases developed in this section builds on
a parallel layered N/V, n/v, n∗/v∗ structure for noun/verb phrases. At times we
gestured at certain syntactic roles for v∗; yet we largely abstracted away from spe-
cific semantic contributions of verbalizing heads, and ignored many further details
regarding the structure of the verbal domain. The remainder of this section begins
to explore how the parallel assignment-variable-based analyses for noun and verb
phrases developed thus far might be extended to incorporate events in the syn-
tax/semantics of vPs/v∗Ps. The account yields a revised syntax/semantics for agen-
tive verb phrases, predicate nominals, and existential ‘there’ sentences (§§8.1–8.4).
Additional composition rules specific to the verbal domain, such as Event Iden-
tification (Kratzer 1996), won’t be required. I leave further developments and
extensions to other categories for future work.
Following the Davidsonian tradition (Davidson 1967, Parsons 1990) it is stan-
dard to treat verbs as predicates of eventualities (events, states) — e.g., ‘rain’ denotes
a set of raining events λe.rain(e); ‘run’ denotes a set of running events λe.run(e).115
In §8.1 we noted the common move in syntax of distinguishing the elements de-
termining nominal/verbal environments n/v from lexical roots (Marantz 1997;
nn. 92, 94). It is rare to find the move represented in compositional semantics
(see Levinson 2007 for a noteworthy exception). Derivations of the contrasting
denotations of simple nominal/verbal predicates from nominalizers/verbalizers and
root phrases (cf. (8.115)) are generally lacking.
In what follows I wish to explore treating a semantic role of certain n/v heads as
being to place sortal constraints on the properties expressed by their complements.
Suppose that events and states are conceived as being included among the en-
tities in E (cf. Chierchia 1994, Kracht 2002, Moulton 2015). Along with un-
sorted type e variables x, y, . . . we can use sorted variables xκ for (functions from
assignments to) things in E of particular sorts — e.g., perhaps for atomic objects,
115
I will often use ‘event’ both for eventualities generally and for events proper; context should
disambiguate.
214
plural objects, or, let’s suppose, for eventualities xε (events xv , states xs ).116 First,
basic root phrases can still be treated as denoting type ⟨s, et⟩ properties — functions
from worlds to sets of (unsorted) individuals. For instance, roots such as those in
(8.6)/(8.115) might be given lexical entries as in (8.116). In (8.116b) the metalan-
guage predicate ‘wood’ picks out a spectrum of wood-ish things — “wood objects,”
such as (say) twigs, branches, as well as a range of “wood doings” (which such range
depending on the specific lexical semantics of North Sámi).
In §8.1 we saw how number features such as [sg] or [pl] can modify these denota-
tions by restricting them to properties of atomic or countable individuals. Parallels
such as between the mass/count distinction and the atelicity/telicity distinction
have led many theorists to treat an aspectual category as the verbal counterpart
of number (cf. e.g. ?, Rijkhoff 2002, Borer 2005a,b, Alexiadou et al. 2007,
Megerdoomian 2008; n. 91).117 In =∣ Hoan the same marker kí indicates plurality
for nouns and “pluractionality” for verbs; just as the modified plural noun kí-!oa-qa
in (8.117a) denotes a set of (countable) head-pluralities, the modified plural verb
kí-tchi-tcu in (8.117b) “gives the sense of repeated action” (Collins 2001: 465) by
denoting a set of (countable) shooting-pluralities.
Not all root (number, aspect) phrases need be compatible with both nominalizing
and verbalizing heads. Compare (8.6)/(8.115) with (8.118); in (8.118b), although
the vP viekhat ‘run’ can be nominalized (‘running’), the root √viekh cannot combine
directly with n.
116
See Levinson 2007, Copley & Harley 2015 on the linguistic importance of distinguishing
sorts for events and states.
117
Following Hiraiwa 2005, number and aspect might be treated as different manifestations of a
“supercategory” #, realized as Num under n and Asp under v.
215
(8.118) a. [ nP [ n /ɑ/] √viellj] ↝ viellja (‘brother’ (n.)) (/∗vielljet/∗vielljat (v.))
b. [ vP [ v /ɑ/] √viekh] ↝ viekhat (‘run’ (v.)) (/∗viekha/∗viekhu (n.))
[ nP [ n /m/] [ vP [ v /ɑ/] √viekh]] ↝ viekhan (‘running’)
(cf. Julien 2015: 5; North Sámi (Uralic))
The meanings of some roots may themselves be sortally restricted, whether in the
lexicon or as a matter of world knowledge (cf. e.g. Harley 2005, Levinson 2007);
some roots may express properties satisfied only by particular sorts of things in E. I
suggest that a general semantic role of certain nominalizing and verbalizing heads
is to provide an explicit source of such sortal constraints. For instance, the v0
head phonologically realized with /e/ in (8.115) — call it simply ‘v’ — might restrict
the property denoted by its complement to a property of events, as reflected in
(8.119) (cf. Borer 2005b). The world variable is now an internal argument of the
verbalizing head, which receives a substantive lexical entry. (xεe is, again, a sorted
variable over elements of De such that xεe (g), for any gg , is an eventuality. I will
ignore aspect.)
This treats the vP representing murret ‘chop wood’ as picking out the set of wood-ish
things in the given world (=wood(g(1s))) that are events — for speakers of North
Sámi, events of wood-chopping. Additional composition rules such as Event Identi-
fication (Kratzer 1996) for combining the root and the verbalizer aren’t required.
External arguments can now be introduced in v∗P, where v∗ heads are given
substantive lexical entries (cf. Chomsky 1995, Kratzer 1996, Folli & Harley
2007, Pylkkänen 2008, D'Alessandro et al. 2017; n. 94). Just as the external
possessors in free R genitives are introduced in Spec,n∗ with a relevant posses-
sion relation pronoun, the external subject in an active sentence such as (8.120)
can be introduced in Spec,v∗ with a relevant agentive relation pronoun (see §7.2;
cf. n. 67).118 In both cases the external argument+relation functions semantically
As with possessive noun phrases, certain v∗ heads may place semantic restrictions on the
118
relation expressed (e.g., Agent, Experiencer, Possessor; cf. Wood & Marantz 2017, nn. 67, 128).
An alternative would be to treat certain v∗ heads as specifying particular thematic relations in their
lexical entry, as in (i):
(i) a. [ v∗P Fluffy [v∗agt [ vP [v t1s ] meow]]]
b. Jv∗agt K = λPet .λye .λxve .λgg . P(xv )(g) ∧ agent(y(g))(xv (g))
Jv∗PK = λxve .λgg . meow(g(1s))(xv (g)) ∧ agent(Fluffy)(xv (g))
216
as a restrictive modifier (see n. 65, §7.2). The set of event-entities ov denoted by
the verb phrase can then be quantified over, as usual, such as by existential closure
or a higher aspectual quantifier (Krifka 1992, Bonomi 1997a, Kratzer 1998a,
Hacquard 2006, 2009). A first approximation with a simple existential closure
operation is in (8.120). (For uniformity I treat the thematic relation like our other
relational predicates as type ⟨e, ⟨s, et⟩⟩ (abbreviated R).)
One motivation for the sort of analysis in the main text may come from passives. Crosslinguistic
work provides evidence that passives retain a layered V-v-v∗ structure (Harley 2013, 2017, Julien
2015, Sundaresan & McFadden 2017, Wurmbrand & Shimamura 2017; cf. Legate 2003).
What distinguishes passives from (e.g.) unergatives and active transitives isn’t the category of the
verb phrase (vP vs. v∗P), but whether the v∗ head (in our terms) takes a thematic argument in
its specifier. If this is right, v∗ heads in passive sentences can be given the same (polymorphic)
lexical entry for purposes of compositional semantics as v∗ heads in active sentences. The resulting
approach to the semantics of v∗Ps parallels our treatments of possessive and non-possessive n∗Ps.
As discussed in §7.2, in some languages the connection between the semantic roles of (agentive)
subjects and possessors are reflected in the morphology, as in (7.49), reproduced in (ii), where the
agentive subject is introduced with the same marker distinguishing free R readings of possessive noun
phrases. In some cases the added markers combining with the possessor/subject are synchronically
or diachronically related to elements with a relational syntax/semantics (see n. 67).
(ii) a. nga kur� [a Mere]
art dog possfr Mere
‘Mere’s dogs’
b. te whakamau-tanga [a Mere] i te taura
art fasten-nomz possfr Mere acc art rope
‘Mere’s fastening of the rope’
c. ka whakamau [a Mere] i te taura.
t/a fasten possfr Mere acc art rope
‘Mere is fastening the rope’
(Harlow 2007: 166, Chung 1973: 652, Maori (Austronesian))
217
(8.120) ‘Fluffy meowed.’
S
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩
(∃) v∗P
Cd t1a
u1s v∗agt vP
Fluffy
R2 g1
v0
meow
v t1s
Jv∗agt K = λPet .λP′et .λxve .λgg . P(xv )(g) ∧ P′ (xv )(g)
Jv∗PK = λxve .λgg . meow(g(1s))(xv (g)) ∧ g(1a)(2R)(Fluffy)(g(1s))(xv (g))
JSK ≈ λgg . ∃xve ∶ meow(@(g−))(xv (g)) ∧ g−(2R)(Fluffy)(@(g−))(xv (g))
Roughly put, this treats the v∗P representing ‘Fluffy meow’ as denoting the set
of things ov which are meowing events in the world of the discourse @(gc ) and
which bear the relevant agent-relation (=gc (2R)) to Fluffy — i.e., the set of meowing
events of which Fluffy is the agent. The sentence is true only if there is such an event.
The sort of analysis in (8.120) may of course be refined. Notably, the derivation
of the quantification over events would ultimately need to take into account the
contributions of particular aspectual heads and their interactions with tense (see also
n. 128).119 As noted in §3.2, Hacquard (2006, 2010) has argued that the higher
aspectual quantifiers raise for type reasons from inside the verb phrase (see also
Moulton 2015). Comparisons with the syntax/semantics developed here of quan-
tifier phrases QP as introducing assignment-quantification/binding are worth ex-
119
For instance, a prominent move is to treat aspects such as perfective and imperfective as
(existential) quantifiers which locate the “running time” of an event (written τ (e)) with respect to a
“reference time” (Klein 1994), provided e.g. by a time pronoun in Tense. A sample implementation
of (8.120) with an entry for the perfective adapted from Kratzer 1998a is in (i). (li is a variable for
times, type l; I ignore any presuppositional constraint associated with the past tense.)
(i) [ S T⟨1,a⟩ [ CP [Cd t1a ]⟨1,s⟩ [ TP l1 g1 [ AspP prfv [ v∗P [u1s R2 -g1 Fluffy] [v∗agt [ vP v-t1s meow]]]]]]]
JprfvK = λPet .λtl .λgg . ∃xeε ∶ P(xε)(g) ∧ τ (xε(g)) ⊆ t(g)
JSK ≈ λgg . ∃xve ∶ meow(@(g−))(xv (g)) ∧ g−(2R)(Fluffy)(@(g−))(xv (g)) ∧ τ (xv (g)) ⊆ g−(1l)
218
ploring. Applications to shifting phenomena such as with temporal (in)dependence,
fake tense, actuality entailments, may yield additional avenues for future research.
The examples thus far have involved eventive predicates. Considering stative
predicates may afford revised analyses of predicative uses of noun phrases, such as
in existential sentences (§§8.1–8.4). First, let’s consider a “bare” existential ‘there’
sentence such as (8.50), reproduced below. As previously, the NumP representing
‘three pillows’ denotes (roughly) the property of being a plural entity with at least
three pillows as atomic parts.
To fix ideas suppose that predicative ‘be’ is a realization of a stative verbalizer vbe
(n. 93; cf. Harley 1995, Kratzer 1996, Folli & Harley 2007). Treating the
nominalizer in (8.121) as semantically vacuous affords a straightforward semantics
for vbe : vbe converts the nominal predicate to a verbal predicate expressing a property
of states os ∈ E. The higher (existential) quantification over eventualities yields a
type t denotation straightway, reflected in (8.123). (xse is, again, a sorted variable
over elements of De such that xse (g), for any gg , is a state.) Drawing on the approach
to predicate nominals suggested in n. 106, the complementizer may be generated
directly in n0 in the main predicate (more on which shortly).
219
examples with nominals expressing downward entailing or non-monotone quantifi-
cational concepts (‘no/few/exactly four Ns’). The truth condition for (8.52) ‘There
are no unicorns’ in (8.124) is too weak.
The truth of ‘There are no unicorns’ isn’t guaranteed by there being some unicornless
state.
Both problems can be addressed with a common solution. §8.4 assumed as a
baseline hypothesis that the YP “pivots” in ‘There be YP’ sentences such as (8.48)–
(8.52) are nPs. Yet there are good reasons for thinking that the nominal predicates
in existential sentences are in general n∗Ps. Notably, it is crosslinguistically com-
mon to form existential sentences via a genitive/possessive construction where the
pivot functions analogously to the noun for the “possessee” (see Creissels 2014,
McNally 2016 and references therein). In the Serbian example in (8.125a) both the
head noun and nonpresuppositional quantifier receive genitive case morphology.
The pattern of genitive morphology in (8.125a) parallels the pattern of genitive
morphology on the quantifier complement from (7.47) (=(8.125b)). In both cases
n∗ can be treated as assigning genitive Case to its complement. In languages such
as Swahili with comitative existential constructions ((8.126)), the comitative ele-
ment could perhaps be analyzed as a realization of n∗ (cf. §7.2). Though Swahili
has a relatively free word order, the (glossed) ‘there (be) na YP’ order is rigid
(Marten 2013). When used with a non-expletive subject the construction yields
a broadly possessional interpretation (cf. (8.126b)). Indeed a prominent idea, fol-
lowing Szabolcsi (1983, 1994) and Kayne (1993, 1994), is that possessive ‘have’
constructions are (in at least some languages) derived from ‘be’ plus a possessive
noun phrase — i.e., on the present architecture, v+n∗P.120 The existential con-
structions in (8.127) are identical to the possessive construction without an overt
“possessor” subject (cf. e.g. Lynch 1978: 99–100, Fortescue 1984: 81, 171, 173,
Onishi 2000: 133, a.o.). Possessive sentences in languages such as Tolai are liter-
ally expressed via an existential construction with a bare possessive n∗P predicate
((8.128); cf. (7.29), (7.51)–(7.50)). In various languages the ‘be’+n∗P structure
and relation+entity in Spec,n∗ are overt in both possessive and existential sentences.
120
Cf. Kayne’s suggestive remark: “Szabolcsi’s claim that Hungarian possessive sentences [e.g.
≈ John has a cat] contain … a copula plus a single argument” — e.g., [be [ n∗P John n∗poss [a cat]]] —
“can become intuitively clear to an English speaker if the Hungarian sentences are thought of as
parallel to the almost acceptable English There is [a cat] of John’s” (1993: 108; see Szabolcsi 1994).
220
For instance, in Irish (8.129), using the PP ag YP ‘at YP’ yields a possessive inter-
pretation ((8.129a)), and using the PP ann ‘in it’ yields an existential interpretation
((8.129b)) (see also Freeze 1992, 2001, Boneh & Sichel 2010). Notably, the
structural possessor/location element is apparently obligatory in existential as well
as possessive interpretations; McCloskey 2014 reports that bare ‘be’+pivot exis-
tentials such as (8.129c) without ann are ungrammatical. An n∗P analysis provides
a natural diagnosis. If the relevant n∗ head(s) in (e.g.) Irish have an EPP-property
or assign a (broadly possessional/locational) θ-role, (8.129c) would be excluded
insofar as the EPP-property/θ-role of n∗ isn’t satisfied/discharged.121
for purely syntactic reasons; unlike e.g. ‘there’, ann can be structurally focused in existential sentences
(McCloskey 2014: 353–354). Whereas codas such as ‘in the store’ in (i) can function as a verbal
modifier, ann in (8.129b)/(ii) must be noun-phrase-internal; as predicted, the movement in (ii-b),
unlike (i-b), is ungrammatical. Revealingly, whereas ann can co-occur with (noun-phrase-internal/-
external) modifier adjuncts, it is in complementary distribution with ag YP (McCloskey 2014),
reflected in (iii): ann and ag YP cannot co-occur in (iii-c) insofar as they compete for the same
position in Spec,n∗.
(i) a. There is a cat on the couch.
b. On the couch, there is a cat.
(ii) a. Níl tae ar bith ann.
is-not tea any in-it
‘There’s no tea.
b. *Ann, níl tae ar bith.
in-it is-not tea any
(iii) a. Tá daoine ann nach mbeadh sásta glacadh leis.
is people in-it negc be.cond satisfied take.nonfin with-it
‘There are people who would not be willing to accept it.’
b. Tá daoine ann ar an bhaile.
is people in-it on the town
‘There are people in the town.’
c. *Tá leabhar ann agt mo dheirfiúr.
is book in-it at my sister (McCloskey 2014: 347, 351–352; Irish)
More careful examination of the syntactic and semantic constraints on the element in Spec,n∗, and
interactions among the pivot, Spec,n∗ PPs, and different types of n∗P-internal and n∗P-external
modifiers, is warranted (cf. also nn. 65, 109). It would be interesting to compare the behavior of ann
with the behavior of obligatory locative elements in other languages lacking dedicated existential
constructions (see Creissels 2014: 25–26). See also n. 100 on certain Romance locative clitics and
German da.
221
b. Mnogo [nekih ljudi] želi pravdu.
many some.gen people.gen want justice
‘Many different people want justice.’
(cf. Hartmann & Milićević 2009: exs. 2, 14, 23; Serbian)
(8.126) a. Ku-li-ku-wa na ma-endeleo sana.
sm7-pst-stm-be with cl6-development much
‘There was a lot of development.’
b. Dunia-ni ku na ku-danganyana kw-ingi.
cl9.world-loc sm17 with cl15-deceive cl15-much
(lit. ‘in the world therein (is) with much deceit’)
‘The world has a lot of deceit.’ / ‘There is a lot of deceit in the world.’
(Marten 2013: 48, 52, 53, Creissels 2014: 40; Swahili)
(8.127) a. Mayroong maysakit na aso (si Maria).
exist.there.lnkr sick lnkr dog sbj Maria
‘There is a sick dog’ (‘Maria has a sick dog’)
(cf. Sabbagh 2009: 683, 700; Tagalog (Austronesian))
b. (Ni-)baj-e ji-iba.
1sg-have-pf cl11-knife
‘There is a knife’ (‘I have a knife’)
(Bassène & Creissels 2011: exs. 18, 20; Jóola-Banjal (Niger-Congo))
(8.128) a. A lolovina lima-i-diat.
art long hand-poss.mrk-3pl
‘They had long arms.’ (lit. ‘(there were) long arms of theirs’122 )
b. Pa ka-gu ta vabirau.
neg possfr -1sg some light
‘I have not got a light.’ (lit. ‘(there is) no light of mine’)
(Mosel 1984: cf. 157, 164; Tolai (Austronesian))
(8.129) a. Tá leabhar agt Riley.
is book at Riley
‘Riley has a book.’
b. Níl arán ar bith ann.
is-not bread any in-it
‘There’s no bread.’
c. *Níl arán ar bith.
is-not bread any (McCloskey 2014: cf. exs. 23, 25; Irish)
222
In light of such data I offer (8.130) as a revised general v+n∗P analysis for (bare)
existential ‘there’ sentences.123 Analyzing the nominal predicates in existential sen-
tences as n∗Ps helps address the worries with (8.123)–(8.124). The contextual
domain restriction is captured via the broadly possessional/locational relation and
122
Tolai doesn’t use an overt ‘be’-like element with non-verbal predicates, as in (i) (Mosel 1984:
138, 159).
(i) a. Ia [a bul]pred .
she art child
‘She is/was a child.’
b. Iau [mamati]pred .
I from-here
‘I am from here.’
123
Given economy principles constraining implicit functional structure (Cardinaletti & Starke
1999, Katzir 2011), one might wonder whether predicative uses would be realized with the implicit
choice-function element in the nP. Support for such an analysis may come from languages in which
the pivot nominal can appear with an overt determiner, as in (ii) with Malagasy ny. Notably, although
ny is elsewhere typically interpreted as specific, as in (i), Law (2011: 1616–1618) reports that it lacks
this interpretation in the pivot of existential sentences.
(i) lasa ny mpianatra.
gone det student
‘The student(s) left.’
(ii) a. tsy misy ny zaza intsony.
not exist det child any longer
‘There are no children any longer.’
b. tsy misy ny fahamarinana.
not exist det justice
‘There is no justice.’ (Law 2011: exs. 113, 35, 116; Malagasy (Austronesian))
The proposed ‘be’+n∗P structure and predicative semantics may help capture insights from alter-
native “small-clause analyses” (Moro 1997, Hazout 2004, McCloskey 2014) and “NP analyses”
(Williams 1984, Chung 1987, McNally 1997, Sabbagh 2009): the single n∗P syntactic argument
of the light verb is a type of predicative noun phrase and a type of small clause (given a crosscategorial
conception of “small clauses” as e.g. v∗P/n∗P/p∗P; cf. Bittner & Hale 1996, Harley & Jung 2015,
Wood & Marantz 2017). As discussed below, saying this still allows for intra-/cross-linguistic
differences in syntactic/semantic properties of the relevant heads, and syntactic/semantic differences
between nominal pivots in existential sentences and other types of predicative constructions.
223
possessor/location — explicit in languages such as Irish, with ann — in Spec,n∗.124
A revised derivation for (8.124) is in (8.131), using ‘0-unicorns’ to abbreviate the
property of having zero unicorns as a part (cf. §§8.2, 8.8.1).125 (For clarity I will
use ‘Rp.loc ’ for the relevant possessional/locational relation.)
124
I continue to leave open the relation between the interpreted material supplying the relevant
domain (i.e., the “subject” of the n∗P) and the overt grammatical subject (if any) in particular
languages, such as existential ‘there’ in English (n. 100); and I ignore potential complications from
distinguishing sorts/types for locations (see e.g. Kracht 2002). McCloskey 2014 proposes to give
ann in Irish existential sentences the semantics of an existential generalized quantifier (type ⟨et, t⟩).
The meaning of ann in existential sentences is thus divorced from its general broadly locative meaning
as a PP. For languages without a specialized element such as ann, McCloskey suggests that the
existential meaning attributed to ann may be distributed among the copula or other verbal head.
The meanings of the copula/verbal element in Irish existential sentences is thus distinguished from
its meaning in existential sentences in (all?) other languages. If the approach to ann suggested in the
main text is on the right track, at least some of the distinctive properties of Irish existential sentences
can be captured without treating the syntax/semantics as radically different in these ways. ann may
be given its usual syntax and (bleached) semantics as a “preposition [which] projects a maximal
phrase [PP] and selects a null pronominal as its complement” (McCloskey 2014: 377n.25). (See
§8.4 on general challenges with assertion-of-existence/instantiation analyses.)
125
Note that whereas the (external head) nP’s world-pronoun in the QP in (8.91) (cf. (8.92)) could
receive a global reading, the account still predicts that no such reading is available for the pivot in
an existential ‘there’ sentence, even if the pivot is part of an n∗P; see n. 106.
224
(8.131) ‘There are no unicorns.’
S
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩
(∃) vP
Cd t1a
vbe n∗P
∃r
⟨2,a⟩ n∗P
X nP
u1s Rp.loc o3 -g1
t1s
F2cf∗ t2a
no# unicorns
JSK ≈ λgg . ∃xse ∃aa ∶ xs (g) = a(g)(2cf∗)(0-unicorns)(@(g−)) ∧
Rp.loc (g−(3e))(@(g−))(xs (g))
Roughly put, this says that the bare existential ‘there’ sentence with ‘no’ is true
iff there is a state os ∈ E such that os manifests some individual concept of an en-
tity having no unicorn as a part — intuitively, a state of having no unicorn as a
part — and the location of os (in @(gc )) is the contextually relevant location gc (3e).
Analogously to our examples of free R genitives, the type ⟨e, t⟩ relation+entity in
Spec,n∗ functions semantically as a restrictive modifier. The relevant locational
domain gc (3e) functions as a sort of metaphorical “possessor” of the witness state
os (see Lyons 1968: §8.4, Clark 1978, Freeze 1992, Barker 1995, Langacker
1995, Heine 1997, Marantz 1997, Borschev & Partee 2002, Heine & Kuteva
2002, Uriagereka 2002b, Larson & Cho 2003, Francez 2007, 2010, Zeshan &
Perniss 2008, Payne 2009, Creissels 2013 for relevant discussion). In a free R
possessive noun phrase ‘X’s N’, the relation+possessor restricts the denotation to
the set of Ns that are R-“possessed” by X; analogously, in (8.131), the denotation
of the vP is restricted to the set of “being-nP” states that are “possessed” by, in the
sense of being located at, gc (3e). If the relevant domain gc (3e) corresponds to the
225
entire world, the truth condition requires that the actual world-state be unicornless.
As in §8.4, there is no implication of N-instantiation/existence associated with the
“existential” ‘there’ construction itself (n. 101). The context-sensitivity of existential
sentences is now derived from the domain pronoun in Spec,n∗. Continuations such
as in (8.51) are still predicted coherent:
The fact that the witness state os at the relevant location gc (4e) is a state no part of
which is a pillow needn’t imply that there are there are no pillows in the world.
The above v+n∗P analysis extends directly to existential sentences with an addi-
tional “coda” phrase — sentences ‘There be YP ZP’ where the post-copular nominal
YP “pivot” co-occurs with a ZP “coda.” The alternative structures in (8.133) are
equally interpretable given our semantics for vbe and n∗ heads (cf. n. 109). In each
⟨i,a⟩
case ∃r QRs to adjoin to its nearest interpretable position (whether in the n∗P or
vP area). The compositional semantics for (b), with a ZP coda (right-)adjoined to
n∗/n∗P, proceeds as in (8.131)–(8.132) (cf. n. 109). In (c) the coda modifies the
verb phrase, as reflected in (8.135) with ‘on the couch’. As previously, vbe converts
the n∗P argument to a predicate of states. The locative coda supplies a further
restrictive modifier, restricting the denotation to states of being on the couch.126
A generalized polymorphic version of the lexical entry from (8.122) is in (8.134)
(cf. n. 65). The type-⟨e, t⟩ denotation for the lower vP segment combines (as in
⟨i,a⟩
(a)–(b)) via function composition with ∃r of type ⟨t, t⟩, yielding the type-⟨e, t⟩ vP
126
Interestingly, the same linkers marking restrictive modification in (i-a) are used also in pred-
icative uses such as (i-b).
(i) a. Karamihan sa mga internasyonal na transaksyon ay nangangailangan ng tiyak
most obl pl international lnkr transaction ay imperf.act.require gen specific
na mga dokumento na transportasyon.
lnkr pl document lnkr transportation
‘Most international transactions require specific transportation documents.’
b. Ang premyo ay isa-ng asul na dokumento na transportasyon.
sbj prize ay a.lnkr blue lnkr document lnkr transportation
‘The prize is a blue transportation document.
(cf. Sabbagh 2016: 652; Tagalog (Austronesian))
226
predicate. (For simplicity I leave ‘the couch’ unanalyzed, and I ignore any additional
domain pronoun in Spec,n∗.)127
⟨i,a⟩
(8.133) a. … [ vP vbe [ n∗P ∃r [ n∗P [us Rp.loc oe -g] [n∗ nP]]]]
⟨i,a⟩
b. … [ vP vbe [ n∗P ∃r [[n∗ nP] ZP]]]
⟨i,a⟩
c. … [ vP ∃r [ vP [[vbe [ n∗P n∗ nP]] ZP]]]
(8.134) Jvbe K = λP1et . . . λPnet .λxse .λgg . P1 (xs )(g) ∧ ⋯ ∧ Pn (xs )(g)
127
To fix ideas I assume an argument structure for the preposition parallel to that for relational
nouns. See Kracht 2002, Levinson 2007 for general analyses of locative PPs as predicates of
eventualities. Such a sortal restriction might be encoded in the lexical entries for certain prepositional
elements, though more would then need to be said to accommodate adnominal uses of locatives
with non-eventive noun phrases (see Kracht 2002: 199–202) — compare (i-a) vs. its ungrammatical
Finnish counterpart with locative adessive case in (i-b). (Thanks to Jussi Suikkanen.)
(i) a. The pillow on the couch is soft.
b. *[Tyyny sohva-lla] on pehmeä.
pillow sofa-ade is soft
c. Jussi [on/nukkui sohva-lla].
Jussi is/slept sofa-ade
‘Jussi is/slept on the couch.’
There are syntactic and semantic differences among codas inside and outside the noun phrase, such
as regarding extraction and discourse status (see Williams 1984, McNally 1997, Hazout 2004,
Bhatt 2006, Francez 2007, 2009, Hartmann 2008, Villalba 2013; also n. 90), e.g.:
(ii) a. There are three cats (in room 12) with a lot of hair.
b. *With how much hair are there three cats (in room 12)?
(iii) a. There are three cats in room 12 (with a lot of hair).
b. In which room are there three cats (with a lot of hair)?
(iv) a. The winners are three cats in room 12.
b. *In which room are the winners three cats?
(v) a. There is usually a teacher in a school.
≈ “for most situations in which there’s a school, there’s some teacher or other in it”
b. There is usually a teacher teaching in a school.
≈ “for most situations in which there’s a school, there’s some teacher or other teaching in it”
227
(8.135) There are three pillows on the couch.
S
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩
(∃) vP
Cd t1a
⟨2,a⟩
∃r vP
pP
∗
vbe nP
u1s
on
X nP the-couch
t1s
F2cf∗ t2a
three# pillows
This says, roughly, that (8.135) is true iff there is an on-the-couch state os which
includes three pillows as parts.
The revised compositional semantics of existential ‘there’ sentences in this sec-
tion has been speculative. Yet the proposed analyses may help systematize a range
of syntactic and semantic data, and avoid concerns with certain prominent accounts.
§8.4 focused on the distribution of quantifier words in the pivot. In addition, first,
the analyses maintain with much syntactic work that the pivot provides the main
predicate, and that overt codas such as in (8.135) are optional and function as (re-
strictive) modifiers (e.g. Williams 1984, McNally 1997, Hazout 2004, Sabbagh
2009, McCloskey 2014, pace Barwise & Cooper 1981, Keenan 1987, Gutiérrez Morales
2006: 25–26). Second, the account avoids syntactic and compositional semantic
problems with attempts to impose a generalized quantifier structure (e.g. Milsark
228
1974, Barwise & Cooper 1981, Keenan 1987, Zucchi 1995, Francez 2007, 2010,
Law 2011; see McNally 2011). The syntax/semantics of quantifier words in the
pivot is unified with their syntax/semantics in predicative uses generally (§8.4).
Third, the analyses provide structural grounds for commonalities between existen-
tial ‘there’ sentences and copular, possessive, and locative sentences, while still dis-
tinguishing them in their syntax and semantics. For instance, although the pivot pro-
vides the main predicate, the account avoids assimilating existential ‘there’ sentences
to copular sentences (e.g. Keenan 1987); and it avoids the semantic challenges
observed in §8.4 with assertion-of-existence/instantiation analyses (Milsark 1974,
McNally 1997, 1998, 2009, Chung & Ladusaw 2004, Sabbagh 2009, McCloskey
2014, Irwin 2018; (8.131)–(8.132)). The contextual domain pronoun+relation
in Spec,n∗ allows for interpretive connections between existential ‘there’ sentences
and locatives. The condition in (8.136a) is intuitively satisfied in our context c
iff the condition in (8.136b) is. Yet in (8.137a) ‘fires’ provides the main predicate
(cf. (8.136a)); in (8.137b) it is an nP subject of a predication structure, generated in
a possible θ-position (whether in the small clause complement of ‘be’ as per (8.136b)
(cf. Wood & Marantz 2017), or in an embedding v∗P; see nn. 93, 125). ((8.136b)
illustrates the structure prior to QR-ing the nP to the edge of the small clause (see
§§7.4, 8.2).)
Similarly, our general ‘be’+n∗P analysis for existentials extends naturally to pos-
sessive sentences such as those in (8.127)–(8.129), in which possessive ‘have’ is
overtly expressed via ‘be’ and a possessor PP: (8.138b) says, roughly, that Irish
(8.129a)/(8.138a) (literally ‘a book is at Riley’) is true iff there is some being-a-
229
book state of which Riley is the possessor (cf. (8.128b), nn. 67, 128). Yet it is
controversial whether ‘have’ is generally analyzable in this way across languages
(see Freeze 1992, Kayne 1993, den Dikken 1995, 1997, Harley 1995, 2002,
Español-Echevarría 1997, Heine 1997, Zeshan & Perniss 2008, Boneh & Sichel
2010, Creissels 2013, Harley & Jung 2015, Myler 2016).
Finally, the analyses in (8.135) and of nonpresuppositional uses in §8.2 may also
shed light on the correlation, observed by Milsark (1974, 1977), between pred-
icates excluded from codas and from copular sentences with nonpresuppositional
noun phrase subjects. Although the predicted LFs for (8.139a) and (8.139b) are
distinct (cf. (8.136)), the resulting semantic values both ultimately involve charac-
terizing an indefinite number of individuals as jackasses (cf. (8.136)). Whatever
exactly explains the oddity of predicating the “individual-level predicate” (Carlson
1980) ‘jackass’ in (8.139a) carries over to (8.139b). (If codas of the form in (8.139b)
are analyzed as reduced relatives, the point is even more straightforward; ‘jackass’ is
directly predicated of the relative-internal representation of ‘sm people’ (cf. Kayne
1994, Law 1999, Bhatt 2006, Sabbagh 2009).)
230
pronoun — to serve as the grammatical subject, other languages lack an overt subject
(e.g. (8.125a), (8.127), (8.128), nn. 100, 123). The verbal element may be implicit,
realized in (say) v or V, or distributed over multiple positions (cf. (8.125a), (8.128),
nn. 93, 100). English uses ‘be’; other languages use a dedicated predicate or co-opt
devices elsewhere used with locatives or possessives (e.g. (8.126)–(8.129), (8.138),
(8.140), nn. 121, 122, or the present tense version of (8.125a) in (8.141)). The
choice of light verb may provide further sources of crosslinguistic variation in the
structural complexity of the verb phrase.
One needn’t assume that all types of existential constructions across languages have
a uniform underlying syntax (contrast Freeze 1992, 2001). It is worth examining
more carefully to what extent the proposed compositional semantics for existential
‘there’ sentences might be adapted for different existential constructions in other
languages. Comparisons among bare existential sentences and existential sentences
with different types of codas (non-relative, reduced relative, relative), and appli-
231
cations to related predicate nominal and possession constructions, may provide
additional directions for future research.128
128
For relevant discussion see Lyons 1968: §8.4, Clark 1978, Mosel 1984: ch. 4, Szabolcsi
1986, Hoekstra & Mulder 1990, Tellier 1991, 1994, Kayne 1993, 2008, den Dikken 1995, 1997,
Harley 1995, 2002, Langacker 1995, Español-Echevarría 1997, Heine 1997, McNally 1997,
2016, Freeze 2001, Borschev & Partee 2002, Czinglar 2002, Dixon 2002, Vangsnes 2002,
Francez 2007, Lee-Schoenfeld 2007, Hartmann 2008, Payne 2009, Sabbagh 2009, Boneh &
Sichel 2010, Bosse et al. 2012, Frajzyngier 2013, Gaeta 2013, Villalba 2013, Wang & Xu
2013, Creissels 2014, McCloskey 2014, Tortora 2014, Myler 2016, Moro 2017; also nn. 67,
90, 93, 100, 121, 123, 127. For instance, the distinction between free R and inherent R readings
of possessive noun phrases (§7.2) has a counterpart with possessive sentences. In some languages,
morphological realizations of the distinction (see (7.29), (7.48)–(7.51), n. 67) are reflected also in
verbal possessives, as in (i)–(ii) with the added marker -tȟá- in free R possessive pronouns ((i-a))
and corresponding free R possessive verb itȟáwa ((ii-a)) (see also Nedjalkov 1997: §1.10, Heine
1997, Dixon 2010: 301–305, Stassen 2009: 210, 660–661, Aikhenvald 2013 and references
therein). The analysis of the n∗P in (8.138) corresponds to the §7.2-analysis of free R readings
(now representing the world-indexing with the relation pronoun). A corresponding LF for an
inherent R possessive sentence such as (iii) (cf. (8.128a)) is in (iv). In (8.138) the relevant relation
is contextually supplied by a world-indexed pronoun; in (iv) it is lexically supplied by the relational
noun ‘brother’. (Cf. Mosel 1984: §§4.3, 4.6, Tellier 1991, 1994, den Dikken 1995, Harley 1995,
2002, Español-Echevarría 1997, Heine 1997, Boneh & Sichel 2010, Myler 2016 for relevant
discussion; also nn. 67, 71, 72. I ignore any additional domain restriction in (iv).)
(i) a. mi-tȟá- wámakȟaškaŋ-pi kiŋ
1sg-poss animal-pl def
‘my animals’
b. mi- tȟuŋkašila
1sg grandfather
‘my grandfather’
(ii) a. Ni-mi-tȟawa.
2sg-1sg-have
‘You are mine.’ / ‘I have you.’
b. Tȟuŋkášila-wa-ya.
grandfather-1sg-have.kin
‘I have him as grandfather.’
(Helmbrecht 2016: 448–451, Williamson 1979: 359; Lakota (Siouan))
(iii) Tá deartháir agt Riley.
is brother at Riley
‘Riley has a brother.’
⟨2,a⟩
(iv) a. [ S T⟨1,a⟩ [[Cd t1a ]⟨1,s⟩ [(∃) [ vP vbe [∃r [ n∗P (…) [X [ nP t1s F2cf∗-t2a brother-Riley]]]]]]]]
∗
b. JSK ≈ λgg . ∃xe ∃aa ∶ x (g) = a(g)(2cf )(bro-of-Riley)(@(g−))
s s
232
The distinction between inherent R and free R readings also has a prima facie counterpart in the
verbal domain with double object constructions. In “high applicatives” (Pylkkänen 2000, 2008)
such as (v), the direct object is an argument of the verb, and the non-selected applied object(s)
supplies an additional thematic participant of the event; in the “true” benefactive in (v-a) the applied
object (‘Jose’) is introduced as the beneficiary of the event described by the verb+direct object
(‘close the door’). In “low” applicative constructions such as (vi), by contrast, the objects are directly
related by a possession-like relation (see also Marantz 1993, den Dikken 1995, Pesetsky 1995,
Harley 2002, Legate 2003, McGinnis 2003, Lecarme 2004, Lee-Schoenfeld 2007, Levinson
2007, Bruening 2010, Larson 2010, 2014, Bosse et al. 2012, Dixon 2012: ch. 25, Bosse 2015,
Harley & Jung 2015).
(v) a. Inepo Hose-ta pueta-ta eta-ria-k.
I Jose-acc door-acc close-appl-prf
‘I closed the door for Jose.’ (Harley 2013: ex. 8; Hiaki (Uto-Aztecan))
b. kit laa-lii-ȼṵq-yaa-na hun karta [hun pluma]inst [hun Mario]com
I applcom -applinst -write-impfv-applcom det letter det pen det Mario
‘I with Mario write a letter with a pen.’
(MacKay 1999: 283; Misantla Totonac (Totonacan))
(vi) a. Bert baked Alice the cookies (for Jose).
b. Minä keräsi-n jokaise-lta opiskelija-lta hänen lopputyö-nsä.
I show-1sg every-toposs student-toposs his/her grade-poss
‘I showed every student their grade.’ (Pylkkänen 2000: 201; Finnish)
c. A:sha mw-andik-il-ile Nu:ru xati.
Asha 3sg.obj-write-appl-t/a Nuru letter
‘Asha wrote Nuru a letter.’
(Kisseberth & Abasheikh 1977: 190; Chimwiini (Niger–Congo))
It would be interesting to explore how the proposed approach to the free/inherent R reading
distinction might be applied to different types of double object constructions. For instance, drawing
on the comparison between high applicatives such as (v) and inherent R readings, the direct object
might be merged as an internal argument of the verb, as reflected in the first-pass analysis in (vii) for
(v-a) (≈ ‘Bert closed (for) Jose the door’). The verb phrase denotes a certain set of closing-the-door
events — those of which Jose is the beneficiary and Bert is the agent. Like with external arguments,
the phrases introducing the non-subject roles supply additional restrictive modifiers (cf. (8.134)).
Different verbal applicative heads may place alternative restrictions on the relation introducing the
applied object, as reflected in (viii) for the instrumental+comitative double applicative in (v-b) (with
verbal prefix lii- + circumfix laa-…-na; cf. nn. 67, 69, 118). Interestingly, in Somali, benefactive
applicative constructions contrast with other types of applicatives in lacking genitive case ((ix-a) vs.
(ix-b); Lecarme 2004). There is no (possessive) n∗P in the representations of the “high” applicatives
in (vii)–(viii). (I continue to ignore potential sortal restrictions in the denotations of certain types of
roots (cf. Harley 2005, Levinson 2007).)
(vii) a. … [ v∗P [u1s Ragt Bert] [v∗agt [ vP [u1s Rben Jose] [vappl [ vP v t1s [ VP close the-door]]]]]]
b. JcloseK = λye .λws .λxe .λgg . close(y(g))(w(g))(x(g))
Jvappl K = λPet .λP′et .λxεe .λgg . P(xε)(g) ∧ P′ (xε)(g)
233
Jv∗PK = λxve .λgg . close(the-door)(g(1s))(xv (g)) ∧ Rben (Jose)(g(1s))(xv (g))
∧ Ragt (Bert)(g(1s))(xv (g))
(viii) a. … [ v∗P [u1s Ragt Bert] [v∗agt [ vP [u1s Rcom Mario] [vappl.com [ vP [u1s Rinst the-pen] [vappl.inst
[ vP v t1s [ VP write the-letter]]]]]]]]
b. Jv∗PK = λxve .λgg . write(the-letter)(g(1s))(xv (g)) ∧ Rinstr (the-pen)(g(1s))(xv (g))
∧ Rcom (Mario)(g(1s))(xv (g)) ∧ Ragt (Bert)(g(1s))(xv (g))
(ix) a. waa noó dagáal.
decl us+applben war
‘it is war for us’
b. is kú kay shéeg!
refl applto poss.1s say
(lit. ‘Introduce me.poss you.refl’)
‘Introduce yourself to me!’ (Lecarme 2004: 467, 465; Somali)
234
In “low” applicatives such as (vi-a), in contrast, the verb (‘bake’) specifies the type of event, and
objects in the double object frame (‘the cookies’, ‘Alice’) are directly related, as reflected in (xii)
for (vi-a). The n∗P introduces the set of individuals o′ that are identical to the cookies and to which
Alice bears the relevant possession-like relation. Importantly, the n∗P cannot in general be embedded
under (say) an extensional vcause , implying a “cause-to-have” interpretation (contrast e.g. Harley
2002, Bruening 2010, Harley & Jung 2015). As is well known from the (so-called) “imperfective
paradox,” the intended object may never come into existence. Discourses such as (x-a) are coherent;
likewise with the perfective in (x-b). The existence of the object o′ — and in double object sentences
such as (vi-a), its possession by the applied object — must rather be introduced as an intended goal
of the baking event ov . There are various ways of deriving this in the syntax and semantics. For
instance, the nominal small clause could be embedded under an intensional verbalizer vgoal , where
the verb originates as a modifier of little v (cf. (xii-a)); or the modality could be introduced directly in
an alternative entry for the root, where LFs with the “wrong” entry are filtered out for type reasons
(cf. (xii-b)) (see Marantz 2005, Levinson 2007, Harley & Jung 2015 on manner modification
in double object constructions; see Arad 2003, Levinson 2007 for general discussion on verbal
polysemies due to multiple denotations for roots). The first-pass alternative analyses in (xii-a)–(xii-b)
yield equivalent denotations for the vP, as reflected in (xii-c). For instance, the entry in (xii-b) says,
roughly, that vgoal takes properties F, F′ and returns the set of F′-events oε such that, for every world
in which oε isn’t interrupted and everything relevant to whether oε is completed proceeds as normal
or intended (written: every u ∈ goal(oε )), there is an F-individual (cf. Bonomi 1997b, Portner
1998, Silk 2016b). Whether the sentence implies that an entity corresponding to the direct object
exists can depend on the contribution of aspect, as reflected in the revised Parsons-style entries for
perfective vs. progressive in (xi), where ‘cul(oε )’ says that oε culminated and ‘in.prog(oε )’ says
that oε is in-progress (cf. Parsons 1990, Szabó 2008, Silk 2016b). The resulting semantic value
for the perfective sentence in (vi-a) is in (xii-c). (I ignore context-dependence of the set of worlds
given by goal (cf. Portner 1998, Silk 2016b). The modalized entries in (xii-a)/(xii-b) might also
explicitly encode that the possible eventuality in which the aim of oε is satisfied include oε as a
nonfinal subpart. For present purposes we can assume that such considerations are reflected in the
nature of the goal relation. I ignore world-indexing of the cul, in.prog, goal relations. I continue
to label the small clause representing the double object frame as n∗P, though, adapting proposals in
Pesetsky 1995, Harley 2002, Harley & Jung 2015, perhaps it might be treated as a p∗P, headed
by a null preposition.)
(x) a. Bert was baking Alice a cake, but he got interrupted; so there’s no cake (for her).
b. Bert baked Alice a cake, but he dropped it on the way to the party; so she never got it.
(xi) a. J∃pv K = λPet .λgg . ∃xεe ∶ P(xε )(g) ∧ cul(xε(g))
b. J∃prog K = λPet .λgg . ∃xεe ∶ P(xε )(g) ∧ in.prog(xε(g))
(xii) [ S T⟨1,a⟩ [ CP [Cd t1a ]⟨1,s⟩ [∃pv [ v∗P [u1s Ragt Bert] [ v∗ [ v∗ v∗agt …
a. [ vP [ v0 [vgoal t1s ] bake]⟨2,s⟩ [ n∗P [t2s Rposs Alice] [X the-cookies]]]] [ pP u1s forben Jose]]]]]]
Jvgoal K = λws .λP⟨s,et⟩ .λP′⟨s,et⟩ .λxεe .λgg . P(w)(xε)(g) ∧ ∀w′s ∶ w′ (g) ∈ goal(xε(g)) → ∃ye ∶ P′ (w′ )(y)(g)
⟨2,s⟩
b. [ vP v t1s [ VP bake2 [ n∗P [t2s Rposs Alice] [X the-cookies]]]]] [ pP u1s forben Jose]]]]]]
Jbake2 K = λP⟨s,et⟩ .λws .λxe .λgg . bake(w(g))(x(g)) ∧ ∀w′s ∶ w′ (g) ∈ goal(x(g)) → ∃ye ∶ P(w′ )(y)(g)
c. JbakeK = λws .λxe .λgg . bake(w(g))(x(g))
JvPK = λxεe .λgg . bake(g(1s))(xε(g)) ∧ ∀ws ∶ w(g) ∈ goal(xε(g)) → ∃ye ∶ Jn∗PK(y)(g[w(g)/2s])
235
JSK = λgg . ∃xve ∶ bake(@(g−))(xv (g))
∧ ∀ws ∶ w(g) ∈ goal(xv (g)) → (∃ye ∶ y(g) = the-cookies ∧ Rposs (Alice)(w(g))(y(g)))
∧ Rben (Jose)(@(g−))(xv (g)) ∧ Ragt (Bert)(@(g−))(xv (g)) ∧ cul(xv (g))
This says, roughly, that (vi-a) is true iff there is an ov such that (a) ov is a baking event of which
(b) Bert is the agent and (c) Jose is the beneficiary; (d) a goal of ov is the existence of an o′ that Alice
possesses (in the relevant sense) and is identical to the cookies — roughly, an o′ such that for all
worlds u in which no relevant interruptions occur and things proceed as intended (Bert doesn’t get
distracted, etc.), the cookies o′ exist and Alice has them (in the relevant sense); and (e) ov culminated.
Intuitively put: in baking, Bert did something with an aim of Alice having the cookies, and Bert did
it for Jose. Examples with combined high and low applicatives, such as (arguably) (xiii), may be
analyzed as in (xiv) (cf. also Kimenyi 1980: 101–107, Legate 2003: 194–199). The verb takes the
double-object n∗P structure as argument, and the verbal applicative head vappl introduces the dative
2nd-person possessor.
(xiii) Alla holisso chim-im-a:-li-tok.
child paper 2dat-3dat-give-1nom-past
‘I gave your papers to the child.’ (Davies 1981: 140; Choctaw (Muskogean))
(xiv) [ vP [u1s Rdat.poss Jose] [vappl [ vP [[vgoal t1s ] give]⟨2,s⟩ [ n∗P [t2s Rposs the-child] [X the-papers]]]]]
JvPK = λxεe .λgg . give(g(1s))(xε(g)) ∧ Rdat.poss (Jose)(g(1s))(xε(g))
∧ ∀ws ∶ w(g) ∈ goal(xε(g)) → ∃ye ∶ y(g) = the-papers ∧ Rposs (the-child)(w(g))(y(g))
Notably, the analysis derives a key move in Silk’s (2016b) largely informal account of creation verbs
and the imperfective paradox, in distinguishing the intensionality associated with the direct object
from the contribution of aspects such as the progressive. Unlike in modal accounts of the progressive
(Portner 1998), (xi) gives ∃prog a simple extensional semantics. There needn’t be any intensionality
in the interpretation of progressive sentences such as (xv) describing activities or processes (Silk
2016b: 28).
(xv) Alice is running.
The semantics in (xii) also avoids the problematic entailments pointed out in Larson 2010 for
Pylkkänen’s (2008) semantics for low applicatives; it captures the modal aspect of the intuitive
“(intended) transfer of possession” interpretation (contrast e.g. Levinson 2007, Pylkkänen 2008,
Bosse 2015); and it does so without ad hoc, non-compositional mechanisms such as in Bruening
2010, Bosse 2015 (e.g., interpreting the lexical verb in an intermediate landing site of non-type-
driven head movement, and not in its base position; vs. interpreting the direct and indirect/applied
objects both in their base positions and in their pronounced positions following non-type-driven
movement to the vP area; and invoking an additional composition rule specific to nodes combining
a Verb of type ⟨e, . . . ⟨e, vt⟩⟩ and Small Clause of type ⟨v, t⟩, yielding a “cause to have” implication
(Bruening 2010: 550–554)). It is worth exploring how the sorts of analyses in (8.138) or (xii) might
be extended to other double object verbs and constructions (see references above and in the main
text). A further interesting connection may be to Beavers 2011, which argues that many double
object sentences more generally have a modal aspect to their meaning (also Harley & Jung 2015).
236
(In the remaining chapters I will put aside the complications from this section
regarding events, the semantics of verbalizing heads, and the argument structures
of verbs. Unless otherwise relevant I will often ignore internal structure of nPs
and assume familiar NP, VP, DP category labels — NP for nP, VP for vP, DP for the
spread of functional projections above nP. I will generally represent quantifier words
introducing assignment-quantification as projecting their own category (QP, DP,
etc.); but, as discussed in §8.3, the account is compatible with treating quantifier
phrases as n∗Ps in which the quantifier adjoins to the lower n∗P segment.)
237
Part III
9 Conditionals
9.1 Local and global readings
Conditionals provide diverse sources of local and global readings of variables and
context-sensitive expressions. For instance, there are (i) global readings in both ‘if’-
clause and consequent clause, as in (9.1); (ii) local readings in the ‘if’-clause, as in
(9.2); and (iii) local readings in the main clause, as in (9.3).
238
b. *Shei yells at Bill if Maryi is hungry.
(Bhatt & Pancheva 2006: exs. 19a, 21a)
(9.5) Adnominal ‘if’-clause. NP-adjunction
[[The [ NP location if it rains]] and [the [ NP location if it doesn’t rain]]] are
within five miles of each other. (Lasersohn 1996: ex. 10)
(9.6) [Context: Lingens and Lauben know they are kidnapped amnesiacs. They
are informed that they will be anesthetized, and a coin will be flipped: if it
lands tails, Lingens will be released in the Stanford library and Lauben will
be killed; if it lands heads, Lauben will be released in the Harvard library and
Lingens will be killed. After the experiment, one of them wakes up and says:]
If the coin landed heads, I am in Widener Library, Harvard.
(Santorio 2012: ex. 6)
(9.7) a. John broughti an umbrella [if it rained]i (…and Alice did [bringj an umbrella
[if it rained]j ] too).
b. Everyonei will come [if John wasn’t invited]i .
c. We shouldi block Shaft A [if the miners are in Shaft A]i .
(cf. Kolodny & MacFarlane 2010)
d. Ii [VP am in Widmore Library [if the coin landed heads]i ].
e. Bert is in Widmore Library if the coin landed heads, and Ii am in Widmore
Library [if the coin landed heads]i too).
(9.8) a. The [ NP righti thing [if utilitarianism is correct]i ] is to donate.
b. [[ DP Myi location [if the coin landed heads]i ] and [ DP myj location [if the
coin landed tails]j ]] are on opposite coasts.
239
derive the relevant range of shifted/non-shifted interpretations in examples such as
(9.4)–(9.5) or (9.7)–(9.8) where the ‘if’-clause combines with a VP or subject NP.
Historically, work on the semantics of conditionals has proceeded largely in
isolation from syntax literatures on ‘if’-clauses and other types of conditional con-
structions. To some extent this is to be expected. Many questions regarding the
semantics of conditional can be addressed without taking a stand on, say, whether
‘if’ is in C or Spec,C in different languages, possibilities for reconstruction, etc. But
if our project is to provide a genuine compositional semantics, we must ensure
that whatever type of semantics we go in for will generalize across the spectrum
of environments in which ‘if’-clauses (and other markers of conditionality) appear.
Whatever syntactic/semantic package we take on board must (i) derive local
readings in the consequent and in the antecedent — shifting in the scope of a sup-
position as well as in the supposition itself, as in (9.2)–(9.3); (ii) must do so in
a way that still allows for global readings in both clauses, as in (9.1); and (iii)
must capture how ‘if’-clauses can combine directly with a VP/NP and shift the in-
terpretation of material within the VP/NP they modify, as in e.g. (9.7a)/(9.8a), as
well as of external material in the sentence, as in e.g. (9.7d). The type of the ‘if’-
clause must be suitable to combine with and modify expressions of multiple types.
The remainder of this section shows how we can satisfy these desiderata, drawing
on independent syntactic work on ‘if’-clauses as free relatives/correlatives. The
compositional semantics affords a uniform analysis of ‘if’-clauses in diverse types
of conditionals — conditionals with sentence-initial/-internal/-final ‘if’-clauses, and
in conditionals with/without an overt modal or a proform such as ‘then’. As we
will see further in §10, the account affords uniform treatments of conditional and
individual proforms, and of conditional, correlative, and interrogative clauses.
So I assume that our best syntactic story for conditionals will involve some other
way of capturing the idea that ‘if’-clauses function to modify a domain. In §§6, 8.7
240
we drew on crosslinguistic data and syntactic analyses to motivate treatments of
individual- and assignment-quantification in headed relative clauses. Syntactic anal-
yses of ‘if’-clauses as free relatives (Iatridou 1991, Lycan 2001, von Fintel 1994,
Bittner 2001, Schlenker 2004, Bhatt & Pancheva 2006) provide analogous mo-
tivations for sources of world- and assignment-quantification in conditionals. Like
other free relatives (Jacobson 1995, Dayal 1996, Caponigro 2012), ‘if’-clauses are
interpreted as definite descriptions. In some languages conditionals are overtly real-
ized as such (cf. also Furbee 1973: 15, Welmers 1973: 433–434, Hale 1976). The
Somali conditional clause from (6.28b) (§6.2.1), reproduced in (9.10), is realized
as a remoteness-marked (modal-past) definite description (cf. §8.8.1). The Warlpiri
construction in (9.11) is ambiguous between a conditionalizing interpretation and
an interpretation as an individual definite description.
However, rather than treating the variable relativized over as a variable over worlds
or events (as in Schein 2003, Schlenker 2004, Bhatt & Pancheva 2006, Haegeman
2010), we can treat it as a variable over assignments: ‘if’-clauses are analyzed as
definite descriptions of possibilities, represented via assignments.
Given the variable means of expressing conditionality, both in English and cross-
linguistically, it is common to treat conditional interpretations as arising indepen-
dent of particular complementizers such as ‘if’ (Bhatt & Pancheva 2006, Rawlins
2008). A prominent approach is to treat the conditional element as raising above the
241
complementizer from within the ‘if’-clause (Bhatt & Pancheva 2006, Arsenijević
2009, Haegeman 2010; cf. Larson 1985, Kalivoda & Zyman 2015). Movement
analyses of conditional clauses provide independently motivated resources for im-
plementing an analysis of ‘if’-clauses into the §3-framework — notably, a comple-
mentizer such as ‘if’, and clause-internal movement of an operator responsible for
conditional interpretations. A schematic LF is in (9.12), where ιh is the raised
operator (implicit in English), parallel to ιo in certain free relatives of individuals
(§§6.1.2, 7.2).129 Preliminary lexical entries for ‘if’ and ιh are in (9.13)–(9.14).
(9.12) CP
⟨i,a⟩
ιh C
⟨j,s⟩ IP
if tia . . . tjs . . .
(9.13) JifK = λaa .λpst .λws .λgg . @(a(g)) ⊑ w(g) ∧ ∀w′s = λg′g .@(a(g′ )), p(w′ )(g)
(to be revised)
(9.14) Jιh K = λAat .λA′at .λgg . ∃aa ∶ (A(a)(g) ∧ ∀a′′a ∶ A(a′′ )(g) → a′′ (g) ⊑ a(g))
∧ A′ (a)(g)
= λAat .λA′at .λgg . ∃aa ∶ (a(g) = the maximal h ∈ G s.t. (↓ A)(h)) ∧ A′ (a)(g)
≈ λAat .λA′at .λgg . [ιa(g)∶ A(a)(g)] A′ (a)(g)
The lexical entry for ‘if’ in (9.13) is a sort of intensional analogue of the entry
for the relative complementizer Crel . The world argument determines a relevant
domain of possibilities. ιh converts the set of possibilities into a definite description
of the maximal plural possibility in the set. The type-⟨at, ⟨at, t⟩⟩ entry for ιh is a
modal analogue of the type-⟨aet, ⟨aet, t⟩⟩ entry for ιo (§§6.1.2, 7.2, 8.8.1). (9.14)
129
Although Bhatt & Pancheva (2006) don’t specify the generation site of the conditional
operator, Haegeman (2010) argues against treating it as moving from within the VP. Haegeman
treats the operator as semantically modal and as sharing properties specifically with syntactically
high (broadly epistemic) modals. Such a view may provide further support for the present treatment
of the operator as moving from above the VP (in particular, from an internal argument in C0if ).
242
is essentially a definite version of the entry for modal verbs such as ‘may’ in §3.130
Let’s consider these components in turn.
First, following general treatments of free relatives as plural definite descrip-
tions, the assignment described by the ‘if’-clause may be a plural assignment repre-
senting a plural possibility (cf. Jacobson 1995, Dayal 1996, Grosu & Landman
1998, Schein 2003, Bhatt & Pancheva 2006). As discussed in §8, the components
of the model E, W, G are structured to include plural objects, or sums (Link 1983,
1998, Schwarzschild 1996). The metalanguage ι operator in (9.14) can again be
understood along the lines of Link’s (1983) σ operator, which returns the maximal
element of a set (formally, the m in the set S such that ∀m′ ∈ S∶ m′ ⊑ m). The
uniqueness implication applies to the items in the model. Just as there may be
multiple functions x ∶ Dg → E mapping g to the unique individual o ∈ E picked out
by a definite description, there may be multiple functions a′ ∶ Dg → G mapping g to
the relevant unique possibility h ∈ G described by an ‘if’-clause.
Even after incorporating plurality, our analysis should reflect some way of re-
stricting the quantification to relevant (salient/live/remote) assignments satisfying
the antecedent. Informally put, the external argument of ‘if’ supplies a topical
In languages such as Toqabaqita, Oceanic the same element mada used in introducing con-
130
ditional clauses, with the irrealis marker sa ((i-a)), introduces an epistemic possibility when used
alone in main clauses ((i-b)). The conditional marker (a)sika in (ii-a) is etymologically related to the
marker for possibility (a)sik in (ii-b); in (ii-c) the introduction of the relevant possibility functions as
a threat (cf. e.g. Dixon 1972: 113, 362, Dixon 2009).
(i) a. Mada sa dani qe qaru …
mada irr rain 3sg.nonfut fall
‘If it rains, …’
b. Mada qe mataqi.
mada 3sg.nonfut be.sick
‘He might be sick.’ (Lichtenberk 2008: 8, 38, 776; Toqabaqita (Austronesian))
(ii) a. Sika chan d� ngia tham� n s� th� m ngo.
‘If he comes, you tell me.’
b. Ngua tu gus� � n� � ng ia saika angama marupki, sik mailu chia mat angama sechithom
ma mndu ngua munaik nithom bono.
‘I thought that possibly one of the cassowaries, maybe it got one of the traps that I left there.’
c. Ngia thamon s� th� m ngo marik, asik tiathik k� lan, asik ngu
2sg.cl1 tell.fut to 1sg.cl3 really asik now only asik 1sg.cl2
chut.m� -nge n� =gu=a chep-ki tiathik.
spear.nonpres-you inst=1sg.poss=art spear-f.sg emph.this
‘Tell me truly, otherwise this time it’s like this, I’ll shoot you with this spear of mine.’
(Stebbins 2012: 47, 157, Stebbins 2009: 372; Mali (Baining, New Britain))
243
(plural) possibility which provides the backdrop for the supposition, as reflected
in (9.15).131
⟨2,a⟩
ιh C′′ ∶ t
C′ ∶ ⟨s, t⟩
w2 g1
⟨2,s⟩ IP ∶ t
244
relatives of individuals treated the external argument of Crel as a selected individual
o in a contextually relevant domain, supplied by the relative phrase.
Given the proposal that ‘if’-clauses are free relatives of possibilities, it is worth ex-
ploring how we might unify our analyses of the relevant types of free relatives. The
alternative analysis in (9.16)–(9.17) parallels the analysis of DP-like free relatives.
(9.16) JifK = λaa .λpst .λws .λgg . @(a(g)) = w(g) ∧ ∀w′s = λg′g .@(a(g′ ))∶ p(w′ )(g)
(9.17) CP⟨2,a⟩ ∶ ⟨t, t⟩
⟨2,a⟩ t
ιh
⟨s, t⟩
Just as the relative phrase ‘what’ is analyzed intuitively as “which relevant thing(s),”
the external argument of ‘if’ is analyzed intuitively as “which relevant world(s).”
The external argument could be construed as an implicit ‘whether’ analogous to the
relative phrase (see e.g. Larson 1985, Kayne 1991 on ‘whether’ being in Spec,C).
In §6 we analyzed relative words as choice-function pronouns. A natural move is
to analyze the ‘whether’-like element in an ‘if’-clause likewise as a choice function
pronoun of worlds — a function s ∈ D⟨st,t⟩ such that p(s(p)) for any pst ((4.19)).
(For clarity I distinguish ‘sf’ for choice-function indices/variables of type ⟨st, s⟩; I
continue to use ‘cf’ with choice functions of type ⟨et, e⟩.) The proposition pronoun
[pst g] functions analogously to the class restrictions in free relatives of individu-
als (§8.8.1). Free relative ‘what’ selects an individual from a subdomain of things,
and free relative ‘who’ selects an individual from a subdomain of persons; likewise
the constituent [whsf -g pst -g] in a free relative ‘if’-clause selects a world from a
domain of relevant worlds. The choice-function pronoun is again (obligatorily)
245
coindexed with the conditional complementizer’s assignment argument. In (9.17)
⟨2,a⟩
the assignment-quantification introduced by the raised pluralization operator ιh
binds the choice-function pronoun, here [wh2sf g2 ], and quantifies over possibilities
in the restricted set that satisfy the property denoted by the ‘if’-clause C. The
compositional semantics derives that the conditional free relative (9.17) picks out
(roughly) the sum of relevant possibilities in which it rained — the unique maximal
possibility h ∈ G such that it rained in @(h), where @(h) is identical to some or other
selected relevant world u ∈ gc (1st) ⊆ W.132 Free relative ‘if’-clauses are analyzed as
intensional analogues of free relatives of individuals. (I return to the extent of the
similarities in §§9.7, 10.)
Note that the semantic type of the ‘if’-clause CP is derived to be type ⟨t, t⟩ — the
same type of the adjoined DPs in our examples with inverse linking and genitive
binding from §7.4 (n. 88). We will see that function composition and the ⟨t, t⟩-
type of the ‘if’-clause can similarly be exploited to help satisfy our desiderata from
§9.1 — e.g., capturing the spectrum of (non-)shifted readings with sentence-initial
‘if’-clauses as well as with sentence-final ‘if’-clauses adjoined to VP and with NP-
adjoined ‘if’-clauses in adnominal conditionals.
246
adjoined to an NP in the main clause (Lasersohn 1996).133 (For simplicity assume
that ‘the’ has a standard ⟨et, ⟨et, t⟩⟩ entry, and treat ‘expensive’ as an ⟨e, t⟩ predicate.)
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a
DP
t1s expensive
the NP ∶ ⟨e, t⟩
fine
w1 g2 ⟨2,a⟩
ιh
⟨2,s⟩
wh2sf -g2 p1st -g1
if t2a you2 -g1 t2s drive
247
JNPK = JCP⟨2,a⟩ K ○ JNP1 K
= λxe .JCP⟨2,a⟩ K(JNP1 K(x))
≈ λxe .λgg . [ιa(g)∶ g(1a)(2e) drives in @(a(g))
∧ @(a(g)) = a(g)(2sf)(g(1a)(1st))] x(g[a(g)/2a]) is a fine in a(g)(1s)
JSK ≈ λgg . [ιx(g)∶ [ιa(g)∶ g−(2e) drives in @(a(g))
∧ @(a(g)) = a(g)(2sf)(g−(1st))] x(g) is a fine in a(g)(1s)]
x(g) is expensive in @(g−)
This says, roughly, that the fine in the maximal relevant possibility h where you
drive is expensive in the actual world @(gc ). The modified subject DP picks out the
unique o ∈ E such that o is the fine in the world (=h(1s)) of the maximal relevant
possibility where you gc (2e) drive — i.e., the maximal possibility in which you drive
and which is identical to some or other possibility h(2sf)(gc (1st)) in the contextually
relevant domain gc (1st). The sentence is true iff o is expensive in the world of the
discourse @(gc ).
Like in simple sentences, the main clause complementizer raises from the world-
argument position of the clause’s main predicate (‘(be) expensive’). The world
argument of the subject predicate ‘fine’ is supplied by a world pronoun. However,
the assignment binder-index on the ‘if’-clause shifts the coindexed world pronoun
[w1 g2 ] to the world of the assignment representing the hypothetical possibility,
i.e. the maximal relevant possibility a(g) where you drive. The ‘if’-clause CP is type
⟨t, t⟩, the predicate is type ⟨e, t⟩, and they combine via function composition to yield
the modified subject NP of type ⟨e, t⟩.
The §9.2-semantics compositionally derives the local reading of the subject NP’s
world pronoun in (9.18). Yet nothing said thus far excludes an LF where the world
pronoun is coindexed with the topmost assignment-binder, e.g. [NP1 fine w1 g1 ],
representing an unattested reading implying that the fine in the actual world is
expensive. Although the complex subject NP needn’t receive a local reading in an
embedded adnominal conditional, as reflected in (9.19), the interpretation of the
world pronoun must still shift, it seems, with the adjoined ‘if’-clause.
(9.19) Alice thinks that the location if it rains is sure to go out of business before
the party.
a. [We’re talking about Alice’s beliefs about the prospects of the different
possible venues for our party, depending on the weather:]
Specific ≈ “the venue in the possibility where it rains is such that Alice
thinks it will go out of business before the party”
248
b. [We haven’t settled on particular possible venues, depending on the
weather; Alice is a downer:]
Nonspecific ≈ “Alice thinks that there will be some venue or other in the
possibility where it rains, and it, whatever it is, will go out of business
before the party”
Intuitively put, this says that binder-indices necessary for interpretability in a given
step in a derivation must do non-trivial semantic work in that step in the derivation.
(9.21) is of course directly satisfied in cases of QR, where the moved expression
necessarily binds its trace. With a base-generated adjunct, (9.21) amounts to a
norm that the modifier genuinely modify the expression to which it is adjoined.
In an adnominal conditional such as (9.18) the ‘if’-clause’s assignment-binder is
“semantically necessary” in the sense of (9.21); without it, CP and NP1 would be
134
The pronounced word order could be derived by rightward QR (cf. e.g. Fox 2002), alternatively
by leftward QR followed by leftward movement of NumP. For simplicity I assume the former.
249
types ⟨at, t⟩ and ⟨e, t⟩, respectively, and hence the complex NP node would be
uninterpretable. So, lest the non-triviality principle be violated, the world-pronoun
must be coindexed with the ‘if’-clause’s assignment-binder, representing the shifted
reading.
Adjudicating between these options would require careful examination of nar-
rowly syntactic considerations. Given our purposes we needn’t take a stand here.135
In either case, note that accepting (9.20) is compatible with treating certain ‘if’-
clauses as base-generated adjuncts; and accepting (9.18) is compatible with treating
(9.21) as a violable (extra-grammatical) interpretive principle. For instance, con-
sider the syntax/semantics for the relevance conditional in (9.22). Like in simple
sentences, the topmost assignment-binder raises from the assignment-argument po-
sition of the main clause complementizer, linking the modal domain for the main
clause to the world of the discourse via the definition of truth-in-a-context. The
‘if’-clause is base-generated in its interpreted position adjoined to the main clause.
Roughly put, (9.22) is true in c iff the maximal relevant possibility where you (=gc (2e))
are hungry — the maximal possibility where you’re hungry and which is included in
the contextually relevant domain gc (1st) — is such that I (=gc (1e)) baked in the
actual world @(gc ). The LF and semantic value in (9.22) thus derive common
intuitions about relevance conditionals, such as that they involve an assertion of
the consequent, and independence of the antecedent and consequent: The ‘if’-clause
introduces a modal topic — the possibility that you’re hungry — but then fails to
comment on it in the main clause; the sentence implies that I actually baked. The
‘if’-clause in the relevance conditional is treated on a par with a “frame-setting” topic
(Reinhart 1981) such as (9.23).
250
9.4 Sentence-final ‘if’-clauses
The account of ‘if’-clauses combining with subject predicates carries over to condi-
tionals with sentence-final ‘if’-clauses that adjoin to verbal predicates. First, note
that treating the world argument of the main predicate as supplied by a world-trace
coindexed with the higher complementizer would fail to capture the role of the ‘if’-
clause in shifting the modal domain:
(9.24) a. [S T⟨1,a⟩ [CP [CI t1a ]⟨1,s⟩ [Alice [VP [VP1 t1s won] [CP if-clause]⟨2,a⟩ ]]]]
b. JVP1 K = λxe .λgg . x(g) won in g(1s)
JVPK = λxe .λgg . [ιa(g)∶ . . . ] x(g[a(g)/2a]) won in g[a(g)/2a](1s)
JCPK ≈ λgg . [ιa(g)∶ . . . ] Alice won in @(g(1a))
JSK ≈ λgg . [ιa(g)∶ . . . ] Alice won in @(g−)
Our syntax/semantics for declaratives from §3 helped capture (among other things)
the apparent obligatory local reading of the predicate’s world argument. Yet we
needn’t assume that all occurrences of complementizers necessarily undergo raising
from their base-generated position (cf. §8.7.1). The relevant modal domain for
interpreting the main predicate in examples with VP-modifiers isn’t in general a do-
main determined by the embedding assignment-quantifier — e.g., T⟨1,a⟩ , determin-
ing @(gc ) — but rather a domain as modified by the adjunct. Accordingly, I suggest
that the main predicate’s world argument in such examples may be supplied by a
world-pronoun. The matrix complementizer in (9.25) can be treated as denoting
the identity function. An LF and derived semantic value is in (9.7d), assuming the
context from Santorio 2012 in (9.6) where ‘I’ receives a local reading.136
136
Note that the vacuous complementizer C∅ is distinct from the unpronounced complementizer
Cd . I represent the world-pronoun in VP1 with an ordinary assignment variable; though, as discussed
in §9.3, I leave open whether the coindexing with the ‘if’-clause may be derived via A-movement.
In terms of the architecture from §8, in an adnominal conditional the ‘if’-clause would QR out of n
adjoining to nP; likewise in an adverbial conditional such as (9.25) the ‘if’-clause would QR out of v
adjoining to vP.
251
(9.25) Sentence-final ‘if’-clause. Shifted indexical. (VP-adjunction)
‘I am in Widmore Library if it landed heads.’
S∶t
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
IP
C∅ t1a
VP ∶ ⟨e, t⟩
I1 g2
in-WL
w1 g2 ⟨2,a⟩
ιh
⟨2,s⟩
wh2sf -g2 p1st -g1
if t2a it2 g1
t2s landed-heads
⟨2,a⟩
JIPK = (JCP K ○ JVP1 K)(λgg .g(2a)(1e))
≈ [λxe .[λTt .[λgg .[ιa(g)∶ g(1a)(2e) landed heads in @(a(g))
∧ @(a(g)) = a(g)(2sf)(g(1a)(1st))] T(g[a(g)/2a])]]
(λgg .x(g) is in WL in g(2a)(1s))] (λgg .g(2a)(1e))
≈ λgg . [ιa(g)∶ g(1a)(2e) landed heads in @(a(g))
∧ @(a(g)) = a(g)(2sf)(g(1a)(1st))] a(g)(1e) is in WL in a(g)(1s)
JC∅ K = λaa .λTt .λgg . T
JSK ≈ λgg . [ιa(g)∶ g(2e) landed heads in @(a(g)) ∧ @(a(g)) = a(g)(2sf)(g−(1st))]
a(g)(1e) is in WL in a(g)(1s)
The conditional is true iff the maximal relevant possibility h ∈ G where the contex-
tually relevant object gc (2e) landed heads, @(h) = h(2sf)(gc (1st)), is such that the
shifted counterpart individual h(1e) is in WL in the world of that possibility h(1s).
The pronoun ‘it’ in the ‘if’-clause is interpreted with respect to the discourse
assignment, while the predicate ‘landed-heads’ receives an obligatory local reading
derived via movement of the complementizer ‘if’. As with the adnominal conditional
252
in (9.18)/(9.20), the ‘if’-clause combines with the lower VP segment via function
composition, yielding the complex VP of type ⟨e, t⟩. The ‘if’-clause shifts the inter-
pretation of the coindexed world-pronoun in VP1 , capturing the local reading of the
sentence’s main predicate. Crucially, although the ‘if’-clause doesn’t combine at the
level of the main clause, the subject pronoun ‘I’ can still receive a local reading under
the supposition. The shifted reading of the subject is compositionally derived from
the general analysis of ‘if’-clauses and function composition. (As in our examples
with modals, one might invoke additional principles specifying that the syntactic
indexing determined by the concrete discourse be such that a(g)(1e) represents an
epistemic counterpart of gc (1e), who is the speaker of c (§§3–4).)
(9.26) [Context: We know everyone’s height. We haven’t settled on how tall one
must be to count as tall.]
Ifi she is talli , she made the team.
253
(9.27) Sentence-initial ‘if’-clause (CP-adjunction)
S∶t
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
CP ∶ t
C∅ t1a
⟨2,a⟩
ιh
⟨1,s⟩
⟨2,s⟩
Cd g2 she3 -g1 t1s made-the-team
wh2sf -g2 p1st -g1
In both (9.27) and (9.28), the individual pronoun representing ‘she’ receives a global
reading. Whereas the world argument of the predicate ‘is tall’ in the ‘if’-clause re-
ceives an obligatory local reading, derived from type-driven movement, the degree-
standard pronoun [d1 g2 ] associated with the adjective receives an optional local
⟨2,a⟩
reading, represented via coindexing with the clause-internal assignment-binder ιh :
The relevant standard for tallness is the standard in the supposition. The possibility
described by the ‘if’-clause is thus a possibility h ∈ G in which gc (3e)’s height in
@(h) = h(2sf)(gc (1st)) is at least as great as the standard determined by h for
254
counting as tall. The conditional is true iff gc (3e) made the team in the world of
that possibility.
In (9.28) the world argument of the sentence’s main predicate (‘made-the-team’)
is supplied, as in §9.4, by a world-pronoun receiving its interpretation from the ad-
joined ‘if’-clause; the derived modal domain, given our metasemantic assumptions,
represents the world of the possibility represented by a(g), i.e. a(g)(1s) = @(a(g)).
The predicted semantic value for (9.29) with IP-adjunction is equivalent to the
semantic value derived in (9.25) where the ‘if’-clause is sentence-final, adjoined to
VP (again on the “shifted indexical” reading from Santorio 2012, where the inter-
pretation of ‘I’ in the main clause is determined relative to the possibility introduced
by the ‘if’-clause).
By contrast, in (9.27) the modal domain for interpreting the main clause is explicitly
identified with @(a(g)). The main predicate’s world argument is supplied by a
world-trace left from movement of the complementizer; and the complementizer’s
assignment argument is supplied by an assignment-variable coindexed with the ‘if’-
clause. In both cases the topmost assignment-binder raises from the assignment
argument position of C∅ , as in (9.25). However, in (9.27), where the ‘if’-clause
adjoins to a full CP, there is an independently motivated mechanism for generating
the vacuous complementizer embedding the conditional: CP-recursion (Iatridou &
Kroch 1993; see Vikner 1995, Browning 1996, Nyvad et al. 2017 for general
discussion). Conditionals with sentence-initial ‘if’-clauses — and correlatives gener-
ally (de Vries 2002) — follow the complementizer in attitude ascriptions.
(9.30) Alice thinks [ CP1 that [ CP2 [if it snows] [ CP3 (then) school will close]]]
255
Hypothetical conditionals (in the sense of Iatridou 1991) can be understood
as a type of correlative construction, in which the free relative clause (obligatorily)
binds a correlate in the main clause (Geis 1970, Iatridou 1991, von Fintel 1994,
Bittner 2001, Schlenker 2004, Bhatt & Pancheva 2006, Arsenijević 2009).
Such data lead Bhatt & Pancheva 2006 to deny that hypothetical ‘if…’ conditionals
without ‘then’ are correlatives. This strikes me a prima facie cost. Like other cor-
relatives, hypothetical ‘if…’ conditionals without ‘then’ consist of a sentence-initial
free relative clause which shifts the interpretation of an element in the main clause.
137
One way of formalizing the relevant notion of adjacency might be that β is structurally adjacent
to α iff (i) α c-commands β , and (ii) there is a non-branching path from β which terminates at
the sister of α. (One could say that α and β are structurally adjacent iff α is structurally adjacent
to β or β is structurally adjacent to α.) For broader discussion of locality effects in correlatives
crosslinguistically, see Dayal 1996, Bhatt 2003, Davison 2009a, Leung 2009, Lipták & Rebuschi
2009, Lipták 2012, Beshears 2017.
256
Unlike relevance conditionals, where the main clause intuitively describes a condi-
tion in the actual world (cf. §9.3), hypothetical conditionals shift the modal domain
with or without ‘then’. The main clause correlate needn’t be overtly expressed —
in conditional correlatives, or in certain correlatives of individuals, such as (9.36b)
from §6.2.1 (see also Iatridou 2013). The relation between relevance conditionals
and hypothetical conditionals with/without ‘then’ is analogous in this respect to
the relation between “frame-setting” topics and individual correlatives (“aboutness”
topics) with/without a proform (Reinhart 1981; cf. Lipták 2012).
The analysis in this section captures the connection between hypothetical ‘if…’ con-
ditionals and correlatives. The free relative ‘if’-clause is coindexed with the assignment-
variable determining the modal domain relevant for interpreting the main clause.
We will return to analyses of ‘then’ and correlative proforms in §9.7. For now,
note that treating hypothetical conditionals generally as correlatives is compati-
ble with acknowledging a contrast between conditionals with and without ‘then’.
Overtly expressing the conditional proform requires raising it from its base position
and topicalizing it (cf. Izvorski 1996, Arsenijević 2009, Lipták 2012), as reflected
in (9.37) (bracketing for now any internal structure in the ‘then’-ZP).
Explicitly topicalizing the proform can have distinctive interpretive and syntactic
effects. It is often claimed that ‘If p, then q’ conditionals carry an implication to the
effect that some/all ¬p-possibilities are ¬q-possibilities (cf. Iatridou 1991, 1994,
von Fintel 1994).
Izvorski 1996 shows that this exhaustiveness implication associated with condi-
257
tional ‘then’ is shared among correlative proforms generally. In correlatives of in-
dividuals the proform is also interpreted at LF in a topicalized position in the left
periphery of the main clause (Lipták 2012). It isn’t implausible that focusing the
proforms in this way leads to the apparent exhaustiveness implications — hence the
exclusion of ‘then’ in (9.33) where the antecedent is already exhaustive. Topi-
calizing the proform can also have syntactic implications, as in (9.34); A-raising
the proform to Spec,C excludes further argument or adjunct extractions out of the
main clause (Iatridou 1991, Iatridou & Kroch 1993, Collins 1998, Bhatt &
Pancheva 2006, Lipták 2012; cf. Dayal 1996, Izvorski 1996, Hiraiwa 2005).
So, the assignment-variable-based syntax/semantics for hypothetical condition-
als in this section unifies ‘if…(then)’ with correlatives in the sense that there is a
left-adjoined free relative clause which binds a correlate in the main clause. In
conditionals with ‘then’ the proform is topicalized. We can capture the idea that
‘if’-clauses function notionally as topics (Haiman 1978, Bittner 2001) without
analyzing all conditional constructions as involving topicalization-driven movement.
Adapting the approach to quantifier domain restriction in von Fintel 1994 (cf. n. 26),
one option would be to treat modal verbs as taking a resource domain argument in
addition to the modal background representing the reading of the modal (epistemic,
deontic, etc.), as reflected in (9.40). (As previously, I use ‘r’ in indices for type ⟨s, at⟩.
Ignore any contextual restriction in the external argument of ‘if’, where W represents
a pronoun contextually identified with W. See n. 28.)
258
(9.40) Modalized conditional (IP/ModP-adjunction)
‘If it rains, he may cry.’
S∶t
T⟨1,a⟩ CP ∶ t
⟨1,s⟩ t
Cd t1a
CP⟨2,a⟩ ∶ ⟨t, t⟩ t
⟨2,a⟩
ιh
⟨3,a⟩
⟨2,s⟩ ⟨3,s⟩
wh2sf -g2 W t1s rains
t1s he3 -g1 t3s cry
if t2a may g2 r1 g1 Cd t3a
JmayK = λaa .λAat .λA′at .λgg . ∃a′a ∶ a′ (g) ⊑ a(g) ∧ A(a′ )(g) ∧ A′ (a′ )(g)
JSK ≈ λgg . [ιa(g)∶ it rains in @(a(g)) ∧ @(a(g)) = a(g)(2sf)(W)]
∃a′ ∶ a′ (g) ⊑ a(g) ∧ g−(1r)(@(g−))(a′ (g)) ∧ g−(3e) cries in @(a′ (g))
This treats the modalized ‘may’ conditional as saying that the maximal relevant
possibility h in which the antecedent is verified is such that some accessible pos-
sibility that is a part of h verifies the consequent. Roughly put, (9.40) is true iff the
maximal relevant possibility where it rains h is such that the contextually relevant
individual gc (3e) cries in some possibility h′ that is a part of h and is included in
the set of accessible possibilities, as determined by the contextually relevant modal
background gc (1r) at the actual world (gc ).
The modal ‘may’ in the consequent is interpreted with respect to the same con-
textually relevant domain of possibilities (=gc (1r)(@(gc ))) as would figure in the
interpretation of an unembedded ‘may’ sentence. The relevant reading is supplied
by the discourse assignment, and the modal background is indexed to the actual
world. The binder-index on the ‘if’-clause is coindexed with the assignment-variable
supplying the modal’s resource domain argument; the role of the ‘if’-clause is simply
259
to restrict the domain to possibilities where it rained. As von Fintel (1994) notes,
this relation between the ‘if’-clause and the modal’s restrictor argument is apparently
stronger than an optional binding relation. For instance, in nested conditionals such
as (9.41) the modal receives the restriction of the closest ‘if’-clause (cf. Bhatt &
Pancheva 2006).
(9.41) If you get back in time for the show, then [if Timmy isn’t tired]i we’ll have toi
take him.
The connection between the topical possibility described by the ‘if’-clause and the
modal’s resource domain may be understood as an instance of the locality require-
ment on correlative correlates discussed above (cf. n. 137). Indeed, drawing on
Dayal’s (1996) account of individual correlatives, von Fintel suggests analyzing
the relation between the ‘if’-clause and restrictor argument as an A-chain (1994:
88–89). On the movement-based approach discussed in §9.3, the (obligatory) coin-
dexing between the ‘if’-clause and the modal’s resource domain argument follows
by type-driven movement.
260
(9.42) Modalized conditional (CP-adjunction)
S∶t
T⟨1,a⟩ CP ∶ t
CP ∶ t
C∅ t1a
CP⟨2,a⟩ ∶ ⟨t, t⟩ CP ∶ t
…if …
⟨3,s⟩
⟨3,a⟩
Cd g2
. . . t3a . . .
may
r g t3s
I suggest that such LFs can represent so-called “double modal” and “information-
sensitive” readings of modalized conditionals.
First, examples such as (9.43) have led some theorists to posit that at least
some modalized conditionals have a covert modal in addition to overt modal in the
consequent (Frank 1996, Geurts 2004, von Fintel & Iatridou 2005, Swanson
2010).
(9.43) If marijuana is illegal here, we have to report Alice. (cf. Geurts 2004: ex.
1)
≈ “for every epistemically accessible world u where marijuana is illegal,
every world v conforming to the law in u is such that we report Alice
in v”
In a Kratzerian restrictor approach, the ‘if’-clause restricts the domain of the covert
(epistemic) necessity modal, and the overt deontic modal is evaluated at each world
in the covert modal’s restricted domain. The (simplified) derivation in (9.44) cap-
tures such “double modal” readings without positing a covert modal. (Assume that
in the intended interpretation r2 represents a modal background for the relevant
laws.)
261
(9.44) “Double modal” reading
S∶t
T⟨1,a⟩ CP ∶ t
CP ∶ t
C∅ t1a
⟨2,a⟩
ιh
⟨3,s⟩
JCP1 K ≈ λgg . ∀a′a ∶ g(1a)(2r)(@(g(2a)))(a′ (g)) → g(1a)(1e) report Alice in @(a′ (g))
JSK ≈ λgg . [ιa(g)∶ marijuana is illegal in @(a(g)) ∧ @(a(g)) = a(g)(2sf)(W)]
∀a′a ∶ g−(2r)(@(a(g)))(a′ (g)) → g−(1e) report Alice in @(a′ (g))
This says, roughly, that the maximal possibility where marijuana is illegal h is such
that for every possibility h′ compatible with the law in @(h), i.e. every h′ ∈ gc (2r)(@(h)),
we report Alice in @(h′ ).
As in (9.27), the correlative ‘if’-clause is coindexed with the assignment-variable
g2 in the adjacent complementizer, which determines the modal domain for evalu-
ating the main clause. The felt “double modal” interpretation follows from the fol-
lowing combination of features: (i) the modal’s modal-background pronoun [r2 g1 ]
receives its interpretation from the discourse assignment gc , as in (9.40); however,
(ii) the world applied to the modal background is the world of the antecedent-
verifying possibility @(h). The discourse context supplies the relevant function
⟨s, at⟩ from worlds to sets of possibilities, gc (2r), which represents the law and
determines the intended deontic reading of the modal. What the law provides may
vary across worlds. In contrast to (9.40), the specific content of the law relevant
for evaluating the modalized main clause is the law in the possibility h in which
262
marijuana is illegal. The ‘if’-clause introduces a topical possibility, and the modal’s
deontic modal background is indexed to the world of that possibility.
The informal intuition in the literature on information-sensitivity is that the
deontic modal’s modal background seems to be updated, in some sense to be ex-
plained, in light of the information in the antecedent, as reflected informally in
(9.45) (e.g. Kolodny & MacFarlane 2010, Dowell 2012, Charlow 2013b, Cariani
et al. 2013, Silk 2014b, 2016a).138
(9.45) [Context: Ten miners are trapped in shaft A or shaft B, but we don’t know
which, and floodwaters are threatening. All ten miners will be saved if we
block the shaft they’re in, but all ten will drown if we block the wrong shaft.
One miner will drown if we block neither shaft.]
If the miners are in shaft A, we have to block shaft A.
≈ If the miners are in shaft A, then, given that information, the deon-
tically preferred worlds are worlds where we block shaft A. (Though,
given our actual information, the deontically preferred worlds are worlds
where we block neither shaft.)
138
On related phenomena with modalized conditionals generally, see Gillies 2010, Yalcin 2012,
Charlow 2013a. Given our purposes I ignore any differences between weak/strong necessity modals
in information-sensitivity (see Charlow 2013b, Silk 2016c).
263
(9.46) “Information-sensitive” reading
S∶t
T⟨1,a⟩ CP ∶ t
CP ∶ t
C∅ t1a
CP⟨2,a⟩ ∶ ⟨t, t⟩ CP ∶ t
⟨2,a⟩
ιh ⟨3,s⟩
CI g2 ⟨3,a⟩
⟨2,s⟩
wh2sf -g2 p1st -g1
⟨4,s⟩
if t2a the-miners t1s in-A have-to
t3s Cd t3a we1 -g1 t4s block-A
r3 g2
This says, roughly, that the maximal relevant possibility where the miners are in
shaft A, h, is such that, for every possibility h′ compatible with the deontic ideal
determined by h — i.e. every h′ ∈ h(3r)(@(h)) — we block shaft A in @(h′ ).
As in (9.44) the modal domain for evaluating the modalized main clause is set by
the assignment-variable g2 in the complementizer coindexed with the correlative ‘if’-
clause. However, the deontic modal-background pronoun — here [r3 g2 ] — receives
a local reading as well. The deontic modal background for evaluating the modal’s
prejacent is determined by the topical antecedent possibility that the miners are in
shaft A. Crucially, this possibility may be a plural object. The plural possibility a(gc )
represents a state throughout which the miners are in shaft A. Which deontic ideal,
set of accessible worlds, etc. is determined by a possibility may be due to a feature of
the possibility qua plurality. The discourse context may be such that gc (3r) implies
that we block neither shaft; yet its image under a, such that the miners are in shaft
A in the world of every part of the plurality a(gc ), may determine a deontic ideal
a(gc )(3r) implying that we block shaft A.
264
Some theorists have appealed to information-sensitive readings to motivate re-
vising traditional semantics for modals and conditionals. For instance, modals’
domains of quantification may be treated as determined relative to an additional
parameter such as an information state (e.g. Kolodny & MacFarlane 2010, Silk
2014b). Plural domains may provide the structure to capture intuitions behind cer-
tain revisionary approaches to information-sensitivity while still relativizing modal
backgrounds simply to worlds, as in the traditional semantics. An analysis of condi-
tionals as plural definite descriptions may thus be of general interest, independent
of the assignment-variable implementation developed here.
Let’s recap. This section has examined how an assignment-variable-based ap-
proach to local/global readings and our accounts of modals and relative clauses
may be extended to conditionals. The syntax/semantics in §9.2 yields a uniform
analysis of ‘if’-clauses in various positions and conditional structures — in sentence-
final positions adjoined to VP, in sentence-initial positions adjoined to IP/CP, and
in adnominal conditionals when adjoined to NP; in conditionals with/without a
proform such as ‘then’; and in conditionals with/without a main clause modal.
‘If’-clauses are analyzed syntactically as free relatives and interpreted as plural defi-
nite descriptions of possibilities, represented by assignments. The account composi-
tionally derives various types of local readings and ways ‘if’-clauses may shift/modify
the interpretation of modals and other expressions, while still allowing for global
readings in the ‘if’-clause and the rest of the sentence. In correlative constructions
the sentence-initial ‘if’-clause binds a correlate in the main clause. The correlate may
be overtly expressed and topicalized such as in hypothetical ‘if…then’ conditionals.
The next section briefly considers how the proposed assignment-variable-based syn-
tax/semantics for hypothetical conditionals might be extended to correlatives and
correlative proforms more generally.
265
can be ambiguous between a conditional and individual correlative interpretation,
as we saw in (9.11), reproduced in (9.47), and (9.48) (see also Cable 2009 on
Lhasa Tibetan, Davison 2009b on Sanskrit).
266
9.7.1 Individual correlatives and proforms
An example with a multiple correlative of individuals is in (9.49).139 (I use Cif for
the complementizer, where JCif K = JifK . The external argument could be repre-
sented with [whsf -g pst -g], as in conditionals, where the semantic value for [p g] is
ultimately identified with {gc (1s)} = {@(gc )}. However, for clarity I represent the
external argument in individual correlative interpretations with a world-pronoun. I
use the English glosses and word order.)
267
S∶t
T⟨1,a⟩ CP ∶ t
⟨1,s⟩ IP ∶ t
Cd t1a
⟨2,a⟩
ιh
Informally, this treats the correlative as saying that the assignment providing a true
answer to the question “which girli played with which boyj ?” verifies the matrix
clause statement “that girli defeated that boyj ”. The correlative clause describes the
unique possibility in which the selected girl o (=a(g)(2cf)(girlg(1s) )) played with
the selected boy o′ (=a(g)(3cf)(boyg(1s) )), where the world u of that possibility is
such that u = gc (1s). The sentence is true iff o defeated o′ in @(gc ).
First, the individual correlative clause in (9.49) is given the same structural
representation as an ‘if’-clause. In (9.49) the world of the possibility introduced in
the correlative clause is specified as being identical to, gc (1s) — given our metase-
mantic assumptions, the world identical to the world of the discourse @(gc ). The
topical possibility is the unique actual possibility in which a certain girl played with
268
a certain boy. The main clause says that that same girl defeated that same boy. The
correlative binding requirement is captured by (i) the syntactic representation of the
proform as a copy of its antecedent relative word and here elided NP,140 and (ii) the
assignment-quantification introduced by ιh in the correlative clause.
In a slogan: Individual correlatives are material relevance conditionals with
donkey pronouns (cf. n. 132, §9.3) — (i) “material” insofar as the modal domain for
the correlative clause is restricted to the actual world gc (1s): the correlative clause
describes a possibility in the actual world; (ii) “relevance” insofar as the modal
domain for the main clause is identified directly with @(gc ) via the syntax/semantics
interface: the main clause comments on the actual world; and (iii) “donkey” insofar
as the main clause proforms are anaphorically identified with their non-c-command-
⟨2,a⟩
ing antecedents [wh-g2 P], via the correlative clause assignment-binder from ιh .
The relevant similarity between correlative proforms and donkey pronouns is
that both are represented (roughly) as copies of a non-c-commanding linguistic
antecedent. Comparing them in this way isn’t to assimilate correlative constructions
to donkey sentences (see also n. 78; more on this below).141 For instance, as
discussed in §6.2, in Hindi a bare nominal can serve as a donkey pronoun but not
the correlate in a correlative.
140
Recall that the anaphoric expression need only be a copy with respect to interpreted material
at LF (§6.2). Possible differences such as with respect to case raise no issues (see Bhatt & Lipták
2009). I assume that [wh]-features are present for syntactic and phonological reasons; correlate
proforms needn’t be [+wh] or spelled-out as relative/wh-phrases. The analysis is also compatible
with there being differences in φ-features in certain examples, as in (i) where the plural proform is
linked to both singular relative phrases. As in §6.2 for the case of donkey pronouns, such examples
may be understood analogously to other phenomena where pronouns’ φ-features are uninterpreted,
such as with “fake indexicals”; see n. 51.
(i) [jo laRkiii jis laRkej se baat kar rahii hai] ve{i,j} ek saath sinemaa jaayeNge
which girl which boy with talk do-prog-pres they together movie go
‘Which girl is talking to which boy, they will go to the movies together.’ (Dayal 1996: 204)
141
Other types of non-c-command anaphora with conventionally anaphoric expressions, as in (i)
with Sinhala ee ‘that.anaph’, may be analyzed similarly. Though conventionally anaphoric pro-forms
are used as the obligatory correlates in correlatives (in languages that have them, as in (1.11) with
Bangla), they may also be used in environments not requiring a matching anaphoric expression, such
as donkey configurations, as in (i) (contemporary Sinhala lacks correlatives; Gair 1998: 306n.5).
(i) [Gunәpaalәgei pawulә gœnә wiswaasәyә nisaa] eyaai karәdәree wœṭuna.
Gunapala.gen wife about belief because that.anaph trouble fell
‘Because of Gunapala’si faith in his wife, hei fell into trouble.’ (Gair 1998: 134)
269
(9.50) a. har aadmii jis ke paas koii gadhaai hotaa hai gadheKOi
every man rel with some donkey has donkey
maartaa hai.
beats
‘Every man who has a donkey beats it.’
b. *[jo aadmii aayaa]i aadmiii acchaa hai.
rel man came man nice is
‘Which man came, man is nice.’ (Srivastav 1991: ex. 45; Hindi)
Individual correlates are also often overtly realized as morphologically complex (see
§§6.2.1, 7.3). In some cases the overt NP in the correlate may differ from the
antecedent NP, typically denoting a contextual superset (e.g. Dayal 1996, Davison
2009a, Beshears 2017) — hence the qualification above that the proforms are an-
alyzed as copies of the antecedent relative/wh word.
That said, there are interesting crosslinguistic similarities between donkey sen-
tences and correlatives. For instance, though Cable 2009 avoids giving “a ‘simple’
conditional analysis” (219n.7; 204–205) of Tibetan correlatives, he notes that the
correlatives are glossed literally as conditional donkey sentences:
(9.51) [Khyodra-s gyag gare nyos yod na] nga-s de bsad pa yin.
you-erg yak what buy aux if I-erg that kill perf aux
‘I killed whatever yak you bought.’
lit. ‘If you bought what/a yak, I killed that/it.’ (Cable 2009: 195; Tibetan)
Indeed correlative proforms are typically formed from a demonstrative — or, in lan-
guages which have them, a specialized anaphoric pronoun.142 Individual correlates
also pattern with donkey pronouns, in contrast to bound-variable anaphors, in being
replaceable with an epithet, as reflected in (9.52) vs. (9.53)/(9.54).
270
(9.54) [jis aadmii-se tum bahut pyaar-se baat kar rahe the]
rel man you much love talk do prog be
us aadmii-ne/haraamii-ne mujh-pe muqadma Thonk rakh-aa hai.
dem man/bastard me-on court.case hammer.in keep be
‘Which man you were talking with so nicely, that man/bastard is suing me.’
(Potts et al. 2009: exs. 27, 29)
A key feature of the account of ‘if’ conditionals in this section is that it yields a uni-
fied semantics for ‘if’-clauses in various structural positions, such as in conditionals
involving adjunction to NP, VP, IP, CP. This feature carries over to correlatives, as
reflected in the DP-adjunction example in (9.56).143
271
S∶t
T⟨1,a⟩ CP ∶ t
⟨1,s⟩ IP ∶ t
Cd t1a
DP ∶ ⟨et, t⟩ VP ∶ ⟨e, t⟩
t1s tall
⟨2,a⟩
ιh she2 -g2 girl-w1 -g1
w1 g1
⟨2,s⟩
The correlative clause CP⟨2,a⟩ describes the unique possibility in which the selected
girl o ∈ E (=a(g)(2cf)(girl1s )) is standing, where the world of that possibility is
identical to the world of the discourse g(1s) = @(gc ). The sentence is true iff that
selected girl o is tall in @(gc ).
The type e individual proform can be lifted to type ⟨et, t⟩ in the usual way.
Analogous to our examples with NP-/VP-adjoined ‘if’-clauses in §§9.3–9.4, the type
⟨et, t⟩ proform DP1 combines via function composition with the adjoined type ⟨t, t⟩
272
correlative clause CP⟨2,a⟩ , yielding the main subject DP of type ⟨et, t⟩. The complex
subject denotes, roughly, the set of properties P characterizing the selected girl
o = a(g)(2cf)(girlg(1s) ) in the relevant actual possibility in which o is standing.
As in the clausal adjunction example in (9.49), the identification of the topical
individual picked out by the relative phrase with the individual picked out by the
correlate is captured by the representation of the anaphoric expression as a copy of
its antecedent, here [F2cf -g2 girl-w1 -g1 ], and the assignment-quantification/binder
introduced by the definite pluralization operator in the correlative clause.
To my knowledge the only compositional semantics for correlatives to explicitly
address DP-adjunction correlatives is Dayal 1996. Dayal gives the correlative clause
the semantics of a generalized individual quantifier (type ⟨et, t⟩), which, in clausal
adjunction examples, binds the proform — represented as a variable — in the main
clause. For DP-adjunction examples Dayal briefly suggests invoking a mechanism of
crosscategorial quantification (1996: 207). Very roughly, the proform variable DP1
is first lifted to type ⟨et, t⟩, yielding λPet .P(i); this is then converted to type ⟨e, t⟩
by adding a property variable Q and abstracting over the proform variable, yielding
λx.[λP.P(x)](Q) = λx.Z(Q). This combines with the type ⟨et, t⟩ correlative clause
to yield an object of type t for the subject DP, which is then converted to type ⟨et, t⟩
by abstracting over the previously introduced property variable Q, yielding roughly
λZet .Z(ιx∶ girl(x) ∧ standing(x)) for a DP such as in (9.56).
This is not compositional. Dayal’s account invokes independent abstraction
rules and principles for introducing property variables into the semantics in order to
derive the semantic value for the modified subject DP — notably, in converting the
proform to predicative type ⟨e, t⟩ to combine with the correlative clause, and then
in converting the result of type t back to generalized quantifier type ⟨et, t⟩ in order
to combine with the clause’s main predicate. Note that in combining the nodes of
type ⟨et, t⟩ it must be stipulated which node is to be converted to predicative type
⟨e, t⟩ (namely, the node for the proform).
The account in this section avoids needing to introduce additional semantic
mechanisms such as these. Correlative clauses and proforms in examples involving
IP/CP adjunction and DP adjunction are given a uniform syntax/semantics: In both
cases the correlative clause denotes an object of type ⟨t, t⟩, and the proform is
represented as a copy of its linguistic antecedent. The shifted interpretation of the
proform is derived from the general analysis of the relevant anaphoric expressions
(following §6.1), and the derived assignment binder projecting to the correlative
clause. The semantic value derived in (9.56) is equivalent to the semantic value
273
derived for the alternative structure in which the correlative clause adjoins at the
clausal level.
T⟨1,a⟩ CP ∶ t
⟨1,s⟩ IP ∶ t
Cd t1a
CP⟨2,a⟩ ∶ ⟨t, t⟩ IP1 ∶ t
...
t2s tall
she2 -g2 girl-w1 -g1
JSK = J(9.56)K ≈ λgg . [ιa(g)∶ a(g)(2cf)(girlg−(1s) ) is standing in @(a(g))
∧@(a(g)) = g−(1s)] a(g)(2cf)(girlg−(1s) ) is tall in @(g−)
The account in this section assimilates individual correlative clauses and conditional
clauses; they include the same definite operator of assignments, which raises from
an equivalent complementizer. In contrast, the implicit quantifier in non-correlative
free relatives such as (6.13), reproduced in (9.59), may be given the same sort of
274
assignment-quantificational semantics as the matrix determiners in §§6–8 (ignoring
worlds and any contextual restriction associated with ‘what’; n. 46).
C
wh3 -g2 E
⟨1,e⟩
The plural definite element ιo picks out a unique maximal individual. The plural def-
inite element ιh in a correlative/conditional picks out a unique maximal possibility.
Yet I think there are reasons to be dissatisfied with approaches along these lines,
reasons both theory-internal and independent of an assignment variable framework.
Analyzing ‘then’ as a simple pronoun leaves various linguistic phenomena with
conditional proforms unexplained. First, crosslinguistic work on correlatives shows
that correlative proforms undergo movement to the left periphery of the main clause
(esp. Izvorski 1996, Lipták 2009b, 2012, also Bhatt 2003, Arsenijević 2009).
275
Interestingly, whether this movement occurs overtly or covertly in a given language
often patterns with certain A-movements. For instance, in English, an overt wh-
movement language, ‘then’ also raises overtly, as in (9.61). An individual correlative
analogue of (9.61a) is in (9.63).
With individual proforms, one might say that the movement patterns with wh move-
ment given their association with the relative/wh phrases in the correlative clause
(cf. n. 139). One might wonder what would provide the basis for the movement
patterns with a conditional proform like ‘then’, if the correlative construction simply
involves world pronoun anaphoric to a pluralization operator. Even if the proform
isn’t itself a wh-phrase and the raising may be triggered for reasons of topicalization,
analyzing (e.g.) ‘then’ as a simple variable leaves it obscure why the overt/covert
status of the movement would correlate with that of wh-words.
Second, if ‘then’ is a simple world pronoun, one might wonder why the pronoun
would in many cases be lexicalized by an expression specified as being anaphoric
to an ‘if’-clause. For instance, although English has various proforms which prima
facie serve as propositional anaphors, such as ‘that’, ‘it’, or ‘so’, only ‘then’ can be
anaphoric to an ‘if’-clause (or other supposition). Likewise, in German, although
proforms such as es can be anaphoric to a proposition, only dann ‘then’ can correlate
with a conditional wenn ‘if’ clause:
276
It isn’t the case that correlative proforms in general lexically specify a particular type
of antecedent. Crosslinguistically, the proform is typically a demonstrative.
Third, in individual correlatives the correlate may consist of a bare demonstra-
tive, as in (9.65a), or a demonstrative with an explicit nominal, as in (9.65b).
144
As in §§9.3, 9.5, I bracket whether the coindexing between the ‘if’-clause and assignment-
variable g2 in the correlate may be derived via movement. I leave ‘then’ in its fronted position,
though I leave open whether it might instead be interpreted in its trace position (cf. Bhatt 2003,
Sportiche 2006). The LF in (9.66) leaves the main clause complementizer position empty. This
choice of representation isn’t forced on us. For instance, one could represent the structure of the
‘if…then’ conditional as in (9.27), and analyze ‘then’ as topicalizing the unpronounced declarative
complementizer’s assignment-variable; the derived semantic value would be equivalent. Yet one
motivation for (9.66) may come from comparisons with V2 (verb-second) languages such as German,
where ‘then’ (e.g. dann) is followed directly by the verb in the complementizer position (see Iatridou
1991, Iatridou & Kroch 1993 for discussion in the context of CP-recursion). ‘Then’ could still be
analyzed as in (9.66), though with the verb in C. I return to these issues in §10.5 when considering
conditional questions.
277
(9.66) ‘If…then’
‘If it landed heads, then I am in Widmore Library’
S∶t
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
CP ∶ t
C∅ t1a
⟨2,a⟩
ιh YP⟨1,s⟩ ∶ ⟨t, t⟩ C∶t
e IP
⟨2,s⟩ then2sf -g2 p1st -g1
wh2sf -g2 p1st -g1
if t2a it2 -g1 t2s heads I1 g2 t1s in-WL
The type s world argument is lifted to type ⟨st, t⟩ in the usual way, and after at-
tachment of the binder-index becomes type ⟨t, t⟩. The ‘then’-phrase combines via
function application with the consequent, shifting the relevant modal domain to
that determined by the ‘if’-clause. Parallel to the individual correlative in (9.49),
the correlative binding requirement is captured by (i) the representation of the
proform as a copy of the implicit ‘whether’-element in the correlative clause, here
[wh2sf -g2 p1st -g1 ], and (ii) the assignment-quantification introduced by ιh . Roughly
put: ‘then’ is to ‘whether’ ((9.66)) as dem/‘that’ is to rel/‘which’ ((9.58)/(9.65)).
Let’s recap. The accounts of relative clauses and conditionals in §§6–9 have
developed a unified assignment-variable-based syntax/semantics for relativization.
This subsection suggested one way of extending the comparisons to correlative
clauses and proforms in individual and conditional correlatives. Alternative inter-
278
pretations are derived from differences in the (individual, modal) relative phrases
in the correlative clause and their relation to corresponding (individual, modal)
elements in the main clause. For instance, individual correlative interpretations
arise when (among other things) the correlative clause is such that the external
argument for the complementizer is identified with the actual world, the relative
⟨i,a⟩
(individual) choice-function pronoun [whcf gi ] is bound by ιh , and the world pro-
noun in the relative-phrase NP is bound long-distance and anchored to the world of
the discourse. Correlative proforms are analyzed uniformly as topicalized copies of
their relative/wh antecedent. I am not aware of other analyses of ‘then’ that capture
the syntactic/semantic connection between conditional proforms and proforms in
individual correlatives.
Our discussion has been speculative. It is worth examining more thoroughly
how the accounts of relativization and conditionality in these sections might help
capture other similarities/differences among free relatives, correlatives, condition-
als, and interrogatives — e.g., regarding the connections between exhaustivity and
uniqueness interpretations and topicalization/wh-movement. §10 examines how
the assignment-variable-based treatments of conditionals and correlatives can be
extended to interrogatives.
279
10 Interrogatives
This section begins investigating how the assignment-variable framework may be
applied to non-declarative sentences, focusing on interrogatives. Key features of
the proposed account are as follows:
280
a. ≈ Does our giving to Charity X follow from what our norms gc (i) enjoin?
Would our giving to Charity X maximize overall happiness?
(10.5) Is Rita richi ?
a. [Context: S knows approximately how much money Rita earns (say,
$X/yr), and S thinks that A does too. Hoping to ascertain A’s views on
whether such a salary counts as rich, S utters (10.5).]
≈ What is the standard for richness like (=value for the degree standard
g(i))? Is it, whatever it is, greater than around $X/yr? (local reading)
b. [Context: We’re millionaires and we agree that one must be a million-
aire to count as rich. Hoping to ascertain Rita’s income, S utters (10.5).]
≈ Is Rita’s income enough to make her a millionaire? (global reading)
281
10.2 Syntax, semantics, metasemantics
It is standard to distinguish at least two elements in the interpretation of interrog-
ative sentences: (i) an interrogative complementizer (call it C? ), which may e.g.
trigger interrogative movement in languages such as English, and (ii) a question
operator (call it Q), which provides the source of the question semantics (e.g. Dayal
1996, Cable 2010, Kotek 2014; note that the lexical item Q is distinct from the po-
tential Q(uantifier) category from §§7.1, 8). Heim 2012 suggests a syntax in which
the question operator is base-generated as an argument of the interrogative com-
plementizer and raises as a quantifier over propositions. Heim’s account provides
precisely the sort of precedent for an interrogative analogue to our §3-treatment of
declaratives. Our syntax/semantics for declaratives treated assignment-quantifiers
as raising for type reasons from an internal assignment argument position of the
declarative complementizer (e.g. ‘that’). Drawing on Heim’s suggestion, we can try
treating Q as raising for type reasons from an assignment argument position of C? .
Whereas Heim includes an independent node for the binder-index to trigger a non-
compositional Predicate Abstraction rule, we can treat Q as combining via function
application with the generalized binder-index, as reflected in (10.6).
(10.6) S
Q⟨i,a⟩
[C0 ]⟨j,s⟩ IP
C? tia …tjs …
282
constitutes the world of the possibility represented by the assignment. (For clarity I
use the underlining in (10.7) to visually distinguish the presuppositional constraint.)
(10.7) JC? K = λaa .λpst .λws .λgg ∶ @(a(g)) = w(g) . ∀ws′ = λg′g .@(a(g′ ))∶ p(w′ )(g)
(10.8) JQK = λAat .λTt .λgg . ∀aa = λgg .g− ∶ ∃g′′g ∶ T = [λg′ ∶ g′ ≈ g′′ . A(a)(g′ ) = A(a)(g′′ )]
a. g ≈ g′ ∶= ∀iτ [¬(τ = s ∧ g(iτ ) = g′ (iτ ) = @(g) = @(g′ )) → g(iτ ) = g′ (iτ )]
(10.9) JQ⟨j,a⟩ K = JQK(J⟨j,a⟩ K) = λT′t .λTt .λgg . ∀aa = λgg .g− ∶ ∃g′′g ∶
T = [λg′ ≈ g′′ . T′ (g′ [a(g′ )/ja]) = T′ (g′′ [a(g′′ )/ja])]
145
Officially, as with T, I leave open whether Q raises to Spec,C or projects its own phrase such as
ForceP (n. 17). In the general definition of the binder-index (§3.5): with C? , τ = s, σ = ⟨s, t⟩; with
Q, τ = a; σ = ⟨t, t⟩.
283
(10.10) Simple yes/no question
‘Did you laugh?’
S ∶ ⟨t, t⟩
Q⟨2,a⟩ CP ∶ t
C
w1 g2
⟨1,s⟩ IP
C? t2a
you2 g1 t1s laugh
JCPK ≈ λgg ∶ @(g(2a)) = g(2a)(1s) . g(1a)(2e) laughed in @(g(2a))
≈ λgg . g(1a)(2e) laughed in @(g(2a)) = g(2a)(1s)
JSK ≈ λTt .λgg . ∃g′′ ∶ T = [λg′ ≈ g′′ . g′ (1a)(2e) laughed in @(g′− ) = g′−(1s)
iff g′′ (1a)(2e) laughed in @(g′′− ) = g′′−(1s)]
This treats the semantic value of the interrogative sentence in (10.10) as a set of
propositions T, where each such proposition is a set of assignments g′ that return
the same truth value for the proposition that a certain individual — the individual
assigned to 2e by the assignment g′ happens to assign to 1a — laughed.
First, note the world pronoun [w1 g2 ] supplying the external argument of the
complementizer. With complementizers such as Crel and ‘if’/Cif in subordinating
clauses there was a natural story about what would supply the external (individual,
world) argument: In restrictive relatives the quantifier’s restrictor argument tar-
gets a specified subset of individuals supplied by the relative phrase. In individual
correlatives the correlative clause targets topical individuals in the (actual) world.
In conditionals the ‘if’-clause targets a topical subdomain of the background modal
possibility relevant for the supposition supplied by the ‘whether’-like element. For
interrogatives a natural thought is that the argument determines the possibility
targeted by the question. In simple unembedded questions such as (10.10) the
external argument of C? supplies a world argument bound by Q;146 the question is
about what is the case in the actual world. In (10.10) the argument is semantically
146
Parallel to the case of correlative clauses discussed in §9.7, the world argument might be rep-
resented with a complex [whsf g2 pst -g], where the semantic value for [p g] is ultimately identified
with (e.g.) {g′−(1s)}. However, to clarify the intended interpretation I represent the world argument
with a simple world-pronoun.
284
trivial, given our general metasemantic assumption that, for any h ∈ G, h(1s)
represents the world of h (§§2, 6.1). We will see more substantive roles for the
argument in more complex examples.
The semantic value in (10.10) captures the local reading of the main predicate’s
world argument: the question nucleus places a constraint on the worlds of the
assignments g′ in each possible answer T. Which world represents the world of the
assignments may vary. The assignments in each answer are otherwise equivalent in
what values are assigned across indices, via the constraint g′ ≈ g′′ ; this constraint
will help capture local readings of context-sensitive expressions (below).
The derived semantic value in (10.10) obviously fails to represent the intended
global reading of ‘you’. The semantic value represents the question as targeting
what assignment to associate with the index 1a, rather than as targeting a property
of the particular individual gc (2e) ∈ E determined by the discourse assignment gc .
The assignments in each T may not even agree on the identity of the individual o ∈ E
that did/did not do the laughing.
One response would be to capture global readings by complicating the semantics
of Q. An alternative is to maintain the simpler lexical entry and semantic value for
interrogative clauses, and capture global readings in the metasemantics of answers.
Our metasemantics for declaratives from §2 treated a declarative sentence S as
true in a context c iff the derived semantic value JSK was true with respect to
the assignment gc representing the context. Correspondingly, I treat a proposition
T ∈ JS?K in the semantic value of an interrogative sentence S? as an answer to S?
in c iff every assignment g′ ∈ T assigns g−c to all assignment-indices.
(10.11) Metasemantics
a. A declarative sentence S is true in c iff JSK(gc ) = 1
b. Tt is an answer to an interrogative sentence S? in c iff (i) T ∈ JS?K , and
(ii) for all g′ ∈ T and assignment-indices ia, g′ (ia) = g−c .
285
contrast: In both cases a bridge principle is required to link a sentence’s com-
positional semantic value to an interpretation and function in discourse.147 The
semantics of T links a certain assignment-index, say 1a, to the assignments g in
the sentence’s semantic value JSK ; and the metasemantics of declaratives treats the
sentence as true in c iff the assignment representing the context, gc , is in that set of
assignments JSK . Analogously, the metasemantics of interrogatives treats a set of
assignments T as constituting an answer in c only if every assignment in T assigns the
assignment representing the context, gc , to that same index — the index that would
be targeted by T in a use of a declarative. In this sense, for declarative sentences
and interrogative sentences alike, global readings are ultimately captured in the
metasemantics.
Capturing global readings in interrogative sentences in the metasemantics has
the advantage of maintaining a uniform theoretical interpretation of assignment-
variables/quantification. If a concrete discourse determines that the assignment
index 1a represents the context, it does so regardless of whether a sentence be-
ing used is declarative or interrogative. Just as assignment-variables coindexed
with ‘wonder’ in (10.13) represent readings of expressions whose values are objects
of Alice’s wondering, assignment-variables coindexed with Q in (10.12) represent
readings whose values are being questioned.
10.3 wh questions
There is a divide in approaches to interrogative wh-words about whether they are re-
lated to relative pronouns, typically construed as λ-binders (Groenendijk & Stock-
hof 1982), or related to indefinites (Karttunen 1977). For instance, on the one
hand, in many languages the same forms can be used for interrogative pronouns
and indefinites (e.g., various Sino-Tibetan and Australian languages; Li 1992, Gair
et al. 1999, Lecarme 1999a, Kratzer & Shimoyama 2002, Mortensen 2003,
Bhat 2004, Thurgood & LaPolla 2017). On the other hand, it is crosslinguis-
147
Cf. e.g. Stalnaker 1978, 2014, Lewis 1980, Dummett 1973, Stanley 1997, MacFarlane
2014, Yalcin 2014.
286
tically common for interrogative words to be morphologically related to relative
words. Relative words generally also have a [wh] feature like interrogative wh
words (n. 110). In some languages the relative clauses in correlatives are even
introduced with interrogative wh words (e.g. Polish; Citko 2009); on the flip side,
in languages such as Sanskrit (Davison 2009a) and Somali (Lecarme 1999a), com-
plement questions are expressed by substituting the interrogative with a relative
construction, and, in the case of Sanskrit, using a correlative.
§§6–9 developed analyses of certain indefinites, relative pronouns, and several
types of anaphoric pronouns as choice-function pronouns. A natural move is to
extend the account to interrogatives and treat wh-words similarly as choice-function
pronouns (see Yatsushiro 2001, Cable 2010 for precedents).148 Indeed relative
forms that are morphologically related to demonstratives are also common (e.g.,
German, Dutch, Tuvaluan (Polynesian); Heine & Kuteva 2002, de Vries 2002,
Bhat 2004). Some languages even use the same pro-forms for each of these func-
tions, as in Lyele (Niger-Congo) (Showalter 1986; see Bhat 2004: esp. §8.3).
Giving the expressions a common semantic contribution, at some level of abstrac-
tion, reflects this (more on which shortly). In the case of [+wh] choice-function
pronouns, just as relative words are targeted by a determiner quantifier so that
the domain is determined from the set of NP-individuals, interrogative words are
targeted by the question operator so that the values for wh-phrases vary across
answers.
An example with a simple wh question is in (10.14). (For purposes of illustration
I show how the variation in values for the wh-phrase can be derived while keeping
the wh-word in situ below C; more on this below. Ignore any contextual restriction
associated with ‘what’, and assume E represents the domain of individuals. Here-
after when describing the answers to a question I often omit the presuppositional
constraint when trivial.)
148
Note that the account is neutral on Cable’s “Q-particle”-based syntax for wh movement and
pied piping. Cable’s Q-particle — also a variable over choice functions — is posited as an element in-
dependent of wh words and functional interrogative elements (complementizer, question operator).
287
(10.14) wh question
‘What hit you?’
S ∶ ⟨t, t⟩
Q⟨2,a⟩ CP ∶ t
w1 g2
⟨1,s⟩
C? t2a
wh1 -g2 E
t1s hit you2 -g1
Jwh1 g2 K = λPet .λgg . g(2a)(1cf)((↓ P)(g))
JCPK ≈ λgg ∶ @(g(2a)) = g(2a)(1s) . g(2a)(1cf)(E) hit g(1a)(2e) in @(g(2a))
A proposition Tt ∈ JSK is an answer to S in c iff
∃g′′g ∶ T = [λg′g ≈ g′′ . g′−(1cf)(E) hit g−c (2e) in @(g′− )
iff g′′−(1cf)(E) hit g−c (2e) in @(g′′− )]
The possible answers to the wh question are propositions T, where each such propo-
sition is a set of assignments g′ that return the same truth value for the proposition
that a selected individual g′ (1cf)(E) ∈ E hit gc (2e).
First, as in (10.10), the global reading of ‘you’ is captured via the metasemantic
condition on answerhood: A set of assignments T in the sentence’s semantic value
constitutes an answer only if g′ (1a) = gc . Given the constraint that g′ ≈ g′′ , the
assignments in each answer constitute an equivalence class with respect to a proposi-
tion about the contextually relevant individual g′ (1a)(2e) = g′′ (1a)(2e) = gc (2e) ∈ E.
Second, the “shifting” of wh-words in the interpretation of interrogatives is as-
similated to the general phenomenon of local readings of context-sensitive expres-
sions. The local reading of ‘what’ is captured in the coindexing between the question
operator and the choice-function pronoun [wh1 g2 ] representing the wh-phrase. I
assume that wh-words, having the feature [wh], must have the same assignment-
variable as the interrogative complementizer, e.g. due to agreement (cf. Chung
1998, Kratzer & Shimoyama 2002, Kratzer 2009, Cable 2010, Johnson 2012).
Relative and wh words thus receive obligatory local readings under the local assignment-
binder — e.g., a matrix determiner in a restrictive relative (§6), ιh in a conditional or
individual correlative (§9), or the question operator in an interrogative. Given the
constraint that g′ ≈ g′′ , the assignments g′ in each answer T assign the same value to
288
the choice-function index and hence select the same individual. Yet the particular
value assigned and individual selected may vary across answers: If E = {o1 , o2 }, the
possible answers are the propositions that o1 hit gc (2e), and that o2 hit gc (2e). The
wh-phrase is targeted by the question, and the possible answers are about different
individuals.
Third, although the assignments g′ in each answer assign the same choice func-
tion to the index 1cf and agree about whether the selected individual hit gc (2e), they
may differ regarding other worldly facts. The possible answers T aren’t singleton
sets.
Questions with multiple wh-phrases raise notorious syntactic/semantic challenges —
e.g., regarding movement and reconstruction, single-/pair-list readings and answers,
and exhaustiveness and uniqueness, such as the apparent implication of (10.15)
that each baby liked a unique toy (e.g. Rullmann 1995, Dayal 2006, 2016 and
references therein).
For present purposes I simply note two features of the assignment-variable account
in this section. It is common in diverse approaches to the semantics of questions
to require all wh-phrases to be interpreted in a specifier position of the interroga-
tive complementizer (e.g. Karttunen 1977, Pesetsky 2000, Cable 2010, George
2011).149 A critical issue in such accounts is what in general requires the movement
and how the order at LF of wh-phrases in multiple wh-interrogatives is derived,
given the crosslinguistic variation in pronunciation rules for wh-words (e.g., re-
quiring all wh-words to be fronted (Bulgarian), requiring all wh-words to be in
situ (Japanese), or allowing variation in movement (English)). Even for languages
such as English with overt wh movement, Rullmann & Beck (1998) have argued
that D-linked wh-phrases (‘which N’) are obligatorily interpreted in situ (also e.g.
Boeckx & Grohmann 2004). The account in this section is compatible with al-
ternative approaches to the syntax/phonology of wh-movement and reconstruction
in different languages. The account captures the local reading of wh-words and
the contribution of wh-words to the semantics of the question without requiring or
forbidding wh-movement to Spec,C at LF. Further, the semantics extends to multiple
wh questions without requiring innovations such as (e.g.) a type-flexible question
149
Contrast Chomsky 1995, Kratzer & Shimoyama 2002. The movement may be triggered for
semantic reasons (Kotek 2014), or syntactic reasons, e.g. that any XP headed by an item with [wh]-
features move to Spec,C.
289
operator or tuple types, which track the number of wh-words and their relative
positions (as in e.g. Higginbotham & May 1981, Groenendijk & Stockhof 1984,
George 2011).
A derivation for a multiple wh question such as (10.15) is as follows (I continue
to use abbreviations such as ‘babyu ’ for the characteristic function of the set of
individuals o ∈ E such that o is a baby in u (§§2, 6.1.3).)
Q⟨2,a⟩ CP ∶ t
w1 g2
⟨2,s⟩
C? t2a
t2s
wh2 -g2 baby-w1 -g1
liked
This says, roughly, that given sets of actual babies and toys — say, b1 , b2 , b3 ∈ babygc (1s)
and t1 , t2 , t3 ∈ toygc (1s) — the set of possible answers is the set of propositions that bi
liked tj . Given the metasemantic condition on answerhood, the world-pronouns in
the noun phrases ‘baby’ and ‘toy’ receive global readings anchored to gc (1s), which
is taken to represent the world @(gc ) of the discourse (§6.1.3). However, as in
(10.14), the world-argument of the main predicate ‘liked’ and the wh-words receive
(obligatory) local readings, targeted by the question. For each possible answer T,
the set of assignments g′ ∈ T constitute an equivalence class with respect to what
actual baby bi = g′ (2cf)(babygc (1s) ) ∈ E and what actual toy tj = g′ (1cf)(toygc (1s) ) ∈ E
are selected, and whether the selected baby bi liked the selected toy tj in the world
@(g′ ) of the possibility represented by g′ . The account derives how each answer in
the multiple wh question is about a particular pair of individuals.
The proposed syntax/semantics of wh interrogatives may afford an improved
290
treatment of examples with intuitively bound readings of pronouns such as (10.17).
The value for the wh-phrase ‘which baby’ varies across possible answers; and the
interpretations of the subject-internal pronoun ‘his’ and the object pronoun ‘him’
are linked to the value for the wh-phrase, though ‘him’ isn’t c-commanded by the
specifier position for the possessor in the genitive DP.
The challenge is to derive the intuitively bound readings of both pronouns from
operations on this (possibly intermediate) syntactic structure. One might posit that
for some syntactic or semantic reason there is subsequent covert movement of the
wh-phrase, and that — unlike the examples of DP-internal movement from §7.4 —
the wh-phrase raises above the entire DP, as in (10.20). (Assume a simplified
analysis of ‘his grandmother’ as ‘the-grandmother-of-him’.)
291
(10.20) a. [CP … [which baby [2 [[DP t2 [D ’s pic-of-the-GM-of-him2 ]] [1
[C C0 [IP t1 made him2 cry]]]]]]]
b. JCPKw ≈ λpst . ∃x∶ x is a baby in w ∧ the y such that y is a picture-of-the-
GM-of-x in w is such that p = [λw′ .y made x cry in w′ ]
Such an analysis derives how the wh-phrase binds both pronouns, but at the cost of
requiring an unlikely movement operation (cf. May 1985, Heim & Kratzer 1998)
and denying that ‘which baby’s picture of his grandmother’ forms a constituent. Al-
ternatively, one might treat the wh-phrase as raising (for some syntactic or semantic
reason) internal to the DP, and posit a mechanism of partial syntactic reconstruction
by which the non-wh portion of the DP is interpreted inside the IP at LF. By some
reconstruction operations to be specified, the wh-phrase and λ-binder generated
from the DP-internal movement remain in Spec of C; hence the wh-phrase existential
quantifier scopes over the interrogative complementizer, which identifies the form
of the answers, and binds the pronouns, roughly as in (10.21).
Details of how the requisite (partial) reconstruction is realized, and whether re-
construction is to be understood in syntactic terms at all, are controversial (cf. e.g.
Chomsky 1995, Heycock 1995, Sternefeld 1998, Fox 2000, Fox & Nissenbaum
2004, Sportiche 2006). Note that the fronted DP ‘which baby’s picture of his
grandmother’ still fails to receive a semantic value.
The assignment-variable-based syntax/semantics for wh interrogatives in this
section captures the intuitively bound reading of (10.17) without requiring particu-
lar commitments on issues regarding the movement of wh-phrases, pied-piping, or
reconstruction. (For present purposes I continue to assume the simplified represen-
tation of the possessive pronoun (see §7.2); and I ignore world-indexing with the
relation pronoun, again using ‘R’ for type ⟨e, et⟩ (see §8.9).)
292
(10.22) Which baby’s picture of his grandmother made him cry?
S
Q⟨2,a⟩ CP
w1 g2
⟨2,s⟩
C? t2a
DP⟨3,a⟩
⟨3,a⟩
ιo XP t2s scared he2 -g2 -baby-w1 -g1
R1 g1 ’s
wh2 -g2 baby-w1 -g1
Roughly put, each possible answer T is a set of assignments g′ that return the
same truth value for the proposition that [the o′ such that o′ bears the contextually
relevant relation gc (1R) to a selected baby o = g′ (2cf)(babygc (1s) ) ∈ E and o′ is
a picture of the grandmother of o (=g′ (2cf)(babygc (1s) ))] is such that o′ scared o
(=g′ (2cf)(babygc (1s) )) in @(g′ ). For each answer T, the set of assignments g′ ∈ T
293
constitute an equivalence class with respect to what actual baby oi = g′ (2cf)(babygc (1s) ) ∈ E
is selected, and whether oi ’s picture of oi ’s grandmother scared oi in the world @(g′ )
of the possibility represented by g′ .
The apparent anaphoric connections between the pronouns ‘his’/‘he’ and the
wh-phrase ‘which baby’ are captured derivatively via (i) the local reading of the wh-
phrase under the question operator, and (ii) the representation of the pronouns as
copies of the antecedent wh-phrase (see n. 140). The variation in values for the
wh-phrase across answers and the intuitive bound readings of the pronouns can be
captured while leaving the wh-phrase in situ and giving the complex subject DP a
particular semantic value. Controversial assumptions about pied piping and wh-
movement of the complex genitive DP, subsequent movement of the DP-internal
wh-phrase, and syntactic reconstruction aren’t required.
The previous examples have ignored differences between interrogative ‘which’
phrases and simplex interrogative pronouns such as ‘who’. Notable differences in
light of the discussion of “specificity” from §§7.1, 8 are differences in D-linking and
related phenomena, such as presuppositionality and syntactic/semantic indepen-
dence. Following Pesetsky 1987, 2000, ‘which N’ phrases are “D(iscourse)-linked”
in the sense that uses generally imply that the individuals in the possible answers
are from a contextually relevant domain. As Pesetsky remarks, the “semantics of
D-linked wh phrases closely tracks the semantics of the definite article the. Context
sets previously mentioned in the discourse qualify a phrase as D-linked, but so do
sets that are … salient” (Pesetsky 2000: 16; cf. Cinque 1990, Rullmann 1995,
Rullmann & Beck 1998). Using ‘which’ in (10.23) is anomalous unless a set of
musicians are relevantly salient (e.g. if Pat is a writer for a music publication, and
A and B have been talking about her recent efforts to scope out a new story).
294
is overtly realized by the wh element, the implicit definite-like element is base-
generated in its interpreted position, and the choice-function pronoun is bound by
the question operator, as in the alternative structures in (10.24). The D-linked wh
phrase can be represented as, say, a Top(ic) Phrase (Rizzi 2001, Grohmann 2003;
cf. (8.40), n. 139). A simplified LF and semantic value with the (a)-option is in
(10.25) (letting ι be a simple type-⟨et, e⟩ definite).150
295
as island (in)sensitivity and (absence of) Superiority effects (Dayal 2006). For
instance, in (10.26) the markedness resulting from crossing the wh island is dramat-
ically reduced with the D-linked wh phrase ‘which movie’. In (10.27)–(10.28), the
lower wh phrase can move over the higher wh phrase only when both are D-linked.
296
for future research (see also §8.8.2). (Hereafter, given our purposes, I will generally
assume the simpler [wh-g NP] syntax/semantics for complex wh phrases.)151
297
Third in some languages bound-variable pronouns and/or donkey pronouns can
be expressed as morphologically complex or with bare nominals (Srivastav 1991,
Mortensen 2003). Although German d-words take an elided complement, in other
languages pronominal elements can be used with an overt nominal (Déchaine &
Wiltschko 2002). Fourth, the proforms in correlatives are generally formed from
a demonstrative element; indeed the correlative binding requirement is typically
referred to as the “demonstrative requirement” (Dayal 1996, Bhatt 2003, Lipták
2009b). Interestingly, the A-movement of the demonstrative correlate in a language
often patterns with wh-movement (Izvorski 1996; cf. n. 139). Uniqueness and
exhaustivity implications associated with wh interrogatives are also observed with
correlatives (Dayal 1996, Izvorski 1996). Some languages even use the same pro-
nouns for each of these functions — as demonstratives, indefinites, interrogatives,
and relatives (Bhat 2004).
The proposed unified semantics gives semantic expression to such intra- and
inter-linguistic relations among the expressions. This isn’t to say that there are
no differences among them — not only morpho-phonologically, but also syntacti-
cally, semantically, distributionally (see nn. 51, 78). For instance, though I have
been ignoring internal projections for features such as φ-features, differences in
the internal structure and pronunciation rules for pronominal elements are to be
expected (Déchaine & Wiltschko 2002, 2017b, Kratzer 2009, Grosz & Patel-
Grosz 2016, Patel-Grosz & Grosz 2017). Ordinary simplex pronouns are in effect
a conventionalized system of demonstratives prioritizing the expression of certain
packages of φ-features152 — over (say) spatial features or the overt realization of a
nominal complement — for retrieving the relevant selectional domain. (Indeed in
some theories the class of pronouns is defined in terms of lacking an overt comple-
ment (cf. Baltin 2012, Patel-Grosz & Grosz 2017).) It isn’t uncommon, in various
language families, for the same format to be used for certain types of pronouns
152
And in some languages features such as tense, aspect, mood, as in (i)–(ii) (Demirdache 1996,
Bhat 2004, Nordlinger & Sadler 2004, Aikhenvald 2008, Adamou 2011; see §6.2):
(i) Isá-gíi baa hádal-kíi qaatáy, oo yiri:
he.emph.past decl talk-def.past take.past and said
‘He began to speak, and said:’ (Lecarme 2008: ex. 10a; Somali)
(ii) Ma taha na fyè e!
you.nondecl follow my.nondecl footprints in
‘Follow me (lit. in my tracks), please!’ (Carlson 1994: 522; Supyire (Niger-Congo))
As Lecarme (2008) puts it regarding Somali, “Since pronouns do not contain nouns that can be
predicated of a stage,” the nominal tense in examples such as (i) is used to “[locate the] individual
temporally, at a past time which overlaps (or coincides with) the time of the event.”
298
and demonstratives, such as in various Chinese dialects with third-person pronouns
and distal demonstratives (cf. Jespersen 1924, Postal 1969, Gair et al. 1999,
Bhat 2004, Luján 2004, Thurgood & LaPolla 2017). Conversely, recall our
examples with nominal tense in Somali from §6.2.1. Like individual pronouns,
Somali demonstratives are compatible with syntactic definiteness marking; in both
cases the co-occurrence has an intensifying effect, as we saw with the emphatic
pronouns in (6.27)–(6.28).
299
Characterizing a crosslinguistically applicable matching requirement (what is uni-
versal, and what is parameterized), and deriving the relevant locality effects in
particular languages has proven far from straightforward (Bhatt 2003, Davison
2009a, Leung 2009, Lipták 2012). Likewise for analyses of syntactic/semantic rela-
tions between indefinites and interrogatives, the internal and external syntax of dif-
ferent classes of pronouns, interactions among the syntax and the phonological and
morphological components in the realization of pronominal and anaphoric expres-
sions, etc. The aim in these sections has been simply to provide an account which
captures a common semantic core among the expressions in question, and thereby
reflects various relations among them crosslinguistically. For present purposes what
relevantly unifies e.g. certain indefinites, relative and wh words, d-words, and cer-
tain anaphoric expressions is that they are analyzed in terms of choice-function pro-
nouns. We have seen how integrating these common analyses in broader assignment-
variable-based syntax/semantics can compositionally derive a wide range of linguis-
tic shifting phenomena in various types of relativization, conditional, and interrog-
ative structures. I hope the proposed semantics may provide a fruitful basis for
delineating further dimensions of difference.
300
(10.33) a. *Ìyá rèi féràn enìkòòkani .
mother his like everyone
(intended: ‘everyonei is liked by hisi mother’)
b. Tai ni ìyá rèi féràn (ti )?
who be mother his like
‘Whoi does hisi mother like?’
(Adésolá 2005: 55, 11; Yorùbá (Niger-Congo))
(10.34) ?Which babyi did only itsi mother say (ti ) was cute?
How to diagnose such examples is controversial (see Safir 2017 for an overview).
Yet given such intralinguistic and crosslinguistic variations, it isn’t implausible that
wh weak crossover effects shouldn’t follow simply from general binding principles,
such as (7.74) in §7.4, but from properties of wh chains within the language. I won’t
pretend to provide a general account of wh weak crossover here; as emphasized
above, the proposed semantics for wh interrogatives is compatible with different
views on the syntactic/semantic status of wh movement. But now that the treat-
ment of wh words is on the table, it may be worth briefly speculating on binding
configurations with pronouns.
To a rough (inadequate) first approximation, consider the constraint in (10.35)
on relations among copies of wh-phrases.153
(10.35) Let αi be an expression with feature [wh] such that there is no coindexed
γi higher than αi ; and let C = (a1i , . . . , ani ) be the sequence of (lower)
j
copies coindexed with αi . Then for every ai ∈ C, there is some aki ∈ C and
j
[+wh]-β such that (β, ai ) is a chain and β ’s [wh]-feature percolates from
aki .
Copies of movement are typically required to be identical to the moved item; in theo-
ries relaxing this requirement the lower copies must at least have the same φ-features
(person, number, gender), agreement features, etc. (cf. Nunes 2004, van Koppen
2007; n. 13). Non-movement copies, in contrast, need only be equivalent with
respect to elements relevant to satisfying requirements for coindexing; that is, they
153
The superscripts in (10.35) are included simply to delineate the copies; they have no theoretical
import. I continue to use ‘copy’ broadly both for traces (n. 13) as well as for copies not derived via
movement (§6.2). Likewise for ‘chain’: the chains needn’t be movement chains (though one may
assume other familiar conditions such as uniformity and c-command); the principle is compatible
with treating chain relations as represented in the narrow syntax or the interfaces. The principle is
formulated to apply at a level at which wh movement has taken place, though it could be reformulated
in other terms.
301
must have the same φ-features (e.g. Kratzer 2009). The principle in (10.35) thus
permits examples such as (10.31a): the copies of whoi = [[wh] wh-g person-w-g]i
are the trace ti and bi = [she-g person-w-g]i in the representation of the possessive
pronoun; ti = [[wh] wh-g person-w-g]i is [+wh]; and (ti ) and (ti , bi ) are chains
(the former trivially so). Examples such as (10.31b), however, are excluded: there
is no [+wh]-β , whose [wh]-feature arises from some aik ∈ C, such that (β, bi ) is a
chain; the pronoun bi lacks a [wh]-feature (n. 140), and the [+wh] trace ti doesn’t
c-command bi . The treatment of “secondary weak crossover” effects, as in (10.32),
proceeds likewise. Unlike (10.32a), (10.32b) is excluded since the only potential
[+wh]-β is tk = [[wh] Which boyi ’s mother]k , and tk c-commands neither copy in the
representations of the possessive pronouns.
Note that the principle in (10.35) carries over to weak crossover effects in (En-
glish) relative clauses — even on the analysis in §6 in which the relative phrase
originates in Spec,Crel , as reflected schematically in (10.36)–(10.37) (cf. §8.7).154
In (10.36)–(10.37) the IP in the relative clause includes two copies of the [+wh]-
C0rel — the [+wh] trace ti , and the coindexed variable oi in the representation of the
pronoun ‘its’. (Representing the pronoun with a copy of the relative phrase would
violate Principle B.) The configuration in (10.36) is permitted since (ti ) and (ti , oi )
are both chains. (10.37) is excluded since the higher copy oi lacks a [wh] feature;
hence there is no available [+wh]-β such that (β, oi ) is a chain.
The general binding principle in (7.74) (§7.4) essentially functions to constrain
movement for purposes of repairing a type-mismatch from introducing new kinds
of binding relations; the interpretive effects arising from QR’ing an expression α are
154
Though relative pronouns are often morphologically related to interrogative pronouns, forms
morphologically related to demonstratives are also common (e.g., in German). Crosslinguistically,
the presence of [wh]/[op]-features with relative pronouns is independent of a wh format, and it is
independent of whether the nominal head is pronounced in situ; see n. 110. For languages with
relative constructions that lack [wh]/[op]-features, the principle in (10.35) wouldn’t apply; weak
crossover effects thus needn’t be predicted (cf. Itô 1986 on the absence of weak crossover effects in
Japanese circumnominals).
302
restricted to those associated with α’s semantic role in its base position. Whereas
QR is a semantically driven mechanism applying for reasons of interpretability, wh
movement and associated reconstruction effects depend on principles and represen-
tations at various grammatical levels. Hence it might not be surprising to find greater
crosslinguistic variation with respect to weak crossover with wh-interrogatives, as
we in fact do. Crosslinguistic variations in weak crossover with wh-interrogatives
might be diagnosed in terms of differences in the status and precise formalization of
a principle such as (10.35) along with independent grammatical differences regard-
ing wh movement — e.g., differences with respect to parameters such as the relevant
command relations in (10.35), at what syntactic level the principle is checked, the
syntactic/semantic status of wh movement, reconstruction, pied-piping etc. I leave
further developments and investigation of relations among different types of weak
crossover configurations for future research.
Q⟨2,a⟩ CP
w1 g2
⟨1,s⟩
C? t2a ⟨3,a⟩
⟨2,s⟩
might
t1s
r1 g2 Cd t3a he3 -g1 t2s -be-the-killer
JSK ≈ λTt .λgg . ∃g′′g ∶ T = [λg′g ≈ g′′ . ∃aa ∶ g′−(1r)(@(g′− ))(a(g′ )) ∧
303
g′ (1a)(3e) is the killer in @(a(g′ ))
iff ∃aa ∶ g′′−(1r)(@(g′′− ))(a(g′′ )) ∧ g′′ (1a)(3e) is the killer in @(a(g′′ ))]
A proposition Tt ∈ JSK is an answer to S in c iff
∃g′′g ∶ T = [λg′g ≈ g′′ . ∃aa ∶ g′−(1r)(@(g′− ))(a(g′ )) ∧ g−c (3e) is the killer in @(a(g′ ))
iff ∃aa ∶ g′′−(1r)(@(g′′− ))(a(g′′ )) ∧ g−c (3e) is the killer in @(a(g′′ ))]
Each possible answer T is a set of assignments g′ that determine the same modal
background R (=g′ (1r), via g′ ≈ g′′ ), and return the same truth value for the
proposition that the contextually relevant individual gc (3e) (=g′ (1a)(3e)) is the
killer in the world of some epistemic possibility R(@(g′ )), as determined by g′ .
Roughly, answers to the epistemic modal question are propositions of the form that
there is/is not an epistemic possibility (=g′ (1r)(@(g′ ))) where gc (3e) is the killer.
Local readings under assignment-quantifiers are represented uniformly in terms
of coindexing between assignment-variables and binder indices (§10.2). The com-
positional semantics of the interrogative elements C? and Q derive the obligatory
local reading of the modal’s world argument t1s . The question nucleus places a
constraint on the worlds of the assignments g′ in each possible answer, i.e. that
gc (3e) is the killer in some world accessible from @(g′ ). Likewise the obligatory
local reading of the embedded predicate’s world argument t2s is captured via the
coindexing between the embedding (declarative) complementizer and the modal’s
binder index. The local reading of the epistemic modal is captured by allowing
the value for the modal-background pronoun [r1 g2 ] to vary across the propositions
comprising the possible answers. The assignments in each answer assign the same
value to 1r; however, the particular epistemic modal background assigned may differ
across answers. The relevant evidence is targeted by the question.
In §4.3 we discussed how there may be reasons for positing conventionalized
locality/globality principles for certain context-sensitive expressions — e.g., a glob-
ality principle for gendered pronouns, or a locality principle for certain types of
epistemic uses of modals. We noted that a locality principle requiring certain modal-
background pronouns to be coindexed with the closest c-commanding assignment-
binder may help capture the linking of epistemic modals to the subject in attitude
ascriptions. Such a principle would apply to epistemic modals in questions as well:
An epistemic modal question such as (10.38) would typically be interpreted as being
about what the evidence is — represented by what modal background in D⟨s,at⟩ to
assign to the index 1r — rather than about what the logical implications are of a
contextually agreed-upon body of evidence gc (1r) at the evaluation world (contrast
304
(10.4)). For present purposes I leave open whether conventionalizing such an
interpretation is appropriate in the general case (cf. Silk 2016a, 2017).
Capturing this idea has proven a persistent challenge for traditional approaches to
questions and quantificational analyses of conditionals (see Isaacs & Rawlins 2008,
Groenendijk & Roelofsen 2009, 2010, Starr 2010; cf. Charlow 2010, 2011 on
challenges with conditional imperatives). An additional challenge is to capture the
various types of local and global readings in both the ‘if’-clause and interrogative
main clause. Consider the following conditional-question analogues of the shifted-
indexical example from Santorio 2012 in §9:
(10.40) [See (9.6). After the experiment, one of the amnesiacs wakes up. Feeling
fuzzy about the experimental protocol, he asks himself:]
If it landed heads, might I be in Widener?
(10.41) [The awoken amnesiac also can’t remember if funds were going to be left
in one of the libraries, or what the standards for richness are wherever he
is.]
(Qk ) [If iti landed heads]j am Ij in Widener and richk ? (cf. Santorio
2012)
In (10.41), for instance, we need to capture (among other things) (i) the global
reading of ‘it’ in the ‘if’-clause; (ii) the local reading of ‘I’ in the consequent, inter-
preted with respect to the assignment representing the conditional supposition; and
(iii) the local reading of the world argument and standard of richness associated
with ‘rich’ in the consequent, targeted by the question operator and varying across
possible answers. The conditional question in (10.41) is in part a question about
how rich one must be to count as rich, on the supposition that the coin landed heads.
In light of crosslinguistic links among conditionals, correlatives, and interrog-
atives, §10.2 suggested as a working hypothesis that we treat the interrogative
complementizer C? as having an analogous argument structure and semantics as
‘if’/Cif . As a way of developing the approach I suggested interpreting the external
305
argument of C? as determining a relevant possibility targeted by the question. In
unembedded questions the argument has been a world argument coindexed with
Q (n. 146); the questions are about what is the case in the actual world. We will
see that this argument, though semantically trivial in the examples thus far, can
play a non-trivial role in the interpretation of complex sentences such as conditional
questions.
306
(10.44) Relevance conditional question
S ∶ ⟨t, t⟩
Q⟨3,a⟩ CP ∶ t
⟨2,a⟩
ιh w 1 - g3
⟨1,s⟩
⟨2,s⟩
wh2sf -g2 p1st -g1 C? t3a t1s there are biscuits
if t2a Alice t2s is hungry
Roughly put, each possible answer T is a set of assignments g′ that return the same
truth value for the proposition that the contextually relevant possibility where Alice
is hungry is such that there are biscuits in @(g′ ).
First, the ‘if’-clause introduces the maximal relevant possibility h where Alice is
hungry. The global reading of the pronoun [p1st g1 ] which supplies the contextually
relevant background domain is captured in the metasemantic answerhood condi-
tion: for each answer T, every g′ ∈ T is such that g′ (1a)(1st) = gc (1st). Second, just
as external argument of ‘if’ determines the possibility targeted by the supposition,
the external argument of C? determines the possibility targeted by the question.
In relevance conditional questions this possibility is the actual world: Intuitively,
(10.43) isn’t about whether there are biscuits in some modal subdomain where Alice
is hungry; it’s about whether there are actually any biscuits. The external argument
307
of C? is again supplied by a world-pronoun coindexed with the question operator.
The assignments g′ in each answer T constitute an equivalence class with respect to
whether there are biscuits in the world @(g′ ) of the possibility represented by g′ .
A remark on interpreting the metalanguage quantification over assignments is
in order. The argument of a in the denotation of the ‘if’-clause varies across the
assignments g′ , g′′ in the set of possible answers; however, as discussed in §§2.2, 9.2,
the items in terms of which the uniqueness condition is stated are images of the
assignments under a, i.e. items h ∈ G in the model. The metalanguage expression
“ιa(g)∶ . . . ” abbreviates the quantificational condition that for some function a ∈ Da ,
its value constitutes the unique maximal plurality h ∈ G such that… (§9.2). Varying
the argument of a has no effect on which h ∈ G constitutes the unique such maximal
plurality in the model.
308
‘Which girl is standing, is she tall?’ (cf. Srivastav 1991: ex. 3a; Hindi)
S∶t
Q⟨3,a⟩ CP ∶ t
⟨2,a⟩
ιh
w1 g3
w1 g1 ⟨1,s⟩
⟨2,s⟩
C? t3a
t1s
Cif t2a she2 -g2 girl-w1 -g1 tall
t2s standing d1 g3
wh2 -g2 girl-w1 -g1
Like with the relative conditional question in (10.44), the modal domain for the
main clause interrogative is targeted directly by the question operator. But whereas
the ‘if’-clause in (10.44) introduces a topical modal possibility, the correlative clause
introduces an actual possibility about a topical individual. As in (9.49), the world
of the possibility introduced in the correlative clause is identified with the world of
the discourse, gc (1s). Though the correlative clause in (10.45) doesn’t shift a modal
domain, it shifts the interpretation of the correlative proform. The correlative clause
introduces a topical girl (=a(g)(2cf)(girlgc (1s) )) who is actually standing, and the
interrogative main clause comments on that same girl, asking whether she is tall.
Each possible answer T is, roughly, a set of assignments g′ which determine the
309
same standard s for counting as tall (=g′ (1d)), and return the same truth value for
the proposition that the selected girl (=a(g)(2cf)(girlgc (1s) )) who is standing in the
actual world @(gc ) is s-tall in @(g′ ).
So, our analyses of correlatives, proforms, and interrogatives compositionally
derive the relevant inventory of readings: (i) the global reading of ‘girl’ in the
correlative clause, (ii) the local reading of the proform in the main clause bound
by the correlative clause, and (iii) the local reading of ‘tall’ in the main clause,
targeted by the question. The global reading of ‘girl’ and correlative clause domain
is captured via the metasemantic condition on answerwood. The local reading of the
correlate follows from the representation of the proform as a copy of its antecedent
relative expression, here [she2 -g2 girl-w1 g1 ], and the correlative clause assignment-
⟨2,a⟩
binder from ιh . The proform in the interrogative clause correctly receives a local
reading under the correlative clause without being targeted by the question. On
the flip side, the world-argument and standard-pronoun [d1 g3 ] associated with
‘tall’ receive local readings under the question operator without being shifted by
the correlative clause. (10.45) is in part a question about how tall one must be
to count as tall. The assignments g′ in each answer determine the same standard
of tallness g′ (1d) (via g′ ≈ g′′ ), though which standard is determined varies across
possible answers. So, the correlative interrogative is correctly derived as a question
about whether a certain girl who is actually standing is tall.
155
As with ‘tall’ in (10.45), assume a simplified context-sensitive semantics for ‘rich’, where ‘o is
d-rich’ abbreviates that o’s degree of wealth is at least as great as the degree-standard d for counting
as rich. As in §9, I leave open whether the coindexing between the ‘if’-clause and adjacent assignment
variable may be established via movement.
310
(10.46) Hypothetical conditional question
‘If it landed heads, am I rich?’
S ∶ ⟨t, t⟩
Q⟨3,a⟩ CP ∶ t
⟨2,a⟩
ιh
w1 g2 ⟨1,s⟩
⟨2,s⟩ I1 g2
wh2sf -g2 p1st -g1 C? t3a t1s
rich
if t2a it2 -g1 t2s heads d1 g3
Roughly, each possible answer T is a set of assignments g′ which (i) determine the
same standard s for counting as rich (=g′ (1d)), and (ii) return the same truth value
for the proposition that the relevant possibility h where the coin gc (2e) landed heads,
@(h) = h(2sf)(gc (1st)), is such that the shifted individual h(1e) is s-rich, provided
(iii) that the world of g′ is identical to the world of h.
The account derives the range of local/global readings for conditional questions
discussed above and in §10.1 — notably, global readings (e.g. ‘it’), local readings
under the conditional supposition (e.g. ‘I’), and local readings in the interrogative
consequent targeted by the question (e.g. ‘rich’). The standard associated with ‘rich’
correctly receives a local reading under the question operator. (10.46) is in part a
311
question about what standard of richness to accept; the question is about the nature
of a topical possibility, not simply about the world narrowly construed. The assign-
ments in each answer agree in what standard of richness g′ (1d) they determine
(via g′ ≈ g′′ ), though which standard is determined varies across the possible an-
swers. By contrast, the interpretations of the pronouns ‘it’ and ‘I’ are constant across
answers. Just as in each possible answer the topical modal possibility h is about
the same contextually relevant object gc (2e), likewise each possible answer is a
proposition about the individual h(1e) representing (say) the epistemic counterpart
of the speaker in that possibility (§3.4). ‘I’ in the interrogative consequent receives a
local reading under the conditional supposition without necessarily receiving a local
reading targeted by the question. The global readings of ‘it’ and specifier argument
of ‘if’ are again captured via the metasemantic condition on answerhood, anchoring
their interpretation to the discourse context. I am not aware of other accounts of
conditionals, questions, or conditional questions which similarly derive the observed
range of local and global readings.
The semantics captures the intuition that the possible answers in a hypotheti-
cal conditional question are specifically about the possibility described by the an-
tecedent. There are two critical moving parts: the presupposition associated with
the interrogative complementizer, and the correlative binding requirement.
First, drawing on on crosslinguistic links between interrogative and conditional
clauses, §10.2 pursued a unified semantics for the complementizer C? in inter-
rogatives and ‘if’/Cif in relativization of possibilities. The relevant contrast in the
entry for C? in (10.7) is that the condition on the external (world, individual)
argument is a presupposition. Intuitively, a no-answer to a conditional question
such as (10.39) shouldn’t end up including possibilities where school is canceled
(and perhaps even where it snows) but fail to verify the interrogative due to being
outside the contextually relevant set of snow-possibilities. The possibilities in each
answer should count as relevantly equivalent due to being equivalent with respect
to whether school is canceled. Implementing the condition as a presupposition
captures this. The assignments in each possible answer T in (10.46) are restricted to
assignments representing the topical modal possibility described by the ‘if’-clause —
assignments g′ such that @(g′− ) = h(1s) = @(h).
By contrast, there isn’t an analogous no-answer relevant in the semantics of
relative clauses or ‘if’-clauses. For purposes of deriving the embedding operator’s
restrictor argument, what matters is simply the items that do satisfy both of the
conditions in question — e.g., in ‘if it snows’, the snow-possibilities which are part of
the relevant domain. That said, it would be interesting to compare presuppositional
312
variants of the lexical entries for Crel /‘if’ in (6.20)/(9.16), analogous to the entry for
C? in (10.7), as in e.g. (10.47).
(10.47) JifK = JCif K = JC? K = λaa .λpst .λw′s .λgg ∶ @(a(g)) = w′ (g) .
∀ws = λg′g .@(a(g′ )), p(w)(g)
(10.48) Alice thinks [ CP1 that [ CP2 [if it snows] [ CP3 (then) school will close]]]
313
tended question meaning. The predicted correlate is instead the adjacent world
argument in Spec,C — an adjacent world-pronoun, as in (10.46), or a topicalized
proform such as ‘then’, as in (10.49) (n. 146).
Q⟨3,a⟩ CP ∶ t
⟨2,a⟩
ιh XP⟨3,s⟩ ∶ ⟨t, t⟩
t3s
⟨2,s⟩ ⟨1,s⟩
wh2sf -g2 p1st -g1 then2sf -g2 p1st -g1
if t2a it2 -g1 t2s heads C? t3a I1 -g2 t1s rich d1 -g3
A proposition Tt ∈ JSK is an answer to S in c iff ∃g′′g ∶ T = [λg′g ≈ g′′ .
[ιa(g′ )∶ g−c (2e) landed heads in @(a(g′ )) ∧ @(a(g′ )) = a(g′ )(2sf)(g−c (1st))]
a(g′ )(1e) is g′−(1d)-rich in @(g′− ), provided @(g′− ) = a(g′ )(2sf)(g−c (1st)) iff
[ιa(g′′ )∶ g−c (2e) landed heads in @(a(g′′ )) ∧ @(a(g′′ )) = a(g′′ )(2sf)(g−c (1st))]
a(g′′ )(1e) is g′′−(1d)-rich in @(g′′− ), provided @(g′′ ) = a(g′′ )(2sf)(g−c (1st))]
Just like in our examples with unembedded interrogatives, the question operator
raises from the assignment argument position of the embedded interrogative com-
plementizer. No mechanism of CP-recursion is predicted. This is a critical feature of
the account, since CP-recursion has been argued to be degraded or impossible under
interrogative complementizers (e.g. Iatridou & Kroch 1993). Unlike (9.30), the
examples in (10.50)–(10.51) are unacceptable with ‘then’.
(10.50) Every boy wonders if his mother comes (∗ then) what he will eat.
(Iatridou & Kroch 1993: exs. 54a–55a)
(10.51) Every boy wonders whether if his toy breaks (∗ then) he will get a new one.
314
The A-movement from topicalizing the proform, as in (10.49), degrades the fur-
ther wh movement in (10.50)–(10.51) (cf. §9.5). The contrast between embed-
ded ‘then’ conditionals with main clause declaratives vs. interrogatives falls out of
our general account of conditional proforms and syntax/semantics for interrogative
(conditional, relative) clauses.156
315
– In individual-correlative interpretations with Cif the correlative clause
targets a possibility describing topical individuals in the actual world.
This topical possibility is commented on by the adjoined main clause.
– In interrogatives the interrogative clause targets the possibility to be
targeted by the question.
157
If only.
316
11 Taking stock
This manuscript has initiated a project of developing a linguistic theory which posits
variables for assignment functions in the syntax, and treats semantic values sys-
tematically in terms of sets of assignments in the model. Principal features of the
account are that it standardizes quantification across domains, and it systematizes
various seemingly diverse linguistic shifting phenomena. Such phenomena include
data with quantifiers and scope, intensionality, and local/global readings in vari-
ous embedded environments, such as with modals, attitude verbs, questions, and
conditionals. The semantics affords a unified analysis of the context-sensitivity of
pronouns, epistemic modals, etc., in the spirit of contextualist theories. Yet it im-
proves in compositionally deriving certain distinctive shifting/binding phenomena
(e.g. with epistemic modals), and in providing a framework for theorizing about
expressions’ different tendencies for local/global readings. Resources for capturing
these phenomena have grown increasingly complex in current theories.
The syntax and lexical/compositional semantics delineate the sources of inten-
sionality and assignment-shifting in the clausal architecture. Binding with indi-
viduals/worlds/assignments is derived uniformly from a generalized binder-index,
which attaches directly to expressions. The account avoids introducing added pa-
rameters of interpretation, quantification-specific composition rules, or interpre-
tive principles (such as for reconstructed phrases, pronouns vs. traces, donkey pro-
nouns). The semantics is fully compositional.
Along the way I appealed to independently motivated resources from the syntax
and semantics literatures in motivating analyses of particular constructions. Cer-
tain features of the account are of general interest, independent of the particu-
lar assignment-variable-based implementation. These include the formalization of
assignment modification; the definition of the generalized binder-index; the ap-
proach to the syntax/semantics interface with determiner quantifiers, modal quan-
tifiers, and various types of complementizers; the treatments of locality/globality
constraints (e.g., with pronouns, epistemic modals); applications to classic puzzles
with names in attitude ascriptions, including apparent non-specific, de dicto, and
bound uses; a unified analysis of certain indefinites, wh-words, relative words, and
anaphoric demonstrative proforms; a general layered n analysis for noun phrases,
with applications to distinctions among weak and strong quantifier words regarding
presuppositionality, specificity, modal independence, and existential ‘there’ sen-
tences (with and without a coda); a unified treatment of various types of relative
and non-relative restrictive modification, with applications to “free R” (modifier)
and “inherent R” (argument) readings of English possessive constructions; a dis-
317
tinction between trace- and pronoun-binding, with applications to weak crossover;
a speculative general treatment of apparent binding out of DPs and weak crossover
effects with donkey pronouns, inverse linking, and genitive binding; compositional
semantics for alternative head-raising and matching analyses of relative clauses,
with extensions to head-internal relative constructions and intensional readings of
relative phrases; uniform compositional semantics for ‘if’-clauses when adjoined to
NP, VP, IP, and CP, and for individual correlative clauses adjoined to the main clause
or directly to the correlate DP; unified analyses of ‘if’-clauses and individual correl-
ative clauses, and of conditional and individual proforms; a unified approach to
relative, conditional, and interrogative complementizers; and a fully compositional
semantics for quantifier raising, wh interrogatives, and relativization.
Our initial focus was on applying the assignment-variable-based framework to
local/global readings with quantifiers, attitude verbs, and modal verbs; however,
we have seen that the potential applications of the account extend more broadly.
Diverse types of shifting phenomena were examined across a range of linguistic
environments, such as relativization structures, conditionals, and interrogatives.
Although I emphasized certain formal similarities among context-sensitive expres-
sions, there are of course differences among them. Issues regarding further (gram-
matical, lexical, metasemantic, conversational) constraints on readings, to help rein
in the flexibility of the system, call for more thorough investigation. The specu-
lative discussions of different types of pronoun binding (bound-variable pronouns,
resumptive pronouns, reflexives), events and the semantics of different verbalizing
heads, and comparisons among conditionals, individual correlatives, and interrog-
atives raise difficult questions about binding principles, traces vs. pronouns, (non-
)linguistic anaphora, interactions with tense/aspect, and wh movement and topical-
ization, among many others. Applications to other types of conventional meanings,
such as conventional implicature, presupposition, and expressives; categories such
as tense, aspect, voice, mood; and expressions and constructions such as resump-
tive pronouns, control constructions, imperatives, counterfactuals, nominalizations,
modal adjectives/adverbs, and ellipsis, may provide further avenues to explore. It
would be interesting to examine possible extensions of the proposed movement-
and agreement-based accounts of different types of local/global readings to issues
such as actuality entailments (Bhatt 2006, Hacquard 2006, 2009), or temporally
(in)dependent readings and nominal/verbal tense (Musan 1995, Lecarme 1999b,
2008). I hope the preliminary developments here may illustrate the fruitfulness
of an assignment-variable-based approach to investigating these and additional lin-
guistic phenomena.
318
Appendix Formal overview: Syntax, Semantics, Metasemantics
A Sample lexical entries
(8.9) JlikesK = λxe .λws .λye .λgg . y(g) likes x(g) in w(g) (cf. (8.116))
(2.4) Jviσ K = λaa .λγσnn . . . λγσ1 1 .λgg . a(g)(iσ)((↓ γ n )(g)) . . . ((↓ γ 1 )(g))
a. For α ∈ {e, s, t}, Jviα K = λaa .λgg . a(g)(iα) b. Jgi K = λgg . g(ia)
(2.5) Jtiσ K = λγσnn . . . λγσ1 1 .λgg . g(iσ)((↓ γ n )(g)) . . . ((↓ γ 1 )(g))
a. For β ∈ {e, s, t, a}, Jtiβ K = λgg . g(iβ) (cf. n. 13)
(3.11) Generalized binder-index
J⟨i,τ ⟩ K = λα⟨⟨τ,⟨1 σ1 ⋯σn , t⟩1 ⋯⟩n ⟩,σ⟩ . λβ⟨1 σ1 ⋯σn , t⟩1 ⋯⟩n .
α(λχ.λγ 1 ⋯λγ n .λg . β(γ 1 )⋯(γ n )(g[(↓ χ)(g)/iτ ]))
(3.6) JthatK = JCd K = λaa .λp⟨s,t⟩ .λgg . ∀ws = λg′g .@(a(g′ )), p(w)(g)
(9.16) JifK = JCif K = λaa .λpst .λw′s .λgg . @(a(g)) = w′ (g) ∧ ∀ws = λg′g .@(a(g′ ))∶ p(w)(g)
(10.7) JC? K = λaa .λpst .λw′s .λgg ∶ @(a(g)) = w′ (g) . ∀ws = λg′g .@(a(g′ ))∶ p(w)(g)
(6.20) JCrel K = λaa .λPet .λye .λxe .λgg . x(g) = y(g) ∧ P(x)(g) (head-raising)
(8.84) JCrel K = λaa .λpst .λxe .λgg . ∀ws = λg′g .@(a(g′ ))∶ p(w)(g) (matching)
(alternatives in (7.11a), §10.5.3)
(8.9) JthinkK = λA⟨a,t⟩ .λws .λxe .λgg . ∀aa ∶ (a(g) is compatible with x(g)’s state of
mind in w(g)) → A(a)(g)
(3.9) JmayK = λA′⟨a,t⟩ .λA⟨a,t⟩ .λgg . ∃aa ∶ A′ (a)(g) ∧ A(a)(g)
(3.8) JTK = λA⟨a,t⟩ .λgg . ∀aa = λgg .g− ∶ A(a)(g)
(10.8) JQK = λAat .λTt .λgg . ∀aa = λgg .g− ∶ ∃g′′g ∶ T = [λg′ ∶ g′ ≈ g′′ . A(a)(g′ ) = A(a)(g′′ )]
319
(8.10) J[sg]K = λP⟨s,et⟩ .λws .λye .λgg ∶ atom(y(g)) . P(w)(y)(g)
J[pl]K = λP⟨s,et⟩ .λws .λye .λgg ∶ count(y(g)) . P(w)(y)(g)
(7.10)/(7.41) JXK = J’sK = λxe .λPet .λye .λgg . y(g) = x(g) ∧ P(y)(g)
(cf. n. 65, (7.11b))
(8.119), (8.120), (8.122), n. 128
Jv∗agt K = λPet .λP′et .λxve .λgg . P(xv )(g) ∧ P′ (xv )(g)
Jvappl K = λPet .λP′et .λxεe .λgg . P(xε)(g) ∧ P′ (xε)(g)
Jvbe K = λPet .λxse .λgg . P(xs )(g)
Jvdo K = λws .λP⟨s,et⟩ .λxεe .λgg . P(w)(xε)(g)
Jvgoal K = λws .λP⟨s,et⟩ .λP′⟨s,et⟩ .λxεe .λgg . P(w)(xε)(g) ∧ ∀w′s ∶ w′ (g) ∈ goal(xε(g)) → ∃ye ∶ P′ (w′ )(y)(g)
Choice-function pronouns (§§4.4, 6, 7.1, 7.3, 8.2, 8.7, 8.8, 9.2, 9.7, 10.3)
a. JFi,cf K = λaa .λPτ t .λgg . a(g)(icf)((↓ P)(g))
∗
b. JFi,cf∗K = λaa .λP⟨s,et⟩ .λws .λgg . a(g)(icf )(↓ P)(w(g))
B Metasemantics / Metalanguage
(2.1) Models M: (2.2) Domains / Semantic types:
– E: set of entities – De = EDg
– T: set of truth-values, {0, 1} – Dt = {0, 1}Dg
– W: set of worlds – Ds = WDg
– G: set of assignmentsM – Da = GDg
– Dg =domain of assignmentsD
– Dαβ = DDβ α
Constraints on readings / Interpretation of assignments: §§1, 2.1, 3.1, 3.3, 3.4, 4.1,
4.3.3, 5, 7.4, 8.5, 8.7, 9.7
Metasemantics: §§2.2, 3.3, 4.1, 6.1.3, 8.7.2, 9.2, 10.2, 10.5
320
C Syntax
Sample trees:
(3.3)
X⟨i,a⟩ CP/C′
⟨j,s⟩ ⋮
C0 tia V tjs
(10.6) S
Q⟨i,a⟩
⟨j,s⟩ IP
C? tia …tjs …
(9.12) CP
⟨i,a⟩
ιh C
⟨j,s⟩ IP
321
(8.11)/(8.40)/(8.87)
QP
Q⟨i,a⟩ (TopP)
(Top) n∗P
n∗ (FP)
(F) nP
(Fcf g)
n (FP)
(F) NumP
(Fcf∗ g) Num N
δ#
(4.1) S
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩ IP
Cd t1a
VP
he1 g1
⟨2,a⟩ CP
thinks t1s
⟨2,s⟩ IP
that t2a
it2 g1 t2s cried
(4.21) ‘Freddoi met Freddok .’
[ S T⟨1,a⟩ [ CP [Cd t1a ]⟨1,s⟩ [[ DP F1cf g1 [ NP Freddo w1 g1 ]]
[ VP met t1s [ DP F2cf g1 [ NP Freddo w1 g1 ]]]]]]
322
(6.25) S
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩ IP
Cd t1a
DP⟨2,a⟩ VP
every⟨2,a⟩ CPrel
liked t1s
it3 g2
toy-w1 -g1
C
wh2 g2
baby-w1 -g1 ⟨2,e⟩
got-w1 -g1
a3 g2
toy-w1 -g1
323
(8.84) D+XP matching relative clause (alternative)
S
T⟨1,a⟩
⟨1,s⟩
Cd t1a
vP
CPrel
X FP
⟨2,s⟩
nP
F2cf t2a
Crel g1 FP vP
w1 -g1 cat
t2s meowed
nP
wh2cf t2a
w1 -g1 cat
(7.80) ‘every boy’s cat’
DP{...⟨2,a⟩... } ∶ ⟨et, t⟩
every⟨2,a⟩ XP ιo⟨3,a⟩ XP
324
(7.83) ‘some child of every parent’
DP {...⟨2,a⟩... } ∶ ⟨et, t⟩
∗∗{⟨2,e⟩,⟨2,a⟩}
DP ∶ ⟨t, t⟩ DP∗⟨3,a⟩ ∶ ⟨et, t⟩
every⟨2,a⟩ XP some⟨3,a⟩ XP
⋮
(8.69) S
T⟨1,a⟩
⟨1,s⟩
Bert
Cd t1a
t1s
thinks⟨2,a⟩ CP
⟨2,s⟩ v∗P
Cd t2a
nP
(v∗) vP
(σ )
t2s smoke
u2s NumP
sm F-o-M
325
(8.92) ‘Callie thinks that the monster which Timmy thinks Alice found ate Fluffy.’
S
T⟨1,a⟩
⟨1,s⟩
Callie
Cd t1a
t1s
thinks⟨2,a⟩ CP
⟨2,s⟩
that t2a
vP
the⟨4,a⟩ n∗P
t2s ate Fluffy
CPrel
X nP1
⟨4,s⟩
Timmy w1 g2
Crel g2
t4s F2cf∗-t4a monster
thinks⟨3,a⟩ CP
⟨3,s⟩
Alice
Cd t3a
t3s
found nP2
u3s
wh2cf∗-t4a monster
326
(8.120) ‘Fluffy meowed.’
S
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩
(∃) v∗P
Cd t1a
u1s v∗agt vP
Fluffy
R2 g1
v0
meow
v t1s
(8.135) ‘There are no unicorns.’
S
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
⟨1,s⟩
(∃) vP
Cd t1a
vbe n∗P
⟨2,a⟩
∃r n∗P
u1s X nP
Rp.loc
o3e g1
t1s
F2cf∗ t2a
no# unicorns
327
(9.17) CP⟨2,a⟩ ∶ ⟨t, t⟩
⟨2,a⟩ t
ιh
⟨s, t⟩
wh2sf g2 p1st g1
⟨2,s⟩ t
⟨2,s⟩
wh2sf -g2 p1st -g1
if t2a you2 -g1 t2s drive
328
(9.49) Hindi multiple correlative:
‘Which girl played with which boy, she defeated him.’ (Dayal 1996)
S∶t
T⟨1,a⟩ CP ∶ t
⟨1,s⟩ IP ∶ t
Cd t1a
⟨2,a⟩
CP1 ∶ ⟨t, t⟩ IP1 ∶ t
⟨2,a⟩
ιh
329
(9.56) Individual correlative (DP-adjunction)
S∶t
T⟨1,a⟩ CP ∶ t
⟨1,s⟩ IP ∶ t
Cd t1a
DP ∶ ⟨et, t⟩ VP ∶ ⟨e, t⟩
t1s tall
⟨2,a⟩
ιh she2 -g2 girl-w1 -g1
w1 g1
⟨2,s⟩
330
(10.45) Correlative question
S∶t
Q⟨3,a⟩ CP ∶ t
⟨2,a⟩
CP1 ∶ ⟨t, t⟩ CP1 ∶ t
⟨2,a⟩
ιh
w1 g3
w1 g1 ⟨1,s⟩
⟨2,s⟩
C? t3a
t1s
Cif t2a she2 -g2 girl-w1 -g1 tall
t2s standing d1 g3
wh2 -g2 girl-w1 -g1
(9.66) S∶t
T⟨1,a⟩ CP
CP ∶ t
C∅ t1a
⟨2,a⟩ CP1 ∶ t
CP1 ∶ ⟨t, t⟩
⟨2,a⟩
ιh YP⟨1,s⟩ ∶ ⟨t, t⟩ C∶t
e IP
⟨2,s⟩ then2sf -g2 p1st -g1
wh2sf -g2 p1st -g1
if t2a it2 -g1 t2s heads t1s in-WL
I 1 - g2
(10.25)[ S Q⟨2,a⟩ [ CP w1 -g2 [[C? t2a ]⟨1,s⟩ [[ TopP ι [ n∗P P1et -g1 X [wh1 -g2 [w1 -g1 [sg]-baby]]]]
t1s laughed]]]]
331
(10.46) S ∶ ⟨t, t⟩
Q⟨3,a⟩ CP ∶ t
⟨2,a⟩ CP1 ∶ t
CP1 ∶ ⟨t, t⟩
⟨2,a⟩
ιh w1 g2
⟨1,s⟩
⟨2,s⟩
C? t3a I1 g2
wh2sf -g2 p1st -g1 t1s
rich
it2 -g1 t2s heads d1 g3
if t2a
(10.49) S ∶ ⟨t, t⟩
Q⟨3,a⟩ CP ∶ t
⟨2,a⟩
CP1 ∶ ⟨t, t⟩ CP1 ∶ t
⟨2,a⟩
ιh XP⟨3,s⟩ ∶ ⟨t, t⟩
t3s
⟨2,s⟩ then2sf -g2 p1st -g1 ⟨1,s⟩
wh2sf -g2 p1st -g1
if t2a it2 -g1 t2s heads C? t3a I1 -g2 t1s rich d1 -g3
332
References
Abbott, Barbara. 2002. Donkey demonstratives. Natural Language Semantics 10,
285–298. [See page 90.]
Abney, Steven Paul. 1987. The English noun phrase in its sentential aspect. Ph.D.
thesis, MIT. [See pages 72, 107.]
Adésolá, Olúsèye. 2005. Pronouns and null operators: A-bar dependencies and
relations in Yorùbá. Ph.D. thesis, Rutgers University. [See page 301.]
Adger, David. 2003. Core syntax: A minimalist approach. New York: Oxford
University Press. [See pages 100, 108, 177.]
Adger, David, Cécile de Cat, & George Tsoulas (Eds.). 2004. Peripheries:
Syntactic edges and their effects. Dordrecht: Kluwer. [See pages 338, 391.]
Adger, David & Gillian Ramchand. 2005. Merge and Move: Wh-dependences
revisited. Linguistic Inquiry 36, 161–193. [See page 184.]
333
Aikhenvald, Alexandra Y. 2013. Possession and ownership: A cross linguistic
perspective. In Aikhenvald & Dixon (2013), pp. 1–64. [See pages 113, 114, 118,
125, 128, 232.]
Aikhenvald, Alexandra Y. & R.M.W. Dixon (Eds.). 2013. Possession and owner-
ship: A cross-linguistic typology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See pages 334,
339, 352.]
Alexiadou, Artemis. 2001a. Adjective syntax and noun raising: Word order
asymmetries in the DP as the result of adjective distribution. Studia Linguistica
55, 217–248. [See page 100.]
Alexiadou, Artemis. 2003. Some notes on the structure of alienable and inalien-
able possessors. In Coene & D'hulst (2003), pp. 167–188. [See pages 99, 108,
110, 115, 117, 119, 124.]
Alexiadou, Artemis, Liliane Haegeman, & Melita Stravou. 2007. Noun phrase
in the generative perspective. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. [See pages 72, 82, 100, 109,
111, 133, 215.]
Alexiadou, Artemis & Chris Wilder. 1998a. Adjectival modification and multiple
determiners. In Alexiadou & Wilder (1998b), pp. 303–332. [See pages 99, 110.]
Alexiadou, Artemis & Chris Wilder (Eds.). 1998b. Possessors, predicates and
movement in the Determiner Phrase. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. [See pages 72,
119, 334, 348, 396.]
Antonenko, Andrei, John F. Bailyn, & Christina Y. Bethin (Eds.). 2008. Formal
approaches to Slavic linguistics (FASL) 16. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic Publica-
tions. [See pages 339, 359.]
Aoun, Joseph & Norbert Hornstein. 1992. Bound and referential pronouns. In
C.-T. James Huang & Robert May (Eds.), Logical structure and linguistic structure:
Cross-linguistic perspectives, pp. 1–23. Dordrecht: Kluwer. [See page 82.]
334
Arad, Maya. 2003. Locality constraints on the interpretation of roots: The case of
Hebrew denominal verbs. Natural Language and Linguistic Theory 21, 737–778.
[See page 235.]
von Prince, Kilu. 2016. Alienability as control: The case of Daakaka. Lingua 182,
69–87. [See pages 115, 123, 125.]
Bach, Emmon, Eloise Jelinek, Angelika Kratzer, & Barbara H. Partee (Eds.).
1995. Quantification in natural languages. Dordrecht: Kluwer. [See pages 359, 361,
363, 380.]
Badulescu, Adriana & Dan Moldovan. 2008. A Semantic Scattering model for
the automatic interpretation of English genitives. Natural Language Engineering
15, 215–239. [See pages 112, 128.]
Bagchi, Tista. 1994. Bangla correlative pronouns, relative clause order, and
D-linking. In Miriam Butt, Tracy Holloway King, & Gillian Ramchand
(Eds.), Theoretical perspectives on word order in South Asian languages, pp. 13–
30. Stanford: CSLI. [See page 5.]
Baltin, Mark. 2012. The structural signature of pronouns. MS, NYU. [See
pages 82, 298.]
Baltin, Mark & Chris Collins (Eds.). 2001. The handbook of contemporary
syntactic theory. Oxford: Blackwell. [See pages 336, 339, 373, 385.]
Barbosa, Pilar, Danny Fox, Paul Hagstrom, Martha McGinnis, & David
Pesetsky (Eds.). 1998. Is the best good enough? Optimality and competition in
syntax. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. [See page 137.]
Barker, Chris. 2002. The dynamics of vagueness. Linguistics and Philosophy 25,
1–36. [See page 9.]
335
Barlow, Michael. 1992. A situated theory of agreement. London: Routledge. [See
page 180.]
Bartsch, Renate. 1973. The semantics and syntax of numbers. In John P. Kimball
(Ed.), Syntax and semantics 2, pp. 52–93. New York: Seminar Press. [See page 157.]
Barwise, Jon & Robin Cooper. 1981. Generalized quantifiers and natural language.
Linguistics and Philosophy 4, 159–219. [See pages 228, 229.]
Basilico, David. 1996. Head position and internally headed relative clauses.
Language 72, 498–532. [See page 206.]
Beaver, David, Itamar Francez, & Dmitry Levinson. 2005. Bad subject: (Non)-
canonicality and NP distribution in existentials. In Efthymia Georgala &
Jonathan Howell (Eds.), Proceedings of SALT 15, pp. 19–43. Ithaca, N.Y.: CLC
Publications. [See page 148.]
Beghelli, Filippo & Tim Stowell. 1997. Distributivity and negation: The syntax
of each and every. In Anna Szabolcsi (Ed.), Ways of scope taking, pp. 71–107.
Dordrecht: Kluwer. [See page 155.]
Bernstein, Judy & Christina Tortora. 2005. Two types of possessive forms in
English. Lingua 115, 1221–1242. [See page 119.]
336
Beshears, Anne. 2017. The demonstrative nature of the Hindi/Marwari correlative.
Ph.D. thesis, Queen Mary University of London. [See pages 256, 270, 271.]
Bhat, D.N.S. 2004. Pronouns. New York: Oxford University Press. [See pages 4, 72,
82, 86, 106, 133, 137, 197, 286, 287, 297, 298, 299.]
Bhatt, Rajesh. 2002. The raising analysis of relative clauses: Evidence from
adjectival modification. Natural Language Semantics 10, 43–90. [See pages 66,
68, 71, 95, 189.]
Bhatt, Rajesh. 2006. Covert modality in non-finite contexts. Berlin: de Gruyter. [See
pages 45, 100, 227, 230, 318.]
Bhatt, Rajesh & Anikó Lipták. 2009. Matching effects in the temporal and locative
domains. In Lipták (2009a), pp. 343–372. [See page 269.]
Bhatt, Rajesh & Roumyana Pancheva. 2006. Conditionals. In Everaert & van
Riemsdijk (2006), pp. 638–687. [See pages 69, 238, 239, 241, 242, 243, 253, 256, 258,
260, 265, 267, 275, 315.]
Bhattacharya, Tanmoy. 1999b. The structure of the Bangla DP. Ph.D. thesis,
University College London. [See pages 72, 100, 103, 108, 119, 129, 130.]
337
Bittner, Maria & Ken Hale. 1996. The structural determination of Case and
agreement. Linguistic Inquiry 27, 1–68. [See pages 72, 223.]
Blutner, Reinhard. 2004. Pragmatics and the lexicon. In Laurence R. Horn &
Gregory Ward (Eds.), The handbook of pragmatics, pp. 488–514. Malden, Mass.:
Blackwell. [See page 188.]
Bodomo, Adams & Ken Hiraiwa. 2010. Relativization in Dàgáárè and its typolog-
ical implications: Left-headed but internally-headed. Lingua 120, 953–983. [See
page 194.]
Boeckx, Cedric, Norbert Hornstein, & Jairo Nunes. 2007. Overt copies in
reflexive and control structures: A movement analysis. In Anastasia Con-
roy, Chunyuang Jing, Chizuru Nakao, & Eri Takahashi (Eds.), University of
Maryland working papers in linguistics 15, pp. 1–45. College Park: University of
Maryland. [See pages 61, 132, 133, 134, 135.]
Boneh, Nora & Ivy Sichel. 2010. Deconstructing possession. Natural Language
and Linguistic Theory 28, 1–40. [See pages 119, 221, 230, 232.]
Bonomi, Andrea. 1997b. The progressive and the structure of events. Journal of
Semantics 14, 173–205. [See page 235.]
Borer, Hagit. 2005a. Structuring sense, Volume I: In name only. Oxford: Oxford
University Press. [See pages 133, 150, 215.]
Borer, Hagit. 2005b. Structuring sense, Volume II: The normal course of events.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See pages 152, 215, 216.]
338
Borschev, Vladimir, Elena V. Paducheva, Barbara H. Partee, Yakov G.
Testelets, & Igor Yanovich. 2008. Russian genitives, non-referentiality, and
the property-type hypothesis. In Antonenko et al. (2008), pp. 48–67. [See
page 123.]
Borschev, Vladimir & Barbara H. Partee. 2002. The Russian genitive of negation
in existential sentences: The role of Theme-Rheme structure reconsidered. In Eva
Hajičová, Petr Sgall, Jirí Hana, & Tomáš Hoskovec (Eds.), Prague linguistic
circle papers, vol. 4, pp. 185–250. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. [See pages 169,
225, 232.]
Bošković, Željko & Jairo Nunes. 2007. The copy theory of movement: A view
from PF. In Corver & Nunes (2007), pp. 13–74. [See pages 133, 135.]
Bowers, John. 2001. Predication. In Baltin & Collins (2001), pp. 299–333. [See
pages 151, 170.]
Bowers, John. 2002. Transitivity. Linguistic Inquiry 33, 183–224. [See page 152.]
Brasoveanu, Adrian. 2007. Structured nominal and modal reference. Ph.d. thesis,
Rutgers University. [See page 93.]
Broekhuis, Hans. 2008. Derivations and evaluations: Object shift in the Germanic
languages. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. [See page 137.]
Browning, M.A. 1996. CP recursion and that-t effects. Linguistic Inquiry 27, 237–
255. [See page 255.]
339
Bruening, Benjamin. 2009. Selectional asymmetries between CP and DP suggest
that the DP hypothesis is wrong. In Laurel MacKenzie (Ed.), University of
Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics, vol. 15.1, pp. 26–35. University of
Pennsylvania. [See page 108.]
Burge, Tyler. 1973. Reference and proper names. Journal of Philosophy 70, 425–
439. [See pages 51, 52.]
Büring, Daniel. 2004. Crossover situations. Natural Language Semantics 12, 23–62.
[See pages 1, 41, 63, 81, 104, 139, 141, 147.]
Cable, Seth. 2009. The syntax of the Tibetan correlative. In Lipták (2009a), pp.
195–222. [See pages 266, 270, 274.]
Caponigro, Ivano. 2002. Free relatives as DPs with a silent D and a CP complement.
In Vida Samiian (Ed.), Proceedings of the Western Conference on Linguistics 2000
(WECOL 2000). Fresno: California State University. [See page 98.]
Caponigro, Ivano. 2003. Free not to ask: On the semantics of free relatives and
wh-words cross-linguistically. Ph.D. thesis, UCLA. [See pages 72, 73, 74, 207.]
Caponigro, Ivano. 2012. Acquiring the meaning of free relative clauses and plural
definite descriptions. Journal of Semantics 29, 261–293. [See pages 74, 241.]
Cardinaletti, Anna & Giuliana Giusti. 2017. Quantified expressions and quan-
titative clitics. In Everaert & van Riemsdijk (2017), pp. 1–61. [See pages 106,
109, 133.]
340
Cardinaletti, Anna & Michal Starke. 1999. The typology of structural defi-
ciency: A case study of the three classes of pronouns. In Henk van Riemsdijk
(Ed.), Clitics in the languages of Europe, pp. 145–233. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
[See pages 72, 102, 103, 133, 209, 223.]
Carlson, Greg. 2003. Weak indefinites. In Coene & D'hulst (2003), pp. 195–210.
[See page 157.]
Carlson, Greg N. 1977. Amount relatives. Language 58, 520–542. [See pages 95,
148, 189.]
Carlson, Gregory N. 1980. Reference to kinds in English. New York: Garland. [See
page 230.]
Carlson, Robert. 1994. A grammar of Supyire. Berlin: de Gruyter. [See page 298.]
Cecchetto, Carlo & Caterina Donati. 2010. On labeling: Principle C and head
movement. Syntax 13, 241–278. [See page 135.]
Chang, Henry Y. 2012. Nominal tense in Tsou: Nia and its syntax/semantics.
In Thomas Graf, Denis Paperno, Anna Szabolcsi, & Jos Tellings (Eds.),
Theories of everything: In honor of Ed Keenan, pp. 43–58. UCLA Working Papers in
Linguistics. [See page 99.]
Chappell, Hilary & William McGregor (Eds.). 1996a. The grammar of inalien-
ability: A typological perspective on body part terms and the part-whole relation.
Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. [See pages 342, 393.]
341
Chappell, Hilary & William McGregor. 1996b. Prolegomena to a theory of
inalienability. In Chappell & McGregor (1996a), pp. 3–30. [See pages 114,
123, 128.]
Charlow, Nate. 2011. Practical language: Its meaning and use. Ph.D. thesis,
University of Michigan. [See page 305.]
Charlow, Nate. 2013b. What we know and what to do. Synthese 190, 2291–2323.
[See page 263.]
Charlow, Simon & Yael Sharvit. 2014. Bound ‘de re’ pronouns and the LFs of
attitude reports. Semantics and Pragmatics 7, 1–43. [See pages 3, 51.]
Cheng, Lisa L.-S. & C.-T. James Huang. 1996. Two types of donkey sentences.
Natural Language Semantics 4, 121–163. [See page 88.]
Chierchia, Gennaro. 1988. Topics in the syntax and semantics of infinitives and
gerunds. New York: Garland Publishing. [See page 198.]
342
Chierchia, Gennaro. 1998. Reference to kinds across languages. Natural Language
Semantics 6, 339–405. [See pages 158, 198.]
Chomsky, Noam. 1965. Aspects of the theory of syntax. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press. [See page 66.]
Chomsky, Noam. 1981. Lectures on government and binding: The Pisa lectures.
Dordrecht: Foris. [See pages 22, 36, 137.]
Chomsky, Noam. 1995. The minimalist program. Cambridge: MIT Press. [See
pages 22, 36, 39, 70, 216, 289, 292.]
Chomsky, Noam. 2008. On phases. In Freidin et al. (2008), pp. 133–166. [See
page 177.]
343
Chung, Sandra. 1987. The syntax of Chamorro existential sentences. In Reuland
& ter Meulen (1987), pp. 191–225. [See pages 168, 223.]
Chung, Sandra. 1998. The design of agreement: Evidence from Chamorro. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press. [See pages 78, 288.]
Chung, Sandra & William Ladusaw. 2004. Restriction and saturation. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press. [See pages 159, 171, 229.]
Cinque, Guglielmo. 1995. On the evidence for partial N-movement in the Ro-
mance DP. In Italian syntax and Universal Grammar, pp. 287–309. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press. [See pages 100, 111, 157.]
Cinque, Guglielmo. 2003. The prenominal origin of relative clauses. MS, NYU
Workshop on Antisymmetry and Remnant Movement. [See page 190.]
Cinque, Guglielmo. 2013. Typological studies: Word order and relative clauses. New
York: Routledge. [See pages 66, 95, 111, 189, 190, 191, 207.]
Citko, Barbara. 2009. What don’t wh-questions, free relatives, and correlatives
have in common? In Lipták (2009a), pp. 49–79. [See pages 207, 265, 274, 287.]
344
Clark, Eve V. 1978. Locationals: Existential, locative and possessive constructions.
In Joseph H. Greenberg (Ed.), Universals of human language, Vol. 4: Syntax, pp.
85–126. Stanford: Stanford University Press. [See pages 225, 232.]
Claudi, Ulrike & Bernd Heine. 1989. On the nominal morphology of ‘alienability’
in some African languages. In Paul Newman & Robert Dale Botne (Eds.),
Current approaches to African linguistics 5, pp. 3–19. Dordrecht: Foris. [See
page 114.]
Coene, Martine & Yves D'hulst (Eds.). 2003. From NP to DP, Vol. II: The expression
of possession in noun phrases. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. [See pages 334,
341, 369.]
Collins, Chris. 1993. Topics in Ewe syntax. Ph.D. thesis, MIT. [See page 89.]
Collins, Chris. 2001. Aspects of plurality in =∣ Hoan. Language 77, 456–476. [See
page 215.]
Cooper, Robin. 1979. The interpretation of pronouns. In Frank Heny & Helmut S.
Schnelle (Eds.), Syntax and semantics 10, pp. 61–92. New York: Academic Press.
[See page 82.]
Copley, Bridget & Heidi Harley. 2015. A force-theoretic framework for event
structure. Linguistics and Philosophy 38, 103–158. [See page 215.]
Corver, Norbert & Jairo Nunes (Eds.). 2007. The copy theory of movement.
Philadelphia: John Benjamins. [See pages 134, 339, 362, 364, 367.]
Creissels, Denis. 2013. Control and the evolution of possessive and existential
constructions. In van Gelderen et al. (2013), pp. 461–476. [See pages 225, 230.]
Cresswell, M.J. 1990. Entities and indices. Dordrecht: Kluwer. [See page 1.]
345
Cresti, Diana & Christina Tortora. 2000. Aspects of locative doubling and
resultative predication. In Steve S. Chang, Lily Liaw, & Josef Ruppenhofer
(Eds.), Proceedings of the Berkeley Linguistic Society 25, pp. 62–73. Berkeley:
Berkeley Linguistics Society. [See page 169.]
Crnič, Luka & Uli Sauerland (Eds.). 2014. The art and craft of semantics: A
festschrift for Irene Heim. Cambridge, Mass.: MITWPL. [See pages 366, 385.]
Culy, Christopher. 1990. The syntax and semantics of internally headed relative
clauses. Ph.D. thesis, Stanford University. [See pages 128, 207.]
D'Alessandro, Roberta, Irene Franco, & Ángel J. Gallego (Eds.). 2017. The
verbal domain. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See pages 108, 150, 152, 216, 358,
383, 391, 395.]
Danon, Gabi. 1996. The syntax of Hebrew determiners. MA thesis, Tel-Aviv Univer-
sity. [See page 106.]
Davidson, Donald. 1967. The logical form of action sentences. In Essays on actions
and events, pp. 105–121. New York: Clarendon Press, 2nd edn. [See page 214.]
Davies, William D. 1981. Choctaw clause structure. Ph.D. thesis, UC San Diego.
[See page 236.]
346
Davison, Alice. 2009b. Correlative clause features in Sanskrit and Hindi/Urdu.
In Paola Crisma & Giuseppe Longobardi (Eds.), Historical syntax and linguistic
theory, pp. 271–291. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See page 266.]
Dayal, Veneeta. 2016. Questions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See page 289.]
Déchaine, Rose-Marie & Martina Wiltschko. 2015. When and why can 1st and
2nd person pronouns be bound variables? In Patrick Grosz, Pritty Patel-
Grosz, & Igor Yanovich (Eds.), NELS 40: Semantics workshop on pronouns, pp.
1–50. Amherst: GLSA. [See pages 82, 102, 133, 135, 137.]
Diesing, Molly (Ed.). 1992. Indefinites. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. [See
pages 157, 159, 168, 177.]
den Dikken, Marcel. 1995. Copulas. MS, Vrije Universiteit Amsterdam/HIL. [See
pages 115, 119, 151, 230, 232, 233.]
347
den Dikken, Marcel. 1997. The syntax of possession and the verb ‘have’. Lingua
101, 129–150. [See pages 230, 232.]
den Dikken, Marcel. 1998. Predicate inversion in DP. In Alexiadou & Wilder
(1998b), pp. 177–214. [See pages 72, 119, 151.]
Dixon, R.M.W. 1969. Relative clauses and possessive phrases in two Australian
languages. Language 45, 35–44. [See pages 118, 190.]
Dixon, R.M.W. 2004. The Jarawara language of Southern Amazonia. Oxford: Oxford
University Press. [See page 175.]
Dixon, R.M.W. 2010. Basic linguistic theory, Volume 2: Grammatical topics. Oxford:
Oxford University Press. [See pages 4, 113, 114, 119, 125, 128, 232.]
Dixon, R.M.W. 2012. Basic linguistic theory, Volume 3: Further grammatical topics.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See page 233.]
348
Donati, Caterina & Carlo Cecchetto. 2015. (Re)labeling. Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT Press. [See pages 66, 100.]
Dowell, J.L. 2012. Contextualist solutions to three puzzles about practical condi-
tionals. In Russ Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics, vol. 7, pp.
271–303. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See page 263.]
Drummond, Alex, Dave Kush, & Norbert Hornstein. 2011. Minimalist con-
strual: Two approaches to A and B. In Cedric Boeckx (Ed.), The Oxford handbook
of linguistic minimalism, pp. 396–426. New York: Oxford University Press. [See
pages 133, 135, 137.]
Dryer, Matthew S. 2005. Order of relative clause and noun. In Martin Haspel-
math, Matthew S. Dryer, David Gil, & Bernard Comrie (Eds.), The world
atlas of language structures, pp. 366–369. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See
page 190.]
Elbourne, Paul D. 2005. Situations and individuals. Cambridge: MIT Press. [See
pages 3, 51, 52, 68, 81, 82, 84, 92, 104, 134, 147.]
Embick, David & Rolf Noyer. 2001. Movement operations after syntax. Linguistic
Inquiry 32, 555–595. [See pages 119, 124.]
Enç, Mürvet. 1981. Tense without scope: An analysis of nouns as indexicals. Ph.D.
thesis, University of Wisconsin–Madison. [See page 174.]
Enç, Mürvet. 1987. Anchoring conditions for tense. Linguistic Inquiry 18, 633–657.
[See page 174.]
349
Enç, Mürvet. 1991. The semantics of specificity. Linguistic Inquiry 22, 1–25. [See
pages 101, 103, 126, 148, 149, 165, 166, 168, 313.]
Epstein, Samuel David & T. Daniel Seely (Eds.). 2002. Derivation and explanation
in the Minimalist Program. Oxford: Blackwell. [See pages 365, 376.]
Everaert, Martin & Henk van Riemsdijk (Eds.). 2006. The Blackwell companion
to syntax. Oxford: Blackwell. [See pages 337, 347, 389.]
Everaert, Martin & Henk van Riemsdijk (Eds.). 2017. The Wiley Blackwell
companion to syntax, Second edition. Blackwell. [See pages 340, 347, 361, 377,
382, 386.]
Fabb, Nigel. 1990. The difference between English restrictive and nonrestrictive
relative clauses. Journal of Linguistics 26, 57–78. [See page 66.]
Falco, Michelangelo & Roberto Zamparelli. 2016. The only real pro-nouns:
Comparing English one and Italian ne as Noun Phrase pro-forms. In Grosz &
Patel-Grosz (2016), pp. 107–134. [See page 86.]
Fara, Delia Graff. 2011. You can call me ‘stupid’,… just don’t call me stupid.
Analysis 71, 492–501. [See page 51.]
Fara, Delia Graff. 2015. Names are predicates. Philosophical Review 124, 59–117.
[See pages 51, 52.]
350
Felser, Claudia. 2015. Syntax and language processing. In Tibor Kiss & Artemis
Alexiadou (Eds.), Syntax: Theory and analysis, vol. 3, pp. 1875–1911. Berlin:
de Gruyter. [See page 136.]
Fiengo, Robert & Robert May. 1994. Indices and identity. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press. [See page 71.]
von Fintel, Kai. 1994. Restrictions on quantifier domains. Ph.D. thesis, University
of Massachusetts, Amherst. [See pages 13, 41, 84, 104, 240, 241, 253, 256, 257, 258, 260.]
von Fintel, Kai. 1998a. Evidence for presuppositional indefinites. MS, MIT. [See
page 149.]
von Fintel, Kai. 1998b. The semantics and pragmatics of quantifier domain
restriction. Vilem Mathesius Lectures, Prague. [See page 102.]
von Fintel, Kai & Irene Heim. 2011. Intensional semantics. MS, MIT. [See pages 9,
10, 11, 17, 25, 34, 57.]
von Fintel, Kai & Sabine Iatridou. 2005. What to do if you want to go to Harlem:
Anankastic conditionals and related matters. MS, MIT. [See page 261.]
von Fintel, Kai & Sabine Iatridou. 2009. Lecture notes for LSA 220: Morphology,
syntax, and semantics of modals. MIT. [See page 31.]
von Fintel, Kai & Lisa Matthewson. 2008. Universals in semantics. The Linguistic
Review 25, 139–201. [See page 133.]
Fodor, Janet Dean. 1970. The linguistic description of opaque contexts. Ph.D. thesis,
MIT. [See pages 9, 10, 43.]
Fodor, Janet Dean & Ivan A. Sag. 1982. Referential and quantificational indefi-
nites. Linguistics and Philosophy 5, 355–398. [See pages 75, 81.]
Folli, Raffaella & Heidi Harley. 2007. Causation, obligation, and argument
structure: On the nature of little v. Linguistic Inquiry 38, 197–238. [See pages 151,
216, 219.]
Fortescue, Michael. 1984. West Greenlandic. London: Croom Helm. [See page 220.]
351
Fox, Danny. 2000. Economy and semantic interpretation. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press. [See pages 22, 36, 68, 71, 137, 292.]
Fox, Danny. 2002. Antecedent-contained deletion and the copy theory of move-
ment. Linguistic Inquiry 33, 63–96. [See pages 22, 36, 38, 68, 71, 249.]
Fox, Danny. 2003. On logical form. In Randall Hendrick (Ed.), Minimalist syntax,
pp. 82–123. Oxford: Blackwell. [See pages 22, 38, 71.]
Fox, Danny & Jon Nissenbaum. 1999. Extraposition and scope: A case for overt QR.
In Sonya Bird, Andrew Carnie, Jason D. Haugen, & Peter Norquest (Eds.),
Proceedings of WCCFL 18, pp. 132–144. Somerville, Mass.: Cascadilla Press. [See
pages 37, 179.]
Fox, Danny & Jon Nissenbaum. 2004. Condition A and scope reconstruction.
Linguistic Inquiry 35, 475–485. [See page 292.]
352
Franks, Steven. 1994. Parametric properties of numeral phrases in Slavic. Natural
Language and Linguistic Theory 12, 570–649. [See pages 107, 150.]
Franks, Steven & Asya Pereltsvaig. 2004. Functional categories in the nominal
domain. In Olga Arnaudowa, Wayles Browne, Maria Luisa Rivera, &
Danijela Stojanovic (Eds.), Formal approaches to Slavic linguistics (FASL) 12,
pp. 109–128. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic Publications. [See pages 107, 122.]
Freeze, Ray. 1992. Existentials and other locatives. Language 68, 553–595. [See
pages 221, 225, 230, 231.]
Freidin, Robert, Carlos P. Otero, & Maria Luisa Zubizarreta (Eds.). 2008.
Foundational issues in linguistic theory: Essays in honor of Jean-Roger Vergnaud.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. [See pages 343, 376.]
Fukui, Naoki & Margaret Speas. 1986. Specifiers and projection. In Naoki Fukui,
Tova R. Rapoport, & Elizabeth Sagey (Eds.), MIT working papers in linguistics
8: Papers in theoretical linguistics, pp. 128–172. Cambridge, Mass.: MITWPL. [See
pages 72, 111.]
Gair, James W. 1998. Studies in South Asian linguistics: Sinhala and other South
Asian languages. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See pages 4, 269.]
Gair, James W., Barbara Lust, K.V. Subbarao, & Kashi Wali (Eds.). 1999. Lexical
anaphors and pronouns in selected South Asian languages: A principled typology.
Berlin: de Gruyter. [See pages 4, 86, 286, 297, 299.]
353
Gallego, Ángel J. 2010. Phase theory. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. [See page 178.]
Geis, Michael. 1970. Adverbial subordinate clauses in English. Ph.D. thesis, MIT.
[See page 256.]
van Gelderen, Elly, Michela Cennamo, & Jóhanna Barðdal (Eds.). 2013.
Argument structure in flux. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. [See pages 345, 353.]
George, Benjamin. 2011. Question embedding and the semantics of answers. Ph.D.
thesis, UCLA. [See pages 289, 290.]
Geurts, Bart. 1997. Good news about the description theory of names. Journal of
Semantics 14, 319–348. [See pages 51, 60.]
Ghomeshi, Jila, Ileana Paul, & Martina Wiltschko (Eds.). 2009. Determiners:
Universals and variation. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. [See pages 103, 133.]
Gil, David. 2013. Genitives, adjectives and relative clauses. In Matthew S. Dryer
& Martin Haspelmath (Eds.), The world atlas of language structures online.
Leipzig: Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology. URL wals.info/
chapter/60. [See pages 111, 118, 190, 375.]
Gil, Kook-Hee, Stephen Harlow, & George Tsoulas (Eds.). 2013. Strategies of
quantification. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See page 133.]
Gillies, Anthony S. 2010. Iffiness. Semantics and Pragmatics 3, 1–42. [See page 263.]
354
Giusti, Giuliana. 1991. The categorial status of quantified nominals. Linguistiche
Berichte 136, 438–452. [See pages 106, 109, 133, 157.]
Giusti, Giuliana. 1992. Heads and modifiers among determiners: Evidence from
Romanian and German. In University of Venice Working Papers in Linguistics, vol.
1.3, pp. 1–19. University of Venice. [See pages 103, 106, 133, 157.]
Giusti, Giuliana. 2002. The functional structure of noun phrases: A bare phrase
structure approach. In Guglielmo Cinque (Ed.), Functional structure in DP and
IP: The cartography of syntactic structures, Vol. 1, pp. 54–90. New York: Oxford
University Press. [See pages 31, 72, 99, 100, 103, 108, 133.]
Giusti, Giuliana & Nedžad Leko. 1995. On the syntax of quantity expressions in
Bosnian. In Laura Brugè (Ed.), University of Venice Working Papers in Linguistics,
vol. 5.2, pp. 23–47. University of Venice. [See pages 109, 157.]
Grimshaw, Jane. 1997. Projection, heads, and optimality. Linguistic Inquiry 28,
373–422. [See page 137.]
Grimshaw, Jane. 2005. Words and structure. Stanford: CSLI. [See page 72.]
Groat, Erich & John O'neil. 1996. Spell-Out at the LF Interface. In Werner
Abraham, Samuel David Epstein, Höskuldur Thráinsson, & Jan-Wouter
Zwart (Eds.), Minimal ideas: Syntactic studies in the minimalist framework, pp.
113–139. Philadelphia: John Benjamins. [See page 37.]
Groenendijk, Jeroen & Floris Roelofsen. 2009. Inquisitive semantics and prag-
matics. MS, ILLC. [See page 305.]
355
Groenendijk, Jeroen & Martin Stockhof. 1984. Studies on the semantics of
questions and the pragmatics of answers. Ph.D. thesis, University of Amsterdam.
[See pages 283, 290.]
Groenendijk, Jeroen & Martin Stockhof. 1991. Dynamic predicate logic. Lin-
guistics and Philosophy 14, 39–100. [See pages 19, 92.]
Groos, Aneeke & Henk van Riemsdijk. 1981. Matching effects in free relatives: a
parameter of matching effects in free relatives: A parameter of core grammar. In
Adriana Belletti, Luciana Brandi, & Luigi Rizzi (Eds.), Theory of markedness
in generative grammar, pp. 171–216. Pisa: Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa. [See
page 73.]
Grosu, Alexander. 2002. Strange relatives at the interface of two millennia. Glot
International 6, 145–167. [See pages 95, 148, 194, 205, 206, 207.]
Grosu, Alexander & Koji Hoshi. 2016. Japanese internally headed relatives: Their
distinctness from potentially homophonous constructions. Glossa 1, 1–31. [See
page 194.]
Grosu, Alexander & Fred Landman. 1998. Strange relatives of the third kind.
Natural Language Semantics 6, 125–170. [See pages 74, 205, 206, 207, 243, 274.]
Grosz, Patrick & Pritty Patel-Grosz (Eds.). 2016. The impact of pronominal form
on interpretation. Berlin: de Gruyter. [See pages 133, 298, 350, 393, 395.]
356
Guéron, Jacqueline & Jacqueline Lecarme (Eds.). 2004. The syntax of time.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. [See pages 368, 370.]
Hacquard, Valentine. 2006. Aspects of modality. Ph.D. thesis, MIT. [See pages 1,
31, 32, 35, 217, 218, 318.]
Haïk, Isabelle. 1984. Indirect binding. Linguistic Inquiry 15, 185–223. [See
pages 139, 147.]
Haiman, John. 1978. Conditionals are topics. Language 54, 565–589. [See page 258.]
Haiman, John. 1985. Natural syntax: Iconicity and erosion. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press. [See pages 114, 124.]
Hale, Kenneth. 1976. The adjoined relative clause in Australia. In R.M.W. Dixon
(Ed.), Grammatical categories in Australian languages, pp. 78–105. Canberra:
Australian Institute of Aboriginal Studies. [See pages 241, 266.]
357
Hamblin, C.L. 1973. Questions in Montague English. Foundations of language 10,
41–53. [See page 283.]
Hanitramalala, Rita & Paul Ileana. 2012. Malagasy quantifiers. In Keenan &
Paperno (2012), pp. 613–645. [See page 106.]
Harley, Heidi. 1995. Subjects, events and licensing. Ph.D. thesis, MIT. [See pages 151,
219, 230, 232.]
Harley, Heidi. 2002. Possession and the double object construction. Yearbook of
Linguistic Variation 2, 29–68. [See pages 230, 232, 233, 235.]
Harley, Heidi. 2005. How do verbs get their names? Denominal verbs, Manner
Incorporation, and the ontology of verb roots in English. In Nomi Erteschik-Shir
& Tova Rapoport (Eds.), The syntax of aspect: Deriving thematic and aspectual
interpretation, pp. 42–64. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See pages 216, 233.]
Harley, Heidi. 2009. The morphology of nominalizations and the syntax of vP. In
Giannakidou & Rathert (2009), pp. 320–342. [See pages 108, 150, 152, 181, 197.]
Harley, Heidi. 2013. External arguments and the Mirror Principle: On the distinct-
ness of Voice and v. Lingua 125, 34–57. [See pages 108, 150, 151, 152, 197, 217, 233.]
Harley, Heidi. 2017. The “bundling” hypothesis and the disparate functions of
little v. In D'Alessandro et al. (2017), pp. 3–28. [See pages 152, 197, 217.]
Harley, Heidi & Hyun Kyoung Jung. 2015. In support of the phave analysis of the
double object construction. Linguistic Inquiry 46, 703–730. [See pages 223, 230,
233, 235, 236.]
Hartmann, Jutta M. 2008. Expletives in existentials: English there and German da.
Ph.D. thesis, Tilburg University. [See pages 101, 103, 148, 169, 170, 171, 227, 232.]
358
Hartmann, Jutta M. & Nataša Milićević. 2008. The syntax of existential sen-
tences in Serbian. In Antonenko et al. (2008), pp. 168–184. [See page 122.]
Haspelmath, Martin. 1995. Diachronic sources of ‘all’ and ‘every’. In Bach et al.
(1995), pp. 363–382. [See pages 106, 297.]
Hastings, Rachel. 2004. The syntax and semantics of relativization and quantifica-
tion: The case of Quechua. Ph.D. thesis, Cornell University. [See pages 95, 194, 207.]
Hazout, Ilan. 2004. The syntax of existential constructions. Linguistic Inquiry 35,
393–430. [See pages 168, 169, 181, 223, 227, 228.]
Heim, Irene. 1982. The semantics of definite and indefinite noun phrases. Ph.D. thesis,
University of Massachusetts Amherst. [See pages 29, 81, 91, 92.]
Heim, Irene. 1990. E-type pronouns and donkey anaphora. Linguistics and Philoso-
phy 13, 137–177. [See pages 81, 84, 91.]
Heim, Irene. 1991. Articles and definiteness. In Arnim von Stechow & Dieter
Wunderlich (Eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of contemporary re-
search, pp. 487–535. Berlin: de Gruyter. [See page 102.]
Heim, Irene. 1994. Interrogative semantics and Karttunen’s semantics for know.
In Rhonna Buchalla & Anita Mitwoch (Eds.), IATL 1, pp. 128–144. Hebrew
University of Jerusalem. [See page 283.]
359
Heim, Irene. 2001. Features of pronouns in semantics and morphology. MS. [See
page 31.]
Heim, Irene. 2012. Lecture notes for 24.973: Advanced semantics. MIT. [See
pages 31, 282, 291.]
Heim, Irene & Angelika Kratzer. 1998. Semantics in Generative Grammar. Oxford:
Wiley-Blackwell. [See pages 12, 15, 19, 22, 29, 35, 36, 37, 66, 68, 70, 82, 98, 111, 131, 135,
144, 184, 292.]
Heine, Bernd & Tania Kuteva. 2002. World lexicon of grammaticalization. Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press. [See pages 86, 106, 113, 118, 150, 225, 287, 297.]
Hendriks, Herman L.W. 1993. Studied flexibility: Categories and types in syntax and
semantics. Amsterdam: ILLC. [See page 98.]
360
Higginbotham, James & Robert May. 1981. Questions, quantifiers and crossing.
The Linguistic Review 1, 41–80. [See page 290.]
Hiraiwa, Ken. 2017. Internally headed relative clauses. In Everaert & van
Riemsdijk (2017). [See pages 66, 94, 194, 207.]
Hoeksema, Jacob (Ed.). 1996b. Partitives: Studies on the syntax and semantics of
partitive and related constructions. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. [See pages 361, 383.]
Hoekstra, Teun & René Mulder. 1990. Unergatives as copular verbs: Locational
and existential predication. The Linguistic Review 7, 1–79. [See page 232.]
Holmberg, Anders. 1993. On the structure of predicate NP. Studia Linguistica 47,
126–138. [See page 103.]
361
Hornstein, Norbert. 2001. Move! A minimalist theory of construal. Oxford:
Blackwell. [See pages 22, 82, 133, 134, 135, 136, 137.]
Hudson, Wesley. 1989. Functional categories and the saturation of noun phrases.
In Juli Carter & Rose-Marie Déchaine (Eds.), Proceedings of NELS 19, pp. 207–
222. Amherst: GLSA. [See page 157.]
Hyslop, Catriona. 2001. The Lolovoli dialect of the North-East Ambae language,
Vanuatu. Canberra: Pacific Linguistics. [See page 114.]
Iatridou, Sabine. 1991. Topics in conditionals. Ph.D. thesis, MIT, Cambridge. [See
pages 69, 238, 241, 253, 256, 257, 258, 275, 277, 315.]
Iatridou, Sabine. 2013. Looking for free relatives in Turkish (and the unexpected
places this leads to). In Umut Özge (Ed.), Proceedings of the 8th Workshop on
Altaic Formal Linguistics (WAFL8), pp. 129–152. Cambridge, Mass.: MITWPL. [See
page 257.]
Iatridou, Sabine & Anthony Kroch. 1993. The licensing of CP-recursion and
its relevance to the Germanic verb-second phenomenon. Working papers in
Scandinavian syntax 50, 1–24. [See pages 255, 256, 258, 277, 314, 315.]
362
Ihsane, Tabea & Genoveva Puskás. 2001. Specific is not definite. In Ur Shlonsky
& Tabea Ihsane (Eds.), Generative grammar in Geneva 2, pp. 39–54. University
of Geneva. [See pages 31, 72, 99, 103.]
Ilkhanipour, Negin. 2016. Tense and modality in the nominal domain. Linguistica
56, 143–160. [See pages 72, 99.]
Ionin, Tania & Ora Matushansky. 2006. The composition of complex cardinals.
Journal of Semantics 23, 315–360. [See pages 151, 157.]
Isaacs, James & Kyle Rawlins. 2008. Conditional questions. Journal of Semantics
25, 269–319. [See page 305.]
Itô, Junko. 1986. Head-movement at LF and PF. In Nobuko Hasegawa & Yoshi-
hisa Kitagawa (Eds.), University of Massachusetts occasional papers in linguistics
11, pp. 109–138. Amherst: GLSA Publications. [See page 302.]
Janssen, Theo M.V. 1997. Compositionality. In Johan van Bentham & Alice
ter Meulen (Eds.), Handbook of logic and linguistics, pp. 417–473. Amsterdam:
Elsevier. [See page 2.]
Jenkins, Lyle. 1975. The English existential. Tübingen: Niemeyer. [See page 168.]
Jensen, Per Anker & Carl Vikner. 1994. Lexical knowledge and the semantic
analysis of Danish genitive constructions. In Steffen L. Hansen & Helle We-
gener (Eds.), Topics in knowledge-based NLP systems, pp. 37–55. Copenhagen:
Samfundslitteratur. [See pages 115, 117.]
363
Jespersen, Otto. 1924. The philosophy of grammar. London: George Allen & Unwin.
[See pages 86, 116, 117, 299.]
Julien, Marit. 2015. Theme vowels in North Sámi: Spanning and maximal expres-
sion. Lingua 164, 1–24. [See pages 150, 151, 152, 214, 216, 217.]
Kalivoda, Nick & Erik Zyman. 2015. On the derivation of relative clauses in
Teotitlán del Valle Zapotec. In Anna E. Jurgensen, Hannah Sande, Spencer
Lamoureux, Kenny Baclawski, & Alison Zerbe (Eds.), Proceedings of the
Berkeley Linguistic Society 41, pp. 219–243. Berkeley: Berkeley Linguistics Society.
[See pages 95, 207, 242.]
Kamp, Hans. 1971. Formal properties of ‘now’. Theoria 37, 227–274. [See page 1.]
Kandybowicz, Jason. 2007. On fusion and multiple copy spell-out: The case of
verbal repetition. In Corver & Nunes (2007), pp. 119–150. [See page 133.]
Kandybowicz, Jason. 2008. The grammar of repetition: Nupe grammar at the syntax-
phonology interface. Philadelphia: John Benjamins. [See page 133.]
Kaplan, David. 1989. Demonstratives. In Joseph Almog, John Perry, & Howard
Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan, pp. 481–563. Oxford: Oxford University
Press. [See pages 1, 17.]
364
Katzir, Roni. 2011. Morphosemantic mismatches, structural economy, and licens-
ing. Linguistic Inquiry 42, 45–82. [See pages 209, 223.]
Kayne, Richard. 1991. Romance clitics, verb movement, and PRO. Linguistic
Inquiry 22, 647–686. [See page 245.]
Kayne, Richard S. 1994. The antisymmetry of syntax. Cambridge: MIT Press. [See
pages 45, 66, 98, 99, 110, 115, 119, 133, 220, 230.]
Kayne, Richard S. 2002. Pronouns and their antecedents. In Epstein & Seely
(2002), pp. 133–166. [See pages 131, 137.]
Kayne, Richard S. 2008. Expletives, datives, and the tension between morphology
and syntax. In Theresa Biberauer (Ed.), The limits of syntactic variation, pp.
175–217. John Benjamins. [See page 232.]
Kelepir, Meltem. 2001. Topics in Turkish syntax: Clausal structure and scope. Ph.D.
thesis, MIT. [See pages 103, 149.]
365
Kennedy, Christopher. 2014. Predicates and formulas: Evidence from ellipsis. In
Crnič & Sauerland (2014), pp. 253–277. [See pages 2, 12, 29, 35, 36, 138.]
Kenstowicz, Michael (Ed.). 2001. Ken Hale: A life in language. Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT Press. [See pages 343, 362, 382.]
Kim, Ji-yung, Yury A. Lander, & Barbara H. Partee (Eds.). 2004. Possessives and
beyond: Semantics and syntax. Amherst: GLSA. [See pages 119, 367.]
Klein, Wolfgang. 1994. Time in language. London: Routledge. [See page 218.]
Kobele, Greg. 2010. Inverse linking via function composition. Natural Language
Semantics 18, 183–196. [See pages 2, 19, 25, 29, 35, 141, 142.]
Kolodny, Niko & John MacFarlane. 2010. Ifs and oughts. Journal of Philosophy
pp. 115–143. [See pages 239, 263, 265.]
366
Koopman, Hilda. 1984. The syntax of verbs: From verb movement rules in the Kru
languages to Universal Grammar. Dordrecht: Foris. [See page 32.]
Koopman, Hilda. 2003. Inside the “noun” in Maasai. In Anoop Mahajan (Ed.),
Head movement and syntactic theory, pp. 77–116. UCLA Working Papers in Lin-
guistics. [See pages 72, 98, 99, 110.]
Koopman, Hilda. 2005. On the parallelism of DPs and clauses: Evidence from
Kisongo Maasai. In Andrew Carnie, Heidi Harley, & Sheila Ann Dooley
(Eds.), Verb first: On the syntax of verb-initial languages, pp. 281–302. Amsterdam:
John Benjamins. [See pages 72, 98, 99, 110.]
Koopman, Hilda & Dominique Sportiche. 1989. Pronouns, logical variables, and
logophoricity in Abe. Linguistic Inquiry 20, 555–588. [See page 32.]
van Koppen, Marjo. 2007. Agreement with (the internal structure of) copies of
movement. In Corver & Nunes (2007), pp. 327–350. [See pages 84, 301.]
Kotek, Hadas. 2014. Composing questions. Ph.D. thesis, MIT. [See pages 282, 289.]
Kratzer, Angelika. 1977. What ‘must’ and ‘can’ must and can mean. Linguistics
and Philosophy 1, 337–355. [See page 34.]
367
Kratzer, Angelika. 1991. Modality/Conditionals. In Arnim von Stechow & Di-
eter Wunderlich (Eds.), Semantics: An international handbook of contemporary
research, pp. 639–656. New York: de Gruyter. [See pages 239, 240, 258.]
Kratzer, Angelika. 1996. Severing the external argument from its verb. In Johan
Rooryck & Laurie Zaring (Eds.), Phrase structure and the lexicon, pp. 109–137.
Dordrecht: Kluwer. [See pages 108, 152, 214, 216, 219.]
Kratzer, Angelika. 2004. Telicity and the meaning of objective case. In Guéron
& Lecarme (2004), pp. 389–424. [See pages 22, 184.]
Kratzer, Angelika. 2009. Making a pronoun: Fake indexicals as windows into the
properties of pronouns. Linguistic Inquiry 40, 187–237. [See pages 17, 78, 82, 134,
135, 177, 178, 180, 184, 288, 298, 302.]
Kratzer, Angelika. 2013. Modality for the 21st century. In Stephen R. Ander-
son, Jacques Moeschler, & Fabienne Reboul (Eds.), The language-cognition
interface: Proceedings of the 19th International Congress of Linguists, pp. 179–199.
Geneva: Librairie Droz. [See page 32.]
368
Krifka, Manfred. 1992. Thematic relations as links between nominal reference
and temporal constitution. In Ivan A. Sag & Anna Szabolcsi (Eds.), Lexical
matters, pp. 29–53. Chicago: Chicago University Press. [See page 217.]
Kripke, Saul. 1979. A puzzle about belief. In Avishai Margalit (Ed.), Meaning
and use, pp. 239–283. Dordrecht: Reidel. [See pages 51, 57.]
Kripke, Saul. 1980. Naming and necessity. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press. [See page 51.]
Larson, Richard & Sungeun Cho. 2003. Temporal adjectives and the structure of
possessive DPs. Natural Language Semantics 11, 217–247. [See pages 115, 225.]
369
Larson, Richard K. 2014. On shell structure. New York: Routledge. [See pages 72,
99, 233.]
Lasnik, Howard. 1989. Essays on anaphora. Boston: Kluwer. [See pages 61, 134.]
Law, Paul. 1999. On the passive existential construction. Studia Linguistica 53,
183–206. [See page 230.]
Law, Paul. 2011. Some syntactic and semantic properties of the existential construc-
tion in Malagasy. Lingua 121, 1588–1630. [See pages 98, 169, 171, 223, 229.]
Law, Paul. 2014. A unified theory of relative clauses. In Jong-un Park & Il-Jae Lee
(Eds.), SICOGG 16, pp. 203–221. Seoul: The Korean Generative Grammar Circle.
[See pages 190, 207.]
Lecarme, Jacqueline. 1996. Tense in the nominal system: The Somali DP. In
Jacqueline Lecarme, Jean Lowenstamm, & Ur Shlonsky (Eds.), Studies in
Afroasiatic grammar, pp. 159–178. The Hague: Holland Academic Graphics. [See
pages 31, 72, 84, 101, 103, 106, 108, 123, 127, 129, 175.]
370
Lecarme, Jacqueline. 2008. Tense and modality in nominals. In Jacque-
line Guéron & Jacqueline Lecarme (Eds.), Time and modality, pp. 195–226.
Springer. [See pages 72, 84, 85, 98, 101, 103, 104, 108, 111, 124, 152, 175, 241, 246, 298,
299, 318.]
Lecarme, Jacqueline. 2012. Nominal tense. In Robert I. Binnick (Ed.), The Oxford
handbook of tense and aspect, pp. 696–718. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See
pages 85, 99, 133, 299.]
Leckie, Gail. 2013. The double life of names. Philosophical Studies 165, 1139–1160.
[See page 188.]
Lees, Robert B. 1960. The grammar of English nominalization. The Hague: Mouton.
[See pages 66, 67, 96, 189.]
Legate, Julie Anne. 2003. Some interface properties of the phase. Linguistic Inquiry
34, 506–516. [See pages 217, 233, 236.]
Leu, Thomas. 2008. The internal syntax of determiners. Ph.D. thesis, New York
University. [See page 133.]
Levinson, Lisa. 2007. The roots of verbs. Ph.D. thesis, New York University. [See
pages 150, 152, 214, 215, 216, 227, 233, 235, 236.]
371
Lewis, David. 1979. Attitudes de dicto and de se. Philosophical Review 88, 513–543.
[See page 69.]
Lewis, David. 1980. Index, context, and content. In Stig Kanger & Helle Ohman
(Eds.), Philosophy and grammar, pp. 79–100. Holland: D. Reidel. [See pages 1,
13, 286.]
Lewis, David. 1986. On the Plurality of Worlds. Oxford: Blackwell. [See page 57.]
Li, Yen-Hui Audrey. 1992. Indefinite wh in Chinese. Journal of East Asian Linguistics
1, 125–155. [See page 286.]
Lichtenberk, Frantisek, Jyotsna Vaid, & Hsin-Chin Chen. 2011. On the inter-
pretation of alienable vs. inalienable possession: A psycholinguistic investigation.
Cognitive Linguistics 22, 659–689. [See pages 112, 128.]
Lidz, Jeffrey & William J. Idsardi. 1998. Chains and phono-logical form.
In Alexis Dimitriadis, Hikyoung Lee, Christine Moisset, & Alexander
Williams (Eds.), University of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics, vol. 5.1,
pp. 109–125. University of Pennsylvania. [See page 133.]
372
Link, Godehard. 1983. The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms: A lattice-
theoretical approach. In Paul Portner & Barbara H. Partee (Eds.), Formal
semantics: The essential readings, pp. 127–146. Malden: Blackwell. [See pages 91,
152, 205, 243.]
Lipták, Anikó & Georges Rebuschi. 2009. Types and distribution of Northern
Basque correlatives. In Nguyen Chi Duy Khuong Richa & Samar Sinha (Eds.),
The 5th Asian GLOW: Conference proceedings, pp. 194–218. New Delhi: FOSSSIL.
[See page 256.]
Lycan, William. 2001. Real conditionals. New York: Oxford University Press. [See
page 241.]
373
Lynch, John. 1973. Verbal aspects of possession in Melanesian languages. Oceanic
Linguistics 12, 69–102. [See pages 113, 115, 126.]
MacFarlane, John. 2014. Assessment sensitivity: Relative truth and its applications.
Oxford: Clarendon Press. [See pages 12, 286.]
Maienborn, Claudia, Klaus von Heusinger, & Paul Portner (Eds.). 2011.
Semantics: An international handbook of natural language meaning An interna-
tional handbook of natural language meaning. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. [See
pages 376, 392.]
Marantz, Alec. 1997. No escape from syntax: Don’t try morphological analysis in
the privacy of your own lexicon. In Alexis Dimitriadis, Laura Siegel, Clarissa
Surek-Clark, & Alexander Williams (Eds.), University of Pennsylvania Working
Papers in Linguistics, vol. 4.2, pp. 201–225. University of Pennsylvania. [See
pages 128, 150, 181, 214, 225.]
374
Marantz, Alec. 2005. Objects out of the lexicon! Argument-structure in the syntax.
Handout, MIT. [See page 235.]
375
May, Robert. 1977. The grammar of quantification. Ph.D. thesis, MIT. [See page 22.]
May, Robert. 1985. Logical form. Cambridge: MIT Press. [See pages 22, 36, 131, 141,
144, 292.]
McCloskey, James. 2014. Irish existentials in context. Syntax 17, 343–384. [See
pages 169, 171, 221, 222, 223, 224, 228, 229, 232.]
McGinnis, Martha. 2003. Lethal ambiguity. Linguistic Inquiry 35, 47–95. [See
pages 179, 233.]
McNeill, David. 1970. The acquisition of language. New York: Harper & Row. [See
page 88.]
376
Merlan, Francesca. 1982. Mangarayi. Amsterdam: North-Holland. [See page 114.]
Mikkelsen, Line. 2011. Copular clauses. In Maienborn et al. (2011), pp. 1805–
1829. [See page 151.]
Milsark, Gary. 1974. Existential sentences in English. Ph.D. thesis, MIT. [See
pages 149, 168, 171, 228, 229, 230.]
Moro, Andrea. 1997. The raising of predicates: Noun phrases and the theory of clause
structure. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [See pages 169, 223.]
Moro, Andrea. 2017. Copular sentences. In Everaert & van Riemsdijk (2017).
[See pages 151, 232.]
Mortensen, David. 2003. Two kinds of variable elements in Hmong anaphora. MS,
University of California–Berkley. [See pages 4, 61, 88, 132, 133, 134, 286, 298.]
Mosel, Ulrike. 1984. Tolai syntax and its historical development. Canberra: Pacific
Linguistics. [See pages 114, 124, 125, 128, 222, 223, 232.]
Moulton, Keir. 2015. CPs: Copies and compositionality. Linguistic Inquiry 46,
305–342. [See pages 22, 31, 32, 68, 70, 214, 218.]
Musan, Renate. 1995. On the temporal interpretation of noun phrases. Ph.D. thesis,
MIT. [See pages 174, 175, 188, 318.]
Myler, Neil. 2016. Building and interpreting possession sentences. Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT Press. [See pages 124, 230, 232.]
Nasu, Norio. 2010. Conditions on copy realization. English Linguistics 27, 126–158.
[See page 133.]
377
Nichols, Johanna. 1988. On alienable and inalienable possession. In William
Shipley (Ed.), In honor of Mary Haas, pp. 557–609. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
[See pages 114, 123, 124, 128.]
Nichols, Johanna. 1992. Linguistic diversity in space and time. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press. [See pages 114, 123, 124.]
Nikiforidou, Kiki. 1991. The meanings of the genitive: A case study in semantic
structure and semantic change. Cognitive Linguistics 2, 149–206. [See page 128.]
Nissenbaum, Jon. 2001. The investigations of covert phrasal movement. Ph.D. thesis,
MIT. [See pages 37, 179.]
Noguchi, Tohru. 1997. Two types of pronouns and variable binding. Language 73,
770–797. [See pages 82, 86, 87.]
Nyvad, Anne Mette, Ken Ramshøj Christensen, & Sten Vikner. 2017. CP-
recursion in Danish: A cP/CP-analysis. The Linguistic Review 34, 449–477. [See
page 255.]
378
Onishi, Masayuki. 2000. Transitivity and valency-changing derivations in Motuna.
In R.M.W. Dixon & Alexandra Y. Aikhenvald (Eds.), Changing valency: Case
studies in transitivity, pp. 115–144. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [See
page 220.]
Özyıldız, Deniz & Rodica Ivan. 2017. The Somali microscope: Personal pronouns,
determiners and possession. In Vera Hohaus & Wanda Rothe (Eds.), Fieldwork
perspectives on the semantics of African, Asian and Austronesian languages 3, pp.
56–69. Universität Tübingen. [See pages 85, 299.]
Palmer, F.R. 2001. Mood and modality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2nd edn. [See page 246.]
Panagiotidis, Phoevos. 2002. Pronouns, clitics and empty nouns. Amsterdam: John
Benjamins. [See page 82.]
Partee, Barbara H. 1973. Some structural analogies between tenses and pronouns
in English. In Partee (2004), pp. 50–58. [See page 1.]
Partee, Barbara H. 1978. Bound variables and other anaphors. In Partee (2004),
pp. 110–121. [See page 112.]
Partee, Barbara H. 1983. Genitives: A case study. In Partee (2004), pp. 182–189.
[See pages 107, 112, 117, 141.]
379
Partee, Barbara H. 1984a. Compositionality. In Partee (2004), pp. 153–181. [See
page 3.]
Partee, Barbara H. 1989b. Many quantifiers. In Partee (2004), pp. 241–258. [See
pages 157, 160, 173.]
Partee, Barbara H. & Mats Rooth. 1983. Generalized conjunction and type
ambiguity. In Rainer Bäuerle, Christoph Schwarze, & Arnim von Stechow
(Eds.), Meaning, use, and interpretation of language, pp. 361–383. Berlin: de
Gruyter. [See page 98.]
380
Patel-Grosz, Pritty & Patrick Grosz. 2010. On the typology of donkeys: Two
types of anaphora resolution. In Martin Prinzhorn, Viola Schmitt, & Sarah
Zobel (Eds.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 14, pp. 339–355. Vienna: Uni-
versity of Vienna. [See page 84.]
Paul, Ileana, Key Cortes, & Lareina Milambiling. 2015. Definiteness without D:
The case of ang and ng in Tagalog. Canadian Journal of Linguistics 60, 361–390.
[See pages 101, 103, 133.]
Paul, Ileana & Lisa Travis. 2006. Ergativity in Austronesian languages: What
it can do, what it can’t, but not why. In Alana Johns, Diane Massam, &
Juvenal Ndayiragije (Eds.), Ergativity: Emerging issues, pp. 315–335. Dordrecht:
Springer. [See page 106.]
Payne, Doris L. 2009. Is possession mere location? Contrary evidence from Maa.
In McGregor (2009), pp. 107–142. [See pages 128, 171, 225, 231, 232.]
Payne, John & Eva Berlage. 2014. Genitive variation: The niche role of the oblique
genitive. English Language and Linguistics 18, 331–360. [See page 119.]
Percus, Orin & Uli Sauerland. 2003. On the LFs of attitude reports. In Matthias
Weisgerber (Ed.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 7, pp. 228–242. Konstanz:
Universität Konstanz. [See pages 3, 35, 51.]
Pesetsky, David. 1995. Zero syntax: Experiencers and cascades. Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT Press. [See pages 233, 235.]
381
Pesetsky, David. 1998. Some optimality principles of sentence pronunciation. In
Pilar Barbosa, Danny Fox, Paul Hagstrom, Martha McGinnis, & David
Pesetsky (Eds.), Optimality and competition in syntax, pp. 337–383. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press. [See page 137.]
Pesetsky, David. 2000. Phrasal movement and its kin. Cambridge: MIT Press. [See
pages 289, 294.]
Pesetsky, David & Esther Torrego. 2001. T-to-C movement: Causes and conse-
quences. In Kenstowicz (2001), pp. 355–426. [See page 72.]
Peters, Stanley & Dag Westerståhl. 2013. The semantics of possessives. Lan-
guage 89, 713–759. [See page 123.]
Portner, Paul. 1998. The progressive in modal semantics. Language 74, 760–787.
[See pages 235, 236.]
382
Pylkkänen, Liina. 2000. What applicative heads apply to. In Elsi Kaiser,
Michelle Minnick Fox, & Alexander Williams (Eds.), University of Pennsylva-
nia Working Papers in Linguistics, vol. 7.1, pp. 197–210. University of Pennsylva-
nia. [See page 233.]
Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1960. Word and object. Cambridge: MIT Press. [See
page 65.]
Rackowski, Andrea Stokes. 2002. The structure of Tagalog: Specificity, voice, and
the distribution of arguments. Ph.D. thesis, MIT. [See pages 108, 150, 152.]
Radford, Andrew. 1997. Syntactic theory and the structure of English: A minimalist
approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [See pages 82, 88, 89.]
Rebuschi, Georges. 2009. Basque correlatives and their kin in the history of
Northern Basque. In Lipták (2009a), pp. 81–129. [See page 265.]
383
Reinhart, Tanya. 1983b. Coreference and bound anaphora: A restatement of
anaphora questions. Linguistics and Philosophy 6, 47–88. [See page 137.]
Reinhart, Tanya. 1987. Specifier and operator binding. In Reuland & ter Meulen
(1987), pp. 130–167. [See pages 139, 147.]
Reinhart, Tanya. 1997. Quantifier scope: How labor is divided between QR and
choice functions. Linguistics and Philosophy 20, 335–397. [See pages 78, 81.]
Reuland, Eric. 2001. Primitives of binding. Linguistic Inquiry 32, 439–492. [See
pages 135, 137.]
Reuland, Eric & Jan Koster. 1991. Long-distance anaphora: An overview. In Jan
Koster & Eric Reuland (Eds.), Long-distance anaphora, pp. 1–26. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press. [See page 135.]
Reuland, Eric J. & Alice G.B. ter Meulen (Eds.). 1987. The representation of
(in)definiteness. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. [See pages 344, 360, 365, 381,
383, 395.]
Rijkhoff, Jan. 2002. The noun phrase. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See
pages 72, 150, 215.]
Rijkhoff, Jan. 2008. Synchronic and diachronic evidence for parallels between
noun phrases and sentences. In Folke Josephson & Ingmar Söhrman (Eds.),
Interdependence of diachronic and synchronic analyses, pp. 13–42. Amsterdam:
John Benjamins. [See page 72.]
384
van Rijn, Marlou. 2017. The expression of modifiers and arguments in the noun
phrase and beyond: A typological study. Ph.D. thesis, University of Amsterdam.
[See pages 112, 113, 114, 117, 118, 123, 124, 125.]
Rizzi, Luigi. 1990. Relativized Minimality. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. [See
page 177.]
Rizzi, Luigi. 1997. The fine structure of the left periphery. In Liliane Haege-
man (Ed.), Elements of grammar: Handbook of generative syntax, pp. 281–337.
Dordrecht: Kluwer. [See pages 30, 39.]
Rizzi, Luigi. 2001. Extraction from weak islands, reconstruction, and agreement. In
Gennaro Chierchia (Ed.), Semantic interfaces: Reference, anaphora, aspect, pp.
155–176. Stanford: CSLI Publications. [See page 295.]
Roberts, Ian. 2001. Head movement. In Baltin & Collins (2001), pp. 113–147.
[See page 30.]
385
Rullmann, Hotze. 2003. Bound-variable pronouns and the semantics of number.
In Brian Agbayani, Paivi Koskinen, & Vida Samiian (Eds.), Proceedings of the
Western Conference on Linguistics, WECOL 2002, pp. 243–254. Department of
Linguistics, California State University, Fresno. [See page 82.]
Rullmann, Hotze. 2004. First and second person pronouns as bound variables.
Linguistic Inquiry 35, 159–168. [See page 17.]
Rullmann, Hotze & Sigrid Beck. 1998. Presupposition projection and the in-
terpretation of which-questions. In Devon Strolovitch & Aaron Lawson
(Eds.), Semantics and Linguistic Theory (SALT) 8, pp. 215–232. Ithaca, N.Y.: CLC
Publications. [See pages 103, 289, 294.]
Safir, Ken. 1984. Multiple variable binding. Linguistic Inquiry 15, 603–638. [See
page 147.]
Safir, Ken. 1985. Syntactic chains. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [See
page 169.]
Safir, Ken. 1999. Vehicle change and reconstruction in a-bar chains. Linguistic
Inquiry 30, 587–620. [See pages 71, 147, 300.]
Safir, Ken. 2004. The syntax of (in)dependence. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. [See
pages 139, 147.]
Safir, Ken. 2017. Weak crossover. In Everaert & van Riemsdijk (2017). [See
page 301.]
Salmon, Nathan. 1986. Frege’s puzzle. Cambridge: MIT Press. [See page 51.]
386
Santorio, Paolo. 2010. Modals are monsters: On indexical shift in English. In Nan
Li & David Lutz (Eds.), Proceedings of SALT 20, pp. 289–308. Ithaca, N.Y.: CLC
Publications. [See pages 3, 12, 14, 15, 35, 51.]
Santorio, Paolo. 2012. Reference and monstrosity. Philosophical Review 121, 359–
406. [See pages 3, 14, 35, 239, 251, 255, 305.]
Satık, Deniz. 2017. The little nP hypothesis. In Andrew Alexander Monti (Ed.),
Proceedings of the 2017 annual conference of the Canadian Linguistics Association,
pp. 1–15. CLA. [See page 108.]
Sauerland, Uli. 1998. The meaning of chains. Ph.D. thesis, MIT. [See pages 22, 66,
67, 95, 189.]
Schlenker, Philippe. 2003. A plea for monsters. Linguistics and Philosophy 26,
29–120. [See pages 1, 19, 35.]
387
Schlenker, Philippe. 2005. Minimize Restrictors! (Notes on definite descriptions,
Condition C and epithets). In Emar Maier, Corien Bary, & Janneke Huitink
(Eds.), Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung 9, pp. 385–416. Nijmegen: Nijmegen
Center for Semantics. [See pages 60, 135, 137.]
Schlenker, Philippe. 2009. Local contexts. Semantics and Pragmatics 2, 1–78. [See
page 3.]
Schwarz, Anne. 2016. All-in-one and one-for-all: Thetic structures in Buli grammar
and discourse. In Doris L. Payne, Sara Pacchiarotti, & Mokaya Bosire (Eds.),
Diversity in African languages, pp. 81–100. Berlin: Language Science Press. [See
page 89.]
Schwarz, Florian. 2009. Two types of definites in natural language. Ph.D. thesis,
University of Massachusetts, Amherst. [See pages 89, 104, 108.]
Sells, Peter. 1987. Binding resumptive pronouns. Linguistics and Philosophy 10,
261–298. [See page 208.]
388
Showalter, Catherine. 1986. Pronouns in Lyele. In Ursula Wiesemann (Ed.),
Pronominal systems, pp. 205–216. Tübingen: Günter Narr. [See page 287.]
Silk, Alex. 2014b. Evidence sensitivity in weak necessity deontic modals. Journal
of Philosophical Logic 43, 691–723. [See pages 263, 265.]
Silk, Alex. 2016b. The progressive and verbs of creation. Journal of Semantics 33,
19–48. [See pages 235, 236.]
Silk, Alex. 2016c. Update semantics for weak necessity modals. In Deontic
logic and normative systems (DEON 2016), pp. 237–255. Milton Keynes: College
Publications. URL https://goo.gl/MwB6qm. [See page 263.]
Silk, Alex. 2017. How to embed an epistemic modal: Attitude problems and other
defects of character. Philosophical Studies 174, 1773–1799. [See pages 3, 11, 28,
49, 50, 54, 188, 305.]
Silk, Alex. 2018. Commitment and states of mind with mood and modality. Natural
Language Semantics 26, 125–166. [See pages 32, 35.]
Siloni, Tal. 1997. Noun phrases and nominalizations: The syntax of DPs. Dordrecht:
Kluwer. [See pages 72, 100, 119.]
Soames, Scott. 2002. The unfinished semantic agenda of Naming and Necessity.
Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See page 51.]
Song, Jae Jung. 1997. The history of Micronesian possessive classifiers and bene-
factive marking in Oceanic languages. Oceanic Linguistics 36, 29–64. [See
pages 113, 114.]
389
Sportiche, Dominique. 2006. Reconstruction, binding, and scope. In Everaert &
van Riemsdijk (2006), pp. 35–93. [See pages 71, 270, 277, 292.]
Stalnaker, Robert. 2014. Context. New York: Oxford University Press. [See
pages 2, 41, 286.]
Stanley, Jason. 1997. Names and rigid designation. In Bob Hale & Crispin
Wright (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of language, pp. 555–585. Oxford:
Blackwell. [See page 286.]
Stanley, Jason. 2002. Nominal restriction. In Gerhard Preyer & Georg Peter
(Eds.), Logical form and language, pp. 365–388. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
[See pages 13, 41.]
Stanley, Jason. 2005. Knowledge and practical interests. Oxford: Oxford University
Press. [See page 14.]
Stanley, Jason & Zoltán Gendler Szabó. 2000. On quantifier domain restriction.
Mind and Language 15, 219–261. [See pages 13, 41.]
Starr, William. 2010. Conditionals, meaning, and mood. Ph.d. thesis, Rutgers
University. [See page 305.]
390
Stassen, Leon. 2009. Predicative possession. Oxford: Oxford University Press. [See
page 232.]
Stebbins, Tonya N. 2009. The semantics of clause linking in Mali. In Dixon &
Aikhenvald (2009), pp. 356–379. [See page 243.]
von Stechow, Arnim. 2003. Feature deletion under semantic binding: Tense, per-
son, and mood under verbal quantifiers. Proceedings of the North East Linguistics
Society 33, 397–403. [See pages 82, 124.]
von Stechow, Arnim. 2008. Tense, modals, and attitudes as verbal quantifiers.
Paper presented at ESSLLI 2008. [See pages 10, 31.]
Stolz, Thomas, Sonja Kettler, Cornelia Stroh, & Aina Urdze (Eds.). 2008.
Split possession: An areal-linguistic study of the alienability correlation and related
phenomena in the languages of Europe. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. [See
page 114.]
Stone, Matthew. 1997. The anaphoric parallel between modality and tense. IRCS
TR 97-06, University of Pennsylvania. [See page 72.]
391
Sudo, Yasutada. 2012. On the semantics of phi features on pronouns. Ph.D. thesis,
MIT. [See pages 3, 82.]
Svenonius, Peter. 2004. On the edge. In Adger et al. (2004), pp. 259–288. [See
pages 72, 100, 177, 178.]
Swanson, Eric. 2010. On scope relations between quantifiers and epistemic modals.
Journal of Semantics 27, 529–540. [See page 261.]
Szabolcsi, Anna. 1983. The possessor that ran away from home. The Linguistic
Review 3, 89–102. [See pages 107, 117, 119, 220.]
Szabolcsi, Anna. 1986. From the definiteness effect to lexical integrity. In Werner
Abraham & Sjaak de Meij (Eds.), Topic, focus, and configurationality, pp. 321–
350. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. [See page 232.]
Szabolcsi, Anna. 1994. The noun phrase. In Ferenc Kiefer & Katalin É. Kiss
(Eds.), Syntax and semantics 27: The syntactic structure of Hungarian, pp. 179–274.
New York: Academic Press. [See pages 72, 103, 107, 220.]
392
Takahashi, Shoichi. 2010. Traces or copies, or both — Parts I and II. Language and
Linguistics Compass 4, 1091–1115. [See page 22.]
Tanaka, Misako. 2015. Scoping out of adjuncts: Evidence for the parallelism between
QR and wh-movement. Ph.D. thesis, University College London. [See pages 37,
179, 300.]
Taylor, John R. 1989. Possessive genitives in English. Linguistics 27, 663–686. [See
pages 119, 128.]
Tellier, Christine. 1991. Licensing theory and French parasitic gaps. Dordrecht:
Kluwer. [See pages 72, 117, 119, 232.]
Thurgood, Graham & Randy J. LaPolla (Eds.). 2017. The Sino-Tibetan languages.
London: Routledge, 2nd edn. [See pages 86, 106, 118, 190, 286, 297, 299.]
Ticio, M. Emma. 2005. Locality and anti-locality in Spanish DPs. Syntax 8, 229–285.
[See page 72.]
Tonhauser, Judith, David Beaver, Craige Roberts, & Mandy Simons. 2013.
Towards a taxonomy of projective content. Language 89, 66–109. [See page 49.]
Trutkowsky, Ewa & Helmut Weiß. 2016. When personal pronouns compete with
relative pronouns. In Grosz & Patel-Grosz (2016), pp. 135–166. [See page 86.]
Tănase-Dogaru, Mihaela. 2007. The category of number: Its relevance for the
syntax and the semantic typology of the nominal group. Ph.D. thesis, University
of Bucharest. [See pages 133, 150.]
393
Uriagereka, Juan. 2002a. Derivations: Exploring the dynamics of syntax. London:
Routledge. [See pages 362, 393.]
Uriagereka, Juan. 2002b. From being to having: Questions about ontology from a
Kayne/Szabolcsi syntax. In Uriagereka (2002a), pp. 192–211. [See page 225.]
Vergnaud, Jean-Roger & Maria Luisa Zubizarreta. 1992. The definite deter-
miner and inalienable construction in French and English. Linguistic Inquiry 23,
595–652. [See page 137.]
Vikner, Carl & Per Anker Jensen. 2002. A semantic analysis of the English
genitive: Interaction of lexical and formal semantics. Studia Linguistica 56, 191–
226. [See page 117.]
Vikner, Sten. 1995. Verb movement and expletive subjects in the Germanic languages.
New York: Oxford University Press. [See page 255.]
de Vries, Lourens. 1993. Forms and functions in Kombai, an Awyu language of Irian
Jaya. Canberra: Australian National University. [See page 190.]
de Vries, Mark. 2005. The fall and rise of universals on relativization. Journal of
Universal Language 6, 125–157. [See page 207.]
Wang, Yong & Jie Xu. 2013. A systemic typology of existential and possessive
constructions. Functions of language 20, 1–30. [See page 232.]
Ward, Gregory & Betty Birner. 1995. Definiteness and the English existential.
Language 71, 722–742. [See page 171.]
394
Ward, Gregory, Richard Sproat, & Gail McKoon. 1991. A pragmatic analysis
of so-called anaphoric islands. Language 67, 439–473. [See page 84.]
Webelhuth, Gert (Ed.). 1995. Government and binding theory and the minimalist
program: Principles and parameters in syntactic theory. Oxford: Blackwell. [See
page 72.]
Williams, Edwin. 1980. Predication. Linguistic Inquiry 11, 203–238. [See page 78.]
Williams, Edwin. 1997. Blocking and anaphora. Linguistic Inquiry 28, 577–628.
[See page 137.]
Wiltschko, Martina. 2016. Fake form and what it tells us about the relation
between form and interpretation. In Grosz & Patel-Grosz (2016), pp. 13–52.
[See pages 4, 82.]
395
Wood, Jim & Alec Marantz. 2017. The interpretation of external arguments. In
D'Alessandro et al. (2017), pp. 255–278. [See pages 108, 152, 216, 223, 229.]
Wurmbrand, Susanne. 2018. The cost of raising quantifiers. Glossa 3, 1–40. [See
page 136.]
Wurmbrand, Susi & Koji Shimamura. 2017. The features of the voice domain:
Actives, passives, and restructuring. In D'Alessandro et al. (2017), pp. 179–
204. [See page 217.]
Yalcin, Seth. 2007. Epistemic modals. Mind 116, 983–1026. [See page 12.]
Zamparelli, Roberto. 2000. Layers in the determiner phrase. New York: Garland
Publishing. [See pages 100, 103, 106, 109, 129, 133, 148, 149, 157.]
Zeshan, Ulrike & Pamela Perniss (Eds.). 2008. Possessive and existential construc-
tions in Sign Languages. Nijmegan: Ishara Press. [See pages 225, 230.]
396
Zucchi, Allesandro. 1995. The ingredients of definiteness and the definiteness
effect. Natural Language Semantics 3, 33–78. [See pages 168, 229.]
397