Syntax and Its Limits PDF
Syntax and Its Limits PDF
OX F O R D S T U D I E S I N T H E O R E T IC A L L I N G U I S T IC S
general editors: David Adger and Hagit Borer, Queen Mary, University of London
advisory editors: Stephen Anderson, Yale University; Daniel Büring, University of California, Los
Angeles; Nomi Erteschik-Shir, Ben-Gurion University; Donka Farkas, University of California, Santa
Cruz; Angelika Kratzer, University of Massachusetts, Amherst; Andrew Nevins, University College
London; Christopher Potts, Stanford University; Barry Schein, University of Southern California;
Peter Svenonius, University of Tromsø; Moira Yip, University College London.
recent titles
Lexical Semantics, Syntax, and Event Structure
edited by Malka Rappaport Hovav, Edit Doron, and Ivy Sichel
About the Speaker
Towards a Syntax of Indexicality
by Alessandra Giorgi
The Sound Patterns of Syntax
edited by Nomi Erteschik-Shir and Lisa Rochman
The Complementizer Phase
edited by E. Phoevos Panagiotidis
Interfaces in Linguistics
New Research Perspectives
edited by Raffaella Folli and Christiane Ulbrich
Negative Indefinites
by Doris Penka
Events, Phrases, and Questions
by Robert Truswell
Dissolving Binding Theory
by Johan Rooryck and Guido Vanden Wyngaerd
The Logic of Pronominal Resumption
by Ash Asudeh
Modals and Conditionals
by Angelika Kratzer
The Theta System
Argument Structure at the Interface
edited by Martin Everaert, Marijana Marelj, and Tal Siloni
Sluicing
Cross-Linguistic Perspective
edited by Jason Merchant and Andrew Simpson
Telicity, Change, and State
A Cross-Categorial View of Event Structure
edited by Violeta Demonte and Louise McNally
Ways of Structure Building
edited by Myriam Uribe-Etxebarria and Vidal Valmala
The Morphology and Phonology of Exponence
edited by Jochen Trommer
Count and Mass Across Languages
edited by Diane Massam
Genericity
edited by Alda Mari, Claire Beyssade, and Fabio Del Prete
Strategies of Quantification
edited by Kook-Hee Gil, Steve Harlow, and George Tsoulas
Nonverbal Predication
Copular Sentences at the Syntax-Semantics Interface
by Isabelle Roy
Diagnosing Syntax
edited by Lisa Lai-Shen Cheng and Norbert Corver
Pseudogapping and Ellipsis
by Kirsten Gengel
Syntax and its Limits
edited by Raffaella Folli, Christina Sevdali, and Robert Truswell
For a complete list of titles published and in preparation for the series, see pp. –.
Syntax and its Limits
Edited by
RAFFAELLA FOLLI, CHRISTINA SEVDALI,
A N D ROBE RT T RU S W E L L
1
3
Great Clarendon Street, Oxford, ox dp,
United Kingdom
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship,
and education by publishing worldwide. Oxford is a registered trade mark of
Oxford University Press in the UK and in certain other countries
© Editorial matter and organization Raffaella Folli, Christina Sevdali, and
Robert Truswell
© The chapters their several authors
The moral rights of the authors have been asserted
First Edition published in
Impression:
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in
a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, without the
prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press, or as expressly permitted
by law, by licence or under terms agreed with the appropriate reprographics
rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction outside the scope of the
above should be sent to the Rights Department, Oxford University Press, at the
address above
You must not circulate this work in any other form
and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer
Published in the United States of America by Oxford University Press
Madison Avenue, New York, NY , United States of America
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
Data available
Library of Congress Control Number:
ISBN –––– (hbk.)
–––– (pbk.)
Printed in Great Britain by
the CPI Printgroup, UK
Contents
General Preface x
Acknowledgements xi
List of Figures and Tables xii
Contributors xiii
Abbreviations xx
Introduction
Raffaella Folli, Christina Sevdali, and Robert Truswell
. Part I: Architectures
. Part II: Syntax and Information Structure
. Part III: Syntax and the Lexicon
. Part IV: Lexical Items at the Interfaces
Part I. Architectures
Harmonic Derivationalism
Winfried Lechner
. Introduction
. Opacity
. The Condition on Extraction from Copies
. Analysis
. Discussion
. Conclusion
Reconstruction, Control, and Movement
Robert Truswell
. Introduction
. Reconstruction Across Control Dependencies
. Lechner’s Double Dissociation
. Trapping and Countertrapping
. Conclusion
Linearizing Empty Edges
Terje Lohndal and Bridget Samuels
. Introduction
. A Phonological Account of the ECP
. Towards a New Account of Empty-Edge Effects
. Conclusion
vi Contents
References
Index
General Preface
The theoretical focus of this series is on the interfaces between subcomponents of the
human grammatical system and the closely related area of the interfaces between the
different subdisciplines of linguistics. The notion of ‘interface’ has become central
in grammatical theory (for instance, in Chomsky’s Minimalist Program) and in lin-
guistic practice: work on the interfaces between syntax and semantics, syntax and
morphology, phonology and phonetics, etc. has led to a deeper understanding of
particular linguistic phenomena and of the architecture of the linguistic component
of the mind/brain.
The series covers interfaces between core components of grammar, including
syntax–morphology, syntax–semantics, syntax–phonology, syntax–pragmatics,
morphology–phonology, phonology–phonetics, phonetics–speech processing,
semantics–pragmatics, and intonation–discourse structure, as well as issues in the
way that the systems of grammar involving these interface areas are acquired and
deployed in use (including language acquisition, language dysfunction, and language
processing). It demonstrates, we hope, that proper understandings of particular
linguistic phenomena, languages, language groups, or interlanguage variations all
require reference to interfaces.
The series is open to work by linguists of all theoretical persuasions and schools of
thought. A main requirement is that authors should write so as to be understood by
colleagues in related subfields of linguistics and by scholars in cognate disciplines.
The current volume explores the relationship between syntax and other com-
ponents of the grammar. It does this by bringing together a range of studies that
investigate whether certain phenomena are best dealt with by enriching the syntactic
component, enriching other components with which the syntax interfaces, or devel-
oping new approaches to the interfaces between components. This method of attack
on architectural problems in theoretical syntax ultimately stems from Chomsky’s
Remarks on Nominalization (), which concerns the relationship between the
syntactic and lexical components. In this volume other domains are also considered,
including information structure, parsing, pragmatic structure, and conceptual struc-
ture. A number of points of convergence emerge, as well as new questions as to the
standard views of how syntax interacts with other types of linguistic information.
David Adger
Hagit Borer
Acknowledgements
In , a conference ‘On Linguistic Interfaces’ (OnLI) was held at the University
of Ulster, bringing together scholars working on a wide range of interface-related
issues. The success of the first OnLI conference and its uniqueness in addressing the
central, interdisciplinary question of the nature of the overall architecture of language
encouraged our sponsors, particularly the University of Ulster Strategic Fund and the
Institute for Research in Social Science, to support the second OnLI conference, which
would not have been possible without their financial and practical assistance.
Most of the chapters in the present volume started their life as papers presented at
OnLI II, held in December at the University of Ulster. We would like to thank
the abstract committee, our colleagues Alison Henry, Catrin Rhys, and Christiane
Ulbrich, our student helpers Megan Devlin, Frances Kane, and Aveen Hassan, all the
speakers, and our university sponsors and the LAGB for their financial support.
The conference was very successful, and the idea for this volume was born during
the conference dinner. In fact, we strongly feel that Elena Anagnostopoulou deserves
a special mention, as it was in conversation with her that the question we wanted to
address with this volume was uncovered: what are the limits of syntax?
Going from an idea to a volume is a long and winding road. We would like to
thank two anonymous Oxford University Press reviewers and Kleanthes Grohmann
for very useful comments on the proposed volume. Also, all the authors for their
contributions, as well as our reviewers, who gave up their time, often with very tight
schedules, to give us comments on the submissions. Finally, we want to express our
gratitude to OUP and in particular Julia Steer for invaluable, prompt, and expert
guidance.
R. F., C. S., and R. T.
List of Figures and Tables
Figures
. Processing difficulty measured as eye fixation times per word in each
sentence zone
. The word maze task
. Word maze results
. Effects of telicity and transitivity in the word maze
Tables
. Mean self-paced reading times in post hoc reanalyses of two prior studies
. Mean speaker change detection errors for the four verb types
. Word maze ANOVA results
. The morphological paradigm of weak pronouns/clitics in Greek
. Narrow syntactic properties of IO resumptives/doubling clitics in Greek
. List of verb-based particles with pragmatic role
. Inflectional properties
Contributors
Theodora Alexopoulou is a Senior Research Associate at the Department of Theo-
retical and Applied Linguistics, University of Cambridge, leading the Education First
Unit, which is devoted to research in second language learning of English and innova-
tion in language teaching through a systematic cross-fertilization between linguistic
research and teaching techniques. After a BA in Greek philology at the University
of Athens, she went to Edinburgh to obtain an MSc. in natural language and speech
processing and then a PhD in Linguistics. Before coming to Cambridge she worked
at the Universities of Edinburgh and York and held an Intra-European Marie Curie
Fellowship at the University of Lille III. Her research interests are in second language
acquisition and theoretical and experimental syntax, focusing on English and Greek.
She has published articles in Language, Cognition, Journal of Linguistics, Natural Lan-
guage & Linguistic Theory, and Lingua, as well as volumes and conference proceedings.
She lives in Cambridge with her husband and two children.
Elena Anagnostopoulou earned her PhD in linguistics from the University of
Salzburg. She is currently Professor of Linguistics and Director of Graduate Studies
at the Department of Philology, University of Crete. Her research interests lie in
theoretical and comparative syntax, typology, and Greek syntax, with special focus on
the interface between syntax and the lexicon, Case, agreement, clitics, and anaphora.
She is currently working on argument alternations, participles, and compositionality,
long-distance anaphora, and Case theory. She is an external collaborator in the SFB
project ‘Collaborative Research Center ’ (University of Stuttgart) on argument
structure and morphosyntax, and was invited to teach theoretical syntax at the Thermi
International Summer School in Linguistics (TISSL) , the Girona International
Summer School in Linguistics (GISSL) , the ENS (EALing ) Fall School ,
and as a Visiting Professor at the Department of Linguistics and Philosophy, MIT
().
Boban Arsenijević received his PhD in linguistics from Leiden University in . His
dissertation attempts to reconcile the quantitative and the decompositional theory of
inner aspect, deriving the effects of the former from the primitives of the latter. He has
since worked at the University of Amsterdam, Universitat Pompeu Fabra in Barcelona,
and CSIC Madrid, and is currently engaged as an Assistant Professor at the University
of Niš. He works in the domains of syntax, semantics, and cognition from a theoretical
perspective, and on Slavic languages, with a focus on Serbo-Croatian. His main fields
of interest are verbal aspect and tense, clausal embedding, Case, syntactic recursion,
and the ontology of syntactic and semantic categories.
xiv Contributors
of word order variation. Since she has taught in the Department of Linguis-
tics at McGill. Her research focuses mainly on phrase structure, head movement,
language typology, Austronesian languages (in particular Malagasy), and the PF
interface.
Aviad Eilam completed his PhD at the University of Pennsylvania in . His dis-
sertation, ‘Explorations in the Informational Component’, argues that information
structure is an autonomous level of representation in the grammar, based on the
analysis of two phenomena: focus intervention and weak crossover effects. He is now
pursuing a career in writing and communications in Washington, DC, and maintains
an interest in linguistic research.
Raffaella Folli is a Senior Lecturer in Linguistics at the University of Ulster. Her
research interests are theoretical and comparative syntax and language processing,
with special focus on the syntax–lexicon and the syntax–semantics interface. She has
published in journals such as Linguistic Inquiry, Journal of Linguistics, Lingua, and
Trends in Cognitive Science, as well as in several edited volumes.
Berit Gehrke is a postdoctoral researcher at the Universitat Pompeu Fabra in
Barcelona. In she completed her PhD at the University of Utrecht on ‘Ps in
Motion: On the Semantics and Syntax of P Elements and Motion Events’. She is
interested in lexical and compositional semantics and the syntax–semantics interface,
and has worked on various topics related to event predicates, time and space, the
kind/token distinction, and modification.
Liliane Haegeman was Professor of English Linguistics at the University of Geneva
(Switzerland) from to . Between and she was Professor of
English Linguistics at the University of Lille III (France). Since she has held a
research position at Ghent University, where she is project leader for the Odysseus
project ‘Comparative Syntax: Layers of Structure and the Cartography Project’. She
has worked extensively on the syntax of English and Flemish, including her native
dialect of West Flemish. Her research is characterized by a constant attention to the
empirical data, which she examines against the background of the generative formal
approach.
Heidi Harley is Professor of Linguistics at the University of Arizona. She is interested
in the interfaces between lexical semantics and syntax, and between morphology and
syntax, and has worked on these questions in English, Italian, Irish, Hiaki, Icelandic,
and Japanese, largely within the Distributed Morphology framework. Her work has
appeared in Linguistic Inquiry, Language, and Journal of Linguistics, among others.
Virginia Hill is a Professor of Linguistics at the University of New Brunswick–Saint
John. She works in comparative and diachronic syntax, with focus on Romanian,
Romance, and Balkan languages. She authored two books, edited several volumes
xvi Contributors
of papers, and published articles in major international journals. She was recently
awarded a Leverhulme Visiting Professorship at the University of Kent.
Eleni Kapogianni completed her PhD on the semantics and pragmatics of verbal irony
at the University of Cambridge (), where she currently teaches introductory and
advanced semantics and pragmatics. Her research focuses on implicature interpreta-
tion in discourse, using evidence from an experimental approach to speakers’ intu-
itions. Her further interests include philosophy of language, intercultural pragmatics,
and discourse analysis.
Winfried Lechner is Associate Professor of German Linguistics and Theoretical Lin-
guistics at the University of Athens, Greece. His main academic interests are located
in the areas of syntax and semantics, focusing on the interaction between these two
components. In recent and current work he has been investigating the logical syntax
of scope, scope freezing, and scope rigidity; consequences of an LF-transparent the-
ory of reflexivization; the cross linguistic typology of same/different; reconstruction
effects; the analysis of opacity phenomena at the syntax–semantics interface; and the
architecture of the grammar.
Terje Lohndal is Associate Professor of English Linguistics at the Norwegian Univer-
sity of Science and Technology in Trondheim. He is the editor of In Search of Universal
Grammar, published by John Benjamins in , and he has published widely, among
others in Linguistic Inquiry and Journal of Linguistics. He received his PhD from the
University of Maryland in .
Marios Mavrogiorgos is an independent researcher specializing in Minimalist Syn-
tax. He received a BA degree in Greek philology (major in linguistics) from the
University of Athens in . He also obtained an MPhil. and a PhD in theoret-
ical linguistics from the University of Cambridge. His PhD thesis was published
in a revised form in by John Benjamins. After the completion of his PhD,
he spent some time doing research in Greece and at MIT, and in – he
took up a temporary teaching fellow position at the University of Ulster. He has
published a number of peer-reviewed articles, and his work mainly focuses on dif-
ferent aspects of clitics in Greek and other languages. Currently he is working on
Tobler-Mussafia languages, on resumption in Greek, and on verbless sentences in
Kurdish.
Dimitris Michelioudakis is a postdoctoral researcher at the University of Cambridge,
where he teaches introductory and advanced syntax and introductory semantics/
pragmatics. He recently completed a PhD in Cambridge on the syntax and inter-
pretation of dative arguments from a macro-/micro-comparative and diachronic
perspective. His research interests include issues of argument structure theory,
especially the typology of non-core arguments, relation-changing constructions,
Contributors xvii
Maryland, College Park. She received her PhD in linguistics from Harvard University
in .
Christina Sevdali is a lecturer in linguistics at the University of Ulster. She received
her BA from the University of Crete and her MPhil. and PhD from the University
of Cambridge. Her main area of expertise is Ancient Greek syntax, but her research
interests also include multilingual acquisition and the syntax–morphology interface,
particularly Case. Her paper ‘Ancient Greek infinitives and Phases’ will appear in
Syntax, and her collaboration with Artemis Alexiadou and Elena Anagnostopoulou
on ‘Patterns of Dative–Nominative Alternations’ will appear in the Proceedings of
NELS .
Marko Simonović (MA, born ) is currently in the final phase of his PhD project
‘Lexicon Immigration Service: Prolegomena to a Theory of Loanword Integration’,
supervised by René Kager and Wim Zonneveld at Utrecht University, the Netherlands.
This dissertation is an attempt at reuniting the generative approaches to language
contact with the insights from sociolinguistics, creating a model which views bor-
rowing as the creation of a new lexical item in the recipient language but also recog-
nizes the ‘transformational’ knowledge accumulated in the bilingual community. His
research is mostly concerned with paradigm uniformity, surface-to-surface relations
in phonology, lexicon stratification, mappings between related varieties (the so-called
interlanguage mappings), and Serbo-Croatian prosody. Apart from formal linguis-
tics, his areas of scientific interest include biolinguistics, sociolinguistics (especially
the standardization and emancipation discourses), science and technology studies
(especially the place of language in the current models), and new materialisms (more
specifically Karen Barad’s agential realism).
Megan Schildmier Stone is a PhD candidate in the Department of Linguistics at
the University of Arizona. She is interested in morphology, syntax, and semantics,
particulary as they pertain to idioms, and has done work on English and Cherokee.
She is currently writing her dissertation, to be completed in May , which uses
both traditional and experimental methods to investigate what idioms can tell us
about the limits of human language.
Robert Truswell is Assistant Professor of Syntax at the University of Ottawa. Prior
to that, he was a PhD student at University College London, and a postdoctoral
researcher at Tufts University and the University of Edinburgh. He has published
on various aspects of the syntax–semantics interface, including the monograph
Events, Phrases, and Questions (Oxford University Press), and has other research
interests in diachronic syntax and the evolution of language.
George Tsoulas is a Senior Lecturer in Linguistics at the University of York. After an
undergraduate degree in linguistics and literature at the University of Strasbourg he
went on to study for a PhD at the University of Paris VIII. His research to date has
Contributors xix
COMP Complementizer
COND Conditional
CONN Connective
ContrP Contrast Phrase
CoorP Coordinate Phrase
COP Copula
CP Complementizer Phrase
CT Contrastive topic
D Determiner
D-Linking Discourse Linking
DAT Dative
DECL Declarative
Deg Degree
DegP Degree Phrase
Dep Grammatical dependency
DET Determiner
DIM Diminutive
DM Distributed Morphology
DO Direct object
DoC Domain of contrast
DP Determiner Phrase
DS Deductive system
EA External argument
EC Explicit comparison
ECP Empty Category Principle
ED Ethical dative
EP Edge Property
EPP Extended Projection Principle
EvalP Evaluative Phrase
F Feminine
F Focal stress (Ch. )
Fem Feminine
FIN Final
FinP Finiteness Phrase
FM Future Marker
FOC Focus
xxii Abbreviations
Neut Neuter
NMLZR Nominalizer
NMP Nominal mapping parameter
NOM Nominative
NP Noun Phrase
NPI Negative polarity item
n.s. Not significant
Num Number
NumP Number Phrase
Oblig Obligatory
Op Operator
Option Optional
OS Overt Structure
P Preposition
PART Particle
PartP Particle Phrase
PAST Past
PCC Person Case Constraint
PEJ Pejorative
Per Person
PERF Perfective
PF Phonological Form
PFV Perfective
PL Plural
POSS Possessive
PP Prepositional Phrase
PRE Prefix
pred Predicative
PredP Predicative Phrase
PRES Present
Q Question
QP Quantifier Phrase
QR Quantifier Raising
QUD Question under discussion
QUOT Quotative
R Romanian
xxiv Abbreviations
REFL Reflexive
REST Revised Extended Standard Theory
ResultP Result Phrase
RMS Rečnik srpskohrvatskoga književnog jezika
RR Restrictive Relative
RRE Reduced Relative Effect
S Speaker
S Subject
S-C Serbo-Croatian
s-variable Situation variable
SA Speech act
SAP Speech act Phrase
SDN Structurally complex De-adjectival Nominalization
SemR Semantic Reconstruction
SG Singular agreement
SGF Subject gap in finite/fronted
SIC Strong implicit comparison
SpeakerDeixisP Speaker Deixis Phrase
Spec Specifier
S/T Stress/tone
SUBJ Subjunctive
SUF Suffix
SynR Syntactic Reconstruction
T Tense
t trace
Tel Telicity
TelicP Telic Phrase
TOP Topic
TopicP Topic Phrase
TP Tense Phrase
Trans Transitivity
u Unvalued
UC Uniformity Condition
V Verb
V Vowel (Ch. )
Abbreviations xxv
V Verb-second
VOC Vocative
VoiceP Voice Phrase
VP Verb Phrase
WCO Weak Cross Over
WF West Flemish
WIC Weak implicit comparison
w.r.t. With respect to
WYSIWYG What you see is what you get
XP/YP Phrases of unspecified category
Yes/NoQ Yes/No question
Introduction
R A F FA E L L A F OL L I , C H R I ST I NA SEV DA L I ,
A N D ROBE RT T RU S W E L L
Since its inception, generative grammar has pursued a ‘divide and conquer’ strategy
with respect to the study of linguistic phenomena, inheriting from its predecessors in
structuralist linguistics and traditional grammar the useful notion that different lin-
guistic phenomena are amenable to modes of explanation which suggest the existence
of clusters of linguistic phenomena, some related to sound, some to grammar, some to
meaning, some to aspects of language use, and so on. To capture this, Chomsky ()
formalized the notion of a ‘linguistic level’ and insisted on the relative autonomy of
these levels. The differentiation of linguistic levels was far from new in itself, of course,
but it takes on a new significance given Chomsky’s mentalist perspective, delivering
a view of the language faculty, and by extension cognition, as something structured,
with differentiated subcomponents, including minimally a lexicon, and phonological,
syntactic, and semantic components, each with their own structural characteristics, in
stark contrast to the then-dominant behaviourist view of the mind as a unitary black
box.
Naturally a theory containing multiple distinct levels of representation raises imme-
diate questions. How many levels are there, and what exactly do the different levels do?
Is it an accident that the levels enumerated in the previous paragraph correspond so
closely to the classical levels of linguistic analysis in structuralist and earlier linguis-
tics? What can a level of linguistic representation look like?
Equally, questions arise immediately about interactions between representations,
now commonly discussed under the term ‘linguistic interfaces’: what does the output
of each level look like, and how does it feed into the next level(s)? How do the multiple
levels interact to produce the range of empirical phenomena that non-theoreticians
happily label with the umbrella term ‘language’?
Connectionism, in many ways the descendent of behaviourism, is similarly distinguished by its rejec-
tion of operations over the structured symbolic representations pervasive in classical cognitive science—see
Fodor and Pylyshyn () for extensive critical discussion.
Folli, Sevdali, and Truswell
primitives, and in the calculation of scope and other relations (see Lakoff for
a summary). For example, McCawley (b) proposed that x killed y was derived
transformationally from an underlying structure like (a), but that there could be
no verb flimp with a meaning equivalent to (c), because combining kiss, girl,
and allergic transformationally into a single word meaning would violate Ross’s
Complex Noun Phrase Constraint.
() a. cause x [become [not [alive y]]]
b. ∗ Bert flimped coconuts
c. ∗ Bert kissed a girl who is allergic to coconuts.
On the assumption that the locality constraints are basically syntactic, this underpins
an argument that the empirical domain of syntactic structures extends beyond the
order of words in sentences, to constrain the set of possible word meanings. If the
claims of Miller and Chomsky and of Generative Semantics both turned out to be
correct, we would have a double dissociation: there are phenomena (like centre-
embedding) relating to the distribution of words and phrases which are outside the
empirical domain of syntactic theory, and there are phenomena (like restrictions
on word meaning) within the empirical domain of syntactic theory, which are not
primarily concerned with the distribution of words and phrases.
Examples along these lines have multiplied in the intervening half-century. For
instance, it has become common, following Chomsky (), May (), Kayne
(), and Huang (), to assume that syntactic transformations derive a level
of Logical Form, representing basically semantic relations such as scope and binding.
Recently, however, more nuanced questions have arisen concerning the interaction
of syntax with pragmatics, and with notions of new and old information, aboutness,
and contrast, typically grouped under the rubric of ‘information structure’, following
Halliday (). It is not clear that information structure is a structure in the same
sense that phrase structure, prosodic structure, and so on are structures. Instead,
‘information structure’ currently appears to be used more as a cover term for a
(fixed, probably quite small, and probably universal) range of options for marking
distinctions within the semantic content of an utterance on the basis of the imme-
diate linguistic and non-linguistic context (this may, of course, be a placeholder for a
more integrated theory of information structure developed along lines stemming ulti-
mately from Kamp and Heim ). Several papers in this collection pursue the
hypothesis that information-structural notions are extraneous to syntax, constraining
the distribution of words and phrases from afar; others propose that information-
structural notions are more or less directly reflected in syntactic structure, as initially
proposed in detail by Rizzi (), allowing at least in principle for the possibility
that information-structural effects on well-formedness might be reducible to classical
syntactic explanations.
Folli, Sevdali, and Truswell
respects to the modules with which it interfaces, but it does not impose any constraints
on what those other modules subsequently do with the representations that it gen-
erates. In other words, the nature of the interfaces for such models is determined
by the information passed along from the phrase structure which is ‘legible’ to the
phonological or semantic components.
Within this latter model, questions arise about the nature of the lexicon and the
extent of its influence over syntactic structure-building. The lexicon here does not
automatically have the übermodule status afforded it by Construction Grammar and
cognate theories, but there are still numerous reasons to suppose that the lexicon
is not simply a set of items serving as an input to a computational system which
manipulates those items. The first concerns semiproductivity among word forms, as
investigated by Jackendoff (), following Chomsky (). Many alternations look
more or less rule-governed, but admit several exceptions and idiosyncrasies: there are
cases in which a rule fails to apply, or the output of the rule displays irregularities
of form or meaning in some cases. In such cases, the regularity makes us want to
treat these alternations within the computational system (typically, syntax), but the
idiosyncrasies make us want to treat the alternations as stored.
A further compelling reason to suspect that the lexicon is less than maximally sim-
ple concerns the treatment of phrasal idioms. The phrasal syntax of idioms is generally
identical to the syntax of non-idiomatic constructions, which appears to suggest a
rule-governed compositional element to the structure of idioms. However, the inter-
pretation of those idioms cannot be determined on the basis of the interpretations of
their component parts: even with apparently compositional idioms such as let the cat
out of the bag, although the cat is in some sense interpreted as ‘the secret’, this interpre-
tation is only available in this particular phrasal context. For construction grammar-
ians, such facts provide the impetus for essentially treating all syntactic composition
like the composition of idioms: the lexically guided construction of phrasal units is all
there is. Among Minimalists, in contrast, idioms are not treated as a reason to eschew
lexicon-independent principles of syntactic composition, but rather as an indication
that the meaning of a lexical item can be sensitive to syntactic context within a partic-
ular locality domain. For example, it is generally assumed, following Marantz ()
and Kratzer (), that there are no idiomatic external argument–verb combinations
Alongside these major architectural distinctions, numerous hybrids and alternatives exist. For exam-
ple, the Parallel Architecture of Jackendoff (), as well as making reference to the lexicon as a Con-
struction Grammar-like übermodule, also contains small interface modules that regulate correspondences
between the structures to which they connect. Unlike certain post-Montagovian theories, then, in the Paral-
lel Architecture the derivations of phonological, syntactic, and semantic representations are not only related
indirectly, through the lexicon, but also through direct interfaces. Meanwhile, Representation Theory
(Williams ) postulates numerous levels of representation (at least eight), with no übermodule and no
module with the privileged status of syntax in recent Chomskyan theories, but instead a general constraint
on correspondences between levels, making reference to homomorphisms from one representation into
another and varieties of disruption of those homomorphisms. We set these aside here, although the debate
ultimately involves them just as much as the options outlined in the main text.
Introduction
that exclude internal arguments (although see Nunberg, Sag, and Wasow for
possible exceptions). On the assumption that the verb is syntactically closer to the
internal arguments than to the external arguments, this could be taken to suggest a
syntactic locality constraint on idiom formation (see below for further discussion).
As with semiproductivity, as described above, there is a clear tension here: idioms
are largely syntactically regular, largely semantically irregular, and there are some
grounds for assuming that there is a syntactic limit on that semantic irregularity. Once
again, this empirical area highlights the complex interactions between lexical storage
of idiosyncratic material and rule-governed computation of complex structures.
How to handle this tension remains an open question. Two major approaches can
be defined. One, the lexicalist approach initiated by Jackendoff () and Wasow
(), and adopted in frameworks such as Lexical-Functional Grammar, relies on
devices such as redundancy rules performing a limited amount of pre-syntactic com-
putation, to capture relations among lexical items without predicting the complete
productivity that we would expect from mechanical application of a regular syntactic
rule. The other, antilexicalist, approach, based on work by Hale and Keyser ()
and subsequently adopted by a range of Minimalist researchers, insists that all rule-
governed behaviour affecting both sound and meaning, even below the word level,
is basically syntactic, and that idiosyncrasies are confined to a special domain at the
bottom of a tree (the domain of L-syntax in Hale and Keyser’s terms).
The architectural commitments of lexicalist and antilexicalist theories are quite
divergent. For lexicalists (see e.g. Wasow , Reinhart , or Koontz-Garboden
, in addition to the above references), the lexicon is much more than a stored
list of correspondences between sounds, meanings, and syntactic features. Rather, it
has a fairly complex internal structure of its own, deriving many alternations between
word forms, with corresponding simplification of the phrase structure. In contrast,
Hale and Keyser’s alternative gives rise to the hope that syntactic notions will prove
useful for the analysis of lexical alternations as well as phrasal phenomena (see also
e.g. Travis and Kratzer ). One promising line of inquiry focusing on the
derivation of verb argument structure and stemming from Hale and Keyser’s work
aims to show that the syntactic position of arguments determines key aspects of their
interpretation, and so ultimately ‘verbs at least in part mean what the syntax allows
them to mean’ (Rosen : ; see also Ramchand ).
Perhaps the poster child for the L-syntactic approach is the incorporation of locality
effects into theories of word-level structure, as anticipated in the Generative Semantics
literature mentioned above, and subsequent research like Baker’s () description
of patterns of noun incorporation. Recent research has focused in particular on the
hypothesis that a particular head delimits the domain of L-syntax. This hypothesis
Following Ramchand (), the domain of L-syntax is sometimes referred to as the ‘first phase’, the
idea being that syntactic limits on lexicosemantic phenomena are a special case of the general notion of
phases as units of sound–meaning correspondence (Chomsky et seq.).
Folli, Sevdali, and Truswell
has in turn inspired many attempts to identify the head in question. For instance, that
head could be the same head which introduces an agent, the head which introduces
‘eventive’ semantics, the head which converts a category-neutral root into a verb,
some combination of these (if a single head has multiple functions), or none of the
above. All of these possibilities continue to be actively investigated (including by many
chapters in this volume), but none is currently universally accepted. The eventual
choice from among these options will directly inform our understanding of the syntax
of idiosyncrasy, and the idiosyncrasy of syntax.
These issues are particularly foregrounded by research in Distributed Morphol-
ogy (DM: Halle and Marantz , Marantz ; see also Harley and Noyer ,
Embick and Noyer , and Harley, to appear, for recent overviews). DM adopts
the antilexicalist position, often referred to as ‘syntax all the way down’, that there
is no word-formation component distinct from syntax: morphemes are syntactic
terminals, and multimorphemic words are represented by particular configurations
of those terminals. More complex morphological phenomena are handled in a post-
syntactic morphological component which allows for further manipulation of ter-
minals prior to insertion of phonological forms, while interpretive phenomena are
handled by the Encyclopedia, which determines the interpretation of a terminal in a
given syntactic context. In a DM approach, then, the lexicon is not an übermodule: the
syntactic, semantic, and morphological computations retain some autonomy. How-
ever, in contrast to classical architectures from the Standard Theory through to GB,
the lexicon’s contribution is also not entirely pre-syntactic: it influences operations
in multiple places throughout the derivation. For DM, in other words, syntactic and
morphological structures are interrelated, because they are partially the same thing:
the generative system responsible for phrase structure is also partially responsible
for word formation. This makes it particularly natural to extend analyses based on
cyclicity and other syntactic locality conditions into the domain of classically ‘lexical’
phenomena; as a corollary, operations which clearly violate such conditions, such
as lowering of T onto V in English, must be treated post-syntactically, in a separate
module with its own rules (Embick and Noyer ).
Many chapters in this volume (particularly those in Part III) investigate this
range of architectural alternatives, arriving at pleasingly consistent conclusions on
the basis of diverse data. Many more chapters are interested in the other questions
raised above. The same goal runs through all the chapters, though: to find ways to
bring concrete evidence to bear on important but abstract architectural questions
and in the process to help us come a step closer to understanding the place (and
the limits) of syntax within the architecture of language. The rest of this intro-
duction contains brief summaries of the empirical coverage of each chapter; the
point of the foregoing is to give a taste of why those empirical questions are worth
investigating.
Introduction
for adjuncts). They can then be prohibited as a special case of a theory of linearization
which cannot linearize two featurally identical sisters. Crucially, that theory is only
viable if a specific ordering of operations in the mapping from syntax to phonology
is assumed. In common with many recent theories of this interface, then, Lohndal
and Samuels advocate a sequential application of operations to transform phrase-
structural representations into phonological representations, in which linearization
crucially precedes vocabulary insertion, integration of adjuncts, and marking of
copies for deletion.
Finally in Part I, O’Bryan, Folli, Harley, and Bever (Chapter ) address the question
of what kind of linguistic information is available during the first stages of sentence
processing. Evidence from three new experiments and a reanalysis of previously pub-
lished results shows that garden path effects induced by a local ambiguity between
main clauses and reduced relatives (Bever ) are conditioned independently by
both transitivity and telicity. The former finding is quite well known and relatively
unsurprising; the latter is new and surprising, but amenable to explanation if telic-
ity is represented syntactically, as suggested by Ramchand () and others, and
hence is available to the parser in the first stages of processing. This chapter therefore
contributes to the debate about the interaction of syntax and grammatically encoded
semantics in online syntactic processing.
can ameliorate the examples in question, and also why the effects are not restricted
to interrogatives, instead showing up across a wider class of sentences with typically
fixed focus structure.
De Cat (Chapter ) argues for an information-structural characterization of root
phenomena, based on data from fragments containing dislocated topics in French and
from politeness markers in Japanese fragments, both restricted to root environments.
De Cat argues that these cases are not straightforwardly captured by approaches to
root phenomena based on clausal syntax, not least because of the existence of root
fragments with no clausal equivalent, and proposes instead an account based on the
hypothesis that root phenomena are degraded in structures that are thetic, and so not
articulated on the level of information structure.
Vermeulen (Chapter ) provides evidence that the mapping between syntax and
information structure is not fully determined by properties of syntactic structure or
information structure, but must instead be described with reference to the mapping
between the two levels. She assumes three primitive information-structural features,
[focus], [topic], and [contrast], which may be combined to represent contrastive
foci or contrastive topics. In Korean, any contrastive phrase, topic or focus, can be
scrambled to medial or initial position. The same is true for Japanese contrastive foci.
Japanese contrastive topics, however, behave like non-contrastive topics in that they
can only be scrambled to initial position. In other words, Korean contrastive topics
behave like other contrastive phrases, while Japanese contrastive topics behave like
other topics. The surprising architectural implication is that there exists a parameter
that distinguishes languages based not on factors related to syntactic structure or
information structure alone, but on the patterns of sensitivity of syntactic structure
to information structure, a conclusion which appears to fit most naturally with a
conception of these two levels as existing in parallel.
Harley and Stone, revisiting a seminal idea from Marantz (), reach the same
conclusion concerning agents, defending the ‘No Agent Idioms’ Hypothesis against
a class of putative crosslinguistic counterexamples. Both chapters therefore suggest
that the introduction of functional structure is ultimately responsible for delimiting
the domain of idiomatic interpretation.
Architectures
Harmonic Derivationalism∗
WINFRIED LECHNER
. Introduction
On a widely held view, cognitive systems consist of discrete, informationally encapsu-
lated subcomponents or modules (Fodor ) operating on mental representations.
As the modules can contain partially incompatible types of information, their expres-
sions need to be modulated by interfaces in order to render representations of one
system interpretable by its neighbouring modules. For the language faculty, the two
central syntax-external modules are model-theoretic semantics and the sensorimotor
system, which are accessed by their respective interfaces, Logical Form and Phonetic
Form. Recently, it has been argued that the modules interfacing with the core syntac-
tic system also include a designated system computing logical inferences, called the
Deductive system (Fox , Gajewski ).
The present chapter outlines a new architecture of the grammar that redefines the
way in which the logical syntax of meanings is derived. Concretely, it is suggested
that the model of the grammar includes two covert components instead of a single
one for deriving the abstract representations which are submitted to model-theoretic
interpretation: an interface to DS, which precedes the overt syntax system, and Logical
Form (LF) which directly interfaces with the semantic component. In what follows
I will, unless ambiguity arises, refer to the DS interface simply as DS.
The assumption of two covert components is justified by empirical as well as the-
oretical considerations. On the empirical side, the DS–LF model is supported by the
fact that it offers an explanation for a class of structural restrictions on covert remnant
movement identified in Lechner (, b), where they are referred to as the
Condition on Extraction from Copies or CEC. Theoretically, the new model offers
∗ I am grateful to the organizers of OnLI II, Raffaella Folli, Christina Sevdali, and Robert Truswell,
for their kind invitation, as well as to the audiences of OnLI and GLOW , Vienna, for valuable
feedback. Robert Truswell provided detailed written comments on an earlier version which helped me to
avoid an inconsistency and led to a radical revision of section .. I am also indebted to Anke Assmann for
email discussion on the cycle and predicate fronting. The title is inspired by the term ‘Harmonic Serialism’
(McCarthy ). Finally, responsibility for any errors remains with the author.
Lechner
at least two attractive features. First, it locates covert scope-shifting operations and
movements that solely serve the purpose of local type adjustment in two different
parts of the grammar, resulting in a clean divide between movement that ensures
interface readability and long-distance procedures which potentially create new inter-
pretations. Second, it will be seen that DS is integrated into the stem of the derivation
by an operation which is already widely used within the syntactic component in
order to model syntactic opacity phenomena (such as Binding Theory obviation—see
below): late insertion of lexical nodes, or Late Merge. Widening the role of Late Merge
to apply not only within narrow syntax but also across modules leads to an increase
of the overall symmetry of the system, while at the same time making optimal use of
the analytical tools already employed in the analysis of opacity.
The chapter is structured as follows. Subsequent to some general remarks on the
relation between interfaces and opacity in section ., section . briefly reviews the
empirical basis for the CEC generalization. Section . attempts an explanation for
the CEC. The analysis to be submitted crucially relies on the new DS–LF model of the
grammar together with standard syntactic mechanisms such as Late Merge and the
cycle. Some ramifications of the model will finally be considered in section ..
. Opacity
As opacity occupies a prominent position throughout the discussion of this chapter,
the current section makes explicit some background concepts as well as the probably
not so familiar notion of opacity at the interfaces.
In principle, linguistic interfaces can modulate the signal which is passed from
one system to the next in two ways: qualitatively by signal transduction, or
quantitatively by altering the amount and internal composition of the information
to be transmitted. The current discussion is concerned with changes across the
quantitative dimension only. These changes determine (i) how much information is
transferred at a given point (amount); (ii) at which point the information is released
(timing); and (iii) where this information is precisely located in the representations
built from the signal (location).
() Quality Quantity
Examples of signal transduction include microphones, which translate acoustic waves into electrical
signals, or scales, which transduce from mass/weight to numbers.
Harmonic Derivationalism
Quantitative factors do not only have an impact on information transfer across mod-
ules, but are also at work within an encapsulated component. It has been argued, for
instance, that information in the syntactic system is packaged in discrete units (factor
(i)), and that sequentially ordering these representations leads to the effect of syntactic
derivations (factor (ii)). In order to show that the computation indeed proceeds in
discrete, derivational steps, it is moreover necessary to find constellations in which
the units are ordered in a particular sequence, subject to conditions which cannot be
inferred from the output. Such constellations, known as opaque contexts, have been
taken to be strongly indicative of an incremental, derivational computation.
The study of opacity in linguistics has generally been restricted to phenomena
located within a specific linguistic component such as syntax, phonology, or morphol-
ogy, where it has been instrumental in guiding the decision among competing models
of the grammar. According to the standard typology of Kiparsky (), opacity
comes in two varieties, which in modern parlance are usually referred to as over- and
underapplication (for important qualifications see Baković ). Overapplication
describes scenarios in which a principle or rule applies even though the context of
that condition is no longer visible in the surface form. By contrast, in environments
that are shaped by underapplication, a principle that should have applied, given the
overt context, failed to do so. Two typical examples of over- and underapplication
in syntax come from the interaction of Binding Theory and movement. Principle A
reconstruction as in () is a manifestation of overapplication because the context of
variable binding, that is c-command, is arguably not met any more subsequent to
movement:
() Which book about himself did no one like?
Overapplication is standardly modelled by assuming that the signal is richer than
it appears, and includes devices such as silent lower occurrences of higher nodes
(copies: Chomsky ).
With the assumption of copies, () ceases to be opaque. However, the analysis now
turns Principle C obviation by A-movement, as in (), into an instance of underap-
plication. Principle C is expected to affect the name in the lower copy located in the
position marked t , barring coreference, but fails to do so. (Copies will be presented
as traces for ease of readability.)
() [This picture of John ] seems to him t to be beautiful.
A popular way to resolve this conflict consists in delaying lexical insertion of the
offending parts (picture of John) to a point of the derivation where the name (John) is
On the derivation vs. representation debate see, among many others, Brody (), Haider (),
natives, that do not require reconstruction, see Sternefeld and Konietzko ().
Lechner
Further evidence and discussion of the CEC can be found in Lechner (, b, to appear).
Harmonic Derivationalism
.. Reconstruction
While movement can be undone for the computation of both relative quantifier scope
and binding relations, it has been observed that scope and binding reconstruction
do not necessarily coincide, indicating that reconstruction involves an additional
mechanism apart from copies (see also Truswell, Chapter below). For instance, short
scrambling in German illustrates that scope reconstruction does not entail binding
reconstruction. Even though (a) admits an inverse reading for the scrambled direct
object QP , it is not possible to construe the anaphor inside the scrambled object as
being bound by the indirect object to its right (Lechner , ). (b) demon-
strates that in the absence of a higher binder, reconstruction results in ill-formedness,
corroborating the hypothesis that short scrambling cannot be undone for binding
(Frey ).
() a. weil wir [einige Freunde von einander∗/ ] allen t vorstellen wollten
since we [some friends of each other to all introduce wanted
‘since we wanted to introduce some friends of each other to everybody’
(∃ > ∀/∀ > ∃)
b. ∗ weil ich [einige Freunde von einander/ ] allen t vorstellen wollte
since I [some friends of each other to all introduce wanted
‘since I wanted to introduce some friends of each other to everybody’
The bifurcation between binding and scope in (b) can be given a natural analysis
on the assumption that binding relations are structurally encoded at LF and that
scope diminishment is delayed to the semantic component, such that the scrambled
object reaches its scope position too late for the principles of Binding Theory and
variable binding to apply. Implemented in terms of Semantic Reconstruction (SemR;
Cresti , Rullmann , von Stechow ), as in (), the inverse reading of the
scrambled QP is derived by having QP bind a generalized quantifier-type trace into
which QP is converted in the inverse reading:
() We introduced [[DP some friends of each other ] [to everybody [T,et,t …]]]
Contexts which lend themselves to an analysis in terms of SemR are opaque, and they
are so in two different ways. Note to begin with that a derivation is always opaque
relative to a given representation. If this representation is taken to be the surface form,
SemR represents a case of rule overapplication, because the principles responsible for
determining scope locate the scope of the fronted quantifier in a configuration which
has been destroyed by movement. But SemR can also be seen as a manifestation of
underapplication. If the structural description includes copies in the source position
of movement, a principle (Principle A) that would have been expected to apply fails
See also Truswell (Ch. below), who discusses interesting challenges for the mixed approach towards
to be visible in the output. The relations can also be stated as follows: SemR describes
overapplication with respect to quantifier scope, and underapplication with respect
to Principle A.
Moreover, opacity in both cases results from the interaction between rules that
belong to two different grammatical components: movement applies in overt syntax,
while reconstruction is delayed to semantics. Since opacity is diagnostic of a serial rule
ordering, this cross-componental opacity presents a strong argument for the view that
syntax precedes semantics, in support of a serial, syntacto centric architecture of the
grammar (Chomsky ). By contrast, it is not evident how the phenomena char-
acterized by the hybrid reconstruction approach can be made to be compatible with
monostratal models such as categorial grammars in which syntactic and semantic
representations are built up simultaneously.
While () presents a strong argument for a theory of reconstruction which admits
both SynR by copies and SemR, the hybrid approach is challenged by the observation
that there are contexts in which SynR and SemR systematically co-vary, in support of
a pure SynR approach (Fox , Lebeaux , Romero ). Such Scope Trapping
environments appear to suggest that the hybrid approach overgenerates, because it
admits unattested combinations of wide binding scope (of situation variables—see
below) and narrow quantifier scope. The trapping generalization relevant for present
concerns contains the two clauses in ():
() a. If a moved DP is construed de dicto, it reconstructs for Binding Theory.
b. If a dislocated DP reconstructs for Binding Theory, it is construed de dicto.
The paradigm in () confirms the validity of (a) (Lechner , to appear, Sharvit
). Both examples, modelled after Russell’s () yacht sentences, are ambiguous
between a consistent de dicto interpretation for the raising subject and a contradictory
de re reading. Interestingly, in (a) the fronted name John can be construed corefer-
entially with the pronominal experiencer him only on the contradictory de re reading
(cf. control (b)). This follows on the assumption that the de dicto construal is pro-
duced by binding the situation variable (s-variable) inside the subject John’s height
to the raising predicate, which makes the referentially opaque reading contingent
upon subject reconstruction into a position below seem. Relevant parts of the LF
representation are made explicit in (), while () provides details for the de re
interpretation:
() a. [John ’s height] seemed to him to exceed his actual height.
(∗ consistent de dicto/✓contradictory de re)
(i) de dicto: ‘It seemed to John that John is taller than he actually is.’
(ii) de re: ‘John obtained the impression: I am taller than I am.’
b. [His height] seemed to him to exceed his actual height.
(✓consistent de dicto/✓contradictory de re)
Harmonic Derivationalism
Russell ambiguities also supply a test for (b). Specifically, (a) can only be under-
stood as a consistent de dicto proposition, indicating that anaphor reconstruction
results in narrow s-binding ((b); (b) serves as control). Thus, if a moved DP
reconstructs for the anaphor licensing, the s-variable must be locally bound to the
next intensional predicate (Romero ):
() a. [Each other ’s height] seemed to the boys to exceed their actual height.
(✓consistent de dicto/∗ contradictory de re)
(i) de dicto: ‘It seemed to each boy that the others are taller than they
actually are.’
(ii) de re: ‘Each boy had the impression: the other boys are taller than they
are.’
b. [Their height] seemed to the boys to exceed their actual height.
(✓consistent de dicto/✓contradictory de re)
() Consistent de dicto reading of (a) abides by Principle A
a. [Each other ’s height]de dicto seemed to the boys to exceed their actual
heightde re .
b. Îs [seemed [Îs to the boys [each other ’s height-in-s ] to exceed their
height-in-s ]]
() Contradictory de re reading of (a) violates Principle A
a. ∗ [Each other ’s height]de re seemed to the boys to exceed their actual
heightde re .
b. ∗ Îs [[each other ’s height-in-s ] [seemed [Îs to the boys to exceed their
height-in-s ]]]
The findings above entail that the hybrid theory can be contained from overgeneration
only if two requirements are guaranteed. First, reconstruction by SemR always has
to result in de re interpretations. Otherwise, it would be possible to derive com-
binations which reconstruct for scope and referential opacity (generating de dicto
readings) but not for Binding Theory. But such constellations are incompatible with
(a). Conversely, syntactic reconstruction by Copy Theory must invariantly produce
Lechner
a de dicto reading. Otherwise, movement could reconstruct for binding and scope
while preserving referential transparency (de re interpretation), in contradiction
to (b).
The first task, i.e. ensuring that SemR is compatible with de re interpretations only,
falls out from a general principle restricting higher-type traces to extensional types.
For further details see Lechner (to appear). It is the second condition where we finally
encounter a first manifestation of the CEC, repeated from above:
() Condition on Extraction from Copies (CEC)
Covert subextraction out of silent copies is as local as possible.
Essentially, what (b) and the paradigm in () demonstrate is that a successful theory
of reconstruction must be able to block long-distance binding of s-variables out of
reconstructed subjects, in order to exclude LF-representations such as (), which
underlie the unattested de re reading.
() ∗ Îs [seemed [Îs to the boys [each other ’s height-in-s ] to exceed their
height-in-s ]]
On the assumption that s-variable binding comes about by silent movement of a
situation pronoun (Percus and Sauerland ), () is straightforwardly excluded
by the CEC. In (), variable s has moved across a closer potential binder (Îs ) in
violation of the minimality condition of the CEC. Thus, the CEC derives an important
restriction on syntactic reconstruction.
This requirement needs to be secured both by the hybrid and the pure SynR approach, and is therefore
. Analysis
Various analytical options can be explored in looking for an explanation of the CEC,
among others the candidates in ():
() Possible explanations of the CEC
a. Silence of the containing node blocks non-local movement
b. Properties of the movement procedure
c. Feature structure of silent copies (locality as a result of an impoverished
feature inventory on silent nodes)
d. Properties of the linearization procedure (locality as a result of order preser-
vation)
e. Architecture of the grammar: the covert component is divided into a part
which admits non-local movement and a part which only licenses local
movement.
Lechner
Hypothesis (a) is not likely to succeed given that elliptical VPs are silent, yet
nonetheless admit non-local movement (An American flag is hanging in front of every
embassy, and a British one is, too). Options (b–d) are either evidently too strong
(b) or vacuous, in the absence of further details. A plausible venue is given by
hypothesis (e), though, according to which the stricter locality conditions expressed
by the CEC reflect the point in the derivation at which these movements occur.
With the information provided in section ., it also becomes possible to be more
specific about how the local processes should be separated from the non-local ones.
In essence, the CEC defines a last-resort strategy for movement, barring all optional
displacement which is not motivated by rendering representations interpretable at the
semantic interface. Moreover, CEC-conforming operations are local since Economy
dictates that they target the closest possible landing site which guarantees inter-
pretability. On this view, the CEC is not a construction-specific principle of the
grammar, but rather exposes a fundamental characteristic of the interface with model-
theoretic semantics: LF admits only local operations which serve to repair type mis-
matches and possibly other processes that are needed to secure LF-transparency (in
the sense of von Stechow ).
The present proposal entails two consequences. First, it presents a more natural
conception of the interface with model-theoretic interpretation than the orthodox
version of LF, which includes both local adjustment operations and non-local scope-
shifting movement. Second, it follows that since local CEC-conforming movement
applies at the LF interface and LF is the last component in the stem of the derivation,
optional, non-local scope-shifting operations must precede LF. Thus, covert move-
ment that applies early in the derivation is subject to more liberal locality conditions
than covert operations that apply late. The grammar therefore has to make avail-
able a second silent component apart from LF for hosting non-local, scope-shifting
operations.
A potential candidate for such a second silent component emerges in form of the
deductive system (Fox , Gajewski , Fox and Hackl ), or, to be precise,
the grammar-internal interface to DS. The following subsection briefly characterizes
some core features of DS and suggests a new way to integrate the DS interface into the
architecture of the grammar.
See Barwise and Cooper () for existentials; see von Fintel () for exceptives.
Gajewski () attributes an idea along these lines to Danny Fox.
Lechner
While this implementation offers the advantage of optimizing the interface with the
(grammar-external) deductive system, as the latter operates on logical skeletons, I will
adopt the more liberal position that lexical insertion by Late Merge can take place at
any point of the derivation, throughout DS and overt syntax. This has the advantage
of rendering the integration of DS representations into the overt syntactic system
more efficient and simpler because movement copies can be generated by standardly
sanctioned mechanisms. Hence, in what follows it will be assumed that DS repre-
sentations can—but do not have to—be completely lexically impoverished. Other
options are conceivable, but as far as I can see, the particular analyses to be advanced
below do not inherently depend on any particular choice as to how representations are
lexicalized.
Subsequent to DS and overt syntax, the derivation reaches the model-theoretic
interface LF. Whereas DS operations are by nature non-local, as they test for different
scope options, all LF movement, prototypically exemplified by type-driven QR, is
strictly local and exclusively serves the purpose of rendering representations readable
at the interpretive interface. Thus, the resulting DS–LF model, schematized in (),
partitions scope-shifting QR and operations required for type repair into two separate
components.
() The DS–LF model
Lexical Insertion by (Wholesale) Late Merge
DS → Overt Syntax → PF
↓
optional scope-shifting rules LF → model-theoretic interpretation
↓
grammar-external obligatory local adjustment
deductive system rules (type-driven QR, . . .)
With the assumptions about the DS–LF model above, the sample derivation for a
scopally ambiguous example such as () proceeds as follows. Assume for reasons
of concreteness that in the case of (), the DS representations resemble the logical
skeleton. The DS for the surface scope reading, given in (), then includes two
determiners and variables in the position of the restrictor arguments and the verb.
In addition to the logical skeleton for the overt scope order, the model also makes
available a second DS representation for the inverse reading (b), in which the object
has been exported across the subject:
() Two policemen spied on every boy.
a. [every Qe,t [two Pe,t [Re,et [every Qe,t ]]]
b. [every Qe,t [two Pe,t [Re,et [every Qe,t ]]]]
Harmonic Derivationalism
Scope Economy now tests whether the wide-scope option derives a new interpretation
that is logically independent from (a) (Fox ). To that end, both (a) and (b)
are transferred to the grammar-external deductive system. Since the external system
confirms the logical independence of the two readings, both DS representations are
further processed by overt syntax. Note that the scope of an expression is not fixed
or interpreted at DS. DS merely explores which among the logically possible scope
relations are legitimated by the grammar-external deductive system, passing licit
configurations on to overt syntax and, eventually, to LF.
In overt syntax, roots and functional morphemes, including formal syntactic fea-
tures, are merged. For the surface scope reading, there is only a single option for lexical
insertion, detailed in (), which correctly derives scope as well as word order:
() Lexical insertion in object narrow-scope representation
a. [two Pe,t [Re,et [every Qe,t ]]]
b. two policemen spied on every boy
As for the inverse reading, it is at least at first sight tempting to correlate long object
movement at DS with Late Merge of the restrictor into the scope position of the object,
as in ():
() Lexical insertion in object wide-scope representation
a. [every Qe,t [two Pe,t [Re,et [every Qe,t ]]]]
b. every boy [two policemen spied on every Qe,t ]
However, this simple conception is contradicted by two facts. First, QR does not
obviate Principle C effects (∗ Two policemen spied on every boy who trusted the guys ).
Hence the restrictor must be inserted low, inside the VP (for motivation see (c),
below). Second, Late Merge into the scope position fails to account for the correct
linearization, because QR does not have an effect on word order. Thus, the system has
to insert the descriptive content in a cyclic fashion, starting with the lower occurrence
of the object, proceeding from there to the higher one, as in (). The higher copy is
then marked as PF-inert (typographically symbolized by strikeout), just as in more
traditional single output models that locate all movement operations, irrespective of
whether they are overt or covert, in the stem of the derivation (Bobaljik , Groat
and O’Neil , Pesetsky ).
Transfer to the grammar-external deductive system minimally involves translation of the logical vocab-
ulary of a natural language into the logical constants of a formal system. Alternatively, one could assume
that DS includes logical constants only (e.g. symbols such as ‘∀’), and that the morphophonological matrix
(every) is provided by Lexical Insertion.
Lechner
(b) captures the default hypothesis that LI is free to apply at any point of the overt
derivation, subject to additional conditions. These conditions are spelled out in (c)
and (d). Following Takahashi, I assume that restrictor arguments of determiners
can be added only within their Case domain ((c); for evidence see discussion of ()
above). Moreover, if a determiner remains unlexicalized throughout the derivation,
it is translated as an individual variable (d). This requirement, which arguably
follows from the hypothesis that natural language quantification is restricted, ensures
that bare determiner insertion precludes not only syntactic but also semantic recon-
struction. Finally, the only new addition to the catalogue of principles regulating
the interplay between LI and the derivation is the Uniformity Condition (UC), ().
The UC in () is meant to express the idea that DPs which are fully assembled and
move need to c-command their lower copies throughout the derivation. In essence,
the UC is a descendant of Fiengo’s () Proper Binding Condition or some ver-
sion of the cycle, relativized to DPs that are ‘complete’ in the sense that both the
determiner and the restrictor NP have been merged. As this in turn presupposes
that both D and NP have been assigned Case by a higher c-commanding head, ()
is intuitively closely related to Takahashi’s Case condition (c). Both conditions
impose c-command requirements on elements that are in need of Case. Hopefully,
future research will reveal directions towards a unification of these two principles (see
Lechner a).
Returning to the analysis of scope freezing with VP-fronting, consider how the
system excludes the unattested object > subject scope order first. For ease of read-
ability, I will subscript DPs which include a lexical restrictor with ‘LI’ and nodes that
consist of D only and are therefore translated as traces (i.e. individual variables) with
‘t’. Offending constellations are underlined. Furthermore, nodes are labelled to guar-
antee better orientation in the tree even though, strictly speaking, DS is categorially
underspecified.
In (a), the object has shifted over the subject at DS, landing in a position above TP.
Subsequent VP-fronting in (b) alters the hierarchical relations between the object
and its copies, as the TP-adjoined occurrence of every student no longer c-commands
the copy inside the higher occurrence of VP. As a result, constellation (b) violates
the UC:
On current assumptions, determiners are translated as bare individual variables (d). Hence, the UC
is a c-command condition on copies, and not on variables. This is interesting because it is usually believed
that the Proper Binding Condition and other generalizations about remnant movement can be reduced
to conditions on licit variable binding configurations (‘a variable needs to be bound at LF/throughout the
derivation’). If the UC is on the right track, it falsifies ‘conditions on variables’-style analyses.
Lechner
() … and [vP teach every student], no one will (¬∃ > ∀/ ∗ ∀ > ¬∃)
a.
every studentli TP
no oneli
T0[nom] vP
not
v0[acc] VP
teach
every studentli
covert, wide DS movement
b.
vP TP
every
studentli TP
not teach
every studentli no oneli vP
not VP
teach
every studentli
overt vP-fronting
Harmonic Derivationalism
Observe also that a minimal variant of (), not depicted here, in which the object
starts as a determiner (every) and the restrictor (student) is late merged above vP
abides by the UC but is excluded by the Case requirement (c), because objects have
to be assigned Case within vP.
() illustrated that complete copies created by movement need to preserve
c-command relations. Evidently, what applies to the object should also hold for the
subject. That is, one is led to expect that if the DP to be carried along by predi-
cate fronting is a subject copy, the base position (Spec,vP) can be filled by the bare
determiner, inducing Late Merge in Spec,TP, but not by the fully assembled DP. The
derivation in () demonstrates that this prediction leads to important, empirically
verifiable consequences.
Suppose that at DS, the object does not cross over the subject but undergoes short
movement only, adjoining to what will later, in syntax, become vP (a). Given this
alternative parse, VP-fronting may target the highest vP segment in (b), remov-
ing the complication which afflicted (b). In (b), the object no longer enters
into ambiguous c-command relations with its copies. However, as can also be seen
from (b), the UC now penalizes the chain created by subject raising, because the
c-command relations for the subject are disrupted by VP-fronting.
() a. TP
no oneli
T0[nom] vP
every studentli vP
no oneli
v0[acc] VP
teach
every studentli
local DS movement
Wholesale Late Merge of restrictors is licensed by Case. This entails that if LI is to apply at DS, a
level which by definition lacks syntactic features such as Case, the Case requirement must be satisfied
retroactively, in overt syntax. A simple way to implement retroactive licensing is to instruct overt syntax
that all complete DP copies reside within the c-command domain of their Case assigner.
Lechner
b.
vP TP
no oneli teach
every studentli
It follows that the only way for the derivation to abide by the UC is to merge only the
determiner in Spec,vP, and to add the restrictor of the subject late, in Spec,TP.
What is of particular importance for present purposes is the fact that applying the
UC to subjects derives the generalization that in contexts of predicate fronting, the
unattested inverse scope order cannot be generated by subject reconstruction below
the object. Specifically, it must be ensured that at LF, which closely resembles (a),
the scope of the subject is not read off its lowest copy. Otherwise, the subject could
be assigned narrow scope with respect to the object, which resides in the lowest type-
compatible node for quantifiers. The UC weeds out such configurations, though, by
requiring that the Spec,vP initially starts as a determiner only. From this it follows that
the subject cannot reconstruct below the object in syntax. Thus, the analysis derives
the fact that unattested scope inversion with predicate fronting cannot be produced
by subject reconstruction into Spec,vP.
The prohibition on inserting complete DPs into remnant-moved predicates has
another desirable consequence. Since bare D s always translate into individual vari-
ables (d), semantic reconstruction below the object is also blocked. Thus, the UC
accounts not only for the unavailability of wide object shift across the subject at DS but
also for the observation that subjects of fronted vPs do not reconstruct into their base
position, either in syntax or by SemR. A single principle accordingly derives both of
the two requirements which must be met by any successful analysis of scope freezing
with predicate fronting.
Finally, the trees in () document the derivation of the legitimate subject > object
scope order. As seen in (a), the object is fully assembled within VP, in accordance
with the Case condition (c), while the restrictor of the subject DP is late merged in
An interesting alternative proposal to restrict subject reconstruction in the same environments based
Spec,TP in order to avoid the conflict with the UC observed in (). In overt syntax,
the vP is fronted (b). Then, at LF, the object undergoes local type driven movement,
adjoining to vP. Subject reconstruction into Spec,vP is furthermore prohibited, as
Spec,vP is occupied by the determiner only. As a result, the analysis correctly predicts
that the derivation unambiguously generates the subject > object order.
() a. TP
no oneLI
T0[NOM] vP
not
v0[ACC] VP
teach
every studentLI
b.
vP TP
teach
every studentli
overt VP-fronting
Turning next to DP-reconstruction, recall that if a DP raises and reconstructs for the
evaluation of binding relations, the CEC admits the local de dicto interpretation, in
which the s-variable moves locally, as in (a), but blocks the constellation (b),
where the s-variable skips the closest possible landing site right below the intensional
operator (seem). Nodes subscripted by ‘PF’ signal spell-out positions, while ‘LF’ sub-
scripts denote reconstructed positions.
Lechner
tion at LF. Finally, the s-variable is locally moved in order to ensure interpretability
(c). Then, one obtains the legitimate narrow-scope reconstructed de dicto interpre-
tation for overtly moved DPs.
() a. [DP-s [seem [Îs … [DP-s …]] (no s-movement at DS)
b. [DP-s [seem [Îs … [DP-s …]]] (subject raising in overt syntax)
c. [DP-s [seem [Îs … [DP-s …]]]
(reconstruction and local s-movement at LF)
To summarize, the DS–LF model offers a natural analysis of phenomena which fall
under the descriptive generalization of the CEC. Silent operations can either apply
early in the derivation, at DS, in which case they may change scope orders and apply
long-distance, or they are delayed to LF, where they are subject to stricter locality
conditions, since as a ‘true’ interface, LF only admits local displacement that serves
the purpose of repairing type mismatches.
. Discussion
Although at this point the contours of a theory become visible, many details are still
missing and important questions need to be asked. I will briefly add a few clarifying
remarks.
First, even though parts of the procedure-fixing interpretation take place prior to
syntax, it is important to observe that the DS–LF model is not a variant of generative
semantics. This is so because all model-theoretic interpretation takes place in a single
component. DS merely contributes another set of restrictions on the possible shape
the logical syntax of natural language expressions can take. For instance, while scope
relations are represented at DS, where they are subject to conditions such as Scope
Economy, it is LF that prepares them for compositional interpretation. As a result,
overt movement can—unlike in theories advocated by generative semanticists—make
a difference to interpretive properties, e.g. by extending binding domains.
Second, one might wonder if DS and LF ever generate contradictory statements
about scope relations. Two questions are relevant here. Can a wide-scope DS—for
instance, a DS encoding inverse scope—end up as a narrow-scope LF? And can
There is a third logically possible derivation to be considered, in which the subject raises, either at DS
or overtly, followed by local movement of the s-variable and reconstruction of the DP.
(i) a. [DP-s … [seem … [DP-s …]]] (subject raising)
b. [Îs … [DP-s … [seem … [DP-s …]]]] (local s-movement)
c. [Îs … [seem … [DP-s …]]] (reconstruction)
This ‘Duke of York’ derivation (Lechner, to appear) is presumably blocked by the fact that s-movement
in (ib) would have to target both subject copies in order to ensure that the s-variable in the lower copy is
bound by Îs , too. This kind of Across-The-Board movement would be a hapax legomenon, though.
I am grateful to Rob Truswell for discussion of this and other issues addressed in this section.
Lechner
As () reveals, opacity is not an exception, but manifests itself in all cells of the matrix
generated by a model that packages information within and across components. This
finding supports the hypothesis that natural language is derivational in the strongest
possible way, as expressed by Harmonic Derivationalism in ():
() Harmonic Derivationalism
Natural language employs procedural signal manipulation and information
packaging within informationally encapsulated systems as well as across com-
ponents.
Late Merge of adjuncts (Lebeaux ) applies within syntax. Late Merge of restrictors across com-
ponents supplies DS representations with lexical content. These restrictors can be inserted high if the
determiner has moved within its Case domain, either at DS or in syntax.
Lechner
. Conclusion
I have proposed a new architecture of the grammar, in which overt syntax is pre-
ceded by a second, covert component, DS, that branches off to the grammar-external
deductive system (Fox ). DS hosts all non-local movement operations (among
them scope-shifting QR and long s-movement) which potentially have an impact
on truth-conditional interpretation. In the current model, it becomes possible to
assign the traditional repository of covert movement (LF) the role of a true inter-
face, whose function is restricted to rendering otherwise syntactically well-formed
representations afflicted by local type incompatibilities interpretable by the rules of
semantics.
The logical skeletons which DS operates on consist of logical, permutation-
invariant symbols and can be—but do not have to be—lexically impoverished. Under-
specified nodes are provided with lexical content by Wholesale Late Merge, either at
DS or in syntax. Admitting Late Merge both within and across components increases
the symmetry of the system by making optimal use of the Late Merge resource inde-
pendently used by the grammar.
Empirically, the DS–LF model provides a set of effective and comprehensive strate-
gies for the analysis of syntactic opacity effects. () repeats the main components of
the analyses from above. Recall that only (e) is new, and can probably be related to
independent properties of Case or the derivational system:
() a. Lexical Insertion can take place throughout the derivation, at DS or in overt
syntax. LI can in principle target any position of a chain.
b. Takahashi (): LI into a node · is admissible only if · is c-commanded
by its Case-assigning head.
c. Takahashi (, ): Non-lexicalized chain positions are filled by (possi-
bly silent) determiners. These positions are converted into individual traces.
d. All syntactic movement that does not take place at the LF interface observes
the Extension Condition. As a repair strategy, LF movement is exempt from
the cycle.
e. Uniformity Condition. If a node · is fully lexicalized, and · is the highest
node of a movement chain, · c-commands its lower occurrences throughout
the derivation.
Harmonic Derivationalism
Even though various aspects of the system look promising, this chapter has pre-
sented only an outline of a theory, with many details still to be added in the future.
For instance, the particular assumptions about how DS interacts with the grammar-
external deductive system and overt syntax will most likely turn out to be in need of
substantial revision. In the present chapter I have assumed that DS representations are
underspecified, so as to minimize changes in the interface from DS to the grammar-
external deductive systems. Other options are conceivable, though, as already alluded
to in section .. For instance, DS might operate on fully lexicalized terms throughout,
which are then stripped off during transfer to the deductive systems. Crucially, these
theoretical choices do not affect the main claim that scope-shifting silent movement
precedes overt syntax.
Also, various open questions remain, some of which have already emerged in
course of the discussion. What, for example, is the underlying explanation for the
UC, i.e. how does Case constrain remnant movement? In some sense, the UC has
the flavour of a condition which should ultimately fall out from the architecture of the
system, similar to the strict cycle condition. Another issue in need of clarification is
that the proper division of labour between DS and overt syntax must be made explicit.
Are optional movements such as scrambling, which are known to have an effect
on scope, computed in syntax, or pre-empted by DS? (See Lechner a for some
speculations.) At the moment, I have to defer answers to these and other questions to
future investigations into the nature of the DS–LF architecture.
Reconstruction, Control,
and Movement∗
ROBE RT T RU S W E L L
. Introduction
We currently suffer from an embarrassment of riches when confronting the proper
analysis of ‘reconstruction effects’, the term given to phenomena in which a con-
stituent is interpreted in a lower position than that in which it is pronounced. The
copy theory of movement (Chomsky , building on earlier work by Barss
among others) provides a minimal syntactic approach to reconstruction effects: there
is no operation of Reconstruction, but instead, simply variation in which copy of a
constituent is interpreted at LF. Complementing this is an approach to reconstruc-
tion effects based on higher-type traces, situated within Heim and Kratzer’s ()
approach to movement dependencies (e.g. Cresti ). On this approach, variation in
the type of trace derives reconstruction effects without any Reconstruction operation,
exploiting instead the power of the compositional semantic mechanism. Several other
possibilities also exist: reconstruction effects could arise as a result of a lowering
operation (May ), of PF-movement with no effect on LF (Sauerland and Elbourne
), of relativizing interpretation to chains rather than single positions (Barss ),
or of a distinct reconstruction relation (Sternefeld ). All of these fit within mod-
ern syntactic theory (some more naturally than others), and most can be distinguished
empirically (see e.g. Fox for arguments against an entirely semantic approach to
scope reconstruction).
Most Minimalists have settled on some combination of the first four options, with
questions remaining about the division of labour between them. Chomsky (: )
∗ Thanks to Caroline Heycock, Ray Jackendoff, Ad Neeleman, and two reviewers (one of whom self-
identified as Winnie Lechner), as well as audiences in Edinburgh, Oxford, and Ottawa, for comments on
these ideas in various stages of development. Portions of this material were first developed, but never pub-
lished, in Neeleman and Truswell (). Subsequent research was conducted as a postdoctoral associate
at Tufts University (–), and as a British Academy Postdoctoral Fellow at the University of Edinburgh
(–).
Reconstruction, Control, and Movement
account for trapping effects, and can capture the balance between trapping and
countertrapping.
In what follows, section . demonstrates the existence of reconstruction across one
non-movement dependency, obligatory control. Section . compares reconstruc-
tion across obligatory control dependencies to the countertrapping effects observed
by Lechner () in A-scrambling and extraction from weak islands. Section .
addresses the balance between trapping and countertrapping effects. Section .
concludes.
The arguments that obligatory control exhibits scope reconstruction were initially presented in Neele-
islands. If every window must scope under forgot in (i), it would provide further evidence that QR out of
control complements is unavailable.
(i) John forgot to close every window.
My intuition broadly concurs with this prediction. However, here, as elsewhere, emphasis can lead to freer
scope possibilities.
(ii) John forgot to close Every Single Window!
(forgot > ∀, ∀ > forgot)
Pending better understanding of this interaction, it is prudent not to read too much into (i).
Reconstruction, Control, and Movement
A natural hypothesis would be that the controller can take scope in the embed-
ded clause because of the dependency between the controller and pro, the empty
subject of the embedded clause. For example, we could adopt the Movement The-
ory of Control (Hornstein , Boeckx, Hornstein, and Nunes ), according
to which obligatory control is a species of A-movement, distinguished by the fact
that it targets a Ë-position in the matrix clause, rather than a Case position (see ()
above). The possibility of scope inversion in sentences like () would then result from
scope reconstruction across an A-movement dependency, plus whatever mechanism
is responsible for local scope inversion (for Hornstein, a combination of vP-internal
subjects and object shift, as in ()).
However, there are grounds for scepticism concerning the Movement Theory of
Control, as discussed in Culicover and Jackendoff (), Landau (, ),
and elsewhere. Without going too far into the details of this ongoing debate, the
major arguments centre around similarities and differences between the grammatical
dependencies underpinning A-movement and many obligatory control relations. A
large number of differences between the properties of the two types of dependency
have now been documented, militating against a reduction of obligatory control to
A-movement.
Firstly, subject control predicates such as promise notoriously violate minimality
constraints on controller choice. Under normal circumstances, pro is controlled by
the closest c-commanding argument: the matrix object if there is one, and the matrix
subject if not.
() a. Johni wanted [proi to blow up the bridge]
b. Johni persuaded Billyj [proj/∗ i to blow up the bridge]
However, promise allows the subject to control pro, despite the presence of an inter-
vening object ().
() Johni promised Billyj [proi/∗ j to blow up the bridge]
Boeckx and Hornstein () attempt to capitalize on this by pointing to the periph-
eral nature of subject control verbs in the grammar of English: they are acquired
late, and informal surveys suggest that they are often not acquired at all. For
Boeckx and Hornstein, then, the exceptional non-locality of subject control depen-
dencies is reflected in their late acquisition and omissibility from the grammar of
English. However, an irreducible difference remains between locality of obligatory
control and of regular A-movement: the locality constraints on A-movement are
absolute, while those constraining obligatory control are a matter of markedness,
and show some variability in controller choice (a phenomenon known as control
shift).
This is most clearly seen, again, with verbs like promise. In (), the subject controls
pro, while in (), following Hust and Brame (), the object controls pro.
() Johni promised Billyj [pro#i/j to be allowed to blow up the bridge]
Truswell
There are also cases, like (), where the antecedent of an A-trace is not the closest
c-commanding NP.
() a. Billyi strikes me as ti weird.
b. Billyi seems to me ti to be losing the plot.
However, these cases have very different properties from the variable control exhibited
by promise. The experiencer argument of strike or seem is never a landing site for A-
movement. This might indicate that the experiencer does not enter into the calculation
of locality in English A-movement dependencies. If so, an analysis can be main-
tained on which the antecedent of an A-trace is the closest c-commanding potential
antecedent. However, such an analysis will not work for promise: () demonstrates
that the object of promise is a potential antecedent of pro, but that antecedent is
nevertheless skipped in the subject control construction in ().
These considerations weigh against a movement-based analysis, building on Lar-
son (), in which the object of promise is inaccessible as a landing site for some
reason. Even if such an analysis were tenable for promise in the general case, it
would fail to explain the discrepancy between raising (which always targets a unique
designated landing site) and control (which exhibits variability in cases like ()
and ()).
In contrast, thematically based theories of controller choice (Jackendoff ,
Farkas , Sag and Pollard , Jackendoff and Culicover ) predict that subject
control exists, and predict which predicates exhibit this exceptional pattern. Such
theories propose that the control properties of a predicate directly reflect its thematic
properties: very roughly, the exceptional control behaviour of promise is related to
the fact that if X promises Y to V, X is committed to bringing about an instance of
V-ing, while if X persuades Y to V, it is Y who comes to have such a commitment.
The controller is the person who is committed to the V-ing, and exceptional cases
of object-control promise can be accommodated as instances of coercion. To the
extent that there is no uniform syntactic representation of such commitments, the
theory of control is also independent of particular syntactic structures, and the fact
that such dependencies do not share the properties of A-movement dependencies is
unsurprising.
Thematic theories of control are also corroborated if control properties, stated
in thematic terms, remain invariant when a predicate appears in different syn-
tactic configurations. Culicover and Jackendoff demonstrate such invariance in
These statements are all complicated by the consideration of dative intervention effects in A-movement.
However, even here, there is an irreducible difference between control and movement: Beaven () shows
that dative intervention constrains A-movement to different extents in different languages, but there are no
dative intervention effects in obligatory control in any language Beaven examined.
Reconstruction, Control, and Movement
Moreover, examples like those in () suggest that c-command is not a necessary condition on the
relationship between controller and controllee, casting further doubt on the analysis of obligatory control as
a species of grammatical dependency. This doubt is perhaps strengthened by examples such as The promise
to leave, where the same person is the agent of promise and leave. However, the latter data, at least, are
amenable to analysis in terms of a null subject of promise.
Landau () discusses ‘partial control’ at length (The director decided pro to meet at , with pro
interpreted as referring to the director and others). However, partial control does not so much invalidate
the claim that the controller is unique as refine our notion of what it means to be a unique controller.
Truswell
It seems, then, that the configuration of pro and controller is regulated by a gram-
matical dependency in complement control constructions, but that this dependency
is independent of the mechanisms underlying controller choice, which are also active
in cases (particularly control in nominals) where there is no evidence of a grammat-
ical dependency. Such a bipartite system is defended by Landau (), who pro-
poses a series of Agree relations between heads in complement control constructions,
partially independent of the lexicosemantic factors determining controller choice.
Although we do not need to follow the specifics of his implementation, we must adopt
this separation of the grammatical dependency from factors relating to controller
choice.
This raises the question of whether scope reconstruction is contingent on this
grammatical dependency or on the thematic control relation. The evidence points
to the former. We have seen, for example, that obligatory control in nominals is not
accompanied by a grammatical dependency. And unlike obligatory control in clauses,
there is no long-distance scope inversion in such cases.
() a. Someone tried to read every book in the library. (∃ > ∀, ∀ > ∃)
b. Someone’s attempt to read every book in the library.
(∃ > ∀,∗ ∀ > ∃)
Likewise, there is no scope inversion in cases of non-obligatory control, where there is
widespread agreement (e.g. Williams ) that there is no grammatical dependency.
() To read every book in the library would be nice for someone.
(∃ > ∀,∗ ∀ > ∃)
The presence of scope reconstruction in obligatory control constructions is tied to the
grammatical dependency, then, rather than the control relation.
More remarkably, such scope reconstruction effects are not accompanied by bind-
ing reconstruction effects, as far as we can tell. Straightforward testing of the bind-
ing principles is marred by various confounds (for Condition A, it is impossible
to tell whether a reflexive in the embedded clause is bound by the reconstructed
If this is accurate, it undermines a reviewer’s suggestion that scope reconstruction across obligatory
control dependencies could be handled by a higher-type pro, analogous to the higher-type traces of Cresti
(). There are independent grounds for scepticism about this suggestion: a major difference between
Cresti’s cases and obligatory control constructions is that two distinct Ë-roles are implicated in obligatory
control, which significantly complicates the statement of a compositional semantics involving a higher-type
pro. Regardless of this, though, if there is a pro in nominal, as well as verbal, obligatory control, then the
availability of a higher-type pro would make scope reconstruction equally available in either case, contrary
to fact.
Reconstruction, Control, and Movement
scope below want is unavailable, we conclude that scope reconstruction into wh-
islands is not possible.
() How many books do you wonder whether Chris wants to buy? (many > want,
∗ want > many)
a. ‘There are three books that I wonder whether Chris wants to buy: Dubliners,
Ulysses, and Finnegans Wake.’
b. ∗ ‘I wonder whether Chris might be interested in buying three books, but
I don’t particularly care whether Chris might be interested in buying two
books or four books.’
Combining these two findings gives a pair of examples in which the requirement that
a many-phrase takes high scope (because there is no scope reconstruction into a weak
island) bleeds the possibility of a pronoun being interpreted within the weak island,
a variant on classical trapping effects.
() a. Every boy must see five pictures from the teacher’s childhood before he can
go home. The teacher must oversee this process, but hasn’t paid attention,
so he is now unsure who has seen which pictures.
Question: How many pictures from hisi childhood does the teacheri need
to know whether every boy has seen?
b. Every boy must see five pictures from his own childhood before he can go
home. The teacher must oversee this process, but hasn’t paid attention, so he
is now unsure who has seen which pictures.
Question: ∗ How many pictures from hisi childhood does the teacher need
to know whether every boyi has seen?
Extraction from weak islands therefore shows the opposite pattern to Mittelfeld scram-
bling or complement control: binding reconstruction is possible, but scope recon-
struction is not. Scope reconstruction and binding reconstruction are therefore dou-
bly dissociable.
The next question is how to account for this. Lechner’s approach is to make use
of two different technologies for capturing reconstruction effects, and associate each
type of effect with a different technology. Binding reconstruction would then be tied
to copy-theoretic Syntactic Reconstruction, while scope reconstruction would be tied
to the use of higher-type traces, as in Cresti () (Semantic Reconstruction). The
implication is that a theory of the distribution of the two types of reconstruction
technology gives a theory of the distribution of the two types of reconstruction effect.
Lechner’s approach is adequate in principle to capture the data he describes.
However, both of his technologies crucially implicate a movement relation. The
demonstration in section . that reconstruction effects exist without movement
dependencies therefore leads us to consider a different approach. In fact, I will suggest
Truswell
that neither of the constructions Lechner describes involves actual movement, but that
both constructions, like complement control, bear similarities to movement relations.
We begin to investigate this possibility by comparing complement control and
Mittelfeld scrambling. Both have the same reconstruction profile: they allow scope
reconstruction, but not binding reconstruction. Moreover, in both cases there are
reasons to suspect that the grammatical dependency in question is not an instance
of movement. For complement control, this has already been discussed above; for
scrambling to the Mittelfeld, I refer the reader to Bayer and Kornfilt (), Neeleman
(), Neeleman and Weerman (), and Fanselow (, ). All of these
researchers propose that the relation between a predicate and a scrambled argument
is direct, rather than mediated by a trace or copy. For Neeleman, and Neeleman
and Weerman, for example, Ë-roles are encoded as dependencies of a verb on its
arguments, and those dependencies form a record of which argument bears which
role. Instead of the movement approach, then, where the intended interpretation is
recovered by virtue of a dependency between a scrambled argument and a trace in
that argument’s Ë-position, Neeleman’s system recovers largely equivalent information
by virtue of a dependency between a scrambled argument and a member of a Ë-
grid.
Nevertheless, both control and scrambling relations share many properties with
movement: all three dependencies require a unique, obligatory antecedent, which
locally c-commands the dependent. Following Koster (), I take these to be the
core properties of grammatical dependencies. For the remainder of this chapter, I will
Winfried Lechner (p.c.) suggests the following argument that scrambling configurations must be
derived by movement. Pair-list readings of wh-questions only arise if a quantifier c-commands the wh-
trace (May , Aoun and Li , Chierchia , Beck b).
(i) a. Which student did John give every book to t? (pair-list)
b. Which book did John give t to every student? (single pair)
The same facts occur in German, despite the fact that German, unlike English, allows scrambling (Lechner
cites Pafel in this connection).
(ii) a. Welches Buch hat Peter jedem Studenten empfohlen?
which book has Peter every.dat student.dat recommended
‘Which book did Peter recommend to every student?’ (pair-list)
b. Welchem Studenten hat Peter jedes Buch empfohlen?
which student has Peter every.acc book.acc recommended
‘Which book did Peter recommend to every student?’ (single pair)
This is surprising if German scrambling allows internal arguments to freely permute; less so if the indirect
object must always c-command the direct object or a trace thereof. However, an alternative interpretation of
these facts is that A-scrambling bleeds A -movement: A -movement cannot apply to an A-scrambled con-
stituent and disrupt the marked, scrambled order of internal arguments. Motivation for such a constraint
can be found in the discussion of scrambling and information structure in Neeleman and van de Koot
(), orthogonal to the question of whether A-scrambling leaves a trace. This evidence for scrambling as
a movement relation therefore seems to me inconclusive.
Reconstruction, Control, and Movement
assume that neither complement control nor scrambling to the Mittelfeld represent
instances of movement, but that (like movement) they are instances of grammatical
dependencies. This is partly for the independent reasons given in the references
above, and partly because complement control and Mittelfeld scrambling do not
show the same reconstruction effects as movement. Movement allows reconstruction
for both scope and binding, while complement control and short scrambling only
show scope reconstruction effects. If we were to analyse complement control and
Mittelfeld scrambling as instances of movement, we would have to find some auxiliary
explanation for the absence of binding reconstruction effects, and I, personally, don’t
see where to start.
We may then ask how movement is different from other grammatical dependen-
cies. Given Koster’s characterization of grammatical dependencies, as used repeatedly
above, the major extra property of movement is that it relates positions which share
a thematic role (to be understood, if necessary, in an extended sense that encom-
passes adjunct ‘participant roles’). In contrast, the antecedent and dependent in a
complement control relation bear different thematic roles, while the dependent in
a base-generated scrambling relation is a predicate (a Ë-role assigner), rather than an
argument.
We can represent these distinctions, in the spirit (if not the letter) of proposals in
Neeleman and van de Koot (), by thinking about the grammatical dependencies
introduced by the elements in these constructions. A Ë-role assigner is dependent
on the Ë-role assignee, whether that argument is a sister of the predicate (as in non-
scrambling constructions) or asymmetrically c-commands it (as in scrambling con-
structions). A trace is dependent on an antecedent with which it shares a Ë-role, while
pro is dependent on a controller which bears a distinct Ë-role. We represent these
three types of dependency as species of the general class of grammatical dependency,
abbreviated as Dep in ().
The claim is more controversial for A-movement. Following May (), some scope reconstruction
effects clearly obtain, often analysed as instances of Quantifier Lowering (Chomsky , , Boeckx
b). Meanwhile, some potential Condition C violations fail to occur under reconstruction, which is
sometimes taken to indicate an absence of binding reconstruction effects (Fox ), apparently contra-
dicted by prima facie cases of reconstruction for Condition A (Takahashi and Hulsey ). The empirical
picture is still somewhat unclear and inconsistent, but I will assume that A-movement can reconstruct for
scope and binding, just like A -movement, with apparent failures of binding reconstruction to be explained
by independent factors, along the lines of the above references. If this turns out to be incorrect, alternative
theories of A-movement can be envisaged which are compatible with the approach being developed here.
In (), simplifying aspects of Neeleman and van de Koot () which are irrelevant to us, a
constituent marked with Dep introduces a dependency, while a constituent marked with Dep# satisfies
that dependency. A constituent subscripted with Dep# satisfies that dependency. Subscripted Ëi and Ëj are
diacritics to identify which constituents share or do not share a Ë-role.
This ‘bottom-up’ approach to dependencies, inherited from Neeleman and van de Koot as well as HPSG
and other frameworks, is the reverse of the standard probe–goal Agree configuration. I leave it as an open
question how much of the present approach could be translated into Agree-based terms.
Truswell
C, unlike Condition A, are ‘everywhere’ conditions, which must be obeyed in every relevant position. It is
straightforward to adjust this if it should turn out that Lebeaux’s analysis is inaccurate, and that Fox ()
was correct to locate all binding-theoretic effects at LF. I make no different predictions from those of anyone
else in this respect.
Reconstruction, Control, and Movement
weak island can be A -bound by an operator outside the island. According to such a
hypothesis, all A -dependencies crossing weak island boundaries are base-generated.
As is well known, binding relations do not behave like grammatical dependencies: for
example, the antecedent need not c-command the dependent.
() a. [[Every boy]i ’s mother] loves himi .
b. I danced [with [every boy]i ] on hisi birthday.
If extraction from a weak island is a base-generated binding relation, it is not a gram-
matical relation. On the hypothesis outlined in (), we would then predict an absence
of scope reconstruction. However, in a base-generated A -binding configuration, the
Ë-criterion insists that Wh and pro share a Ë-role, as Wh is never in a Ë-position. Again
according to (), then, we expect that binding reconstruction will be displayed.
There is much scope for future research along these lines. Postulation of pro at
the foot of an A -chain has the effect of making extraction from weak islands look
like an instance of null resumption, as mentioned by both reviewers. A recent strand
of research has concentrated on interactions between island-sensitivity and recon-
struction in a variety of resumptive constructions across languages (Aoun and Ben-
mamoun , Aoun, Choueiri, and Hornstein , Aoun and Li , Guilliot
and Malkawi , , , Rouveret ). Typically (see in particular Rouveret
, and Guilliot and Malkawi ), differences among resumptive constructions
in these respects are cashed out in terms of a typology of pronominal elements, itself
derived from independent research into the syntax and semantics of pronominals,
such as the distinction between e-type and bound readings (Evans , Elbourne
). A logical next step for this research would therefore be to situate these claims
about reconstruction into weak islands, with respect to this typology of resumptive
elements.
There are many competing analyses of extraction from weak islands, and I have
no new evidence directly supporting the A -bound pro analysis over any competitors.
Equally, I cannot presently explain why particular reconstruction effects are tied to
This is actually Cinque’s analysis of strong islands, which (on his definition) can only be escaped by
NP. Weak islands, such as the wh-islands described above, can be escaped by NP or PP. Adapting Cinque’s
ideas in this way therefore has consequences for locality theory, which I have not presently investigated.
Similar questions arise concerning the syntax and semantics of copy-raising, in which two A-positions
are related and the lower position is occupied by a pronoun. Fujii () demonstrates limited binding
reconstruction, without scope reconstruction, in copy-raising sentences. However, Asudeh and Toivonen
() demonstrate that even the full range of binding reconstruction effects is not attested. (Asudeh and
Toivonen is a pre-publication version of Asudeh and Toivonen . The relevant discussion was
omitted from the published version.) Clearly, more research is needed to reconcile the two sets of facts.
A further interesting piece of theoretical housekeeping for the future concerns the integration of this
line of research with the claims of Takahashi and Hulsey (). Their combination of wholesale late merger
and trace conversion has the effect of rendering many copies indistinguishable from pronouns. Given that
the resumptive literature assumes that pronouns at the foot of chains are independently necessary, it is
natural to ask how much of Takahashi and Hulsey’s analysis can be reformulated using pronouns instead
of copies.
Truswell
particular relations in the way I have suggested. However, I believe that the dissocia-
tion of scope reconstruction from binding reconstruction in this way has a good deal
of promise. Lechner’s double dissociation shows that reconstruction effects are not
a monolithic class, although there is a clear tendency in GB and Minimalism to treat
them as such. A major property of copy-theoretic approaches to reconstruction effects
is that, all else being equal, they treat all reconstruction effects as being of a piece,
and this dissociation should cast doubt on that project. On the other hand, Lechner’s
own analysis of the double dissociation is still closely tied to movement dependencies,
and the foregoing considerations should call this into question.
On the present approach, reconstruction effects are not limited to movement rela-
tions, and this appears to be accurate. However, movement does retain a privileged
position in the taxonomy of reconstruction effects: movement is unique in that it is
a grammatical dependency which relates positions which share a Ë-role, as a mat-
ter of definition according to (). According to (), then, only movement should
display both scope and binding reconstruction effects: there is ‘more reconstruction’
in movement dependencies than anywhere else. However, Lechner’s double disso-
ciation is also predicted, as a consequence of the independence of the two types of
reconstruction.
Disregarding this traditional conception of LF, there are two major possibilities:
either different types of relation are represented at different levels, or they are rep-
resented at a single level, in such a way as to allow the representation of scope and
binding more autonomy than in traditional LFs, for example by defining multiple
types of chain over surface representations. Neither of these options suffers from the
problem just described for traditional LFs, because in each case, the position in which
a phrase takes scope does not automatically guarantee that a phrase can enter into
binding relations from that position, or vice versa.
To choose between these two options, we must decide how independent scope
reconstruction and binding reconstruction are from each other. To assign dif-
ferent phenomena to different levels of representation is an analytical move
reflecting a hypothesis that the phenomena in question are encapsulated from
each other. Representing them at the same level predicts that they will interact
directly.
In fact, a demonstration that scope reconstruction and binding reconstruction
interact substantially was given as early as May (), concerning ‘trapping effects’
such as ().
() a. Two people seem to be dancing with every senator.
(∃ > ∀, ∀ > ∃)
b. Two people seem to themselves to be dancing with every senator.
(∃ > ∀,∗ ∀ > ∃)
() shows that scope reconstruction interacts with binding: the fact that Two people
enters into binding relations in the matrix clause in (b) bleeds scope reconstruction
into the embedded clause.
The existence of trapping effects suggests a representation of scope and binding at
the same level: if we were to adopt the alternative, according to which scope relations
are determined at level L and binding relations are determined at a different level L ,
we would face the extra complexity of stating that the position of a constituent in L
constrains the position of the counterpart of that constituent in L , and vice versa.
The whole point of levels of representation is to avoid having to state such intricate
global similarities as these.
We must represent scope and binding at the same level, then, but that level should
not be LF in the traditional sense. As an alternative, I suggest a chain-based theory
of reconstruction, as in Barss (), or Aoun and Li (). Such approaches have
two main advantages, compared to approaches which treat reconstruction as the
inverse of movement, whether as lowering or as interpretation of lower copies. First,
chain-based approaches need not be so closely tied to movement, depending on
the definitions of ‘chain’ that we adopt. Secondly, the possibility exists of defining
multiple types of chain, and relating different types of chain to different types of
Truswell
reconstruction effect. This gives us the power to account for Lechner’s dissociations
between reconstruction effects.
We define the following, maintaining the agnosticism about the precise formulation
of the binding theory from footnote :
() a. X and Y are members of the same scope chain iff X and Y are related by a
grammatical dependency.
b. X and Y are members of the same binding chain iff X and Y share a Ë-role.
() a. X can take scope from the position of Y only if X and Y are members of the
same scope chain.
b. (i) An anaphor or bound variable X can be bound from the position of Y
only if X and Y are members of the same binding chain.
(ii) A pronoun or R-expression X must be locally free or free, respectively,
in the position of Y if X and Y are members of the same binding chain.
This means that the syntactic representation fed to the semantic component encodes
information about potential scope and binding relations, but this representation does
not unambiguously represent information about these relations, in contrast to stan-
dard assumptions about copy-theoretic LFs after deletion of uninterpreted copies (see
May for the original proposal that LF did not fully disambiguate scope and bind-
ing relations). However, no great problem arises from this: the information encoded in
a representation like the one sketched here determines predicate–argument relations,
as well as information on which elements may, or must not, be referentially depen-
dent on which other elements, and which elements may be in the scope of which
others.
Clearly, this is only an outline of a theory of reconstruction. Particular priorities for
the future are a sharpening of the definition of ‘scope chain’ in the light of the patterns
of fixed scope discovered by Aoun and Li () in double object constructions; an
investigation of ‘Lebeaux effects,’ or failures of Condition C reconstruction, within
these terms; and an expansion to further apparent cases of reconstruction without
movement, such as the pseudocleft connectivity discussed by Higgins () among
many others.
However, immediately, several analytical opportunities open up which are unavail-
able on other approaches. The system is designed to accommodate dissociations such
as those described by Lechner, which are so puzzling on more standard approaches.
Moreover, a promising treatment of movement as a composite relation emerges:
movement dependencies are simply simultaneously scope chains and binding chains,
or in other terms, grammatical dependencies which hold between elements which
share a Ë-role.
Reconstruction, Control, and Movement
Finally, the chains we propose, unlike standard chains, arguably respect Chomsky’s
() Inclusiveness principle, which states that syntactic properties of complex struc-
tures project from the lexicon. Chains normally violate this principle because they
involve annotation of syntactic structures with lexicon-external diacritics. However,
the present conception of scope chains and binding chains arguably escapes this
problem, because the information about chain membership, on this view, must be
recoverable from the syntactic structure in any case: we must know in any case which
syntactic dependencies hold in that structure, and which constituents share which
Ë-role. Given that scope chains are just syntactic dependencies and binding chains
are just shared Ë-roles, information about scope and binding chains is already implic-
itly represented in the structure. The explicit labelling of these relations as chains
is redundant, and carried out purely for expository clarity. There is no violation of
Inclusiveness in the fundamentals of the analysis being developed.
We can now return to the significance of trapping effects. The core of trapping
effects is that, if a constituent enters into binding relations in a given position, it also
takes scope in that position, and vice versa. That core is independent of the relation
of movement to reconstruction effects, and can be stated in the following way.
() The Trapping Generalization
Each constituent is interpreted in only one position.
However, we can now also state a further generalization concerning the distribution of
Lechner’s countertrapping effects, the dissociations discussed in section ., although
() is strictly superfluous, being implicit in the foregoing.
() The Countertrapping Generalization
Individual types of reconstruction can sometimes target more positions than
multiple cooccurring types of reconstruction.
The balance between these two generalizations is determined by the interaction of
scope chains and binding chains. To illustrate, let us begin by considering (). In
(), the story is essentially as in May (): the scope chain and binding chain of two
people each consist of the surface position and the trace position, and the constituent
can in principle be interpreted in either position. In the lower position, it can be
interpreted within the scope of every senator, so scope ambiguity is predicted, unless
Principle A forces two people to bind a reflexive from its surface position, as in (b).
Because of the Trapping Generalization, if the binding theory forces interpretation
of a constituent in a given position, that constituent must also take scope in that
position.
Essentially the same is true in (): the scope chain of two people contains the
surface position and pro. If two people may take scope from its surface position or
the position of pro, scope ambiguity arises, as in (a). However, if it must bind a
Truswell
reflexive from its surface position, as in (b), then it must also take scope from its
surface position, and the scope ambiguity disappears.
() a. Two people want to dance with every senator.
(∃ > ∀, ∀ > ∃)
b. Two people have persuaded themselves to dance with every senator.
(∃ > ∀,∗ ∀ > ∃)
Where raising and complement control differ is in the nature of their binding chains:
binding chains are determined by thematic relations. The trace of a raised con-
stituent shares a Ë-role, and so a binding chain, with its antecedent, while pro and its
antecedent have distinct Ë-roles, and are therefore not members of the same binding
chain.
This distinction is reflected in the possibility of being bound from the foot of
the chain. The examples in (), repeated from (), demonstrate this. (a) shows
that a raised reflexive can be bound in its base position, while (b) shows that a
reflexive contained within a controller cannot be bound in the position of pro. This
is as expected if raising dependencies are binding chains but control dependencies
are not.
() a. Stories about himself appear to have upset every senator.
b. ∗ Stories about himself have managed to upset every senator.
Likewise, because a binding chain can cross a weak island but a scope chain cannot,
a failure of scope reconstruction into a weak island can bleed binding possibilities
within the weak island (see () above).
We see, then, that the Trapping Generalization, as formulated in () without ref-
erence to movement, is all that is necessary to capture trapping effects, but something
like the distinction between scope chains and binding chains is required to capture the
cases described by the Countertrapping Generalization: the Trapping Generalization
forces scope chains and binding chains to interact to determine a single locus of
interpretation for each element, but scope reconstruction is possible to positions that
binding reconstruction cannot touch, and vice versa, because of the non-identity of
scope chains and binding chains.
It follows as a theorem from this approach to trapping and countertrapping that
dissociations such as Lechner’s will only be found in non-movement constructions,
because scope chains and binding chains always coincide in movement dependencies.
This approach therefore rests on the correctness of theories of complement control,
scrambling, and extraction from weak islands as base-generated. Only time will tell
whether such theories are tenable, but the prize, if they can be made to work, is a
theory of the distribution of trapping and countertrapping effects, an account of cases
of reconstruction without movement, and a new reductionist approach to movement
relations.
Reconstruction, Control, and Movement
. Conclusion
The major aim of this chapter has been to sketch a theory of reconstruction effects
which takes dissociations between those effects seriously, while still allowing for inti-
mate interactions between different types of reconstruction, such as trapping effects.
Dissociating reconstruction effects involves relating each to a different type of relation
(syntactic in one case, purely thematic in the other), while capturing the interactions
involves representing those two types of relation at the same level. Finally, the con-
sideration of two different types of relation makes it natural to consider movement
relations as the cooccurrence of the syntactic and thematic relation.
This approach suggests several immediate avenues for exploration. Of course, there
is much work to do in sharpening this analysis beyond the outline given here. Hand
in hand with this comes the requirement that the general validity of the approach be
demonstrated, by showing that it at least does not damage our current understanding
of other patterns of scope and binding relations, and other types of reconstruction
effect. Perhaps most intriguing, though, are the implications for the general theory
of grammar. One major reason for the adoption of the copy theory of movement in
Chomsky () and much subsequent work is that it allows for a natural treatment
of reconstruction effects, building on work on ‘layered traces’ in Barss () and
elsewhere. However, there has been a degree of unanswered criticism of the copy
theory (see Neeleman and van de Koot and references therein). Moreover,
Neeleman and van de Koot have also demonstrated the invalidity of claims that copy
theory is indispensable to the Minimalist analysis of movement dependencies, given
the existence of alternative Minimalist approaches to movement, such as lexicalized
traces. The present chapter reinforces Neeleman and van de Koot’s criticisms, by
demonstrating that an approach such as the copy theory, which ties reconstruction
effects to movement, fails to capture all instances of reconstruction effects. Both
putative advantages of the copy theory are therefore called into question, while the
criticisms of that theory remain unanswered. This chapter therefore lends support to
the programme of developing non-copy-theoretic forms of Minimalism (Brody ,
Neeleman and van de Koot ).
. Introduction
Syntax creates sound–meaning pairs. Within Chomskyan generative grammar, this
is typically described in terms of transferring (portions of) syntactic structures to
the phonological/phonetic and semantic/conceptual interfaces through PF and LF,
respectively. However, to paraphrase Chomsky and Halle (), whether the output
of the syntactic component and the input of the phonological component are the
same thing is an empirical issue. (The same, of course, holds for the semantic side.)
Indeed, since work by Selkirk and others during the early s, much work on the
syntax–phonology interface has focused on how to derive phonological domains from
syntactic structures under the assumption that these two representations are related
but non-isomorphic. This issue of domains is, however, but one piece of the much
larger puzzle of how to characterize the transformations at PF which turn hierarchical,
phonology-free morphosyntactic structures into linear phonological representations.
Within the Distributed Morphology framework, Harley and Noyer (), Embick
and Noyer (), and more recently Embick (), Samuels (), Arregi and
Nevins (), and Idsardi and Raimy () have argued that PF comprises a number
of crucially ordered operations which serve to introduce, concatenate, and group
phonological content while reducing the dimensionality of the syntactic representa-
tion. The goal of the present chapter is to further our understanding of the syntax–
phonology interface by considering the interplay of linearization, copy deletion, and
vocabulary insertion within a model which assumes multiple transfer, the copy the-
ory of movement, and direct correspondence between phonological and syntactic
domains.
The specific case study that we will focus on relates to what we will call ‘empty
edges’: phonologically contentless edges of certain domains. Whether to characterize
∗ The authors would like to thank audiences at Syracuse University, the University of Oslo, OnLI II at
the University of Ulster, and GLOW . We are also grateful to the editors of this volume, as well as Artemis
Alexiadou and two anonymous reviewers for their helpful comments.
Linearizing Empty Edges
() a. ?∗ I saw the train yesterday [CP ∅ ∅ [IP Mary was waiting for]]
b. I saw the train yesterday [CP ∅ that [IP Mary was waiting for]]
c. ?∗ I saw the child yesterday [CP ∅ ∅ [IP Mary was waiting for]]
d. I saw the child yesterday [CP who ∅ [IP Mary was waiting for]]
While it has long been known that an overt C (b) can ameliorate a sentence like
(a), An points out that filling Spec,CP can also license a postposed relative clause,
as in (d).
The paradigm in () is not the only one where an empty edge seems to be associated
with degradation. The following examples illustrate that we find such cases in many
environments.
() a. I believe very strongly [CP that [IP John liked linguistics]]
b. ∗ I believe very strongly [CP ∅ [IP John liked linguistics]]
(An a: )
() a. [CP That [IP the teacher was lying]], Ben already knew.
b. ∗ [CP ∅ [IP the teacher was lying]], Ben already knew.
(Stowell )
() a. I distrust [NP the claim [CP that [IP Bill had left the party]]]
b. ∗ I distrust [NP the claim [CP ∅ [IP Bill had left the party]]]
(Stowell )
() a. Mary believed that Peter finished school and Bill, [CP that [IP Peter got a job]]
b. Mary believed that Peter finished school and Bill, [CP ∅ [IP Peter got a job]]
(Bošković and Lasnik )
The question is, what renders these sentences with phonologically empty CP-edges
unacceptable? For some of the cases above, the adjunct yesterday or very strongly seems
like the obvious culprit; for example, () and () differ only in the presence or absence
of such an adjunct. But that does not account for the data we just presented in ()–().
Nor is CP the only category involved in this phenomenon: unacceptability correlated
with empty edges also extends to other phrases, including vP (), DP (), and AP ().
() a. Eat the cake John did and eat the cookie Mary did.
b. ∗ [vP Eat the cake] John did and [∅spec ∅v the cookie] Mary did.
() a. John likes this book of linguistics and Mary, that book of physics.
b. ∗ John likes this book of linguistics and Mary, [∅spec ∅D book of physics]
() a. Eager to win the Pulitzer Prize, John is, and eager to win the Nobel Prize,
Mary is.
b. ∗ [AP Eager to win the Pulitzer Prize], John is, and [∅spec ∅A to win the Nobel
Prize, Mary is]
Linearizing Empty Edges
Based on these facts, An (a: ) argues for the following generalization:
() Intonational Phrase Edge Generalization (IPEG)
The edge of an I-phrase cannot be empty (where the notion of edge encom-
passes the specifier and the head of the relevant syntactic constituent).
Let us provide some background. For Selkirk (), an I-phrase is a sequence of pitch
accents that are flanked by a boundary tone or pause. Nespor and Vogel () observe
that grammatically related pauses coincide with the end of an I-phrase. Specifically,
Nespor and Vogel () argue that certain constituent types are obligatorily (and
cross linguistically) parsed as I-phrases. These include root clauses, parentheticals,
tag questions, vocatives, non-restrictive relative clauses, and some moved elements
(Selkirk , , , Nespor and Vogel , Bošković , An a).
An (a) argues that all the environments above where we have seen empty
edges being impermissible are contexts in which the phrase with the empty edge is
obligatorily parsed as a separate I-phrase. An attempts to rationalize this by adopting
the following assumptions (see An a: and references cited there):
() a. I-phrasing must occur at the juncture between two prosodic words.
b. I-phrases are isomorphic with syntactic constituents that are obligatorily
parsed as I-phrases.
c. Prosodic words can be informally defined as phonologically independent
words that bear stress.
Consider the case where the edge of an obligatory I-phrase domain—for the sake of
concreteness, the edge of a CP—is phonologically null. The third assumption pre-
vents phonologically null elements from building prosodic words, and by the first
assumption, only prosodic words can host an I-phrase boundary. The first prosodic
word, and hence the first context eligible to host an I-phrase boundary, will be located
somewhere within IP. However, the second assumption says that the edge of the CP—
the obligatory I-phrase domain—should coincide with the I-phrase boundary. Thus,
a CP with only null elements in its edge creates a mismatch between the syntactic
domain and the prosodic domain, producing a deviant sentence.
Thus far, we have only discussed what happens when the left edge of an I-phrase
is empty. In other work, An (b: ) proposes a symmetrical alternative to the
IPEG that addresses what is permissible at both the left and right edges by adding
the additional condition that only null elements, not unpronounced copies, trigger
violations:
() The Ban On Null Edge (BONE)
If a clause is parsed as a separate I-phrase, its left and right boundary positions
cannot be occupied by phonologically empty elements, where the phonological
emptiness stems from non-insertion of phonological content.
Lohndal and Samuels
The dichotomy between traces/copies and other null elements is necessary given that
sentences like (), with right edges that have been evacuated via movement, are
acceptable.
() [CP Who did Mary [vP see [VP see who]]]
This raises the question of which interface condition should be preferred, given that
the two appear to be extensionally equivalent due to the distribution of null elements
and traces/copies: a general but asymmetrical statement like the IPEG, or a symmet-
rical one which is more restricted like the BONE? We will provide an alternative to
both: a symmetry-preserving solution under which the distinction between copies
and null elements follows from the order of operations at the interface.
[The current approach] suggests a partial answer to the conceptual question why specifier and
head are special in the syntax. Note that for a long time, it has been taken for granted that
the two positions enjoy a special relationship to each other, frequently instantiated as Spec–
head agreement. However, there may not be an a priori reason for this. For example, X-bar
geometrically, the relation between head and complement may in fact be regarded as closer
than that between specifier and head. However, the behavior of specifier and head with respect
to I-phrasing suggests that they are counted as a unit in PF. Of course, this is not an explanation.
However, from this point of view, it seems more natural that the specifier and the head enjoy
Linearizing Empty Edges
a close relationship to each other, because they are treated as one element at the interface.
(An a: )
provide a new account which locates the source of unacceptability in failed lineariza-
tion rather than the ECP or problematic intonation.
However, note that cases such as Will will come tomorrow show that the constraint cannot be formu-
lated solely in terms of phonological features. The fact that these two instances of will are separate lexical
items, or have different labels, seems to play a role here. This could suggest that it is a label, rather than EP,
which persists to mark an element’s position in the workspace.
Linearizing Empty Edges
will create problems for linearization, not copies. Similarly, reduplication occurs at a
later stage (following Raimy et seq.), so identical elements created through that
process are permitted.
The key component to our analysis is that the linearization algorithm only succeeds
in reducing the adjacency statements to a single ordered pair when the elements to
be linearized are distinct. If the elements are non-distinct, the derivation crashes at
that point. A special case of this is when two adjacent elements only have EPs: these
elements are non-distinct, so they will cause linearization to crash. We need to define,
then, exactly what features are present at the time of linearization, because this is what
determines the permissible configurations.
The conclusion and order of operations for which we argue accords with more
general observations about the effects of unpronounced copies and null elements
in morphophonology; see Samuels (: §.). The correct generalization seems to
be that morphophonology ‘knows about’ null elements, which trigger phonological
cycles and produce cyclic blocking effects, but that unpronounced copies are phono-
logically inert, setting aside phrasal stress, which we will discuss shortly. These well-
known morphophonological effects argue (contra Embick ) that unpronounced
copies are eliminated earlier than null elements, the latter persisting until the handoff
to phonology proper.
We schematize the relevant steps along the path from syntax to phonology as
follows:
()
α β
β γ
⇓
β , α , α, β
⇓
vocabulary insertion
⇓
copies marked for non-pronunciation
⇓
α, β
⇓
marked copies deleted
⇓
#ùaùbùgù%
This may be one way of explaining Raimy’s () arguments that reduplication does not create identity
or dependency between the base and reduplicant, unlike copying of syntactic elements for internal Merge.
Lohndal and Samuels
This sketch is not meant to be an exhaustive list of the operations which occur at PF.
For instance, phrasal stress must be assigned before it has been determined which
copy will be pronounced: as has been noted since Bresnan (), stress assigned to
an unpronounced lower copy (to put it in modern terms) shows up on a higher copy,
as in the object question below.
() What book did you read what book?
Following Kahnemuyipour () and Sato (), stress is initially assigned to the
lower copy of what book on the first derivational cycle and carries over to the higher
copy which is ultimately pronounced. Insofar as c-command is relevant to selecting
which copy to pronounce (Nunes ), all of this must occur before the tree is
linearized. It also seems to imply that copy deletion cannot be characterized as simply
failing to perform Vocabulary Insertion on the node which will not be pronounced;
the node must be filled and its full phonological content copied, with the original
copy only subsequently being deleted. For this reason, we depart from Idsardi and
Raimy (), who (following Embick and Noyer ) view the insertion of phono-
logical features as concurrent with the establishment of linear precedence relations
and elimination of hierarchical relations along an already ‘immobilized’ structure.
We will see in the next section why it is crucial that marking copies for deletion and
actually deleting them are sequentially separate.
() a. see
DP see
∅EP ∅EP
∅EP IP
principles familiar from the regular clausal spine apply, and the ordering of the
adjuncts as determined on their plane is later integrated with the main structure. This
is one way of cashing out Chomsky’s claim that adjuncts are pair-merged rather than
set-merged.
Notice that the crash above was caused by the adjunct being adjacent to a null C;
the specifier of CP played no role, and indeed there is no reason to assume that the
specifier was projected. Omitting Spec,CP—consistent with Bare Phrase Structure—
in the case of all restrictive relative clauses and embedded CPs, there is no need for
special pleading in () or (b), which are problematic for An (a) for reasons
discussed in the previous section.
() a. I believe [CP ∅EP [IP John liked linguistics]]
b. [CP ∅EP [IP Mary was waiting for the child]]
If we follow Starke’s () analysis, again consistent with our Bare Phrase Structure
approach, we see why adjuncts to a matrix clause like the ones below (from Selkirk
) pose no problem; in Starke’s system, the adjunct in CP and the subject in TP
are adjacent, with no null element intervening.
() a. [CP [AP True to herself], [TP she planned to remain there]]
b. [CP [PP On the fourth of July], [TP we’ll have a parade and fireworks]]
Even though the adjunct in CP is connected through an EP, there will only be one
such bare EP, and hence no problem for linearization. Thus there is no empty C in
these cases, as Starke’s analysis allows for there to be a phrasal CP without a C head.
This is shown in the following structures:
() a. [CP ∅EP [TP she planned to remain there]]
b. [CP ∅EP [TP we’ll have a parade and fireworks]]
Such cases are therefore correctly predicted to be acceptable.
Now we must also consider the case of a null edge created by movement, as in (),
repeated below.
() [CP Who did Mary [vP see [VP see who]]]
The acceptability of such sentences follows naturally from the order of operations for
which we argued on independent grounds: marking one copy for non-pronunciation
renders it distinct from its neighbour, so it can be linearized without incident.
Let us also look at cases of crashes involving other categories. First, vP:
() ∗[ Eat the cake] John did and [∅v [ ∅V the cookie]] Mary did.
vP
Here we follow Selkirk () in treating these as CP adjuncts. Nothing would go wrong if they are
instead TP-level adjuncts, as long as the adjuncts are not adjacent to a null C.
Linearizing Empty Edges
Since both the v and V nodes are instantiated by null elements with only EP, the
linearization algorithm crashes. Note that even if these heads have some semantic
content—for example, if the v head is really a silent cause—it would not make a dif-
ference. On the PF side, silent elements only have EPs since their semantic/syntactic
features have already been converted to phonological ones via Vocabulary Insertion
prior to the point of linearization. So a silent cause behaves exactly as any ∅EP on the
PF side, as desired. Similarly, if one wants to argue for a silent that in (), this would
be fully compatible with the analysis we have proposed.
() ∗ I saw the train yesterday [that Mary was waiting for]
We can also account for the unacceptability of nominal complementation without an
overt C, as in (b), if the embedded CP is within a covert PP (cf. Kayne, in press).
() a. I distrust the claim [PP ∅P [CP that Bill left the party]]
b. ∗ I distrust the claim [PP ∅P [CP ∅C Bill left the party]]
This is motivated in part by languages like Norwegian, in which this structure appears
overtly (a). In fact, in Norwegian, the preposition is obligatorily pronounced, as
shown in the examples below.
() a. Jeg stoler ikke på påstanden [PP om [CP ∗ (at) Bill forlot festen]]
I trust not on the claim about *(that Bill left the party
‘I distrust the claim that Bill left the party.’
b. ∗ Jeg stoler ikke på påstanden [PP ∅ [CP at Bill forlot festen]]
I trust not on the claim that Bill left the party
‘I distrust the claim that Bill left the party.’
Note that the complementizer at ‘that’ cannot be dropped.
Our account also gives insight into a difference between finite and non-finite
clauses, if we adopt the movement theory of control (Hornstein , Boeckx, Horn-
stein, and Nunes ):
A consequence of this account is that there cannot be multiple null heads in the skeleton of a clause
(i) a. [CP ∅C [CP That [IP John is a genius]] was believed by many people]
b. ∗ [CP ∅C [CP ∅C [IP John is a genius]] was believed by many people]
Something else must be going on here, which may be related to a semantic need for a complementizer to
encode factivity.
Lohndal and Samuels
. Conclusion
We argue that the unacceptable sentences in sections . and .., previously
attributed to ECP or IPEG violations, crash due to a failure during linearization.
Specifically, two syntactic objects cannot be linearized if they bear only EP and are
thus non-distinct at the point when the linearization algorithm () applies. Our
Linearizing Empty Edges
account eliminates the troublesome assumptions that plagued An’s account: reliance
on the notion of violations of Bare Phrase Structure, late insertion of C, suspicious
intonational phrasing, and the mysterious relationship between IPEG violations and
unacceptability of a syntactic flavour.
As a final note, we would like to place the account for which we have argued here
in a larger context. Boeckx () argues that the empty edge phenomenon is one
manifestation of a more general filter ∗ XX which applies to different types and tokens
of linguistic objects at different levels of representation. This more general princi-
ple would then supersede not only the IPEG but also the me–lui constraint (Kayne
, Bonet ), the Obligatory Contour Principle in phonology (Leben ),
the what–what filter familiar from multiple wh-movement languages (Bošković and
Nunes ), and more. That is to say, non-distinctness is dispreferred across various
linguistic domains, though the levels at which it is disallowed may vary from lan-
guage to language. The present work also sits alongside arguments by Samuels (:
Chapter ) that phenomena such as the IPEG and second-position clitic placement
need not be described in terms of prosodic phrasing mediating between syntactic and
phonological representations; purely syntactic representations will suffice to describe
the pattern of acceptable and unacceptable configurations.
. Introduction
One fundamental question for structural models of sentence comprehension which
assume that syntax plays a crucial role in the first stage of parsing is what kind of
syntactic information is available during that stage. The experimental studies reported
here take as a starting point two classifications of verbs which have played a crucial
role in the study of verb alternation and the syntax–lexicon interface: a classification
in terms of argument structure and a classification in terms of aspectual structure. The
first type of classification, which (following Perlmutter ) proposes a tripartite dis-
tinction between transitive, unaccusative, and unergative verbs, has been previously
shown in the processing literature (MacDonald , Stevenson and Merlo ) to
be crucial (see sections .. and .. below). In this chapter we concentrate on the
second classification of verbal predicates, in terms of aspectual information (Vendler
), and present evidence that event structure information, in particular telicity, is
accessed by the processor during online comprehension.
information. The event denoted by a verb may entail the existence of a process, may
entail an endpoint, may be homogeneous or have distinct stages of completion, and
may be punctual or non-punctual. Accordingly in Vendler’s schema, verbs divide
into four classes, a class of verbs indicating states and three types of events:
() a. Activities (e.g. applaud): events that go on for a time, with homogenous sub-
parts and without a necessary endpoint. They are atelic.
b. Accomplishments (e.g. write the book): events that have a process portion
which proceeds via distinct stages to a logically necessary endpoint. They
often involve a transition, followed by a resultant state. They are telic.
c. Achievements (e.g. stop or trip): change-of-state events that culminate at the
moment they occur and lack a preceding process. They are telic.
Vendler established these classifications with a number of syntactic tests. One famous
test which is often used to distinguish between telic and atelic events is the modifica-
tion by adverbials such as for an hour/in an hour/at o’clock.
() a. Mary pushed the cart (in/for an hour)(at o’clock).
Activity (atelic)
b. Mary wrote the book (in/for an hour)(at o’clock).
Accomplishment (telic)
c. Mary crossed the finish line (in/for an hour)(at o’clock).
Achievement (telic)
These tests are based on the fact that adverbials like for an hour modify atelic events,
whereas in an hour modifies telic events. If the activity can extend for some time
period such as for an hour without any endpoint being specified, then this implies
homogeneity and atelicity. In contrast, if the event denoted by the verb can be com-
pleted in some delineated time period such as in an hour, then the verb’s meaning
implies completion, and thus heterogeneity, an endpoint, and telicity. The third test,
at o’clock, distinguishes between telic events which unfold over an extended period,
called ‘accomplishments’, and telic events which occur at a single moment, called
‘achievements’.
Much work in theoretical linguistics has taken this as a starting point and has
convincingly argued that event structure has implications for syntactic structure. For
example, it has been observed that telic events always have objects in their syntactic
structure, albeit sometimes only underlyingly (Tenny ). The question of how to
represent the connection between telic events and syntactic objects has been the focus
of much work on the lexicon–syntax interface. More generally, in the literature the
observation that events might have complex internal structure (possibly involving
causation components, process components, and endpoints) has caused many to
propose that since event structure determines the mapping to syntax, complex event
structure must surface in the syntax as complex phrase structure (e.g. Pustejovsky
, Borer ). In other words, events might contain subevents and these idealized
subparts have consequences for the syntax. For example, an endpoint subpart in
the aspectual semantics of a verb will be represented in the syntax by a particular
functional projection. Verbs denoting different types of events, then, will be associated
with different syntactic structures (Travis , van Hout , Borer , Ritter and
Rosen , Ramchand , among many others).
The syntactic structure related to the subevents associated with a particular verb is
the event structure of that verb. In this perspective, each argument of a verb occupies
a given position associated with a subpart of the event in the syntactic structure.
The interpretation of the argument itself is determined by the aspectual properties
associated with that projection.
Considering now specifically telic events, the correlation between event endpoints
and syntactic objecthood follows from the fact that the endpoint functional projection
is lower in the syntactic structure than the base position of the external argument. The
event in John broke the vase is telic because it implies that the theme the vase reaches
a final change of state. In the event structure analysis, the vase undergoes movement
to occupy the specifier position of the telic functional projection, labelled TelicP
in ().
() . . . vP
DPAgent v
John
v TelicP
DPTheme Telic
V tTheme
break
Verb Telicity in Sentence Comprehension
Because the telic functional projection is situated lower than the position of the
external argument John, only internal arguments (like the vase) are available to fill its
specifier. Hence only internal arguments may affect the telicity of a verbal predicate.
.. Argument structure and the reduced relative effect: MacDonald’s study
Previous research (MacDonald ) has shown that the reduced relative effect is
affected by the argument structure of the verb, as predicted by Pritchett (). In a
reduced relative clause sentence, the initial verb must receive a transitive reading when
the initial noun phrase is eventually interpreted as the direct object. Verbs may differ
in the degree to which they promote a reduced relative reading in English because
transitive verbs can be either obligatorily transitive, such as capture, or optionally
transitive, such as fight. In a self-paced reading experiment, MacDonald found that
less processing difficulty occurred in reduced relatives with obligatorily transitive
verbs as in (a) than with optionally transitive verbs as in (b). This effect was found
on the main verb (was in ()).
() a. The ruthless dictator captured in the coup was hated throughout the country.
b. The ruthless dictator fought in the coup was hated throughout the country.
This result suggests that the information that a verb requires an object may lead the
comprehension system to be less committed to a main-clause reading of the initial
portion of the sentence. One possible explanation is that if the processor accesses the
information that a verb requires an object, it leaves open the possibility that the initial
noun phrase might be the required object. For example, in (a) the verb capture is
stored with the information that it requires a direct object. This information may
influence the processor to leave open the possibility that the ruthless dictator is the
Verb Telicity in Sentence Comprehension
direct object in a reduced relative construction. Thus, in this case the processor would
not immediately commit to the analysis of the ruthless dictator as the subject of a
main clause. The reduction in the reduced relative effect associated with obligatorily
transitive verbs has been found in several subsequent studies (Townsend and Bever
: –).
.. Telicity and the reduced relative effect: the Event Structure Processing hypothesis
The previous sections briefly reviewed the syntax–semantics literature concerning the
connection between a verb’s argument structure and its event structure. We reviewed
the hypothesis that telic events are associated with a syntactic structure with a par-
ticular functional projection representing the endpoint of the event. The effect of this
superstructure is that telic events must represent an underlying direct object syntac-
tically, filling the specifier of the telic functional projection. This raises the question
of whether verb event structure influences online structural ambiguity resolution (see
Sanz , and Townsend and Bever : ).
Because many transitive verbs are also telic, the possibility that event structure
influences online resolution represents a potential confound in MacDonald’s findings.
Most of MacDonald’s () optionally transitive verbs were atelic (fifteen atelic verbs
vs. three telic verbs), and most of her obligatorily transitive verbs were telic (fifteen
telic verbs vs. three atelic verbs). Thus, MacDonald’s finding could be due to telicity
rather than transitivity. Since telic verbs must have internal arguments, we predict less
processing difficulty in reduced relatives with telic verbs such as (c) and (d) than
in those with atelic verbs such as (a) and (b).
O’Bryan, Folli, Harley, and Bever
() a. Atelic, optionally transitive: The actress sketched by the writer left in a hurry.
b. Atelic, obligatorily transitive: The actress escorted by the writer left in a hurry.
c. Telic, optionally transitive: The actress tripped by the writer left in a hurry.
d. Telic, obligatorily transitive: The actress noticed by the writer left in a hurry.
Both telic and atelic verbs can be obligatorily transitive or optionally transitive,
as shown in (). This allows us to tease apart the relative effects of telicity and
transitivity.
The hypothesis of the current research is that event structure is not simply a by-
product of argument structure, but rather is an independent semantic feature of the
verb, with independent consequences for the processing of syntactic structure. We will
refer to this hypothesis as the Event Structure Processing hypothesis. The endpoint
part of a predicate’s meaning entails having a theme argument filling the specifier
position of the telic functional projection. This information is represented in the verb’s
lexical entry (see Folli and Ramchand for proposals along these lines), and
we hypothesize that it is used immediately by the processor in online comprehension.
Our goal in this chapter is to show that telicity has an effect on comprehen-
sion that is not reducible to transitivity. We will present results from four different
comprehension experiments, including prior and current studies, designed specifi-
cally to investigate this question. First, we review prior experiments bearing on the
hypothesis.
Table . Mean self-paced reading times in post hoc reanalyses of two prior
studies
Trans Tel N Example Reduction verb-ed by the N main verb
The N
escorted Reduced . . .
Atelic
by the N Unreduced . . .
Oblig mainV. . .
RRE . . .
Trans
The N
noticed Reduced . . .
Telic
by the N Unreduced . . .
mainV. . .
RRE . –. .
The N
sketched Reduced . . .
Atelic
by the N Unreduced . . .
Option mainV. . .
RRE . . .
Trans
The N
tripped Reduced . . .
Telic
by the N Unreduced . . .
mainV. . .
RRE . . .
number of unique verbs. Combining across both studies, there were a total of items
and native English-speaking participants.
For the post hoc analysis, the verbs were categorized as obligatorily or optionally
transitive based on the results of a questionnaire administered to eight monolingual
English speakers. The verbs were categorized as telic or atelic by three judges, and the
categorizations were then confirmed using an in an hour versus for an hour forced-
choice task administered to native English speakers.
Table . shows the mean self-paced reading times in both studies combined for
each of the verb types in each of the sentence regions. In the mean reading times,
each item from the two studies is represented equally.
A repeated measures ANOVA on all items from both studies was conducted for
each sentence region. The independent variables were telicity (telic vs. atelic) and
transitivity (obligatory vs. optional). The dependent variable was the reduced relative
effect (RRE), measured as mean reading time for the ambiguous sentence minus
the corresponding unambiguous sentence in each region. The results show that on
the verb-ed by region, the RRE was significantly smaller when the embedded verb
was telic rather than atelic, F = ., p < .. There was a trend towards a smaller
RRE when the embedded verb was optionally rather than obligatorily transitive,
O’Bryan, Folli, Harley, and Bever
F = ., p = .. The interaction between telicity and transitivity was not signifi-
cant on this region, F = ., p > .. There were no significant effects of telicity,
transitivity, or the interaction between the two on the noun phrase or main verb
regions. On the main verb region, there was a trend towards a smaller RRE when
the embedded verb was telic rather than atelic, F = ., p = .. The numeri-
cal difference between the transitivity conditions on the main verb region was in
the same direction as the transitivity differences reported by MacDonald ().
All statistical analyses were conducted by item. By-participant analyses were not
possible because telicity and transitivity were not planned factors in the original
experiments.
In summary, the post hoc reanalysis showed that verb telicity had a statistically
significant effect on the amount of processing difficulty that arose in the earliest
possible disambiguation region, the verb-ed by region. The reduced relative effect
was significantly smaller when the embedded verb was telic than when it was
atelic.
The results provided preliminary evidence for the relevance of telicity to online
sentence comprehension. This finding is consistent with our hypothesis that the verb
contributes information about its event structure, which is used without delay in
resolving structural ambiguity. These initial results provided the motivation for addi-
tional balanced, controlled experiments.
fact is critical for separating telicity from the causative alternation. Verbs in the atelic
optionally transitive condition, e.g. sketched, were object drop verbs. Stative predicates
were avoided in all conditions.
The auditory sentence comprehension experiment tested the Event Structure Pro-
cessing hypothesis using the speaker change monitoring task. Forty-four native
English-speaking participants heard the spoken sentences and indicated whether they
heard a word or part of a word spoken by a different speaker than the rest of the sen-
tence. The rationale for the task is that listeners will have more difficulty detecting the
speaker change when sentence factors impose a greater processing load (Townsend
and Bever ). In the experimental sentences, the speaker change always occurred
on the first syllable of the noun in the by-phrase, e.g. writer in (). The dependent
variable was the reduced relative effect, measured as the percentage of speaker change
detection errors for the ambiguous sentence minus for the corresponding unambigu-
ous sentence.
The results, shown in Table ., followed the same pattern found in the self-paced
reading data: significantly less processing difficulty occurred when the embedded verb
was telic than when it was atelic, F = ., p < .; F = ., p < ..
Effect size was measured using Cohen’s f as . for the by-participants analysis and
. for the by-items analysis, indicating a medium effect size (Cohen ). There was
not a significant main effect of transitivity or a significant interaction between telicity
Table . Mean speaker change detection errors for the four verb types
Transitivity Telicity Example Reduction Detection Errors
The N
escorted Reduced .
Atelic
by the N Unreduced .
Obligatorily mainV. . . RRE .
Transitive
The N
noticed Reduced .
Telic
by the N Unreduced .
mainV. . . RRE −.
The N
sketched Reduced .
Atelic
by the N Unreduced .
Optionally mainV. . . RRE .
Transitive
The N
tripped Reduced .
Telic
by the N Unreduced .
mainV. . . RRE −.
O’Bryan, Folli, Harley, and Bever
and transitivity, all ps > .. Since the speaker change syllable occurred on the noun
in the by-phrase, this result is consistent with the self-paced reading results.
The auditory sentence comprehension results provided further support for the
Event Structure Processing hypothesis. However, a limitation of the study was that
it only allowed examination of effects on the noun in the by-phrase. Thus, an experi-
mental task that would be sensitive to processing effects throughout the sentence was
needed.
150
100
RRE in ms.
50
–50
–100
verb’ed by the writer left in a hurry
Atelic Oblig-Trans Telic Oblig-Trans
Atelic Option-Trans Telic Option-Trans
Fig. . Processing difficulty measured as eye fixation times per word in each sentence zone
telicity and transitivity, F = ., p > ., F < . A planned contrast analysis
revealed a significantly smaller reduced relative effect in the obligatorily transitive telic
condition compared to the obligatorily transitive atelic condition, F = ., p < ..
Neither transitivity, telicity, nor the interaction between the two significantly
affected the size of the reduced relative effect in region (the by-phrase) or region
(the adverbial following the main verb), all ps > ..
The eye-tracking experiment revealed the same pattern of results found in the
speaker change monitoring experiment and the self-paced reading reanalysis: less
processing difficulty occurred in the disambiguating region of reduced relative clause
sentences when the embedded verb was telic compared to atelic. The results also repli-
cated the pattern of results that MacDonald () found for the effect of obligatory
transitivity. The planned contrast analysis yielded a result that is important for sup-
porting the Event Structure Processing hypothesis: telicity significantly lessens the
reduced relative effect, even for obligatory transitive verbs, which are not unaccusative
and do not undergo the causative alternation. Thus, all of the results have supported
the hypothesis that event structure, specifically verb telicity, is used during online
sentence comprehension.
Here we return to the question of whether telicity was a confound in MacDonald’s
() experiment. The self-paced reading and eye-tracking experiments replicated
her finding that obligatory transitivity affects online comprehension. However, we
also found that telicity had a significant main effect. These effects showed up in the
same zone (main verb) in the eye fixation data, but there was no interaction between
telicity and transitivity. These results increased our motivation to be more precise
about where the telicity and transitivity effects arise in the disambiguating region.
O’Bryan, Folli, Harley, and Bever
Such precision would require a measure that allows examination of the effects as each
word is integrated into the sentence. The word maze (Freedman and Forster ,
Nicol, Forster, and Veres ) is the appropriate task for this purpose.
.. Methods
The word maze experiment used the experimental sentences from O’Bryan et al.’s (in
preparation) speaker change monitoring and eye-tracking studies, with a few changes
in the particular verbs used. There were sets of experimental sentences. The verbs
were controlled for lexical frequency using the Kučera–Francis database (Kučera and
Correct
Computer Screen Response
The ... LEFT
Fig. . The word maze task (Freedman and Forster )
Verb Telicity in Sentence Comprehension
.. Results
The results of the word maze are shown in Fig. .. The y-axis indicates the size of
the reduced relative effect in milliseconds. The x-axis depicts the words in the target
sentence.
Fig. . shows the same data presented differently. The x-axis still reflects the words
in the sentence, but the y-axis shows how much the results went in the predicted
direction. Dark bars show the difference between the atelic and telic conditions. Light
bars show the difference between the optionally transitive and obligatorily transitive
conditions.
The analysis of variance results are presented in Table ..
The effects of telicity and transitivity on the reduced relative effect throughout the
critical regions (by through the ‘next word’ region, which is one word following the
main verb) were negatively correlated at –..
400
300
RRE in ms.
200
100
–100
verb’ed by the writer left
150
100
Difference in RRE (ms.)
50
–50
–100
actress verb’ed by the writer left in
atelic - telic option.trans - oblig.trans
verb was telic compared to when it was atelic. Thus the word maze results further
support the Event Structure Processing hypothesis.
The word maze results also show that transitivity had a significant effect on the
RRE. On the noun in the by-phrase and on the main verb (but not on the earlier by
region), the transitivity effect was significant in the predicted direction. That is, the
RRE was significantly smaller when the embedded verb was obligatorily transitive
compared to when it was optionally transitive. As noted above, MacDonald ()
found the same pattern of results in a self-paced reading experiment. One difference
between MacDonald’s study and the current studies is that her reduced relative clause
sentences used prepositional phrases such as in the coup in () instead of by-phrases.
Verb Telicity in Sentence Comprehension
embedded
verb by the noun main verb
Factor(s) F p F p F p F p F p
Telicity . n.s. . <. < n.s. . . . n.s.
Transitivity . . . <. . n.s. . <. . <.
Telicity × . <. . <. < n.s. < n.s. . <.
Transitivity
() The ruthless dictator fought in the coup was hated throughout the country.
In the word maze on the early disambiguation (by) region, the transitivity effect was
significant in the opposite direction from the effect on the main verb. MacDonald’s
() Experiment A also found the same pattern: the obligatorily transitive condi-
tion resulted in a larger RRE than the optionally transitive condition on the prepo-
sitional phrase preceding the main verb. MacDonald reports but does not explain
this result, because it is not the focus of her paper. The difficulty that subjects have
in the obligatorily transitive condition in this early region is understandable, because
an obligatorily transitive verb requires a direct object which must immediately follow
the verb in any active sentence. For example, consider the obligatory transitive verb
capture. In the sentence The ruthless dictator captured in the coup . . . , when the prepo-
sition in is encountered, it becomes clear that the sentence cannot be a grammatical
simple main clause. In other words, in the reduced relative, the preposition following
the verb signals the processor that the required direct object is absent from the surface
direct object position. Thus, anything other than a noun phrase in this position, such
as by, a preposition, or an adverbial, should result in processing difficulty.
Less processing difficulty occurs in the optionally transitive condition prior to the
main verb, because a simple main-clause interpretation can be maintained. Consider
the optionally transitive condition sentence in () until the main verb disambigua-
tion point (indicated by the pipe ‘|’): The ruthless dictator fought in the coup | was
hated throughout the country. This sentence beginning could have a simple main clause
structure with the ruthless dictator as the subject, since fought requires no direct object.
When the main verb was occurs following coup, processing difficulty will ensue, espe-
cially because there was not a cue that a reduced relative structure should be posited
earlier in the sentence. Thus, the optionally transitive condition has a small RRE prior
to the main verb and a very large RRE on the main verb. This pattern of results was
found in the word maze experiment as well as in MacDonald’s Experiment A.
The word maze results did show an interaction between telicity and transitivity on
by. In order to understand this, it is important to note that the two factors, each with
O’Bryan, Folli, Harley, and Bever
two levels, make four verb conditions. The interaction indicates that one of these four
verb conditions has the smallest RRE of all: the optionally transitive telic condition.
However, even with the interaction taken into account, telicity and transitivity have
significant main effects on the RREs in the word maze.
The condition with the smallest RREs on by, the optionally transitive telic condi-
tion, is the condition in which the verbs are unaccusative in their intransitive usage.
This finding is consistent with Stevenson and Merlo’s () claim that reduced rel-
atives with unaccusative embedded verbs are easier to understand than those with
unergative embedded verbs. Unaccusatives that can occur in reduced relative clause
sentences also undergo the causative alternation as shown in ().
() a. The writer tripped the actress.
b. The actress tripped.
This finding raises the question of whether the relevant factor in online comprehen-
sion is telicity, unaccusativity, or the causative alternation. If unaccusativity or the
causative alternation were the relevant factor, the difference between the telic and
atelic condition should be found only for optionally transitive verbs. The speaker
change monitoring and eye-tracking results revealed a significant difference between
the telic and atelic conditions for obligatorily transitive verbs, which are neither unac-
cusativen or unergative and do not undergo the causative alternation. Thus, our results
support the claim that telicity is the relevant factor rather than unaccusativity or the
causative alternation.
In order to understand the word maze results, it is important to notice a
general pattern that occurs in all four verb conditions. When a lot of processing
difficulty occurs on the early region, less processing difficulty occurs on the main verb.
Conversely, when very little processing difficulty occurs on the early by region, a lot of
processing difficulty occurs on the main verb. Processing difficulty on the early region
suggests that the processor may have disambiguated the sentence as a reduced relative.
If this is the case, there will be less processing difficulty on the main verb, presumably
because the processor has already determined that the structure is a reduced relative.
Little or no processing difficulty on the early by region indicates that disambiguation
has not occurred and a simple main-clause analysis is still being considered. When
this is the case, there will be a great deal of processing difficulty at the disambiguation
point, on the noun in the by-phrase or on the main verb region. Because of this
pattern in the word maze data, the interaction between telicity and transitivity on
the main verb is probably due to the interaction on by. The optionally transitive telic
condition has the smallest RRE on by and the largest RRE on the main verb.
The pattern just described explains why a negative correlation in the early disam-
biguation region would lead to the continuation of the negative correlation later in the
sentence on the main verb. However, it does not explain why a negative correlation
exists in the early disambiguation region. It would have been possible for telicity and
transitivity to pattern together, yielding a positive correlation, but they do not.
Verb Telicity in Sentence Comprehension
The negative correlation between the telicity and transitivity effects throughout the
word maze sentence regions depends on the subtraction of the telicity and transitivity
conditions. The telicity effect is computed as the atelic condition minus the telic
condition, and the transitivity effect is computed as the optionally transitive condition
minus the obligatorily transitive condition. The subtractions are done in this way
because of a similarity between the telic verb condition and the obligatorily transitive
verb condition: both require an object. The difference between them is that telicity
involves requiring an underlying direct object (internal argument and theme), while
obligatory transitivity involves requiring a surface direct object. Thus, the negative
correlation in the early disambiguation region can be understood as follows: in the
reduced relative clause sentence, integration of the preposition by is facilitated by the
verb’s requiring an underlying direct object (i.e. being telic), and it is inhibited by
the verb’s requiring a surface direct object (i.e. being obligatorily transitive).
The facilitating effect of telicity thus shows up as reduced eye fixation times at the
disambiguating main verb.
In the self-paced reading reanalysis, the facilitating effect of telicity appeared much
earlier in the sentence, on the verb-ed by region, suggesting that a cue to the complex
structure is available to the processor at that point in the sentence, presumably the
word by itself. There are a few reasons why this cue might be more likely to have
an immediate effect on the processor in self-paced reading than during eye-tracking.
In self-paced reading, the sentence is artificially chunked, and the reader presses a
button to progress through the sentence. Once the button has been pressed for the
next chunk, the previous chunk disappears and is no longer available to the reader.
The inability to look back encourages the reader to make maximum use of available
cues in each chunk as it occurs. In contrast, during eye-tracking, the sentence remains
available on the screen, as during normal reading, and backtracking is possible. Con-
sequently less salient cues to complexity may be safely left for later consideration.
Finally, the need for button pressing during self-paced reading gives the processor
additional time to work between the appearance of chunks of text, while the button
press is occurring, which amplifies the effect of early cues to complexity.
(a) what is the basis for the acquisition of such constraints? In this case, how does
the child learn to incorporate the statistical effect of telicity in the embedded verb?
(b) what is the computational mechanism that causally links telicity to a reduction
in the reduced relative effect in particular? Constraint-based models can capture the
facts but require further explanation of how the constraints are learned and why the
constraints have the effects that they do.
A relevant hypothesis concerning reduced relative clause processing that we have
not yet discussed is that of McKoon and Ratcliff (). They claim that the meaning
of the reduced relative construction is incompatible with some verbs. They assert that
the reduced relative structure indicates ‘participation in an event caused by some
force or entity external to itself ’. They further claim that events that are internally
caused by the head noun phrase are incompatible with the meaning of the reduced
relative construction. They consider internally caused events to be compatible with
the corresponding unreduced relative clauses because they have a distinct, bi-eventive
meaning. They claim that The horse raced past the barn fell is ungrammatical because
whenever someone races a horse, the horse must internally cause the racing event.
Their account also predicts that The horse raced by the new jockey fell is ungrammatical.
This false prediction leads us to doubt that their account could be accurate. In any
event, McKoon and Ratcliff ’s account does not explain our findings. Consider the
reduced relative clause sentences from the speaker change monitoring, eye-tracking,
and word maze experiments, repeated in () for convenience.
() a. Atelic, optionally transitive: The actress sketched by the writer left in a hurry.
b. Atelic, obligatorily transitive: The actress escorted by the writer left in a hurry.
c. Telic, optionally transitive: The actress tripped by the writer left in a hurry.
d. Telic, obligatorily transitive: The actress noticed by the writer left in a hurry.
Only one of our conditions could be considered to include an event internally caused
by the head noun phrase: the optionally transitive telic condition, (c). McKoon and
Ratcliff ’s account would then predict that (c) is ungrammatical and thus should
show the greatest reduced relative effect. This prediction was not borne out. In fact, the
eye-tracking and word maze experiments showed that (c) had the smallest reduced
relative effect. If none of our verb conditions are considered to involve internal causa-
tion, McKoon and Ratcliff ’s account does not explain why significantly less processing
difficulty occurred in the telic conditions.
Let us now consider how a structurally based model could approach the facilitating
effect of telicity in terms of the ease of recovering from the main-clause analysis. In
such models, the reduced relative effect is attributed to the processing cost associ-
ated with revising the structural analysis. In this case, the independent facilitating
effect of telicity could only be accounted for if its structural representation is distinct
from the structural representation of simple transitivity. One example of a processing
model which proposes an important role for lexically projected syntactic structure is
Verb Telicity in Sentence Comprehension
Stevenson and Merlo’s () Competitive Attachment model. In such a model, dis-
tinct and competing structural analyses are ordered in terms of their computational
complexity. The effect of telicity could be accounted for by assuming the lexical pro-
jection of distinct object positions in telic and atelic obligatorily transitive verbs, and
consequent differences in the ease of reassigning the correct structure to the initially
incorrect analysis.
If the facilitating effect of telicity is indeed structural, it must be the case that
a smaller amount of reanalysis is necessary to switch to a reduced relative clause
structure from an erroneous main-clause analysis of a telic verb than from a main-
clause analysis of an atelic verb. In other words, there must be some respect in which
the structural analysis of a clause containing a telic main verb shares unique structural
similarities with the analysis of a reduced relative clause.
In recent syntactic theory, the Spec,TelicP position has structural and semantic
properties which are closely related to the properties of resultative participles: the
preterite participles used in passives and perfects in English. The subject of the
reduced relative is ascribed the property of having undergone the action described
by the verb; this is the characteristic meaning of such participles (e.g. Embick ,
Kratzer ). The passive participle in a reduced relative is thus a subtype of resulta-
tive participle. A tree representing this general idea is presented in ().
() … vP
vPassive ResultP
DPTheme Result⬘
-ed V0 tTheme
trip
Similarly, with telic verbs, the underlying object in Spec,TelicP is an inner subject
(Hale and Keyser ), entering into a predication relation with the verbal head lower
in the tree. Telicity involves a transition into an end state, and the verb provides
Harley () argues that in fact the predication relation (a small clause) is the key factor in producing
a telic or resultative interpretation in these sentences, and that dedicated functional projections such as
TelicP and ResultP are not required or motivated. On this approach, the structural characteristic held in
common by telic predicates and the resultative participles would be the inner subject structural relation
associated with the predication represented in each.
O’Bryan, Folli, Harley, and Bever
the specification of what that end state is. Hence, telic verbs structurally represent
a resultant state in very much the same way that a resultative participle does.
() … vP
DP v⬘
the writer
vActive TelicP
DPTheme Telic⬘
-ed V0 tTheme
trip
Notice that the TelicP portion of the tree in () is structurally identical with the
ResultP portion of the tree in (), and indeed its semantic interpretation is very
similar.
With atelic transitive verbs, on the other hand, the object does not move into
Spec,TelicP and this special result-state predication relation is not established. This
is illustrated in ().
() … vP
DP v⬘
the writer
vActive VP
V0 DP
to introduce a TelicP into the derivation, with a place holder waiting for the object to
occupy its specifier. The structure at this point is represented in ().
() … vP
DP v⬘
The actress
vActive TelicP
DPe Telic⬘
??? Telic0 VP
-ed V0 te
trip
When the processor needs to reanalyse this structure as a reduced relative tree like
that in (), due to encountering a disambiguation cue that rules out the main-clause
analysis, the only structural adjustment required is the replacement of the placeholder
DP (indicated with ??? in ()) with the erstwhile subject DP the actress, accompanied
by a featural adjustment to v from Active to Passive.
In contrast, when the processor has developed a main-clause analysis of an atelic
transitive verb, as in The actress chaperoned . . . , the structure at that point is as repre-
sented in (), with an object placeholder occupying the sister-to-V position.
() … vP
DP v⬘
the actress
vActive VP
V0 DPe
chaperoned ???
At the disambiguation point, the change to the reduced relative structure in ()
will require the projection of an additional functional projection, ResultP, and
corresponding movement from the sister-of-V to Spec,ResultP, along with reanalysis
In an optionally transitive verb, however, the object placeholder will not be posited by the processor,
requiring an even greater amount of restructuring to recover from the main-clause analysis. Consequently,
the facilitating effect of transitivity is still accounted for.
O’Bryan, Folli, Harley, and Bever
of the position of the actress and the features of the v . This is clearly a more taxing
process.
In other words, current syntactic theory provides structures for telic and atelic
transitive predicates and resultative participles which provide the basis for a struc-
tural reanalysis that predicts the facilitating role of telicity in online processing of
ambiguous obligatorily transitive sentences. Without such a structural distinction,
however, such syntactically driven models will erroneously predict that the two types
of transitive verb should behave identically at reanalysis.
Our data do not unambiguously choose between these explanations. Furthermore,
the wide range of studies of reduced relative constructions suggest that both structural
and probabilistic processes may be involved. Superficial features of the reduced rela-
tive verb sequence that correlate with a simple declarative sentence have been found
to increase the strength of the reduced relative effect (e.g. McRae et al. ). The
structural differences between the erroneous main-clause analysis and the correct
analysis may also affect the overall difficulty (e.g. Stevenson , Frazier and Clifton
). This invites consideration of models that explicitly integrate the operation of
immediately available pattern-completion constraints with the assignment of syntac-
tic derivations.
One such model is the analysis-by-synthesis framework (Townsend and Bever
). In such a model, comprehension involves the formation of meaning represen-
tations based on both probabilistic information and structural derivation. The model
predicts that the initial comprehension of sentences is based on pattern recognition,
reflecting statistically and informationally dominant patterns, without the benefit of
a complete or correct derivational syntax. In this model, semantic event structure
information carried by individual verbs contributes directly to the initial meaning
representation, as suggested by our results. The model then involves an almost par-
allel assignment of derivational structure, followed by a comparison of the proba-
bilistic and structural analyses. The contribution of such a model is that it provides
an architecture for integrating pattern-based analysis, derivation-based analysis, and
reconciliation of the two kinds of information.
At a more general level, our findings are relevant to the longstanding debate about
the interaction of syntax and grammatically encoded semantics, and its relevance for
sentence comprehension. Telicity, and more generally event structure, is an intrinsic
lexical and categorical semantic property of verbs, but as we have seen, it has strong
syntactic reflexes and lends itself to a structural characterization. We have shown that
online sentence comprehension is sensitive to this factor. Because of its position at
the cusp of the syntax–semantics interface, event structure will prove to be a fruitful
testing ground for experimental investigation of the role that syntactic computations
and semantic categories play in online comprehension.
Part II
. Introduction
Although much current work in generative linguistics recognizes the significance of
information structure (IS), questions remain regarding its precise representation and
role in the grammar. This chapter goes some way toward answering these questions,
by showing that IS plays a crucial part in a specific phenomenon, namely, focus
intervention effects in declarative sentences.
The phenomenon of focus intervention is illustrated in the wh-questions in () and
(), where a certain type of operator preceding the wh-phrase yields an unacceptable
sentence. In () the operator is the Korean particle man ‘only’, while in () it is
the negative polarity item (NPI) daremo ‘anyone’ in Japanese. Man and daremo are
therefore categorized as intervention triggers.
() ∗ Minsu-man nuku-lûl po-ass-ni?
Minsu-only who-acc see-past-q
‘Who did only Minsu see?’ (Beck : )
() ?∗ Daremo nani-o yom-ana-katta-no?
anyone what-acc read-neg-past-q
‘What did no one read?’ (Tomioka : )
In questions involving a disjunction, intervention effects are manifested in the absence
of an alternative question reading, rather than degradedness (Beck and Kim ).
∗ This chapter is based on my dissertation (Eilam ) and updates a short paper from the proceedings
of NELS (Eilam, to appear). I first and foremost thank Tony Kroch for calling my attention to the novel
data reported here. I am grateful to Dave Embick and Satoshi Tomioka for extended discussions, as well
as Catherine Lai, Laia Mayol, Satoshi Nambu, Florian Schwarz, Yanyan Sui, the editors of this volume,
and audiences at Bar Ilan University, the Workshop on Prosody, Syntax, and Information (WPSI) at the
University of Delaware and OnLI II at the University of Ulster.
Here I discuss only elements which are crosslinguistically stable intervention triggers, i.e. the operators
corresponding to English only, even, and also, and NPIs (see Kim , Beck ). I label these ‘only-type
operators’; the phrase consisting of the operator and its associate (Minsu-man ‘only Minsu’ in ()) is the
intervener.
Eilam
Thus, in (), the intervention trigger only preceding a disjunctive phrase in English
leaves the question with just a yes/no interpretation, allowing it to be answered as in
(b), but not (a).
() Does only John like Mary or Susan?
a. Mary. [∗ AltQ]
b. Yes. [✓Yes/NoQ]
Until recently, the general consensus was that these crosslinguistically robust pat-
terns indicate syntactic ill-formedness, although the precise description of this ill-
formedness remained a matter of debate (see e.g. Pesetsky , Kim , Grohmann
). Beck (), however, notes that all of the syntactic analyses fail to accurately
define the set of intervention triggers, or make use of a definition which is ultimately
semantic. Accordingly, she pursues a semantic approach to intervention. The basic
idea is that focus-sensitive operators interfere with the semantic relation between the
question operator high in the clause and the wh-phrase or disjunction, because they
take the place of the question operator in evaluating the alternatives introduced by
the latter. Although this idea overcomes the above-mentioned weakness of syntactic
analyses, Tomioka () points out various observations which both Beck’s analysis
and the syntactic alternatives are unable to explain. These include a great deal of inter-
speaker variability in judgements, and the amelioration of intervention effects when
the intervener is an embedded subject or not a subject.
Eilam () adds further evidence against syntactic and semantic analyses, show-
ing that they derive incorrect predictions. First, intervention effects are not read off
the hierarchical structure, as demonstrated by the fact that they may arise even when
an intervener follows a wh-phrase or disjunction, i.e. when the allegedly necessary
c-command relations do not hold. Second, intervention effects can be ameliorated or
eliminated in certain contexts, which render the potential intervener a non-focus in
IS terms, but do not change its semantic status. If this were a syntactic or semantic
phenomenon, it should be immune to contextual changes. Moreover, this finding
indicates that what underlies intervention effects is not the semantics of only-type
operators, as Beck () claims, but rather the IS notion of focus.
Building on the above-mentioned observations, Eilam () develops an IS anal-
ysis of focus intervention first proposed in Tomioka (). Wh-questions and alter-
native questions are associated with a rigid informational articulation, in which the
wh-phrase and disjunctive phrase, respectively, constitute the IS focus. Since just
one such focus is allowed per sentence, any phrase including an only-type operator
can be accommodated only if it is a non-focus in the informational articulation of
the sentence. This accommodation may be achieved via the syntax, prosody, and/or
context; various strategies and relevant examples of accommodation are provided
below.
Focus Intervention in Declaratives
discussion here, unlike a link, is not restricted to shifting topics or to sentence-initial position.
Eilam
in the hearer’s knowledge store where the information contributed by the focus is
to be entered. The tail signals how the information is to be entered under a given
address, and necessarily lacks intonational prominence. This informational articula-
tion is illustrated with the English example from Vallduví () in (), where the
boss constitutes the topic, hates is the focus, and broccoli is the tail. In this case, the
hearer is instructed to go to the entry ‘the boss’ and substitute the new information
‘hates’ for V in the existing record ‘The boss V broccoli’.
() The boss hates broccoli. (Vallduví : )
Returning to the issue of different notions of focus, we find that a semantic focus
involving an operator like only or even tends to also be the IS focus of the sentence it
occurs in, but does not have to be. This claim is discussed at length in Vallduví ()
and Dryer (), and is illustrated in example (b) above, where the first only-phrase
is the IS focus and the second is not.
The question, then, is what happens when an only-phrase, i.e. a potential intervener,
is not the informative portion of the sentence. If intervention effects persist, we can
conclude that semantic focus is the underlying cause, while absence or amelioration
of the effects indicates that the IS notion of focus is the relevant one. The findings
presented in Tomioka () and Eilam () are unequivocal: intervention effects
are ameliorated or eliminated in contexts where a potential intervener is not the IS
focus. These contexts include wh-questions in which the intervener is an embedded
subject or a non-subject, which were mentioned above, as well as the English example
in () and (). Here the potential intervener is provided in a context preceding an
alternative question, as opposed to the absence of such a context in the unacceptable
example in ().
() Context: The graduate students in linguistics took two preliminary exams, in
syntax and phonology, last week. The results were surprising: there was one
exam that all the students, including John, passed, but no one except John
passed the other.
() Did only John pass syntax or phonology? (Eilam : )
Now compare () with (), repeated from ():
() ∗ Does only John like Mary or Susan?
Crucially, () does not differ from () in its syntax or semantics, but rather only
in its information structure and concomitant prosody. The semantic focus only John
is part of the backgrounded material in (), as indicated by the lack of prosodic
prominence, enabling it to be accommodated in the alternative question and thus
avoiding an intervention effect.
‘∗ ’ indicates that the alternative question reading is unavailable.
Focus Intervention in Declaratives
Having established that IS focus, rather than semantic focus, plays a role in inter-
vention effects, the obvious question is why this is the case. In other words, what well-
formedness condition(s) do intervention structures violate? The answer originally
given in Tomioka () and elaborated on in Eilam () is that an IS focus cannot
be integrated in the informational articulation of wh-questions and alternative ques-
tions, which already has one such focus, namely, the wh-phrase or disjunctive phrase.
Given that a sentence contains one and only one focus (Lambrecht ), any element
outside the focus must be a topic or a tail. However, a phrase involving an only-type
operator can be neither of the two. It cannot be a topic because it is non-referential
(cf. Reinhart ), and it is incompatible with tailhood as long as it bears prosodic
prominence (cf. Vallduví ). The resulting mismatch between the components of
the sentence and the informational articulation derives judgements of degradedness,
i.e. intervention effects.
In order to express the intended meaning of the sentences in question, it is nec-
essary to transform the potential intervener into a non-IS focus, and this is precisely
what the various repair strategies noted above do. For example, scrambling as in (b)
and (b) places the intervener in the phonologically reduced domain which follows
foci, including wh-phrases, allowing the intervener to function as (part of) the tail.
The effect of phonological reduction, or deaccenting, can also be illustrated in English
alternative questions. When the disjunction precedes the potential intervener only
Mary in (), the sentence is acceptable because the latter does not have a pitch accent,
and can thus be in the tail. Attempting to mark Mary with a pitch accent, as would
be expected of the associate of only, eliminates the alternative question reading ().
This refutes the claim of Beck and Kim () whereby () bears out the role of
c-command in intervention effects; on the contrary, together with () it confirms
that the effects are not sensitive to hierarchical relations. This is obviously unexpected
under a syntactic or semantic approach.
() Did John or Susan invite only Mary? (Beck and Kim : )
() ∗ Did John or Susan invite only MARY ?
All in all, the case for an IS approach to intervention effects, based on wh- and alter-
native questions, is rather strong. What would make the case even more compelling
is data from environments other than questions. That is, if the ill-formedness of inter-
vention configurations reflects basic constraints on the informational articulation of
sentences, there is no reason to assume that intervention effects should be limited
to questions. Indeed, we have already observed that they appear in declarative sen-
tences; the next section takes up the relevant examples and shows that they decisively
adjudicate in favour of an IS analysis.
See Eilam (, ) for a range of additional evidence for the IS approach and against its competi-
tors.
Eilam
exception is Rooth (), who mentions an example analogous to () in the context of his theory of focus
realization. However, he erroneously attributes the degradedness of () to an unspecified phonological
constraint, and does not note its acceptable counterparts in ()–().
Focus Intervention in Declaratives
cannot answer the QUD What does only John eat?; as illustrated in (b), this would
require the illicit configuration of (a). (b), however, can be the answer to the latter
QUD, as shown in (c), since the configuration is well-formed (cf. (b)).
() a. QUD: Who eats only rice?
b. Only JOHN eats only rice.
→ No one other than John eats rice.
() a. QUD: What does only John eat? / What is eaten by only John?
b. ∗ Only John eats only RICE.
c. Only RICE is eaten by only John.
→ No one other than John eats rice.
Decisive evidence that this difference between the sentences is not a function of the
active/passive distinction is provided in (), a specificational construction which has
the same entailment as the passive in (c).
() Rice is the only thing that only John eats.
→ No one other than John eats rice.
The configurations schematized in () thus affect not only the judgements speakers
give for a sentence but also potentially its truth-conditions. These configurations are
information-structural in nature, as they make crucial reference to the notion of IS
focus, and should therefore be accounted for under the IS approach to intervention.
However, there are certain aspects of the declarative data which distinguish them from
questions and thus require further attention.
The key difference between the question and declarative contexts is the fact that
in the latter case, the problematic only-phrases—i.e. the interveners—are not IS foci.
Rather, since they are material repeated from a lead-in sentence, whether an inter-
rogative or a declarative, they are not potential candidates for focus-hood. Why are
these only-phrases nevertheless incompatible with the informational articulation of
the declarative sentences under discussion? I argue that they cannot fulfil the role of
the two available IS categories in these examples, topic and tail. They cannot be topics
because of their non-referentiality, as mentioned in section .. The only-phrases in
the declarative examples cannot be tails as well because subjects are default topics
(Reinhart , Lambrecht , Erteschik-Shir ), and subjects preceding the
nuclear stress are specifically incompatible with tailhood (Vallduví ). In order
for a subject to be a tail, it typically has to appear in a postnuclear position, which is
by and large not possible in English. In a language like Catalan this option is available
and utilized, as in (), where the object de pa is the topic, and the subject mon germà
the tail. The awkward English translation, using right-dislocation, reflects the lack of
an appropriate equivalent in this language.
Focus Intervention in Declaratives
This approach seems to fare no better than syntactic analyses, since it does not make
the IS distinctions necessary to tell apart well-formed vs. ill-formed configurations
involving potential interveners. In fact, given a further assumption Beck makes, which
is crucial for her theory, the focus structures described here refute the constraint in
(). In the analysis of intervention in wh-questions, Beck assumes that only-type
operators always attach to verbal projections and clausal nodes, even in cases of
apparent DP adjunction. This derives the same LF representation, in (), for both the
Eilam
acceptable and unacceptable examples in () and () (Q/A in these representations
is the operator evaluating question/answer congruence).
() [Q/AC [∼C [onlyD [∼D [onlyE [∼E [JohnF drank beerF ]]]]]]]
() Only JOHN drank only beer.
() ∗ Only John drank only BEER.
As the representations are identical, there is no obvious way to predict the well-
formedness of (). Although Beck gives independent motivation for the assumed
positions of the only-type operators in these representations, they are needed in any
case in her theory. If only-type operators could attach locally to DP subjects, interven-
tion effects in wh-questions would not be expected under the theory to begin with.
That is, the potential intervener would evaluate the alternatives introduced by the DP
subject and would not interfere with the relation between the higher question operator
and wh-phrase. Furthermore, because focus association is not selective according
to Beck (see footnote ), the semantic computation cannot be fixed so as to avoid
unintended associations. All in all, there seems to be no way to salvage the theory and
still be able to capture the entire range of attested data.
Two types of potential non-information-structural explanations for intervention
in declaratives have been assessed here. Both fall short, because the acceptable and
unacceptable sentences do not seem to differ in any relevant syntactic or semantic
property. Rather, it is only their informational articulation, created by different pre-
ceding contexts and structures, and possibly reflected in the prosody, which teases
them apart. Accordingly, only an IS approach of the type first proposed to account for
intervention in questions is able to cover this data.
In order to get the theory off the ground, Beck is forced to make the debatable assumption that ∼
is not selective in choosing which foci to evaluate. See Wold () for an alternative model, involving
coindexing.
Focus Intervention in Declaratives
C É C I L E DE C AT
. Introduction
To what extent should syntax encode meaning? The way this question has been
addressed within the generative framework has fluctuated over the past four decades,
but the general tendency has been to complexify the syntactic component to account
for much of the complexity of natural language. In the early days of Generative Seman-
tics, all meaning was assumed to be present at D-structure. The current Minimalist
view is that many combinatorial properties of semantics are derived from syntax, and
that (at least some) systematicities of compositional semantics are associated with
phrase structure (Ramchand ). The Cartographic approach in particular assumes
transparent mapping between form and interpretation, and ‘syntacticizes as much as
possible the interpretive domains’ (Cinque and Rizzi : ), based on evidence
from word order and the order of overtly realized functional morphemes.
This chapter questions the extent to which syntax is necessary to account for two
phenomena with discourse/pragmatic properties, with the following preoccupation
in mind: how should we use Occam’s Razor to dispose of undesirable theoretical
entities? More specifically: should we rely on syntax (as opposed to other components)
to explain restrictions on the distribution of phenomena with a discourse import, as
advocated by the Minimalist Program and implemented in the classic Cartographic
∗ I would like to thank Shigeru Miyagawa, Reiko Vermeulen, Mika Kizu, and Hidekazu Tanaka for
comments and enlightening remarks about the Japanese data (which doesn’t imply they agree with my
analysis), and Mika Takewa for her generous help in gathering these data. Special thanks to Kristine Bentzen
for comments and discussion. Many thanks also to the audiences at the Department of Linguistics at KU
Leuven (), the GIST workshop (Ghent, ), OnLI II, Belfast, , and the SLE workshop on
‘New Forays into Root Phenomena’.
Root Phenomena as Interface Phenomena
approach? Or should we minimize the role of syntax when these restrictions can
be captured by other components of grammar, as advocated e.g. by Culicover and
Jackendoff ()?
The empirical basis for this discussion is root phenomena in non-sententials. The
root properties of non-sententials have been discussed in the literature (Stainton
, Culicover and Jackendoff ) but to my knowledge the extent to which non-
sententials can host root phenomena has not been investigated per se.
The chapter is organized as follows. Section . defines root phenomena in general
and lays out the central research question (i.e. to what extent syntax should encode the
root properties of clauses/utterances). Section . introduces the syntactic structure
relevant to the subsequent discussion: fragments (or non-sententials), i.e. non-clausal
structures with root properties. The main evidence is provided in the following two
sections, demonstrating that French fragments can host ‘dislocated’ topics (section
.) and that Japanese fragments can host (root) politeness markers (section .).
Conclusions are drawn in section ..
(in preparation) for an analysis of French dislocation as a root phenomenon and its licensing in embedded
clauses.
De Cat
. Non-sententials/Fragments
Spontaneous speech prominently features utterances that, in spite of not manifesting
themselves as full clauses, are fully interpretable by their addressee. As an extreme
example of what can be achieved using such fragments, consider the exchange in
Although see Wiklund, Bentzen, Hrafnbjargarson, and Hróarsdóttir () and Bentzen () for
evidence that the key interpretive feature of the host may be the ability to convey the Main Point of the
Utterance rather than being asserted or non-presupposed.
Root Phenomena as Interface Phenomena
(), involving three people. Imagine Person A looking out of the window and utter-
ing (a) (signalling the presence of a strange sheep) and fainting immediately after-
wards. Person B then comments (b) to Person C, who concludes (c) with regard
to A.
() a. Oh, un mouton à pois!
oh a sheep with dots
‘Oh, a dotted sheep!’
b. Difficile à imaginer.
hard to imagine
‘[That’s] hard to imagine.’
c. D’où son malaise.
from where his faintness
‘Hence his faintness.’
Fragments (also known as non-sententials, as in Progovac, Paesani, Casielles, and
Barton , or Bare Argument Ellipsis, as in Culicover and Jackendoff ) are
verbless utterances interpreted as full propositions with assertoric force. The whole
exchange in () takes place without a single full clause being uttered: the utterances
appear to consist of just a DP (a), an AP (b), and a PP (c). Note also that the first
fragment occurs out of the blue, i.e. without any preceding linguistic context.
A question that has been hotly debated since the s is whether such non-
sentential utterances should be analysed syntactically as full clauses or not.
Recent proponents of the ‘yes’ option include Merchant (, , ); recent
proponents of the ‘no’ option include Culicover and Jackendoff (), Stainton
(), and Progovac ().
Merchant () proposes that fragments are fully propositional in the syntax,
but that most of their structure remains unpronounced. He analyses fragments as
derived by ellipsis, and more specifically as a form of sluicing. Merchant argues that
the fragment occupies the specifier of a left-peripheral phrase (which he suggests may
be FocusP) whose head is endowed with an E feature. This feature has two functions:
(i) it instructs PF not to parse its complement (and hence not to pronounce it); and
(ii) it consists of a partial identity function over propositions, which is intended to
ensure that the complement of an E-endowed head has an appropriate antecedent in
the discourse, essentially ensuring that the content of the unpronounced structure
is identifiable or recoverable. Crucial for the argument developed below is the fact
that, under the ellipsis analysis, the full structure must be inherited verbatim from
the immediately preceding discourse. Merchant (b) uses island sensitivity as key
evidence for his sluicing analysis: he attributes the unacceptability of the answer in
() to the illicit movement the pronounced constituent would have had to undergo to
reach the Spec,FocusP position.
De Cat
() Q: Does Abby speak the same Balkan language that Ben speaks?
A: ∗ No, Charlie.
No, she speaks the same Balkan language that Charlie speaks.
However, Merchant also recognizes that a direct interpretation approach is needed for
at least some fragments, for which there exists no full-blown syntactic counterpart (as
in (c)).
Culicover and Jackendoff () and Stainton () argue that the syntactic ellip-
sis approach cannot account for all fragments, and that the direct interpretation
approach should be postulated as default, because it is more economical. Key evidence
(to which we will return later) comes from cases where the fully pronounced structure
would be ungrammatical, for instance as a result of an island violation. Examples of
such fragments are provided below (all are adapted from Culicover and Jackendoff
). In each example, the context is provided in (a), the fragment in (b), and the full
syntactic structure one would have to postulate for it following Merchant’s analysis is
given in (c).
() a. Haruko has been drinking sake all weekend.
b. Yes. And shochu.
c. ∗ And shochu, Haruko has been drinking sake t all weekend.
() a. Whose sake has she been drinking?
b. Her mother’s.
c. ∗ Her mother’s, she has been drinking t sake.
() a. Haruko drinks sake that comes from a very special part of Japan.
b. Where?
c. ∗ Where does Haruko drinks sake that comes from a very special part of
(Japan)?
() a. Yasu met a child who speaks Urdu.
b. With a Japanese accent?
c. ∗ With a Japanese accent, Yasu met a child who speaks Urdu t.
In addition to these, some examples of fragments have no full-clause equivalent at all:
() a. Would you like a drink?
b. How about tea?
Furthermore, Merchant’s sluicing analysis predicts that fragments cannot occur out
of the blue (as they require a context sentence to be copied from), contrary to what
we observe in (a) (see also () below).
Stainton () beautifully argues that such fragments have pragmatic Force
in spite of not having syntactic Force, which implies that there is no one-to-one
correspondence between ‘what [is] done (a “full-fledged speech act” i.e. propositional,
force-bearing and literal) and what [is] used (lexical projections, not of semantic type
Root Phenomena as Interface Phenomena
t, not having [an expression encoding] force, and not embedded in any higher tree)’
(Stainton : ).
like dislocated elements, as shown by the indexing in ()), but only if there is a syntactic host for the clitic.
Exploring what makes the presentative voilà a possible clitic host is, however, beyond the scope of this
chapter.
The data set used in this study comes from two French corpora of spontaneous interaction between
children and adults: the York corpus (available on childes) and the Cat corpus. They contain speech from
four children (between the ages of ; and ;—ages are given in year;months.days), and adults from
Belgium, Canada, and France. Recordings took place fortnightly (York corpus) or monthly (Cat corpus) and
lasted minutes. For details regarding the transcription and coding procedures, see De Cat and Plunkett
(), and De Cat ().
De Cat
ticipants [. . .] that determines the way in which the CG content develops’ (Bianchi and Frascarelli : ).
It is unclear whether they can be embedded at all (Bianchi and Frascarelli speculate that the
() FocusP
AdvP FocusP
celui-là
‘that one’ PP Focus
comme ça
Focus[E] TP
‘like that’
on le colorie?
‘we it colour’
Root Phenomena as Interface Phenomena
() FocusP
FocusP AdvP
maintenant
PP Focus ‘now’
Incidentally, note that the impossibility of using -mas- in the fragments above provides additional
evidence against a sluicing analysis: if these were syntactically full clauses copied from an antecedent in the
discourse, they would involve verbs and the use of -mas- rather than -des- would be obligatory. Merchant’s
variable island repair strategy, which is invoked to account for the extractability of question words out of
elided islands, can therefore not be invoked here, on account of the presence of des rather than the expected
mas.
De Cat
There are exceptions, in which new information does appear in the embedded clause: see Delin ().
Root Phenomena as Interface Phenomena
sluicing analysis. An analysis in terms of reduced clefts has been shown to be inade-
quate on interpretive grounds. Here again the conclusion has to be that non-clausal
structures can host a root phenomenon, in spite of not projecting a C-domain.
. Conclusions
The data discussed here provide clear evidence for the existence of syntactically non-
clausal structures with root properties. The observation that non-sententials (or frag-
ments) have pragmatic Force is not new (Stainton ). What is new is evidence that,
in spite of lacking syntactic Force, fragments can host phenomena that are restricted
to root hosts when they occur in full clauses. These include root phenomena with
an information-structural import (the dislocated topic in French complex fragments)
and root phenomena expressing speaker anchoring (politeness marking in Japanese
fragments).
Two general conclusions can be drawn from the above. First, the empirical domain
of syntax should not necessarily be coextensive with the sentence or clause: smaller
structures also need to be accounted for—not just because they are pervasive in
spontaneous speech, but also because they display syntactic phenomena in need of
an explanation. This does not automatically call for a revision of core minimalist
assumptions (as demonstrated by Progovac ). Secondly, the existence of root
phenomena in fragments that cannot be captured by a full-clause analysis shows that
what confers root properties to a host is not necessarily syntactic. If the interpretive
component needs to be relied on to confer root status to a syntactic structure in those
cases, should we not confer the same role in full clauses? I would be tempted to follow
the wisdom of William of Occam, especially if it leads us towards a better account for
learnability.
. Introduction
This chapter is concerned with the syntactic and interpretive properties of contrastive
focus and contrastive topic in Japanese and Korean, and their interaction with the
particles contrastive wa and nun. As illustrated below, a contrastive wa- or nun-
phrase may appear in situ, in (a) for Japanese and (a) for Korean, or undergo
movement, as in (b,c) and (b,c). The kind of contrast implied is indicated by the
possible continuation in parentheses.
() a. John-ga Sue-ni ano hon-wa ageta.
John-nom Sue-to that book-wa gave
b. John-ga ano hon-wai Sue-ni ti ageta.
c. ano hon-wai John-ga Sue-ni ti ageta.
‘John gave that book to Sue.’ (‘But, I’m not sure about this other book.’)
∗ Earlier versions of parts of this chapter were presented at GLOW , Japanese/Korean Linguistics
, and the Workshop on Formal Altaic Linguistics in , the Colloquium on Generative Grammar in
, and at the University of Potsdam in . I thank the participants for their helpful comments. I would
also like to thank Daniel Büring, Jieun Kim, Ad Neeleman, Kriszta Szendrői, and Michael Wagner for the
numerous inspiring discussions. Thanks are also due to my informants for their immeasurably patient
help. Parts of this research have been funded by the FWO (No. G), the AHRC (No. ), and
the British Academy (No. SG).
There are non-contrastive wa and nun as well, which appear on non-contrastive topics (Kuno’s
‘theme’). They have a different set of grammatical properties and are generally assumed to be separate lexical
items from contrastive wa and nun, respectively. This chapter is not concerned with non-contrastive wa and
nun. (See Heycock for an overview on wa and C. Lee and Hetland for nun.)
For reasons not entirely clear to me, a wa- or nun-marked phrase sometimes prefers not to surface
adjacent to the verb. This is perhaps due to the phonological fact that a non-contrastive wa-/nun-phrase
forms a separate prosodic domain, but the verb typically forms a domain with an immediately preceding
phrase (Nagahara , Nakanishi , Jun ). An adverbial can be inserted to circumvent this issue
without affecting the claims being made.
Vermeulen
In Korean, the nominative case marker is realized as ka after a vowel and as i elsewhere. Similarly, the
accusative marker is realized as lul if following a vowel and as ul elsewhere, and the particle ‘nun’ as nun
after a vowel and as un elsewhere.
‘Contrast’ and its Relation to wa and nun
information structure. Contrastive wa- and nun-phrases that are interpreted as topics
show the predicted distribution for contrastive topics, but those that are interpreted
as foci do not.
These predictions do not follow from an approach that assumes designated func-
tional projections for discourse-related notions, such as the cartographic approach
(Rizzi ). The data discussed here, therefore, support an approach that assumes
mapping rules at the interface between syntax and information structure, and argues
against an approach that assumes that much of discourse is part of syntax.
In section . I clarify the definitions of topic, focus, and contrast that this chapter
adopts. Section . examines the syntactic distribution of contrastive topics and con-
trastive foci on those definitions. Section . demonstrates that the set of predictions
that follow from Neeleman et al. () are borne out. In section . I examine the
meaning associated with contrastive wa and nun, and argue that it is compatible with
both topic and focus, providing syntactic evidence.
That John in B’s utterance in () is indeed a sentence topic, rather than John in A’s
request, is suggested by three facts. First, native speakers do not interpret the imper-
ative uttered by A as being about John. Secondly, B’s utterance is also felicitous if the
request is less specific about what is to be the topic of discourse, such as tell me about
someone in your class. Finally, a well-known property of a sentence topic is that it
must be referential (Reinhart ). The infelicity of B’s reply in () demonstrates this
I have consulted four native speakers regarding the English data reported here. The reported judge-
property. Non-specific quantifiers are not referential and therefore cannot function as
sentence topics (Endriss ). The fact that A’s request in () is possible, where the
target of the request is not specific, also shows that, by analogy, John in A’s request in
() is not a sentence topic.
() A: Tell me about some people in your class.
B: Few students are from Canada.
For [focus], I adopt the standard definition that it provides a highlighted piece of new
information with respect to the rest of the sentence. As such, it can be identified as
the item corresponding to the wh-part of a preceding question (Rooth ).
[Contrast] is a notion that can combine with focus or topic (Molnár and Winkler
, and references therein). There are some interpretive differences between con-
trastive topic and contrastive focus, which, I argue, derive from the view that focus is a
propositional notion, while a topic is an utterance-level notion. I assume that contrast
implies the rejection of at least one alternative in the set of relevant alternatives
generated by the contrastive item. Thus, a contrastive focus implies the rejection of at
least one alternative proposition, while a contrastive topic implies the rejection of at
least one alternative utterance (S. Tomioka ). I will not examine the details of
the semantics of the notion [contrast], due to lack of space, although I will discuss
proposals for contrastive wa and nun in section .. However, I will introduce below
some discourse contexts which require a contrastive focus and a contrastive topic.
A context requiring a contrastive focus is an instance of correction, such as (),
where B corrects the statement by A. In B’s sentence, Rosa is a contrastive focus.
B asserts that the alternative proposition expressed by A’s utterance, namely that
John saw Claire yesterday, is false. (Focus is indicated by small caps and contrast
is indicated by italics.)
() A: John saw Claire yesterday.
B: No, he saw ROSA yesterday.
{[John saw Rosa], [John saw Claire]}
Another context which requires a contrastive focus is provided by a disjunctive ques-
tion. In (), Rosa in B’s utterance is a contrastive focus. The explicit mention of the
alternative Claire has the effect that the reply implies that the alternative proposition,
‘John saw Claire yesterday’, is false. The contrastive reading can be further strength-
ened by the use of the focus-sensitive particle only.
() A: Did John see Claire or Rosa yesterday?
B: He saw (only) ROSA yesterday.
A contrastive topic is required in a context like () (Büring , , S. Tomioka
). A’s question is about Bill, but B’s reply is about Maxine. Maxine is therefore a
‘Contrast’ and its Relation to wa and nun
The topics in (iB) are sometimes referred to as ‘list-topics’. I assume that these topics are all ‘contrastive’
in the sense discussed in the main text: they all imply the rejection of an alternative utterance and they all
show the same syntactic behaviour in Japanese and Korean as discussed in the main text. The first clause
of (iB) implies that the speaker is unwilling to make the assertion that Mary bought a book, and similarly,
the second clause implies that the speaker is unwilling to make the assertion that John bought flowers.
In this case, it is most probably because the speaker knows that the propositions expressed by the salient
alternative utterances are false. (iiB) implies that the same assertion cannot be made about the male pop
stars, possibly because the speaker is not sure about the male pop stars.
Vermeulen
John give to Sue?’, can also undergo the same kind of scrambling as in () and (). The same holds for
Japanese (see ()–() below). Thus, one may wonder whether there is a grammatically relevant distinction
between contrastive focus and ordinary focus in these languages and, even if there is a distinction, whether
the notion licensing the above kind of scrambling is [focus] rather than [contrast]. There are reasons to
believe that contrastive focus and ordinary focus are indeed distinct and that it is [contrast] that is the
relevant notion. First, all my informants report that a contrast between the book and another item must
be implied if scrambling takes place, as in the (b), (c) examples, but not if ‘the book’ remains in situ, as
‘Contrast’ and its Relation to wa and nun
and takes scope, and scrambling has the effect of marking the sister constituent as
the scope of contrast, which Neeleman et al. call ‘the domain of contrast’. The idea is
schematized in (). I take this scope-marking operation to be an instantiation of
a mapping rule relevant for [contrast]. In other words, the information-structural
notion [contrast] that is common to contrastive topics and contrastive foci can be
marked syntactically in Korean.
() Syntax: [YP XPi [YP. . . ti . . . ]]
|
Information Structure: CF/CT Domain of Contrast
(CF = Contrastive Focus; CT = Contrastive Topic)
The domain of contrast (DoC) for a contrastive item contains material used to calcu-
late the size of the set of relevant alternatives. The difference between (b) and (c) is
that the domain of contrast for the contrastive topic in the former does not contain
the subject, while the one for the latter does:
() b. [TP John-i [VP I CHAYK-UN i [VP=DoC Sue-eykey ti cwuess-e]]]
() c. [TP I CHAYK-UN i [TP=DoC John-i Sue-eykey ti cwuess-e]]
I assume that contrast is always based on an expression that is minimally a proposition
(Schwarzschild ). Thus, existential closure must apply in the case of ( b). Consid-
ering that the contrastive item is a topic, the set of alternatives will contain utterances,
yielding the set in (). For ( c), the subject is included in the set of alternative utter-
ances, yielding the set in (). For () and (), which involve contrastive foci, the set
of alternatives will contain alternative propositions, calculated in the same manner.
() {Assert[someone has given the book to Mary], Assert[someone has given a CD
to Mary], …}
() {Assert[John has given the book to Mary], Assert[John has given a CD to
Mary], …}
Considering that a contrastive topic is analysed here as a composite of [contrast] and
[topic], one may wonder whether a contrastive topic in Korean could be subject to
the rule for [topic], rather than [contrast]. However, this is unlikely to be the case, as
non-contrastive topics, which share with contrastive topics the feature [topic], must
occupy a clause-initial position in this language, as widely reported (Choe , Choi
, , Han ).
in the (a) examples (see also Choi , ). Second, long-distance scrambling is known to require a
contrastive interpretation in the two languages. Indeed, my informants allow long-distance scrambling in
cases of correction and disjunctive questions, but not in answering a simple wh-question. It is not clear to
me at present why a contrastive interpretation is more easily accommodated for clause-internal scrambling,
but clearly a distinction between contrastive focus and ordinary focus is necessary to account for such data,
and it is [contrast] that licenses scrambling. See Vermeulen () for further discussion and relevant data.
Vermeulen
Like other scope-marking operations, the effects of marking the domain of contrast
can best be observed in sentences with more than one scope-taking item. I examine
sentences that contain both contrastive focus and contrastive topic in section ..
Contrastive topics, however, are clearly subject to a different rule. I propose that
they are subject to the mapping rule for [topic] in Japanese. It is widely reported
that non-contrastive topics typically occupy clause-initial position in Japanese too
(see Heycock for an overview), and in Vermeulen () I provide arguments
that non-contrastive topics must occupy clause-initial position. Following Neeleman
and van de Koot (), I propose that the placement of a topic in clause-initial
position is motivated by its effects at the interface, as was the case for scrambling of
contrastive topics and foci in Korean. Specifically, it marks the rest of the sentence as
the comment, allowing for a transparent mapping between syntax and information
structure, as shown below. In other words, the information-structural notion [topic]
that is common to contrastive and non-contrastive topics is syntactically marked in
Japanese. Contrastive topics show movement properties, while non-contrastive topics
show properties of being base-generated in its surface position, binding a pro (Hoji
, Saito ).
() Syntax: [YP XPi [YP … ti /proi … ]]
|
Information Structure: Topic Comment
Recall that a contrastive wa-phrase can appear in non-initial positions, as in ().
However, the data in () and () show clearly that contrastive topics are restricted to
clause-initial position. Those contrastive wa-phrases in non-initial positions therefore
cannot be topics on the standard definition of contrastive topics.
In sum, as far as the syntax–information structure interface is concerned, Korean
contrastive topics are subject to the rule relevant for [contrast], while those in Japanese
are subject to the rule for [topic], but contrastive foci in the two languages are subject
to the rule for [contrast]. The data discussed in this section show patterns that differ
from what is assumed in the literature. The following two sections provide further
arguments that the standard characterizations are inadequate, and offer an alternative
account.
topics in the sense defined in section .. It can also mark items that refer to discourse topics, such as He in
(i) (Vallduví and Engdahl ). Thus, the fact that a non-contrastive wa-phrase may sometimes occupy
a non-initial position, as in the example in (c), and in (c), is not problematic. The interested reader is
referred to the article for further discussion. See also fn. .
; see also Rizzi ), as schematized below. I assume that a comment is a propo-
sition that is predicated of a topic via an assertion operator (Krifka ), capturing
the idea that focus is a propositional notion.
() [Utterance topic [Comment focus [Background … ]]]
I have argued above that scrambling of a contrastive item marks the sister constituent
of the scrambled item as the domain of contrast, (). If focus is a propositional
notion, the domain of contrast for a contrastive focus, which is relevant for the inter-
pretation of a contrastive focus, must also only contain propositional material. Con-
sidering that topic is an utterance-level notion, it follows that it cannot be contained
inside a proposition and hence also not inside the domain of contrast for a contrastive
focus. It is predicted then that a contrastive focus cannot move to a position above a
topic. This is illustrated in (a).
On the other hand, when a contrastive topic undergoes scrambling in Korean,
what is in the domain of contrast for this contrastive topic is material taken from
its comment, the propositional content expressed by the utterance. As such, it can
contain a focus. Thus, in Korean, we predict that a contrastive topic can move to
a position above a focus. Similarly, in Japanese, movement of a contrastive topic to
clause-initial position marks its comment (). Thus, the structure in (b) should be
well-formed in both languages.
If there is no scrambling of a contrastive topic or focus, no domain of contrast
is overtly marked. There is no mapping instruction in such cases and the ordering
between the two items is predicted to be free, as shown in (c) and (d).
() a. [ CF [ … CT … tCF … ]]
b. [ CT [ … CF … tCT … ]]
c. [ … CT … CF … ]
d. [ … CF … CT … ]
These predictions allow us to test the claims made in the previous section, namely
that Korean contrastive topics may appear in a non-initial position, while contrastive
topics in Japanese are limited to clause-initial position. Moreover, if these predictions
are correct, they provide strong support for the current interface-based approach
to the syntax of contrastive focus and contrastive topic. These patterns are difficult
to capture on a cartographic approach which assumes that topics and foci move to
designated syntactic positions (Rizzi ), or that contrastive items are licensed by
moving to the specifier of a functional projection for contrast (Vallduví and Vilkuna
, Molnár and Winkler ), either overtly or covertly. We saw in section . that
a contrastive focus can undergo scrambling in Japanese and Korean. Thus, putting
aside the issue of optionality, overt movement of a contrastive focus to a designated
position must be possible in these languages. It is unclear then why (c), where
the contrastive focus has remained in situ, is well-formed, but (a), where it has
‘Contrast’ and its Relation to wa and nun
undergone movement, is not. Below, I show that these predictions are correct for
both Japanese and Korean.
The following exchange shows that the predictions in (a) and (c) are borne
out in Korean. The question in () is about John, but the reply in () is about Bill,
making Bill a contrastive topic. The presence of -man ‘only’ on the object khong ‘beans’
ensures that it is a contrastive focus. In (a), the contrastive topic and contrastive
focus appear in their base-generated positions in that order, bearing out the prediction
in (c). In (b), the contrastive focus has scrambled across the contrastive topic and,
as indicated, this results in infelicity, bearing out the prediction in (a). (Henceforth,
I will provide the context-setting material in English, if similar contexts have been
used previously, for space reasons.)
() What did John eat at the party?
() Well, I don’t know about John, but …
a. Bill-un KHONG-MAN mekesse. (CT CF)
Bill-nun beans-only ate
b. KHONG-MAN i Bill-un ti mekesse. (CFi CT ti )
‘as for Bill, he was eating only beans.’
The following exchange shows that the predictions in (b) and (d) are also correct:
() Who ate the pasta at the party?
() Well, I don’t know about the pasta, but …
a. BILL-MAN khong-un mekesse. (CF CT)
Bill-only beans-nun ate
b. khong-uni Bill-man ti mekesse. (CTi CF ti )
‘as for the beans, only Bill ate them.’
I now turn to Japanese. Due to the fact that contrastive topics in Japanese must appear
in clause-initial position, it may appear that none of the predictions can be tested.
However, the prediction in (a) can be shown to be correct by examining data
involving an embedded clause. A contrastive topic can appear in an embedded clause,
What is at the core of the predictions in (a) and (b) is whether the structures are mapped to an
ill-formed or well-formed structure with respect to (). Thus, the same reasoning for (a) and (b)
should apply to structures where movement of one contrastive item does not cross the other contrastive
item, giving rise to another pair of predictions in (i).
(i) a. [ CF [ … tCF … CT … ]]
b. [ CT [ … tCT … CF … ]]
Due to lack of space, I cannot discuss these predictions. However, Vermeulen () shows that these
predictions are borne out for both Japanese and Korean. The fact that (ia) is ill-formed shows that the
ill-formedness of the structure in (a) cannot be reduced to a Relativized Minimality violation (Rizzi
) either, by assuming that the feature composition of a contrastive topic may be richer than that of a
contrastive focus, for instance.
Vermeulen
as shown in (), uttered in the context in (). The context makes kono CD ‘this CD’ a
contrastive topic, as it shifts the topic of discourse from the book. The presence of kare
‘his’, which is coreferential with the matrix subject Bill, ensures that the embedded
clause is not a direct quotation.
() John finds a book on Sue’s desk and he asks Bill to tell him something about
the book. Bill does not know anything about the book, but he knew how Sue
obtained a CD that was also on the desk. So, he decides to tell John about the
CD. In describing this situation, you utter ().
() Billj -wa [CP kono CD-wai Mary-ga karej -no mise-de Sue-ni ti
Bill-wa [CP this CD-wa Mary-nom he-gen shop-at Sue-to
ageta to] omotteiru.
gave that thinking
‘Billj thinks that as for this CD, Mary gave it to Sue in hisj shop.’
Independently, a contrastive focus can undergo long-distance scrambling in cases of
correction:
() Bill-wa [John-ga Sue-ni CD-o ageta to] omotteiru.
‘Bill thinks that John gave Sue a CD.’
() Ie, ANO HON-Oi Bill-wa [John-ga Sue-ni ti ageta to] omotteiru.
no that book-acc Bill-wa John-nom Sue-to gave comp thinking
‘No, Bill thinks that John gave a book to Sue.’
The prediction here is that it should be impossible to combine these two operations,
as this will result in the ill-formed structure in (a). The prediction is borne out: the
example in (), uttered as a correction of the statement in () is infelicitous.
() Billk thinks that Mary gave this book to Jenny in hisk shop.
() ‘No, Bill didn’t know anything about the book, but …
SUE-NI i Billk -wa [CP kono CD-waj Mary-ga karek -no mise-de ti tj
Sue-to Bill-wa this CD-wa Mary-nom he-gen shop-at
ageta to] omotteiru.
gave that thinking
Lit.: ‘it’s to Sue that Billk thinks that as for this CD, Mary gave it to her in hisk
shop.’
Crucially, the sentence is acceptable if the focus remains in situ, which is possible in
the same context, in accordance with the prediction in (b):
Slight unnaturalness arises here due to the repeated mention of Bill-wa in (), but this does not affect
() … Billk -wa [CP kono CD-waj Mary-ga karek -no mise-de SUE-NI tj ageta to]
omotteiru.
‘… Billk thinks that as for this CD, Mary gave it to Sue in hisk shop.’
The data in this section provide support for the idea that overt displacement of topics
and contrastive items in these languages has direct consequences for the mapping
between syntax and information structure. Moreover, the Korean data provide further
evidence against the standard view that a contrastive nun-phrase can function as a
contrastive topic only in clause-initial position.
The data considered in the literature regarding contrastive wa involve predominantly cases where the
subject bears contrastive wa. However, the same contrastive interpretation obtains when an object in situ
is marked with contrastive wa in similar contexts, and Hara’s analysis can be extended straightforwardly to
these cases (Yurie Hara, p.c.).
Vermeulen
Hara extends the analysis to non-quantified DPs. In a context where there are two
relevant individuals, Mary and Bill, that John could have helped, the example in ()
has the implicature that John probably did not help Bill.
() John-ga mary-wa tasuketa.
John-nom Mary-wa helped
‘John helped Mary.’
The stronger alternative that () induces is that John helped both Mary and Bill,
which the speaker thinks could be false. However, the speaker just asserted that John
helped Mary. The hearer can therefore infer that the intended implicature is that John
did not help Bill.
Contrastive nun in Korean has a meaning very much like that encoded by con-
trastive wa in Japanese (Choi , C. Lee , , , M. Lee , Hetland
). Thus, where only Yenghi and Inho are the relevant individuals that Swuni could
have met, the sentence in () implies that Swuni did not meet Yenghi.
() Swuni-ka inho-nun manna-ss-e.
Swuni-nom Inho-nun meet-past-decl
‘Swuni met Inho.’ (Choi : , slightly modified)
Similarly, C. Lee () proposes that contrastive nun evokes a scalar implicature like
that induced by contrastive wa in Japanese on Hara’s proposal. The sentence in ()
implies that no more than one person came: a stronger scalar alternative is that ‘two
people came’ and the implicature is that it could be false.
() han saram-un w-ass-ta.
one person-nun come-past-decl
‘One person came.’ (C. Lee : (b), slightly modified)
There are obviously differences amongst the proposals offered in the literature. How-
ever, one common feature is that a contrastive wa- or nun-phrase generates a set
of alternatives and has a particular implicature, akin to uncertainty, regarding the
alternatives. I believe that this line of analysis provides a correct characterization of
the interpretation of contrastive wa- and nun-phrases in general. However, although
contrastive topics are typically marked by contrastive wa and nun in Japanese and
Korean respectively, nothing inherent in this interpretation makes a contrastive wa- or
nun-phrase a topic, i.e. what the rest of the sentence is about, introducing the referent
as the topic of discourse. I propose that contrastive wa- and nun-phrases can also
function as foci. Contrastive wa and nun attached to a focus has the function of further
modifying the meaning of the focus, in a similar fashion to focus-sensitive particles
such as dake/man ‘only’, and sae/to ‘even’ (Kuroda , , Oshima ). Con-
trastive wa- and nun-phrases have prosodic properties that are identical to contrastive
‘Contrast’ and its Relation to wa and nun
foci in the respective languages (S. Tomioka , Kim , and references therein).
Thus, if they are not interpreted as contrastive topics, the most natural analysis is that
they are foci.
There are other reasons to believe that contrastive wa- and nun-phrases that are
not topics are indeed foci. First, recall that topics must be referential (section .).
The fact that quantifiers such as nanninka ‘some people’ in () and han saram ‘one
person’ in () can be marked by contrastive wa and nun, and receive a non-specific
reading, suggests that they are not topics. Secondly, a contrastive wa- or nun-phrase
can correspond to a wh-expression in the preceding question. Thus, the sentences in
() and () can be uttered as answers to ‘Who did John help?’ and ‘Who did Swuni
meet?’ respectively (Choi , Hara ). If we take this diagnostic test for focus
seriously, then one must conclude that the contrastive wa- and nun-phrases are foci.
Finally, the predictions discussed in the previous section provide syntactic evidence
that contrastive wa- and nun-phrases need not be contrastive topics. Specifically,
contrastive wa- and nun-phrases that are foci should not be subject to the restriction
for contrastive topics in (a), repeated below:
() a. [ CF [ … CT … tCF … ]]
The prediction is correct for both languages. The Japanese utterance in () contains a
contrastive wa-phrase in situ in the embedded clause, which by virtue of its non-initial
position and non-specificity cannot be a contrastive topic. In correcting this state-
ment, the contrastive focus Sue-o can undergo long-distance scrambling, as shown
in (). The contrast between (b) and () would be unexpected if all contrastive
wa-phrases were contrastive topics, as standardly assumed in the literature.
() Billj -wa [CP Mary-ga sukunakutomo -nin-ni-wa Jane-o karej -no mise-de
syookai-sita to] omotteiru.
‘Bill thinks that Mary introduced Jane to at least three people in his shop.’
() a. Ie, Billj -wa [CP Mary-ga sukunakutomo -nin-ni-wa
no Bill-wa Mary-nom at least -cl-to-wa
SUE-O karej -no mise-de syookai-sita to] omotteiru. (foc-WA CF)
Sue-acc he-gen shop-at introduced that thinking
b. ?Ie, SUE-Oi Billj -wa [CP Mary-ga sukunakutomo
no Sue-acc Bill-wa Mary-nom at least
-nin-ni-wa ti karej -no mise-de syookai-sita to] omotteiru.
-cl.-to-wa he-gen shop-at introduced that thinking
(CFi foc-WA ti )
‘No, it is Sue that Bill thinks that Mary introduced to at least three people in
his shop.
Vermeulen
The prediction is also correct for Korean, as shown below in a similar context. The
felicity of () shows furthermore that a contrastive nun-phrase in clause-initial
position is not necessarily a contrastive topic, contra the standard description in the
literature.
() Ceketo sey-myeng-uy haksayng(tul)-un Chelswu-lul mannass-e.
‘At least three students saw Chelswu.’
() a. Aniyo. ceketo sey-myeng-uy haksayng(tul)-un
no at least -cl-gen student-pl-nun
YENGHI-LUL mannass-e.
Yenghi-acc saw-decl (foc-NUN CF)
b. Aniyo. YENGHI-LULi ceketo sey-myeng-uy
no Yenghi-acc at least -cl-gen
haksayng(tul)-un ti mannass-e.
student-pl-nun saw-decl (CFi foc-NUN ti )
‘No. At least three students saw Yenghi.’
I have proposed that contrastive wa and nun are not inherent markers for contrastive
topics. So why are contrastive topics typically marked by these particles in Japanese
and Korean? I argue that this is because there is a significant overlap in the implicature
induced by contrastive wa and nun and the interpretation of a contrastive topic. The
implicature induced by the particles, as discussed above, is that the speaker thinks
that a stronger scalar alternative to the proposition expressed by the sentence could
be false, and the interpretation of a contrastive topic is that the speaker is rejecting an
alternative assertion for some reason. If this is on the right track, one might expect
that contrastive topics can be marked by other means than contrastive wa or nun. This
is true at least for Japanese: they may be marked by nara (Munakata ):
() Who ate the pasta?
() Well, I don’t know about the pasta, but …
suupu-nara Mary-ga tabete ita yo.
soup-nara Mary-nom eating past part
‘as for the soup, Mary was eating (it).’
Note that in English, too, the so-called B-accent can mark items that are not topics in the sense of
In English too, therefore, it seems plausible that the B-accent only indicates a contrast of the type that is
compatible with contrastive topics and the topic status of a contrastive topic is identified by discourse (see
Molnár , Hetland , and Wagner for related ideas).
‘Contrast’ and its Relation to wa and nun
. Conclusion
I have examined the syntactic distribution of contrastive topics and contrastive foci
in Japanese and Korean, adopting the definitions independently motivated by dis-
course considerations for these notions, and their interaction with contrastive wa in
Japanese and contrastive nun in Korean. In doing so, I have argued that the meaning
encoded by contrastive wa and nun is compatible with both topic and focus. I have
provided a number of syntactic arguments against the standard characterizations
offered in the literature that contrastive wa-phrases are invariably contrastive topics,
and that contrastive nun-phrases are contrastive topics in clause-initial position and
contrastive foci elsewhere. The arguments were based on predictions that follow from
a particular theory of mapping at the interface (Neeleman et al. ), which does not
postulate designated functional projections for topic, focus, or contrast in the syntax.
The observed data are difficult to capture on an approach that assumes much of the
discourse is represented in the syntax, such as the cartographic approach (Rizzi ;
see also Haegeman and Hill, Chapter below).
Part III
. Introduction
If one assumes that the layers of morphology mirror the hierarchy of syntax (Baker
, ) and that there is a correlation between phonological and syntactic cycles
(Embick , Marantz , Michaels , Travis , among others), then the
treatment of vowels in hiatus (i.e. VV sequences) in Ojibwe, an Eastern Algonquian
language, offers a perfect laboratory to examine different syntactic architectures that
are imprinted on the phonology. We argue that the three different possible outcomes
of vowel hiatus mirror three different configurations—all created through head move-
ment. Piggott and Newell () previously proposed that, while VV sequences are
allowed to remain across Spell-out domains, a VV sequence within a Spell-out domain
is resolved through vowel deletion and a post-syntactic operation creates the context
where consonant insertion applies. In this chapter we investigate a particular problem
for the proposals of Piggott and Newell and solve it by allowing complex adjunction
within a word. While these adjuncts can be complex, we argue that they are not
phrasal. We propose that tools of the grammar allow the creation of complex heads in a
separate workspace that are spelled out and then merged into the structure. Crucially,
we maintain the standard position in linguistics, stated explicitly in Baker (: ),
that words cannot contain phrasal material.
Valentine (). We adopt the theory of Distributed Morphology (Halle and Marantz
), which postulates that words are generated by principles that are essentially the
same as those that generate sentences, a proposal also adopted by Baker (). These
principles manipulate abstract items, consisting of bundles of features; concrete real-
ization is determined post-syntactically. We also adopt the theory of cyclic derivation
now referred to as derivation-by-phase (Chomsky , ). Phonetic interpreta-
tion is determined at the Spell-out of elements of the phase to the PF interface, while
meaning is assigned at the simultaneous transfer to the LF interface. Since phase-by-
phase interpretation is cyclic, phonological and semantic properties determined on
cycle n are transferred to cycle n + . Cyclic derivation has been a fundamental ele-
ment of linguistic theory for decades. It has informed developments in phonological
theory such as SPE (Chomsky and Halle ), Lexical Phonology (Kiparsky ,
), and Stratal OT (Kiparsky , Bermúdez-Otero, in preparation).
While syntactic operations feed Spell-out, Distributed Morphology assumes that
structure can be adjusted post-syntactically. Two relevant post-syntactic operations
are Lowering and Local Dislocation (Embick and Noyer ). Lowering occurs
before the operation that inserts vocabulary items and adjoins a head to the head of its
complement, while Local Dislocation applies after vocabulary insertion and adjoins a
head to an immediately adjacent head.
adverb can appear in different positions in a sentence without affecting the meaning.
However, (c) shows that an adverb cannot separate a tense morpheme from a verb.
() a. owadi gi‰namadabi
owadi gi:-namadabi
over there past-sit
‘He sat over there.’
b. gi‰namadabi owadi
gi:-namadabi owadi
past-sit over there
‘He sat over there.’
c. gi‰ (∗ owadi) namadabi
gi: (∗ owadi namadabi
past (∗ over there sit
‘He sat over there.’
The occurrence of the negative particle ga‰wi‰ ‘not’ is further proof that the tense
morpheme and the verb are not treated as separate words. While the negative particle
always precedes the verb, it cannot appear between the tense morpheme and the verb
(e.g. wi‰(∗ ga‰wi‰)namadabisi‰ ‘he will not sit’).
Restrictions on the mobility of adverbs also provide evidence that another pre-
radical morpheme, the modifier, is not an autonomous word. Adverbs may occur
before or after verbs, but they never occur between a modifier and a verb.
() a. wi‰ba gi‰inidago+in
wi:ba gi:-ini-dagoSin
early past-away-arrive
‘He arrived there early.’
b. gi‰inidago+in wi‰ba
gi:-ini-dagoSin wi:ba
past-away-arrive early
‘He arrived there early.’
c. ∗ gi‰ini wi‰ba dago+in
gi:-ini wi:ba dagoSin
past-away early arrive
‘He arrived there early.’
d. ∗ gi‰ wi‰ba ini dago+in
gi: wi:ba ini dagoSin
past early away arrive
‘He arrived there early.’
The negative particle cooccurs with an obligatory negative suffix /-si:/ attached to the verb.
Piggott and Travis
The absence of the subject agreement prefix in (a) is a consequence of the fact that the second verb is
in the Conjunct mode, where subject agreement is encoded in suffixes rather than prefixes.
It has been noticed (e.g. Valentine : –) that an emphatic particle may appear immediately after
a tense morpheme or even after a modifier. It is interesting to note that Valentine considers these to be slips
of the tongue. Nevertheless, this observation does not undermine our claim that tense morphemes and
modifiers are not autonomous words, because the occurrence of emphatic particles may be prosodically
controlled, in a manner similar to the insertion of the expletive ‘fuckin’ in an English word such as ‘fan-
fuckin’-tastic’. In others words, emphatic particles are inserted at prosodically well-defined boundaries in
Ojibwe (and in other Algonquian languages). Dahlstrom () cites some Fox examples showing that
preverbs can be separated from verbs by both subject and object DPs. All of the examples come from old
sources (Michelson , Bloomfield ) and have not been replicated in any recent fieldwork that we
are aware of. These examples need to be studied more closely.
Adjuncts Within Words and Complex Heads
The preverbal modifier position is occupied by elements with a range of meanings. Valentine ()
asserts that the range of meanings associated with such elements include desire, obligation, direction,
quantity, quality, manner, and number. Hence, in addition to directional elements such as /bi/ ‘here, towards
speaker’, /ini/ ‘there, away from speaker’, and /biba:/ ‘around’, there are also attributives (e.g. /wa:bi/ ‘white’)
and locatives (e.g. /ipa:/ ‘above’, /nitami/ ‘in front’), manner (e.g. /gi:mo:dZi/ ‘quietly’, /ginibi/ ‘quickly’), etc.
While ‘here’ and ‘there’ may seem like goals, we are treating them all as modifiers.
Adjuncts Within Words and Complex Heads
() a. gi‰mo‰dÇia‰nimita‰gozi
gi:mo:d-i a:nimita:gozi
quiet-fin talk
‘He whispers.’
b. [[gi:mo:d-i ] a:nimita:gozi ]
The preverbal element in () consists of a root /gi:mo:d/ and the final which we assume
instantiates the category-defining suffix /i/. Together these form the modifier.
Taking these two complications together—the existence within a word of vowel
hiatus and the existence within a word of complex material—we are forced to con-
front a larger question: what are the restrictions on word formation? Since Baker
(), the assumption within the Chomskyan paradigm (and Distributed Morphol-
ogy: Halle and Marantz ) has been that concatenation of heads creates words.
These heads may be combined through a variety of means such as head movement
to a higher head, head lowering, and Local Dislocation (see Embick and Skin-
ner ), but in all these cases, the word is an X which dominates only other
X and no phrasal material. Baker () encodes this restriction in the following
filter:
() Morphological well-formedness condition (Baker : )
*X
|
Xn , where n is greater than
Forms consisting of a modifier plus a verb or noun such as the ones we have just seen,
however, challenge such a restrictive view of word formation. Below we first present
our view of how such forms can be constructed without giving up a restricted view
of word formation, and then we examine other accounts that allow phrasal material
within words and discuss some concerns raised by these accounts.
Note that the same root is independently attested in the verb /gi:mo:dizi/ ‘to sneak around’.
As will be mentioned again below, more recently the theoretical viability of head movement has been
questioned. We follow Baker and others (e.g. Bobaljik , Embick , Halle and Marantz , Harley
and Noyer ) in assuming there is head movement and that complex heads spell out as words.
See Embick (: ) for a discussion of the ‘packaging’ of heads into words.
Piggott and Travis
structure that they adjoin to. Further, in order to account for complex adjuncts, we
propose that complex heads can be created under certain configurations of Merge.
Note that this modifier cannot undergo Late Adjunction since its phonological realization must be
() TP
T vP
Advn vP
v VP
So the question is how the resulting structure, a word, is able to have an adjunct
embedded within it. We turn to this problem now.
Advn vP
√
Advn v VP
Constructions such as these have led other researchers to propose analyses where
phrasal material may appear within words, and to propose that words in languages
like Ojibwe are not formed through head movement. Below we will discuss two such
accounts, Mathieu () for Ojibwe and Wojdak () for Nuu-chah-nulth; but
first we propose a solution that maintains a restrictive definition of word. We argue
that it is possible to create complex heads in a separate workspace and then head-
adjoin this already complex (and spelled-out) head into the existing structure. In the
end, this gives the appearance of having word-internal phrases, but we will argue that
this analysis has both empirical and conceptual advantages.
.. An account
Our account for this construction contains three steps—all independently motivated.
The first step is to accept the traditional view of head movement that creates a head-
adjoined structure such as that given below through internal merge even though
this involves waiving the Extension Condition on Merge of Chomsky () (see
Matushansky and Harley for alternatives).
See Mathieu (), and Barrie and Mathieu (), for similar data and discussion.
We say ‘the traditional view’ because many have claimed that there are theory-internal reasons to
want to exclude head movement as a possible mechanism of Universal Grammar (see e.g. Chomsky ,
Piggott and Travis
() XP
X YP
Y X <Y> WP
In the second step, we accept the proposal that head adjunction may occur by exter-
nal merge as well as internal merge. It has long been accepted that the merging of
phrasal material has two possible forms—external merge, where material is taken
from another workspace, and internal merge, where material is taken (copied) from
the structure that is being merged to. Ideally the merging of heads and the merging
of phrasal material should have parallel possibilities, and it is not clear how external
merge of a head to create a structure similar to () could be ruled out. Therefore, one
should expect to find head adjunction structures created by external merge as well,
resulting in a structure such as () below.
() XP
X YP
Z X Y WP
Here, the material adjoined to the head X is taken from the numeration and is not
a head copied from the existing structure. Naoko Tomioka (, ) posits such
adjunction structures to explain the verbal properties of resultative verb complexes in
Japanese. A relevant example is given in ().
() Kotaro-ga hi-o huki-keshi-ta.
K-nom fire-acc blow-extinguish-past
While it is tempting to give a translation such as ‘Kotaro blew on the fire until it was
extinguished’ with huki ‘blow’ as the main verb, Tomioka gives two arguments against
such an analysis. First, Japanese words are head-final, so one would expect the order to
be keshi-huki ‘extinguish-blow’ if huki ‘blow’ were the main verb taking the result keshi
‘extinguish’ as its complement, but this is not the correct order. Second, she shows that
huki ‘blow’ cannot take hi ‘fire’ as a direct object with the meaning intended in this
construction. The example below shows that the direct object of huki ‘blow’ is what is
being blown out of the mouth, not what is being blown on.
Koopman and Szabolcsi ). This is still a matter of debate, however (see e.g. Lechner , Roberts
). Given that we adopt the basic assumptions of Distributed Morphology, we also are proponents of
head movement.
This is especially the case in views of head movement such as Matushansky (), where the first
V DP
V V fire-acc
blow extinguish
These structures are constructed through Pair Merge (as opposed to Set Merge),
where, in Chomsky’s words ‘we might intuitively think of · as attached to ‚ on a
separate plane, with ‚ retaining all of its properties on the “primary plane” ’ (Chomsky
: –).
The third step of this argument would allow such complex head structures to be
created in a separate workspace. In other words, it is accepted that specifiers can be
built in a separate workspace, be sent to Spell-out, and then added to a more complex
structure as a single spelled-out phrasal unit (e.g. Nunes and Uriagereka ). We
argue that complex heads of the sort that were created by external merge in ()
above may also be built in in a separate workspace, be sent to Spell-out, and then
added to a more complex structure as a single spelled-out head unit. These complex
heads will not, however, be able to select complements because they will not be able
to have unsatisfied selectional features at Spell-out. They will, then, only be able to act
as adjuncts. It is exactly this structure that is found in the Ojibwe examples we saw in
() and (). We repeat () in () below and give the appropriate derivation in ().
The complex head of /gi:mo:d/ and /i/ is created in a separate workspace. Then this
complex head is head adjoined to the V via external merge.
() a. gi‰mo‰dÇia‰nimita‰gozi
gi:mo:d-i a:nimita:gozi
quiet-fin talk
‘He whispers.’
b. [[gi:mo:d-i ] a:nimita:gozi ]
Piggott and Travis
() I. Workspace
a VP
√
a V XP
gi‰mo‰d -i a‰nimita‰gozi
X YP
II. Workspace VP
V XP
X YP
a V
√ a‰nimita‰gozi
a
gi‰mo‰d -i
.. Consequences
We have proposed first that complex heads may be created both within a structure
via external merge and further that complex heads may be created in a separate
workspace and then externally merged with another head in the structure. We have
done this for the conceptual reason of maintaining a strict view of wordhood. One
might ask, however, if we are creating a less restrictive system by allowing merged
heads not to project to a phrasal node. In other words, when two heads are merged,
how do we know if this is Set Merge or Pair Merge? While this question requires
more careful consideration, we tentatively propose that these structures are created
only in modifier relationships. More specifically, we propose that phrasal projections
are created whenever merge involves feature checking. If selection is done via feature
satisfaction (e.g. Svenonius ), then the projection is always phrasal. When there
is an adjunct relation, no feature is checked and no phrasal projection is formed. This
√ √
has the interesting fall-out that a and little x can create a head only when the has
no arguments.
Now we turn to two analyses in the literature that account for word-internal com-
plexity by allowing phrasal material to appear within words. We begin with Wojdak’s
() account which allows word formation through a process called Local Spell-out.
Then we review Mathieu’s () account, which allows phrasal movement to create
words.
()
-’in
pl.imp -šiL
&
perf -c’uq
in.mouth -p’aë čamas
taste sweets-
There are two reasons why this sort of analysis will not address the issues raised
by the Ojibwe data we are investigating. First, in Wojdak’s account, it is crucial that
linearization within the word (and the affixal status) is determined by the affixation
information on at least one of the merged elements. In each of the spelled-out domains
above, there is a suffix being added. This affixal information is encoded on the lexical
An additional problem is that it is not clear to us how the syntactic structure is decided a priori. The
tree given has no labels and it is difficult to determine, without knowing the final morpheme order, what
semantic relationships are responsible for creating this structure.
Adjuncts Within Words and Complex Heads
item and does not percolate up to complex nodes. For example, we examine the
status of the constituent that contains -p’aÆ and čamas. We might assume that -p’aÆ
is the head of this structure and that -p’aÆ percolates its features to the projection
that immediately dominates it. One has to assume, however, that the suffixal status
of the lexical item is not percolated to this projection since this projection does not
behave as a suffix with respect to the material that it merges with next, in this case
-c’uq.
However, if affixal status cannot project to complex constituents, it is not clear how
two complex structures can be merged as is needed in the structure we are dealing
with repeated in ().
() vP
Advn vP
√
Advn v VP
At the point where Advn and vP are merged, as neither one is a lexical category and
therefore cannot bear the necessary affixal information, there would be no subsequent
affixation, contrary to fact.
The second problem arises because within the system of Local Spell-out that Woj-
dak presents, the three responses to vowel hiatus would be left unexplained. There
should be two types of phonological juncture in her system—those created by Local
Spell-out and those created at the edge of a saturated constituent (DP and CP). As
Piggott and Newell (, ) argue, Ojibwe clearly has phasal domains that are
not as small as every branching category nor as large as a DP. In other words, there
are phase edges within DPs, something that cannot be accounted for in any obvious
way in the system of Local Spell-out.
Chomsky ()). The borders of DPs and CPs therefore constitute “edges”.’ Mathieu
() observes a similar restriction in Ojibwe:
Let me point out that, although my claim is that Ojibwe INs [incorporated nouns] are phrasal,
this does not mean that they are necessarily fully phrasal. . . . I want to argue that the very high
functional tier of a nominal phrase in Ojibwe does not get incorporated.
The dilemma, then, is the following. Does one allow for phrasal incorporation and
then seek to explain why not all phrases incorporate, or does one restrict word for-
mation to heads and explain the apparent complexity of some elements within words
in a different manner? We choose the latter route for several reasons. First, there is
an account in the literature that would rule out head-movement in an example such
as (b). Li (), in an effort to explain why head movement does not move lexical
categories through functional categories back to lexical categories, proposes a notion
of improper head movement (much like improper XP movement from an A-position
to an A -position, back to an A-position). Whatever the analysis, the observation is
an important one. Head movement never contains C material between two Vs in,
for instance, productive causative constructions. We should not be surprised, then,
that D material is not found between N and V. When the restrictions on phrasal
incorporation begin to resemble restrictions on head movement, one must suspect
a missed generalization, and we assume that the lack of the higher DP material in
Ojibwe Noun Incorporation structures can be explained through this already existing
restriction on head movement.
Another reason not to accept the idea that only higher material in the phrase
structure is prohibited from appearing within a complex word comes from different
bits of data we have seen in this chapter. In section .. we saw free-standing adverbs
that have variable positions in the clause. In the body of the chapter, we have been
accounting for other adverbs that must appear within the verbal stem. It appears to be
a lexical characteristic whether an adverb belongs to the first or second group, and it
has nothing to do with structure. In other words, high adverbs (/Za:Zi/ ‘already, long
ago’) as well as low adverbs (/e:ga:dZ/ ‘slowly’) appear independently, and high adverbs
(/mat(w)e:-/ used when the event occurs at a distance from the speaker) as well as low
adverbs (/gi:mo:dZi/ ‘quietly’) appear within the verbal complex. Within our account,
adverbs would be lexically specified as to whether they can appear merged with the
category-defining head without projecting. In the Local Spell-out account, it seems
that the adverbs that attach to the verb would have to be merged low, and those that
appear independently would have to be merged high even though there would be no
semantic support for this distinction.
This discussion raises the question of what sort of incorporated structures our
account would rule out. We have claimed that base-generated complex heads cannot
Languages will also specify what is possible. Japanese allows external merge of heads for manner
contain argument structure. Any selection process will entail feature satisfaction,
and any feature satisfaction will entail projection to a phrasal constituent. While
√ √
proud-a might be a possible adjunct, proud-a-of-his-son, where the adjective has a
complement, would not be. We also would not expect noun incorporation to include
a full possessor.
. Conclusion
The interface between syntax and phonology highlights particular issues concerning
what words can consist of. To summarize the puzzle, it appears that phrase-like
material can appear within words in Ojibwe—there are phonological breaks and the
material can be complex. This suggests that the restriction of what can appear within a
word (and what can incorporate) has to be loosened in some languages. However, we
have argued that there are empirical and conceptual reasons to resist such a conclu-
sion. In both the Local Spell-out account of Wojdak () and the NP incorporation
account Mathieu (), something has to be said about the limits of what elements
can undergo these processes. We argue that these restrictions on word formation
follow from restrictions on head movement. The complexity observed within Ojibwe
words is not a case of phrasal material within a word but rather, complex adjunct
heads.
Of course arguments and argument-taking heads can be incorporated into higher heads through
head movement. For example, the head N of an argument can be incorporated into a V, or an argument
taking P can be incorporated into a V leaving behind its complement (see Baker ).
In Mathieu (, ), there is an example with a possessor given below.
(i) obezhgoogzhiimi
o-bebezhgoogzhi-im-i
-horse-poss-vai
‘He/she has a horse.’
It is noteworthy, however, that this construction contains a denominal verb and the overall meaning is
one of possession. This raises questions as to what the accurate structural analysis of this construction
would be, and whether one can have a possessive within an incorporated noun with a full verb. Again,
Dahlstrom () gives one Fox example from Michelson () where a possessed noun seems to have
been incorporated. More work needs to be done to understand the full range of this phenomenon.
. Introduction
The received view for languages like English and German is that in adjectival passives
the external argument of the underlying verb is not syntactically active, based on its
lack of control into purpose clauses and the absence of the disjoint reference effect.
In both respects, verbal passives behave differently, leading to the conclusion that the
external argument is present in the syntax, even in the absence of by-phrases (cf.
Baker, Johnson, and Roberts , Kratzer , among others). This is illustrated
by German, in which a morphological difference is made between adjectival passives,
which combine a past participle with sein ‘be’ ((a), (a)), and verbal passives, which
appear with werden ‘become’ ((b), (b)).
() a. ∗ Der Reifen war aufgepumpt, um die Fahrt fortzusetzen.
the tyre was inflated in order the journey to continue
intended: ‘The tyre was inflated in order to continue the journey.’
b. Der Reifen wurde aufgepumpt, um die Fahrt fortzusetzen.
the tyre became inflated in order the journey to continue
‘The tyre was (being) inflated in order to continue the journey.’
() a. Das Kind war schlampig gekämmt.
the child was slopp(il)y combed
‘The child was combed in a sloppy manner.’
(i) Disjoint reference: Someone (else) (has) combed the child.
(ii) Reflexive: The child (has) combed him/herself.
∗ For comments on earlier versions of this chapter, I thank Artemis Alexiadou, Boban Arsenijević,
Edit Doron, Scott Grimm, Louise McNally, Antje Roßdeutscher, Florian Schäfer, Rob Truswell, and two
anonymous reviewers. This work was supported by grant JCI-- from the Spanish Ministry of
Science and Innovation.
This does not hold universally. Anagnostopoulou (a), for instance, argues that one type of adjecti-
val passive in Greek (the -menos-type) has agentive properties that the German one lacks, including implicit
agents that can control into purpose clauses; this is further refined in Anagnostopoulou and Samioti (Ch.
below).
Gehrke
only appears with (potentially) reflexive predicates but not with other ones (see also
McIntyre ), and that, more generally, there are no differences between verbal and
adjectival passives with respect to external arguments: both contain passive Voice
heads that license this argument. This cannot be the whole story, since it does not
straightforwardly account for two facts to be discussed in this chapter: (i) not all by-
phrases that are possible with verbal passives are possible with adjectival passives, and
(ii) the differences between (apparent) external arguments with adjectival and verbal
passives go beyond purpose clauses and the disjoint reference effect.
The third theoretical option, then, which will be pursued here, is to maintain that
these constructions are adjectival passives, which have implicit external arguments
(in line with Bruening, to appear, McIntyre ) but whose by-phrases are different
from those with verbal passives (contra Bruening, to appear).
The overall topic of this chapter touches on several interface issues. First, there are
well-known issues concerning the lexicon–syntax interface. It is generally assumed
that the participles in adjectival passives are ultimately adjectives, but there is dis-
agreement as to whether such adjectives are formed in the lexicon (as implicitly
assumed for German by Maienborn a and subsequent work) or in the syntax
(e.g. Kratzer ). Here, I will take a syntactic position and treat adjectival passives
as true passives, which contain verbal structure associated with eventivity and which
undergo adjectivization at some point of the derivation. Thus, even though Bruening’s
(to appear) account will be argued to be incomplete, his overall conclusion that word
formation in the case of adjectival passives is syntactic in nature also underlies the
current proposal.
The main contribution of this chapter, however, lies at the syntax–semantics inter-
face. In particular, I will be concerned with the question what it means to have verbal
structure within adjectives and what the consequences are for the nature of the under-
lying event. My answer to this question will be that as a consequence of the adjectival
categorization of verbal material, the event associated with the verbal predicate does
not get instantiated but instead remains in the kind domain. I will propose that it
follows from this that event participants also remain in the kind domain and do not
get instantiated.
The chapter is structured as follows. Section . discusses the difference between
by-phrases with verbal and adjectival passives, as well as event-related modification
with adjectival passives in general, and establishes that even with adjectival passives
there are two kinds of by-phrase, event- and state-modifying ones. Section . out-
There are also cases where (English) adjectival passives allow for purpose clauses, as shown by McIntyre
() (see also Alexiadou, Gehrke, and Schäfer for similar examples from German). In a footnote,
Bruening dismisses purpose clauses as a diagnostic for external arguments, but does not further address
why they are more degraded with adjectival passives.
As we will see, adjectival participles touch upon another issue concerning word formation, namely
whether or not words can contain phrasal material. For reasons of space, I cannot address this issue in
sufficient detail or from a more global perspective, but see Piggott and Travis (Ch. above) for discussion.
Gehrke
lines the general proposal, according to which adjectival passives involve event kinds
rather than event tokens; event-related modifiers will be argued to modify this kind,
whereas state modifiers modify a state token. Section . concludes.
account, according to which such modifiers are licensed pragmatically, are not fully spelled out, nor does
she systematically investigate the properties of acceptable vs. unacceptable modifiers or provide a positive
characterization of the acceptable ones.
Still Puzzled by Adjectival Passives?
I will compare the by-phrases with the two passives to work out the differences and
understand the nature of the restrictions.
A first observation is that the complements of the by-phrases that are unacceptable
with adjectival passives (e.g. ()) are definite noun phrases that refer to a particular
entity in the discourse, whereas those in the acceptable ones such as () are indefinite
NPs or bare nouns. Second, only with verbal passives does an indefinite noun phrase
in a by-phrase introduce a discourse referent, which can be picked up by pronominal
anaphora in the subsequent sentence (a), not with adjectival passives (b).
() a. Die Zeichnung wurde von einem Kind angefertigt. Es hatte rote Haare.
the drawing became by a child produced it had red hairs
‘The drawing has been produced by a child. He/she had red hair.’
b. Die Zeichnung ist/war von einem Kind angefertigt. Es hatte rote Haare.
the drawing is/was by a child produced it had red hairs
‘The drawing is/was produced by a child. He/she had red hair.’
Third, only the complements of by-phrases with verbal participles (with werden
‘become’) but not with adjectival ones (with sein ‘be’) can be modified by common
intersective modification, such as adjectival (token) modification (a) or restrictive
relative clauses (b).
() a. Die Zeichnung {wurde/∗ ist/∗ war} von einem blonden Kind angefertigt.
the drawing {became/is/was by a blond child produced
‘The drawing {has been/is/was} produced by a blond child.’
b. Die Zeichnung {wurde/∗ ist/∗ war} von einem Kind angefertigt, das ich
the drawing {became/is/was by a child produced which I
im Kindergarten getroffen habe.
in the kindergarten met have
‘The drawing {has been/is/was} produced by a child that I met at the kinder-
garten.’
Finally, even in the presence of a by-phrase there is no control into purpose clauses in
adjectival passives, unlike what we find in verbal passives:
() Die Zeichnung {wurde/∗ ist/∗ war} von einem Kind angefertigt, um seinen
the drawing {became/is/was by a child produced in order its.dat
Eltern eine Freude zu machen.
parents.dat a happiness to make
‘The drawing {has been/is/was} produced by a child in order to make his/her
parents happy.’
Kind modification is possible (e.g. red ink in (a)), which follows from the general proposal underly-
In sum, the complements of by-phrases that appear with adjectival passives in Ger-
man, unlike those with verbal passives, are non-referential and have a rather generic
flavour. In the following section, we will see that this holds quite generally for event-
related modifiers of adjectival passives that name a participant of the underlying event.
() a. Die Karte ist/war mit einem Bleistift geschrieben. Er war blau.
the card is/was with a pencil written he was blue
‘The card is/was written with a pencil. It was blue’
b. ∗ Die Karte ist mit einem kurzen Bleistift geschrieben.
the card is with a short pencil written
intended: ‘The card is written with a short pencil.’
A second restriction, the generality of which has gone practically unnoticed, is that
the event in adjectival passives lacks spatiotemporal location (see Gehrke for a
more detailed discussion). It has been observed that adjectival passives are incompat-
ible with temporal frame adverbials (() is from von Stechow ; see also Rapp
).
() ∗ Der Computer ist vor drei Tagen repariert.
the computer is before three days repaired
intended: ‘The computer is repaired three days ago.’
The ban on temporal modification of the underlying event is more general, though.
For example, a modifier like recently cannot modify the underlying event but only the
state denoted by the construction. In particular, () can only mean that the door was
in the opened state recently (and probably is no longer), but not that the door is in the
opened state, with the opening having taken place recently.
() Die Tür war kürzlich geöffnet.
the door was recently opened.
‘The door was opened recently.’
What has not been noted is that spatial modifiers that pick up the location of the event
that brought about the consequent state are also generally bad.
() Die Reifen sind in der Garage aufgepumpt.
the tyres are in the garage inflated
intended: ‘The tyres are inflated in the garage.’
Based on these facts, I concluded in Gehrke () that the underlying event in
adjectival passives is not instantiated, and proposed that adjectival passives involve
Embick () claims for English adjectival passives that they give rise to an ambiguity with recently,
in allowing the second reading that is impossible in (). However, he shows this only with attributive
participles (e.g. the recently opened door), which actually display the same ambiguity in German. Rapp
() convincingly argues for German that such attributive participles should be analysed as reduced
relatives involving verbal rather than adjectival passives; it is possible that this analysis extends to English.
These examples are acceptable if the spatial frame creates some kind of temporal frame for the state
itself (see Maienborn b for further discussion). Under this reading, however, the PP clearly modifies
the consequent state, not the underlying event.
Gehrke
event kinds rather than tokens. More specifically, adjectival passives instantiate the
consequent state kind of an event kind.
This analysis was further supported by the observation that the restrictions on
event-related modification of adjectival passives match the restrictions on possible
antecedents of adverbial so, as described in Landman and Morzycki (), who treat
so as an event kind anaphora (in analogy to the nominal kind anaphora such; cf.
Carlson a). In particular, spatial and temporal modifiers, which modify an event
token, cannot antecede so, and they are also unacceptable with adjectival passives.
Furthermore, manner modifiers, which Landman and Morzycki propose to treat as
event kind modifiers, are acceptable in both, as they name or establish subkinds.
Finally, instruments, when they are acceptable, also name a subkind and can thus be
treated as manner in a broad sense, as the following example (from the Frankfurter
Rundschau corpus) indicates:
() Ihr weißgetünchter Körper ist mit Binden geschnürt.
her whitewashed body is with bandages strapped
‘Her whitewashed body is strapped with bandages.’
The with-phrase here does not name the actual instrument of an actual event that
brought about the state the subject is in, but rather makes the kind of state that the
subject is in more concrete: it is of the kind that would result from a strapping-with-
bandages-event kind, which in turn is a subkind of strapping event.
We can now make sense of the two-way distinction within manner adverbs pro-
posed by Anagnostopoulou (a): an adverb that relates to the degree to which
an object is in a particular state associated with the consequent state of an event
kind should always be acceptable with adjectival passives. This is arguably the case
in (a). If the modifier relates to the event itself, on the other hand, it names a
particular (sub)kind of event, under the current proposal. We can assume, then, that
only those modifiers are allowed that name established event kinds with identifiable
consequent states. With the unacceptable modifiers in () and (), however, there are
no established event kinds: there is no established event kind of emptying something
slowly or with pleasure, as much as there is no established event kind of emptying
with a pitchfork or by my niece.
Finally, I want to propose that a consequence of the idea that the event remains
in the kind domain and is not instantiated is that implicit event participants, such
as agents or instruments, are not instantiated either and equally remain in the kind
domain. From this, in turn, their more generic character and their inability to intro-
duce discourse referents follow.
Similar restrictions have been observed on kind modification in the nominal domain, which is only
possible if the modified noun refers to a ‘well-established kind’ (first by Carlson a):
(i) The {Coke / ??green} bottle has a narrow neck.
Still Puzzled by Adjectival Passives?
In sum, state modifiers (such as degree adverbs and temporal modifiers of the
state) are generally available with adjectival passives. Event-related modification, on
the other hand (manner adverbs, instruments), is only available if it modifies an
event kind and names an established subkind. In the next section we will see that
a distinction between state (token) and event kind modification similar to the one we
observed for adverbs is found with by-phrases with adjectival passives. In particular,
there is one type of by-phrase that behaves like the other event-related modifiers in
naming a subkind, whereas another type modifies the state directly.
One might wonder whether with-phrases can be of two types as well, then. I cannot come up with
examples of state-modifying with-phrases, however, so I assume that such phrases always modify events.
Gehrke
() a. Er ist von einer Melodie beeindruckt. Er hatte sie gestern im Radio
he is by a melody impressed he had her yesterday in the radio
gehört.
heard
‘He is impressed by a melody. He heard it yesterday on the radio.’
b. Er ist von einer Melodie beeindruckt, die er gestern im Radio
he is by a melody impressed which he yesterday in the radio
gehört hat.
heard has
‘He is impressed by a melody that he heard on the radio yesterday.’
To provide a syntactic explanation for the facts regarding prosody, word order, and
un-prefixation, I will first outline the main proposal. This proposal will depart from
Schlücker (), who treats by-phrase I as a ‘V-adjunct’ (following Maienborn
a) and by-phrase II as a ‘VP-adjunct’ (in the sense of Kratzer ). One reason
to depart from this account is that the modifiers under discussion are phrases, and
phrases adjoin to phrases (e.g. VPs), not to heads (such as Vs). Hence, both types
of by-phrase should adjoin at least to a VP, or to an even larger structure. Second,
Schlücker overlooked the crucial division between eventive and stative predicates,
i.e. the fact that by-phrase II appears only with stative predicates. Nevertheless, her
(informal) observation about the different nature of the complements fits the proposal
underlying this chapter. With these observations in hand, let us now turn to the
proposal.
analyse them as complex adjunct heads that are formed in a separate workspace and participate in word
formation via head movement. They furthermore argue that restrictions on such modification follow from
restrictions on head movement. If we adopt this proposal, the modifiers under discussion could be seen as
V-adjuncts. A potential problem, though, is that they can contain material that makes them appear more
phrasal than the Ojibwe adjuncts discussed, such as prepositions and adjectival kind modification (recall
red ink in (a)). Hence, I will continue to treat them as phrases modifying phrases (along the lines of
Kratzer ), and to derive the restrictions from the kind semantics.
Gehrke
There is one more thing we have to take into account, which is not discussed in
detail here but rather taken for granted. An adjectival passive commonly ascribes a
stative property to an object, which is the theme of the underlying verb; this stative
property is associated with the result or consequent state of the underlying verb, and
it is commonly assumed that the input has to be a resultative or telic verb, which
could be represented in various ways (see Gehrke for more details). Since the
precise implementation is not relevant at this point, I will simply follow McIntyre
() in representing this by a cause-relation and in labelling the agent or causer
‘Initiator’.
At this point, let us return to the question whether adjectival passives contain a
passive Voice layer, as suggested by Bruening (to appear). Essentially, we need to
account for the differences between the two passives with respect to the (un)restricted
availability of by-phrases and their (in)ability to introduce discourse referents. This
could be captured in two ways. First, we could argue against Bruening (to appear)
and follow the more traditional view that there is no VoiceP in adjectival passives (as
advocated by Kratzer , ). By-phrases with adjectival passives would then be
licensed by the causative semantics of the underlying verb.
Alternatively, we could follow Bruening (to appear) in assuming (something like)
passive Voice heads for both passives, but amend this syntactic account with a seman-
tic account of the differences between the two (as suggested in Alexiadou, Gehrke,
and Schäfer ). In the remainder of this chapter, I will spell out such a semantic
account and propose to place the differences in a separate head, solely responsible
for adjectivization. Leaning more towards the second option, then, I will actually not
commit to a separate VoiceP but will represent the Initiator argument as part of the
lexical semantics of the verb. Let us turn to the actual proposal.
The lexical semantics of a resultative verb, in this case schließ(en) ‘(to) close’, is given in
(a): there is an event e, which brings about a state s, with the holder of the state (the
theme) being y and the Initiator of the event being x. Passive participle formation
in (b) existentially quantifies over the external (Initiator) argument.
Following Lieber (), it is generally assumed that the participle is turned into
an adjective by zero-affixation (e.g. Kratzer , Maienborn a):
() cop [AP [A [geöffnet] ∅]]
The verb’s event variable has to be existentially bound (as a kind) at some stage
of the derivation, and this could happen either when the participle is formed or
when the participle is adjectivized. I propose that the event variable is bound as a
kind when the participle is adjectivized, i.e. when the category is changed or specified
(depending on the precise implementation). This allows a uniform analysis of passive
participles, whether they are used in verbal or adjectival passives.
Hence, at the stage of participle formation (b) both verbal and adjectival passive
participles are still identical. What makes adjectival passives different from verbal
passives is the adjectivization of the participle. At this point, it is also determined
that the implicit Agent of the event stays in the kind domain (represented as xk ). The
semantics of the adjectival head and the output of adjectivization are given in (c)
and (d), respectively. The internal argument of the underlying verb, in turn, is the
subject of the AP and thus has to be externalized at some point. McIntyre () and
Bruening (to appear) propose different versions of Î-abstraction of the verb’s object at
the point of adjectivization, and in principle either will do for our purposes. I will gloss
over the details here and assume that the output of adjectivization after externalization
of the verb’s internal argument is as in (e).
From this analysis it follows that an adjectival passive refers to the instantiation of
a result or consequent state kind of an event kind. The state is instantiated at some
later stage and temporally located, so that temporal modifiers can access the state’s
temporal index.
Event-related modifiers (including by-phrase I) have to apply before adjectiviza-
tion, since they modify an event, not a state, and since the event is closed off and
not accessible any more after adjectivization. From this it follows that adjectivization
I assume that e (and likewise s), without a subscript, ranges over both event (state) kinds and tokens,
and that the extension of any event predicate includes event kinds and event tokens.
Note that McIntyre () and Bruening (to appear) collapse the tasks I distribute over Part (pas-
sivization, existential quantification over the external argument) and Adj (stativization, externalization
of the internal argument) into one passive Voice head, which they label Part and Adj, respectively. The
dissociation of passivization and adjectivization is motivated by the idea that at the point of participle for-
mation both verbal and adjectival participles are alike, and more importantly by the need for an attachment
site for event-related modification before adjectivization, which renders the event inaccessible for further
modification (see below).
Some operator binds the state variable and asserts that the state takes place at an instant, which is part
can also target phrases (following Kratzer , ), and the relevant phrase in this
case is PartP. Event-related by-phrases, then, adjoin to PartP (the same holds for by-
phrases with verbal passives, since at this point both passives are the same). Adverbial
modification in general, then, either applies to the event kind (before (c)) or to the
state token (after adjectivization).
Part A
geschlossen ∅
() represents the phrasal case involving a modifier of the event kind (instruments,
by-phrase I). The input is the PartP and the PP modifier adjoined to it.
() Phrasal adjectivization: event kind modifiers
AP
PartP A
∅
PP Part
since only lexical adjectivization is compatible with the adjectival prefix un- (following
Kratzer ).
Finally, an adjectival passive with a by-phrase modifying a state token (by-phrase
II) is represented in ().
() Modifiers of AP: state modifiers
AP
PP A
. Conclusion
In this chapter I have shown that event-related by-phrases with German adjectival
passives are crucially different from by-phrases with verbal passives, since only a
subset of the by-phrases that are acceptable with verbal passives are also acceptable
with adjectival passives, and since furthermore those with adjectival passives do not
introduce a discourse referent. Based on the general restrictions on event-related
modification with adjectival passives, I proposed that German adjectival passives refer
to the instantiation of a consequent state kind of an event kind, and that therefore
event participants of such event kinds do not get instantiated but remain in the kind
domain as well. Finally, I argued that by-phrases with adjectival passives are acceptable
only if they modify either the event kind (naming an established subkind) or the
(consequent) state token (which is only possible with stative verbs).
The key idea underlying this proposal is that (re)categorization of verbal structure
as an adjective has consequences for the semantic nature of the underlying event:
it does not get instantiated. We should expect this idea to have repercussions for
the analysis of other non-verbal categories that have been argued to contain verbal
structure, such as nominalizations. Furthermore, we should expect some parallels
between event participants of deverbal adjectives and deverbal nouns.
A comparison of by-phrases with adjectival passives and with nominalizations
might be revealing for the overall question whether or not adjectival passives contain
Voice. Alexiadou, Anagnostopoulou, and Schäfer () argue that, in English, by-
phrases can be licensed by Voice (e.g. in verbal passives) or by encyclopedic knowl-
edge associated with the (underlying) verb (e.g. in -(a)tion nominalizations). They also
suggest that the German counterpart of -(a)tion is -ung. Unlike adjectival passives,
such nominalizations do not combine with phrases headed by von ‘by’, but only with
phrases headed by durch ‘through’ (introducing both agents and causers). This, in
turn, might indicate that the von-phrases in adjectival passives are licensed by Voice
after all and not just by encyclopedic knowledge. A more detailed investigation would
have to address the general question concerning prepositions across verbal and nom-
inal domains, also from a crosslinguistic perspective; however, this has to be left for
future research.
. Introduction
The chapter focuses on de-adjectival nominalizations, which show insightful interface
effects in two distinct domains of grammar in Serbo-Croatian (S-C): the morphosyn-
tactic process of derivation of nouns from adjectival stems, and the phonological pro-
cess of stress/tone assignment. In both domains, the results of the observed processes
come in two general flavours. As for morphosyntax, there is, on the one hand, a class
of nominalizations which are fully compositionally (transparently) derived from a
very broad set of adjectival stems using always the same derivational morpheme
(-ost). Due to these characteristics, we analyse such nominalizations as members of
the (extended) paradigm of the adjectival stems in S-C. On the other hand, there
are nominalizations which pattern together for being strikingly idiosyncratic: they
are derived only from a limited number of stems, use various derivational suffixes,
and come in most cases with a semantic shift with respect to the compositional
interpretation. In the other domain, stress and tone assignment, there is a comparable
dichotomy: there is a class of nominalizations in which the positions of tone/stress are
predictable from their position in the base word, and there is another class in which
another pattern emerges (either the phonologically unmarked pattern or the stress
pattern imposed by the suffix), resulting in a deviation from the prosodic properties
of the base word.
∗ We are grateful to René Kager, Tanja Samardžić, Marieke Schouwstra, Wim Zonneveld, our two
anonymous reviewers, and the audience of OnLI II for the many useful comments on the previous versions
of this chapter. The research presented here is partly supported by the research projects FFI- by
MICINN, and OI by MPNRS.
There are adjectives that do not nominalize at all, such as comparatives and superlatives, and very few
which derive only the other type of nominalizations, and which we briefly mention and discuss in fn. as
well as in section .. But with a marginal approximation, one can say that all adjectives that appear as
predicates also derive this type of noun.
Stress Assignment in Serbo-Croatian
We show that there is a neat match between these two domains. De-adjectival nom-
inalizations which are productive, and part of the paradigm, i.e. which are spelled out
to phonology with a rich and straightforward syntactic structure, have their stress and
tone copied from the base adjective. In idiosyncratic de-adjectival nominalizations, to
which we assign a less rich syntactic structure (a bare concatenation of the two ele-
ments), the unmarked prosodic pattern emerges, i.e. these nominalizations undergo
a purely phonological tone/stress assignment, insensitive to any non-phonological
features, most importantly the surface prosody of the base. Finally, even though a
strong correlation as described can be observed, there are cases where particular
stems do not derive one of the two types of nominalizations, i.e. where one of the
types takes on the interpretive effects normally typical of the other type, or where
the phonological environment does not allow for the contrast to be brought out (see
section ..).
The research question can be stated as follows: why does structurally complex,
transparent interpretation go hand in hand with stress/tone assignment sensitive
to the surface prosodic pattern of the base adjective? And why are there gaps in
this correlation? Our account crucially relies on the fact that faithfulness to the
surface prosody of the base word is a tool in the reconstruction of the internal
morphological structure of a complex word. When its components stand both for
their own lexical semantic contribution and for a sequence of syntactic structure,
identification of the elements is vital for the recoverability of the structure. When
the complex word has a non-transparent interpretation and as such constitutes a
lexical entry, its internal structure is not crucial for its interpretation and its syntactic
behaviour, so it also need not be recoverable, and phonology therefore does not take
the surface prosody of the base adjective into account. This analysis is supported
by the experimental findings that ‘modifying the stress of the stem will impede or
slow down access’ (Steriade , quoting Cutler ). The gaps are ascribed to
particular constraints, mostly phonology-internal but sometimes syntax-internal, on
the derivation of one of the two types of nominalization. As we shall see, there are
various ‘handshakes’, or guaranteed alignments, between syntactic structures and the
phonological structures which serve as their exponents, so that the variation explored
here is systematically excluded in many contexts for both semantic and phonological
reasons.
We make use of Steriade’s () concept of Lexical Conservatism to establish a
link between the internal syntactic structure of a derived word and the activation
of phonological constraints which require the preservation of the prosodic prop-
erties of the base adjective. The constraint family LC militates against the intro-
duction of novel allomorphs by enforcing the copying of the surface properties of
the listed allomorph in every new form. In the case at hand, LC(Stress/Tone)
requires the copying of the surface stress pattern of the base adjective. Crucially,
this constraint is sensitive to whether the form does or does not belong to the
Arsenijević and Simonović
Capital letters are used to mark prosodic prominence, which is marked by stress and tone in Serbo-
Croatian. The representations of Serbo-Croatian prosody are discussed further in section ..
Arsenijević and Simonović
Asymmetries between the two classes of nominalizations are best visible when the
same adjectival stem derives both a LDN and a SDN. Looking at examples of this
type, the following asymmetries can be observed.
When used for properties of particular persons and objects, matching in denota-
tion Moltmann’s () type of tropes, SDNs are more suitable, and LDNs are often
unacceptable.
() SlUčaajnoost/∗ slučAAjnOOst ovog uzorka ne dovodi se u pitanje.
randomness.sdn/ldn this sample.gen not lead refl in question
‘The random nature of this sample does not come into question.’
More precisely, LDNs are out if they have undergone a lexical semantic shift, becoming
idiosyncratic—usually in taking, as a more prominent or even the only one, one type
of reference: to events, situations, concepts, or some other semantic class. For all
meanings other than properties as instantiated in particular referents, some of which
are discussed in what follows, the LDN is a better candidate than its SDN counterpart
(the SDN often cannot receive the relevant interpretation). For instance, LDNs can
be modified by adverbials that select for quantized eventualities, while their SDN
counterparts cannot.
() a. česta opAAsnOost nekadašnja rudarska solidAArnOost
frequent danger.ldn earlier.adj miners’ solidarity.ldn
‘frequent danger’ ‘miners’ solidarity from the past’
b. ∗ (njegova) česta Opaasnoost ∗ nekadašnja rudarska sOlidaarnoost
Another asymmetry relates to a subtle intuition: while LDNs can have a generic
meaning, referring to a concept, an intensional property, SDNs always seem to imply a
bearer of a property, as instantiated in a particular referent. This asymmetry is similar
to the one between unaccusatives on the one hand and transitive verbs that allow for
a zero object on the other, where the former (e.g. sink, float, break) do not imply the
existence of an agent, and the latter (e.g. eat, read, wash) do imply the existence of an
affected participant.
() a. ta mala ljubAAznOOst o kojoj pričam, koju niko nije
that little kindness.ldn about which talk.sg which nobody neg.aux
pokazao …
shown
‘that little kindness that I’m talking about, which nobody manifested’
b. ta mala ljUbaaznoost o kojoj pričam, koju niko nije
that little kindness.sdn about which talk.sg which nobody neg.aux
pokazao …
shown
‘that little kindness that I’m talking about, which nobody manifested’
An SDN always denotes a property holding of a referent. An LDN may also have this
interpretation, but it is more naturally interpreted as talking about a generic notion,
intensional or extensional.
() a. KnjIžeevnoost ovog teksta je upitna.
literariness.sdn this.gen text.gen is questionable
‘The literariness of this text is questionable.’
b. KnjIžeevnoost ovog autora je upitna.
literariness.sdn this.gen author.gen is questionable
‘The literariness of this author is questionable.’
( unless the context makes literariness a natural property of an author)
c. KnjižEEvnOOst ovog autora je upitna.
literature.ldn this.gen author.gen is questionable
‘The literature (by this author) is questionable.’
d. KnjižEEvnOOst ovog teksta je upitna.
literature.ldn this.gen text.gen is questionable
‘The literature of/by this text is questionable.’
( unless a context is made where a certain piece of literature is part of a
certain text)
Finally, while semantic counterparts of LDNs are derived by many different (stem-
specific) suffixes, the semantics specific to SDNs only comes with nouns built by the
suffix -ost which is added to an adjectival stem.
Arsenijević and Simonović
That these suffixes are stem-specific means that they are also in mutual exclusion: where one is used to
derive a noun from an adjective, the others derive ill-formed words. Together with their shared semantics,
this implies that they belong to the same class, or even different instantiations of formally the same suffix.
As briefly discussed again in section . below, adjectives that involve an additional argument of
their degree component, such as comparatives, superlatives, or adjectives denoting equal degrees of two
arguments, also cannot derive SDNs. Assuming the reason is the impossibility of embedding the second
argument in the nominalization, this further confirms our analysis.
Stress Assignment in Serbo-Croatian
Finally, it is not necessarily the case that the semantic SDN–LDN asymmetry
triggers different phonological output. There are nominalizations like hUmaan-
oost ‘humanity/humaneness’, which have both the SDN and the LDN interpreta-
tion. Moreover, even in proper LDN–SDN pairs, one finds variation among the
speakers of S-C, such that one of the forms is not actively used, leaving the other
with both interpretations available, as in the case of hUmaanost above. In section
.. we show that the neutralization of the contrast is phonologically conditioned,
but also that the contrast is systematically blocked in some categories where it
could not be meaningful. In sum, the distinction is not always available, but we
shall show that whenever it is systematically unavailable, it is unavailable for a
reason.
Before presenting the analysis, we need to point out that a detailed analysis of
a closely related phenomenon in Slovenian can be found in Marvin (: –).
Although the focus of her research is on participant-denoting deverbal nominaliza-
tions, Marvin does observe asymmetries in Slovenian that parallel those discussed
in our chapter. Moreover, she sketches a syntactic analysis which shares one crucial
property with the analysis outlined here and discussed in more detail in Arseni-
jević (, ): that (in her case Slovenian) LDNs involve a syntactic simplex in
the adjectival component, while SDNs involve phrases (Marvin labels them ‘roots’
and ‘APs’). However, whereas in Slovenian the SDN/LDN distinction is prosodically
brought out in a small number of nominalizations from simplex native adjectives, in
S-C its scope is much larger and includes most Latinate adjectives (see Simonović
). On the theoretical side, while we agree in the general intuition that one type
derives from a simple item, and the other from a non-trivial syntactic structure, we
argue here that the latter type involves a rich syntactic structure (an entire PredP),
i.e. that it cannot be accounted for only in terms of categorial heads typical for
the current theory of Distributed Morphology (such as vC, vE, Voice: see Marantz
, Anagnostopoulou and Samioti, Chapter below). Also, the present chap-
ter devotes more attention to the sensitivity of phonology to syntactic structures,
while Marvin is primarily interested in the syntactic, phase-theoretic aspects of the
problem.
Transitive and unergative verbs make -ost-nominals from the passive participle, and with unaccusative
hit.ActPart-ost sing.ActPart-ost
An explanation is due in respect of what is traditionally referred to as the active
participle in S-C. This form is rather a subject-oriented participle, which assigns a
process or result interpretation of the respective verb to the subject (i.e. the agent)
if the verb is transitive or unergative, and only a result interpretation to the subject
of the verb if it is unaccusative (in this case, to the patient or theme). Only the latter
nominalize, and hence only result interpretations are attested on nominalizations of
the active participle.
The restrictions on participles in deriving SDNs can be formulated in a simpler
way: only those participles which can also be used with a copula, with an internal
argument as the subject, and receive an adjectival interpretation, can derive SDNs
with the ending -ost (see footnote above).
() a. Ruka je utrnul-a / obamrl-a.
arm is go numb.ActPart-F.Nom be paralysed.ActPart-F.Nom
‘An/The arm is numb/paralysed.’
b. Jovan je pevao (pesmu).
J Aux sing.ActPart song
‘Jovan sang a/the song.’
vs.
∗ Pesma je pevala.
song Aux sing.ActPart
intended: ‘The song went on.’
hence:
∗ peval-ost
sing.ActPart-ost
intended: ‘the property of having sung’ or ‘the property of having been sung’
This, together with the fact that the typical interpretation for an SDN is that of a
property as holding for a particular referent, suggests that a predication actually
underlies each SDN or, in syntactic terms, that SDNs derive from PredPs. As PredP is
a relatively high structural projection, this account also predicts that SDNs will always
have a transparent interpretation, i.e. that they will not be able to establish idiomatic
meanings, while LDNs will have available both options: compositional and idiomatic
interpretations (see Anagnostopoulou and Samioti, Chapter below, and Harley and
Stone, Chapter , for extensive discussion of the syntactic boundaries for idiomatic
interpretations).
Stress Assignment in Serbo-Croatian
Arsenijević () argues for a syntactic analysis in which the main asymmetry
between SDNs and LDNs is in their syntactic complexity. LDNs are derived from a
bare stem, without any internal syntactic structure (i.e. its structure is eliminated in
the process of lexicalization), while SDNs involve a richer structure, where a PredP is
nominalized.
() A simplified schematic representation of the syntactic structures of SDNs and
LDNs
N N
-ostN Opasan
-ostN PredP
Jovan Pred
Pred AdjP
Opasan
SDN: Opaasnost LDN: opAAsnOst
The semantic asymmetries are derived from the syntactic difference: LDNs nominal-
ize a concept corresponding to the lexical meaning of the stem, while SDNs nominal-
ize a predicative relation between an argument and a verbal or nominal predicate.
Nominalized predications are argued to be restricted to denote property instantia-
tions, i.e. tropes, and nominalized lexical meanings, by default, property types, but
they are also free to syntactically derive any other type of denotation, in particular
tropes and eventualities. While Arsenijević () merely hints at a phonological
analysis, in terms of the order of Spell-out, in this chapter we aim at providing a deeper
phonological analysis and drawing out the implications that it has for the status of
syntactic structure in a phonological process such as stress and tone assignment.
One anonymous reviewer remarks that our analysis of SDNs incorrectly predicts that they should allow
for accusative complements and expressions like *veoma opasnost ‘very dangerousness’, drawing a parallel
with similar effects observed on nominalizations of complex structures (see a summary in Kornfilt and
Whitman ). As for modifiers like veoma ‘very’, we explain their ungrammaticality in nominalizations
by the requirement of their scalar semantics for a positive morpheme (Kennedy and McNally ), and
the intervention effect of the nominalizing suffix. As we are discussing de-adjectival rather than deverbal
nominalizations, and adjectives in S-C do not take accusative complements, there is no reason why SDNs
should take accusative complements (in nominalized participles, the participle is already incompatible
with a complement in the accusative case). But it lends further support to our analysis, as asymmetries
in preserving complements of the base adjective do appear in the predicted way:
(i) a. on je bio impotEntan [u tom trenutku], ona je bila dOsaadna [preko svake mere]
he Aux been impotent at that moment she Aux been boring over every measure
b. njegova [impotEntnoost / ∗ impotEncIja [u tom trenutku]] /
his impotence.sdn *impotence.ldn at that moment
njegova [dOsaadnost / ∗ dOsaada [preko svake mere]]
his boringness.sdn *boredom.ldn over every measure
Arsenijević and Simonović
We argue that the relevant notion in this respect is that of paradigm. We take the
paradigm of a stem to include all the forms that can productively be built from each
member of the relevant class of stems, irrespective of the syntactic class of the product
(i.e. belonging to the nominal category in this particular case does not prevent an
item from being a member of the paradigm of an adjectival stem). Under such a
definition, de-adjectival nouns are members of the paradigms of adjectival stems,
as long as they can be derived from each member of one or more morphosyntactic
classes of adjectival stems. Paradigms are characterized by a high degree of trans-
parency: words derived are interpreted strictly compositionally with respect to the
internal structure. Derivations which do not satisfy this condition, and hence stand
outside the paradigm of the stem involved, are rather idiosyncratic in their nature,
and the derived word is prone to a shift in lexical meaning. This is especially likely to
be the case if the derivation proceeds via a relatively simple structural configuration,
as is the case with LDNs.
We have tested our predictions on data extracted from the dictionary (RMS
–) and through acceptability judgements of more than ten native speakers
of S-C. It was empirically confirmed that each of the adjectives of the relevant type
can derive a SDN, although in a small number of cases, these came with a degree
of (arguably pragmatic) degradation. Only a restricted number of adjectives were
attested to derive LDN forms. In what follows, we turn to the productivity of the
two types of nominalization. A generalization can be formulated that the more struc-
turally complex the stem is, the more likely that only a SDN will be derived from
it. For instance, as already discussed, participial and other adjectival forms which
arguably involve a VP structure (e.g. S-C counterparts of the English -able adjectives)
can only ever derive a SDN: their LDN counterparts are systematically ungram-
matical. Certain phonological restrictions apply as well, and these are discussed in
section ..
What we have seen so far has provided some converging evidence for our initial
proposal that in the default case, the SDN is a member of the paradigm of the adjectival
stem, while the LDN is an idiosyncratic instance of lexical derivation. This is also the
hypothesis on which we build our analysis of the sensitivity of phonology to syntactic
structures.
. Phonology
This section brings our phonological account, which makes crucial use of inter-
face constraints, in particular of their capacity to distinguish between members of
paradigms of the base (SDN) and lexicalized derivations (LDN). In order to present
our phonological account, we first need to introduce some preliminaries on S-C
prosody and the representations we use.
Stress Assignment in Serbo-Croatian
(tataataH →) tatAAtA: long rising span over second and third syllable
(tatata → taH tata →) tAtata: short falling accent on the first syllable
(taatata → taaH tata →) tAAtata: long falling accent on the first syllable
.. The locus of variation: -ost prosody and the default pattern
Ost-suffixation generally does not affect the lexical tone/stress of the adjectival stems.
As () shows, both surfacing rising span (a,b) and lexical falling accent (allowed
only in loanwords: see Simonović ) are preserved in the derived abstract nouns.
From this we can conclude that the suffix -ost either has no underlying tone or has
an underlying tone which gets overridden by that of the base. If the latter is the case,
-ost would be exceptional with respect to all the other nominalizing suffixes, which all
attract stress/tone () and which we further discuss in section ...
() a. gramAtIčn- ‘grammatical’ + -ost gramAtIčnoost ‘grammaticality’
b. UvEl- ‘withered’ + -ost UvEloost ‘witheredness’
c. konkrEtn- ‘concrete’ + -ost konkrEtnoost ‘concreteness’
The situation in the adjectival stems which surface with post-cyclic prosody—
tone/stress aligned with the left edge of the word, spelled out as an initial falling
accent—is much less clear. The few available generative descriptions are unclear as
to what the main pattern is. For instance, Inkelas and Zec () quote the example
in () to show that -ost is one of the suffixes after whose addition a High is added
at the right edge of the word. Note that the initial falling tone of jEdnaak is assigned
post-cyclically.
() jEdnaak ‘equal’ + -ost jednAAkOOst ‘equality’
On the other hand, Zec () presents the examples in (), in which the toneless
stems do not have any change of the position of stress/tone.
() a. lUUd ‘insane’ + -ost lUdoost ‘insanity’
b. hUmaan ‘humane’ + -ost hUmaanoost ‘humanity’
It is clear that jednAAkOOst and hUmaanoost are expected to display the same pattern
and that one of them has to be exceptional. As it turns out, the pattern in jednAAkOOst
is the odd one out, but this actually arises due to the specificity of its semantics.
As already hinted in footnote above, adjectives involving an overt degree argument,
We refer the interested reader who is wondering about the rationale behind the assignment of the
initial high tone to toneless words to Zec and Zsiga () for a recent account.
The fact that -ost is productive and applied to virtually every adjectival stem cannot be a basis for
a whole account here. For instance, the comparative suffix -ijii is just as productive, but it does affect
the stress/tone (e.g. the comparative forms of the adjectives in () are gramatIčnIjii, ‘more grammatical’,
uvElIjii ‘more withered’, and konkrEtnIjii ‘more concrete’).
Zec () also has a class of adjectival stems for which a floating lexical High is assumed. It is not
clear to us what the evidence in favour of this representation is. Furthermore, most examples provided by
Zec () are problematic to a sizeable number of our informants.
Stress Assignment in Serbo-Croatian
such as comparatives and superlatives, cannot derive any nominalizations. The adjec-
tive jEdnAAk ‘equal’ is neither comparative nor superlative, but still involves a degree
argument, as it specifies that a certain property holds to the same degree of two or
more referents. In a copular construction, it involves a second argument, which is an
argument of degree, just as in comparatives.
() Nisam ja jednak sa tobom.
neg.am I equal with you
‘I’m not equal to you.’
Our model hence predicts for this adjective that it cannot derive a SDN. However,
while comparatives are usually hard to take to the generic level (cf. ∗ biggerness,
∗ smarterness in English), the meaning associated to jEdnaak ‘equal’ can be taken to
the generic level, and hence this stem derives a LDN: jednAAkOOst ‘equality’.
In sum, the adjectives with post-cyclic prosody do not, as a group, show any evi-
dence for a H in the lexical representation of -ost. However, as we have seen already
in the examples in section ., there is a sizeable number of nominalizations derived
from adjectives which surface with post-cyclic prosody (e.g. Ispraavan) in which there
is a semantically conditioned variation in prosody between the pattern of copying the
surface pattern of the base adjective (Ispraavnoost) and creating a rising span on the
right edge (isprAAvnOOst).
Consulting the native speakers on our dataset of over nominalizations which
have a base which surfaces with post-cyclic prosody has enabled us to state the fol-
lowing generalizations about the distribution of the rising span (as in isprAAvnOOst):
() It never arises when the syllable preceding the suffix is short. So we only ever
have kIsel+oost ‘sourness’ and hrApav+oost ‘coarseness’, but no comparable
derivates with a rising span.
() Pace jednAAkOost, there are no de-adjectivals which have a single consonant
preceding -ost and rising span (hUmaanost, sImultaanost, Androgiinost, etc.).
() In the de-adjectivals with a long closed penult, the rising span is generally
possible and the variation depends on the semantic opposition between the
SDN and LDN.
The emergent prosodic pattern with a rising span points at a general tendency for
stress and weight to cooccur, formalized in the famous Stress-to-Weight constraint
Note that in words of the type Opaasnoost/opAAsnOOst and ljUbaaznoost/ljubAAznOOst, we are
assuming syllable boundaries cutting though the clusters consisting of fricatives and sonorants (sn, zn,
šn, žn, etc.) in spite of the fact that they can be syllable onsets in S-C (e.g. sneg ‘snow’ and znoj ‘sweat’).
We claim that these clusters are possible syllable onsets only word-initially. This claim is sustained by their
distribution. First, there are no S-C words in which these clusters are preceded by a consonant (which
would enforce the syllabification of the clusters as onsets): there are words like kasno and grozno as well as
words such as lipsati ‘to die’ and obzir ‘regard’, but no words like *kapsno and *grobzno. Note that we do not
claim anything about clusters of the type fricative + plosive (sp, sk, etc.), which never occur in the context
relevant here.
Arsenijević and Simonović
(Kager : ), as well as the fact that coda consonants seem to contribute to weight
in S-C. The fact that a ‘rising accent’ span is built at the end of the word, attracted
by a heavy syllable, is a well-attested preferred pattern in S-C (see e.g. Werle :
– discussion of the Rightward tone shift). The new insight is that this pattern
is not restricted to words which have an underlying tone (as generally assumed), but
actually occurs also in toneless environments under certain conditions and that it is
not only vowel length, but also coda consonants which create the environment for
the shift.
In order to make sense of the emergence of the rising span, it is instructive to
look at the -ost-nominalizations derived from monosyllabic and disyllabic toneless
adjectives.
() čIl(ii) ‘chirpy’ + -ost čIloost
glAtk(ii) ‘smooth’ + -ost glAtkoost
pEgav(ii) ‘freckled’ + -ost pEgavoost
čUUln(ii) ‘fleshly’ + -ost čUUlnOOst ∗ čUUlnoost
The generalization is that if the base contains a short syllable, the initial short falling
accent is carried over to the noun. However, if there is a long syllable in the base (so the
base adjective has a falling accent as in čUUlnii), the rising span arises: čUUlnOOst,
∗ čUUlnoost. There is, however, a small class of apparent exceptions to this generaliza-
There is one important difference between the adjectives of the type čUUlnii and those
of the type jOOn.skii. The latter class is exceptional in that its paradigm lacks the
indefinite forms, most importantly the nominative singular masculine form, the only
form in the adjectival paradigm which has a null ending. So there is the form čUUlan,
but there is no form ∗ joonsk/∗ joonsak.
This means that the entire paradigm of the adjectives of the type jOOn.ski has the
initial long closed syllable, whereas the paradigm of the words like čUUlnii always
contains a form like čUU.lan in which the long syllable is not closed. This seems to be
the point at which the grammar makes the distinction—only the consistently closed
syllable with a long vowel is good enough to ‘arrest’ the H in all the derivates. The
relevance of the syllabification clearly points at the importance of the surface form of
the base in word derivation, which is one of the main ingredients of our analysis. Here
we can see the first interesting handshake between syntax and prosody: due to the
There are no adjectival bases longer than one syllable which have a long syllable with a falling accent.
Stress Assignment in Serbo-Croatian
semantics of the adjectivizing suffix -sk, these adjectives will only ever derive SDNs.
The reason, in short and with some simplification, is that this suffix always attaches to a
noun interpreted as a referential nominal expression, hence always carrying complex
internal syntax, which cannot be represented in the flat structure of LDN. As we shall
see below, the hyperfaithfulness to the surface form of the base in SDNs is one of the
main features of the S-C system, for which our model accounts.
In sum, because most adjectives do have full paradigms, the default pattern in this
class is: the falling accent if it is hosted by a short syllable or a rising span if it is headed
by a long syllable. In this sense, the pattern encountered in polysyllabic derivations
can be seen as an extension of this default pattern.
Both stress-to-weight effects and the influence of syllabification on the prosody
are underexplored for S-C. Given the restricted focus of this chapter, we leave it to
future research to provide a complete picture. For present purposes, it is important
to clearly delineate the locus of variation in de-adjectivals, where phonology favours
different output forms based on semantic/syntactic structure. As we have already seen,
in the case at hand variation is by and large restricted to the many nouns derived from
toneless adjectives (which means that they surface with an initial falling accent) whose
stem ends in a consonant cluster preceded by a long vowel e.g. Ispraavn(ii) ‘correct’.
In these cases the options supplied by the phonology are the following:
() the pattern which copies the post-lexical surface prosody of the base adjective:
Ispraavn(ii) + -ost — Ispraavnoost
() the emergent ‘unmarked’ stress pattern with a rising span on the right edge:
Ispraavn(ii) + -ost — isprAAvnOost.
This is exactly the locus of prosodic differentiation between SDN and LDN de-
adjectivals: the pattern copying of the base adjective prosody prevails in SDNs,
whereas the default pattern with a rising span arises in LDNs.
At this point, having defined the locus of variation, we can understand better
another important handshake between syntax/sematics and the phonological form:
the three categories which are not able to derive LDN due to their syntactic and
interpretive properties (as shown in ()) also have phonological structures which
cannot derive a prosodically distinct LDN: participles (both active and passive) and
adjectives in -(lj)iv ‘-able’ never create the right environment for systematic variation
between the two classes of de-adjectivals. This is because participles never end in a
combination of a long vowel and a consonant cluster (so -ost can never be preceded
by a heavy closed syllable) and (lj)iv has its own lexically specified H which leads to
-ljiv always being part of a rising span (e.g. vId-e-ti ‘to see’, vIdljIv ‘visible’).
The same default is true of borrowed (Latinate) nouns in -a. Generally, only closed long syllables
‘arrest’ the High: nOOrma, sAAlva, fAArma, but mOOdA, lAAmA, fAAmA (see Simonović, in preparation).
The default short accent is falling: sEpsa, mOka, pAsta.
Arsenijević and Simonović
In the following section, we present the formal model in which we show how the
interface (syntactic/semantic) constraints interact with the prosodic ones, leading to
an account of the fact that SDN de-adjectivals copy certain surface properties of the
base adjective, unlike their LDN counterparts.
As the tableaux in () show, the Max(stress) constraint is never violated because
there is no lexical stress to be unfaithful to. The constraint LC(stress/tone)paradigm
only plays a role in the evaluation of the candidates for correctnessSDN , whereas in
the case of correctnessLDN , whose meaning has to be retrieved from the lexicon, it is
always vacuously satisfied.
In order to show that our ranking predicts the lack of variation in nouns whose
base has a lexical stress/tone (e.g. konkrEtnoost) and in those whose base has no long
closed final syllable (e.g. hUmaanoost), in () and () we give the tableaux for these
nouns.
Arsenijević and Simonović
() a. /humaan + oost/ ∼ humannessSDN MAX(S /T) LC(S /T)PARADIGM PROSODY LC(S/T)
BASE:
hUmaan
a. humAAnOOst ∗! ∗ ∗
F b. hUmaanoost
As expected, the general constraint LC(s/t) never chooses the winning candidate
in our tableaux. It may well be the case that this is not accidental, i.e. that surface
properties (such as syllabification and surface prosody) cannot be copied outside
paradigms. If this is the case, it can be explicitly encoded into our basic model. LDNs
(and comparable non-transparent derivations) can be defined as those derivations
which do not have the surface form of the base as part of their input. This automatically
makes the general constraint LC(stress/tone) vacuous and superfluous. Also, the
remaining LC constraint would not have to be indexed to a subset of nominalizations;
it would just be vacuously satisfied in all the cases where it has nothing to compare to
(i.e. in all LDNs). Our dataset is not sufficient to confirm such a generalization, but our
analysis clearly puts this hypothesis on the research agenda and shows how different
outcomes of this research are to be formalized. The important conceptual point here
(as one of our reviewers suggests) is that, with or without this final intervention, we do
not deny that LDNs are related and even synchronically derived from the adjectival
base. However, (at least in S-C) they are crucially unable to copy the surface prosody
of the base. These are all questions which require further research.
Note that our constraint set as it is now also makes clear predictions about the
possible constellations in languages: we exclude the option where the non-paradigm
members copy more properties of the base than the paradigm members. Even in a
language in which LCparadigm is ranked below the general LC, the general constraint
will block allomorphy in both paradigm members and non-members. In this sense,
LCparadigm can never really be ranked below LC, it can either be subsumed under it
or promoted above it. Crucially, since there is no constraint which militates against
Stress Assignment in Serbo-Croatian
(because the paradigm becomes unstable, or for some other reason), its meaning will
tend to become less transparent.
A system that marks whether a complex lexical item is a member of a paradigm
or not yields a higher productive capacity. Members of a paradigm which become
lexicalized, with an idiosyncratic meaning, no longer trigger a blocking effect on the
productive formation of their counterpart paradigm members: the two layers have
independent lives.
Answer : The reason lies in the relation of (a)symmetry. It has been argued that
grammar avoids symmetry (Kayne , Moro ). Asymmetric relations are
more easily linearized, and more easily assigned roles in the interpretive relation
of predication. In the case of S-C de-adjectival nominalizations, structures com-
ing from a paradigm (i.e. SDNs) are characterized by a rich syntactic structure, in
which the stem and the suffix stand in an asymmetric relation. The stem is more
deeply embedded than the suffix, and according to the traditional models of Spell-
out should be spelled out to phonology first (Uriagereka , Chomsky ; also
Marvin in relation to a similar empirical pattern). In such a configuration,
phonology receives the input in an asymmetric relation, and preserves the prosody
of the element that it receives first (as if the first element were spelled out, as it
were, on its own, i.e. when the base adjective is pronounced), which is the stem
(see the schematic representation in ()). The structure of an idiosyncratic nomi-
nalization (LDN) is flat: it involves two items in a symmetric relation. In such a case,
phonology has no handle to resolve the symmetry. It proceeds without prosodic
assignment, and assigns tone and stress only at its own interface with phonetics, as a
last-resort strategy, insensitive to any information which is not contained in the lexical
representation.
The two answers above are not mutually exclusive. They may be taken as two
perspectives on the same phenomenon, or even as two forces conspiring to give it
its shape. In any case, the analysis we provide opens many interesting new questions
about the interaction between syntax and semantics on the one hand and phonology
on the other. For instance, while phonology may only stipulate the fact that certain
suffixes come with a lexically specified high tone and some not, our model gives us
a handle to explain why this is the case. Suffixes that most often or always appear in
the shallow type of syntactic structure are most often also the first syntactic head in
the word spelled out to phonology. Hence, if we take it that suffixes by default have no
tone specified in the lexicon, suffixes of the described type will most often still surface
with a tone—one that is phonologically assigned. Suffixes that appear in more complex
It is possible that some asymmetry comes from the projecting nature of the nominalizing suffix, and
that this is why the final domain of the noun is targeted by the prosodic assignment. Arsenijević ()
argues that the stress is indeed assigned to the suffix, and then as a consequence of a general rule in S-C
moves to the penult syllable of the entire word.
Stress Assignment in Serbo-Croatian
structures often enough, where they are not the first head in the word to be spelled
out, will also surface without a high tone often enough. It is expected, then, that the
former type of suffixes will eventually be stored in the lexicon with a high tone, and
those of the latter type will remain toneless. Being lexically encoded with a high tone
also marks for a particular suffix that it has a higher capacity to take the derived word
out of its stem’s paradigm, and to form a new paradigm from the derived word.
are the reasons for the dichotomy in S-C, and are there any comparable phenomena
in other languages? The two features of S-C which have conspired to produce the
dichotomy are the availability of a suffix which does not affect the prosody of the base
(unavailable in say French or Italian) and the ungrammaticality of the other common
means of expressing the trope meaning: ‘X’s being Y’:
() ∗ Jovanovo budenje opasan / ∗ Jovanovo bivanje
Jovan’s being.perf dangerous.nom *Jovan’s being.imperf
opasnim
dangerous.inst
‘Jovan’s being dangerous’
Before we move on to other languages we need to remind the reader that the
dichotomy is not omnipresent in S-C either. There seems to be a pressure to have
a single nominalization from every adjective. And indeed, in many cases, even S-C
speakers report allowing a single form from a single adjective for all functions even
where there is room for variation. This pressure is even stronger in Dutch, which
allows the conversion of infinitives, so that what is expressed in S-C as Jovanova
Opaasnoost ‘Jovan’s dangerous-N’ can be expressed in Dutch as Jovans gevaarlijk-
heid ‘Jovan’s dangerous-N’, but also as Jovans gevaarlijk zijn ‘Jovan’s dangerous
be(N)’.
Despite the existence of the converted copula, there seem to be tendencies which
point at a distribution similar to that in S-C.
There is a stress-shifting micro-class of nominalizations which matches the S-C
pattern: two adjectives "dakloos ‘homeless’ and "werkloos ‘unemployed’ allow a stress
shift in heid nominalization (-heid being comparable to -ost—see below). This stress
shift tends to strongly correlate with LDN contexts.
() a. Daar komt hij weer met zijn "dakloosheid/??dak"loosheid/ "werkloos-
heid/??werk"loosheid.
‘Here he goes again with his homelessnessSDN / unemployednessSDN .’
(Implication: He is homeless/unemployed.)
b. Daar komt hij weer met zijn ??"dakloosheid/dak"loosheid/ ??"werkloos-
heid/werk"loosheid.
‘Here he goes again with his homelessnessLDN / unemployednessLDN .’
(Implication: Homelessness/unemployment, as a general issue, is his
favourite subject.)
Furthermore, Dutch also has Latinate nominalizations, which are much more
widespread than those in S-C. Booij (: ) notes that the suffixes -heid (native)
and -iteit (Latinate) are synonymous, but show an interesting asymmetry in distri-
bution: whereas -iteit only combines with non-native bases, -heid can attach to both.
Arsenijević and Simonović
His examples are ab"surdheid and absurdi"teit (the base being ab"surd) for non-native
bases and ge"woonheid and ∗ gewoni"teit (from ge"woon ‘ordinary’) for native bases.
Two remarks are in order here. First, just like in S-C, the productive native suffix is
the one which leaves the stress pattern intact, whereas the borrowed one is stress-
attracting. Second, ab"surdheid, although dispreferred by most speakers, will surface
in contexts in which S-C has SDNs.
() de duidelijke absurdheid / ?absurditeit van die regel
the clear absurdness ?absurdity of that rule
Also, for many adjectives for which heid-nominalization is held impossible and absent
from dictionaries, it actually surfaces in SDN contexts, in which the generally accepted
nominalization is blocked.
() a. De seksueelheid / ∗ seksualiteit van hun relatie staat buiten kijf.
the sexual-heid *sexual-iteit of their relationship is beyond dispute
‘The sexualness/sexuality of their relationship is beyond dispute.’
b. Hij moet per se zijn speciaalheid / ∗ specialiteit bewijzen.
he must at any price his special-heid *special-iteit prove
‘He has to prove his specialness at any price.’
In this section we have made an attempt to sketch the broader picture and initiate
some discussion on the general conditions on the prosody–syntax interactions of the
type discussed in this chapter.
. Conclusion
This chapter has examined the role that syntax and semantics play in the domain of
phonology, more precisely in prosody assignment in derived words. We discussed
an empirical domain, that of de-adjectival nominalizations, where a correlation can
be observed between the prosodic pattern of the derived noun and the types of
interpretation it may be assigned. The correlation is very strong in the majority of
cases, but it also faces certain restrictions, yielding considerable paradigm gaps: cases
where only one prosodic pattern is empirically confirmed, and the nominalization
expresses all the available types of meaning. Using a syntactic analysis that explains
the semantic effects, we proposed a model of the phonology of S-C and its interface
with syntax, in which both the phonology–semantics correlations and the gaps receive
a formal analysis and explanation. The central role in accounting for the correlation
effects is played by the tendency of Lexical Conservatism, in interaction with some
relevant syntactic and phonological properties, such as the structural complexity of
SDNs or syllable weight. In the last section we have made an attempt to show the larger
Stress Assignment in Serbo-Croatian
picture in which other factors, such as the availability of different shapes of affixes in
the lexicon and language contact, are situated.
It is our hope that we have opened many exciting windows and closed as few doors
as possible, and that future research will interact with this contribution in ways that
will enable further insights into the prosody–syntax interaction.
. Goals
The goal of this chapter is to explore what special meaning is and how it arises
in word formation. On the basis of adjectival participles in Greek, we investigate
a distinction between idioms and the concept of ‘contextual allosemy’ introduced
in recent work by Marantz (, ). Marantz argues that contextual allosemy
is the semantic analogue of contextual allomorphy and amounts to local polysemy
resolution within a specific context. The chapter investigates adjectival participles
from this perspective; as is well known, adjectival participles have been claimed in the
literature to give rise to special and/or non-compositional meanings (semantic drifts,
idioms), in contrast to verbal passive participles (Wasow and much subsequent
literature). Traditionally, this observation has been linked to the lexical vs. syntactic
nature of the two types of participles. In recent literature on English, however, the
lexical nature of adjectival participles has been argued to be an oversimplification
because there is a class of adjectival participles that behave syntactically like verbal
∗ Different versions of this chapter have been presented at the nd GLOW Colloquium, University of
Nantes, – April ; the Roots Workshop, University of Stuttgart, June ; the Workshop on Lin-
guistic Interfaces (OnLI II), University of Ulster, – December ; and Stuttgart University, June .
We would like to thank the audiences, especially Artemis Alexiadou, Winfried Lechner, Asaf Bachrach,
Orin Percus, Peter Svenonius, Gertjan Postma, Danny Fox, Alec Marantz, David Embick, Andrew Koontz
Garboden, Lisa Travis, Christina Sevdali, Raffi Folli, Heidi Harley, Antje Roßdeutscher, Florian Schäfer, and
Giorgos Spathas. An extensive discussion of this material which does not take into account the distinction
between allosemy and idiomaticity is presented in Anagnostopoulou and Samioti (forthcoming). The dis-
cussion of allosemy and idiomaticity is new and relies heavily on recent work by Alec Marantz (, ).
We are grateful to Alec Marantz for making his paper available to us, and to Roberta d’Alessandro, who
gave us the opportunity to present this material at a mini-course held at Leiden University (– September
). We thank Roberta, the students, and participants for their input, and one anonymous reviewer for
comments.
Allosemy, Idioms, and their Domains
(a) Purely stative participles which lack the implication of a prior event (in Greek,
these are -tos participles); and
(b) resultative adjectival participles which denote a state resulting from a prior
event (in Greek, these are -menos participles).
The semantic and syntactic differences between the two forms have been treated as
resulting from the different height of attachment of participle affixes in Anagnos-
topoulou (a), Alexiadou and Anagnostopoulou (), and Anagnostopoulou
and Samioti (forthcoming). According to this proposal, the participle affix -tos
attaches directly to the root in stative participles (this is a case of what Marantz
calls ‘inner affixation’), while in resultative participles the affix -menos attaches above
a verbalizing head (this is a case of ‘outer affixation’). On the basis of a study of the
two types of participle, we will discuss the locality conditions on idiomaticity and
allosemy in participles displaying inner and outer affixation, and whether and how
these locality conditions can be derived from appealing to the notion of a Spell-out
domain at PF and LF (the phase). Drawing on the results of Anagnostopoulou and
Samioti (forthcoming), as these have been interpreted by Marantz (, ), we
will provide evidence in favour of the following points:
(a) Idiom formation and contextual allosemy should be kept distinct, as they show
different interpretive properties and are subject to different locality restrictions.
(b) Both -tos and -menos forms can yield idioms that are not necessarily related to
idioms formed by the corresponding verbs. The boundary for idiomatic inter-
pretations for participles is Voice, just as has been observed for phrasal idioms.
Crucially, stative and resultative participles may give rise to idiomatic readings,
as long as external argument/agentivity features are absent (in accordance with
Marantz ; see Harley and Stone, Chapter below, for discussion of phrasal
idioms subject to the same condition and a reanalysis of potential counterex-
amples to this generalization).
(c) Greek stative -tos participles very often show special meanings, not in the
sense that they are non-compositional but in the sense that they do not have
Anagnostopoulou and Samioti
. Background
As is well known, there are two types of word formation: one forming words show-
ing irregularities, such as paradigmatic gaps, non-predictable meaning, irregular
forms, and one for morphologically productive, semantically transparent and mor-
phophonologically predictable forms. In many theories, this difference has been
linked to the hypothesis that there are two places for word formation: lexicon vs.
syntax (e.g. Wasow , Dubinsky and Simango , Horvath and Siloni ),
derivation vs. inflection (e.g. Anderson , Perlmutter , Spencer ), level I
vs. level II (e.g. Siegel , Kiparsky , Mohanan ).
Adjectival/stative vs. verbal/eventive passive participles in languages like English
have been widely assumed in the literature to present a paradigmatic case exempli-
fying the double nature of word formation. For example, stative/adjectival participles
may show special morphology, while eventive/passive participles always show regular
morphology:
() a. the shaven man
b. The man was shaved by John.
Moreover, stative participle formation is associated with idiosyncrasy in meaning,
unlike verbal participle formation:
() a. the hung jury (Someone hung the jury.)
b. ∗ The jury was being hung.
In English and other languages (though not universally; see Dubinsky and Simango
on Chichewa), the stative vs. eventive participle distinction correlates with a
split between derivation and inflection (Wasow , Marantz , , Horvath
and Siloni ). Stative participles are adjectives and passive participles are verbs, as
shown by ‘very’ vs. ‘very much’ modification in () and (). In English, ‘very’ modifies
exclusively adjectives and ‘very much’ verbs, as indicated by the contrasts between
Allosemy, Idioms, and their Domains
(b) vs. (c) and (b) vs. (c), respectively. The fact that the stative participle respected
is modified by ‘very’ in (a) presents evidence that it qualifies as an adjective. On the
other hand, passive respected in (a) is modified by very much, qualifying as a verb.
() a. Your family was very respected. (Adjectival)
b. John is very fond of your family.
c. ∗ John is very much fond of your family.
() a. Your family was very much respected by the neighbours. (Verbal)
b. John very much respects your family.
c. ∗ John very respects your family.
Wasow () argued that the properties distinguishing adjectival from verbal par-
ticiples may receive a principled explanation if the two participle types are formed in
two different components of the grammar (an approach widely adopted since then;
see Horvath and Siloni for a recent analysis along these lines). On this view,
adjectival passives are formed in the lexicon, and they show idiosyncratic forms and
meanings due to the fact that words in the lexicon have special listed properties.
On the other hand, verbal passives are formed in syntax, the locus of regularity,
productivity and compositionality, which in turn explains their transparency in form
and meaning.
Marantz (, ) and Arad (, ) argue that the difference between
‘regular’ and ‘irregular’ affixation can be derived in a syntactic approach to word
formation by appealing to the point in the derivation at which an affix is merged
with its complement. They propose that there are two domains for word formation
delimited by a category-defining head, as shown in (). Attachment of x directly to
the root, as in (a), leads to irregular word formation, while attachment above the
category-defining heads (little v, a, n), as in (b), leads to regular word formation:
() a. x b. x
Root x x n, v, a
Root n, v, a
On this view, there is a split between ‘inner’ and ‘outer’ morphology:
‘Inner morphology’ attaches to roots or complex constituents below the first little x (x =
{v, n, a}) node head (phase head) above the root. All morphology above the first x node is ‘outer
morphology’ including all ‘category changing’ derivational morphology. (Marantz : )
But cf. Strong Lexicalist approaches such as Levin and Rappaport (), who argue that all participles
are formed in the lexicon, adjectival participles are formed by verbal ones via a category changing rule, and
the properties distinguishing adjectival from verbal participles derive from their difference in category. See
Dubinsky and Simango () for evidence against this view and Marantz () for discussion of Wasow’s
analysis, as compared to Levin and Rappaport’s.
Anagnostopoulou and Samioti
The main properties associated with inner vs. outer affixation are summarized in ().
() Inner affixation Outer affixation
Regularity Potential special form and Predictable form and pre-
special meaning dictable meaning
Selection Attaches inside morphology Attaches outside morphology
determining lexical category determining lexical category
The special role of category-defining heads is linked to the hypothesis that they are
‘phase heads’ (Chomsky , ) which delimit cyclic domains leading to the
semantic interpretation and phonological Spell-out of the chunk of syntactic struc-
ture they merge with, i.e. the root or a more complex constituent formed by inner
affixation. Once a chunk of structure is shipped off to PF and LF for pronuncia-
tion/interpretation, its phonological Spell-out and semantic interpretation cannot be
altered. As a result, further affixation cannot access the properties of the Root. The
empirical generalization this hypothesis is based on will be called here ‘the idiosyn-
crasy generalization’ in () and is linked to the phase-based hypothesis summarized
in ():
() The idiosyncrasy generalization
When affixes attach directly to the root, idiosyncratic meanings may arise.
When affixes attach outside category-defining heads, the result is a meaning
predictable from the meaning of the stem.
() The phase-based hypothesis
Roots are assigned an interpretation in the context of the first category-
assigning head/phase head merged with them, which is then fixed throughout
the derivation.
Arad (, ) presents extensive evidence from Hebrew denominal verbs sup-
porting () and the inner vs. outer architecture.
Marantz () argues that inner vs. outer affixation can correctly derive the dif-
ferences between adjectival passives, which are taken to involve inner affixation, and
verbal passives, which are taken to involve outer affixation. According to Marantz
(: ):
Merger with root implies properties sensitive to properties of the root:
• Negotiated (idiosyncratic) meaning of root in context of morpheme.
• Semi-productivity (better with some roots than others).
• Meaning of construction must depend on root semantics independent of argu-
ment structure.
• Corollary of the above: cannot involve the ‘external argument’ of the verb.
Allosemy, Idioms, and their Domains
and verbal participles, even though both can be claimed to be formed by outer affixa-
tion. We will postpone a more detailed discussion of – for later on (section .),
after having investigated the interpretive properties of adjectival participles in Greek
from the perspective of Marantz’s (, ) theory of interpretive domains in
word formation.
. Greek -menos and -tos Adjectival Participles: Outer and Inner
Architecture
Next to adjectives, Greek has two adjectival constructions: the participle in -menos
and what traditional grammars call the ‘verbal adjective’ in -tos.
() anig-men-os anix-t-os ‘opened’ / ‘open’
open-men-m.sg.nom open-t-m.sg.nom
They have a similar function to adjectives, i.e. they appear in attributive and predica-
tive positions:
() a. to anix-t-o parathiro
the.neut.sg.nom open-t-neut.sg.nom window
‘the open window’
b. to anig-men-o parathiro
the.neut.sg.nom open-men-neut.sg.nom window
‘the opened window’
() a. To parathiro ine anix-t-o.
the window is open-t-neut.sg.nom
‘The window is open.’
b. To parathiro ine anig-men-o.
the window is open-men-neut.sg.nom
‘The window is opened.’
-menos and -tos participles show a number of semantic and syntactic differences
discussed in Markantonatou et al. (), Georgala (), Kordoni (), Anag-
nostopoulou (a), Alexiadou and Anagnostopoulou (), among others. The
most fundamental one is that -menos participles denote a state resulting from a prior
event, while -tos forms lack event implications. They denote what has been called ‘a
characteristic state’ by Markantonatou et al. (). Consider the examples in ():
() a. I patates ine tiganis-men-es.
the potatoes are fry-men-f.pl.nom
‘The potatoes are fried.’
Passives are verbal in Greek and therefore there is never an ambiguity between verbal and adjectival
hold forever after the event that brings them about. Target state participles in () are
compatible with the adverbial akoma ‘still’, while resultant state participles in () are
incompatible with it:
() Ta pedhia ine akoma krimena.
the children are still hidden
-tos participles lack event implications (they are licensed after verbs of creation in
(), they do not permit result-oriented modification) and agentivity (no agent-
oriented modification, no by-phrases or instruments). Alexiadou and Anagnos-
topoulou () take this to mean that they involve root attachment:
() Asp (root attachment of Asp)
√
ANIG Asp
open
-t-
-menos target state participles which include the implication of an event (they are not
licensed after verbs of creation in (), they license result-oriented modifiers) but lack
agentivity (no agent-oriented modification, no by-phrases or instruments) involve v
attachment (v is taken by Alexiadou and Anagnostopoulou to be the eventivizing
head):
() Asp (v attachment of Asp)
√ men
v ANIG
open
Finally, -menos resultant state participles which include both implication of an event
and agentivity (agent-oriented modification, licensing of by-phrases and instruments)
involve Voice attachment (Voice is taken to introduce the external argument):
() Asp (Voice attachment of Asp)
Voice men
v Voice
√
ANIG v
open
Important for present purposes is the proposal that -tos participles instantiate ‘inner-
cycle’ attachment while -menos participles instantiate ‘outer-cycle’ attachment:
() Root cycle Outer-cycle attachment
-tos root
-menos
functional … root …
head
Anagnostopoulou and Samioti
This leads us to expect that -tos forms will show properties of inner affixation and -
menos forms of outer affixation. Prima facie evidence in favour of the inner vs. outer
division in () comes from the observation that there is a striking difference in the
productivity of -menos as opposed to -tos participles. While all verbs of the appropriate
semantic type, i.e. all telic, many atelic, and even some (coerced?) statives, can form
-menos participles, there are many gaps in the formation of -tos participles. Some
examples illustrating this are listed in ():
() a. vizag-menos ∗ vizax-tos ‘nursed’
b. rimag-menos ∗ rimax-tos ‘ruined’
c. doule-menos ∗ doulef-tos ‘worked out’
d. louz-menos ∗ lous-tos ‘shampoo bathed’
e. pirag-menos ∗ pirax-tos ‘hurt, tampered’
Note that out of , verbs listed in the online Lexicon of Anastasiadi-Simeonidi
ing), -tos participles display outer-cycle attachment when they denote ability/possibility, in which case they
have a meaning comparable to -able adjectives in English. An example is given in (i):
(i) a. Afti i dikaiologia ine pistef-t-i.
this the excuse is believe-t-f.sg.nom
‘This excuse can be believed/is believable.’
b. Afto to asteri ine ora-t-o.
this the star is see-t-neut.sg.nom
‘This star can be seen/is visible.’
We will come back to these later on (section .), when we discuss the question of idiomaticity and the
role of Voice.
Another case where -tos attaches above little v and hence should be analysed as an instance of outer
affixation is with negated perfect of result participles (corresponding to English participles with un- pre-
fixation). These will not be discussed at all here. The reader is referred to Anagnostopoulou and Samioti
(forthcoming) for detailed discussion of -tos participles showing outer affixation.
Allosemy, Idioms, and their Domains
*‘whitened’ *‘cleaned’
b. ∗ pag-o-tos ∗ ler-o-tos
*‘frozen’ ‘dirtied’
c. ∗ diaplat-i-tos ∗ arost-i-tos
*‘widened’ *‘sickened’
d. ∗ sten-ef-tos ∗ berd-ef-tos
*‘tightened’ *‘confused’
For some of these examples (the ones based on adjectival roots), there is an alternative well-formed
formation based on the root + the adjectival ending: ∗ kathar-is-tos ‘cleaned’ vs. kathar-os ‘clean’, ∗ aspr-is-
tos ‘whitened’ vs. aspr-os ‘white’, ∗ sten-ef-tos ‘tightened’ vs. sten-os ‘tight’. Alexiadou and Anagnostopoulou
() analyse this as an instance of blocking. See below for discussion.
Anagnostopoulou and Samioti
e. ∗ diav-as-tos ∗ mir-as-tos
Despite the presence of verbalizers, the -tos participles in () do not have event
implications (they denote characteristic states), and they do not license manner mod-
ification, agent PPs, or instruments:
() a. ∗ To fagito ine kala / prosektika magir-ef-t-o.
the food is well carefully cooked
b. ∗ To fagito ine magir-ef-t-o apo tin Maria.
the food is cooked by the Mary
c. ∗ Ta fita ine fit-ef-t-a me diaforetika ergalia.
the plants are planted with different instruments
The participles of the type illustrated in () show that the abstract little v heads
described in the decomposition literature, i.e. the semi-functional heads introducing
eventive interpretations (and licensing result-oriented manner modification), must
be dissociated from morphological verbalizers. This leads to the question of how to
An anonymous reviewer suggests that the data in () are not sufficient to justify the separation of vC
and vE. According to the reviewer, one could account for these facts by making a parallel with subject demo-
tion accounts of passives and put -tos in the agent position. The reviewer furthermore points out: ‘Splitting a
category in two is costly and shouldn’t be done so easily.’ We are fully aware of the theoretical complications
entailed by the separation of vC and vE we are arguing for here (as well as in Anagnostopoulou and
Samioti, forthcoming), and we do not feel that we have done this ‘so easily’. Concerning the data in (),
-tos participles with vC do not permit any kind of modification, not just agent-oriented modification.
For example, they do not permit the result-oriented modifier kala ‘well’ in (a) which has been argued
for by Anagnostopoulou (a) and Alexiadou and Anagnostopoulou () to be introduced at the v
level and not at the Voice level (see Anagnostopoulou a, Alexiadou and Anagnostopoulou , and
Anagnostopoulou and Samioti, forthcoming, for more details). Moreover, the -tos participles with a vC do
not have event implications, as evidenced by tests like the Embick-based test presented in (), and they
denote characteristic states, just like their counterparts without verbalizers. We believe that Greek readers
would never disagree that the -tos participles with vC lack event implications; it is a very strong intuition.
Non-Greek readers can perhaps get a sense of what the interpretation of such participles is via the English
participles in the first column of () and () discussed in section ..
Allosemy, Idioms, and their Domains
reply to this concern is that roots are not categorized, but rather they are classified according to the
basic ontological types ‘individual’, ‘state’, ‘event’. This assumption is not only necessary for the narrow
goal of understanding the distribution of vC in -tos participles (see also Anagnostopoulou and Samioti
forthcoming) but, more broadly, in order to explain why e.g. the interpretation of the noun ‘dog’ (in the
dog) feels more ‘literal and natural’ than the interpretation of the verb ‘dog’ (in to dog). See Marantz ()
for a characterization of this type of polysemy as a process of type-shifting allosemy. See Levinson (,
) for extensive argumentation based on this type of polysemy that the ontology of roots must allow for
at least predicates of individuals, predicates of states, and predicates of events.
See Alexiadou () for discussion of such formations.
Anagnostopoulou and Samioti
This shows that there is a formal requirement for -tos to attach to a verbal element,
even when this verbal element is not, at the end, licensed as a description of an
event.
Generalization II: As shown in (), it is often the case that -tos does not combine with
Rootstate + verbalizer because there is an adjective available blocking the -tos form (as
pointed out by Alexiadou and Anagnostopoulou ).
() a. aspr-iz-o ‘whiten’ aspr-iz-men-os aspr-os/i/o ‘white’ ∗ is-tos
b. mavr-iz-o ‘blacken’ mavr-iz-men-os mavr-os/i/o ‘black’ ∗ is-tos
c. kitrin-iz-o ‘yellow’ kitrin-iz-men-os kitrin-os/i/o ‘yellow’ ∗ is-tos
d. prasin-iz-o ‘green’ prasin-iz-men-os prasin-os/i/o ‘green’ ∗ is-tos
e. kathar-iz-o ‘clean’ kathar-iz-men-os kathar-os/i/o ‘clean’ ∗ is-tos
f. megal-on-o ‘grow’ megal-o-men-os megalos ‘big’ ∗ o-tos
An anonymous reviewer asks: ‘What does it mean to be of a verbal category, but not to involve a
description of an event? And why would such a description not be licensed?’ These questions are exactly the
questions one can raise once a dissociation between vC and vE is introduced. Since vC is semantically empty,
then a form containing vC can, in principle, be verbal without involving a description of an event. Note that
the crosslinguistic distribution of stative expressions shows that it is not always the case that there is one-
to-one correspondence between the category of an expression and its ontological type. In many languages,
stative predicates e.g. expressing possession or psychological states are categorized as verbs, while in other
languages they are categorized as adjectives or nouns.
Allosemy, Idioms, and their Domains
roots can directly combine with verbal inflection to yield verbs, as shown in the first
column of ().
() a. ftiax-n-o ‘make’ ftiax-tos ‘made’
b. lin-o ‘loosen’ li-tos ‘loose’
c. per-n-o ‘take’ par-tos ‘taken’
d. klev-o ‘steal’ klef-tos ‘stolen’
e. din-o ‘give’ do-tos ‘given’
f. plek-o ‘knit’ plek-tos ‘knitted’
g. klin-o ‘close’ klis-tos ‘closed’
On the basis of the three generalizations examined so far, we can conclude that -tos
must attach to elements that are ‘verbal’. When roots modify an event, as in (), they
qualify as verbal in the relevant sense and -tos combines with them directly. When
roots modify an entity or a state, however, verbalizers are required before -tos attaches
to them. Crucially, these verbalizers do not introduce an event variable, and therefore
-tos participles never have event implications (and the syntactic properties associated
with an event interpretation).
Two comments on (): (i) Sometimes verbal roots form verbs via the formative -n- plus inflection,
as in (a,c). (ii) As pointed out by Antje Roßdeutscher (p.c.), it is interesting that the roots in klin-o ‘close’
and anig-o ‘open’ are classified as verbal and not adjectival in Greek.
Anagnostopoulou and Samioti
licensing arguments, etc., i.e. vE) introduced above, the Marantz/Arad hypothesis as
a hypothesis about idioms can, in principle, be tested in two ways:
(a) Taking literally the proposal that, once a root is categorized, it is assigned a
range of meanings fixed for the rest of the derivation, what should be tested is
whether the presence of a verbalizer vC in -tos participles yields such an effect.
In other words, are there significant differences between -tos participles with a
verbalizer and -tos participles without a verbalizer with respect to idiomaticity,
in comparison to the corresponding verbs?
(b) Assuming, alternatively, that it is the presence of eventive vE which defines
a cyclic domain for interpretation (phase), it should be tested whether the
presence of an eventive little v fixes meaning in such a way that affixes attaching
above it always lead to predictable interpretations. In other words, are there
significant differences between -tos and -menos forms and the corresponding
verbs with respect to idiomaticity?
The answer to the first question is negative. The internal composition of stative -tos
participles does not correlate in any way with (non-)idiomaticity. Participles of both
types (simplex without a verbalizer or complex with a verbalizer) can have idiomatic
readings lacking from the corresponding verbs. This is illustrated in () and ()
below:
() Stative -tos participles showing direct attachment of -tos to Rootevent
Verb Participle Idiomatic interpretation
of participle only
a. sfing-o sfix-tos
tighten tight ‘careful with money’
b. ftin-o ftis-tos
spit lit. spitted ‘spitting image’
c. klin-o klis-tos
close lit. closed ‘introverted’
() Stative -tos participles showing attachment of -tos to Root + verbalizer
Verb Participle Idiomatic interpretation
of participle only
a. kol-a-o kol-i-tos ‘close friend’
glue lit. glued
b. xtip-a-o xtip-i-tos ‘striking’
bang, hit, whip lit. whipped
c. xon-ev-o xon-ef-tos ‘inside the wall’
digest no lit. meaning
Allosemy, Idioms, and their Domains
The answer to the second question is once again negative. -menos participles may have
idiosyncratic readings, just like the -tos participles in () and ():
() striv-o stri-menos geros strif-to tsigaro
twist crotchety old man lit. ‘twisted (rolled) cigarette’
Importantly, the -menos participle in () only has the idiomatic (non-literal) reading
when modifying a [+human] noun, while the verb and the -tos participle can only
have the literal meaning. But this is the reverse of what is expected if () and () are
understood as referring to idioms and if the relevant phase head is taken to be vE (the
abstract eventivizing head). What would be expected under such an interpretation of
() and () is that the characteristic state -tos participle has the idiomatic reading and
the -menos participle the compositional meaning. It is furthermore expected that the
idiomatic reading of the -menos participle depends on the idiomatic interpretation of
the corresponding verb, i.e. exactly the opposite of what we see in (). And, in fact,
there is robust evidence that there is no necessary correlation between the meaning of
verbs and the meaning of the corresponding -menos participles. One can distinguish
between the following three cases:
(i) Idiomatic verb Non-idiomatic participle
kathar-iz-o kathar-iz-menos
lit. ‘clean’ only lit. ‘cleaned’
idiom. ‘kill’
para- (meaning exaggeration) or when combined with clitic doubled object to skini ‘the rope’:
(i) a. O Janis to paratravikse.
the Janis it para-pulled
‘John went too far.’
Anagnostopoulou and Samioti
() Verb
a. O Janis travik-s-e tin porta.
the Janis pulled the door
‘Janis pulled the door.’
b. ∗ O Janis travik-s-e to epixirima.
the Janis pulled the argument
‘Janis pulled the argument.’
() Participle
a. ?I porta ine trav-ig-meni.
the door is pulled
‘The door is pulled.’ (Lit. interpretation)
b. To epixirima ine trav-ig-meno.
the argument is pulled
‘The argument is far-fetched.’ (Only idiom. interpretation)
(iii) Idiomatic verb: one meaning Idiomatic participle: another
xon-ev-o xon-e-menos
lit. ‘digest’ lit. ‘digested’
idiom. ‘like’ idiom. ‘understood’
() Verb literal, participle literal
a. O Janis xonep-s-e to fagito.
the Janis digested the food
‘Janis digested the food.’
b. To fagito ine xone-meno.
the food is digested
‘The food is digested.’
() Verb idiomatic, participle idiomatic
a. O Janis den xonevi ta mathimatika.
the Janis not digests the maths
‘Janis dislikes mathematics.’
b. Ta mathimatika den ine xone-mena.
the mathematics not are digested
‘Maths is not understood.’
To conclude, in this section we have argued that the hypothesis () based on the
generalization () is not a hypothesis about idioms, regardless of how exactly we
interpret hypothesis (), i.e. whether we take vC or vE to be the relevant phase head.
present and, therefore, by-phrases and instruments are licit (see Lekakou for
detailed argumentation). Crucially, -tos participles denoting ability/possibility never
have idiomatic readings. All participles belonging to this class have exactly the same
meanings as the corresponding verbs, and their interpretations are compositional. We
believe that this is not a coincidence but relates to the fact that these forms contain
Voice. The obligatory presence of Voice does not permit idiomatic interpretations of
these participles.
(b) Greek has a productive process of yielding ability/possibility -tos participles from
the verbal root combined with the adjectival prefix aksio- ‘worth-’ (see Samioti ,
in progress, and Anagnostopoulou and Samioti, forthcoming, for a more detailed
discussion):
() a. aksi-agapi-tos ‘worth loving’
b. aksi-o-thavmas-tos ‘worth admiring’
c. aksi-o-meleti-tos ‘worth studying’
d. aksi-o-katafroni-tos ‘worth despising’
Semantically, such formations implicate an external argument (a generic/
impersonal argument corresponding to English ‘one’), which points to the presence
of a (middle) Voice head similar to the one found with the -able/-tos forms in ().
Interestingly, whenever the prefix aksio- combines with an idiomatic participle, the
non-compositional meaning is lost, as shown in ():
() a. trav-ig-menos aksi-o-travix-tos
lit. ‘pulled’ only lit. ‘worth pulling’
idiom. ‘far-fetched’
b. stri-menos aksi-o-strif-tos
lit. ‘twisted’ only lit. ‘worth twisting’
idiom. ‘crotchety’
This constitutes a further piece of evidence that the presence of Voice blocks idiomatic
interpretations of participles.
(c) Agentive adverbs like ‘deliberately’ and agent-oriented manner adverbs like
‘carefully’ systematically prevent idiomatic interpretations. See Alexiadou, Anagnos-
topoulou, and Schäfer () among many others for discussion of these as diagnos-
tics for the presence of an agentive Voice head:
() a. trav-ig-menos prosektika/skopima travigmenos
lit. ‘pulled’ only lit. ‘carefully/deliberately pulled’
idiom. ‘far-fetched’
b. stri-menos prosektika/skopima strimenos
lit. ‘twisted’ only lit. ‘carefully/deliberately twisted’
idiom. ‘crotchety’
Allosemy, Idioms, and their Domains
(d) Agentive and instrument PPs, which also modify an agentive Voice head present
in the structure, have the same effect of forcing compositional interpretations in ():
() stri-menos jeros idiom. ‘crotchety man’
BUT
stri-menos apo kapion/ me kati only lit. ‘twisted by someone/
with something’
The effects of Voice illustrated in (a)–(d) above support Marantz’s (, ) gen-
eralization that the syntactic head that projects an agent defines a locality domain for
idiomatic meanings of participles, as stated explicitly in prediction (b):
() boundary for domain of special meaning
agent
v
head projecting agent
(Marantz’s : ())
() Predictions: (Marantz’s : ()):
a. No idioms with fixed agents (root in agent position, context for special
meaning)
b. No eventive-passive idioms, but possible non-eventive stative idioms
c. No idioms with causative morpheme and lower agentive verb, but possible
idioms with causative and lower non-agentive verb
In Marantz (), the difference between verbal and adjectival participles with
respect to idiomaticity, i.e. (b), is linked to agentivity. But notice that both even-
tiveness and agentivity are properties attributed to the same head v in (), and one
could equally well assume that eventiveness is the relevant factor. This is the direction
taken in Marantz (, ), who links the difference between verbal and adjectival
passives to the verbal/eventive vs. adjectival/stative nature of English participles. In a
decomposition system where Voice is separated from a lower little v, this amounts to
claiming that little v is the relevant head. The Greek data discussed in this section,
however, show that Voice and not little v is the crucial head for idioms.
that we should separate allosemy from idiomaticity, and that the domain for idioms
is larger than the domain for allosemy.
In this section, we will argue that the concept of ‘allosemy’ correctly characterizes
a set of systematic meaning differences between -tos and -menos participles, which
relate to the absence in the former and the presence in the latter of the contentful
head vE.
determination of root meanings conflate “idiomatic” special meanings with polysemy. […] Clearly complex
words can acquire special meanings and uses; like phrases, complex words can be idiomatic in the sense
of conveying meanings not computable from the meanings of their parts. Marantz () is confusing if
not simply wrong in conflating the question of “idiom” with the notion of “special meaning” or “meaning
choice” associated with polysemy. For the issue of root […] polysemy, the relevant locality domain for
“fixing” meaning appears to be the phase, while for idioms, the domain is clearly larger […]. Idioms,
then, involve a type of meaning that’s built on top of polysemy resolution […]. Idiom formation seems
constrained to the domain of an external argument.’
Implicitly, Voice must also be taken to count as such a head, perhaps in the spirit of the notion of
the derivation in which either the category head or the root might be phonologically
interpreted. As a result of head movement, a verbal root ends up in the same Spell-out
domain as Voice and little v and is not spelled out in the complement domain of little v
(only the arguments of the root are). Therefore, the Voice/v complex does not interfere
with Tense serving as the context for Vocabulary Insertion (VI) at the root (and vice
versa): all three heads (root–v–Voice) are spelled out at the same time, namely in the
complement domain of the next phase head higher up, C.
(b) The second issue concerns adjacency, namely the requirement that the root
needs to be adjacent to the conditioning environment T for VI. Crucially, phono-
logically null heads do not block adjacency between the root and the conditioning
environment for stem allomorphy, while spelled out little v heads do. Compare (),
which contains an empty head, to (), with the overt v head -ize. The presence of -ize
blocks allomorphic choice at the root conditioned by Tense:
√
() QUANTUM + ize + past = quantized, ∗ quintized, ∗ quantumized, etc.
have to conclude that vC is ignored when present in a -tos participle, i.e. it does
not disrupt the semantic adjacency between -tos and the root.
The comparison between -menos and -tos participles reveals that they indeed show
systematic differences in their interpretation, relating to the presence vs. absence of
a vE head. Secondly, that vE counts for allosemy, as stated in predictions (i) and (ii)
above, while vC doesn’t (prediction (iv)). In what follows, we first discuss examples
without an overt verbalizer and then proceed to cases with an overt verbalizer.
An example without a verbalizer is ():
() a. spas-tos vs. b. spas-menos
break-tos break-menos
‘folding’ ‘broken’
(a) and (b) both appear to involve direct attachment of -tos and -menos to a
(verbal) root. (b), however, clearly contains an abstract verbalizer/eventivizer vE
between the root and -menos, while vE is absent from (a). The literal meaning
of ‘break’ is retained in the -menos participle in (b), while (a) has a distinct
interpretation: it means ‘folding’ and applies to objects consisting of parts that can
‘break into’ smaller pieces:
() spas-ti ombrella / spas-to trapezi
break-ti.f umbrella break-to.neut table
‘folding umbrella’ ‘folding table’
And a very similar meaning difference can be seen in () based on the root PLATH
(and its allomorph PLAS- ‘form/create’):
() a. plas-tos b. plas-menos
create-tos create-menos
‘false/forged’ ‘created’
In both () and () the -menos forms in (b) have the regular meanings of the
corresponding verbs ‘make’ and ‘create’. On the other hand, in (a) and (a)
the root has the interpretation ‘made up’, i.e. something ‘made’/‘created’ and there-
fore unreal/false/fake. Interestingly, only the -menos participle in (b) can have an
idiomatic reading (it means ‘stoned/drugged’ or ‘angry’), while the other three forms
cannot, once again indicating that idiomaticity is subject to conditions on top of
allosemy.
The data discussed so far verify predictions (i)–(iii) above, namely that -menos
participles have meanings based on the corresponding verbs while -tos participles do
not, and that the meanings of the roots in -menos participles are not the same as in
-tos participles due to the presence in the former and the absence in the latter of an
abstract vE head. We now turn to prediction (iv) stated above, exploring the role of
an overt vC head in a -tos participle.
As it turns out, the meaning distinctions between -menos and -tos participles are
as they have been described so far, despite the presence of an overt vC head in a -tos
participle. To illustrate, consider the following examples:
() a. kokin-is-tos vs. b. kokin-is-menos
red-v-tos red-v-menos
‘made red’ ‘made red’
In both examples, the root means ‘red’. In the context of -tos, however, ‘red’ acquires a
very specific meaning, ‘red sauce/cooked in a red way’. As a result, kokin-is-tos can
only mean ‘something cooked with a red sauce/in a red way’. On the other hand,
kokinismenos can apply to anything that has become red as a result of a ‘becoming
red event’:
() kokin-is-to kreas / kotopoulo / ∗ magoulo
red-v-to meat chicken *cheek
‘meat/chicken with a red sauce’
() kokin-is-meno derma / magulo / mati / xroma
red-v-meno skin cheek eye colour
‘skin/cheek/eye/colour that has turned red as a result of an event’
Allosemy, Idioms, and their Domains
A similar contrast is found with -tos and -menos forms based on the root GEM (‘full’)
in ():
() a. gem-is-tos vs. b. gem-is-menos
full-v-tos full-v-menos
‘stuffed’ ‘filled’
The meaning of the root is similar in (a) and (b), but gemis-tos means ‘stuffed’ and
applies to stuffed things (tomatoes, chickens, etc., a much more specific meaning)
while gemismenos applies to anything that is filled as a result of a filling event:
() a. gem-is-tes tomates b. gem-is-meno bukali
full-v-tes tomatoes full-v-meno bottle
‘stuffed tomatoes’ ‘filled bottle’
As with example () without a verbalizer, the two meanings are closely related but
sufficiently distinct to be expressed by different roots in English. The same can be seen
in ():
() a. xtip-a-o b. xtip-i-tos c. xtip-i-menos
bang/hit-sg striking/whipped hit
Note that in all the examples ()–() the question of idiomaticity does not arise,
because there is nothing unpredictable or ‘non-literal’ in the meaning of the -tos and
-menos forms. It is just that the root has a different sense in the context of -tos than
it has in the context of little vE, the head present in verbs and in the corresponding
-menos participles.
A final example illustrating the systematic meaning difference between -menos and
-tos participles with verbalizers is ():
() a. xon-ev-tos vs. b. xon-e-menos
unclear-v-tos unclear-v-menos
‘inside the wall’ ‘digested’
What is interesting about this example is that the meaning of the root XON is rather
underspecified and becomes fixed in context. In the context of -tos, the final mean-
ing is ‘inside the wall’. On the other hand, xon-e-menos means ‘digested’, just like the
meaning of the corresponding verb.
a
part root
-tos
() Greek -tos ‘verbalized’ stems
a
part
v root
-tos
In () the little v head is semantically empty and therefore ignored for allosemy. As
pointed out by Marantz, it is crucial that -tos is not a little a head but rather part of the
inflectional domain. In order to condition contextual allosemy, -tos must fall within
the same Spell-out domain of the root and not define its complement as a Spell-out
domain, i.e. it must behave like the T head in ‘taught’ and not like a C head. This was
also proposed by Alexiadou and Anagnostopoulou () for independent reasons:
recall that part is analysed as an Aspect stativizing head in ()–(). Independent
evidence that -t- is not a little a head but rather an inflectional head comes from the
fact that -t- is present in both adjectival forms and nominals. This would be difficult
to explain if -t- was a little a head. More specifically, -t- can be found in nouns that
have exactly the same structure as -tos adjectives, except that they are nouns (e.g. they
have fixed gender):
() pag-o-to
ice-v-to.neut.sg
‘ice cream’
The noun in () has the same internal composition as a -tos participle. It consists
of an entity-/quantity-denoting root PAG- (‘ice’), a verbalizer, and the -tos ending.
This time, however, the result is a noun meaning ‘ice cream’, which has fixed gender
(neuter). The same root combined with a verbalizer can give the verb ‘freeze’:
() pag-on-o
ice-v-sg.nonpast.active
‘freeze’ (used causatively and anticausatively)
Allosemy, Idioms, and their Domains
From pagono in () a -menos participle can be created while a -tos one cannot:
() a. pag-o-menos b. ∗ pag-o-tos
ice-v-menos *ice-v-tos
‘frozen’
Given the unavailability of (b), it cannot be claimed that the noun in () is created
on the basis of an adjective. Hence, -t- in () cannot be analysed as a little a head.
Some more examples of this type are given below:
() a. kopan-is-ti
wipe-v-ti.f.sg
a type of cheese
b. kalam-o-ti
reed-v-ti.f.sg
a type of roof
c. grap-to
write-to.neut.sg
exam paper
In conclusion, the Greek vC head identified by Anagnostopoulou and Samioti (forth-
coming) in Greek characteristic state -tos participles is the LF analogue of a zero
head at PF. It does not count for interpretation in two related respects: (a) it does
not introduce an event variable; (b) it is ignored when the meaning of the root is
determined in the context of the part head -tos.
. English Participles from the Perspective of Greek: vC, vE, and Voice
in English
Marantz (, ) argues that similar cases to the ones discussed in the previous
sections are also attested in English (he also discusses Japanese causatives which
present a similar pattern; Volpe ). () contains two types of participles. On the
left, participles are based on nominal roots to which an -ize verbalizer attaches. On
the right, participles are based on nominal roots which become adjectives through the
adjectival head -al; the verbalizer -ize attaches next and, finally, the participle affix -ed:
() a. quantized energy d. globalized universe
b. pulverized lime e. nationalized island
c. atomized individual f. fictionalized account
The adjectives on the left correspond to Greek -tos participles with a contentless
head vC: they may be interpreted as describing a state (‘in quanta’) that was not
necessarily brought about via an event described by the embedded verb (‘to quantize’).
Anagnostopoulou and Samioti
Pulverized lime can mean ‘lime in powder form’ (no event of crushing implied) and the
root is interpreted as ‘powder’. An atomized individual is separated from society not
necessarily as a result of a separation event. On the right, the adjectives describe states
resulting from events, and correspond to Greek -menos participles with a contentful
vE head. Marantz attributes the difference between the two groups of participles to
the adjectival suffix -al, an exponent of little a. Being a phase head, -al intervenes
between little v and the root, preventing the part head from serving as a context for
determination of the meaning of the root.
Bruening (to appear) investigates the interpretive differences between adjectival
and verbal passives and points out that the most striking difference between the two
is the case of missing inputs. There are many examples of adjectival passives in English
that do not exist either as verbal passives or as active transitive verbs. In () we list
Bruening’s examples:
() a. bedridden, destined, dilapidated, embattled, hagridden, laden, stricken,
unkempt
b. bedecked, bedraggled, bejewelled, belated, beloved, bemused, benighted,
benumbed, bereaved/bereft, beribboned, beringed, besotted
According to the Oxford English Dictionary, in some of these cases the active verb used
to exist, mostly with adjectival passives beginning with the prefix be-. There is also
a productive class of English adjectival passives formed from nouns, and especially
body-part nouns:
() a. bearded, mustachioed, one-eyed, long-haired, broad-chested, big-eared
weak-chinned, thick-skinned, club-footed, gap-toothed, pigtailed, six-
fingered, long-necked, big-boned, honey-tongued, smooth-cheeked
b. scaled body, maned head, clawed feet, fanged frog, frilled lizard, long-tailed
weasel, flop-eared bunny, duck-billed platypus
c. landed gentry, spiked collar
Bruening hypothesizes that these are derived from an intermediate non-existent verb
form derived from an N and meaning ‘possessing N’ perhaps via a null affix.
Greek presents evidence that the classes in () and () should not be treated along
exactly the same lines. The participles in () contain a zero vC and the participles
in () a zero vE. Starting from those in (), we have seen that Greek has similar
cases of -tos participles based on nouns which combine with a semantically empty but
phonologically overt vC, leading to forms that are non-existent as verbs. In Greek, the
relevant nouns are not body parts but other types of noun, which do however lead to
forms often conveying the meaning ‘possessing/having the property N’. The example
we saw was (), repeated here:
() kamban-a ‘bellN ’ ??kamban-iz-o ‘bellV ’ kamban-is-tos ‘sounding like a bell’
Allosemy, Idioms, and their Domains
The -tos participles in () are unambiguously non-eventive in Greek, and it is clear
that the overt verbalizer in them is an exponent of a semantically empty v. On the
basis of the evidence from Greek, then, it could be proposed that the ‘missing input’
cases listed by Bruening in () contain a semantically empty v (vC), which happens
to also be phonologically empty.
On the other hand, the cases in () seem to contain an empty vE, which can be
modified etc. (see e.g. http://www.thefreedictionary.com/hagridden: ‘a man hagrid-
den by the future—haunted by visions of an imminent heaven or hell upon earth’
(C. S. Lewis)). These are predicted to correspond to -menos participles in Greek, and
this is correct: e.g. ‘destined’ is prooris-menos in Greek, ‘embattled’ is mach-o-menos,
and ‘benumbed’ is moudias-menos. Note that the Greek counterparts of the English
words in () are based on existent verbs, namely moud-iaz-o (to become numb), pro-
oriz-o (to determine beforehand), mach-ome (to fight).
Turning, finally, to the question of idiomaticity in English, Bruening’s (to appear)
investigation leads him to conclude that there are no special conditions on the
idiomatic interpretations of adjectival participles that are qualitatively distinct from
the conditions on the idiomatic interpretations of phrasal idioms. Bruening calls the
former ‘semantic drifts’ and the latter ‘idioms’, and takes the position that ‘Semantic
drift and phrasal idioms are just two names for the same thing: special interpretations
of syntactic structures’ (Bruening, to appear) . He argues for a frequency-based the-
ory of idioms, according to which there is an inverse relation between frequency and
size of syntactic structure, such that special interpretations become less frequent the
larger a syntactic structure is. Therefore, there are more idioms consisting of just a
verb and its object than idioms consisting of a subject, a verb, and an object. Bruening
proposes that the reason why there are more idioms with adjectival passives than with
The noun ‘stamp’ can also be used as a basis of the verb stamb-ar-o (stamp-v-sg) in Greek which
means ‘spot’. That verb can be used as a basis for both a -tos and a -menos participle, with the usual semantic
and syntactic differences between the two.
Anagnostopoulou and Samioti
actives and verbal passives is because adjectival passives have a stative use that is not
the same as the verbal active or passive. Therefore, speakers will have a reason to
limit a special interpretation just to the adjectival passive, while, when they encounter
a special interpretation of the verbal passive, they will have no reason to assume
that this interpretation is not available to the active, which is truth-conditionally
equivalent to the passive. He argues that this is indeed what we find. Verbal passives
with idiomatic meanings usually correspond to actives with the same meaning, while
adjectival passives have special meanings different from the meanings of actives and
passives. He furthermore points out that there is at least one example of a verb forming
a verbal passive with a meaning not available to the active. The verb ‘be born’/‘be
born again’/‘be reborn’, has distinct active and passive uses, as shown in () and
() (Bruening’s (), ()). The active only has literal and scientific uses while the
passive has non-literal/metaphoric uses. Note that the progressive in () provides
evidence that this is a case of a true passive:
() a. Mammals bear live young./∗ Live young are borne by mammals.
b. A child was born to/∗ by Mary and Joseph./∗ Mary and Joseph bore a child.
c. She bore him a child./∗ He was borne a child (by her).
d. That child’s soul was reborn to the same mother/∗ That mother rebore the
soul of her first child.
() a. At this very moment, the prophesied saviour is being born to unsuspecting
parents.
b. At this very moment, the soul of the Dalai Lama is being reborn in a tiny
village.
On the basis of idiomatic reborn, he concludes that passive idioms are not excluded in
principle. They are just very rare. Bruening does not address the agentivity restriction
on idioms, and it is not clear to us what he would say about this restriction in connec-
tion to the passive. But notice that the ‘be born’ examples in () and () clearly lack
agentivity properties. This is evident from the fact that what could be characterized
as an ‘external argument’ is not introduced by the preposition by but rather by the
preposition to (in (b,d)), and has the interpretation of an affected indirect object
argument (in the active (c) this argument is realized as him). Therefore, the data
he discusses do not actually challenge the generalization/hypothesis that there is an
agentivity restriction blocking idiomatic interpretations of passive participles, just as
it blocks agent-based subject–verb idioms (Harley and Stone, Chapter below). At
this stage, the reason for the agentivity restriction is unclear to us. But notice that, if
the allosemy hypothesis is correct, then this restriction could not simply be attributed
to the status of Voice as a phase head, unless we had a theory that could answer in a
principled manner why the vE phase head defines a domain for allosemy, while the
Voice phase head defines a domain for idiomaticity.
the context-dependent meaning view of idioms has some advantages over the ‘phrasal
lexicon’ approach.
In section ., we point out the different consequences for compositionality of the
two hypotheses. In section ., we discuss whether there are structural constraints on
idiomatic meanings, and if so, what these might be. We dismiss one overly restrictive
proposal, and in section . we pursue the No Agent Idioms hypothesis, arguing
against an alternative explanation for the paucity of agent–verb idiom combinations,
and that one class of counterexamples to the hypothesis are in fact object-experiencer
constructions, lacking true Agent subjects. Other counterexamples have atypical syn-
tactic properties, which we take to indicate the possibility that they contain derived,
rather than base-generated, subjects. Section . concludes.
. Compositionality
Below, we introduce the two conceptions of the nature of idioms described above and
discuss the relationship of each to the compositionality hypothesis. The first, we argue,
treats idioms as true exceptions to compositionality and opens the door to a general
re-evaluation of basic compositionality as a fundamental tenet of the theory. The
context-dependent meaning approach, on the other hand, maintains compositionality
in its traditional form.
The compositionality hypothesis states that the meaning of a complex expression is
constructed from the meanings of its parts and the combinatoric structure imposed
on them by the syntactic computation. Discussions of compositionality frequently
feature a disclaimer about idioms: idiomatic expressions are thought of as cases in
which strict compositionality breaks down. The meaning of chew the fat ‘chat, gossip’,
for example, cannot be computed from the context-independent meanings of chew,
the, and fat. This VP has two distinct interpretations: one which is computed from
such context-independent meanings and an idiomatic one which is not.
()
Ditransitive Construction
Sem CAUSE-RECEIVE < agt rec pat >
↓
←−
←−
←−
PRED < >
↓
Syn V Subj Obj Obj
compositional: their meanings are computed from the meanings of their parts and
the way they are put together. It’s just that the meanings of their parts are potentially
dependent on the syntactic and lexical context.
This intuition about the relationship of idiomatic interpretations to individual
lexical entries is reflected in the organization of idioms in English-language dictio-
naries. The special meanings for idioms are typically listed as submeanings under
the headword for the head of the phrase, not as separate headwords themselves. For
example, the Merriam–Webster Dictionary and the Oxford English Dictionary list chew
the fat under the headword chew. On this conception of idiomatic interpretation,
compositionality holds, albeit in a rather indirect way. The verb chew is polysemous,
just like, for example, the noun mouth. The catch is that one of its senses is only
available when it appears in combination with a certain DP object, the fat, which
presumably also is polysemous and receives a special interpretation in combination
with chew. ,
We consider the fact that the context-dependent meaning approach allows us to
preserve a traditional notion of compositionality to be a significant argument in its
favour. It therefore seems important to explore further implications of this view of
idiomatic meaning within modern syntactic theory. In particular, in the next sec-
tion we turn to the question of the existence of structural constraints on idiomatic
domains.
similar to, but crucially distinct from, the concept of ‘Idiomatically Combining Expressions’ of Nunberg,
Sag, and Wasow (). Their Idiomatically Combining Expressions are restricted to cases where a clear
metaphorical analogue for each subpart of the idiom exists, as in spill the beans, where ‘spill’ corresponds to
‘tell’ and ‘the beans’ corresponds to ‘a secret’, in which it seems very reasonable to attach these interpretations
as individual subentries in the polysemous semantics for each of these subparts. In our conception here,
however, the same contextually dependent interpretations are employed in idioms where no such neat
correspondence exists between subparts of the idiom and the content it expresses, as in kick the bucket
for ‘die’ or chew the fat for ‘chat’—what Nunberg et al. term ‘Idiomatic Phrases’. The catch in the present
treatment is that in such expressions the special meaning contributed by the lexical items bucket or fat will
be effectively zero. See Stone (in preparation) for further discussion, and Horvath and Siloni (to appear) for
arguments against mutually dependent listing of information concerning a single idiomatic interpretation
in multiple entries (e.g. under both chew and fat).
See Anagnastopoulou and Samioti (Ch. above) for a relevant discussion of polysemy and idiomatic-
ity. Specifically, they discuss how locality restrictions on idiomaticity and polysemy differ.
The ‘No Agent Idioms’ Hypothesis
and only information within the phase that is being interpreted could condition the
selection of the appropriate truth-conditions needed for this representation; this is
a consequence of the Phase Impenetrability Condition of Chomsky (). We thus
predict that there should be strict structural limitations on the domain relevant for
idiomatic interpretations. In this section we review some proposals concerning the
structural constraints on idioms and identify one that appears to have the properties
predicted by phase theory.
As noted by a reviewer, alternative possibilities exist. For example, a constraint of the type, ‘Idiom
constituents cannot receive a theta-role from an idiom-external predicate’ would predict the absence of
idiomaticity in (b) as well. It is perhaps worth noting that the phase-based interpretive constraint described
above, however, is more general; it follows as a consequence of how the ‘phase’ construct is intended to
function in the theory, and is straightforwardly connected to the other roles phases play in non-idiomatic
domains.
Harley and Stone
In order to rule out the occurrence of such patently impossible idioms, Koopman and
Sportiche propose the following structural constraint on idiomatic interpretations:
() If X is the minimal constituent containing all the idiomatic material, the head of
X is part of the idiom.
This, in a sense, represents a formalization of the intuition that drives lexicographers
to often list idiomatic interpretations as subentries of a single lexical item. See Horvath
and Siloni (, to appear) for a formal treatment of idioms as stored under heads of
phrases. Further, while Koopman and Sportiche do not seek to place limits on the size
of the constituent which can bear idiomatic meaning, their constraint does reflect the
fact that local relations between idiomatic constituents are of paramount importance.
with n in spec-ies, but the interpretations of the two are only tangentially related. On
√
the Categorization Hypothesis about idiomatic meaning, spec only acquires specific
meanings as the result of such categorization, and such a meaning, once acquired in
a given structure, should carry through for the rest of the derivation.
Obviously, on this view idiomatic interpretations of phrasal constituents must be a
different phenomenon entirely, perhaps simply an extreme form of metaphorical or
figurative language use (Alec Marantz, p.c.). As such, the Marantz–Arad proposal is of
perhaps limited relevance to the issues being addressed here. However, as a concrete
structural proposal concerning the appropriate domain for idiomatic interpretation,
we feel it appropriate to address the question of whether there is a qualitative dif-
ference between the idiosyncratic meanings assigned at the first merge of an acate-
gorial root with its categorizing head, and idiosyncratic meanings that arise later. In
particular, we find it implausible to suggest that meanings acquired upon first merge
must persist in the interpretation throughout the derivation. It seems clear that truly
idiosyncratic semantics can be assigned following the first cycle of categorization, as
also argued by Borer () and Anagnostopoulou and Samioti (, Chapter
above).
Consider, for example, the cases in () below. In each group of words based on a
common root, there is at least one word derived from a derivation of that root which
bears a meaning that does not obviously arise from the meaning of the derived stem
plus the meaning contributed by the affix; this meaning is presented in boldface:
() a. edit
edit-or ‘one who edits’
edit-or-ial . ‘of or relating to the editor’
. ‘opinion article’
b. nature
natur-al ‘of nature’
natur-al-ized . ‘made natural’
. ‘became a citizen by residing in country’
√
c. sanit-
sanit-ary ‘clean’
sanit-ari-um ‘institution for mentally ill’
√
d. audit-
audit-ory ‘to do with audition’
audit-ori-um ‘large performance space’
e. class
class-ify ‘sort’
class-ifi-ed ‘sorted’
class-ifi-ed-s ‘small newspaper advertisements’
Harley and Stone
√
f. nat-
nat-ion ‘community of people possessing a territory and government’
nat-ion-al ‘of a nation’ (not an antonym of private)
nat-ion-al-ize . ‘make national’
. ‘government takeover of business’
(antonym of privatize)
g. √domin-
domin-ate ‘rule or control’
domin-at-rix ‘female top in ritualized sexual domination’
√
h. instit-
instit-ute ‘put a system into place’
instit-ut-ion . ‘a system that has been put into place’
. ‘an organization or building, especially a public
care facility’
institut-ion-al . ‘of a system that has been put in place’
. ‘grim, like a public care facility’
institut-ion-al-ize . ‘make institutional’
. ‘commit to a care facility’
i. universe
univers-ity ‘institution of higher learning’
√
j. hospit-
hospit-al ‘institution for medical care’
hospit-al-ity ‘welcomingness’
It should be clear, for example, that the root of national has merged with at least
two categorizing heads, realized by the suffixes -tion and -al. On the Marantz–Arad
hypothesis, then, the meanings associated with national should figure composition-
ally in the meaning of nationalize. However, on at least one of its uses, nationalize
has a considerably distinct range of interpretations which are not compositionally
related to the meaning of national. For example, we can speak of a ‘national company’,
intending to refer to a company with operations throughout the country. However,
to ‘nationalize’ a company is not necessarily to cause it to have operations through-
out the country, but rather to implement a government takeover of the company.
In this sense, nationalize is the antonym of privatize. If the meaning of national
figured in the meaning of nationalize, and the same held true for private and pri-
vatize, we would expect private and national to be antonyms. Other similar cases
might include the pairs conserve∼conservation, relate∼relation, deduce∼deduction,
protect∼protector∼protectorate, economic∼economical, specify∼specifier.
Furthermore, there are clear cases of roots which have no independent mean-
ing following merger with the first categorizer. The meanings of these roots are
The ‘No Agent Idioms’ Hypothesis
The First Merge Hypothesis is correct in the sense that no root will contribute a
meaning entirely independently of the syntactic context, given that all roots must
be categorized. What we wish to emphasize here, however, is that idiosyncratic
interpretations of complex constituents created after the first categorizer has merged
arise in exactly the same way and are phenomenologically indistinguishable from the
idiosyncratic interpretations assigned at the first categorizing node. The main point
is that interpretations of complex constituents even after the first categorizer can still
be idiosyncratic, and need not contain the meaning specified at the first categorizer
as a proper subpart. The more structure a given phrase contains, the less likely it is
to be idiosyncratically interpreted, simply because of the increasing number of pieces
involved. However, the data do not suggest the existence of a qualitative difference
between an idiomatic phrase and an idiomatic word—that is, until we arrive at the
domain of the external argument.
See the appendix of Horvath and Siloni (to appear) for some suggested counterexamples involving
unergative verbs with different types of subject. The examples (run, fly) that they discuss in detail are verbs
of motion, however, which have been extensively shown to alternate between unergative and unaccusative
structures (see e.g. Hoekstra and Mulder , among many others; Folli and Harley provide a recent
overview). Fly, for example, undergoes lexical causativization (The pilot flew the plane to New York), not
usually considered possible for unergative verbs (∗ The boy laughed the baby).
Harley and Stone
Horvath and Siloni (to appear) argue that Nunberg et al.’s observation about animates should be recast
as an observation concerning NPs referring to human entities, which strictly preserve animacy, hence
concreteness, and are therefore less likely to occur in idioms describing abstract situations; thus, they claim,
the paucity of Agent NPs in idioms is attributable to the cognitive bias against abstract interpretations of
human-denoting NPs.
Harley and Stone
but that should be just as unlikely as using an animate-referring NP in an abstract context, so either way,
these are predicted to be rare cases, according to Nunberg et al.’s hypothesis. Yet rare and non-existent are
still distinct.
In what follows, we omit discussion of subject–V idioms involving derived subjects, e.g. with unac-
cusative verbs, as it should be clear in the theory presented below that they are predicted to exist. See
Chtareva () and Everaert () for examples of this type.
The ‘No Agent Idioms’ Hypothesis
Nunberg et al. also describe and give the date of a Linguist List post by Alexis
Manaster-Ramer, saying he gives ‘a number of other idioms of this type (in several
languages) (Nunberg et al. : )’; we reproduce Manaster-Ramer’s post in full
here, thanks to the archival powers of the Internet:
Horvath and Siloni () give additional examples in Hebrew and Hungarian:
() a. Ha-goral he’ir lo panim.
the-fate lit up to+him face
‘He had good luck.’ (lit: ‘Fate lit up its face to/on/at him.’)
Harley and Stone
tion is recognizably distinct from its ‘literal’ or typical interpretation, in a way that depends on the semantic
category of its external argument. ‘Fear seized him’, for example, involves a special interpretation of ‘seize’
which is triggered by the fact that the external argument denotes an emotional state. In this sense, we believe
these examples to be parallel to Marantz’s.
About this idiom, Chtareva writes: ‘Kondrashka is a personal male name, but in case of this idiom
it does not refer to a person. In its archaic idiomatic usage the word used to refer to paralysis, but most
native speakers are not aware of this meaning anymore. In the th century literature, the word appears
in an idiom X xvatil Kondrashka meaning “X was paralysed”. The idiom in (a) is a modern day variant
of this archaic idiom. It is resistant to any word order variations other than OSV with the focus stress on
Kondrashka, since it immediately follows the focus marker chut’. It is a “frozen” idiom in terminology of
Nunberg et al. ().’
The ‘No Agent Idioms’ Hypothesis
are internal arguments. We will discuss each set of examples from above in inverse
order, beginning with Chtareva’s observations about Russian.
Chtareva argues that in all these cases of subject–verb idioms, the external argu-
ment is a Cause, rather than an Agent (despite the fact that all the verbs in () can
have an Agent subject in non-idiomatic uses), and that in all the cases in (), the open
object variable bears an Experiencer, rather than a Patient, role. She demonstrates
that the examples in () exhibit the syntactic behaviour associated in Russian with
psych-predicates, rather than the behaviour typically associated with agentive verbs.
We summarize her discussion below.
Chtareva shows that none of the structures in () can undergo passivization, or
be modified by an agent-oriented adverbial like on purpose, although non-idiomatic
interpretations of the same predicates can do so, as shown in examples (c,d)
below:
() a. ∗ Ivana spetsial’no chut’ KONDRASHKA ne (s)xvatil.
Ivan.acc on purpose almost Kondrashka.nom not grabbed
‘Ivan was frightened to death on purpose.’
b. ∗ Ivan byl sxvach-en Kondrashkoi.
Ivan.nom was grabbed-p.prt Kondrashka.instr
‘Ivan was frightened to death.’
c. Kondrashka spetsial’no chut’ ne (s)xvatil Ivan.
Kondrashka.nom on purpose almost not grabbed Ivan.acc
‘Kondrashka almost grabbed Ivan on purpose.’
d. Ivan byl sxvach-en Kondrashkoi.
Ivan.nom was grabbed-p.prt Kondrashka.instr
‘Ivan was grabbed by Kondrashka.’
Chtareva shows that the reciprocal binding possibilities mirror those of object-
experiencer predicates like radujut ‘gladden’, as can be seen by comparing (a) and
(a). They do not parallel the binding possibilities of normal transitive agentive
predicates like priglasili ‘invite’, illustrated in (b) and (b):
() a. Ivana i Mariju radujut uspexi drug druga.
[Ivan.acc and Mary.acc]i gladden.pl success.nom.pl [each other]i
‘Each other’s success gladden Ivan and Mary.’
Nunberg et al. (: , fn. ) note that the literature has not been clear on the point of ‘whether the
relevant thematic role [of the subject] should be determined relative to the literal meaning of the expression,
or to its idiomatic meaning’. It should be clear from the preceding discussion that we are using the latter.
As noted by a reviewer, the failure of passivization could be alternatively explained if these idioms
don’t fall into Nunberg et al.’s class of Idiomatically Combining Expressions; there are, of course, many
non-passivizable idioms. The failure of passivization, then, is not diagnostic of these idioms’ non-Agentive
status; rather, it is merely consistent with it.
According to Chtareva adverbial chut’ ne ‘almost’ generally does not appear in passive constructions.
writes: ‘The [Kondrashka] idiom … is a “frozen” idiom in that it resists scrambling and can only appear in
Acc–NOM–V order with a focus stress on the subject. This focus stress is not identificational in the sense of
É. Kiss () since it doesn’t involve picking an element out of a set, but rather emotive in the sense of King
(), who describes it as emphatic stress on a constituent in “emotive” speech. Such focused elements are
“marked with sentence stress and occur immediately before the verb, following preverbal topic”, which is
exactly the case [in this idiom].’
Chtareva argues that the accusative case on the Experiencer object is inherent rather than structural,
and the absence of a true external argument is a Burzio’s generalization effect, following Belletti and Rizzi
().
Harley and Stone
but rather acquire their subject hood via movement. Since the important condi-
tioning factor in idiomatic interpretations is the configuration of the base-generated
structure, not the derived structure, idioms involving such subjects do not count as
counterexamples to Marantz’s generalization; indeed, they are predicted to exist, since
the surface subject is base-generated as an internal argument. Within a syntactico-
centric theory of argument structure, it is not particularly surprising to see normally
agentive verbs used in such object-experiencer frames. It should be clear that when
they are used in such frames, idiomatization is predicted by Marantz’s theory to be
possible.
A similar set of potential counterexamples in Spanish were brought to our atten-
tion by Violeta Vázquez-Rojas (p.c.), and are illustrated in () below. These involve
transitive verbs with fixed nominative subjects and accusative objects. Very tellingly,
however, they all contain the reflexive clitic se, and exhibit unusual word order: the
nominative subject is mandatorily sentence-final, and the accusative object must be
in preverbal position.
() a. A Juan se lo va a cargar el payaso.
dat Juan se acc.sg go to carry the clown
‘Juan is going to be in deep trouble.’ (lit. ‘The clown is going to carry Juan
away.’)
b. A Juan se lo llevó la trampa.
dat Juan se acc.sg carried the trap
‘Juan underwent a terrible fate.’ (lit. ‘The trap took Juan away.’)
Omission of se renders the idiomatic reading unavailable, as illustrated in ():
() a. ?A Juan lo llevó la trampa.
dat Juan acc.sg carry the trap
b. A Juan lo va a cargar el payaso.
dat Juan acc.sg go to carry the clown
‘The clown is going to carry Juan away.’ (only literal meaning)
We take the reflexive morphology and the word order preference to indicate again an
internally base-generated position for the subject in the syntax for these examples as
well.
A reviewer notes that Pesetsky () establishes a distinction between two classes of object-
experiencer verbs, ones whose subject is a Cause (worry-type) and ones whose subject is a Theme (appeal-
type), and wonders which class the Experiencer interpretations of the idioms here fall into. This would
matter if either of the classes had base-generated external arguments in Pesetsky’s analysis. In fact, it does
not matter. In Pesetsky’s analysis, even the Causer subject of PsyCaus object-experiencer verbs is base-
generated internally to the VP, as the object of a caus preposition in the complement of V. It then raises
to the external (thematic) Cause position. Its internal base-generation thus explains its backward binding
properties. Pesetsky’s analysis is thus compatible with the No Agent hypothesis of idiom formation for both
classes of object-experiencer verbs.
The ‘No Agent Idioms’ Hypothesis
Turning now to the cases discussed by Horvath and Siloni from Hebrew and Hun-
garian, we have not yet pursued a systematic investigation of their properties along
the lines of the Russian cases discussed above, but an informal discussion with Edit
Doron seems to point in the same direction. None of Horvath and Siloni’s cases in ()
can be passivized, although their non-idiomatic counterparts can be (again, this may
be due to their not being Idiomatically Combining Expression idioms, rather than
to their non-agentive status: see footnote above). Further, the word order in (c)
is typical for these expressions; Doron comments that (b) is more felicitous in the
inverted order of (c), with the purported idiomatic external argument ha-ru’ax ‘the
wind’ appearing at the end of the sentence. This VOS word order is quite atypical
for Hebrew, which most frequently exhibits SVO or VSO order. Although further
investigation is required, these idioms do seem to have a syntax that is atypical for
agentive expressions in the language, which is at least consistent with the possibility
that they involve derived, rather than base-generated, subjects.
We know even less about the Hungarian examples; however, judging by their
translation, they appear to exhibit the semantic qualities of object-experiencer psych-
predicates. An investigation of their syntactic properties will have to await future
work. It is also worth recalling Manaster-Ramer’s remarks concerning word order in
his example from German and parallel cases he doesn’t give from Polish and Hindi:
Florian Schäfer (p.c.) provides the following definition of this idiom from a German
source: If ‘the devil rides someone’, this person acts ‘blindfold, imprudent or stupid[ly];
the person is obsessed (by the devil) and wanton.’ Semantically, then, this is similarly
non-agentive in character, like a causative object-experiencer psych-predicate; inter-
estingly, however, Schäfer points out that the expression does passivize:
Note that there are many different classes of verbs which have derived subjects; object-experiencer
verbs are only one such class. Our claim here is not that all these idioms have the semantics of object-
experiencer structures. Rather, it is that they do not have base-generated Agents—their subjects are derived.
For the Hebrew, Hungarian, and German examples we do not have the diagnostics yet to establish this
conclusively. Here we are merely claiming that the atypical word order patterns evident in these expressions
are suggestive that something unusual is going on syntactically—something which is consistent with,
though not diagnostic of, a derived subject status for these purported Agents. More broadly, we can ask
why all these purported counterexamples to the No Agent Idioms Hypothesis have such unusual syntactic
structures. If Agent-dependent idiomatic interpretations are in principle freely available in the language
faculty, why aren’t there more examples that have a syntax that is typical for agentive verbs?
Harley and Stone
nonetheless requires listing as an idiomatic expression, as the same meaning cannot be expressed by other
verbs with literal content similar to smile: ∗ Lady Luck grinned at him, for example. However, this is expected:
smile (on) has a ‘conferred favour’ meaning that grin, laugh, etc. do not—and it has this meaning quite
independently of cooccurrence with Lady Luck. We can say, with a similar ‘conferred favour’ meaning:
The fates smiled on him, The king smiled on him, etc. (∗ The king grinned at him does not have the meaning
‘conferred favour’ either). Consequently, the DP Lady Luck is expected to be able to occur (compositionally)
with the verbal expression smile on. No idiomaticity is necessary to explain the meaning of this expression,
as the context-independent meanings associated with each of the elements account for the meaning of the
expression. Similarly, whatever meaning Lady Luck grinned at him has, it has by virtue of the meanings of
the individual components, Lady Luck (a personification of fate, fortune, etc.) and grinned at him (which
can suggest an implication of mockery, perhaps). Again, no idiomatic listing for the whole collocation is
necessary (or, according to the hypothesis here, possible).
The ‘No Agent Idioms’ Hypothesis
. Conclusions
We conclude that Marantz’s generalization remains empirically unchallenged, and
that it is reasonable to take it as the foundation from which to draw theoretical
conclusions about the status of Agent arguments in syntax and semantics. In this
section, we consider the implications of this conclusion for theories of the syntax–
semantics interface, and predictions for various domains of investigation that seem
to us to be indicated.
Above we have suggested that the explanation for the distribution of idiomatic
domains could be the status of the phase as a Spell-out domain; interpretations can
Harley and Stone
only depend on constituents contained within a single phase (Stone ). Kratzer
() proposes a more purely semantic account. Below, we sketch Kratzer’s proposal
and draw attention to a theoretical consequence which contrasts with that of the
phase-based approach.
Kratzer’s (, ) account of Marantz’s lists of special Verb+Object interpre-
tations treats verbal idiomaticity as contextually dependent polysemy, as described
above, putting the idiomatic meaning entirely in the truth-conditions specified in the
verb’s semantics. As noted above, this move is justified on conceptual grounds if we
want to preserve compositionality and avoid construction grammar-style listing of
phrasal meanings. Idiomatic interpretation must be linked to individual lexical items.
Context-dependent meanings for individual lexical items are justified independently
on empirical grounds, for items like jinks, caboodle, and gamut (see () above), which
only occur in particular lexical and structural contexts. Phrasal meaning remains a
function of the meaning of the lexical items in the sentence and the way they are put
together.
Kratzer’s semantic proposal restricts the verbal truth-conditions from referring to
the content of the external argument by proposing that the external argument is not
directly semantically selected by the verb, but rather is introduced by a separate pred-
icate, a Voice predicate. In other words, context-dependent meanings in her approach
can only be conditioned by arguments which are directly semantically selected by the
relevant head. As Harley () notes, this has a significant consequence for the syntax
of internal arguments: if dependent idiomatic semantics can be conditioned only
by arguments of the relevant head, this entails that internal arguments must be direct
arguments of their verb roots, contra several proposals according to which internal
arguments, like external ones, are introduced by dedicated functional projections (e.g.
Ramchand , Borer , , Basilico ). This contrasts with the phase-
based domains of interpretation view, where selection of the conditioning constituent
need not be relevant at all; rather, any constituent contained within the same phase as
the idiomatically interpreted head is accessible to provide the relevant conditioning,
regardless of whether it is selected for by the head in question. The different empir-
ical predictions made by these two approaches to conditioning of special meanings
is an area ripe for further investigation. For example, it is worth asking whether
Note that Kratzer’s polysemous analysis is motivated by the original ‘light verb’ kinds of cases dis-
cussed by Marantz, where the particular identity of the object is not fixed, but the idiomatic interpretation
is conditioned by objects which are members of a particular semantic class. This approach allows for a
kind of ‘continuum’ of idiomaticity, according to which fixed idioms are subject to exactly the same kind
of interpretive process but simply more constrained in the specification of their triggering environment,
which is dependent on a particular DP, rather than on a particular semantic class of DPs. Caboodle items
are the logical extreme, where no context-independent interpretation exists. Note that it is very likely that
caboodle items are very common in the I-language of speakers, where an unfamiliar lexical item is learned
within a particular collocation and is only used by that speaker in that context, although in E-language as
a whole it might have an independent existence. See the Eggcorn Database (http://eggcorns.lascribe.net/)
for several plausible cases.
The ‘No Agent Idioms’ Hypothesis
non-s-elected adjuncts within the vP may condition special interpretations for the
verb; this would be possible on the phase-based approach, though perhaps not on
Kratzer’s.
Whether the conditioning environment for the idiomatically defined head is
constrained via semantic composition or via syntactic Spell-out, the basic context-
dependent meaning approach comports well with several other ideas about the rela-
tionship of meaning to structure from various theoretical domains. For example,
the notion that idiomatic interpretation is crucially dependent on the idiosyncratic
content of one or more heads is consistent with Koopman and Sportiche’s proposal
concerning the headedness of idioms.
Another promising connection can be found in the treatment of lexical mean-
ing in the Distributed Morphology framework. In the DM view, Root elements are
the only locus at which linguistic structure interfaces with encyclopedic knowledge.
If contextually-dependent special truth-conditions are encyclopedic in nature, they
should only be statable for Roots. Idioms, then, should have to contain Roots, and be
unable to consist purely of functional structure. The location of idiomaticity in Root
elements entails that functional material in the clause will still necessarily contribute
its compositional content to the interpretation of the sentence, exactly as argued by
McGinnis ().
Locating idiomatic meaning in truth-conditions associated with Roots also makes
predictions in the psycholinguistic domain. It entails that activation of a root’s lexical
entry will at least temporarily activate all its interpretations, idiomatic as well as literal,
until the conditioning environment is detected and the system settles on the most
likely licensed interpretation. Early activation of multiple meanings of this kind has
been detected both behaviourally and in imaging studies in the case of homophones
like batAnimal and batSportingEquip ; see e.g. Gunter, Wagner, and Friederici ().
We consider that investigation of such activation with idiomatic interpretation is a
promising direction for future research.
Another open research question is whether there are other syntactic constraints on
idiomatic structures. We have argued that the No Agents constraint holds for idioms
with open variables which must then compose with other, non-idiomatic material.
However, in proverbial expressions, where the whole sentential structure is fixed, as
in That’s the pot calling the kettle black, it seems to be the case that a genuinely agentive
argument receives an idiomatic interpretation in the context of the whole. Pending a
satisfactory definition of what it means to receive an idiomatic interpretation, it could
be that such fully fixed expressions are relevant to the debate concerning the nature
of the No Agent constraint, bearing, perhaps, on whether it is a syntactic or semantic
effect.
Though see Glasbey () and McGinnis () for further debate.
Part IV
. Introduction
In this chapter, I examine a particular comparative construction in Japanese—the so-
called yori-comparative, exemplified in ().
() Watashi-no musuko-wa watashi yori(mo) se-ga takai.
I-gen son-top I yori-mo height-nom tall
‘My son’s taller than me’. (Oda : ())
This is discussed alongside an English comparative construction that as far as I know
has received little attention before now—the of-phrase comparative, as in Of John and
Mary, John is taller. These classes of comparative are compared with a third—the com-
pared to comparative, exemplified by Compared to John and Mary, John is tall (Beck,
Oda, and Sugisaki , Kennedy ). Close comparison of yori, the of-phrase, and
compared to reveals that they are broadly alike in their syntactic properties, but exhibit
fine-grained distinctions in their lexical semantics that have significant consequences
for the interpretations of the sentences in which they occur.
My project is situated in the context of recent investigations of the crosslinguistic
semantics of comparison (Beck et al. , Oda , Kennedy , Beck et al. ,
Hohaus , Pearson ). The goal of these studies is to identify the dimensions
along which languages vary in how they form comparatives. For instance, Kennedy
∗ For Japanese judgements I am grateful to Hiroki Narita; any data not accompanied by a citation were
elicited from him. My understanding of the semantics of the comparative was much improved by a very
enjoyable class on that topic taught at MIT by Sigrid Beck and Irene Heim in spring . For helpful
comments, thanks to an anonymous reviewer, Amy Rose Deal, Michael Yoshitaka Erlewine, Peter Jenks,
Li Julie Jiang, Toshiko Oda, Orin Percus, Maria Polinsky, and to the audiences of the Language Universals
and Linguistic Fieldwork workshop at Harvard University and of OnLI II. I am responsible for all mistakes
and shortcomings.
Pearson
() considers the possibility that variation may be found in whether a language
employs so-called implicit or explicit comparison. () provides Kennedy’s definitions.
() a. Explicit comparison
Establish an ordering between objects x and y with respect to gradable prop-
erty g using a morphosyntactic form whose conventional meaning has the
consequence that the degree to which x is g exceeds the degree to which y
is g.
b. Implicit comparison
Establish an ordering between objects x and y with respect to gradable prop-
erty g using the positive form by manipulating the context such that the
positive form is true of x and false of y.
This distinction is inspired by the observation that although comparisons are proto-
typically formed by employing comparative morphology and a than-constituent, as
in (), they need not be, as illustrated by ().
() John is taller than Mary.
() Compared to Mary, John is tall.
() and () exemplify different strategies for communicating that John’s height is
greater than Mary’s. () is an example of an explicit comparison (EC) sentence,
whereas () instantiates implicit comparison (IC). While English has the resources
to employ either strategy, there is debate over whether there are languages that only
employ IC, with Japanese supplying a test case. I argue that Japanese is indeed an
implicit-comparison-only language. This aligns my position broadly with the anal-
yses of Beck et al. () and Oda (), although I recognize the limitations of
their accounts identified in Kennedy (). I argue that these problems are due
to treating implicit comparison constructions as a homogeneous class. Instead, I
adopt Pearson’s () division of IC into strong implicit comparison (SIC) and
weak implicit comparison (WIC). Kennedy’s arguments, which focus on Japanese
comparatives employing the postposition yori, show only that yori-comparatives do
not instantiate strong implicit comparison; they do not argue against treating yori-
comparatives in terms of weak implicit comparison. I argue that this is the cor-
rect classification for yori-comparatives, and give a corresponding semantics for this
construction.
In order to motivate the distinction between strong and weak IC, it is instruc-
tive to examine the of-phrase comparative. Here are some more examples of this
construction.
() a. Of John and Mary, John is the tall one.
b. Of John and Mary, only John is tall.
The Japanese Comparative
I assume a typed metalanguage where the basic types are e, t, and d—the types of individuals, truth
(a) denotes the degree argument of the gradable predicate (e.g. feet in
feet tall), or
(b) combines with another constituent to form a quantifier over degrees
(comparative morphemes e.g. -er, -est, less, too, enough).
(iv) The constituent with which the comparative morpheme combines is typi-
cally a than-constituent such as than Mary (is) and denotes the standard of
comparison.
() illustrates one recent syntactic implementation of these ideas, due to Bhatt and
Pancheva ().
() John is taller than Mary is.
IP
Johni I
I aP
is
aP DegP
ti a
-erj than Mary is tall
a AP
DegP A
-erj tall
The than-constituent than Mary is tall late merges with the comparative morpheme
-er in the position to which it has moved as a consequence of Quantifier Raising,
ensuring that -er and the than-clause form a constituent at LF. Furthermore, Bhatt
and Pancheva argue that the site of the Late Merger is the position in which the than-
clause is pronounced; this position obligatorily marks the scope of the comparison.
The than-clause contributes the set of degrees to which Mary is tall. -er is a quantifi-
cational element denoting the proper subset relationship, which takes the denotation
of the than-clause as its first argument and the denotation of John is t tall as its second
argument, where t is the trace of -er, interpreted as a variable of type d. Given standard
assumptions about QR, the LF includes an index immediately below the position to
Whether the than-constituent in English is always clausal, or whether it may sometimes be a smaller
phrase is controversial. I adopt the term than-constituent in order to avoid a commitment to a particular
view on this issue.
The Japanese Comparative
which -er moves, which serves as a variable binder. This yields as the second argument
of -er a predicate of degrees—the set of degrees to which John is tall. (a) is a bracketed
representation of (), enriched to show degree abstraction, while the truth-conditions
are in (b).
() a. [DegP -er [than [Îd Mary is t t tall]]] [Îd John is t tall]
b. [[(a)]] = iff
{d : Mary is tall to degree d} ⊂ {d : John is tall to degree d}
The result is a streamlined mapping between LF syntax and semantics: the semantics
of the comparative morpheme specifies that it seeks two arguments, each of which
describe a set of degrees, while the syntactic processes of Quantifier Raising and Late
Merger make these elements available to the interpretive component. Assuming this
characterization of explicit comparison, let us return to my claim that the sentences
in (), repeated in (), are not examples of EC constructions.
() a. Compared to Mary, John is taller.
b. Of John and Mary, John is the taller one.
The requirement that explicit comparison incorporate a morphosyntactic form that
accomplishes a given comparison involves not only comparative morphology, but also
a than-constituent that forms a constituent with the comparative morpheme at LF.
(a) and (b) involve no than-constituent, although one might wonder whether
compared to Mary and of John and Mary perform the same function. This hypothesis
obviously would not work for (b): while than-constituents introduce standards of
comparison, the of-phrase furnishes both the standard of comparison and the other
individual being compared. Moreover, if compared to Mary and of John and Mary
had the syntactic and semantic functions of a than-constituent, then the syntactic
distribution of these phrases would be expected to be confined to positions that let
them mark the scope of the comparison. This is not borne out: the examples below
show that the placement of these constituents is relatively free.
() a. John is taller than Mary.
b. John is taller compared to Mary.
c. John is the taller one of John and Mary.
() a. ∗ John is than Mary taller.
b. John is, compared to Mary, taller.
c. John is, of John and Mary, the taller one.
() a. ∗ John than Mary is taller.
b. John, compared to Mary, is taller.
c. ?John, of John and Mary, is the taller one.
Pearson
section ., while its consequences are discussed in section .. One theme that
emerges is that although yori, the of-phrase, and compared to are broadly alike in
syntactic properties, the semantics of compared to is significantly different from that
of yori and the of-phrase. These lexical distinctions have consequences for whether the
constructions in which the items participate involve weak or strong implicit compar-
ison, thereby partially determining the inventory of modes of comparision exhibited
by the languages in question. These issues are summarized in section ..
Actually, he identifies four properties of IC, but only employs three of these in his investigation of
yori-comparatives.
One might wonder whether the infelicity of (b) is due not to Mary’s and John’s closeness in height,
but to the fact that any height over foot might be considered tall. Indeed, Kennedy notes that implicit
comparisons carry an implicature that the predicate does not hold of the standard of comparison. The
reader is invited to check that this is not what is at work here by verifying that the sentence is also infelicitous
in a context where Mary is foot inches tall and John is only inch taller than that.
Pearson
minimum standard gradable adjectives in IC constructions that does not apply to EC.
This restriction reveals itself in a context where the minimum standard adjective is
true of both of the compared objects, as in (). Explicit comparison is felicitous in
this context (a), but implicit comparison is not (b).
() Context: Rod A and rod B are bent, rod B more so than rod A.
a. B is more bent than A.
b. ??Compared to A, B is bent. (Kennedy : ())
Kennedy notes that in this context, a yori-comparative is felicitous ().
() Ano sao-wa kono sao yori magatte-iru.
that rod-top this rod yori bent-be
‘That rod is more bent than this rod’. (Adapted from Kennedy : ())
Finally, Kennedy observes that differential measure phrases are available with explicit
but not implicit comparison.
() a. John is one inch taller than Mary/John is taller than Mary by one inch.
b. Compared to Mary, John is one inch tall/Compared to Mary, John is tall
by one inch.
He reports that differential measure phrases are available with yori-comparatives,
however.
() Gozira-wa Rodan yori hyaku-ton omoi.
Godzilla-top Rodan yori -tons heavy
‘Godzilla is tons heavier than Rodan’.
Kennedy concludes that yori-comparatives instantiate explicit rather than implicit
comparison. This conclusion is a little hasty, however. The diagnostics all involve
properties of IC constructions that employ the positive form of the predicate, thereby
diagnosing strong implicit comparison. English weak implicit comparison exhibits
none of the properties Kennedy identified for SIC, as can be verified by adding
comparative morphology in (b), (b), and (b). While Kennedy’s arguments
show that yori-comparatives do not involve strong implicit comparison, they do not
exclude the possibility that they instantiate weak implicit comparison—that is, that
yori-comparatives have a covert comparative morpheme, even though there is no
overt material to supply its first argument. I think that a WIC analysis is preferable
In Kennedy’s original example, magatte-iru is modified by motto, yielding an expression that means ‘be
very bent’. While the status of motto is controversial (see fn. below), modification of a minimum standard
predicate by this expression arguably produces a relative predicate, and is therefore best avoided for this
test. The judgement remains unchanged.
In fact, matters are more complicated still. In Pearson () I argued that Kennedy’s diagnostics
involving crisp judgements and differential measure phrases are not good tests for strong implicit com-
The Japanese Comparative
to an EC analysis. In this, I concur with Oda (), although in the next subsection
I identify shortcomings of her implementation.
WIC: one but not both of Kennedy’s criteria for implicit comparison is satisfied. This
is the classification of yori-comparatives that I endorse in this chapter.
This view raises the question of where the comparative meaning appears, given
that it does not surface overtly. Here Oda’s proposal and mine part company. Oda’s
answer is that there is no dedicated morpheme meaning -er, but rather that Japanese
adjectives are inherently comparative in meaning. A sample lexical entry is in ().
() [[takai]] = Îx.max(Îd.tall(d)(x)) > c. (Based on Oda : (a))
where (i) c is a contextually supplied standard; (ii) for any set X, max(X) is X’s
largest element.
According to this view, takai denotes the set of individuals that are taller than some
contextually supplied standard of height. This predicts that there is no strong implicit
comparison in Japanese: by definition, SIC involves the positive form of the adjective,
yet according to Oda, Japanese adjectives have no positive form. This prediction is
not borne out: there is a class of comparatives, which I call kurabetara/kuraberuto
comparatives, that pass the diagnostics for SIC. () provides examples.
() a. Ziro-ni kurabe-ta-ra Taro-wa se-ga takai.
Ziro-dat compare-past-cond Taro-top height-nom tall
‘Compared to Ziro, Taro is tall’.
b. Ziro-ni kurabe-ru-to Taro-wa se-ga takai.
Ziro-dat compare-pres-cond Taro-top height-nom tall
‘Compared to Ziro, Taro is tall’. (Sawada : ())
Sawada () demonstrates that this construction exhibits the hallmarks of strong
implicit comparison. For reasons of space, I discuss only the crisp judgement diag-
nostic; the reader is referred to Sawada’s work for additional data. Unlike yori-
comparatives, kurabetara/kuraberuto comparatives are infelicitous in crisp judgement
contexts:
() Context: There are two papers. One is pages long and the other is pages
long.
a. Ano peepaa-ni kurabe-tara kono peepaa-wa nagai.
that paper-dat compare-cond this paper-top long
‘Compared to that paper, this paper is long.’
b. Ano peepaa-ni kurabe-ru-to kono peepaa-wa nagai.
that paper-dat compare-pres-cond this paper-top long
‘Compared to that paper, this paper is long.’
I conclude that the view that Japanese gradable predicates are inherently comparative
is incorrect. On the other hand, I am convinced by Beck et al.’s arguments that
yori-comparatives do not involve EC. Japanese has both strong and weak implicit
The Japanese Comparative
In some work, motto ‘much, very’ is taken to be the morpheme associated with the comparative of
superiority. See Beck et al. () for arguments that this gloss is incorrect.
An anonymous reviewer suggests that yori might itself be the comparative morpheme. One argument
against this is that yori-constructions do not always express comparisons, as we shall see in the next section.
An anonymous reviewer reports finding () acceptable. I suspect that variations in judgement
concerning this sentence reflect the degree to which speakers are prepared to assign it an interpretation
involving focus or covert exhaustification—in essence, an unpronounced counterpart of the only that
renders the sentence acceptable in (c).
(d) may be less acceptable for some speakers than (a–c); however it seems to be an improvement
on ().
Pearson
Section . introduced the idea that the of-phrase restricts attention to contexts
whose domains of discourse have a certain structure. We can model this in a Kapla-
nian semantics that distinguishes two levels of meaning. A character is a function
from a context to a content, which is in turn a function from a world to an extension
(entities in the world or truth values). Kaplan’s notion of context is intended to provide
the elements required in order to furnish referents for indexicals, for example by
specifying who the speaker is in the case of I. I shall enrich this by letting the domain
of discourse U be a contextual parameter too. Additionally, I add to the metalanguage
the basic types k, the type of contexts, and s, the type of worlds. The character of
a sentence is of type k, s, t, that of a one-place predicate type e, k, s, t, and
so on.
We are now in a position to model the semantics of the of-phrase by manipulating
the context parameter. I assume that the of-phrase is a sentence modifier, type
k, s, t, k, s, t. Its semantics is as follows.
() [[of x and y]] = Θk,s,t Îck Îws .˜(c[U = {x, y}])(w) =
Where c[U = {a, b}] is that context c that is just like c except that the domain
of discourse of c consists only of a and b.
Let us see what interpretation this semantics assigns to ??Of John and Mary, John
is tall. I need a lexical entry for tall, along with a semantics for the operator POS,
which is an existential quantifier over degrees, and therefore indirectly saturates the
degree argument of a predicate like tall in the absence of comparative morphology.
The following suffice for my purposes.
() [[tall]] = Îdd Îxe Îck Îws .x is d-tall in w.
() [[POS]] = ÎDd,t Îck Îws .∃d ∈ D : d ≥ s
Where s is the contextually salient degree standard.
A sentence of form P(x), where P is a gradable predicate used in its positive form,
asserts that there is some degree d to which x is P such that d is at least as great as
See Percus () for extensive discussion of this framework.
Readers may be concerned that by letting the semantics of the of-phrase manipulate the context
parameter, we obtain a system that violates Kaplan’s () prohibition against monsters; we appear to
be contradicting his claim that operators that manipulate the context parameter are absent from natural
language. On the other hand, recent crosslinguistic work on indexical shift (e.g. Schlenker , ,
Anand and Nevins , Anand ) has undermined the empirical case for banning monsters, which was
originally based only on English. Moreover, the controversy over the status of monsters is really concerned
with whether (i) there are operators that quantify over contexts, much as modal operators quantify over
worlds, and (ii) the reference of an indexical expression can shift in the scope of such operators. The
modification of the context performed by the of-phrase given the semantics in () exhibits neither of
these characteristics.
The semantics is similar to that proposed for compared to in Kennedy () in that both induce a
the degree standard d made salient in the context. I illustrate this by providing the
interpretation of John is tall.
() a. John is tall.
b. LF: [[DegP POS] [Îd John is t -tall]]
c. [[(b)]] = Îck Îws .∃d ∈ {d : John is d-tall in w} : d ≥ s
The degraded sentence ??Of John and Mary, John is tall has the following meaning.
() a. ??Of John and Mary, John is tall.
b. [[(a)]] = [[Of John and Mary]](Îck Îws .∃d ∈ {d : John is d-tall in w} :
d ≥ s)
= (Îck Îws .∃d ∈ {d : John is d-tall in w} : d ≥ s)
This says that in a context in which the domain of discourse consists solely of John
and Mary, John’s height is at least as great as the contextually salient degree standard.
But this shifting of the domain does not necessarily have any effect on the degree
standard. Suppose that in the original context, the standard is just the average height
of a human being; indeed, this seems to be the standard with respect to which John
is tall is interpreted out of the blue. Notice that in order for this degree standard to
be available, it need not be the case that the domain of discourse includes the entire
human race; suppose we are discussing whether every syntactician is tall, confining
our attention to syntacticians who attended the conference On Linguistic Interfaces
. The question of interest might nonetheless be whether every such syntactician is
tall relative to the average human, rather than relative to, say, the semanticists and
phonologists at the conference. This suggests that the degree standard in a context and
the domain of discourse in that context are in principle independent of one another.
Consequently, adjusting the discourse domain to include only John and Mary does
not necessarily make any difference to the standard with respect to which John is tall
is evaluated. It is in this sense that the contextual shift induced by the of-phrase is
redundant in the simple case involving the positive form of the gradable predicate.
The next step is to state more explicitly how comparative morphology in (a) saves
the sentence from the degraded status of (). I said that in implicit comparison sen-
tences like (a), there is no overt material that performs the syntactic and semantic
function of a than-constituent; the of-phrase supplies the standard of comparison in
an indirect way, by manipulating the context. Let us suppose then that in such a case,
For simplicity, I omit world and context variables from the LFs. I have in mind an extensional
framework where world arguments of predicates are encoded in the syntax as silent pronominals (Percus
); the same could be assumed for context arguments, as sketched e.g. in Percus ().
This will follow if the domain of discourse, but not the standard of comparison, is a parameter of the
Kaplanian context.
In this I disagree with Kennedy (, ), who explicitly assumes that manipulation of the context
predicate would take as its argument the subject watashino musukowa, ‘my son’. The
sentence would be true if and only if, in the context that is just like the actual context
except that the domain of discourse consists of me and my son, my son is tall. The
same thing goes wrong here as with ??Of John and Mary, John is tall. Nothing is
contributed by adjusting the context to one in which the domain of discourse consists
of the speaker’s son and the speaker. A covert comparative morpheme resolves this
redundancy. The next step is to give a semantics for this morpheme. I follow Kennedy
() in assuming that the Japanese counterpart of -er takes an individual rather than
a degree as its first argument—i.e. it has the semantics of English -er . Since I think
that yori-comparatives involve weak implicit comparison, this argument is supplied
by a covert pronominal proi ; this is analogous to my analysis of English WIC. The
truth-conditions of () are computed below.
() a. My son [[is tall -er proi ] [yori me]].
b. [[is tall -er proi ]] = [[-er ]]([[proi ]])([[tall]]) =
Îye Îck Îws .max({d : tall(d)(y)(c)(w) = }) > max({d : tall(d)(gc (i))(c)(w)
= })
c. [[yori me]] = [[yori]](me) =
ÎPe,k,s,t Îye Îck Îws .P(y)(c[U = {me, y}])(w) =
d. [[[[is tall -er proi ] [yori me]]]] = [[yori me]]([[is tall -er proi ]]) =
Îye Îck Îws .[Îxe Îck Îws .max({d : tall(d)(x)(c )(w ) = }) >
max({d : tall(d)(gc (i))(c )(w ) = })](y)(c[U = {me, y}])(w) = =
Îye Îck Îws .max({d : tall(d)(y)(c[U = {me, y}])(w) = }) >
max({d : tall(d)(gc[U={me,y}] (i))(c[U = {me, y}])(w) = })
e. [[My son [[is tall -er proi ] [yori me]]]] =
[[[[is tall -er proi ] [yori me]]]](my son) =
Îck Îws .max({d : tall(d)(my son)(c[U = {me, y}])(w) = }) >
max({d : tall(d)(gc[U={me,my son}] (i))(c[U = {me, my son}])(w) = })
(a) is true if and only if, in that modified context that is just like the actual context
except that the domain of discourse is the speaker and the speaker’s son, the height
of the speaker’s son exceeds the height of the individual supplied by the assignment
function. Since in such a context the only plausible standard is the speaker, I derive the
intuitively correct meaning, ‘My son is taller than me’. The following section discusses
some consequences of my proposal.
. Consequences
.. Non-comparative yori-constructions and of-phrase constructions
Recall that one of the motivations for treating yori-comparatives as examples of
implicit comparison was the ability of yori-phrases to occur in non-comparative
sentences, as in (a), repeated below.
Pearson
Assuming the view of focus semantics sketched informally above, () communicates
that John decided to go to America, and he did not decide to go to any other location
included among the focus alternatives of America. On the assumption that focus
alternatives are constrained by the domain of discourse, the contextual manipulation
performed by the of-phrase derives that John did not decide to go to Europe, in
accordance with our intuitions.
The counterpart of this sentence involving the yori-construction receives a parallel
analysis. I adopt the simplifying assumption that this sentence involves the two-
place predicate decide to go to; yori-phrases can be predicate modifiers of two-place
predicates as well as one-place predicates like tall. The semantics of yori is therefore
type-flexible; the entry appropriate to the case involving a two-place predicate appears
below.
() [[yori−place ]] =
Îxe ÎRe,e,k,s,t Îye Îze Îck Îws .P(y)(z)(c[U = {x, y, z}])(w) =
In general, for any n-place predicate Q, yori combines with some individual x to form
a modifier of Q whose contribution is to shift the context to one whose domain of
discourse has n + members: it is that set consisting of x and Q’s arguments. I assume
that in (), America is again focus marked:
() a. Ken decided to go to [America]F yori Europe.
b. [[yori−place ]](Europe)(decide-to-go-to)(America)(Ken) =
ÎcÎw.(decide-to-go-to)([America]F )(Ken)(c[U =
{Europe, America, Ken}])(w)
() communicates that Ken decided to go to America, and that he did not decide
to go to any other location from among America’s focus alternatives. I said that only
members of the domain of discourse can be included among the focus alternatives.
Given the contextual manipulation performed by the yori-phrase, this domain con-
sists of Europe, America, and Ken. Plausibly, then, the set of focus alternatives is just
{Europe, America}, since Ken is not a location. I thereby derive that Ken did not decide
to go to Europe.
The view that yori-comparatives instantiate implicit comparison makes room for a
unified treatment of those constructions with cases where the yori-construction does
not have a comparative meaning. Adjusting with types where appropriate, a single
lexical entry for yori accommodates both types of case, given the assumption that the
domain of discourse may play various possible roles in recovering the meaning of yori-
sentences. Where it supplies a standard of comparison, a comparative meaning results,
while a non-comparative meaning is available if the domain of discourse constrains
focus alternatives. By adopting the view that of-phrases likewise constrain the domain
of discourse, I derive that of-phrase constructions also tolerate non-comparative inter-
pretations.
Pearson
fact, whether John is compared to Mary makes no difference to his height either: his
height cannot change as a consequence of such an event. Yet we can say that when
compared to Mary, John is tall. I suggest that the reason for this is that, although
comparing John to Mary cannot change the properties that he has, such comparison
changes one’s perceptions of those properties. That is, the constraint on modification
of ILPs with when-adjuncts is circumvented in the case of compared to because the
meaning of tall is coerced to mean roughly seem tall. Since seem tall is not individual-
level—I may seem tall in one situation but not in another, depending on who I am
standing next to, say—there is no question of violating this constraint. Evidence in
favour of this view can be found in the equivalence of the sentences in (), which
disappears when compared to is omitted, as in (); compare the continuations in ().
() a. Compared to Mary, John is tall.
b. Compared to Mary, John seems tall.
() a. John is tall.
b. John seems tall.
() a. ?John seems tall compared to Mary, but he isn’t tall compared to Mary.
b. John seems tall, but he isn’t tall.
I conclude that compared to y is a universal quantifier over world–individual pairs
w , z such that w involves a comparison with y by z; x is A compared to y asserts that
for every such pair, z perceives x to be A.
() [[compared to y]] = Θk,s,t Îck Îws .∀w, z[Acc(w, w )& w involves a
comparison with y by z] [z perceives ˜(c)(w ) to be true]
Where Acc(w, w ) iff w is like w in all relevant respects.
We are now in a position to understand why Compared to Mary, John is tall is
acceptable—that is, why the phrase compared to Mary is not redundant, even though
tall is used in its positive rather than comparative form. Below I display the composi-
tion of the compared to phrase with John is tall.
() a. Compared to Mary, John is tall.
b. [Compared to Mary] [[Deg POS] [Îd [John is [d -tall]]]]
c. [[[Deg POS] [Îd [John is d -tall]]]] = ÎcÎw.∃d ∈ {d : John is d -tall in w} :
d≥s
d. [[(b)]] = ÎcÎw.∀w, z[Acc(w, w )& w involves a comparison with Mary by z]
[z perceives it to be true that ∃d ∈ {d : John is d -tall in w } : d ≥ s]
This says that in any accessible world involving a comparison with Mary, one perceives
John’s height to be at least as great as the contextually salient standard for tallness.
Strong implicit comparison in Japanese with kurabetara/kuraberuto works in the same
Pearson
. Conclusion
Let us summarize what we have learned about the syntax and semantics of the
of-phrase, yori, and compared to. In section ., I presented arguments that the of-
phrase and the compared to phrase are syntactic adjuncts. Space considerations have
prevented me from discussing the syntax of the yori-phrase in detail, but Beck et al.
() propose that this constituent has the syntactic status of a relative clause; I refer
the reader to their paper for arguments in favour of this view. If so, then each of the
implicit comparison constructions this chapter has been concerned with (indirectly)
provides its standard of comparison by means of a syntactic adjunct. It seems then that
the implicit/explicit comparison distinction can be characterized in purely syntactic
terms, with reference to whether the material that provides the standard of compari-
son is an argument or adjunct. I leave it to future work on a wider range of languages
to confirm or falsify this hypothesis.
I would like to end, however, by observing that when we look at a finer-grained
distinction—that between weak and strong implicit comparison—the category of
a given comparative construction does not appear to be deducible from syntactic
properties alone. Consider the yori-comparative and the kurabetara/kuraberuto com-
parative. I argued that the former employs a covert comparative morpheme, but the
latter does not, thereby predicting that yori-comparatives display the characteristics
of weak implicit comparison, and kurabetara/kuraberuto comparatives exhibit those
of strong implicit comparison. Suppose I am correct that these facts follow from the
different semantics of yori and kurabetara/kuraberuto—one producing an adjusted
context, and the other being a modal quantifier. This would imply that in the end, the
question of which mode of comparison a given constituent gives rise to can only be
answered by appeal to properties of the lexical entries in question.
Bare Number∗
T H E OD OR A A L E XOP OU LOU, R A F FA E L L A F OL L I ,
AND GEORGE T SOUL AS
. Introduction
The last fifteen years have seen a resurgence of studies on the structure and interpreta-
tion of bare nominals, partly in the wake of Chierchia’s seminal paper ‘Reference
to Kinds across Languages’. Within his framework, Chierchia proposes the existence
of a semantic parameter, the Nominal Mapping Parameter (NMP) that governs the
distribution of bare nouns across languages and explains to a significant degree the
correlations between the bare form and its denotations. The NMP is formulated in
terms of the possible combinations of two binary features [±pred], [±arg]. If the
parameter is set to [+pred, −arg], a positive specification of the former feature means
that lexical nouns in the language have predicative (property, type e, t) denotations,
and as a result cannot be used bare in argument position. To appear as arguments,
nouns in these languages must be accompanied by argumentizing functional struc-
ture, typically a D (type: e, t, e or e, t, e, t, t as the case may be). An example
of such a language is French, where bare arguments are altogether disallowed:
() ∗ Cuisiniers
ont maltraité Ganelon.
cooks have mistreated Ganelon
‘Cooks have mistreated Ganelon.’
Conversely, languages of the [−pred, +arg] type do not require argumentizing func-
tional structure: their bare NPs can serve as arguments referring typically to kinds
(type e). Typical examples of such languages are Chinese, Japanese, and Korean.
∗ We would like to thank the audiences of LAGB , workshop on Bare nouns: Syntactic Projections
and their Interpretation, Université Paris Diderot, Laboratoire de Linguistique Formelle, UMR CNRS
(), OnLI II (), Workshop on Current Issues on Semantics and Pragmatics at York (), Mediter-
ranean Syntax Meeting (), Syntax Group at Cambridge (), and Workshop Celebrating thirty years
from ‘On the Syntax and Semantics of Resumptive Pronouns’ by Edit Doron (). We are also grateful
for discussion to Giuliana Giusti, Gennaro Chierchia, Napoleon Katsos, and Giuseppe Longobardi.
Bare Number
A language may also choose a positive specification for both attributes [+pred,
+arg]. This is the case in English, where bare arguments can occur only if they are
plural or mass but otherwise will require a determiner in order to appear in argument
position.
All the different types of language given above have been extensively studied. In
this chapter we will be focusing on languages of the [+pred, −arg] type, a cate-
gory in which the Romance languages have figured most prominently. A significant
observation regarding at least some languages in this category is that despite what
the general setting [+pred, −arg] entails, we do observe bare arguments in certain
structural positions. The positions in question are on the one hand those which, using
technical vocabulary corresponding to GB assumptions, are lexically governed (i.e.
complement to a verb or preposition) and, on the other, positions associated with
specific information-structural notions. The literature on e.g. Italian or Spanish has
converged on the idea that these languages have in their inventory of determiners
or D-like elements a phonologically null element which is used in these cases. The
strict syntactic conditions correspond to the requirement for the null element to
be identified. Whether or not a language has a null D seems to escape principled
explanation at least insofar as the NMP is concerned. Italian and Spanish have it,
French does not. Despite the focus on the status and availability of a null D, one
theoretical possibility that has remained under-explored is that languages with (some)
bare arguments which lack a null D may use other functional structure to achieve the
same effect as a null D. Here is a little thought experiment. Imagine a language, call it
Freek, which uses bare arguments fairly liberally, to wit more than Italian, i.e. not only
in the designated lexically governed positions. However, like French, it can be shown
not to have a null D. Imagine also that Freek allows both bare singular and plural
arguments. A question that immediately arises in the context of the classification given
by the NMP is: which class does Freek belong to? Clearly, it is not a [−pred, +arg]
language. Nouns in Freek are not all mass and it does not have a developed classifier
system. Freek must be either [+pred, +arg] or [+pred, −arg]. Taking a narrow view
of the NMP we must reject the possibility of filing Freek together with English as a
[+pred, +arg] language, since it allows bare singular arguments as well as bare plurals.
Regarding the second possibility, i.e. that Freek is a [+pred, −arg] language, it would
appear that taking a very narrow view of the NMP, we would also have to rule this
possibility out since, by assumption, Freek lacks a null D. What to do? It seems that
there are three possibilities:
A. Freek does not, and crucially cannot, actually exist. It is an impossible language.
B. Sub-parametrize the [+pred, +arg] setting so as to allow:
A language that would choose [−pred, −arg] as its setting would not be able to use nominal arguments
Haegeman, and Stavrou (). The nominalizing/argumentizing role of D in Italian has been debated
by Longobardi (), Chierchia (), and Giusti (). We here restrict discussion to bare nouns in
Greek and do not discuss the analysis of the Greek definite article, which has been a matter of debate in
the Greek literature (see e.g. Horrocks and Stavrou , Androutsopoulou , Panagiotidis , and
Kolliakou ).
Bare Number
‘A secretary, you will find her easily/sooner or later you will find her.’
b. Gramatea tha (∗ ti) vrite sigura.
secretary will (∗ her.cl find.pl certainly
‘A secretary, you will find her certainly.’
The examples in () show that in Italian, CLLD can be used with indefinite topics
and that, just as for definite topics, the dislocated element is a DP and it is resumed
by the pronominal clitic la. In contrast, in Greek we see a case of Topicalization
where the topic is bare and the comment cannot contain the clitic ti. The scopal
properties of indefinite topics also differ between the two languages: Greek CLLD-
ed indefinites resist opaque or de dicto readings (Iatridou , Alexopoulou and
Kolliakou ):
() a. Mia kokini fusta tin psahno edho ke meres
a red skirt it look for.sg here and days
‘I’ve been looking for a red skirt for a few days …’
b. =ke de boro na vro kamia pu na m’aresi.
and not can.sg subj find.sg none that subj me please.sg
‘… and I cannot find any that I like.’
c. ke de boro na thimitho pu tin eho vali.
and not can.sg subj remember.sg where her.cl have.sg put
‘… and cannot remember where I put it.’ (Alexopoulou and Kolliakou )
Alexopoulou, Folli, and Tsoulas
In Italian, on the other hand, the corresponding example in (a) is ambiguous and
can therefore have both (b) and (c) as a possible continuation:
() a. Una gonna rossa la cerco da un po’
a red skirt her.cl look for.sg for a while
‘A red skirt I’ve been looking for for a while …’
b. ma non ne ho trovata nessuna che mi piaccia.
but not of them.cl have.sg found none.f that me.cl please.sg.subj
‘… but have not found any one that I like.’
c. ma non riesco a ricordarmi dove l’ho messa.
but not reach.sg to remember where her.cl have.sg put
‘… but I cannot remember where I’ve put it.’
Thus, we can draw a preliminary conclusion here and say that while CLLD is employed
in both Greek and Italian to encode discourse topics, Italian encodes topics exclusively
by means of CLLD, irrespective of ‘referentiality/specificity’, whereas Greek employs
Topicalization for non-referential topics as in ():
() a. Fetos i moda ine apesia; idika i bluzes ine aparadektes.
this year the fashion is awful; especially the blouses are outrageous
‘I hate this year’s fashion; the blouses are especially outrageous.’
b. Mia kokini bluza psahno edo ki ena mina ke de boro na
a red blouse look for.sg here and one month and not can subj
vro puthena kamia pu na m’aresi.
find.sg anywhere any one that subj me like.sg
‘A red blouse I’ve been looking for for a month now and I cannot find one that
I like.’
These examples highlight two crucial differences between the two languages in these
structures: Greek, unlike Italian, uses bare nouns where a nominal has a weak indef-
inite reading; Greek has a gap where Italian has an obligatory clitic pronoun. We
interpret this type of data as showing that if Greek does not employ the (otherwise
available) clitic which is categorially a D, this is because the moved constituent is not
a DP headed by a null D.
Furthermore, these differences can be taken as a starting point to uncover further
related contrasts in the two languages. Alexopoulou and Folli () single out the
availability of Indefinite Argument Drop (IAD), Bare Subnominal Deletion (BSD),
and the distribution of bare nouns more generally as the relevant related facts. With
respect to IAD, in Greek the possibility of dropping an indefinite argument is not
restricted to the CLLD cases discussed above, but is available also in examples of
intrasentential anaphora, as observed by Dimitriadis (), (see also Giannakidou
and Merchant , Panagiotidis , and Tsimpli and Papadopoulou ):
Bare Number
Some context is needed for the exchange in (b). For instance, if a new helpline is set up in a university,
available to faculty, students, and the general public, but what is of interest is if students specifically use it,
then (b) can be a felicitous exchange.
Alexopoulou, Folli, and Tsoulas
D NumP
Num …
NP
Note that under option (C), pursued here, in principle any head in ‘. . .’ may fulfil the argumentizing
function. The question is, of course, primarily empirical but there may be good conceptual reasons to
restrict it to Num and D. We will return briefly to this question at the end of the chapter.
Alexopoulou, Folli, and Tsoulas
There are of course numerous issues regarding the order of the different projections
etc. We will, however, gloss over these issues as they are for the most part orthogonal
to the issues addressed in the present work. Our proposal pertains solely to the
possibility of endowing Num with features and functions similar to those of D in the
relevant contexts and languages. We do not claim that if Num can do the work of D
then D is surplus to requirements in any sense, but simply that in certain cases Num
alone will suffice.
Let us now turn to the distribution of bare nouns in Greek.
gather.sg ∗ stamp-sg/stamps-pl
‘She collects stamps.’
Furthermore, Greek bare singulars cannot license plural interpretations in () and
() (adapted from Espinal : (a)).
() Psahno aftokinito; = ena mikro gia tin poli ki ena fortighaki ya
look for.sg car one small for the city and one van for
ekdromes.
trips
‘I’m looking for a car. = A small one for the city and a van for trips.’
Finally, unlike Catalan (), Greek bare nouns are compatible both with qualitative
and descriptive adjectives as well as classifying ones (). Examples like (b) and
(c) show that such nominals denote individuals, a possibility unavailable in Catalan.
() a. Per a aquest espectecle necessitareu faldilla llarga / escocesa / de quadres.
for to this event need.fut skirt long kilt plaid
‘For this event you will need a long skirt/a kilt/a plaid skirt.’
Alexopoulou, Folli, and Tsoulas
to saying that NumP just lacks quantificational force that can interact scopally with
operators/quantifiers. The semantic explanation can be cast in Carlson’s view of
kinds: bare nouns are directly mapped to arguments and denote kinds. Kinds are
names. Names, be they kinds or ordinary proper names, do not interact with seman-
tic operators/quantifiers scopally. Chierchia () has a different way of deriving
scopelessness which turns basically on two elements. First, he assumes with Fox
() that scope-shifting operations are constrained by economy considerations and
do not apply unless they produce a different interpretation. Second, scope-shifting
operations, being movement operations, leave behind traces/copies, and the natural
assumption regarding the type of trace/copy that a DP leaves behind is that it is the
same as that of the moved constituent itself. Given that kind-denoting nominals leave
behind kind-level traces, the interpretation assigned to a sentence turns out to be the
same either in the movement or the in situ case, and as a result there is no scope
shifting taking place.
One immediate challenge for the semantic analysis is the fact that Greek systemat-
ically employs the definite article for direct reference to kinds. We turn to reference
to kinds next.
For the technical explanation, we refer the reader to Chierchia (: –).
The empirical content of the notion of ‘established kind’ is unclear. Dobrovie-Sorin and Pires de
Oliveira () suggest that it is altogether dispensable, as it follows from the need for a taxonomy in
order to establish kinds anyway. Note also that Greek has no predicate that means ‘extinct’; the closest
is ‘disappear’, which can accept kinds and existential indefinites as subjects.
Bare Number
The question raised by () is what prevents bare nouns in Greek from referring to
kinds in a general way. If, under our hypothesis, Num is the argumentizing head in
Greek, why is it that NumP cannot support direct kind reference? This is a striking
difference between Greek and English bare nominals, which can be used for direct
kind reference (when plural).
Note, however, that under certain circumstances bare plurals can be used to denote
kinds despite the general preference to employ the definite article. Consider the fol-
lowing examples involving coordinated nouns:
() a. Dinosavri ke tiranosavri ehoun eksafanisti edo kai
dinosaurs.nom and tyrannosaurs.nom have.pl disappeared here and
ekatomiria xronia.
millions years
‘Dinosaurs and tyrannosaurs disappeared millions of years ago.’
b. (Karharies kai) falenes spanizoun sto Saroniko.
sharks.nom and whales.nom are rare in the Saronic
‘Sharks and whales are rare in the Saronic Gulf.’
It is known that coordination can render grammatical bare nouns that are otherwise
unavailable. For instance, Heycock and Zamparelli () show that bare singulars are
allowed in English when coordinated, and so are coordinated bare nouns in French
(which generally bans bare nouns). A crucial property of such nouns is that, though
bare, they have a definite interpretation. To account for this, Heycock and Zamparelli
() propose that the coordinated nouns move as a unit (CoorP) to the specifier
of a DP with a null head. An analysis of (a) in this spirit would involve a null D
hosting the coordinate bare nouns; in Spec,DP the coordinated nouns would acquire a
definite meaning and, as a result, refer to kinds, by proxy. Postulating a null D in Greek
to account for () would need some motivation beyond examples like (a). More
importantly, coordination is not always obligatory for the licensing of bare nouns
with kind readings. The bare noun in (b) is possible even without coordination.
In addition, bare plurals in object position can also have kind readings, as in ():
() O Kostas meleta karkinous.
the Kostas study.sg cancers
‘Kostas studies cancers.’
Alongside the kind reading, () also has a reading of a plurality of types/kinds of
cancers. We do not offer a full analysis of these examples, but in section .. we
discuss how these cases of bare kind-denoting nouns can be understood within our
analysis of Greek number.
Alexopoulou, Folli, and Tsoulas
. Number
In the preceding sections we have formulated the hypothesis that in Greek a bare noun
is in fact a NumP, and that the Num head is what is responsible for turning a bare
N into an argument. We have also argued, concomitantly, that this is a theoretical
possibility that is not generally excluded by any principle of the grammar. The ques-
tion now is how Num actually performs this function. Let us begin with the simple
cases. In simple cases Num has a relatively simple semantic contribution. To keep
the definitions general we can proceed adopting Chierchia’s () general view and
assume a single denotational domain which looks very much like the denotation of
a mass term in that it contains both singularities and pluralities. The lattice structure
looks as follows:
⎡ ⎤
() {a, b, c}
⎣ {a, b} {a, c} {c, b} ⎦
a b c
The structure in () is a ‘complete atomic join semilattice’. Given this, we can repre-
sent the denotation of a singular as ():
() abc
What is missing from the denotation of the singular is the pluralities, and what is
missing from the plural is the singularities or atoms, as one would expect.
Bare Number
D NumP
Num …
±Singular
±Augmented … NP
√
N
⎡ ⎤
{a, b, c}
⎣ {a, b} {a, c} {c, b} ⎦
a b c
We return in the next section to the definition of the [±Augmented] feature. Now,
this representation encapsulates the fact that there is no unmarked number value in
any sense useful for our purposes. In other words, the plural is not derived from the
singular and the singular is not derived from the plural. Rather, both number-marked
denotations are derived from the application of Num to the nominal number-neutral
root. Informally, [+sing] will yield atomic individuals whereas [−sing] will yield the
A similar view is taken also by Farkas and de Swart ().
Each assumption, taken individually, is not uncontroversial, though.
Alexopoulou, Folli, and Tsoulas
Or, in the absence of a determiner, the language must allow free or almost free application of type-
in some implementations required, among other things, in order to serve as a target for EPP satisfaction.
Alternatively, the EPP can be cross-categorial targeting any maximal projection (Holmberg ). This
means that the syntactic functions of D can be played by other functional heads, such as Num in the case of
Greek. Note that, if we assume that EPP is cross-categorial, it may but need not be satisfied by Num. Thus,
merging of a Determiner above Num is not precluded.
Bare Number
by many others (see Zweig for a very careful exposition and references). Accord-
ing to such view, the multiplicity involved in the plural in Greek is an implicature.
Following the discussion above, the meaning of a plural is:
() [[Falenes]] = Falena(x) ∧ |x| >
The second conjunct in () is the implicature.
Note now that under this account the semantics of the plural on mass nouns
becomes rather obvious. Assuming it is conjunctive like in (), we will have:
() [[Muds]] = Mud(x) ∧ Ï(x) > y
where Ï is the appropriate measure function and y an amount supplied contextu-
ally. This conjunctive semantics gives clear expression to the multiplicity implicature.
Roughly, () means ‘there is mud and lots of it’ rather than ‘there are many instances
of mud’.
Turning to the concerns of the present chapter, we adopt the suggestion made in
the same work for mass nouns, that a [+singular] number specification acts as a
type-shifting device (e, t, e) shifting basic NP denotations (properties) to entities
(kinds). There are two comments to make here about this proposal. First, although
Tsoulas’ () analysis specifically suggests that the type shifting in question is one
between properties and kinds, and, as a result, in the context of that work Num was
essentially identified with ∩ , we can question the necessity of this association. As is
well known, there is a variety of functions that express the relations between the e, t
and e domains (Partee ). If we assume that e is the argumental type, it is
conceivable that the output of the type-shifting function will not necessarily be a kind.
A host of thorny technical, formal, and empirical issues arise at this point which we
cannot address in any degree of satisfactory detail here. The main issue is whether
Num is a unique functor or an ambiguous one which e.g. on one occasion maps a
property to its entity correlate (typically a kind) and on another maps a property to
an individual that instantiates it (a choice function), and on yet a third occasion maps
a property to the prototypical individual if the property (concept) in question has
a prototype, and so on. If that is the case, what determines the type of function
that we have? We will not pursue this issue further here in detail. Note, though, that
it is precisely this flexibility in the mapping that allows the type-shifting properties
of number not to get in the way of ordinary composition—i.e. not every predicate
is, nor has to be, a predicate of entity correlates of properties (kinds or whatever
your favourite ontology wants them to be). Sometimes they will have to be just plain
individuals.
One might pursue a formalization of this in terms of the concept of a reified implicature proposed, in
Second, there appears to be no a priori reason not to generalize this idea beyond
mass nouns and propose that, in addition to its type-shifting properties, which is a
general property of number, the singular triggers an atomicity implicature, just as the
plural triggers a multiplicity/quantity one.
This set of assumptions provides semantic content to the hypothesis that Num is
an argumentizing head, which in the first part of the chapter was argued for from a
syntactic point of view. As we saw above, a number of comparative advantages flow
from this proposal when Greek is considered alongside Italian. The semantic proposal
here completes the account elegantly if we can show its feasibility. Within this system,
let us consider first the neutral case in an example like ().
() Mpikan kleftes ke sikosan ta pada.
broke in.pl burglars and lifted.pl the all
‘Burglars broke in and took everything.’
The bare plural kleftes will still denote pluralities of thieves since, regardless of type
shifting, the implicature remains and rules out a singular reading. Similarly, in cases
of the bare singular like (), a single plumber (rather than a team thereof) will do as
is expected.
() Psahno idravliko.
look for.sg plumber
‘I am looking for a plumber.’
It should be noted that these are defaults that can be overridden in context; we take this
to be a particular strength of the account. For example, consider a situation where the
speaker explains to the hearer the need to install a new alarm system (in the hearer’s
house). In this case the speaker may use either a bare singular or plural:
() Me afto to sinagermo dhen beni/benoun kleftis/kleftes me
with this the alarm neg enter.sg/enter.pl burglar/burglar(s) with
kanena tropo.
no way
‘With this alarm there is no way burglars will be able to enter.’
The speaker in this case is not committed to the fact that, in the case of the singular,
a thief operating alone will not be able to enter, implying that a gang of thieves might
actually succeed, and she is not committed, by using the plural, that a gang of thieves
will not manage to enter but a lone burglar might just be able to sneak in. The speaker is
indifferent to the internal composition of the thieving party. As we showed in section
.., bare nouns in Greek are not number-neutral. What happens then in the case
in ()? Under our account, the reason for the apparent number neutrality is that
the context renders the implicature inoperative, and as a result number only fulfils its
argumentizing/type-shifting function.
Alexopoulou, Folli, and Tsoulas
catures are neutralized (or cancelled). Such examples then should be possible only
when contextually relevant factors either force the neutralization of the implicature
or, equivalently, allow the speaker to choose not to reify the relevant implicatures.
The case of coordinated nouns (), repeated in (), is a case in point:
() a. Dinosavri ke tiranosavri ehoun eksafanisti edo kai
dinosaurs.nom and tyrannosaurs.nom have.pl disappeared here and
ekatomiria xronia.
millions years
‘Dinosaurs and tyrannosaurs disappeared millions of years ago.’
b. (Karharies kai) falenes spanizoun sto Saroniko.
sharks.nom and whales.nom are rare in the Saronic
‘Sharks and whales are rare in the Saronic Gulf.’
It has been suggested to us (N. Katsos, p.c.) that these are better as answers to ques-
tions of the type Do you have/Are there whales and sharks in the Saronic Gulf? The
introduction of whales and sharks into the question is probably a relevant factor that
opens the possibility of not reifying the implicatures (the speaker is indifferent to the
quantities), which results in kind reference.
Much further work is undoubtedly needed in order to disentangle the various
factors that influence the reification of such implicatures.
The reasoning above leads us to the following picture. Noting the crosslinguistic
connection between kind reference and nominal bareness we have reached the follow-
ing conclusions for Greek: first, determinerless number phrases may be type-shifted
but carry multiplicity/atomicity implicatures that must be neutralized for the bare
NumP to denote a kind. When these implicatures are neutralized, bare nouns can refer
to kinds, as examples like () show. When this is not the case, the definite article with
its maximal/universal quantificational force must be used. Interestingly, in the case of
a definite singular, we are led to the conclusion that it names a kind, whereas in the
case of a definite plural it denotes a maximal collection of individuals, which is another
way to get to the kind.
The NMP governs form–meaning mappings but—to put it simply, almost too
simply—leaves us with the question of where exactly these settings are recorded in
the system. The NMP is not associated with any specific functional head. What view
of parameters countenances this type of setting and how? These are issues that prevent
linguists, at least of a certain persuasion (which we largely share), from allowing the
NMP full status as a parameter. We would like to close this chapter with some very
speculative remarks about how the theory developed here may help reformulate the
NMP in a way that would make it a parameter along the lines of the Borer–Chomsky
Conjecture. Our suggestion is rather simple, assuming the universal DP structure in
(), repeated in ().
() DP
D NumP
Num …
NP
One may suggest that what is actually parametrized is the content of Num. For con-
creteness, and leaving other features aside, we have:
() ±RefCard
Num =
±TypeShift
where RefCard denotes the basic semantic value of number, which we take to be
[±singular], and TypeShift is the ability of Num to be the argumentizing head (its
D-like property). This gives us the following possibilities:
⎡ ⎤
() +RefCard, +TypeShift
⎢ +RefCard, −TypeShift ⎥
Num = ⎢ ⎣ −RefCard, +TypeShift ⎦
⎥
−RefCard, −TypeShift
Roughly speaking, this produces the following typology:
[+RefCard, +TypeShift] As we showed in the the rest of this chapter, this case is
exemplified by Greek, where Num both argumentizes the lexical noun and also
provides information regarding referential cardinality, as evidenced by the lack in
general of nouns to give number-neutral readings.
[+RefCard, −TypeShift] This is the case of Italian, and Romance languages in
general, where D is required for NPs to function as arguments.
Bare Number
[−RefCard, +TypeShift] This is the case of Chinese and similar languages, where
Num shifts always to e but the noun remains number-neutral. The familiar pat-
terns (classifier systems etc.) follow.
[−RefCard, −TypeShift] Unlike the original Nominal Mapping Parameter, in this
formulation two negative values are not excluded. A language where nouns are
always number-neutral and Num does not have the type-shifting function would
be very similar but not quite identical to English.
If the approach outlined above can be maintained—and a lot of further work is
required to demonstrate that—we will have a reformulation of the NMP in terms of
the properties of number which looks much more like other parameters. We will now
leave these speculative remarks as exactly that, speculative, hoping to return to them
in future work.
. Conclusion
In this chapter we tried to probe a little further into the typology entailed by Chier-
chia’s () Nominal Mapping Parameter, focusing on subtle differences within
rather than across the language types defined by the parameter. We discovered that
the general classification can be maintained to a large extent in the face of data from
the distribution of bare nouns in Greek when contrasted with Italian. We argued that
Greek lacks a null D but that the function of D is played by Number. We further
argued that the locus of variation between Greek and Italian is the choice of the
argumentizing head, Num in the case of Greek, D in Italian. The proposal accounts for
a number of empirical contrasts between the two languages that are directly linked to
the availability of bare nouns: the availability of CLLD for indefinite topics, Indefinite
Argument Drop, and bare subnominal deletion.
The variation we postulate between Greek and Italian provides a promising way to
understand a range of unexpected crosslinguistic contrasts. But at the same time it
raises a number of questions about the nature of the syntax–semantics interface. If
languages can vary in the choice of their argumentizer, what is the range of possible
argumentizing heads? How is this choice constrained? In other words, what makes a
‘good’ argumentizer and what blocks a less good one? These questions are particularly
pressing for our case, Greek, which has a definite article but, evidently, freely allows
number phrases to act as arguments. Conversely, if Greek can build arguments out of
number phrases, why does Italian need additional functional structure, namely D? In
other words, why is Greek different from Italian if they are parametrically set alike?
We have here identified the locus of their variation. We still need to understand why
this variation arises.
. Introduction
Our chapter is embedded within a broader theoretical debate concerning the status
of resumption at the interfaces. Two opposing views have been put forward.
According to the view popularized by Pesetsky (), resumption is a purely
PF phenomenon: all there is in the narrow syntax is a copy of the moved DP. The
resumptive clitic is the result of partial pronunciation of this copy that takes place in
a post-syntactic component.
According to the view maintained by Boeckx (a, ), resumption is present
in the narrow syntax in the form of a clitic which doubles the moved DP. To phrase it
differently, resumption and clitic doubling are reduced to the same input (for Greek,
see Alexiadou and Anagnostopoulou , and Alexiadou and Varlokosta ).
In this chapter, we aim to contribute to this discussion by focusing on obligatory
resumption (mainly on resumption of indirect objects (IOs)) in Greek free relatives
(FRs), and in Greek restrictive relatives introduced by the complementizer pu ‘that’
(pu-RRs). These constructions are exemplified in (a) and (b), respectively:
() a. Ghnórisa ópjon ∗ (tu) édhosan tin ipotrofía.
met.sg who.sg.m.acc *(cl.sg.m.gen gave.pl the scholarship.acc
‘I met whoever they gave the scholarship to.’
b. Ghnórisa ton mathití pu ∗ (tu) édhosan tin ipotrofía.
met.sg the student.acc that *(cl.sg.m.gen gave.pl the scholarship.acc
‘I met the student that they gave the scholarship to.’
∗ For helpful comments and discussion at different stages of this work, we would like to thank Ian
Roberts, Sabine Iatridou, and Dimitris Michelioudakis, as well as the audiences of the Athens Reading
Group ( June ), the rd Mediterranean Syntax Meeting (– October ), and OnLI II (the nd
conference on Linguistic Interfaces, – December ). Moreover, we would like to thank an anonymous
reviewer for valuable comments. Remaining errors are, of course, our own.
Obligatory Resumption in Greek Relatives
sg – mu me
sg – su se
sg.m tos tu ton(e)
sg.f ti tis ti(n)(e)
sg.neut to to to
pl – mas mas
pl – sas sas
pl.acc ti tus tus
pl.fem tes tus tis/(tes)
pl.neut ta tus ta
of the fact that enclisis in Greek occurs exclusively in root contexts (i) (on the properties of enclisis in Greek,
see Mavrogiorgos : ch. , Terzi ).
(i) Dhos tu tu Kosta tin ipotrofia.
give.sg.imp cl.sg.m.gen the Kostas.gen the scholarship.acc
‘Give Kostas the scholarship.’
Obligatory Resumption in Greek Relatives
The pattern is repeated in () with IO resumptives in FRs, and in () with IO
resumptives in pu-RRs.
() a. ∗ Ópju échun (ídhi) tu dhósi ipotrofía.
who.sg.m.gen have.pl (already cl.sg.m.gen given scholarship.acc
‘Whoever they have (already) given a scholarship to.’
b. Ópju tu échun (ídhi) dhósi ipotrofía.
who.sg.m.gen cl.sg.m.gen have.pl (already given scholarship.acc
‘Whoever they have (already) given a scholarship to.’
() a. ∗ Tu mathití pu échun (ídhi) tu dhósi
the student.gen that have.pl (already cl.sg.m.gen given
ipotrofía.
scholarship.acc
‘The student that they have (already) given a scholarship to.’
b. Tu mathití pu tu échun (ídhi) dhósi ipotrofía.
the student.gen that cl.sg.m.gen have.pl (already given scholarship.acc
‘The student that they have (already) given a scholarship to.’
Resumptive placement, therefore, provides us with the first counterargument to a
purely PF account of resumption. If the resumptive clitic realized the case and phi-
feature substructure of the lower copy of movement, the question that would have to
be addressed is how it would reach its preverbal position. Introducing verb and/or
clitic movement to the PF component could derive the right serialization. However,
it would depart from the well-motivated claim that head movement is a narrow syn-
tactic phenomenon (arguments for the narrow syntactic status of head movement are
provided in Lechner and Roberts ; for Greek clitic movement as syntactic
movement see Anagnostopoulou b, Mavrogiorgos , and references therein).
(ii) Sensitivity to the selecting predicate. To proceed to the evidence from selection,
it can be shown that IO resumptives, like IO doubling clitics, are sensitive to the
subcategorization properties of the selecting predicate.
That doubling clitics are sensitive to the selecting predicate is shown in (). As
pointed out in Anagnostopoulou (b: fn. ), a restricted set of verbal predicates,
including epofelúme ‘to take advantage of ’, proighúme ‘to precede’, proedhrévo ‘to pre-
side over’, proipárcho ‘to pre-exist’, and iperischío ‘to prevail’ do not allow cliticization,
or clitic doubling of their (Genitive) DP complements.
() a. Iperischíi tu simathití tu.
prevails.sg the classmate.gen his
‘He prevails over his classmate.’
Obligatory Resumption in Greek Relatives
b. ∗ Tu iperischíi.
cl.sg.m.gen prevails.sg
‘He prevails over him.’
c. ∗ Tu iperischíi tu simathití tu.
cl.sg.m.gen prevail.sg the classmate.gen his
‘He prevails over his classmate.’
Significantly, the exact same predicates do not allow resumption of their complements
(see () for resumption in FRs, and () for resumption in pu-RRs).
() ∗ Lipíthika ópjon tu iperíschises.
felt sorry.sg who.sg.m.acc cl.sg.m.gen prevailed.sg
Intended meaning: ‘I felt sorry for the person you prevailed over.’
() ∗ Lipíthika ton mathití pu tu iperíschises.
felt sorry.sg the student.acc that cl.sg.m.gen prevailed.sg
Intended meaning: ‘I felt sorry for the student that you prevailed over.’
The sensitivity to the subcategorization properties of the selecting predicate provides
us with an additional counterargument to a strictly PF account of resumption. If
obligatory resumption in FRs did not have a narrow syntactic existence, we wouldn’t
expect it to show any sensitivity to the properties of the selecting predicate.
(iii) Weak Cross Over (WCO). The same conclusion is supported by the interference
of resumption with binding phenomena, such as WCO.
As reported in the literature, IO doubling clitics cancel WCO violations. Thus, in
(a), the IO tu káthe pedhjú ‘every child’ cannot bind the pronominal variable inside
the subject i mitéra tu ‘his mother’ (Anagnostopoulou b). In the presence of an
IO doubling clitic, though, the bound variable reading becomes an option (b).
() a. I mitéra tu??i/j édhose tu káthe pedhjúi fajitó.
the mother.nom his gave.sg the every child.gen food.acc
‘His??i/j mother gave [every child]i food.’
b. I mitéra tui/j tui édhose tu káthe pedhjúi fajitó.
the mother.nom his cl.sg.m.gen gave.sg the every child.gen food.acc
(Anagnostopoulou b: )
Significantly for our purposes, the same effect can be replicated with IO resumptives
in free () and restrictive relatives (). Thus, in (a) and in (a), the pronominal
tu within the subject DP i adherfí tu ‘his sister’ cannot be bound by the fronted IO. In
(b) and (b), on the other hand, resumption of the IO renders the bound variable
construal of the pronominal possible.
Because for some speakers IO resumptives are always obligatory in FRs and in pu-RRs, we repeat the
For instance, in Anagnostopoulou’s (b: –) terms, the genitive of IOs is ‘non-structural’, because,
even though it is theta-related and it does not enter into case alternations, it may be freely subject to clitic
doubling. What is crucial for our purposes is that the genitive in question is theta-related, and consequently
of relevance to LF.
See also N. Richards (), who makes the same assumption in order to account for case stacking in
Lardil.
Our assumptions concerning the technical implementation of case alternations will be set out in the
next section.
Of course, this does not preclude the possibility that obligatory resumption satisfies a non-case-related
requirement, such as the circumvention of intervention effects. Such examples were discussed in section
...
Obligatory Resumption in Greek Relatives
which the case required by the matrix is the same as the case required by the relative
predicate (), (b) interrogatives (), and (c) RRs introduced by the inflected relative
pronoun o opíos () (on the optionality of IO resumption in these constructions, see
Alexopoulou b).
() a. Tilefónisa ópju ?(tu) édhosan tin ipotrofía.
phoned.sg who.sg.m.gen ?(cl.sg.m.gen gave.pl the scholarship.acc
‘I phoned whoever they gave the scholarship to.’
b. Tilefónisa tu mathití pu ?(tu) édhosan tin
phoned.sg the student.gen that ?(cl.sg.m.gen gave.pl the
ipotrofía.
scholarship.acc
‘I phoned the student that they gave the scholarship to.’
It should be clarified that, whereas case considerations explain why DO resumptives are unnecessary
in FRs and in pu-RRs, they do not explain why they are impossible. A possibility worth exploring is that the
illicitness of DO resumptives relates to the fact that, unlike their IO counterparts, they are only compatible
with D-Linked antecedents (see Kotzoglou and Varlokosta ). This line of approach correctly predicts
that, in examples such as (i), where the antecedent is interpreted as presupposed in the discourse, DO
resumptives are rendered grammatical.
(i) Pjon mathiti tis Irinis su sistisan?
which student the Irene.gen you.gen introduced.pl
Mu sistisan to mathiti tis Irinis pu (ton) epenesan stin akadhimía
me.gen introduced.pl the student.acc the Irene.gen that (him praised.pl in.the academy
‘Which of Irene’s students did they introduce to you? They introduced to me Irene’s student that they
praised in the Academy.’ (Kotzoglou and Varlokosta : )
As we will suggest in the following section, the observed contrast between DO and IO (resumptive) clitics
could be captured by assuming that these two types of clitic have a different featural content: whereas DO
(resumptive) clitics are positively marked with respect to a topicality feature [+topicality], IO (resumptive)
clitics are underspecified [±topicality].
Daskalaki and Mavrogiorgos
Proclitic ✓ ✓
Sensitivity to the ✓ ✓
selecting predicate
Intervention effects ✓ ✓
Obviation of WCO ✓ ✓
Obligatory Resumption in Greek Relatives
.. Assumptions
Our account is developed within Kayne’s () raising analysis of relativization,
according to which the relative CP is the complement of an external D head (for
Greek, see Alexiadou and Anagnostopoulou , Alexiadou and Varlokosta ,
and Alexopoulou a). Within this framework, we further make the following three
assumptions.
... The IO object moves to its surface position First, we assume that the resumed
IO moves to its surface position. Movement is an integral part of any raising analysis
of relative clause formation. Its application in Greek resumptive relatives is justified
by the fact that resumptives in Greek, unlike resumptives in Semitic languages, are
sensitive to strong islands, as shown in () and () (Alexopoulou b). The
interference of IO resumptives with WCO, and intervention effects (section ..),
which at first glance poses a problem for an A -movement analysis, will be discussed
in section ...
() a. ∗ Sinándisa ópjon éfijes afú tu édhoses tin
met.sg who.sg.m.acc left.sg after cl.sg.m.gen gave.sg the
prosklisi.
invitation.acc
‘I met whoever you left after you gave them the invitation.’
(Adjunct Island)
Our account builds on Mavrogiorgos’ () analysis of IO cliticization/clitic doubling (based on
Anagnostopoulou b). Note that any other account that captures the construction of an A-chain
between the doubled DP and the clitic (such as that of Anagnostopoulou b, which involves movement
of features to the cliticization position, or that of Roberts , which does not involve movement at all but
assumes the building of an Agreement chain) would be fine in principle, although there must be a device
present ensuring that the deletion and respecification of the case feature on the doubled DP is possible.
Daskalaki and Mavrogiorgos
... The IO object moves from [Spec, vAPPL ] Second, we assume that the input to
relativization is a double object construction (Daskalaki ) rather than a preposi-
tional ditransitive (Alexiadou and Anagnostopoulou ). Our assumption is based
on the observation that the relativized IO in Greek has to be animate (), patterning
in this respect with DP goals (a) rather than with prepositional goals (b) (for a
detailed discussion of the two options, see Daskalaki ).
() a. ∗ Episkéftika ópja chóra tis éstila etísis.
visited.sg which country cl.sg.f.gen sent.sg applications
Lit.: ‘I visited whichever country I sent it applications.’
b. ∗ Episkéftika ti chóra pu tis éstila etísis.
visited.sg the country that cl.sg.f.gen sent.sg applications
Lit.: ‘I visited the country that I sent it applications.’
... The relativized argument can have its case altered Third, in order to account
for the observation that relativized arguments always surface with the case required by
the matrix predicate, we will assume that arguments may have their case altered in the
course of the derivation (different implementations of case alternations can be found
in Daskalaki , for A -chains, in Merchant a, Béjar and Massam ,
and Fujii for A-chains, and in N. Richards for case stacking phenomena).
Specifically, we will assume that relativized arguments bearing structural case may
have their case value deleted and respecified under Agree/concord with the external
D. Deletion of genitive, on the other hand, converges only when the matrix predicate
is also subcategorized for genitive (), or when genitive is retained on a resump-
tive/doubling clitic (a). This is because, as discussed in section .., genitive is
interpretable and, consequently, relevant for the theta interpretation of the relativized
argument at LF.
A question that arises at this point is why it is possible for genitive to delete from the lower copy of the
IO but not from its doubling/resumptive clitic. We believe this can be taken to follow from the fact that in
our account the IO and its resumptive/doubling clitic constitute two distinct syntactic objects. Alternatively,
we could assume that case is assigned to the clitic, and that the IO moves before case percolation takes place.
Regarding examples such as (), a reviewer asks how the externally assigned genitive instructs LF
to assign the relativized argument its internally required theta-role. Under the view that the genitive of
IOs and of objects of verbs of communication is associated with the same general theta-role (goal), the
interpretation of the relativized argument shouldn’t be a problem.
This particular proposal for clitic doubling could be related to the observed phenomenon that clitics
in Greek cannot double bare nouns, although they may double quantifiers (including indefinites) under
certain conditions (e.g. D-linking). This restriction on doubling would be explained if bare nouns and
(some) indefinites are not DPs (see Alexopoulou, Folli, and Tsoulas, Ch. above), assuming that the D
head may only c-select a D-type complement.
Daskalaki and Mavrogiorgos
() D P
D D P
D NP
Step : Subsequently, the derived D PIO is merged in [Spec, vAPPL ] and it gets
both case and theta marked by the vAPPL head. The latter, we assume, has
interpretable phi-features and genitive case. Assignment of genitive case
does not render the D PIO inactive (see Anagnostopoulou b), which
accounts for why it agrees with v∗ in phi-features.
Step : After case assignment, the IO clitic (i.e. D ) incorporates into vAPPL . Fol-
lowing Roberts (), we will be assuming that incorporation is a syntactic
operation that is subject to the subset principle, according to which the
incorporee must constitute a proper subset of the features on the incorpo-
rator. In this particular case, if we assume that the clitic pronoun contains
phi-features, a D-feature, and Case (pace Roberts ), the vAPPL head
must contain at least these features in order for incorporation to take place.
Although PCC effects might suggest that the phi-features that are found on
the resumptive clitic are distributed among the vAPPL head and the v∗ -head
(see Step below), we could either assume that a token of a feature type (in
this case number on vAPPL ) would license incorporation of a constituent
containing phi-features, or alternatively that the clitic incorporates into the
v∗ –vAPPL complex (which contains all the tokens of the features found on
the clitic). The latter alternative would be possible in Roberts’s system, as
incorporation is contingent on Agree, and according to our analysis the
resumptive clitic agrees with both the vAPPL head and the v∗ -head.
Step : v∗ is merged. It probes the incorporated IO clitic and checks its person
features (based on proposals by Anagnostopoulou b for the PCC. For
a discussion and alternatives see Michelioudakis ). The incorporated
clitic moves along with vAPPL to v∗ , forming an A-chain between the clitic
and the D PIO in situ (see Anagnostopoulou b, and references therein).
Step : After T is merged, the IO clitic, which has incorporated into vAPPL , moves
along with vAPPL to T. The head of the A-chain is now in T.
Step : The D PIO is A -moved from the derived A-position in T to the specifier
of CP. Specifically, D PIO is probed in the TP domain because it is linked
to the clitic in T. Furthermore, it gets probed by the C-head because, being
headed by a relative pronoun, it bears a wh-feature.
An issue that arises at this point is why the C head probes the D P
IO substructure, rather than the
higher D P. The latter option would result in both the clitic and the IO being attracted to C. In order to avoid
this result, we can either assume that the wh-feature does not percolate to the higher D , or that movement
Obligatory Resumption in Greek Relatives
Step : The relative CP merges with an external D, which is eventually case marked
by the matrix predicate. The fronted D PIO has its case re specified through
concord with the external D.
Step : Finally, at LF the genitive-marked IO clitic is interpreted as the goal argu-
ment of the relative predicate, and so is the fronted D P through co-
reference.
A schematic summary of the suggested derivation is provided in ():
() DP case respecification by matrix predicate
D CP
DP
FR pronouni C⬘
C TP
T⬘
A⬘ -chain clIO–V–vAPPL–v∗–T
v∗ P
tui edhosan
pro v∗⬘
vAPPLP
(clIO–V–vAPPL–v∗)
Spec
A-chain
DPIO vAPPL⬘
(FR pronouni)
(vAPPL–clIO) VP
DPDO
(V)
tin ipotrofía
case assignment/
clitic incorporation
(Step ) (in Greek, as in other null subject languages, the verb (parts) move(s) to T
obligatorily—see Alexiadou and Anagnostopoulou ).
(ii) Selection. The sensitivity of IO clitics to the selecting predicate can be explained if
we assume that the verbs which do not allow for an IO resumptive/doubling clitic do
not have a vAPPL head. Rather, they have a genitive DP that is licensed by a V-head by
theta-relation. We assume that both the theta-role and the genitive case are assigned
by such V-related parts such as prepositions: e.g. iper (cf. ipertero tinos/iperischio
tinos).
(iii) WCO. The cancellation of WCO in the presence of IO clitics follows from the fact
that the IO clitic has moved to T, forming an A-chain with the D PIO (see Anagnos-
topoulou b). As a result of this, the D PIO is interpreted in the T position, which
is higher than the subject position (assuming that the subject is reconstructed to the
base Spec,vP position). A -movement of the D PIO starts off from this higher, derived
position, ensuring that no variable appears below the subject. By way of illustration,
consider the derivation of an example such as (b), which we give in ().
() DP case respecification by matrix predicate
D CP
DP
C⬘
FR pronouni
C TP
T⬘
A⬘ -chain clIO–V–vAPPL–v∗–T
tui edhose v∗P
DPSUB
i adhelfi tui v∗⬘
v∗
vAPPLP
(clIO–V–vAPPL–v∗)
Spec
A-chain
DPIO vAPPL⬘
(FR pronouni)
(vAPPL–clIO) VP
(edhose)fajitó
case assignment/
clitic incorporation
Obligatory Resumption in Greek Relatives
of grammatical notions. For example, the treatment of inherent case in this chapter
suggests that case cannot be analysed as a purely PF phenomenon across all construc-
tions, against what has been standardly assumed in the literature (e.g. Distributed
Morphology). Moreover, the current model of the narrow syntactic component and
its connection to the interfaces is put to the test by the data of IO resumption: can
the two interfaces communicate with each other or not, and why? In our analysis we
kept the traditional grammar model intact and tried to derive the facts by positing the
requirement that LF-related narrow syntactic features must survive until LF. However,
other plausible grammar models could derive the same results in different ways. We
think that our current knowledge of the interfaces and the evidence we have from
obligatory resumption cannot distinguish between such grammar models, so further
research is needed in order to decide which model is the right one.
Ethical Datives
A Puzzle for Syntax, Semantics, Pragmatics,
and their Interfaces∗
DIM I T R I S M IC H E L IOU DA K I S A N D E L E N I KA P O G IA N N I
. Introduction
In this chapter we examine ethical datives as a case study of issues such as (a) the way
syntax provides input to semantics and in turn to pragmatics, specifying (part of) its
well-formedness/felicity conditions and, conversely, (b) the way in which pragmatics
filters, evaluates and/or modulates the syntactic/LF output. For the purposes of this
chapter, we define ethical datives (henceforth EDs) as those (usually weak/clitic)
pronominal forms that have no effect on the truth-conditions of the event and can
thus be contrasted to all other types of dative argument which are realized by similar
pronominal forms: indirect object (IO) (goal) datives, different kinds of benefac-
tive/malefactive arguments, dative experiencers, external possessors, etc.
The two defining properties of EDs which are most relevant for our discussion are
the following: (i) they necessarily refer to a discourse participant; either the speaker
(when first person), the hearer (when second person), or a reported speaker (when
third person); (ii) being entirely optional and non-truth-functional, they denote some
kind of (non-truth-evaluable) relation between a discourse participant, i.e. the ref-
erent of the ED, and the described event. In languages such as Greek and Spanish
(()–()), this turns out to be an evaluative attitude of a discourse participant towards
an event of which he or she does not form part (neither as an agent nor as being
actually involved in it, exhibiting various degrees of affectedness). In other languages,
non-truth-functional pronominal forms may encode other types of relation between
∗ We would like to thank Elena Anagnostopoulou, Kasia Jaszczolt, Ian Roberts, Ioanna Sitaridou, and
two anonymous reviewers for useful comments and discussion, as well as the audience and the organizers
of OnLI II. All errors are our own.
Michelioudakis and Kapogianni
a participant and an event or a proposition (e.g. evidentiality: see Speas and Tenny
, Arsenijević ).
() ¡Me ensucias tu pantalón!
sg.dat.cl dirt.sg your trousers
‘To my disappointment, you are dirtying your trousers!’ (Peruvian Spanish)
() ¡Que buena se nos puso Maria!
how nice refl pl.dat.cl became Maria
‘How nice Maria became, to our delight!’ (Spanish)
() Pos mu megalosan etsi ta pedhakia su!
how sg.dat.cl grew.pl so much the children.dim your
‘How much did your little children grow, to my delight!’ (Greek)
() I Maria ine kali kopela, ala mu psifizi LAOS.
the Mary is nice girl but sg.dat.cl votes LAOS
‘Mary is a nice girl, but, to my disappointment, she votes for the Nationalist
Party.’ (Greek)
Exploring the well-formedness conditions of constructions with EDs, it turns out that
there is probably more syntax to them than one would assume based on their appar-
ently high degree of optionality and underdeterminacy/underspecification. First, the
requirement that ethical datives refer to discourse participants is in fact subject to
crosslinguistic variation (languages with speaker-oriented EDs vs. languages with
addressee-oriented EDs vs. languages with [+Participant]-oriented EDs, with the
latter either including or excluding logophoric third person). As such, the orientation
of EDs in each language seems to correlate with the kind and the strength of the
Person Case Constraint (PCC) effects (see Bonet ) that arise in combinations of
EDs with direct object (DO) clitics or even other dative clitics. If this requirement is
syntactically encoded, it can further form the basis of a fairly straightforward account
of several other structural properties (e.g. no DP in A-position, no wh-movement, etc.,
see section ..). Secondly, the interpretive similarities between EDs and expres-
sions associated with CP-projections like EvalP may correlate with the exceptional
binding behaviour of the former.
We further discuss issues of meaning derivation and compositionality, and we
claim that it is not likely that a syntactically encoded expression may lack any
encoded meaning whatsoever; despite their intrinsic context-dependent polysemy,
using Grice’s criterion of cancellability we show EDs to always encode an irreducible
non-cancellable content, namely an underspecified evaluative attitude. Further evi-
dence from purely pragmatic functions of the EDs, such as their ironic exploita-
tion, will strengthen the hypothesis concerning their detachment from the truth-
See also Horn () for a related construction in English, e.g. ‘I love me some him’.
Ethical Datives
conditional content (sensu stricto) of the sentence and their role as evaluative ancillary
propositions which take scope over the event described in the sentence.
. Ethical Datives are a Class of their Own: Grammar and Meaning
.. Syntax
Despite the apparent diversity in the potential interpretation of EDs (their referent can
be delighted/disappointed/surprised/disapproving/caring, etc.), they clearly form one
syntactic class and can be differentiated as a whole from all other sorts of dative, on the
basis of a number of criteria. On the semantics side, as already implied, the crucial
dividing line is not the one between s-selected (goals, sources, and experiencers of
piacere-type predicates) and non-s-selected datives (benefactives, malefactives, EDs,
etc.), but rather the one between datives that contribute to the truth-conditions of the
event and those that do not. For instance, ()–() are all pairs of propositions that can-
not both be describing the same state of affairs, and in ()–() in particular they cannot
both be true at the same time, assuming that the subject and the object in the (a)
examples are coreferential with the respective XPs in the (b) examples. (a) and (b)
can both be true, but they do not have to be. On the other hand, (a) and (b) can
both be uttered felicitously to describe the same state of affairs without contradicting
each other; on the contrary, if one of the two is negated, then it entails the falsity of
the other.
() a. Mu dhini ena kapelo.
me.dat.cl gives a hat
‘He is giving me a hat.’ (Goal)
b. Su dhini ena kapelo.
you.dat.cl gives a hat
‘He is giving you a hat.’
() a. Mu pleni ena kapelo.
me.dat.cl washes a hat
‘He is washing a hat for me/washing me a hat.’
(Potential recipient benefactive)
For the purposes of this discussion, we assume a typology of datives such as the one found in Miche-
lioudakis (), who builds on distinctions previously made by Pylkkänen (), Cuervo (), Boneh
and Nash (, ), Bosse, Bruening, and Yamada (): (a) canonical indirect object (IO) dative
DPs, i.e. goals (or sources, for a restricted number of predicates); (b) IO-like benefactive dative DPs, i.e. the
equivalents of for-PPs, with buy- or creation/change of state predicates, with a potential recipient reading; (c)
IO-like malefactives, i.e. DP counterparts of adversatively affected on-PPs, with predicates of destruction
or other causative predicates; (d) ‘free’ benefactives/malefactives, with no recipient/possessor entailments;
(e) dative experiencers of piacere-type predicates; (f) external possessor (unaffected) datives, in languages
such as French and Hebrew; (g) ethical datives.
Also assuming that, under standard Gricean considerations (cf. the maxim of quantity), me implicates
... Restrictions on full DPs EDs are always pronominal; in particular, in Greek
and Romance they are exclusively realized as clitics and no (coindexed) XP can appear
in an A-position (cf. also Cuervo and Roberge and Troberg ), although
Ethical Datives
clitic (both first/second person and third person), only allowing for clitic clusters with third person
accusative clitics. The weak PCC, on the other hand, only excludes first/second person direct object clitics
in the presence of third person dative clitics, thus also allowing for clitic clusters with first/second person
dative clitics and first/second person direct object clitics, i.e. dat–acc and dat–acc combinations,
alongside dat–acc, dat–acc, and dat-acc ones.
Ethical Datives
course participant, usually a reported speaker (as clearly illustrated with the contrast
between (b) and (c)). Given this restriction, we conclude that EDs are neces-
sarily [+Participant], taking this to subsume both author/addressee indexicals and
logophoric pronouns.
() a. Sinandisa / milisa me to Janii . Tui/∗k arostise i Maria.
met.sg spoke.sg with the John him.ED.cl fell ill.sg the Mary.nom
‘I bumped into Johni . Mary fell ill on himi/∗k .’ (ED)
b. I Mariai paraponjete pu dhen tisi/∗k meletai o Janis.
the Mary complains that not her.ED.cl studies the John.nom
‘Mary complains that, to her regret, John does not study enough.’ (ED)
c. I Mariai paraponjete pu dhen tisi/k edhosan to vravio.
the Mary.nom complains that not sg.f.dat.cl gave.pl the prize
‘Maryi complains that they did not award the prize to heri/k ’ (IO)
Therefore, we propose that EDs are introduced by a specialized high Applicative
head (), which carries an uninterpretable [+Participant] feature, construed as in
Adger and Harbour (), higher than the high applicatives that introduce recip-
ients/benefactives etc. (see Cuervo on this possibility), with which EDs can
cooccur. This can account for all the properties discussed in this and the previous
sections.
To begin with, the postulation of a [+Participant] probe straightforwardly cap-
tures the PCC effects in ED–DO and ED–dative clitic combinations. If we adopt an
approach to the PCC along the lines of Adger and Harbour (), a head with such a
feature specification should block any lower arguments with this feature specification,
allowing only for third person DOs, which are not specified for [±Participant] at all,
and third person IOs, which are specified as [−Participant] (as in Adger and Harbour
and Anagnostopoulou b, ).
Thus, () represents a transitive predicate phrase in Greek with potentially three
clitics: (a) an ED clitic which is necessarily specified as [+Participant] as required
by its probe, i.e. an uninterpretable but partially specified [+Participant, uAuthor]
feature bundle on ApplED ; (b) an IO clitic which can only be [−Participant], i.e., non-
logophoric third person dative pronouns, but not [+Participant], i.e. a first/second
person, in the context of an ED, as such features in the Agree domain of ApplED would
We are following here Béjar’s () proposal that syntactic heads can also be generated with fully or
partly specified uninterpretable features (see also McGinnis : ); i.e. an uninterpretable feature may
enter the derivation either completely unvalued or partially valued.
Third person datives, being necessarily affected and semantically animate, i.e. capable of conscious
experience, are always specified for the [Participant] feature, albeit as [−], which differentiates them from
first/second person expressions, i.e. discourse [+] participants; third person accusatives on the other hand
lack such entailments, therefore they may be totally unspecified for this feature and lack it completely (both
of these assumptions are also shared by Adger and Harbour’s , and Anagnostopoulou’s b, ,
accounts of the PCC).
Michelioudakis and Kapogianni
pre-empt valuation of the [+Participant] probe by the ED; and (c) a DO clitic, which
can only be third person, i.e. not specified for [±Participant]; any other specification is
disallowed in the Agree domain of either a [uParticipant] ApplIO or a [+Participant]
ApplED .
() ApplEDP
ED ApplED⬘
¸[+Participant]
ApplED ApplIOP
[+Participant]
IO ApplIO⬘
[+Participant](∗/ED—)
¸[−Participant]
ApplIO VP
[uParticipant]
V DO
∗[+Participant]
¸Person:3, no[±Participant]
As for the fact that EDs can only be clitics/weak pronouns, it should be borne in mind
that no descriptions (DPs) or (other) quantified phrases qualify as [+Participant],
although the latter may contain [+Participant] expressions; we assume that this fea-
ture is borne by D and is not projected up to QP. Only personal pronouns then
count as possible goals for [±Participant] probes. This generalization, combined
with the fact that dative personal pronouns tend to cliticize obligatorily, in Greek
and most Romance languages among others, derives the apparent restriction to cli-
tics/weak pronouns. Therefore, only dative clitics can be merged in Spec,ApplED in
the first place, which also explains the ban on PP alternants/substitutes, true clitic
doubling, etc.
This also seems to account for the unavailability of wh-movement. Wh-phrases,
which are arguably quantified phrases too, do not count as [+Participant] either,
so their unavailability amounts to the fact that they cannot even be externally
merged. This is quite consistent with the fact that the first merged position of EDs
should in principle be subject to the same locality restrictions as any other non-core
argumental/high applicative position. Furthermore, their external merge position
is the very same position where ‘free benefactives/malefactives’ are merged anyway,
which does not prevent them from undergoing some (restricted) A -movement (see
() and ()).
‘u’ here stands for ‘unvalued’, referring to features that are inserted without a value from the lexicon
of two basic theta-features: [c(ause change of state)] and [m(ental state)], each of which may or may not be
present in the theta-cluster, and which may bear (when present) either a [+] or a [−] value ([+c] for causing
a change of state, [−c] for being caused to suffer such a change, [+m] for necessarily being a conscious
participant of the event, and [−m] for necessarily lacking consciousness).
[Hearer] might in fact be a privative feature (see Harbour ), in which case the [±] notation is
irrelevant.
Michelioudakis and Kapogianni
Similar observations, i.e. a ban on modal expressions in conditionals, are reported in Haegeman
(b); given that evaluative expressions such as EDs are actually possible in conditionals, we probably
need to assume not that modal projections are totally absent from conditionals, but rather that some modal
expressions are excluded due to semantic reasons specific to conditionals; in our case, evaluative adverbs
are simply excluded by the fact that conditionals do not denote (propositions presented as) facts.
Michelioudakis and Kapogianni
an event is represented here as a relation R between the individual x and the object of
evaluation p). Also, in contrast to evaluative adverbs, an ED can freely occur within
the antecedent of a conditional ().
() a. Dhistichos, i Maria i tha arjisi i dhen tha erthi katholu.
unfortunately the Mary or fut is late.pfv or not fut comes.pfv at all
‘Unfortunately, Mary will either be late or will not come at all.’
b. Dhistichos, an i Maria arjisi, dhen tha tin sinandisis.
unfortunately if the Mary is late.pfv not fut her.acc.cl meet.pfv.sg
‘Unfortunately, if Mary comes late, you will not be able to meet her.’
c. ∗ An, dhistichos, i Maria arjisi, dhen tha tin
if unfortunately the Mary is late.pfv not fut her.acc.cl
sinandisis.
meet.pfv.sg
‘If, unfortunately, Mary comes late, you will not be able to meet her.’
() a. Dhen mu pandreftikes na mu ftiaksis dhiki su ikojenia.
not sg.dat.cl married.sg subj me.dat.cl create.sg your family
‘You did not marry [which would give me joy], to create [to my delight] your
own family.’ ∼ (p • R(x, p))
b. Dhen mu pandreftikes ke mu emines monos/moni.
not me.dat.cl married.sg and me.dat.cl stayed.sg alone.m/f
‘You did not marry [to my disappointment], and now you live alone [to my
disappointment].’ ∼ p • R(x, ∼ p)
() Dhen pandreftikes eftichos.
not married.sg fortunately
∗ ‘You did not marry [which would give me joy].’ ∗ ∼ (p • R(S, p))
‘Fortunately, you did not marry.’ ∼ p • R(S, ∼ p)
As an anonymous reviewer points out, this analysis predicts that an ED cannot scope over two
conjoined events. This prediction is indeed borne out:
(i) I Maria mu arjise ke echase to treno.
the Mary me.dat.cl was late and missed the train
‘Mary was late (for which I sympathize) and missed the train’ (=no entailments about the evaluation
of the latter event; another ED should be present to convey sympathy for that one as well).
What follows • denotes the non-truth-conditional tier of the sentence meaning (following Potts ).
S here stands for ‘Speaker’. But see () below for a more precise formulation of the denotation of
evaluative adverbs.
Ethical Datives
The scopal properties of tense/time with regards to the evaluativity expressed by EDs are rather
unclear, since the intuitions about relevant examples are quite subtle; in general, it seems that time reference
takes scope over evaluativity, irrespective of tense (e.g. the speaker may hold some evaluative attitude in
the present for a past event, if this still has some effect on him/her).
Michelioudakis and Kapogianni
‘For which x, did x arrive earlier (whoever arrived earlier, it is strange that they
did)?’
() Pjo pedhi dhen mu efaje to fajito tu?
which child not me.dat.cl ate.sg the meal its
‘Which child did not eat their meal to my disappointment?’
∗ ‘For which x, x a child, did x not eat their meal (whoever did not eat their
Interestingly, according to an anonymous reviewer, ‘this reading is available for Spanish EDs’. How-
ever, we consider the relevant judgements to be robust in Greek. If there is really a difference between the
Greek and the Spanish facts, it might be the case that a universal closure operation is also at play for EDs
in Spanish.
Ethical Datives
To sum up, our diagnostics indicate that EDs modify events rather than fully-fledged
propositions, while they take scope over constituents that include the external argu-
ment, if there is one. Therefore, the head introducing EDs indeed appears to merge
higher than v∗ P/VoiceP. Consequently, EDs cliticize directly to T, while all other
clitics first incorporate into v∗ /Voice which then moves to T. The ED adjoins to the
left of Voice–T, i.e. to the left of the clitic(s)–V complex. Thus, in transitive clauses,
the ED is a defective intervener (i.e. a potential goal with no unvalued/undeleted
uninterpretable features) between T and the EA, which needs to value its uninter-
pretable Case via Agree with T. This defective intervention effect can be circumvented
if we assume that the ED clitic only has a bundle of phi-features (Person/Participant,
Number, Gender, and possibly Case), while T also has an uninterpretable [D] feature
which forces it to probe further down even after matching the ED clitic’s features (see
Chomsky on multiple Agree and re-probing).
Moreover, it seems preferable to assume that this ApplP is not part of the lower
phase, which is why the EA’s raising does not violate the Phase Impenetrability Con-
dition; in other words, Spec,Voice/v∗ still counts as part of the phase edge. Our
analysis could then be compatible with the fact that T selects VoiceP/v∗ Ps rather than
ApplPs if we assumed some version of Late Merge, as is often assumed for (other)
cases of adjuncts (see Fox and Nissenbaum ). These additional assumptions seem
necessary to make our analysis compatible with ‘bottom-up’ compositionality. At this
point, it must be noted that EDs are perhaps not unique in being merged at such
a high point. Although it can be shown that most argumental datives merge below
EA, ‘free benefactives’ too may merge above EA (but they are still distinguishable
from EDs as they are licensed by a [u(±)Participant] probe, like all other argumental
datives, rather than [+Participant] alone), which is why they behave identically to IO
clitics with respect to the PCC, among others. For instance, it is well known (since
von Stechow , see also Anagnostopoulou and Alexiadou ) that repetitive
again (and its counterpart ksana in Greek) scopes over EAs; interestingly, ‘free’/non-
recipient benefactives/malefactives, but not other argumental datives, may scope over
ksana ‘again’ (). Assuming that ksana can adjoin either to VoiceP or ApplP, in the
latter case ksana is a VoiceP-adjunct and ApplP necessarily dominates VoiceP. This
accounts for the non-cooccurrence of EDs and ‘free’ benefactives/malefactives, as
well as the presuppositional/interpretive behaviour of the latter (which befits VoiceP-
external phrases), as illustrated in () and () above.
() Mu to ksanalinis, se parakalo, ja na
sg.dat.cl sg.neut.acc.cl again solve.sg please for subj
dho pos jinete?
see.sg.pfv how is made
See also Rivero () on phenomena that call for a very high VoiceP-external ApplP, actually above
TP.
Michelioudakis and Kapogianni
(i) ‘You’ve solved it for me before, but can you do it again, so that I see how
you do it?’ ksana>Benef
(ii) ‘I know you’ve solved it before, but can you do it again, this time for me,
so that I see how you do it?’ Benef>ksana(>EA)
On the other hand, the fact that EDs really seem to be akin to evaluative adverbs,
modulo the (size of the) unit that they take as a complement, may mean that they are
indeed associated with the corresponding projection in the left periphery, i.e. EvalP,
following Cinque ().
Indirect evidence in favour of the idea that EDs and evaluative adverbs share some
(syntactically relevant) featural and structural properties also comes from relativized
minimality effects in cases such as the following (). Left-dislocation of an embed-
ded evaluative adverb seems to be sensitive to the intervention of an ethical clitic
((), ()). Preposing of similar adverbs has been reported to be ungrammatical in
English (cf. Postal and Ross ). Nevertheless, in our case it is clear that the adverb
originates in the embedded clause, as the positive evaluation is only appropriate
for the embedded event. As it moves, it obviously obtains the subject orientation
of the matrix EvalP. In the embedded clause, it would be oriented to the embed-
ded subject/reported speaker (b), unless complemented by an overt PP explicitly
stating the orientation of the adverb, as in (c), which is practically equivalent to
(a). Furthermore, (d) is not ruled out by some ban on the cooccurrence of EDs
and evaluative adverbs. Their cooccurrence is only deemed (at worst) superfluous,
like the cooccurrence of two evaluative adverbs, but not as sharply ungrammatical
as (d).
() a. Eftichos, kafchjete oti tha pai sti Ghalia ke etsi tha isichasume
fortunately boasts that fut goes to the France and so will rest.pl
apo dhafton.
from him
‘Fortunately, he boasts that he will go to France so he will stop bothering us.’
[fortunatelyi [he boasts [CP …ti …]]]
b. Kafchjete oti eftichos tha pai sti Ghalia ke etsi tha isichasume
boasts that fortunately fut goes to the France and so will rest.pl
apo dhafton.
from him
‘He boasts that he will fortunately go to France so he will stop bothering us.’
[hei boasts [CP Si …fortunatelyi/∗k …]]
This probably implies that projections such as EvalP can marginally be iterated, a possibility which is
usually not realized due to semantic/pragmatic rather than purely syntactic reasons.
Ethical Datives
c. Kafchjete oti, eftichos ja mas, tha pai sti Ghalia ke etsi tha isichasume
boasts that happily for us fut goes to France and so fut rest.pl
apo dhafton.
from him
‘He boasts that he will go to France, which is most fortunate for us, so he
will stop bothering us.’
[CP Sk … hei boasts [CP Si …fortunately for usk+/∗i …]]
d. ∗ Eftichos, mas kafchjete oti tha pai sti Ghalia ke etsi tha
fortunately us.dat.cl boasts that will go.sg to the France and so will
isichasume apo dhafton.
rest.pl from him
∗ [fortunately [he ED boasts [
i CP …ti …]]]
If we then view the ED as a non-core argument with two parts contributing to its inter-
pretation, i.e. an overt part in Spec,Appl and a null counterpart in Spec,Eval binding
it, we can assign a very restricted semantics to the applicative head, perhaps only a
function of type s, t, s, t, that essentially restates the semantics of its complement,
i.e. the event, while the non-truth-conditional content comes precisely from the Eval
head, as is the case with evaluative adverbs. The difference then would be that the full
meaning of the evaluative adverb is a conventional implicature as in (), while not all
of the ED’s meaning is conventionally implicated. Instead, the abstract argument in
Spec,Eval, being null and not corresponding to the content of any specific evaluative
adjective/adverb, necessarily underspecifies the precise value/content of the evalua-
tive attitude and calls for pragmatic enrichment, depending on the semantics of the
event and the context of the utterance (see section . below). On the other hand,
the virtual absence of any semantic content from ApplED may be what allows it to be
iterative, as in French (); see also Jouitteau and Rezac () for plenty of examples
with multiple EDs.
() Kaca te me nous a glissé.
Kaca you.sg.dat.cl me.dat.cl us.dat.cl has slipped
‘Kaca has slipped.’
(Some French varieties, from Jouitteau and Rezac : , who do not pro-
vide any translation for ethical clitics)
Also, importantly, the analysis entails the existence of an LF-interpretable part of
the expression in the left periphery, outside of what would count as the binding
domain of the ethical clitic (most probably the TP) under any definition of binding
domain/governing category/complete functional complex, etc. Therefore, this may
account for the binding facts observed in (), i.e. the fact that the ED behaves as
if it doesn’t belong to TP in terms of binding.
theory as one of the main characteristics of ironic utterances (Grice : , Sperber
and Wilson ), and it is reasonable to suppose that a structure that is inher-
ently evaluative would be a very effective tool for irony. The apparent ambigu-
ity/underdeterminacy of EDs at the level of LF is what allows for even more possi-
bilities of ironic exploitation.
Two issues concerning the ironic exploitation of EDs are of interest to the aims of
the present study: (a) on which part of the meaning of the ED can irony operate? and
(b) what is the scope of irony over EDs and sentences that contain EDs?
There are various theories on the strategies and devices through which irony oper-
ates (e.g. Grice , , Clark and Gerrig , Sperber and Wilson , Giora
, de Saussure and Shulz ). One common assumption of all of them is that the
ironist dissociates him/herself from the expressed meaning. This act of dissociation
(or detachment) is a key notion for understanding the way irony works with EDs.
Examining the intended meaning of examples () and (), we observe that it is an
evaluation which does not entail any sincere emotional involvement of the speaker, as
would be the case if the sentences were uttered literally. Therefore, we can assume that
the ironic strategy operating on EDs is not as simple as reversing the literal meaning
of the proposition expressed, which would involve taking an expression of ‘delight’ to
mean ‘disappointment’ and vice versa.
What we can propose instead is that irony exploits the inherent role of the ED
as an evaluator, by switching between different kinds of evaluation: the emotionally
nuanced pair of ‘delight/disappointment’ entails the notion of empathy (or sympathy)
which can be ironically reversed to express apathy or disapproval. In other words,
the ironist literally expresses a feeling of delight or disappointment (depending on
the nature of the event) while ironically intending an emotionally detached (usually
negative) evaluation. This observation also concurs with the consideration of irony as
‘reversal of evaluation’ rather than a strict reversal of meaning (Partington ).
As far as the process of meaning construction is concerned, the above observations
indicate that, when irony is involved, the function of the ED is to intensify the atti-
tude expressed by the ironist, which is an emotionally detached evaluation. For this
purpose, what is reversed by the irony is the emotional involvement/empathy, which
is entailed by the inherent (underspecified) evaluative character of the ED.
In order to investigate the scope of irony over EDs and sentences that contain EDs,
it is worth discussing the following ironic utterances:
() a. [Mu kurazese poli]!
b. [Mu] kurazese poli!
c. Mu [kurazese poli]!
sg.dat.cl get tired.sg much
‘You are getting too tired me.ED’
Intended:
a. ‘You are not getting very tired (and I can’t be sincerely unhappy about it).’
b. ‘You are getting very tired, for which I don’t feel any sympathy.’
c. ‘You are not getting very tired and I am unhappy about it.’
() Eftichos [i kathijites mas ine poli eksipni]. Dhe tha katalavun oti antigrafume.
‘Fortunately our teachers are very clever. They will not understand that we are
cheating.’
In (a) the whole sentence, including the ED, is used ironically. In contrast, in a
context where the addressee is actually getting tired, the only ironic part of (b) is
the use of the ED, assuming that the speaker is not being sincere about feeling sorry
for the fact that the addressee is getting tired. Therefore, aside from a global scope
over the whole sentence, irony can also take scope over one single element, in this
case the ED. The observation that irony can operate on the ED independently from
the rest of the sentence is also compatible with considering the meaning of the ED to
be a separate proposition.
On the other hand, as a further comparison between EDs and evaluative adverbs,
we may contrast (c) to the example in (). In the case of evaluative adverbs, there
is a possibility that the adverb remains out of the scope of irony, so that in () the
proposition ‘our teachers are very clever’ is used ironically to mean the exact opposite
and the adverb evaluates the intended ironic meaning ‘fortunately, our teachers are
stupid (and they will not understand we are cheating)’. On the contrary, EDs can never
fall out of the scope of irony, when it is present in the sentence. This is illustrated
by example (c), where the ironic use of ‘you are getting too tired’ would be used
ironically to mean ‘you are very relaxed’. In this case the ED would not be able to
retain a literal meaning of (semantically underspecified) emotional involvement, but
it would be ironically reversed to indicate emotional detachment.
The above observations about the scope of irony are in line with our proposal about
the semantic type of EDs: denoting a relationship between an event and an evalu-
ator, while also being distinct from the truth-conditional meaning of the sentence,
irony can operate on them separately. However, the reverse (irony operating on the
whole sentence except the ED) does not seem possible. This is another indication
about the levels of meaning construction of the ED, which becomes fully specified
(its evaluative character is resolved as positive—delight—or negative—detriment) at
the level of explicit meaning, its resolution being dependent on the meaning of the
asserted event it evaluates. Therefore, when a higher-level pragmatic phenomenon
operates on the propositional meaning of the described event (negating or revers-
ing its meaning), this necessarily affects the value of the evaluation conveyed by
the ED.
Ethical Datives
. Conclusions
The ED is a grammatically encoded expression that adds some non-truth-conditional
meaning to the sentence in which it appears. This is not exceptional if, for instance,
one compares the ED to other overt expressions, often discourse-related and
speaker/hearer-oriented, whose meanings seem to constitute conventionalized impli-
catures. What is exceptional is the fact that it originates in the thematic domain and
relates to the event semantics, while not all of its content is in fact encoded. The first
peculiarity seems to constitute a challenge for a bottom-up interpretation of the Com-
positionality Principle, which can be circumvented through a couple of assumptions
about the syntax of such expressions, e.g. the distribution of its denotation to distinct
heads, as well as perhaps the admission of Late Merge of adjuncts/non-core arguments
into our system. The other puzzling peculiarity of EDs, the fact that their meaning has
to be inferred (i.e. not all of it is conventionalized/encoded), even on the basis of purely
contextual information, points towards an interaction between syntax/LF, semantics,
and pragmatics such as the one outlined in the previous section. Such an interac-
tion in the interpretation of grammatically encoded expressions (putting aside cases
of deixis/anaphora) apparently contradicts conceptions of compositionality such as
Hintikka’s () ‘determinacy thesis’: ‘It is only the meanings of the parts and their
[…] mode of combination that matter’ (Partee : ). It is clear that these are
not enough for the interpretation of ethical clitics. Therefore, the ‘determinacy thesis’
might have to be reformulated as affecting only truth-conditional expressions, while
leaving room for partly conventionalized, context-dependent non-truth-conditional
expressions, such as EDs.
. Introduction
This chapter examines the viability of a syntactic analysis of pragmatic markers of
direct address. They appear either on the left or on the right edge of the utterance, as
those illustrated in (), from Romanian (R) and West Flemish (WF).
() a. Hai, plecăm.
hai leave.pl
‘We are leaving (injunction)’/‘There, we are leaving now.’ (R)
b. K’en kennen da nie wè.
I en know.sg that not wè
‘I don’t know that, you know.’ (WF)
Discourse particles have received a lot of attention in the context of discourse studies
but, with some notable exceptions (e.g. Munaro and Poletto , Del Gobbo and
Poletto ), they have so far been left aside by syntacticians. In this chapter, we
examine to what extent a syntactic analysis is possible and what it would look like.
Our proposal builds on our own earlier work in this area. We refer in particular to
Haegeman (, ) for early discussion of the syntax and interpretation of some
WF discourse particles, and Hill (a, b, ) for the discussion of the syntax
and interpretation of Romanian particles. Inspired by Speas and Tenny (), we will
elaborate an account that postulates a speech act layer dominating the left periphery
(LP) of clauses, and which hosts the relevant pragmatic markers as well as vocative
phrases in WF and R. Differently from Speas and Tenny, we will postulate that the
layers we identify are directly related to the speech event as such, i.e. the establishment
of a rapport between speaker and hearer in terms of either ‘attention-seeking’ or of
∗ Liliane Haegeman’s research is funded by the FWO -Odysseus-Haegeman-G. We thank
the audience of OnLI II for their comments. Thanks to two reviewers for their very useful comments, which
have helped us in the revisions of the chapter. Needless to say, they cannot be held responsible for the way
we have used their input.
The Syntacticization of Discourse
‘bonding’. Thus our account corroborates proposals for the syntactic representation
of the speech event made by Munaro and Poletto (), Sigurðsson (, ),
and Giorgi (), among others.
Because this is pioneering work, we will confine our analysis to a restricted set
of data, namely verb-based particles that ‘profile the speaker–hearer relationship’
(Kirsner and van Heuven ), and which are used as pragmatic markers, as in ().
We will show that our two investigations along these lines, which had initially been
undertaken independently of each other, for R and WF respectively, turned out to
concur in the syntactic analysis that was elaborated, which seems to us a promising
direction.
Though we concentrate on verb-based particles, we assume that other direct address particles will have
a similar distribution to those discussed here and will be amenable to a similar analysis. Cf. Haegeman
() for the WF particle da.
While the large majority of these particles are etymologically related to verbs of movement or percep-
tion, this cannot be generalized. WF né, for instance, is probably related to the verb nemen ‘take’, and the
Haegeman and Hill
In this chapter, we concentrate on nè(m), wè, zé/zè for WF, and on hai and its
cooccurrence with lasă for R. We leave the other particles (in WF and R) for future
study.
In both WF and R, some particles have two distinct conversational uses that cor-
relate with their distribution in the clause and/or with the intonation. For example, R
hai has an injunction reading when followed by a subjunctive clause (a) introduced
by the subjunctive marker să, but it has an evaluative reading when followed by an
indicative clause introduced by the indicative conjunction că ‘that’ (b).
() a. Hai să citim.
hai subj read.pl
‘C’mon, let’s read.’
b. Hai că este nemaipomenit.
hai that is unbelievable
‘It is unbelievable, really.’
With falling intonation, WF zè occurs in final position and can be followed only by
de stressed material. It has an evidential reading, conveying to the interlocutor that
there is salient contextual evidence for the content of the proposition expressed by
the utterance. With rising intonation, on the other hand, zé has an attention-drawing
function in the speech event and can appear either clause-initially or clause-finally.
The two particles may cooccur, with specific distribution restrictions, summarized in
(); in our notation the accents in zé vs. zè are intended to represent rising (zé) and
falling (zè) intonation. The intonation pattern determines the position: with falling
intonation the particle must be final, with rising intonation zé can be initial (a) or
final (d). In the latter case the particle with rising intonation must follow that with
falling intonation (e). We return to these points in section ...
() a. Zé, Valère is doa!
zé Valère is there
‘Look, Valère is there!’
b. Valère is doa zè.
Valère is there zè
‘Valère is there, as you see.’
WF particle da (Haegeman ), which is not discussed here but shares the distribution of utterance-final
particles such as wè, is not obviously related to any verb. Similarly, R lasă is not related to a verb of movement
or perception. However, it remains true crosslinguistically that verbs of movement and perception verbs
have often grammaticalized into particles, and this point certainly merits further study.
As pointed out by an anonymous reviewer, many of the particles seem to display the imperative form,
which in some Romance languages is the same found in compounding; maybe this is the ‘barest’ possible
form, and this is why we find an imperative. Alternatively, the imperative form is related to the direct
address to the interlocutor (Zanuttini ) and is encoded in the discourse projections. For discussion of
imperatives as particles, see also Derolez and Simon-Vandenbergen ().
The Syntacticization of Discourse
(i) Some of these particles display sensitivity to clause-typing: e.g. R uite and WF wè
are incompatible with interrogatives in fluent intonation:
() a. ∗ Uite cine vine?
uite who comes
b. ∗ Ee’j gedoan wè?
have you finished wè
(ii) R verb-based particles show selectional properties; e.g. they may select a CP with
a Force head că (‘that’).
() Hai că vine.
hai that comes
‘OK, s/he’s coming.’
Haegeman and Hill
c. Să vină!
subj come.sg
‘S/he better come!’
d. A nu deranja!
inf not come
‘Do not disturb!’
(v) The particles display rigid ordering restrictions. Some are initial, others are final,
others may be initial and final, but with constraints. We have already mentioned the
fixed word order of R hai > lasă above. In WF, for instance, zé/zè ‘see’ can be both
initial and final, with different intonation patterns and interpretations, whereas wè
is always final. Wè can be followed by zé, with rising intonation, but not by zè, with
falling intonation. Neither zè nor zé can precede wè.
() a. K’een gedoan wè zé
I have finished wè zé
b. ∗ K’een gedoan wè zè
c. ∗ K’een gedoan zè/zé wè
I have finished zè/zé wè
(vi) As shown in Hill (b) and Haegeman (to appear), the verb-based particles
interact with the syntax of vocatives in terms of their distribution and (for R) their
inflection. In both languages examined, the vocative displays distributional con-
straints in relation to the particle (), regardless of whether it occurs in initial or
final position. R displays person and number agreement between the vocative and
the verb-based particle (e,f). This agreement relation looks similar to subject/object–
verb agreements in narrow syntax, in general. We interpret this agreement rela-
tion as a reflex of a local Spec–head relation between the vocative nominal and the
verb/particle.
() a. K’een gedoan wè Valère
I have finished wè Valère.voc
b. ∗ K’een gedoan Valère wè
c. Zé Valère k’een gedoan
zé Valère.voc I have finished
d. ∗ Valère zé k’een gedoan
e. Lăsaţi fetelor că plecăm.
lasă.pl girls the.voc that go.pl
‘There there, girls, we’ll be leaving.’
f. ∗ Lasă fetelor, că plecăm.
lasă.sg girls the.voc that go.pl
Haegeman and Hill
(vii) Further compelling support for a syntactic treatment of direct address parti-
cles is discussed in Miyagawa (), who examines the distribution of allocutive
agreement in Souletin (Basque dialect; data from Oyharçabal ). This agreement is
determined by the interlocutor addressed in the utterance but not otherwise expressed
overtly. If agreement is considered to be the Spell-out of uninterpretable features
which have to be valued by a goal with the corresponding interpretable features, the
existence of allocutive agreement presupposes the presence of a goal controlling the
agreement. This sort of data offers support for encoding speaker and interlocutor roles
in the syntax.
Each particle has many slightly different overtones/values, depending on the con-
text. For instance, the WF particle wè can be used to accompany a statement, in
which case the speaker will use it to strongly endorse the content of his utterance
by somehow appealing to his experience, and (thus) to reassure the interlocutor,
or even to threaten him—near-equivalent to English ‘you see’, or ‘you know’ (a).
However, the same particle may also be used with an imperative (b,c), implying that
the speaker has the authority to utter the imperative—more like the emphatic use of
English do.
() a. Dat is nie gemakkelijk wè.
that is not easy wè
‘It’s not easy, you know.’ (WF)
b. Zet je mo wè.
sit you part wè
‘Do sit down.’
c. Komt doa nie an wè.
come there not on wè
‘Don’t you dare touch that.’
The particles we are investigating have similar functions: when used to accompany
statements, WF wè, for instance, serves to display the communicator’s competence
and trustworthiness; with imperatives, it may display either benevolence or authority,
depending on the content of the imperative. Along the lines of Wilson’s (, )
analysis, we formulate the hypothesis that the direct address particles are geared to
influencing the interlocutor’s epistemic vigilance.
structure in the same way that the argument structure of a lexical verb is projected.
Due to their categorial feature [V], the verb-based particles we examine here may be
argued to provide empirical support for such hypotheses. In this section, we recast
Speas and Tenny’s () hypothesis in a cartographic representation of the LP (Rizzi
, ), whose aim is to maximally syntacticize the interpretive domains (cf.
Cinque and Rizzi ).
be regularly embedded (unlike the analogues of ‘seem’), and it allows for imperative
morphology, which ‘seem’-type verbs rule out.
We are thus faced with a paradoxical situation: where hai is not a verb, it has no
TP domain, but it can display the morphology of imperative verbs. That is, hai can
have the endings for phi-features and mood (i.e. haideţi ‘haide+pl.imp’), which are
a property of T.
hedging; Tschizmarova ). Future work should aim to sort out to what extent syntax is responsible for
such variety (see also Speas and Tenny ).
Haegeman and Hill
The central point is that the interpretation of hai varies, rather than being fully fixed
in the lexical semantics of this particle. While the distribution of hai in this mapping is
limited, the combination between its location, complementation, and the predication
it belongs to allow for significant proliferations in the compositional meanings, which
also explains the list of numerous pragmatic values associated with hai.
We refer the reader to the discussion of the various hedging values in Tschizmarova (: ).
An anonymous reviewer informs us that the order corresponding to the R sequence Vocative > hai
appears in Greek as well with the particle ade (see also the word order in R ()):
(i) Jani ade parata mas
John.voc ade leave.imp us
‘John do leave us alone.’ (in the sense of ‘stop pestering us’)
The Syntacticization of Discourse
only hai can license a că (‘that’) indicative clause ((a,c) vs. (f)). We take the
observed distribution of the vocative in (a–d) as well as the observed restrictions
on agreement between the vocative and the particles to indicate that: (i) the vocative
is in a local relation with hai, not with vai, and (ii) the că ‘that’ CP is in a sisterhood
relation with hai, but not with vai. Thus, vai helps us to determine a hierarchy for
particles; however, it is not a particle of direct address, so we do not further analyse
its properties and syntactic behaviour.
() e. Vai(∗ ţi) fetelor haideţi că nu e bine.
vai (pl) girls hai.pl that not is good
‘Ah-ah, girls, this is not good, really.’
f. Vai (∗ că) nu te cred, Dane, hai.
vai (∗ that not you believe Dan.voc hai
‘Ah, c’mon Dan, I don’t believe you.’
is the specifier of SA. This structural articulation captures the privileged relation
between vocatives and injunctive particles, which had already been noticed in the
descriptive grammars of languages from various genetic groups (e.g. Schadeberg
for Umbundu).
() [saP [sa ] [SAP VOCATIVE [SA hai] [ForceP Utterance/ că…]]]
The unmarked order is that in which the vocative precedes hai, with hai in SA. When
the vocative is preceded by hai we assume that this is due to hai moving up to the
higher head sa. The interpretation of the utterance is determined by the relative
positions of the particle and the vocative: (), in which the vocative precedes hai,
foregrounds the vocative, for attention-drawing, whereas the order in which hai pre-
cedes the vocative foregrounds hai, conveying exasperation or enhanced mitigation.
The pitch is higher on the foregrounded item. Hence, the movement maps a different
value for the interpersonal feature.
The interpretive differences indicate that the movement of the particle from SA to
sa in R is not optional. Of course, it would be desirable for the trigger and constraints
for the head movement of the particle to be clarified. At this point we have two
suggestions for looking at this, and we intend to explore these in future work. On
the one hand, as suggested in Hill (a, b, ), the movement of the head
SA to sa is reminiscent of the way V moves to v. In this view, particle syntax is tied to
verb syntax, which ties in with the fact that many (though not all—cf. footnote )
discourse particles on the periphery of the utterance are etymologically related to
verbs. On the other hand, the derivation proposed here is also reminiscent of the
derivation of PPs proposed by Kayne (), according to which both the preposition
and its complement are merged on the clausal spine, and in which the ‘constituency’
of the PP is derived through subsequent movement of the complement and the
preposition.
Utterance-final hai is derived by the movement of the complement ForceP to the
specifier of the head sa. Alternatively, the vocative itself may also be fronted (in
which case the word order is again Voc > hai, although it is obtained at a higher
level).
Data with cooccurring particles such as () suggest either that particles may cluster
in one head, in the same way that in many languages clitics can be seen to cluster or,
alternatively, that more than one particle layer may be available. The latter option is
the conclusion reached independently by Haegeman (to appear) for WF and which
we discuss in the next section. Having discussed the syntax of the WF particles, we
briefly examine its applicability to the R particles in section ...
We thank an anonymous reviewer for OUP for drawing our attention to this point.
The Syntacticization of Discourse
Obviously the precise analysis of these data must depend on the syntax of V. We refer to the literature.
For one proposal for the analysis of V in cartographic terms see Haegeman () and van Craenenbroeck
and Haegeman ().
Haegeman and Hill
two final particles. The combined particles are subject to specific ordering constraints.
() illustrates some of the combinations.
() a. Né, men artikel is gedoan wè (∗ zé).
né my article is finished wè (∗ zé)
b. ∗ Men artikel is gedoan wè (∗ zè) (né).
Based on restrictions on the number of cooccurring verb-based particles, as in (),
and in particular on the observation that an initial particle (né) may cooccur with a
final one (wè, zè), we conclude that two speech act layers must be available. Given
the restriction on the number of particles in WF, we provisionally postulate two
articulated speech act projections. The observed distributional restrictions on the WF
particles provide further clues concerning the internal organization of the functional
domain that encodes speech event properties.
too, the two SA projections must be further articulated in a structure with two shells,
saP and SAP. In WF, vocatives always follow the particle, whether this be initial (a)
or final (b).
() a. Né Valère, men artikel is gereed (wè).
né Valère my article is ready (wè
‘Look Valère, my paper is ready (you know).
b. ∗ Valére né, men artikel is gereed (wè).
Valère né my article is ready (wè
c. (Né) Men artikel is gereed wè Valère.
(né my article is ready wè Valère
‘Look, my paper is ready you know, Valère.’
d. ∗ (Né) Men artikel is gereed Valère wè.
(né my article is ready Valère wè
The different positions of the vocative—initial or final—coincide with a difference
in interpretation: the initial vocative has an ‘appeal’ or attention-seeking function,
aiming at establishing a discourse relation; the final vocative consolidates the already
established relation of the speaker with an ‘addressee’ (see also e.g. Schegloff ).
In line with Hill (b), Haegeman (to appear) proposes that, in order to accom-
modate the vocatives, each of the two SA projections be articulated following our
proposal in section .: that is, each speech act projection is a shell structure, mod-
elled on the structure of vP/VP, where, analogously to a ditransitive V, the SA head
selects a complement (ForceP) and has an ‘indirect object’ (the vocative phrase) as its
specifier. The resulting SAP is dominated by a higher shell saP (analogous to vP), with
the particle moving from the lower head SA to sa, the higher head. Thus the structure
in () is updated to include a representation of the vocative syntax, and the sequence
né–vocative–CP is schematically represented as follows:
() a. [saP [sa né [SAP vocative [SA né . . . [ForceP . . .
Furthermore, given that two particles can cooccur, Haegeman (to appear) proposes
that there are two speech act projections, each articulated in the double shell structure,
and each with a specialized discourse function, where saP dominates saP. (b)
summarizes our conception of the fully articulated speech event layer: it includes an
attention-seeking layer (sa/SAP) and a consolidating/bonding layer (sa/SAP):
() b. [saP [sa né] [SAP VOC [SA né ]
[saP [sa wè] [SAP VOC [SA wè ] [ForceP ]]]]]
(a), with initial né and final wè, is derived as in (b). In (b) wè is merged as
SA; it selects ForceP as its complement and the vocative Valère as its specifier. Then
sa merges with SAP: the particle wè moves from SA to sa and attracts ForceP to
The Syntacticization of Discourse
its specifier, leading to the linear sequence in which the clause precedes the particle,
which in turn precedes the vocative. As shown in (c), the particle né is then merged
as SA, the lower head of the higher speech act projection, selecting saP as its
complement. Again, né head-moves from SA to sa.
() a. Né, k’een a gedoan wè Valère
b. [saP ForceP [sa wè] [SAP Valère [SA wè] [ForceP]]]
c. [saP [sa né] [SAP [SA né]
[saP ForceP [sa wè] [SAP Valère [SA wè] [ForceP]]]]]
The utterance-final position of né in (a) is derived on the basis of (c), by further
moving saP in (c) to the specifier of sa, headed by né, as in (b).
() a. K’een a gedoan wè Valère né
b. [saP [saP ForceP [sa wè] [SAP Valère [SA wè] [ForceP]]]
[sa né] [SAP [SA né] [saP]]]
shell of saP, though the data obviously would also be compatible with it moving to
the head of the higher shell, sa.
() a. Hai lasă Dane nu te enerva.
hai lasă Dan.voc not refl upset
b. [saP [sa ] [SAP [SA hai] [saP [sa lasă][SAP Dane [SA lasă] [ForceP]]]]]
In (), ForceP precedes lasă as well as the bonding vocative. To derive this order
we propose that ForceP moves to Spec,saP. This movement has an effect on the
information structure: the moved ForceP is foregrounded. We tentatively assume that
this displacement is thus related to a focusing movement.
() a. Hai nu te enerva Dane, lasă.
hai not refl upset Dan.voc lasă
b. [saP [sa ] [SAP [SA hai] [saP ForceP [sa ] [SAP Dane [SA lasă]
[ForceP]]]]]
In (), the vocative is initial, and precedes lasă, and hai is in final position. Though
initial, the vocative does not carry the high pitch for attention-drawing and retains
its bonding function associated with SAP. We assume therefore that the vocative
occupies Spec,SAP. To derive the final position of hai we assume that saP moves
to the initial position, Spec,saP. As a result, the attention is focused on the entire
proposition, while final hai conveys empathy.
() a. ?Dane, lasă, nu te enerva, hai.
Dan.voc lasă not refl upset hai
b. [saP [saP [sa ] [SAP Dane [SA lasă] [ForceP]]] [sa ]
[SAP [SA hai] [saP [sa ] [SAP Dane [SA lasă] [ForceP]]]]]
() is slightly degraded. In this example the vocative is merged in the vocative
position of the higher SAP, in which it has an attention-drawing function. The
final position of the particle lasă is derived by moving ForceP to Spec,saP with a
foregrounding effect. At this point it is not clear to us what causes the degradation of
this example.
() a. ?Dane, hai nu te enerva, lasă.
Dan.voc hai not refl upset lasă
b. [saP [sa ] [SAP Dane [SA hai] [saP ForceP [sa ] [SAP [SA lasă]
[ForceP]]]]]
In (), both the low particle and ForceP have moved to higher positions. The double
movement is a marked option and the sentence is awkward, although acceptable.
Again, it is not clear to us yet what causes this degradation.
The Syntacticization of Discourse
See Derolez and Simon-Vandenbergen () for some discussion of the properties of the particles.
Haegeman and Hill
. Introduction
The chapters in this volume address the question: how much of grammar is syntax?
In contemporary linguistics, the answer is often: a great deal. Syntactic structure lies
at the heart of much of what we understand about natural language.
Perhaps the best-established case of this is the link between structure and meaning,
at the heart of the body of successful research on the syntax–semantics interface, and
of work in formal semantics more generally. Here, as in other domains, we can ask to
what extent a particular set of facts is best explained by syntactic factors, and to what
extent a purely semantic explanation would be more successful. And yet the mere
possibility of syntactic explanations for semantic phenomena has been an advantage
of formal semantics over earlier, primarily philosophical, semantic work. Accounts
of variable quantifier scope in terms of covert syntactic movement, for example,
have led to the discovery that inverse scope readings are often subject to the same
restrictions as overt movement.
This chapter illustrates this advantage by bringing syntactic evidence to bear on a
puzzle that has previously been considered only at the interface between semantics
and pragmatics. The puzzle concerns so-called ‘asymmetric’ uses of the coordinator
and, illustrated in (). The most natural interpretation of these sentences is that the
first conjunct is temporally or causally prior to the second conjunct.
∗ For helpful comments, suggestions, and discussion, I would like to thank Kai von Fintel, Danny Fox,
Claire Halpert, Sabine Iatridou, Hazel Pearson, David Pesetsky, and two anonymous reviewers, as well as
audience members at both NELS and OnLI II.
For example, variable scope can be found between subjects and objects in languages like English. In a
sentence such as someone loves everyone, either the subject or object can take wide scope.
Bjorkman
() a. The lights came on and the singer stepped onto the stage.
b. The sniper shot him and he died.
The clauses in () are asymmetrically coordinated in that their temporal/causal inter-
pretations do not persist when the two clauses are reversed, as in ():
() a. The singer stepped onto the stage and the lights came on. (= (a))
b. He died and the sniper shot him. (= (b))
This asymmetric use of and is striking because it diverges sharply from fundamentally
symmetric truth-functional connective ∧, which does allow the clauses it coordinates
to be reversed. Considering sentences such as those in (), classical logic and modern
formal semantics both widely assume that ∧ is the default or natural interpretation of
natural language and.
() a. Water freezes at °C and London is the capital of England.
b. London is the capital of England and water freezes at °C. (= (a))
The existence of asymmetric uses of and therefore presents a puzzle and a stumbling
block for any unified semantic treatment of and. It has generally been argued that the
logical interpretation of and is semantically basic, and that asymmetric interpreta-
tions arise from general rules of pragmatic inference (Grice , Schmerling ,
Posner , Carston , ), though a minority have argued that asymmetric
interpretations are basic and logical ones derived (Bar Lev and Palacas , Txurruka
).
Despite considerable disagreement among these analyses, they are united in assum-
ing that the solution lies somewhere at the interface of semantics and pragmatics.
This chapter approaches the puzzle from a very different perspective, arguing that its
solution lies in the interaction of syntax and semantics.
More specifically, I show that the difference between symmetric and asymmetric
interpretations for clausal coordination can be traced to the syntactic size of the con-
stituents being coordinated. This contrast is masked when matrix clauses are coor-
dinated, but revealed in embedded contexts, where smaller clausal constituents (TPs)
visibly contrast with larger ones (CPs). It is only when smaller clausal constituents are
coordinated that asymmetric readings emerge, while symmetric or logical interpre-
tations are limited to coordinations of larger constituents.
I argue that these generalizations extend to matrix coordination, which is struc-
turally ambiguous between TP- and CP-coordination. Incorporating this ambiguity
A connection between the size of conjoined constituents and asymmetric interpretations is not an
entirely new idea. Such a connection is suggested by Posner () for English, and has been advanced for
asymmetric coordination constructions in German by a number of authors (the German facts are discussed
briefly in section ..). This has expressed the intuition that smaller coordinated constituents result in a
greater degree of semantic integration between two clauses. As far as I know, however, the details of this
proposal, and its implications for the formal semantic analysis of coordination more generally, have not
previously been developed.
A Syntactic Answer to a Pragmatic Puzzle
into the analysis of asymmetric and also opens the door to a wider unification,
including VP-coordination and conditional interpretations of clausal and. More
broadly, I argue that the assumption that natural language will mirror properties of
classical logic—specifically, that and has the semantics of ∧—has obscured a broader
pattern in the use of and to coordinate clauses and subclausal elements.
to the puzzle of asymmetric and can be found at the interface between syntax and
semantics.
Though this possibility has not previously been pursued as part of a general analysis
of clausal coordination, it fits naturally into a broader picture of coordination in
natural language. Coordination of other syntactic categories is well known to vary in
interpretation with the size of the constituents being coordinated, both in the nominal
domain (Bergmann , Dowty , Winter , et seq.) and in subclausal coordi-
nation of VPs (Goldsmith , Lakoff , Postal ). With such other examples
in view, it should come as no surprise that the same kind of variation shows up at the
clausal level.
The judgements reported in this section are the author’s own, with confirmation from an informal
the subcategorization requirements of an embedding verb: e.g. You can depend on my assistant and that
he will arrive on time. It is therefore possible that (a) does involve CP-coordination, but that report’s
subcategorization requirements (for a non-null complementizer) are violated by the second conjunct. This
possibility would fail to explain, however, the systematic differences between pairs of sentences such as
(), which we will see throughout this section.
A Syntactic Answer to a Pragmatic Puzzle
acceptable, despite the clauses occurring in the reverse of the sequence of events
described in the scenario.
() Scenario: same as ()
a. The engineer has confirmed that the valley flooded and the dam broke.
(= TP-coordination)
b. The engineer has confirmed that the valley flooded and that the dam broke.
(= CP-coordination)
In summary, the syntactic difference between coordinated TP and CP constituents
correlates with an interpretive difference between asymmetric and logical coordi-
nation. TP-coordination is judged acceptable only in situations compatible with an
asymmetric interpretation, while CP-coordination is compatible not only with situa-
tions that involve no relationship between two situations, but also with situations that
support a backwards relationship.
It thus appears that TP-coordination, at least in embedded contexts, gives rise to
asymmetric and: it expresses a ‘forward’ temporal or causal relationship between
events, it is felicitous only in contexts that involve such event relationships, and it
does not allow its conjuncts to be reversed while maintaining its interpretation.
CP-coordination, by contrast, has the symmetric properties of logical and: it
remains felicitous in any situation where both conjuncts are true, regardless of the
relationship between events, and its interpretation is stable when its conjuncts are
reversed, just as P ∧ Q is true whenever Q ∧ P is true.
The same paradigm of embedded coordination can be found in languages other
than English; indeed, yet stronger evidence for this pattern can be found by looking
at languages that require overt complementizers for all embedded finite clauses. In
English, any of the examples identified so far as TP-coordination could potentially
involve CP-coordination (with the second complementizer being silent), but this is
not possible in languages with no silent complementizer.
One such language is Modern Greek which, as we see in (), requires the comple-
mentizer oti to introduce embedded finite clauses.
There is also evidence that this is true of embedded non-finite clauses, with the complementizer for:
(i) a. The opposition planned for the vote to take place and the government to fall.
b. The opposition planned for the vote to take place and for the government to fall.
(ib), but not (ia), seems to be compatible with a plan in which the government is not planned to fall as a
result of the vote.
An interpretive contrast between embedded TP- and CP-coordination also arises beyond the domain of
attitude and reportative verbs. The same contrast can be found under modals such as necessary and possible:
(ii) a. It is possible that it will rain tomorrow and we’ll cancel the party.
b. It is possible that it will rain tomorrow and that we’ll cancel the party.
(iib), but not (iia), seems to be true if it rains tomorrow but the party is cancelled for some other reason.
Thank you to an anonymous reviewer for pointing out the relevance of the modal examples.
Greek data are from Sabine Iatridou (p.c.).
A Syntactic Answer to a Pragmatic Puzzle
Dutch data are from Erik Schoorlemmer (p.c.). Like English, Dutch allows both symmetric and asym-
metric interpretations for matrix coordination of sentences—the interaction of this with Dutch’s status as
a V language is discussed below.
Bjorkman
() I saw a man with a telescope (… though he was close enough to see with the
naked eye).
Essentially the same explanation can be applied to cases in which it is world knowledge
that favours a reverse temporal relationship, such as (), repeated from ().
() She did her Ph.D in the US and she did her MA in Canada.
If clausal coordination is structurally ambiguous, () can be understood as a case
in which world knowledge influences the resolution of the ambiguity in favour of
logical/symmetric and—just as world knowledge influences the syntactic parse of a
sentence like ():
() I saw a man with a teapot.
() is in principle ambiguous, but our knowledge about teapots and seeing strongly
influences a particular parse of the clause-final adjunct.
Finally, some syntactic contexts will require even matrix and to be parsed as CP-
coordination. I argue that the backwards interpretations conveyed by focus, repeated
in () from (), should be understood in this way.
() A: Did Bill break the vase?
B: Well, the vase BROKE, and HE dropped it.
Significantly, this class of counterexamples requires separate focus in each of the
coordinated clauses. Given the proposal that focus involves a relationship between
the focused element and a projection in the left periphery (as in e.g. the articulated
CP of Rizzi ), the appearance of two separate foci reasonably requires that each
conjunct project its own CP layer—and thus the logical symmetric interpretation of
CP-coordination. Listeners are free to draw reverse temporal/causal inferences on the
basis of logical and, because it does not convey any such relation on its own—and
On the analysis proposed here, the direction in which these resolutions occur—towards logical inter-
pretations for and from asymmetric ones—suggests that there is a preference to parse clausal coordination
as coordination of smaller constituents (TPs) rather than larger ones (CPs), in the absence of other deter-
mining factors. This is supported by the following contrast, pointed out by an anonymous reviewer:
(i) The old king has died of a heart attack and a republic has been formed.
a. But the second event happened before the first one.
b. But the first event happened before the second one.
This raises the question of whether there is a general preference for coordination of smaller constituents. It
is relevant to observe in this context that VP-coordination is often preferred to clausal coordination when
two clauses share the same subject: while (ii a) is in no way ungrammatical, (ii b) appears to be somewhat
preferable.
(ii) a. (?)The students read the book and they had many questions about it.
b. The students read the book and had many questions about it.
The contrast in (ii) could be explained by a general preference for smaller conjuncts over larger ones, but
more research would be necessary to confirm this point.
Bjorkman
indeed, the reverse interpretation in () has been reported to be less direct than the
forward interpretation usually available to coordination (e.g. Carston ).
Supporting this view is the fact that world knowledge or context can allow us to
infer the same reverse relationship for embedded CP-coordination, in (b), that we
find for matrix coordination with focus, as in (a):
() a. WELL, the millionaire DIED, and the butler gave him POISON.
b. We know that the millionaire died and that the butler gave him poison.
… and so we can conclude that the butler intentionally murdered him.
Rather than being problematic for the account of asymmetric and proposed in
this chapter, as they have been for past accounts, these cases of backwards inter-
pretations for and are fully compatible with the view that matrix coordination is
structurally ambiguous between TP-coordination (asymmetric) and CP-coordination
(symmetric). The focus-based reverse interpretations, moreover, provide more posi-
tive evidence for this position, with the assumption that focus requires an associated
left-peripheral projection.
We might expect to find yet stronger evidence for this conclusion in languages
where there is wider evidence for a distinction between TP and CP constituents in
matrix contexts. Verb-second word order in Germanic languages is generally argued
to involve the CP layer of the clause, and so coordination of two V clauses should
necessarily involve coordination of CPs. On the present account we would therefore
predict that coordination of matrix clauses in Germanic languages would always have
logical (non-asymmetric) interpretations.
This prediction, however, is not borne out. Dutch, for example, allows both logical
and asymmetric interpretations when V clauses are coordinated (Erik Schoorlem-
mer, p.c.):
() De sluipschutter schoot hem neer en hij stierf.
the sniper shot him down and he died
‘The sniper shot him and he died (because he was shot OR independently).’
This kind of example clearly presents a challenge for the simple structural account
articulated so far, particularly if the finite verb in a V clause occupies exactly the
same position as an embedding complementizer.
Despite this challenge, however, there is another source of evidence that the inter-
pretation of clausal coordination is structure-dependent. This evidence comes from
what has been called the SGF (Subject Gap in Finite/Fronted) construction (Höhle
, ), found in German, Dutch, and some other V Germanic languages.
In this construction, a non-subject argument is fronted within the first of two
coordinated matrix clauses, resulting in a postverbal subject. The second clause is
verb-initial, but contains a subject gap. The two clauses appear to share the same
A Syntactic Answer to a Pragmatic Puzzle
subject, though that subject is contained within the first conjunct and has not ATB-
extracted. () provides an example from German (from Heycock and Kroch :
(b)):
() Das Gepäck ließ er fallen und rannte zum Hinterausgang.
the-acc luggage let he fall and ran to the rear exit
‘He dropped the luggage and ran to the rear exit.’
What is especially striking about this construction, in light of the embedding facts
discussed in the previous section, is that it has only asymmetric interpretations
(Höhle , cited in Höhle , Reich ). It has been argued that SGF con-
structions involve a constituent slightly smaller than a full CP—perhaps C (Höhle
, Heycock and Kroch ). SGF coordinations thus provide evidence internal
to languages like Dutch and German that not only the syntax but also the interpre-
tation of clausal coordination is crucially dependent on the size of the constituents
coordinated.
The puzzle nonetheless remains of why the coordination of full V clauses in these
languages is not restricted to symmetric logical interpretations of and. A possibility
worth investigating is that merely distinguishing TP- and CP-coordination oversim-
plifies the structural contrasts relevant for coordination’s interpretation. It may be
instead that embedded clauses introduced by a complementizer differ in size, or
some other relevant property, from matrix V-clauses. Pursuing this possibility would
require a more thorough investigation of the interaction of V and coordination than
is possible here, however.
At this point it is worthwhile to discuss a final alternative to the view,
assumed throughout this section, that the symmetric interpretations of embed-
ded CP-coordination and matrix logical and are the same, or at least relevantly
parallel. Another possibility is that the symmetric interpretation of embedded CP-
coordination is subtly different from ordinary logical and.
Most significantly, embedded CP-coordination differs from its matrix counterpart
in the presence of the embedding verb itself. We might wonder whether it is the
interaction of this verb with multiple complementizers that gives rise to apparently
symmetric interpretations. In cases of embedded disjunction with or, for example, the
natural interpretation of disjoined CPs is one of multiple possible speech acts (rather
than propositions).
English, despite no longer being V, preserves an example of this construction in the nursery rhyme
() The newspaper reported that a new government was elected or that there was
a riot.
It is certainly the case that () communicates that one of two possible reporting
events took place, rather than that a disjunction itself was reported. Similar interpreta-
tions are possible with embedded CP-coordination, though less unambiguously than
in the case of disjunction. Such interpretations suggest that symmetric interpretations
might arise from the independence of two reported speech acts: if embedded CP-
coordination associates each proposition with an independent speech act, then there
would be no assertion that the propositions themselves were linked.
CP-coordination does not require the existence of multiple speech acts, however,
as illustrated by (). Association with separate speech acts thus cannot provide a
complete explanation for the symmetric interpretations available to such sentences—
there is no necessary causal or temporal connection between the conjoined clauses
in ().
() In a single breath, my friend told me that she was moving to the West Coast
and that her computer had been acting up.
Distinguishing embedded CP-coordination from matrix logical and also multiplies,
rather than simplifies, the puzzles concerning and’s interpretation. This distinction
would still provide no explanation of why embedded TP-coordination should be
restricted to asymmetric readings: this restriction cannot be accounted for in terms
of speech acts, as embedded TP-coordination can be used to communicate temporal
or causal connections originally made across multiple speech acts in a discourse.
It is worth noting more generally, moreover, that we should be cautious when
extending to and conclusions drawn from the behaviour of or. Though these two
connectives are often considered to be parallel to one another, or shows much more
restricted behaviour in asymmetric contexts. Or lacks asymmetric readings at the VP
level altogether (Postal ), and its asymmetric readings at the clausal level are much
more restricted than and’s (Culicover and Jackendoff ), appearing only in some
tense/mood contexts (future-oriented and imperatives), and not allowing non-ATB
extractions that are possible with conditionally interpreted clausal coordination.
Should a distinction between matrix and embedded coordination prove motivated,
however, the more general point of this chapter remains: that structural factors play an
important role in accounting for the various interpretations of clausal coordination
that we do in fact find. In the next section I discuss how this kind of syntactically
motivated approach fits in not only with what we know about coordination, but
with what we know about the connection between natural language and classical
logic more generally. This lends further support to the view that an analysis of and’s
Note that the second that here is obligatory: TP-disjunction does not appear to be possible in this
example.
A Syntactic Answer to a Pragmatic Puzzle
variability is to be found, at least in part, in the syntax, rather than in the interaction
of semantics and pragmatics, as previously assumed.
. Discussion
Section . has argued that syntax plays a role in determining the interpretation
of clausal coordination, with smaller clausal constituents giving rise to asymmetric
interpretations while larger ones give rise to symmetric logical interpretations. This
section turns to broader issues, discussing how a syntactic perspective on asymmetric
vs. logical and relates not only to coordination of other categories but also to more
general questions in natural language semantics.
One of and’s best-known properties is its ability to join constituents of many
different syntactic—and semantic—types. This on its own presents a puzzle for the
semantics of and, though one to which formal answers have long been available,
beginning in the proposals of Gazdar () and Partee and Rooth ().
These proposals, and many that followed them, have continued to view the symmet-
ric meaning of logical ∧ as the the ‘normal’ or ‘basic’ meaning of and. If we set clausal
coordination to one side, however, and focus on coordination of subclausal con-
stituents (often referred to as VP-coordination, though the coordinated constituents
can often include auxiliaries and modals outside VP), we find widespread and striking
asymmetric interpretations. Indeed, asymmetric interpretations are required in cases
in which the Coordinate Structure Constraint appears to be violated, when extraction
takes place out of only one of two coordinated VPs (Ross , Goldsmith ,
Lakoff ). This is illustrated by the non-equivalence of the (a) and (b) examples
in () and ().
() a. What did Alice [go to the store] and [buy t]?
b. = What did Alice [buy t] and [go to the store]?
() a. How many courses can a student [take t] and [stay sane]?
b. = How many courses can a student [stay sane] and [take t]?
The same is true of what Culicover and Jackendoff () call ‘left-subordinating and’.
Left-subordinating and is in many ways parallel to asymmetric and, but has a more
specific conditional interpretation illustrated in ().
Left-subordinating and has been most often discussed for the fact that its first conjunct can be an
imperative clause, as in: Move and I’ll shoot! (Bolinger , Han , Schlücker , Russell ). Its
first conjunct can also be a DP, though the type of the DP is fairly restricted (Culicover ). Finally, a
sufficiency modal can occur in the first conjunct, as in: You only have to go to the North End and you’ll
find good cheese (von Fintel and Iatridou ), though no other modals can occur in these sentences. In
these ways, left-subordinating and differs from the simple asymmetric and that is the focus of this chapter,
though Bjorkman (forthcoming) discusses possible connections between the two at slightly greater length.
Bjorkman
() a. Alice shows up late one more time and she’ll be fired.
b. Our parents find out about this and we’ll be disowned.
c. The dam breaks and the valley will be flooded.
Culicover and Jackendoff observe that this left-surbordinating and, when embedded,
requires TP- rather than CP-coordination, just as I have argued here is required for
asymmetric and.
() Culicover and Jackendoff (: )
a. You know, of course, that you drink one more beer and you get kicked out.
(= … that if you drink one more beer you get kicked out.)
b. You know, of course, that you drink one more beer and that you get kicked
out.
( = … that if you drink one more beer you get kicked out.)
Both VP-coordination and left-subordinating and provide further examples of cases
in which the coordination of smaller clausal constituents results in an asymmetric
interpretation, and more generally of cases in which and’s interpretation and its syntax
are closely related to one another.
In the nominal domain, though asymmetric interpretations are not equally appar-
ent, we also find clear connections between the size of coordinated elements and
their interpretation. Thus (a), with DP-coordination, must refer to two individuals,
while (b) can refer to either one or two (Bergmann , Dowty , Winter ,
et seq.):
() a. the officer and the lady
b. the officer and lady
This is again a close connection between the interpretation of coordination and its
syntax. Focusing on these kinds of example, the dissimilarities between and and logi-
cal ∧ seem to vastly outweigh their commonalities: at every level of structure, coordi-
nation with and admits of asymmetric interpretations, and these interpretations vary
with the size of the constituents being conjoined. This puts further pressure on the
view that a pragmatic approach to asymmetric and is favoured by considerations of
theoretical parsimony: this argument assumes that logical ∧ has a clear advantage in
accounting for a broader range of and’s interpretations, which does not seem to be the
case.
This highlights a yet broader question: why would we suppose in the first place that
the connectives of classical logic have precise counterparts in natural language? Why
Temporal asymmetries can be found with some nominals, primarily those related to or derived from
would we be surprised if and lacks any such counterpart, any more than we would
be surprised to find that natural language is often ill-suited to talking precisely about
mathematics?
Indeed, the view that natural language faithfully reflects classical logic has been
losing ground for some time. This has been particularly clear in the development
of analyses of conditionals, and counterfactual conditionals in particular. The once
widespread view that if–then conditionals express the truth-functional relationship of
material implication encountered serious problems in accounting for counterfactual
conditionals, in addition to the fact that material implication provides unintuitive
truth-conditions for natural language conditionals. Early efforts to deal with these
problems sought to retain the basics of the material implication analysis, enriched
with a theory of pragmatics (Grice )—much as Grice proposed a pragmatic
approach to asymmetric and. Subsequently the modal analyses of Stalnaker ()
and Lewis () were developed for conditionals, later refined by the modal restric-
tion analysis of conditionals developed by Kratzer (, ). The modal restric-
tion analysis has the additional advantage of acknowledging the syntactic structure
of if–then conditionals, which does not map well onto a two-place truth-functional
operator such as →.
The historical development of the semantic analysis of conditionals has a lesson to
teach in approaching the analysis of other basic semantic elements: that the contribu-
tions of classical logic to natural language semantics do not guarantee that there are
lexical items that correspond directly to logical connectives. Just as material implica-
tion has been abandoned in the analysis of conditional if–then, there is no reason to
think that logical conjunction should necessarily survive as the best or most complete
analysis of and.
This is not to say that there is no role for logical connectives in the analysis of natural
language; the very success of formal semantics proves that the tools of formal logic are
directly applicable to natural language semantics. It is instead only to argue that there
is increasing reason to abandon the longstanding (and very reasonable) hypothesis
that the words traditionally used to translate the connectives of formal logic—and,
or, if, etc.—are entirely semantically equivalent to those connectives.
Neither is this to say that there is not a great deal of work for semantics—and
pragmatics—to do in the analysis of and. But it may be that there is little to be gained
in relegating asymmetric and to the domain of pragmatics: when we consider the wide
range of interpretations available to and that do not resemble ∧, we are faced with a
An anonymous reviewer observes that it seems significant that the inference patterns licensed by
∧ are also licensed by and, which is not the case for material implication and if–then conditionals. It is
worth noting, however, that the inference patterns licensed by ∧ are also licensed by two sentences asserted
independently of one another, with no syntactic connection between them. The semantics of and must
therefore account for the fact that both clauses are asserted to be true, but this does not require that and be
semantically reducible to ∧.
Bjorkman
difficult semantic problem, but the syntactic differences that match these semantic
differences can provide a scaffolding for a successful semantic analysis.
. Conclusion
As should now be clear, this chapter argues that syntax plays a central role, and a
wide-reaching one, in the grammar of language as a whole, and also in the domain of
coordination. This conclusion is a natural one, given that syntax plays a central role
in encoding the structural properties that lie at the heart of natural language.
This chapter focused on the puzzle of asymmetric interpretations of and, a topic
previously discussed at the interface of semantics and pragmatics. I have argued that
the answer to this puzzle may lie instead at the syntax–semantics interface, based
on evidence that smaller clausal constituents participate in asymmetric coordination,
while larger clausal constituents (at least large enough to contain the complemen-
tizer that) participate in and’s traditional symmetric interpretation. This proposal has
the advantage that it puts asymmetric and, often discussed in isolation from other
coordination structures, on a clear continuum with other asymmetric coordinations,
including well-studied cases of VP-coordination and left-subordinating and. Though
this chapter has not developed any specific semantic analysis of and, the syntactic facts
discussed here provide the foundation for such an analysis. The correlation between
interpretations of coordination and the size of conjoined constituents suggests that it
is properties of those constituents that influence the interpretation of coordination,
rather than any variation in the denotation of and itself. At the same time, the deno-
tation of and may be the source of the directionality of the connection between con-
juncts, when such a connection is available. There is a great deal of known variation
in both the categorial and interpretive restrictions for and-like coordinators across
languages. Developing a semantics for and that accommodates the observations made
here may also open the door to a more comprehensive crosslinguistic semantics for
coordination.
Two more general points can be distilled from this discussion. The first is that
syntax can play a role in solving puzzles of interpretation; indeed, we may often
miss relevant syntactic evidence simply because a puzzle has been framed in entirely
semantic and pragmatic terms. The second, yet broader, is that too great a focus on
traditional logical analyses can obscure the true systematicity of natural language:
by departing from an analysis of and as ∧, a structural approach to variability in
the interpretation of clausal coordination becomes possible, in turn giving greater
insight into the possibility of a unified approach to coordination across a fuller range
of syntactic categories (VP, DP, NP, etc.). As our analysis of natural language advances,
we are better able to analyse language on its own terms, granting in turn deeper
appreciation of its structure.
References
Abels, Klaus (). Successive Cyclicity, Anti-locality and Adposition Stranding. Ph.D thesis,
University of Connecticut, Storrs.
Adger, David, and Harbour, Daniel (). The syntax and syncretisms of the Person Case
Constraint. Syntax : –.
Alexiadou, Artemis (). Functional Structure in Nominals: Nominalization and Ergativity.
Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Alexiadou, Artemis (). On the role of syntactic locality in morphological processes: the
case of (Greek) nominals. In A. Giannakidou and M. Rathert (eds), Quantification, Definite-
ness, and Nominalization, –. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Alexiadou, Artemis, and Anagnostopoulou, Elena (). Parametrizing Agr: word order, verb-
movement and EPP-checking. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory : –.
Alexiadou, Artemis, and Anagnostopoulou, Elena (). Asymmetries in the distribution of
clitics: the case of Greek restrictive relatives. In F. Beukema and M. den Dikken (eds), Clitic
Phenomena in European Languages, –. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Alexiadou, Artemis, and Anagnostopoulou, Elena (). Structuring participles. In C. Chang
and H. Haynie (eds), Proceedings of the th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics,
–. Somerville, Mass.: Cascadilla Press.
Alexiadou, Artemis, Anagnostopoulou, Elena, and Schäfer, Florian (). The properties of
anticausatives cross-linguistically. In M. Frascarelli (ed.), Phases of Interpretation, –.
Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Alexiadou, Artemis, Anagnostopoulou, Elena, and Schäfer, Florian (). PP licensing in
nominalizations. In A. Schardl, M. Walkow, and M. Aburrahman, Proceedings of NELS ,
–. Amherst, Mass.: GLSA.
Alexiadou, Artemis, Gehrke, Berit, and Schäfer, Florian (). Adjectival participles revisited.
Paper presented at the Workshop on Aspect and Argument Structure of Adjectives and
Participles (WAASAP), University of Greenwich, London.
Alexiadou, Artemis, and Gengel, Kirsten (). Classifiers as morphosyntactic licensors of NP
ellipsis: English vs. Romance. In S. Lima, K. Mullin, and B. Smith (eds), NELS : Proceedings
of the Thirty-Ninth Annual Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society, –. Amherst,
Mass.: GLSA.
Alexiadou, Artemis, Haegeman, Liliane, and Stavrou, Melita (). Noun Phrase in the Gen-
erative Perspective. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Alexiadou, Artemis, and Müller, Gereon (). Class features as probes. In A. Bachrach and
A. Nevins (eds), Inflectional Identity, –. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Alexiadou, Artemis, and Stavrou, Melita (). Adjective–clitic combinations in the Greek DP.
In B. Gerlach and J. Grijzenhout (eds), Clitics in Phonology, Morphology, and Syntax, –.
Amsterdam: Benjamins.
References
Alexiadou, Artemis, and Varlokosta, Spyridoula (). Free relatives in Modern Greek. In
A. Alexiadou (eds), Studies in the Morpho-Syntax of Greek, –. Newcastle upon Tyne:
Cambridge Scholars.
Alexopoulou, Theodora (a). Free and restrictive relative clauses in Greek. In Proceedings
of the th International Conference on Theoretical and Applied Linguistics, April –, ,
–. Thessaloniki: Aristotle University.
Alexopoulou, Theodora (b). Resumption in relative clauses. Natural Language & Linguistic
Theory : –.
Alexopoulou, Theodora, and Folli, Raffaella (). Topic-strategies and the internal structure
of nominal arguments in Greek and Italian. MS, University of Cambridge and University of
Ulster.
Alexopoulou, Theodora, and Kolliakou, Dimitra (). On linkhood and Clitic Left Disloca-
tion. Journal of Linguistics : –.
An, Duk-Ho (a). Clauses in noncanonical positions at the syntax–phonology interface.
Syntax : –.
An, Duk-Ho (b). Syntax at the PF Interface: Prosodic Mapping, Linear Order, and Deletion.
Ph.D thesis, University of Connecticut, Storrs.
Anagnostopoulou, Elena (). Clitic Dependencies in Modern Greek. Ph.D thesis, University
of Salzburg.
Anagnostopoulou, Elena (). On experiencers. In A. Alexiadou, G. Horrocks, and
M. Stavrou (eds), Studies in Greek Syntax, –. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Anagnostopoulou, Elena (a). Participles and Voice. In A. Alexiadou, M. Rathert, and
A. von Stechow (eds), Perfect Explorations, –. Berlin: de Gruyter.
Anagnostopoulou, Elena (b). The Syntax of Ditransitives: Evidence from Clitics. Berlin:
Mouton de Gruyter.
Anagnostopoulou, Elena (). Strong and weak person restrictions. In L. Heggie and
F. Ordonez (eds), Clitic and Affix Combinations: Theoretical Perspectives, –. Amster-
dam: Benjamins.
Anagnostopoulou, Elena (). Clitic doubling. In M. Everaert and H. van Riemsdijk (eds),
The Blackwell Companion to Syntax, vol. , –. Oxford: Blackwell.
Anagnostopoulou, Elena, and Alexiadou, Artemis (). Ò˛ÙÂÚ ·Ò·ÙÁÒfiÛÂÈÚ
ÛÙÁ Û˝ÌÙ·ÓÁ ˜·È ÂÒÏÁÌÂfl· ÙÔı ÂÈÒÒfiÏ·ÙÔÚ Ó·Ì‹ ÛÙ· Ì›· ÂÎÎÁÌȘ‹ [Some pre-
liminary observations on the syntax and interpretation of the adverb ksana in Modern
Greek]. Paper presented at the University of Athens, April .
Anagnostopoulou, Elena, and Samioti, Yota (). Domains for idioms. Paper presented at
the Roots Workshop, University of Stuttgart, June .
Anagnostopoulou, Elena, and Samioti, Yota (forthcoming). Domains within words and their
meanings: a case study. In A. Alexiadou, H. Borer, and F. Schäfer (eds),The Syntax of Roots
and the Roots of Syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Anand, Pranav (). De De Se. Ph.D thesis, MIT.
Anand, Pranav, and Nevins, Andrew (). Shifty operators in changing contexts. In R. Young
(ed.), Proceedings from Semantics And Linguistic Theory XIV, –. Ithaca, NY: CLC.
Anderson, Stephen (). Where’s morphology? Linguistic Inquiry : –.
References
Androutsopoulou, Antonia (). The distribution of the definite determiner and the syntax
of Greek DPs. In K. Beals, R. Knippen, and J. Denton (eds), Papers from the th Annual
Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, –.
Aoun, Joseph, and Benmamoun, Elabbas (). Minimality, reconstruction, and PF move-
ment. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Aoun, Joseph, Choueiri, Lina, and Hornstein, Norbert (). Resumption, movement, and
derivational economy. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Aoun, Joseph, and Li, Yen-Hui Audrey (). Scope and constituency. Linguistic Inquiry :
–.
Aoun, Joseph, and Li, Yen-Hui Audrey (). The Syntax of Scope. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.
Aoun, Joseph, and Li, Yen-Hui Audrey (). Essays on the Representational and Derivational
Nature of Grammar: The Diversity of Wh-Constructions. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Arad, Maya (). Locality constraints on the interpretation of roots: the case of Hebrew
denominal verbs. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory : –.
Arad, Maya (). Roots and Patterns: Hebrew Morpho-Syntax. Dordrecht: Springer.
Arregi, Karlos, and Nevins, Andrew (). Morphotactics: Basque Auxiliaries and the Structure
of Spellout. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Arsenijević, Boban (). On two types of deadjectival nominalisation in Serbian. Suvremena
Lingvistika : –.
Arsenijević, Boban (). Semantic ontology of deadjectival nominalisations. Recherches lin-
guistiques de Vincennes : –.
Arsenijević, Boban (). Evaluative reflexions: evaluative dative reflexive in south east Serbo-
Croatian. In R. Etxepare and B. Fernández (eds), Variation in Datives: A Microcomparative
Perspective, –. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ashby, William (). An acoustic profile of right-dislocations in French. Journal of French
Language Studies : –.
Asudeh, Ash, and Toivonen, Ida (). Copy raising and perception. MS, Carleton University;
revised version published as Asudeh and Toivonen ().
Asudeh, Ash, and Toivonen, Ida (). Copy raising and perception. Natural Language &
Linguistic Theory : –.
Atlas, Jay (). Aboutness, fiction, and quantifying into intentional contexts: Prior, Quine,
and Searle on propositional attitudes. Paper presented at the Symposium on Reference,
University of Duisberg, March.
Backus, Ad (). The role of semantic specificity in insertional codeswitching: evidence from
Dutch Turkish. In R. Jacobson (ed.), Codeswitching Worldwide II, –. Berlin: Mouton
de Gruyter.
Baeskow, Heike (). A revival of Romance roots. Morphology : –.
Baker, Mark (). The mirror principle and morphosyntactic explanation. Linguistic Inquiry
: –.
Baker, Mark (). Incorporation: A Theory of Grammatical Function Changing. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
Baker, Mark (a). The macroparameter in a microparametric world. In T. Biberauer (ed.),
The Limits of Syntactic Variation, –. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
References
Baker, Mark (b). The Syntax of Agreement and Concord. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Baker, Mark (). On the morphosyntactic distinctiveness of adjectives. Paper presented
at the Workshop on Adjectives and Relative Clauses: Syntax and Semantics, Università Ca’
Foscari, Venice.
Baker, Mark, Johnson, Kyle, and Roberts, Ian (). Passive arguments raised. Linguistic
Inquiry : –.
Baković, Eric (). Opacity and ordering. In J. Goldsmith, J. Riggle, and A. Yu (eds), The
Handbook of Phonological Theory, nd edn, –. Oxford: Wiley–Blackwell.
Bar Lev, Zev, and Palacas, Arthur (). Semantic command over pragmatic priority. Lingua
: –.
Baraga, Frederic (). A Theoretical and Practical Grammar of the Otchipwe Language. Mon-
treal: Beauchemin & Valois.
Barker, J., and Bolger, P. (). Manual for eye tracking hardware and software: eyesamv.exe
and accompanying files. MS.
Barrie, Michael, and Mathieu, Éric (). Head movement and noun incorporation. Linguistic
Inquiry : –.
Barss, Andrew (). Chains and Anaphoric Dependence: On Reconstruction and its Implica-
tions. Ph.D thesis, MIT.
Barwise, Jon, and Cooper, Robin (). Generalized quantifiers in natural language. Linguistics
and Philosophy : –.
Basilico, David (). Particle verbs and benefactive double objects in English: high and low
attachments. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory : –.
Bäuerle, Rainer (). Pragmatisch-semantische Aspekte der NP-Interpretation. In M. Faust,
R. Harweg, W. Lehfeldt, and G. Wienold (eds), Allgemeine Sprachwissenschaft, Sprachtypolo-
gie und Textlinguistik: Festschrift für Peter Hartmann, –. Tübingen: Narr.
Bayer, Josef, and Kornfilt, Jaklin (). Against scrambling as an instance of move-alpha. In
N. Corver and H. van Riemsdijk (eds), Studies on Scrambling: Movement and Non-Movement
Approaches to Free Word-Order Phenomena, –. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Bazzanella, Carla (). I segnali discorsivi. In L. Renzi, G. Salvi, and A. Cardinaletti (eds),
Grande grammatica italiana di consultazione, vol. : Tipi di frase, deissi, formazione delle
parole, –. Bologna: Il Mulino.
Beaven, Alexander (). Control is almost definitely not movement (probably): new evidence
from dative intervention. Honours thesis, University of Edinburgh.
Beck, Sigrid (a). Quantified structures as barriers for LF movement. Natural Language
Semantics : –.
Beck, Sigrid (b). Wh-Constructions and Transparent Logical Form. Ph.D thesis, Universität
Tübingen.
Beck, Sigrid (). Intervention effects follow from focus interpretation. Natural Language
Semantics : –.
Beck, Sigrid (). The grammar of focus interpretation. In U. Sauerland and H.-M. Gärtner
(eds), Interfaces + Recursion = Language? Chomsky’s Minimalism and the View from Syntax–
Semantics, –. Berlin: de Gruyter.
References
Boeckx, Cedric (). Islands and Chains: Resumption as Stranding. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Boeckx, Cedric (). Bare Syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Boeckx, Cedric (). What happens when syntax faces the sensori-motor systems, phyloge-
netically and ontogenetically. Paper presented at ConSOLE XVIII.
Boeckx, Cedric, and Hornstein, Norbert (). Reply to ‘Control is not movement’. Linguistic
Inquiry : –.
Boeckx, Cedric, Hornstein, Norbert, and Nunes, Jairo (). Control as Movement. Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bolinger, Dwight (). The imperative in English. In To Honor Roman Jakobson: Essays on
the Occasion of his Seventieth Birthday, vol. , –. The Hague: Mouton.
Bonami, Olivier, and Boyé, Gilles (). French pronominal clitics and the design of Paradigm
Function Morphology. In G. Booij, L. Ducceschi, B. Fradin, E. Guevara, A. Ralli, and S. Scalise
(eds), Online Proceedings of the th Mediterranean Morphology Meeting (MMM) Fréjus –
September , –. Bologna: Università degli Studi.
Bonami, Olivier, and Godard, Danièle (). Lexical semantics and pragmatics of evaluative
adverbs. In L. McNally and C. Kennedy (eds), Adjectives and Adverbs: Syntax, Semantics, and
Discourse, –. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Boneh, N., and Nash, L. (). Non-core datives are merged high. Paper presented at the th
EDiSyn meeting, San Sebastian/Donostia, June.
Boneh, N., and Nash, L. (). High and higher applicatives: the case of French non-
core datives. In M. Byram Washburn, K. McKinney-Bock, E. Varis, A. Sawyer, and B.
Tomaszewicz (eds), Proceedings of the th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, –
. Somerville, Mass.: Cascadilla Press.
Bonet, Eulàlia (). Morphology after Syntax: Pronominal Clitics in Romance. Ph.D thesis,
MIT.
Booij, Geert (). The Phonology of Dutch. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Borer, Hagit (). The projection of arguments. In E. Benedicto and J. Runner (eds), Uni-
versity of Massachusetts Occasional Papers in Linguistics : Functional Projections, –.
Amherst, Mass.: GLSA.
Borer, Hagit (). Deriving passives without theta-grids. In S. Lapointe, D. Brentari, and
P. Farrell (eds), Morphology and its Relations to Phonology and Syntax, –. Stanford, Calif.:
CSLI.
Borer, Hagit (). Structuring Sense, vol. : The Normal Course of Events. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Borer, Hagit (). Roots and categories. Paper presented at the th colloquium on Gen-
erative Grammar, University of the Basque Country, Vitoria-Gasteiz. Handout available at
http://www-bcf.usc.edu/∼borer/rootscategories.pdf.
Bošković, Željko (). On the Nature of the Syntax–Phonology Interface. Amsterdam: North-
Holland Elsevier.
Bošković, Željko, and Lasnik, Howard (). On the distribution of null complementizers.
Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Bošković, Željko, and Nunes, Jairo (). The copy theory of movement: a view from PF. In
N. Corver and J. Nunes (eds), The Copy Theory of Movement, –. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
References
Bosse, Solveig, Bruening, Benjamin, and Yamada, Masahiro (). Affected experiencers.
Natural Language & Linguistic Theory : –.
Bresnan, Joan (). Sentence stress and syntactic transformations. Language : –.
Brody, Michael (). Lexico-Logical Form: Toward a Radically Minimalist Theory. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
Broihier, Kevin (). Slavic relatives, resumptive pronouns, and learnability. MS, MIT.
Bruening, Benjamin (). Ditransitive asymmetries and a theory of idiom formation. Lin-
guistic Inquiry : –.
Bruening, Benjamin (to appear). Word formation is syntactic: adjectival passives in English.
Natural Language & Linguistic Theory: –.
Büring, Daniel (). The Meaning of Topic and Focus. London: Routledge.
Büring, Daniel (). On D-trees, beans, and B-accents. Linguistics and Philosophy :
–.
Carlson, Greg (a). Reference to Kinds in English. Ph.D thesis, University of Massachusetts,
Amherst.
Carlson, Greg (b). A unified analysis of the English bare plural. Linguistics and Philosophy
: –.
Carstens, Vicki (). The Morphology and Syntax of Determiner Phrases in Kiswahili. Ph.D
thesis, University of California, Los Angeles.
Carston, Robyn (). Conjunction, explanation, and relevance. Lingua : –.
Carston, Robyn (). Thoughts and Utterances: The Pragmatics of Explicit Communication.
Oxford: Blackwell.
Chierchia, Gennaro (). Questions with quantifiers. Natural Language Semantics :
–.
Chierchia, Gennaro (). Reference to kinds across languages. Natural Language Semantics
: –.
Choe, Hyon Sook (). Focus and topic movement in Korean and licensing. In K. É. Kiss
(ed.), Discourse Configurational Languages, –. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Choi, Hye-Won (). Topic and focus in Korean: the information partition by phrase struc-
ture and morphology. In Ho-min Sohn and J. Haig (eds), Japanese and Korean Linguistics ,
–. Stanford, Calif.: CSLI.
Choi, Hye-Won (). Optimizing Structure in Context: Scrambling and Information Structure.
Stanford, Calif.: CSLI.
Chomsky, Noam (). The logical structure of linguistic theory. MS, Harvard University.
Revised version published as Chomsky ().
Chomsky, Noam (). Remarks on nominalization. In R. Jacobs and P. Rosenbaum (eds),
Readings in English Transformational Grammar, –. Waltham, Mass.: Ginn.
Chomsky, Noam (). The Logical Structure of Linguistic Theory. New York: Plenum.
Chomsky, Noam (). Conditions on rules of grammar. Linguistic Analysis : –.
Chomsky, Noam (). Lectures on Government and Binding. Dordrecht: Foris.
Chomsky, Noam (). A minimalist program for linguistic theory. In K. Hale and S. J. Keyser
(eds), The View from Building : Essays in Honor of Sylvain Bromberger, –. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam (). The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
References
Chomsky, Noam (). Minimalist inquiries: the framework. In R. Martin, D. Michaels, and
J. Uriagereka (eds), Step by Step: Essays on Minimalist Syntax in Honor of Howard Lasnik,
–. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam (). Derivation by phase. In M. Kenstowicz (ed.), Ken Hale: A Life in
Language, –. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam (). Beyond explanatory adequacy. In A. Belletti (ed.), Structures and
Beyond: The Cartography of Syntactic Structures, –. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chomsky, Noam (). On phases. In C. Otero, R. Freidin, and M.-L. Zubizarreta (eds),
Foundational Issues in Linguistic Theory: Essays in Honor of Jean-Roger Vergnaud, –.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Chomsky, Noam, and Halle, Morris (). The Sound Pattern of English. New York: Harper &
Row.
Chomsky, Noam, and Lasnik, Howard (). Filters and control. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Chtareva, Angelina (). How do subject idioms make YOU feel? An experiencer analysis of
subject idioms in Russian. Qualifying paper, University of Arizona.
Chtareva, Angelina (). An experiencer analysis of subject idioms in Russian. In S. Franks,
F. Gladney, and M. Tasseva-Kurktchieva (eds), Formal Approaches to Slavic Linguistics: The
South Carolina Meeting , –. Ann Arbor: Michigan Slavic Publications.
Cinque, Guglielmo (). Types of Ā-dependencies. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Cinque, Guglielmo (). Adverbs and Functional Heads. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cinque, Guglielmo, and Rizzi, Luigi (). The cartography of syntactic structures. In B. Heine
and H. Narrog (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Analysis, –. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Clark, Herbert, and Gerrig, Richard (). On the pretense theory of irony. Journal of Exper-
imental Psychology: General : –.
Cohen, Jacob (). Statistical Power Analysis for the Behavioral Sciences, nd edn. New York:
Academic Press.
Cole, Peter, and Hermon, Gabriella (). The typology of wh-movement: wh-questions in
Malay. Syntax : –.
Crain, Stephen, and Steedman, Mark (). On not being led up the garden path: on the use
of context by the psychological syntax processor. In D. Dowty, L. Karttunen, and A. Zwicky
(eds), Natural Language Parsing: Psychological, Computational, and Theoretical Perspectives,
–. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cresti, Diana (). Extraction and reconstruction. Natural Language Semantics : –.
Cuervo, Marí Cristina (). Datives at Large. Ph.D thesis, MIT.
Culicover, Peter (). One more can of beer. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Culicover, Peter, and Jackendoff, Ray (). Semantic subordination despite syntactic coordi-
nation. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Culicover, Peter, and Jackendoff, Ray (). Control is not movement. Linguistic Inquiry :
–.
Culicover, Peter, and Jackendoff, Ray (). Simpler Syntax. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Cutler, Anne (). Auditory lexical access: where do we start? In W. Marslen-Wilson (ed.),
Lexical Representation and Process, –. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
References
Dobrovie-Sorin, Carmen, and Pires de Oliveira, Roberta (). Reference to kinds in Brazilian
Portuguese: definite singulars vs. bare singulars. In A. Grønn (eds), Proceedings of SuB ,
–. University of Oslo.
Dowty, David (). Type raising, functional composition, and non-constitutent conjunction.
In R. Oehrle, E. Bach, and D. Wheeler (eds), Categorial Grammars and Natural Language
Structures, –. Dordrecht: Reidel.
Drachman, Gaberell (). Some properties of clitics (with special reference to Modern
Greek). In A. Alexiadou and A. Hall (eds), Studies on Universal Grammar and Typological
Variation, –. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Dryer, Matthew (). The pragmatics of focus-association with only. Paper presented at the
Winter Meeting of the LSA, Boston, Mass.
Dubinsky, Stanley, and Simango, Silvester Ron (). Passive and stative in Chichewa: evi-
dence for modular distinctions in grammar. Language : –.
Eilam, Aviad (). The absence of intervention effects in Amharic: evidence for a non-
structural approach. Brill’s Annual of Afroasiatic Languages and Linguistics : –.
Eilam, Aviad (). The information structural basis of focus intervention effects. MS, Uni-
versity of Pennsylvania.
Eilam, Aviad (). Explorations in the Informational Component. Ph.D thesis, University of
Pennsylvania.
Eilam, Aviad (to appear). Focus intervention in declaratives. In N. LaCara, L. Fainleib, and
Y. Park (eds), Proceedings of NELS . Amherst, Mass.: GLSA.
É. Kiss, Katalin (). Identificational focus versus information focus. Language : –.
Elbourne, Paul (). Situations and Individuals. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Embick, David (). Voice systems and the syntax/morphology interface. In H. Harley (ed.),
Papers from the UPenn/MIT Roundtable on Argument Structure and Aspect, –. Cam-
bridge, Mass.: MIT Working Papers in Linguistics.
Embick, David (). On the structure of resultative participles in English. Linguistic Inquiry
: –.
Embick, David (). Linearization and local dislocation: derivational mechanics and inter-
actions. Linguistic Analysis : –.
Embick, David (). Localism versus Globalism in Morphology and Phonology. Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
Embick, David, and Noyer, Rolf (). Movement operations after syntax. Linguistic Inquiry
: –.
Embick, David, and Noyer, Rolf (). Distributed Morphology and the syntax/morphology
interface. In G. Ramchand and C. Reiss (eds), The Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Interfaces.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Emonds, Joseph (). Root and Structure-Preserving Transformations. Ph.D thesis, MIT.
Emonds, Joseph (). Unspecified categories as the key to root constructions. In D. Adger,
C. De Cat, and G. Tsoulas (eds), Peripheries: Syntactic Edges and their Effects, –.
Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Endo, Yoshio (). Locality and Information Structure: A Cartographic Approach to Japanese.
Amsterdam: Benjamins.
References
Endriss, Cornelia (). Quantificational Topics: A Scopal Treatment of Exceptional Wide Scope
Phenomena. Dordrecht: Springer.
Epstein, Samuel David, Groat, Erich, Kawashima, Ruriko, and Kitahara, Hisatsugu (). A
Derivational Approach to Syntactic Relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Erteschik-Shir, Nomi (). On the Nature of Island Constraints. Ph.D thesis, MIT.
Erteschik-Shir, Nomi (). The Dynamics of Focus Structure. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press.
Espinal, Maria Teresa (). Bare nominals in Catalan and Spanish: their structure and mean-
ing. Lingua : –.
Evans, Gareth (). Pronouns. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Everaert, Martin (). Auxiliary selection in idiomatic constructions. MS, University of
Utrecht.
Fanselow, Gisbert (). Features, Ë-roles, and free constituent order. Linguistic Inquiry :
–.
Fanselow, Gisbert (). Free constituent order: a minimalist interface account. Folia Linguis-
tica : –.
Farkas, Donka (). On obligatory control. Linguistics and Philosophy : –.
Farkas, Donka, and de Swart, Henriëtte (). Bare nominals in the typology of indefinites.
Reader for ESSLLI’ course on the Typology of Noun Phrases.
Farkas, Donka, and de Swart, Henriëtte (). The Semantics of Incorporation: From Argument
Structure to Discourse Transparency. Stanford, Calif.: CSLI.
Farkas, Donka, and de Swart, Henriëtte (). The semantics and pragmatics of plurals.
Semantics and Pragmatics : –.
Fiengo, Robert (). Semantic Conditions on Surface Structure. Ph.D thesis, MIT.
Fiengo, Robert (). On trace theory. Linguistic Inquiry , –.
Fodor, Janet Dean (). The Linguistic Description of Opaque Contexts. Ph.D thesis, MIT.
Fodor, Jerry (). The Language of Thought. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Fodor, Jerry (). The Modularity of Mind. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Fodor, Jerry, and Lepore, Ernie (). Impossible words? Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Fodor, Jerry, and Pylyshyn, Zenon (). Connectionism and cognitive architecture: a critical
analysis. Cognition : –.
Folli, Raffaella (). Constructing Telicity in English and Italian. Ph.D thesis, University of
Oxford.
Folli, Raffaella, and Harley, Heidi (). On the licensing of causatives of directed motion:
waltzing Matilda all over. Studia Linguistica : –.
Folli, Raffaella, and Ramchand, Gillian (). Prepositions and results in Italian and English:
an analysis from event decomposition. In H. Verkuyl, A. van Hout, and H. de Swart (eds),
Perspectives on Aspect, –. Dordrecht: Springer.
Fox, Danny (). Economy and scope. Natural Language Semantics : –.
Fox, Danny (). Reconstruction, binding theory, and the interpretation of chains. Linguistic
Inquiry : –.
Fox, Danny (). Economy and Semantic Interpretation. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Fox, Danny, and Hackl, Martin (). The universal density of measurement. Linguistics and
Philosophy : –.
References
Fox, Danny, and Nissenbaum, Jon (). Extraposition and scope: a case for overt QR. In
S. Bird, A. Carnie, J. Haugen, and P. Norquest (eds), WCCFL : Proceedings of the th West
Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, –. Somerville, Mass.: Cascadilla Press.
Frascarelli, Mara (). Subjects, topics and the interpretation of referential pro. Natural
Language & Linguistic Theory : –.
Frascarelli, Mara, and Hinterhölzl, Roland (). Types of topics in German and Italian. In
K. Schwabe and S. Winkler (eds), On Information Structure, Meaning and Form, –.
Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Frazier, Lyn, and Clifton, Charles (). Construal. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Frazier, Lyn, and Fodor, Janet Dean (). The sausage machine: a new two-stage parsing
model. Cognition : –.
Freedman, Sandra, and Forster, Kenneth (). The psychological status of overgenerated
sentences. Cognition : –.
Frey, Werner (). Syntaktische Bedingungen für die semantische Interpretation: Über
Bindung, implizite Argumente und Skopus. Berlin: Akademie.
Fujii, Tomohiro (). Cycle, linearization of chains, and multiple case-checking. In S. Blaho,
L. Vicente, and E. Schoorlemmer (eds), Proceedings of ConSOLE XIII, –. Leiden: Student
Organization of Linguistics in Europe.
Gajewski, Jon (). L-analyticity and natural language. MS, MIT.
Gazdar, Gerald (). A cross-categorial semantics for coordination. Linguistics and Philoso-
phy : –.
Gazdar, Gerald, Klein, Ewan, Pullum, Geoff, and Sag, Ivan (). Generalized Phrase Structure
Grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.
Gehrke, Berit (). Passive states. In V. Demonte and L. McNally (eds), Telicity, Change, and
State: A Cross-Categorial View of Event Structure, –. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Georgala, Effi (). The translational correspondence between the Modern Greek formations
ending in -tos and -menos and their equivalent forms in German. In Proceedings of the th
International Conference on Greek Linguistics.
Gese, Helga (). Implizite Ereignisse beim Zustandspassiv. Paper presented at the workshop
‘Zugänglichkeit impliziter Ereignisse’, Universität Tübingen.
Giannakidou, Anastasia, and Merchant, Jason (). On the interpretation of null indefinite
objects in Greek. In J. Veloudis and M. Karali (eds), Studies in Greek Linguistics , –.
Thessaloniki: Aristotle University.
Giannakidou, Anastasia, and Merchant, Jason (). Why Giannis can’t scrub his plate clean:
on the absence of resultative secondary predication in Greek. In A. Mozer (ed.), Greek
Linguistics ’: Proceedings of the rd International Conference on Greek Linguistics, –.
Athens: Ellinika Grammata.
Gill, Kook-Hee, and Tsoulas, George (). Peripheral effects without peripheral syntax: the
left periphery in Korean. In D. Adger, C. D. Cat, and G. Tsoulas (eds), Peripheries: Syntactic
Edges and their Effects, –. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Giora, Rachel (). On irony and negation. Discourse Processes : –.
Giorgi, Alexandra (). About the Speaker: Toward a Syntax of Indexicality. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Giusti, Giuliana (). La sintassi dei determinanti. Padua: Unipress.
References
Giusti, Giuliana (). Parallels in clausal and nominal periphery. In M. Frascarelli (ed.),
Phases of Interpretation, –. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Givón, Talmy (). Introduction. In T. Givón (ed.), Topic Continuity in Discourse, –.
Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Glasbey, Sheila (). Let’s paint the town red for a few hours: composition of aspect in
idioms. In A. Wallington (ed.), Proceedings of the ACL Workshop: The Lexicon and Figurative
Language, Sapporo, Japan, –.
Goldberg, Adele (). Constructions: A Construction Grammar Approach to Argument Struc-
ture. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Goldsmith, John (). A principled exception to the Coordinate Structure Constraint. In
W. Eilfort, P. Kroeber, and K. Peterson (eds), CLS , Part : The General Session, –.
Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.
Green, Georgia (). Main clause phenomena in subordinate clauses. Language : –.
Grice, H. Paul (). Logic and conversation. In P. Cole and J. Morgan, Speech Acts, –.
New York: Academic Press.
Grice, H. Paul (). Further notes on logic and conversation. In P. Cole (ed.), Pragmatics,
–. New York: Academic Press.
Grice, H. Paul (). Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Grimshaw, Jane (). Extended projection. MS, Brandeis University.
Grimshaw, Jane (). Locality and extended projection. In P. Coopmans, M. Everaert, and
J. Grimshaw (eds), Lexical Specification and Insertion, –. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Groat, Erich, and O’Neil, John (). Spell-out at the LF interface. In W. Abraham, S. D.
Epstein, H. Thráinsson, and J.-W. Zwart (eds), Minimal Ideas, –. Amsterdam:
Benjamins.
Grohmann, Kleanthes (). Prolific Domains: On the Anti-locality of Movement Dependencies.
Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Grohmann, Kleanthes (). Top issues in questions: topics–topicalization–topicalizability. In
L. L.-S. Cheng and N. Corver (eds), Wh-Movement: Moving On, –. Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT Press.
Guilliot, Nicolas, and Malkawi, Nouman (). When resumption determines reconstruction.
In D. Baumer, D. Montero, and M. Scanlon (eds), Proceedings of the th West Coast Confer-
ence on Formal Linguistics, –. Somerville, Mass.: Cascadilla Press.
Guilliot, Nicolas, and Malkawi, Nouman (). Reconstruction and islandhood in Jordanian
Arabic. In M. Mughazy (ed.), Perspectives on Arabic Linguistics XX: Papers from the Twentieth
Arabic Linguistics Symposium, –. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Guilliot, Nicolas, and Malkawi, Nouman (). Weak versus strong resumption: covarying
differently. In A. Rouveret (ed.), Resumptive Pronouns at the Interfaces, –. Amsterdam:
Benjamins.
Gunter, Thomas, Wagner, Susanne, and Friederici, Angela (). Working memory and lexical
ambiguity resolution as revealed by ERPs: a difficult case for activation theories. Journal of
Cognitive Neuroscience : –.
Gutzmann, Daniel (). Eine Implikatur konventioneller Art: Der Dativus Ethicus. Linguis-
tische Berichte : –.
Haegeman, Liliane (). Interjections and phrase structure. Linguistics : –.
References
Haegeman, Liliane (). The interpretation of the particle da in West Flemish. Lingua :
–.
Haegeman, Liliane (). Verb second, the split CP and initial null subjects in early Dutch
finite clauses. Geneva Generative Papers : –.
Haegeman, Liliane (). Conditionals, factives, and the left periphery. Lingua :
–.
Haegeman, Liliane (). Operator movement and topicalisation in adverbial clauses. Folia
Linguistica : –.
Haegeman, Liliane (a). The internal syntax of adverbial clauses. Lingua : –.
Haegeman, Liliane (b). The movement derivation of conditional clauses. Linguistic Inquiry
: –.
Haegeman, Liliane (to appear). The cartography of discourse markers in West Flemish. Studia
Linguistica.
Haider, Hubert (). Deutsche Syntax: Generativ. Tübingen: Gunter Narr.
Hale, Kenneth, and Keyser, Samuel Jay (). On argument structure and the lexical expres-
sion of syntactic relations. In K. Hale and S. J. Keyser (eds), The View from Building : Essays
in Honor of Sylvain Bromberger, –. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Halle, Morris, and Marantz, Alec (). Distributed morphology and the pieces of inflection.
In K. Hale and S. J. Keyser (eds), The View from Building : Essays in Linguistics in Honor of
Sylvain Bromberger, –. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Halliday, Michael (). Notes on transitivity and theme in English, pt . Journal of Linguistics
: –.
Han, Chung-hye (). Asymmetry in the interpretation of -(n)un in Korean. In N. Akatsuka,
H. Hoji, S. Iwasaki, S.-O. Sohn, and S. Strauss (eds), Japanese/Korean Linguistics , –.
Stanford, Calif.: CSLI.
Han, Chung-hye (). The Structure and Interpretation of Imperatives: Mood and Force in
Universal Grammar. New York: Garland.
Hara, Yurie (). Grammar of Knowledge Representation: Japanese Discourse Items at Inter-
faces. Ph.D thesis, University of Delaware.
Harbour, Daniel (). Person hierarchies and geometries without hierarchies or geometries.
Paper presented at Leipzig Morphology Colloquium. Handout distributed as OPAL ,
Queen Mary, University of London (http://webspace.qmul.ac.uk/dharbour/QMOPAL--
Harbour.pdf).
Harbour, Daniel (). Morphosemantic Number: From Kiowa Noun Classes to UG Number
Features. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Harley, Heidi (). Merge, conflation, and head movement: the first sister principle revisited.
In K. Moulton and M. Wolf (eds), NELS : Proceedings of the Thirty-Fourth Annual Meeting
of the North East Linguistics Society, –. Amherst, Mass.: GLSA.
Harley, Heidi (). How do verbs get their names? Denominal verbs, manner incorporation,
and the ontology of roots in English. In N. Erteschik-Shir and T. Rapoport (eds), The Syntax
of Aspect, –. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Harley, Heidi (). The bipartite structure of verbs cross-linguistically, or, Why Mary can’t
exhibit John her paintings. In T. Silva and H. Mello (eds), Conferências do V Congresso
Internacional da Associação Brasileira de Lingüística, –. Belo Horizonte: ABRALIN and
FALE/UFMG.
References
Hohaus, Vera (). The semantics of motion verbs and comparison in Samoan. Master’s
thesis, Universität Tübingen.
Höhle, Tilman (). Subjektlücken in Koordinationen. MS, Universität zu Köln.
Höhle, Tilman (). Assumptions about asymmetric coordination in German. In J. Mascaró
and M. Nespor (eds), Grammar in Progress: GLOW Essays for Henk van Riemsdijk, –.
Dordrecht: Foris.
Hoji, Hajime (). Logical Form Constraints and Configurational Structures in Japanese. Ph.D
thesis, University of Washington, Seattle.
Holmberg, Anders (). Scandinavian stylistic fronting: how any category can become an
expletive. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Holton, David, Mackridge, Peter, and Philippaki-Warburton, Irene (). Greek: An Essential
Grammar of the Modern Language. London: Routledge.
Hooper, Joan, and Thompson, Sandra (). On the applicability of root transformations.
Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Horn, Laurence (). ‘I love me some him’: the landscape of non-argument datives. In
O. Bonami and P. Cabredo Hofherr (eds), Empirical Issues in Syntax and Semantics : Papers
from CSSP /Questions empiriques et formalisation en syntaxe et sémantique : Travaux
présentés à CSSP , –.
Hornstein, Norbert (). Logical Form: From GB to Minimalism. Oxford: Blackwell.
Hornstein, Norbert (). Movement and control. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Hornstein, Norbert (). On A-chains: a reply to Brody. Syntax : –.
Hornstein, Norbert (). Move! A Minimalist Theory of Construal. Oxford: Blackwell.
Hornstein, Norbert (). A Theory of Syntax: Minimal Operations and Universal Grammar.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Horrocks, Geoffrey, and Stavrou, Melita (). Bounding theory and Greek syntax: evidence
for wh-movement in NP. Journal of Linguistics : –.
Horvath, Julia, and Siloni, Tal (). Against the little-v hypothesis. Rivista di grammatica
generativa : –.
Horvath, Julia, and Siloni, Tal (). Active lexicon: adjectival and verbal passives. In
S. Armon-Lotem, G. Danon, and S. Rothstein (eds), Current Issues in Hebrew Linguistics,
–. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Horvath, Julia and Siloni, Tal (). Hebrew idioms: the organization of the lexical component.
Brill’s Annual of Afroasiatic Languages and Linguistics : –.
Horvath, Julia, and Siloni, Tal (to appear). The thematic phase and the architecture of gram-
mar. In M. Everaert, M. Marelj, E. Reuland, and T. Siloni (eds), Concepts, Syntax, and their
Interface. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Huang, Cheng-Teh James (). Logical Relations in Chinese and the Theory of Grammar. Ph.D
thesis, MIT.
Huang, Cheng-Teh James (). Reconstruction and the structure of VP: some theoretical
consequences. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Hust, Joel, and Brame, Michael (). Jackendoff on interpretive semantics. Linguistic Analysis
: –.
Iatridou, Sabine (). Clitics and island effects. In R. Izvorski and V. Tredinnick (eds), Uni-
versity of Pennsylvania Working Papers in Linguistics , –. Philadelphia: Penn Linguistics
Club.
References
Idsardi, William J., and Raimy, Eric (). Three types of linearization and the temporal aspects
of speech. In T. Biberauer and I. Roberts (eds), Principles of Linearization, –. Berlin:
Mouton de Gruyter.
Inkelas, Sharon, and Zec, Draga (). Serbo-Croatian pitch accent: the interaction of tone,
stress and intonation. Language : –.
Jackendoff, Ray (). Semantic Interpretation in Generative Grammar. Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT Press.
Jackendoff, Ray (). Morphological and semantic regularities in the lexicon. Language :
–.
Jackendoff, Ray (). The Architecture of the Language Faculty. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Jackendoff, Ray (). Foundations of Language: Brain, Meaning, Grammar, Evolution. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Jackendoff, Ray, and Culicover, Peter (). The semantic basis of control in English. Language
: –.
Jaeggli, Osvaldo (). Topics in Romance Syntax. Dordrecht: Foris.
Jaeggli, Osvaldo (). Three issues in the theory of clitics: case, double NPs, and extraction.
In H. Borer (ed.), The Syntax of Pronominal Clitics, –. New York: Academic Press.
Johnson, Kyle (). How far will quantifiers go? In R. Martin, D. Michaels, and J. Uriagereka
(eds), Step by Step: Essays on Minimalist Syntax in Honor of Howard Lasnik, –.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Johnson, Kyle, and Tomioka, Satoshi (). Lowering and mid-size clauses. In G. Katz,
S.-S. Kim, and W. Haike (eds), Proceedings of the Tübingen Workshop on Reconstruction,
–. Tübingen: Arbeitsberichte des Sonderforschungsbereichs.
Jouitteau, Mélanie, and Rezac, Milan (). The French ethical dative: syntactic tests.
Bucharest Working Papers in Linguistics : –.
Jun, Sun-Ah (). The Phonetics and Phonology of Korean Prosody. Ph.D thesis, Ohio State
University.
Kager, René (). Optimality Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kahnemuyipour, Arsalan (). The Syntax of Sentential Stress. Ph.D thesis, University of
Toronto.
Kamp, Hans (). A theory of truth and semantic representation. In J. Groenendijk,
T. Janssen, and M. Stokhof (eds), Formal Methods in the Study of Language, –. Ams-
terdam: Mathematisch Centrum.
Kamp, Hans, and Partee, Barbara (). Prototype theory and compositionality. Cognition :
–.
Kaplan, David (). Demonstratives: an essay on the semantics, logic, metaphysics, and
epistemology of demonstratives and other indexicals. In J. Almog, J. Perry, and H. Wettstein
(eds), Themes from Kaplan, –. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Katz, Graham (). Manner modification of state verbs. In L. McNally and C. Kennedy
(eds), Adjectives and Adverbs: Syntax, Semantics, and Discourse, –. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Kay, Paul (). An informal sketch of a formal architecture for Construction Grammar.
Grammars : –.
Kayne, Richard (). French Syntax: The Transformational Cycle. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.
References
Kayne, Richard (). Two notes on the NIC. In A. Belletti, L. Brandi, and L. Rizzi (eds), Theory
of Markedness in Generative Grammar: Proceedings of the GLOW Conference, –.
Pisa: Scuola Normale Superiore.
Kayne, Richard (). The Antisymmetry of Syntax. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Kayne, Richard (). Prepositional complementizers as attractors. Probus : –.
Kayne, Richard (in press). Why isn’t ‘this’ a complementizer? In P. Svenonius (ed.), Functional
Structure from Top to Toe: A Festschrift for Tarald Taraldsen. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kehler, Andrew (). Coherence, Reference, and the Theory of Grammar. Stanford, Calif.:
CSLI.
Kennedy, Christopher (). Antecedent-contained deletion and the syntax of quantification.
Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Kennedy, Christopher (). Vagueness and grammar: the semantics of relative and absolute
gradable adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy : –.
Kennedy, Christopher (). Modes of comparison. In M. Elliott, J. Kirby, O. Sawada,
E. Staraki, and S. Yoon (eds), Papers from the rd Annual Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic
Society, –. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.
Kennedy, Christopher, and McNally, Louise (). Scale structure, degree modification, and
the semantics of gradable predicates. Language : –.
Kim, Jieun (). A unified theory of contrastive topic and RFR. In SFU Working Papers in
Linguistics: Proceedings of the nd International Conference on East Asian Linguistics.
Kim, Shin-Sook (). Intervention effects are focus effects. In N. Akatsuka and S. Strauss
(eds), Japanese/Korean Linguistics , –. Stanford, Calif.: CSLI.
Kim, Shin-Sook (). Focus intervention effects in questions. Paper presented at Theoretical
East Asian Languages , Harvard University.
King, Tracy Holloway (). Configuring Topic and Focus in Russian. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Kiparsky, Paul (). Historical linguistics. In W. O. Dingwall (ed.), A Survey of Linguistic
Science, –. College Park, Md.: Linguistic Program, University of Maryland.
Kiparsky, Paul (). Lexical phonology and morphology. In I.-S. Yang (ed.), Linguistics in the
Morning Calm, –. Seoul: Hanshin.
Kiparsky, Paul (). Some consequences of lexical phonology. Phonology Yearbook :
–.
Kiparsky, Paul (). Opacity and cyclicity. The Linguistic Review : –.
Kirsner, Robert, and van Heuven, Vincent (). Boundary tones and the semantics of the
Dutch particles hè, hoor, zeg and joh. In C. Cremers and M. den Dikken (eds), Linguistics in
the Netherlands , –. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Kishimoto, Hideki (). Topic prominency in Japanese. The Linguistic Review : –.
Kizu, Mika (). Cleft Constructions in Japanese Syntax. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Kolliakou, Dimitra (). Nominal Constructions in Modern Greek: Implications for the Archi-
tecture of Grammar. Stanford, Calif.: CSLI.
Koontz-Garboden, Andrew (). States, Changes of State, and the Monotonicity Hypothesis.
Ph.D thesis, Stanford University.
Koontz-Garboden, Andrew (). Anticausativization. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory
: –.
References
Koopman, Hilda, and Sportiche, Dominique (). The position of subjects. Lingua :
–.
Koopman, Hilda, and Szabolcsi, Anna (). Verbal Complexes. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Kordoni, Valia (). Participle-adjective formation in Modern Greek. Paper presented at the
th International Lexical-Functional Grammar Conference, Athens.
Kornfilt, Jaklin, and Whitman, John (). Afterword: nominalizations in syntactic theory.
Lingua : –.
Koster, Jan (). Domains and Dynasties: The Radical Autonomy of Syntax. Dordrecht: Foris.
Kotzoglou, George, and Varlokosta, Spyridoula (). Clitics in Greek restrictive relatives: an
integrated approach. In M. Georgiafentis and G. Kotzoglou (eds), Reading Working Papers
in Linguistics : –.
Kratzer, Angelika (). Partition and revision: the semantics of counterfactuals. Journal of
Philosophical Logic : –.
Kratzer, Angelika (). Conditionals. In A. Farley, P. Farley, and K.-E. McCullough (eds),
Papers from the Parasession on Pragmatics and Grammatical Theory, Twenty-Second Regional
Meeting of the Chicago Linguistics Society, –. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.
Kratzer, Angelika (). The event argument and the semantics of Voice. MS, University of
Massachusetts, Amherst.
Kratzer, Angelika (). Severing the external argument from its verb. In J. Rooryck and
L. Zaring (eds), Phrase Structure and the Lexicon, –. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Kratzer, Angelika (). Beyond ‘ouch’ and ‘oops’: how descriptive and expressive meaning
interact. Paper presented at the Cornell Conference on Theories of Context Dependency.
Kratzer, Angelika (). Building statives. In L. Conathan, J. Good, D. Kavitskaya, A. Wulf,
and A. Yu (eds), Proceedings of the th Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society,
–.
Kratzer, Angelika (). Building resultatives. In C. Maienborn and A. Wöllstein-Leisten (eds),
Events in Syntax, Semantics, and Discourse, –. Tübingen: Niemeyer.
Krifka, Manfred (). A compositional semantics for multiple focus constructions. In
J. Jacobs (ed.), Informationsstruktur und Grammatik, –. Wiesbaden: Westdeutscher
Verlag.
Krifka, Manfred (). Quantifying into question acts. Natural Language Semantics : –.
Krifka, Manfred (). How to interpret ‘expletive’ negation under bevor in German. In
T. Hanneforth and G. Fanselow (eds), Language and Logos: Studies in Theoretical and Com-
putational Linguistics, –. Berlin: Akademie.
Kučera, Henry, and Francis, Winthrop Nelson (). Computational Analysis of Present-Day
American English. Providence, RI: Brown University Press.
Kuno, Susumu (). The Structure of the Japanese Language. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Kuroda, Sige-Yuki (). Generative Grammatical Studies in the Japanese Language. Ph.D
thesis, MIT.
Kuroda, Sige-Yuki (). Focusing on the matter of topic: a study of wa and ga in Japanese.
Journal of East Asian Linguistics : –.
Lakoff, George (). On generative semantics. In D. Steinberg and L. Jakobovits (eds),
Semantics: An Interdisciplinary Reader in Philosophy, Linguistics, and Psychology, –.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
References
Lakoff, George (). Frame semantic control of the Coordinate Structure Constraint. In
A. Farley, P. Farley, and K.-E. McCullough (eds), Papers from the Parasession on Pragmatics
and Grammatical Theory, Twenty-Second Regional Meeting of the Chicago Linguistics Society,
–. Chicago: Chicago Linguistic Society.
Lakoff, George, and Johnson, Mark (). Metaphors We Live By. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Lambrecht, Knud (). Information Structure and Sentence Form: Topic, Focus, and the Mental
Representations of Discourse Referents. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Landau, Idan (). Elements of Control: Structure and Meaning in Infinitival Constructions.
Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Landau, Idan (). Movement out of control. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Landau, Idan (). Movement-resistant aspects of control. In W. Davies and S. Dubinsky
(eds), New Horizons in the Analysis of Control and Raising, –. Dordrecht: Springer.
Landman, Meredith, and Morzycki, Marcin (). Event-kinds and manner modification. In
N. M. Antrim, G. Goodall, M. Schulte-Nafeh, and V. Samiian (eds), Proceedings of the Western
Conference in Linguistics (WECOL) , –. Fresno: California State University.
Larson, Richard (). Promise and the theory of control. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Lebeaux, David (). Language Acquisition and the Form of the Grammar. Ph.D thesis, Uni-
versity of Massachusetts, Amherst.
Lebeaux, David (). Where does binding theory apply? Technical Report –, NEC
Research Institute, Princeton, NJ.
Lebeaux, David (). Where does Binding Theory Apply? Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Leben, William (). Suprasegmental Phonology. Ph.D thesis, MIT.
Lechner, Winfried (). On syntactic and semantic reconstruction. Wiener Linguistische
Gazette –: –.
Lechner, Winfried (). Two types of reconstruction. Studia Linguistica : –.
Lechner, Winfried (). Semantic and syntactic effects of head movement. MS, University of
Cyprus.
Lechner, Winfried (). Extending and reducing the MLC. In A. Stepanov, G. Fanselow, and
R. Vogel (eds), Minimality Effects in Syntax, –. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Lechner, Winfried (). Interpretive effects of head-movement. MS, Universität Tübingen.
Lechner, Winfried (). Criteria for diagnosing covert movement (and some remarks on the
Duke of York). Paper presented at Diagnosing Syntax, Utrecht University/Leiden Univer-
sity, – January. Handout available from: http://users.uoa.gr/∼wlechner/Diagnostics
.pdf.
Lechner, Winfried (a). Prospects and limits of a hybrid approach to reconstruction. Paper
presented at the Workshop on Reconstruction Effects in Relative Clauses, Zentrum für Allge-
meine Sprachwissenschaft, Berlin. Handout available from: http://users.uoa.gr/∼wlechner/
Berlin.pdf.
Lechner, Winfried (b). Some formal conditions on logical syntax. Paper presented at
GLOW , University of Vienna, April –. Handout available from: http://users.uoa.gr/
∼wlechner/GLOW.pdf.
Lechner, Winfried (to appear). Diagnosing covert movement with the Duke of York and recon-
struction. In L. Cheng and N. Corver (eds), Diagnosing Syntax. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
References
Lee, Chungmin (). Contrastive topic: a locus of the interface—evidence from Korean and
English. In K. Turner et al. (ed.), The Semantics/Pragmatics Interface from Different Points of
View, –. New York: Elsevier Science.
Lee, Chungmin (). Contrastive topic and/or contrastive focus. In W. McClure (ed.),
Japanese/Korean Linguistics . Stanford, Calif.: CSLI.
Lee, Chungmin (). Contrastive (predicate) topic, intonation, and scalar meanings. In
C. Lee, M. Gordon, and D. Büring (eds), Topic and Focus: Crosslinguistic Perspectives on
Meaning and Intonation, –. Dordrecht: Springer.
Lee, Mina (). Overt Focus Movement and Minimal Information Marking. Ph.D thesis,
University of Southern California.
Lekakou, Marika (). In the Middle, Somewhat Elevated: The Semantics of Middles and its
Crosslinguistic Realization. Ph.D thesis, University College London.
Levin, Beth, and Rappaport, Malka (). The formation of adjectival passives. Linguistic
Inquiry : –.
Levinson, Lisa (). The Roots of Verbs. Ph.D thesis, New York University.
Levinson, Lisa (). Arguments for pseudo-resultative predicates. Natural Language & Lin-
guistic Theory : –.
Lewis, David (). Counterfactuals and comparative possibility. Journal of Philosophical Logic
: –.
Li, Yafei (). X -binding and verb incorporation. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Lieber, Rochelle (). On the Organization of the Lexicon. Ph.D thesis, MIT.
Link, Godehard (). The logical analysis of plurals and mass terms: a lattice-theoretical
approach. In R. Bäuerle, C. Schwarze, and A. von Stechow (eds), Meaning, Use, and Inter-
pretation of Language, –. Berlin: de Gruyter.
Lochbihler, Bethany, and Mathieu, Éric (). Phrasal noun incorporation in Ojibwe. Paper
presented at the th Algonquian Conference, York University, Toronto.
Lohndal, Terje, and Pietroski, Paul (). Interrogatives, instructions, and I-languages: an
I-semantics for questions. Linguistic Analysis : –.
Longobardi, Giuseppe (). Extraction from NP and the proper notion of head government.
In A. Giorgi and G. Longobardi (eds), The Syntax of Noun Phrases: Configuration, Parameters,
and Empty Categories, –. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Longobardi, Giuseppe (). Reference and proper names: a theory of N-movement in syntax
and Logical Form. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Mackridge, Peter (). The Modern Greek Language: A Descriptive Analysis of Standard Mod-
ern Greek. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Maienborn, Claudia (a). Das Zustandspassiv: Grammatische Einordnung—Bildungs-
beschränkung—Interpretationsspielraum. Zeitschrift für Germanistische Linguistik :
–.
Maienborn, Claudia (b). On Davidsonian and Kimian states. In I. Comorovski and K. von
Heusinger (eds), Existence: Semantics and Syntax, –. Dordrecht: Springer.
Maienborn, Claudia (). Strukturausbau am Rande der Wörter: Adverbiale Modifikatoren
beim Zustandspassiv. In S. Engelberg, A. Holler, and K. Proost (eds), Sprachliches Wissen
zwischen Lexikon und Grammatik, –. Berlin: de Gruyter.
Marantz, Alec (). On the Nature of Grammatical Relations. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
References
McGinnis, Martha (). On the systematic aspect of idioms. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
McGinnis, Martha (). Painting the wall red for a few hours: a reply to Glasbey ().
Snippets : –. http://www.ledonline.it/snippets/allegati/snippets.pdf.
McGinnis, Martha (). Phi-feature competition in morphology and syntax. In D. Harbour,
D. Adger, and S. Béjar (eds), Phi Theory: Phi-Features across Modules and Interfaces, –.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
McIntyre, Andrew (). Adjectival passives and adjectival participles in English. In
A. Alexiadou and F. Schäfer, Non-Canonical Passives, –. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
McKoon, Gail, and Ratcliff, Roger (). Meaning through syntax: language comprehension
and the reduced relative clause construction. Psychological Review : –.
McNally, Louise (). On recent formal analyses of topic. In J. Ginzburg, Z. Khasidashvili,
C. Vogel, J.-J. Lévy, and E. Vallduví (eds), The Tbilisi Symposium on Language, Logic, and
Computation: Selected Papers, –. Stanford, Calif.: CSLI.
McRae, Ken, Spivey-Knowlton, Michael, and Tanenhaus, Michael (). Modeling the influ-
ence of thematic fit (and other constraints) in on-line sentence comprehension. Journal of
Memory and Language : –.
Merchant, Jason (). The Syntax of Silence: Sluicing, Islands, and the Theory of Ellipsis.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Merchant, Jason (). Fragments and ellipsis. Linguistics and Philosophy : –.
Merchant, Jason (a). Polyvalent case, geometric hierarchies, and split ergativity. In
J. Bunting, S. Desai, R. Peachey, C. Straughn, and Z. Tomkova (eds), Proceedings of the nd
Annual Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, vol. : The Parassesions, –. Chicago:
Chicago Linguistic Society.
Merchant, Jason (b). ‘Small structures’: a sententialist perspective. In Progovac et al. (:
–).
Merchant, Jason (). Variable island repair under ellipsis. In K. Johnson (ed.), Topics in
Ellipsis, –. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mertens, Piet, Goldmann, Jean-Philippe, Wehrli, Éric, and Gaudinat, Arnaud (). La syn-
thèse de l’intonation à partir de structures syntaxiques riches. TAL (Traitement Automatique
des Langues) : –.
Michaels, Jennifer (). To alternate or not to alternate: what is the boundary? Paper pre-
sented at the th annual meeting of the North East Linguistic Society, MIT.
Michelioudakis, Dimitris (). Dative Arguments and Abstract Case in Greek. Ph.D thesis,
University of Cambridge.
Michelson, Truman (). Notes on Algonquian languages. International Journal of American
Linguistics : –.
Miller, George, and Chomsky, Noam (). Finitary models of language users. In R. D. Luce,
R. Bush, and E. Galanter (eds), Handbook of Mathematical Psychology, vol. , –. New
York: Wiley.
Miyagawa, Shigeru (). Agreements that occur mainly in the main clause. In L. Aelbrecht,
L. Haegeman, and R. Nye (eds), Main Clause Phenomena: New Horizons, –. Amster-
dam: Benjamins.
Mohanan, Karuvannur Puthanveettil (). The Theory of Lexical Phonology. Dordrecht:
Reidel.
References
Newell, Heather (). Aspects of the Phonology and Morphology of Phases. Ph.D thesis, McGill
University.
Newmeyer, Frederick (). On split CPs, uninterpretable features, and the ‘perfectness’ of
language. In B. Shaer, W. Frey, and C. Maienborn (eds), ZAS Working Papers : Proceedings
of the Dislocated Elements Workshop, –. Berlin: Zentrum für Allgemeine Sprachwis-
senschaft.
Nicol, Janet, Forster, Ken, and Veres, Csaba (). Subject–verb agreement processes in com-
prehension. Journal of Memory and Language : –.
Nunberg, Geoffrey, Sag, Ivan, and Wasow, Thomas (). Idioms. Language : –.
Nunes, Jairo (). Linearization of Chains and Sideward Movement. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT
Press.
Nunes, Jairo, and Uriagereka, Juan (). Cyclicity and extraction domains. Syntax : –.
O’Bryan, Erin (). Event Structure in Language Comprehension. Ph.D thesis, University of
Arizona, Tucson.
O’Bryan, Erin, Folli, Raffaella, Harley, Heidi, and Bever, Thomas G. (in preparation). Event
structure affects on-line sentence comprehension. MS, University of Arizona and University
of Ulster.
Oda, Toshiko (). Degree constructions in Japanese. Ph.D thesis, University of Connecticut,
Storrs.
Ormazabal, Javier, and Romero, Juan (). The object agreement constraint. Natural Lan-
guage & Linguistic Theory : –.
Oshima, David (). Morphological vs. phonological contrastive topic marking. In
R. Edwards, P. Midtlyng, C. Sprague, and K. Stensrud (eds), Proceedings from the st Annual
Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, –.
Oyharçabal, Bernard (). Verb agreement with non arguments: on allocutive agreement. In
J. I. Hualde and J. Ortiz de Urbina (eds), Generative Studies in Basque Linguistics, –.
Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Pafel, Jürgen (). Skopus und Logische Struktur. Arbeitspapiere des Sonderforschungs-
bereichs , Bericht . Universität Tübingen.
Panagiotidis, Phoevos (). Pronouns, Clitics, and Empty Nouns: ‘Pronominality’ and Licens-
ing in Syntax. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Parsons, Terence (). Events in the Semantics of English: A Study in Subatomic Semantics.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Partee, Barbara (). Compositionality. In F. Landman and F. Veltman (eds), Varieties of
Formal Semantics, –. Dordrecht: Foris.
Partee, Barbara (). Noun phrase interpretation and type-shifting principles. In J. Groe-
nendijk, D. de Jongh, and M. Stokhof (eds), Studies in Discourse Representation Theory and
the Theory of Generalized Quantifiers, –. Dordrecht: Foris.
Partee, Barbara, and Rooth, Mats (). Generalized conjunction and type ambiguity. In
R. Bäuerle, C. Schwarze, and A. von Stechow (eds), Meaning, Use, and Interpretation of
Language, –. Berlin: de Gruyter.
Partington, Alan (). Irony and reversal of evaluation. Journal of Pragmatics : –.
Pearson, Hazel (). How to do comparison in a language without degrees: a semantics for
the comparative in Fijian. In M. Prinzhorn, V. Schmitt, and S. Zobel (eds), Proceedings of
Sinn und Bedeutung , –.
References
Percus, Orin (). Constraints on some other variables in syntax. Natural Language Semantics
: –.
Percus, Orin (). Indexicality and compositional semantics. Handouts for a class taught at
the European Summer School for Logic, Language and Information, Ljubljana.
Percus, Orin, and Sauerland, Uli (). Pronoun movement in dream reports. In M. Kadowaki
and S. Kawahara (eds), Proceedings of NELS , –. Amherst, Mass.: GLSA.
Perlmutter, David (). Impersonal passives and the unaccusative hypothesis. In Proceedings
of the th Annual Meeting of the Berkeley Linguistics Society, –.
Perlmutter, David (). The split morphology hypothesis: evidence from Yiddish. In
M. Hammond and M. Noonan (eds), Theoretical Morphology: Approaches in Modern Lin-
guistics, –. New York: Academic Press.
Pesetsky, David (). Zero Syntax: Experiencers and Cascades. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Pesetsky, David (). Some optimality principles of sentence pronunciation. In P. Barbosa,
D. Fox, P. Hagstrom, M. McGinnis, and D. Pesetsky (eds), Is the Best Good Enough? Optimality
and Competition in Syntax, –. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Pesetsky, David (). Phrasal Movement and its Kin. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Pesetsky, David, and Torrego, Esther (). T-to-C movement: causes and consequences. In
M. Kenstowicz (ed.), Ken Hale: A Life in Language, –. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Philippaki-Warburton, Irene (). Word order in Modern Greek. Transactions of the Philo-
logical Society : –.
Philippaki-Warburton, Irene, Varlokosta, Spyridoula, Georgiafentis, Michalis, and Kotzoglou,
George (). Moving from theta-positions: pronominal clitic doubling in Greek. Lingua
: –.
Piggott, Glyne (). Aspects of Odawa Morphophonemics. New York: Garland.
Piggott, Glyne (). Extrametricality and Ojibwa stress. McGill Working Papers in Linguistics
: –.
Piggott, Glyne, and Grafstein, Ann (). An Ojibwa Lexicon. Ottawa: National Museum of
Man, Mercury Series, Canadian Ethnology Service Paper .
Piggott, Glyne, and Newell, Heather (). Syllabification and the spell-out of phases in Ojibwa
words. In E. Dobler and Y. Furukawa (eds), McGill Working Papers in Linguistics , –.
Piggott, Glyne, and Newell, Heather (). Syllabification, stress, and derivation by phase in
Ojibwa. MS, McGill University.
Piñango, Maria, Zurif, Edgar, and Jackendoff, Ray (). Real-time processing implications of
enriched composition at the syntax–semantics interface. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research
: –.
Poletto, Cecilia, and Zanuttini, Raffaella (). Sentential particles and remnant movement.
In P. Benincà and N. Munaro (eds), Mapping the Left Periphery: The Cartography of Syntactic
Structures, vol. , –. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pollard, Carl, and Sag, Ivan (). Head-Driven Phrase Structure Grammar. Stanford, Calif.:
CSLI.
Pollock, Jean-Yves (). Verb movement, Universal Grammar, and the structure of IP.
Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Posner, Roland (). Semantics and pragmatics of sentence connectives in natural language.
In J. Searle, F. Kiefer, and M. Bierwisch (eds), Speech Act Theory and Pragmatics, –.
Dordrecht: Reidel.
References
Postal, Paul (). Three Investigations of Extraction. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Postal, Paul, and Ross, John Robert (). A problem of adverb preposing. Linguistic Inquiry
: –.
Potts, Chris (). The Logic of Conventional Implicatures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Prince, Alan, and Smolensky, Paul (). Optimality Theory: constraint interaction in gen-
erative grammar. New Brunswick, N.J.: Rutgers University Center for Cognitive Science
Technical Report .
Pritchett, Bradley (). Grammatical Competence and Parsing Performance. Chicago: Univer-
sity of Chicago Press.
Progovac, Ljiljana (). Negative and Positive Polarity: A Binding Approach. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Progovac, Ljiljana (). Structure for coordination, part . Glot International : –.
Progovac, Ljiljana (). The syntax of nonsententials: small clauses and phrases at the root.
In Progovac et al. (: –).
Progovac, Ljiljana, Paesani, Kate, Casielles, Eugenia, and Barton, Ellen (). The Syntax of
Nonsententials: Multidisciplinary Perspectives. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Pustejovsky, James (). The geometry of events. In C. Tenny (ed.), Studies in Generative
Approaches to Aspect, –. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Lexicon Project Working Papers, .
Pylkkänen, Liina (). Introducing Arguments. Ph.D thesis, MIT.
Raimy, Eric (). The Phonology and Morphology of Reduplication. Berlin: Mouton de
Gruyter.
Raimy, Eric (). Asymmetry and linearization in phonology. In A. M. Di Sciullo (ed.),
Asymmetry in Grammar, vol. : Morphology, Phonology, Acquisition, –. Amsterdam:
Benjamins.
Ralli, A. (). MÔÒˆÔÎÔ„fl· Athens: Patakis.
Ramchand, Gillian (). Verb Meaning and the Lexicon: A First Phase Syntax. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Ramchand, Gillian (). Minimalist semantics. In C. Boeckx (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of
Linguistic Minimalism, –. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rapp, Irene (). Zustand? Passiv? Überlegungen zum sogenannten ‘Zustandspassiv’.
Zeitschrift für Sprachwissenschaft : –.
Rapp, Irene (). The attributive past participle: structure and temporal interpretation. In
C. Féry and W. Sternefeld (eds), Audiatur vox Sapientiae: A Festschrift for Arnim von Stechow,
–. Berlin: Akademie.
Reich, Ingo (). What asymmetric coordination in German tells us about the syntax and
semantics of conditionals. Natural Language Semantics : –.
Reinhart, Tanya (). Pragmatics and linguistics: an analysis of sentence topics. Philosophica
: –.
Reinhart, Tanya (). Wh-in-situ in the framework of the Minimalist Program. Natural
Language Semantics : –.
Reinhart, Tanya (). The theta system: an overview. Theoretical Linguistics : –.
Richards, Marc (). Object Shift, Scrambling, and Symmetrical Syntax. Ph.D thesis, Univer-
sity of Cambridge.
Richards, Marc (). On feature inheritance: an argument from the Phase Impenetrability
Condition. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
References
Richards, Norvin (). Lardil ‘case stacking’ and the structural/inherent case distinction. MS,
MIT.
Richards, Norvin (). Uttering Trees. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Ritter, Elizabeth (). Two functional categories in noun phrases: evidence from Modern
Hebrew. In S. Rothstein (ed.), Perspectives on Phrase Structure: Heads and Licensing, –.
New York: Academic Press.
Ritter, Elizabeth (). Where’s gender? Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Ritter, Elizabeth, and Rosen, Sarah (). Delimiting events in syntax. In M. Butt and
W. Geuder (eds), The Projection of Arguments: Lexical and Syntactic Constraints, –.
Stanford, Calif.: CSLI.
Rivero, María Luisa (). Intensionality, high applicatives, and aspect: involuntary state con-
structions in Bulgarian and Slovenian. Natural Language & Linguistic Theory : –.
Rizzi, Luigi (). Relativized Minimality. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Rizzi, Luigi (). The fine structure of the left periphery. In L. Haegeman (ed.), Elements of
Grammar: Handbook of Generative Syntax, –. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Rizzi, Luigi (). Locality and left periphery. In A. Belletti (ed.), Structures and Beyond: The
Cartography of Syntactic Structures, –. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
RMS (–). Reènik srpskohrvatskoga književnog jezika (–). Novi Sad–Zagreb: Matica
srpska–Matica hrvatska.
Roberge, Yves, and Troberg, Michelle (). The high applicative syntax of the dativus com-
modi/incommodi in Romance. Probus : –.
Roberts, Ian (). Agreement and Head Movement: Clitics, Incorporation, and Defective Goals.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Romero, Maribel (). Focus and Reconstruction Effects in Wh-Phrases. Ph.D thesis, Univer-
sity of Massachusetts, Amherst.
Rooth, Mats (). Association with Focus. Ph.D thesis, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.
Rooth, Mats (). A theory of focus interpretation. Natural Language Semantics : –.
Rooth, Mats (). Second occurrence focus and Relativized Stress F. In M. Zimmermann and
C. Féry (eds), Information Structure: Theoretical, Typological, and Experimental Approaches,
–. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rosen, Sara (). The syntactic representation of linguistic events. Glot International : –.
Ross, John Robert (). Constraints on Variables in Syntax. Ph.D thesis, MIT.
Ross, John Robert (). On declarative sentences. In R. Jacobs and P. Rosenbaum (eds),
Readings in English Transformational Grammar, –. Waltham, Mass.: Ginn.
Rossi, Mario (). L’intonation, le système du français: description et modélisation. Paris:
Ophrys.
Roussou, Anna, and Tsimpli, Ianthi Maria (). On the interaction of case and definiteness
in Modern Greek. In I. Philippaki-Warburton, K. Nicolaidis, and M. Sifianou (eds), Themes
in Greek Linguistics, –. Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Rouveret, Alain (). Phasal agreement and reconstruction. In C. Otero, R. Freidin, and
M.-L. Zubizarreta (eds), Foundational Issues in Linguistic Theory: Essays in Honor of Jean-
Roger Vergnaud, –. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Rullmann, Hotze (). Maximality in the Semantics of Wh-Constructions. Ph.D thesis, Uni-
versity of Massachusetts, Amherst.
References
Sternefeld, Wolfgang (). Syntactic vs. semantic reconstruction. Technical Report SfS-
Report--, Universität Tübingen.
Sternefeld, Wolfgang (). Wide scope in situ. In T. Hanneforth and G. Fanselow (eds),
Language and Logos: Studies in Theoretical and Computational Linguistics, –. Berlin:
Akademie.
Sternefeld, Wolfgang, and Konietzko, Andreas (). Telescoping by continuations. Paper
presented at the Workshop on Reconstruction Effects in Relative Clauses, Zentrum für
Allgemeine Sprachwissenschaft, Berlin.
Stevenson, Suzanne (). Competition and recency in a hybrid network model of syntactic
disambiguation. Journal of Psycholinguistic Research : –.
Stevenson, Suzanne, and Merlo, Paola (). Lexical structure and parsing complexity. Lan-
guage and Cognitive Processes : –.
Stone, Megan (). Idioms and domains of interpretation. Talk presented at the Arizona
Linguistics Circle .
Stone, Megan (in preparation). Idioms in the Lexicon: Theoretical and Experimental Perspectives.
Ph.D thesis, University of Arizona, Tucson.
Stowell, Tim (). Origins of Phrase Structure. Ph.D thesis, MIT.
Suñer, Margarita (). The role of agreement in clitic doubling constructions. Natural Lan-
guage & Linguistic Theory : –.
Svenonius, Peter (). C-selection as feature-checking. Studia Linguistica : –.
Svenonius, Peter (). Extending the extension condition to discontinuous idioms. In
P. Pica, J. Rooryck, and J. van Craenenbroeck (eds), Linguistic Variation Yearbook , –.
Amsterdam: Benjamins.
Szabolcsi, Anna, and Zwarts, Frans (). Weak islands and an algebraic semantics for scope
taking. Natural Language Semantics : –.
Tabossi, Patrizia, Spivey-Knowlton, Michael, McRae, Ken, and Tanenhaus, Michael ().
Semantic effects on syntactic ambiguity resolution: evidence for a constraint-based resolu-
tion process. In C. Umiltà and M. Moscovitch (eds), Attention and Performance XV: Con-
scious and Unconscious Information Processing, –. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Takahashi, Shoichi (). Decomposition and Identity. Ph.D thesis, MIT.
Takahashi, Shoichi (). The composition and interpretation of tough movement. Paper
presented at GLOW , – April, University of Vienna.
Takahashi, Shoichi, and Hulsey, Sarah (). Wholesale late merger: beyond the A/Ā distinc-
tion. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Tenny, Carol (). The aspectual interface hypothesis. In I. Sag and A. Szabolcsi (eds), Lexical
Matters, –. Stanford, Calif.: CSLI.
Terzi, Arhonto (). Clitic combinations, their hosts, and their ordering. Natural Language
& Linguistic Theory : –.
Tomioka, Naoko (). Resultative Constructions: Cross-Linguistic Variation and the Syntax–
Semantics Interface. Ph.D thesis, McGill University.
Tomioka, Naoko (). Word-internal modification without the syntax–morphology inter-
face. In R. Folli and C. Ulbrich (eds), Interfaces in Linguistics: New Research Perspectives,
–. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
References
Tomioka, Satoshi (). Pragmatics of LF intervention effects: Japanese and Korean wh-
interrogatives. Journal of Pragmatics : –.
Tomioka, Satoshi (). Contrastive topics operate on speech acts. In M. Zimmermann and
C. Féry (eds), Information Structure: Theoretical, Typological, and Experimental Perspectives,
–. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Townsend, David, and Bever, Thomas G. (). The use of higher-level constraints in moni-
toring for a speaker demonstrates functionally distinct levels of representation in discourse
comprehension. Language and Cognitive Processes : –.
Townsend, David, and Bever, Thomas G. (). Sentence Comprehension: The Integration of
Habits and Rules. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Travis, Lisa deMena (). The syntax of adverbs. In D. Fekete and Z. Laubitz (eds), McGill
Working Papers in Linguistics: Special Issue on Comparative Germanic Syntax, –.
Travis, Lisa deMena (). Event Phrase and a theory of functional categories. In P. Koskinen
(ed.), Proceedings of the Canadian Linguistic Association, –. Toronto Working Papers
in Linguistics.
Travis, Lisa deMena (). The l-syntax/s-syntax boundary: evidence from Austronesian. In
I. Paul, V. Phillips, and L. Travis (eds), Formal Issues in Austronesian Linguistics, –.
Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Truswell, Robert (). Events, Phrases, and Questions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tschizmarova, Ievelina (). Hedging functions of the Bulgarian discourse marker xajde.
Journal of Pragmatics : –.
Tsimpli, Ianthi Maria (). Focusing in Modern Greek. In K. É. Kiss (ed.), Discourse Config-
urational Languages, –. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tsimpli, Ianthi-Maria, and Papadopoulou, Despina (). Aspect and argument realization: a
study on antecedentless null objects in Greek. Lingua : –.
Tsoulas, George (). On the grammar of number and mass terms in Greek. In C. Halpert,
J. Hartman, and D. Hill (eds), Proceedings of the Workshop in Greek Syntax and Semantics
at MIT, –. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Working Papers in Linguistics.
Tsoulas, George, and Kural, Murat (). Indexical pronouns as bound variables. In S. Bird,
A. Carnie, J. Haugen, and P. Norquest (eds), Proceedings of the th West Coast Conference
on Formal Linguistics, –.
Txurruka, Isabel (). The natural language conjunction and. Linguistics and Philosophy :
–.
Uriagereka, Juan (). Multiple spell-out. In S. Epstein and N. Hornstein (eds), Working
Minimalism, –. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Valentine, J. Randolph (). Nishnaabemwin Reference Grammar. Toronto: University of
Toronto Press.
Vallduví, Enric (). The Informational Component. Ph.D thesis, University of Pennsylvania,
Philadelphia.
Vallduví, Enric, and Engdahl, Elisabet (). The linguistic realization of information packag-
ing. Linguistics : –.
Vallduví, Enric, and Vilkuna, Maria (). On rheme and kontrast. In P. Culicover and
L. McNally (eds), The Limits of Syntax, –. New York: Academic Press.
References
van Craenenbroeck, Jeroen (). Invisible last resort: a note on clefts as the underlying source
for sluicing. Lingua : –.
van Craenenbroeck, Jeroen, and Haegeman, Liliane (). The derivation of subject-initial V.
Linguistic Inquiry : –.
van Hout, Angeliek (). Event Semantics of Verb Frame Alternations: A Case Study of Dutch
and its Acquisition. Ph.D thesis, Universiteit van Tilburg.
van Riemsdijk, Henk (). Categorial feature magnetism: the endocentricity and distribution
of projections. Journal of Comparative Germanic Linguistics : –.
Vendler, Zeno (). Linguistics in Philosophy. Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press.
Vermeulen, Reiko (). Non-topical wa-phrases in Japanese. In R. Folli and C. Ulbrich (eds),
Interfaces in Linguistics: New Research Perspectives, –. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Vermeulen, Reiko (). Word order variation and information structure in Japanese and
Korean. In A. Neeleman and R. Vermeulen (eds), The Syntax of Topic, Focus and Contrast: An
Interface-Based Approach (Studies in Generative Grammar), –. Berlin and New York:
Mouton de Gruyter.
Volpe, Mark (). Japanese Morphology and its Theoretical Consequences: Derivational Mor-
phology in Distributed Morphology. Ph.D thesis, State University of New York, Stony Brook.
von Fintel, Kai (). Restrictions on Quantifier Domains. Ph.D thesis, University of Mas-
sachusetts, Amherst.
von Fintel, Kai, and Iatridou, Sabine (). Anatomy of a modal construction. Linguistic
Inquiry : –.
von Stechow, Arnim (). Comparing semantic theories of comparison. Journal of Semantics
: –.
von Stechow, Arnim (). Syntax und Semantik. In A. von Stechow and D. Wunderlich
(eds), Semantik: Ein Handbuch der zeitgenössischen Forschung/Semantics: An International
Handbook of Contemporary Research, –. Berlin: de Gruyter.
von Stechow, Arnim (). The different readings of wieder ‘again’: a structural account.
Journal of Semantics : –.
von Stechow, Arnim (). German participles II in Distributed Morphology. MS, Universität
Tübingen.
Wagner, Michael (). Contrastive topics decomposed. MS, Cornell University.
Wasow, Thomas (). Transformations and the lexicon. In P. Culicover, T. Wasow, and
J. Bresnan (eds), Formal Syntax, –. New York: Academic Press.
Werle, Adam (). Word, Phrase, and Clitic Prosody in Bosnian, Serbian, and Croatian. Ph.D
thesis, University of Massachusetts, Amherst.
Wiklund, Anna-Lena, Bentzen, Kristine, Hrafnbjargarson, Gunnar Hrafn, and Hróarsdóttir,
Thorbjörg (). On the distribution and illocution of V in Scandinavian that-clauses.
Lingua : –.
Williams, Edwin (). Predication. Linguistic Inquiry : –.
Williams, Edwin (). Remarks on lexical knowledge. Lingua : –.
Williams, Edwin (). Representation Theory. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Wilson, Deirdre (). Word meaning, concepts and procedures. Paper presented at the
Conference on Word Meaning, University of Oslo.
References
de dicto interpretation –, –, ellipsis , –, –, , , , –
deductive system , –, , –, – Empty Category Principle , , ,
DS–LF model , , , –, – encapsulation , , , , , –,
degree , , , –, –, , – encyclopedia , , ,
DegP –, English , , –, –, –, , –,
deletion: , , , –, –, –, , –,
of case feature –, –, , –, –, –,
of copies , , , –, –, , , , –, –,
of vowels , , – , , , , , , –, ,
subnominal , –, , , , , –, –, ,
de re interpretation –, , –, , , –, –,
derivational morphology –, , , , –, –, –, , –,
, –, –, , , –, –, , ,
derivational workspace, see workspace , , –
derived subject , , –, ; see also enrichment, pragmatic , , ,
passive; raising epenthesis , –, ,
destressing, see deaccenting epistemic vigilance ,
direct address –, –, –, , EPP, see Extended Projection Principle
discourse particle, see particle, discourse e-type pronoun
disjoint reference , –, evaluative expression –, –, –,
disjunction –, –, , , , –, –
– EvalP ,
dislocation , , , –, event , , –, –, , , –, ,
left-dislocation –, , –, –, , , –,
Clitic Left Dislocation , –, , , , , –, –, ,
, –, –, –, –
right-dislocation , –, , , , accomplishment
achievement
Distributed Morphology , , , , , , activity
, , , , , endpoint –, –
ditransitive , , , , eventive predicate , , , , ,
D-linking –, , , , ,
DM, see Distributed Morphology eventivizer , , , –, –, ,
domain: , –, –
binding , , event kind , –, –, –
Case , , Event Structure Processing hypothesis –,
cyclic , , ; see also phase –, ,
locality , , homogeneity ,
of contrast –, process –, ,
of deaccenting , punctuality
of special meaning , –, , , subevents
, –, , see also aspect; causation; modifier,
of word-formation , , , , event–related; state
prosodic –, , ; see also intonational evidentiality , –, –
phrase exclamative
Spell-out, see phase Extended Projection Principle ,
see also Condition on Extraction Domain; Extension Condition , , ,
locality; phase eye-tracking –, –
double object construction, see ditransitive
D-structure , faithfulness , –
Dutch , , –, , – feature checking , , ,
focus , , , –, –, –,
economy , , , , –, –, –,
Scope Economy , , , –, , , , –, , ,
ECP, see Empty Category Principle , –
Edge Property , – contrastive focus , –
Index
scope trapping , –, , , –; see Romance languages , , , , ,
also countertrapping effects ; see also Catalan; French; Italian;
variable scope, see quantifier, scope Romanian
inversion Romanian , –, –, , –
question , –, , –, –, root (morphology) , , , , , , ,
, , , , –, , , , –, –, –, –,
, –, –, ,
alternative –, –, –, , , root clause , , ,
root phenomena , –, –, –,
tag , –,
wh- –, –, –, –, , , Russian , , ,
, ,
pair–list reading of scope, see quantifier, scope
Question Under Discussion – scrambling , , , , , –, , ,
questionnaire , –, –,
long-distance , ,
QR, see quantifier, Quantifier Raising self-paced reading , –, –, , –
semantic drift , ,
raising , , , , –, , , , , , semiproductivity –,
, , Semitic languages , see also Hebrew
copy-raising sentence processing , , , , –, –,
reanalysis, see sentence processing –, –
reconstruction , –, , –, –, , reanalysis –
–, –, Serbo-Croatian , , –
for binding , –, –, , –, serial ordering , , , , –
for scope , , –, –, –, –, situation variable, see binding of situation
variable
Semantic Reconstruction (SemR) –, , Slovenian ,
, , –, , sluicing –, –, –
Syntactic Reconstruction (SynR) –, , Spanish , , , –, , –,
, , Peruvian ,
referential opacity, see de dicto interpretation; speaker change monitoring –, –,
opaque context Spec–head agreement , ,
referential transparency, see de re interpretation specificational construction , , ; see
relative clause , , , , –, , also pseudocleft
– speech act , , ,
as island, see Complex Noun Phrase Speech Act Phrase , , , , ,
Constraint –, –
free , –, –, –, , – Spell-out , , , , , , –, ,
non-restrictive , –, , , , , –, ,
raising analysis of ,
reduced –, –, –, Local Spell-out –, ,
restrictive , , , , –, , Standard Theory
–, , state –, , , –, –, , ,
zero relative –
Representation Theory change of –; see also aspect, telic; event,
REST, see Revised Extended Standard Theory accomplishment; event, achievement
restrictor , –, , –, , – characteristic state –, , , ,
restructuring result state –, , –, –, ,
result, see event, endpoint; participle, passive, , , , , –, ,
resultative; state, result state ResultP –
resumption , , , , –, –, state kind ,
stative predicate , , , , –,
Revised Extended Standard Theory , , , , , ,
right-dislocation, see dislocation stativizer , ,
Index
In preparation
The Syntax of Roots and the Roots of Syntax
Edited by Artemis Alexiadou, Hagit Borer, and
Florian Schäfer