0% found this document useful (0 votes)
31 views8 pages

Issues With Translating Conditionals: "If A Then B": "If I Shoot You With This Gun, You Will Die"

The document discusses issues with translating natural language conditionals into propositional logic. It notes that the English expression "if A then B" is used in various ways that do not always map onto the logical conditional. Specifically, counterfactual conditionals (e.g. "if humans had built Stonehenge") cannot be translated as the material conditional because they are not truth functional. Meanwhile, the translation of indicative conditionals (e.g. "if it rains tonight") as the material conditional is controversial because some conditionals that are logically true seem intuitively false.

Uploaded by

Mohd
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
31 views8 pages

Issues With Translating Conditionals: "If A Then B": "If I Shoot You With This Gun, You Will Die"

The document discusses issues with translating natural language conditionals into propositional logic. It notes that the English expression "if A then B" is used in various ways that do not always map onto the logical conditional. Specifically, counterfactual conditionals (e.g. "if humans had built Stonehenge") cannot be translated as the material conditional because they are not truth functional. Meanwhile, the translation of indicative conditionals (e.g. "if it rains tonight") as the material conditional is controversial because some conditionals that are logically true seem intuitively false.

Uploaded by

Mohd
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 8

Issues With Translating Conditionals: "If A then B"

The most notorious mismatches between the meaning of a logical connective


and the meaning of its natural language counterpart are found with
conditional statements. The English language expression “if A then B” is
used in a variety of ways, and not all of them map onto the meaning of the
conditional as defined in propositional logic.

In the lecture on the logic of conditional statements I said that a conditional


is any statement that is logically equivalent to a statement of the form “If A
then B”, and I defined the truth conditions for such statements as follows:

“If A then B” is FALSE when the antecedent “A” is true and the consequent
“B” is false; for all other combinations of truth values, the conditional is
TRUE.

So, for example, given the conditional statement

“If I shoot you with this gun, you will die”

the only scenario in which this statement is FALSE is the case where I shoot
you with this gun but you don’t die, i.e. the case where the antecedent is true
but the consequent is false.

Now, here’s the odd bit: for all other assignments of truth values, the
logical conditional is assigned the value true.

That includes cases where the antecedent is false. On this definition of the
conditional, BOTH of the following statements are TRUE:
(1) “If I don’t shoot you with this gun, you will die.”

(2) “If I don’t shoot you with this gun, you won’t die.”

Most of us, looking at these two statements, will wonder how either of these
follows from the original conditional claim. It’s not like we have strong
intuitions the other way. It’s just … we don’t know why we should feel any
particular way about them.

So, right off the bat, we can say that there is a mismatch between the
semantics of the logical conditional as defined in propositional logic, and our
intuitions about natural language conditionals.

To talk about this further, let’s clarify our language a bit.

The logical conditional, the conditional as defined by the truth table


definition in propositional logic, is known as the MATERIAL
CONDITIONAL.

The material conditional is what is represented by the various conventional


symbolizations used in logic textbooks, usually one of these:

 A→B
 A⊃B

The material conditional, by definition, is false is when A is true and B is


false, and true otherwise.

This interpretation allows us to write various logical equivalents:


(A → B) (“if A is true then B is true”) is logically equivalent to ~(A & ~B)
(“it is not the case that A is true and B is false”).

Also, (A → B) (“if A is true then B is true”) is logically equivalent to (~A ∨


B) (“either A is false or B is true”).

It’s a standard logic exercise to write the truth tables for these expressions to
demonstrate that they are indeed logically equivalent.

Now, the question that thousands of logic students have asked their logic
instructors, and hundreds of philosophers and logicians have written about, is
this:

What is the relationship between the material conditional and


conditional statements expressed in natural language?

If you push this question deeply enough it opens up vast areas of research in
analytic philosophy.

I’ll give you a little tour of the issues, but I can’t possibly do the topic justice.
A little tour is enough to appreciate the general point, which is that there are
many uses of “if-then” in natural language that are well described by the
material conditional, and there are many other uses that are not.

1. Indicative vs Counterfactual Conditionals

In English there are at least two different kinds of conditional. Consider the
following part of English conditionals:

(1) “If humans did not build Stonehenge, then nonhumans did.”
(2) “If humans had not built Stonehenge, then nonhumans would have.”

Conditional (1) seems clearly true.

Conditional (2) seems clearly false. There is no reason to think, for example,
that if humans had not built Stonehenge, then aliens would have.

Yet it is natural to regard each of them as composed of two component


propositions — “humans did not build Stonehenge” and “nonhumans built
Stonehenge” — using a two-place “if-then” connective.

But if one is true and the other is false, then the conditional connective
cannot be the same in both cases.

We call the conditional connective in (1) an indicative conditional. Here are


some other examples of indicative conditionals:

(3) “If it rains tonight, we shall get wet.”

(4) “If the roof leaked last night, there will be water on the kitchen
floor.”

We call the conditional in (2) a subjunctive or counterfactual conditional.


Here are some other examples of counterfactual conditionals:

(5) “If it were to rain tonight, we would get wet.”

(6) “If the roof had leaked last night, there would be water on the kitchen
floor.”

2. Counterfactual Conditionals and the Material Conditional


It is clear that the counterfactual conditional is NOT correctly translated into
propositional logic as the material conditional A → B.

This is because counterfactual conditionals are not truth functional.

Consider the claim “if you had put your sandwich down, a dog would
have eaten it.”

Suppose we regard this statement as a compound made up from the


counterfactual conditional connective and the two propositions “you put your
sandwich down” and “a dog ate your sandwich”.

In a situation in which you ate your sandwich quickly, without putting it


down, while surrounded by hungry dogs, both components are false, and the
counterfactual conditional is true.

But in a situation in which you ate your sandwich quickly, without putting it
down, but there are no hungry dogs present, both components are again false,
but the counterfactual conditional is false.

From this it follows that the counterfactual conditional is not a truth


functional connective. What determines the truth of the counterfactual
conditional isn’t JUST the truth of the component statements. We need to
know MORE than just the truth values of the components in that situation.

To handle the semantics of counterfactual, or subjunctive, conditionals, we


need more machinery than propositional logic gives us. The truth table for the
material conditional won’t do the job.

3. Indicative Conditionals and the Material Conditional


The material conditional connective in propositional logic is intended to
model the semantics of indicative conditionals, not counterfactual
conditionals.

But even the claim that the indicative conditional is correctly translated as A
→ B is controversial in logic and philosophy.

On the one hand, one can argue that if the indicative conditional is truth
functional at all, it has to be the material conditional, since no other truth
table is a serious candidate.

And there are arguments that the semantics of the indicative conditional
really does follow the truth table rules.

Consider this conditional statement: “if it rains, then the match will be
cancelled”. It seems clear that this implies that “either it will not rain, or it
will rain and the match will be cancelled”. But this statement is true if and
only if either “it will rain” is false or “the match will be cancelled” is true.
That is, if and only if the material conditional is true.

So what’s the problem with translating indicative conditionals using →?

Well, recall that the material conditional A → B is true whenever the


antecedent A is false or the consequent B is true (or both). However, the
following conditionals all seem quite wrong, even though the first two have
false antecedents and the last has a true consequent.

(1) “If my cat has fleas, then my cat’s name is Sam.”

(false antecedent, true consequent)


(2) “If my cat has fleas, then the Earth is the largest planet in the solar
system.”

(False antecedent, false consequent)

(3) “If carbon is an element, then the computer I’m typing on is an


iMac.”

(true antecedent, true consequent)

If we’re following the truth table for the material conditional, all of these are
TRUE statements. Yet they don’t strike us as true, at least at first glance.

The problem seems to arise from the fact that in each case the antecedent has
nothing to do with the consequent: believing the antecedent is true gives us
no reason to think that the consequent is true.

One might conclude that for an indicative conditional to be true, there must
be some connection between the antecedent and the consequent, such that the
truth of the former is relevant to the truth of the latter.

If we pursue this line of thought, we’ll be lead to the conclusion that the
indicative conditional is not truth functional — whether “if A then B” is true
will depend not just on whether A and B are true or false, but also on what
they actually say, and in particular, on whether there is the right kind of
connection between what A says and what B says.

The alternative is to defend the view that indicative conditionals have the
same truth conditions as material conditionals. How? By demonstrating how
the problematic examples only seem to get the semantics wrong. There are
several well known defenses of this view in the literature but I won’t bother
to go into them here.

The take-away point of this discussion is that conditional relationships are


expressed in many different ways in natural language, and only some of those
ways are well described by the material conditional of propositional logic.
Counterfactual conditionals clearly do not follow the semantics of the
material conditional. Whether, and what sorts of, indicative conditionals can
be interpreted as material conditionals, is a subject of ongoing debate.

However, we should note that when we’re using conditional argument forms
like modus ponens and modus tollens in argument analysis, we’re assuming
that the conditional follows the logic of the material conditional. Otherwise
the following argument forms would not be valid:

1. If A then B
2. A
Therefore, B (modus ponens)

1. If A then B
2. Not-B
Therefore, not-A (modus tollens)

This is an important point to keep in mind.

You might also like