Issues With Translating Conditionals: "If A Then B": "If I Shoot You With This Gun, You Will Die"
Issues With Translating Conditionals: "If A Then B": "If I Shoot You With This Gun, You Will Die"
“If A then B” is FALSE when the antecedent “A” is true and the consequent
“B” is false; for all other combinations of truth values, the conditional is
TRUE.
the only scenario in which this statement is FALSE is the case where I shoot
you with this gun but you don’t die, i.e. the case where the antecedent is true
but the consequent is false.
Now, here’s the odd bit: for all other assignments of truth values, the
logical conditional is assigned the value true.
That includes cases where the antecedent is false. On this definition of the
conditional, BOTH of the following statements are TRUE:
(1) “If I don’t shoot you with this gun, you will die.”
(2) “If I don’t shoot you with this gun, you won’t die.”
Most of us, looking at these two statements, will wonder how either of these
follows from the original conditional claim. It’s not like we have strong
intuitions the other way. It’s just … we don’t know why we should feel any
particular way about them.
So, right off the bat, we can say that there is a mismatch between the
semantics of the logical conditional as defined in propositional logic, and our
intuitions about natural language conditionals.
A→B
A⊃B
It’s a standard logic exercise to write the truth tables for these expressions to
demonstrate that they are indeed logically equivalent.
Now, the question that thousands of logic students have asked their logic
instructors, and hundreds of philosophers and logicians have written about, is
this:
If you push this question deeply enough it opens up vast areas of research in
analytic philosophy.
I’ll give you a little tour of the issues, but I can’t possibly do the topic justice.
A little tour is enough to appreciate the general point, which is that there are
many uses of “if-then” in natural language that are well described by the
material conditional, and there are many other uses that are not.
In English there are at least two different kinds of conditional. Consider the
following part of English conditionals:
(1) “If humans did not build Stonehenge, then nonhumans did.”
(2) “If humans had not built Stonehenge, then nonhumans would have.”
Conditional (2) seems clearly false. There is no reason to think, for example,
that if humans had not built Stonehenge, then aliens would have.
But if one is true and the other is false, then the conditional connective
cannot be the same in both cases.
(4) “If the roof leaked last night, there will be water on the kitchen
floor.”
(6) “If the roof had leaked last night, there would be water on the kitchen
floor.”
Consider the claim “if you had put your sandwich down, a dog would
have eaten it.”
But in a situation in which you ate your sandwich quickly, without putting it
down, but there are no hungry dogs present, both components are again false,
but the counterfactual conditional is false.
But even the claim that the indicative conditional is correctly translated as A
→ B is controversial in logic and philosophy.
On the one hand, one can argue that if the indicative conditional is truth
functional at all, it has to be the material conditional, since no other truth
table is a serious candidate.
And there are arguments that the semantics of the indicative conditional
really does follow the truth table rules.
Consider this conditional statement: “if it rains, then the match will be
cancelled”. It seems clear that this implies that “either it will not rain, or it
will rain and the match will be cancelled”. But this statement is true if and
only if either “it will rain” is false or “the match will be cancelled” is true.
That is, if and only if the material conditional is true.
If we’re following the truth table for the material conditional, all of these are
TRUE statements. Yet they don’t strike us as true, at least at first glance.
The problem seems to arise from the fact that in each case the antecedent has
nothing to do with the consequent: believing the antecedent is true gives us
no reason to think that the consequent is true.
One might conclude that for an indicative conditional to be true, there must
be some connection between the antecedent and the consequent, such that the
truth of the former is relevant to the truth of the latter.
If we pursue this line of thought, we’ll be lead to the conclusion that the
indicative conditional is not truth functional — whether “if A then B” is true
will depend not just on whether A and B are true or false, but also on what
they actually say, and in particular, on whether there is the right kind of
connection between what A says and what B says.
The alternative is to defend the view that indicative conditionals have the
same truth conditions as material conditionals. How? By demonstrating how
the problematic examples only seem to get the semantics wrong. There are
several well known defenses of this view in the literature but I won’t bother
to go into them here.
However, we should note that when we’re using conditional argument forms
like modus ponens and modus tollens in argument analysis, we’re assuming
that the conditional follows the logic of the material conditional. Otherwise
the following argument forms would not be valid:
1. If A then B
2. A
Therefore, B (modus ponens)
1. If A then B
2. Not-B
Therefore, not-A (modus tollens)