GELL - How To Read A Map
GELL - How To Read A Map
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
Royal Anthropological Institute of Great Britain and Ireland is collaborating with JSTOR
to digitize, preserve and extend access to Man
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
HOW TO READ A MAP: REMARKS ON THE
PRACTICAL LOGIC OF NAVIGATION
ALFRED GELL
Two theories of navigation are compared: first, the theory of mental maps, currently in use
among psychologists and social geographers interested in problems of spatial cognition; and
secondly the theory of 'practical mastery' deriving from P. Bourdieu. 'Mental maps' do not seem
to resemble artefactual maps, or fulfil the same functions. Everyday navigation cannot, however,
be understood as merely habitual. A new theory of navigation is proposed, based on the logical
distinction between non-token-indexical 'maps' and token-indexical 'images'. It is argued that the
function of a map is to generate images, and that the navigational utility of images arises because
they are referrable to coordinates on a map. This theory is applied to Micronesian navigation and
to the material presented by Frake in this issue. It is argued that all navigation, from the simplest to
the most sophisticated, has a uniform logical basis.
The article by Professor Frake (this issue, pp. 252-68) demonstrates, in a most
convincing way, the ingenuity of which the unlettered are capable in the
performance of cognitively challenging tasks. He argues that the data he has
unearthed on medieval navigation, like the better-known material provided by
Gladwin (I970) and Lewis (I972) on Micronesian navigation, show that the
'primitive' mind cannot be contrasted to the modern one as 'dumb' versus
'smart', a position he attributes to Hallpike (I 979) in particular. He believes that
tasks performed by non-literate people in the course of their everyday lives
'can be seen as displays of high orders of cognitive ability' (p. 253). I concur
emphatically with Frake's view, but I am not sure that the material he discusses
is really very damaging to the Hallpike position, as spelled out in chapter 3 of
Foundations ofprimitive thought (I979: 94 sqq.).
Hallpike is very explicit in stating that 'primitives' are not inferior in
intelligence to 'modern' men, but that it is the nature of their technological
milieu, which lacks the kind of 'challenges' which call forth the powers of
'operatory intelligence' in literate and/or technologically advanced societies,
which is responsible for the prevalence of 'pre-operatory' modes of thought
among them. In selecting the example of navigation in the tidal North Sea and
the Atlantic seaboard Frake has focused attention on a set of environmental
'givens' offering the prospect of both enormous hazards and rich rewards
-exactly the kind of situation which would challenge men to seek technical
solutions to the technical problems involved.
Hallpike is perfectly prepared to concede that the Micronesian navigators use
techniques which qualify as 'operational' in the Piagetian sense (I979: 309-I I). I
am sure that he would be equally ready to admit medieval navigators to this
Man (N.S.) 20, 27I-86
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
272 ALFRED GELL
category, given the material adduced by Frake. These facts support his basic
contention that in order to perform cognitively complex tasks, Piagetian
intelligence, up to the operatory stage, in necessary. This is also implicitly
accepted by Frake.
The danger for the point of view which Frake is trying to sustain arises just
here. Can one really assert that navigating a boat, without a chart or a magnetic
compass, is really an 'everyday' task? Is is not rather a very special task,
requiring long training, memorisation of a mass of detailed information,
and considerable mental agility in applying this fund of information to the
ever-changing circumstances of an actual sea voyage? The only weakness in
Hallpike's argument exposed by Frake is its reliance on the rather tautologous
principle that, other things being equal, primitive thought is primitive, except
where it turns out that other things are not equal, and then primitive thought
becomes non-primitive. And things are not equal when men are faced with
difficult navigational tasks, which they must either solve or put their lives at
very great risk.
I believe that, in order to establish the cognitivist or 'intellectualist' position
espoused by Frake in his opening remarks, it is necessary to provide a more
comprehensive account of 'everyday' navigation than either he himself pro-
vides, or is to be found in the writings of the cognitive psychologists on whom
he bases himself. What needs to be shown is that everyday navigation, not of the
kind seen as technically specialised or 'difficult', actually involves the same
logical operations as are involved in the more spectacular navigational feats
described by Frake, Gladwin, Lewis, etc.
It is significant that 'culture' is sometimes described as a map; it is the analogy which occurs to
an outsider who has to find his way about in a foreign landscape and who compensates for his lack
of practical mastery, the prerogative of the native, by the use of a model of all possible routes. The
gulf between this potential, abstract, space, . . . devoid of landmarks or any priviledged centre
. and the practical space ofjourneys actually made, or actually being made, can be seen from the
difficulty we have in recognising familiar routes on a map or a town plan until we are able to bring
together the axes of the field of potentialities and the 'system of axes linked unalterably to our own
bodies, and carried about with us wherever we go' as Poincar6 puts it which structures practical
space into up and down, right and left, front and behind.
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ALFRED GELL 273
Mental maps
In what follows I wish to defend a version of the mental map theory against the
(behaviouristic) practical mastery theory. But I also wish to point out certain
ambiguities in the currently accepted notion of 'mental maps' which have been
invoked very freely, and perhaps rather uncritically, by cognitive psychologists
and geographers (Lynch I960; Downs & Stea I977; Gould & White I974; Canter
I977; Oatley I977; Neisser I976). Is the idea of a mental map to be taken
seriously, or is it a vague metaphor? If mental maps really exist, are they like
non-mental maps? Oatley, a psychologist, is at pains to stress that mental maps
are not 'static' like artefactual maps, but dynamic: 'the navigator's mental map is
a process, not a picture' (546). Lewis, speaking of the mental maps presumed to
underly the navigational prowess of the desert Aborigines, describes the 'map'
as a continually updated 'image' of the territory:
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
274 ALFRED GELL
It would appear then, that the essential psychophysical mechanism was some kind of dynamic
image or mental 'map', which was continually updated in terms of time, distance, and bearing,
and more radically realigned at each change of direction, so that hunters remained at all times
aware of the precise direction of their base and/or objective (I976: 262).
Such remarks are confusing if one wishes to take the 'map' notion at all
seriously, since the objects we have in our possession, and refer to as 'maps', have
none of these characteristics and would be quite useless to us if they did. How
would we fare if the trusty London A to Z in the glove compartment of the car
insidiously metamorphosed into a different edition, showing all the familiar
places in new locations, every time we undertook a journey from Piccadilly to
Marble Arch? We only update maps when the geography of the world changes,
not whenever we move about ourselves. Whatever Oatley and Lewis are talking
about when they invoke the idea of a mental map, it is clearly not anything like
an artefactual map, and does not deserve to be known by the same name.
Quite apart from the instances in which mental maps are given attributes
totally at variance with ordinary maps, there is a more basic problem with
mental map theory, even when mental maps are understood, as they generally
are by geographers, to have the features normally associated with non-mental
maps (e.g. Lynch I960; Downs & Stea I977). Mental map theorists assume that
just having a map is sufficient to ensure navigational success, and therefore
attribute instances of successful navigation to the possession of such maps. But
this is not very true to our experience of actual map use. In real life the question
of map use only arises when we do not know how to accomplish a journey or
find a location. Our criterion for claiming that we 'know the way' between A
and B is that we have no need for maps, or other directions, in order to make that
journey. Does this mean that we have a mental map which shows the way
between A and B and that we 'consult' this map in order to find the way? Surely
not. If mental maps are the mental equivalents of artefactual maps (a memorised
replica of the relevant artefactual map) then if we 'know the way' between A and
B we will not need to consult our mental map in order to get there, just as we
would not have needed to consult our artefactual map, if we had one. Therefore
it cannot be true that 'knowing the way between A and B' is the same as 'having a
mental map which shows, inter alia, the route between A and B'. We appear to
be on the horns of a dilemma. Either mental maps are so unlike artefactual maps
as to fail to qualify as 'maps' at all, or if mental maps are really like maps, then
they cannot be invoked in the explanation of spatially knowledgeable way-
finding performances which, by definition, occur without the assistance of
maps.
Let us turn to the alternative theory, mapless practical mastery. We can
suppose that practical mastery of the environment consists of possessing
complete knowledge of what the environment looks like from all practically-
available points of view (which would not include the view from the horizontal
plane of projection of a standard map, since the world never appears to anybody
as it does in a map). Way-finding is carried out as follows; the subject identifies
his position by matching the landscape image which opens up around him with
one previously filed. In order to proceed towards a chosen destination he moves
so as to create around himself a chain of linked landscape images corresponding
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ALFRED GELL 275
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
276 ALFRED GELL
not more subjectively burdensome than speaking one's native tongue. Since
Chomsky's demolition of Skinner's Verbal behavior, linguists have abandoned
habit-formation, dispositions to respond, conditioning, etc. as explanatory
concepts in accounting for linguistic performance, and perhaps there is no better
reason for retaining them in the explanation of navigational performance either
(Chomsky I959).
Seen in this light, the apparent dissimilarity between the experienced native
and the map-using stranger has diminished somewhat, but has hardly been
eliminated altogether. What we have to show is that native and stranger perform
an essentially similar task in an essentially similar way, but that the process
takes place subliminally and inaccessibly in the instance of the experienced
native, whereas the stranger is obliged to wrestle with his navigational problems
in public.
If we confine our attention to the native we can hardly expect to make much
progress, since he himself does not know how he does it, and all we know is that
he can do it; how, we are unable to say. The only way in which we can
reconstruct the unobservable mental processes underlying effortless navigation
is to look more closely at the relatively accessible mental processes of the
map-user who, on the language-use analogy, is in the position of a non-speaker
of a language who uses a published grammar and vocabulary laboriously to
create sentences which would come effortlessly to the lips of a native speaker.
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ALFRED GELL 277
t 9 ''''',,,'
t ~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~~..X . fR.. . .
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
278 ALFRED GELL
places along a projected route. Clearly he is not really doing anything radically
different from the map-using stranger, who also matches up his current visual
impressions with landscape-images at each stage of the journey. The stranger
has constructed these images from a map, while the native derives them from
personal experience, but otherwise their mental processes are identical. In
particular, it cannot be said that the stranger navigates in a different kind of
'space'-Cartesian as opposed to practical-since both stranger and native can
be seen to rely on matching up a series of 'expected landscapes' seen from a
particular set of subject-centred coordinates, with the world as perceived. This
is so despite the fact that the map-user's expectations are derived from a map
which knows nothing of such subjective coordinates and which represents the
world from everybody's and nobody's point of view.
The gap between the experienced native and the map-using stranger seems to
have narrowed considerably, but the most difficult and contentious part of the
argument is still to be accomplished. I have so far only succeeded in showing
that the map-user makes up for his deficit in prior experience of the landscape,
which otherwise sets him apart from the experienced native, by the use of an
artefact, a map. But it has yet to be shown that the experienced native makes use
of a 'mental map'; all that has so far been attributed to him is the possession of a
complete series of partial views, in the form of accumulated images of what the
world looks like seen from points A, B, C, D, along the route A- B -> C -> D.
This multiplicity of partial views does not add up to a map, which is a
perspectiveless, synoptic whole encompassing all locations and all routes be-
tween these locations. But this is just what is presupposed by the theory of
mental maps, if the notion of a mental map is to be taken seriously. It must now
be demonstrated that the experienced native must refer to a map in order to
evaluate the spatial significance of the concordance between a filed image of a
landscape and his current perception of his surroundings. I must show that in
order for practical navigation to take place, it is not merely sufficient that a
landscape-image be matched to a perceived landscape, but that the landscape-
image must be identified with coordinates on a mental map.
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ALFRED GELL 279
where Medicine Rock is, and moreover, if I am standing in front of a sign saying
'Welcome to Medicine Rock' I know where I am, too.
The defining property of maps is that they consist of one or more spatial
propositions with non-token-indexical truth conditions (Mellor I98I). By
non-token-indexical is meant that tokens of these propositions are true indepen-
dently of the spatial coordinates in which they are uttered or entertained as
beliefs. Saying 'King's Cross station is north of the LSE' is to utter a token of the
proposition-type which is true if King's Cross station and the LSE are where the
proposition in question asserts. If this proposition is true, all its tokens will be
true, wherever they are uttered. On the other hand, saying 'King's Cross station
is north of here' is to say something which is true only if said south, and not too
far west or east of King's Cross. It is true if uttered in the LSE, or in Croydon, or
in Ouagadougou, but not true if uttered in Oslo, Cambridge, or Islington.
Tokens of this spatial proposition have truth values which vary according to the
spatial coordinates (or index) at which they are uttered, and for this reason it is a
token-indexical spatial proposition. The essential point, however, is that the
truth value of a token-indexical spatial proposition is logically dependent on the
truth-value of an underlying non-token-indexical spatial proposition. Thus
the truth value of 'King's Cross station is north ofhere' uttered in Ouagadougou,
is dependent on the truth of the proposition 'Ouagadougou is south of King's
Cross'. But the truth values of non-token-indexical spatial propositions
are not logically dependent on the truth values of any token-indexical spatial
propositions.
Spatial knowledge-systems consist, therefore, of compendia of non-token-
indexical spatial beliefs. It is only on the basis provided by non-token-indexical
spatial beliefs that the agent can derive token-indexical beliefs about his current
location in space. This is the fundamental reason why the notion advanced by
Bourdieu, that 'practical' space is ego-centric, defined exclusively by the
coordinates which meet at the agent's own body, must be rejected as logically
unsound. We are obliged at all times to locate our bodies in relation to external
coordinates which are unaffected as we move about, and it is in relation to these
coordinates that we entertain token-indexical beliefs as to our current location in
space, and the locations of other places relative to ourselves. It is only on these
logical rather than psychological grounds that the theory of 'mental maps' can
finally be defended. We have mental maps, not as a matter of contingent fact,
but as a matter of logical necessity, because the logical form of spatial knowledge
is non-token-indexical. If we entertained only token-indexical spatial proposit-
ions, which could not be reduced to non-token-indexical spatial propositions,
we should be logically debarred from possessing spatial knowledge or coherent
spatial beliefs of any kind at all.
I will now explore this idea in a little more detail. The points to bear in mind
are i) that token-indexical and non-token-indexical spatial beliefs have different
kinds of logical truth conditions; ii) spatial knowledge is grounded in non-
token-indexical (map) beliefs, and iii) that perceptually based judgements as to
the agent's own position in space always take the form of token-indexical spatial
beliefs. Point iii) is a new element in the argument so far. Very schematically, all
perceptualjudgements are token-indexical beliefs, beliefs which have transitory
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
280 ALFRED GELL
truth conditions which are dependent on them being held just when the target
object of perception is being perceived. Thus, perception consists of making
judgements such as 'this is a crow', ajudgement which remains truejust as long
as the crow sits there and allows itself to be perceived; when the crow takes to the
air and flies away, goodbye to that particular perceptual belief.
Thus the agent, perceiving himself (by matching images) to be at a particular
location, utters the perceptual judgement 'Ah! Here we are at Marble Arch,' a
token whose truth conditions are bound up with its being uttered at Marble
Arch, and not anywhere else. On the other hand, knowing where Marble Arch
is (and hence where the agent is, as he utters his token indexical judgement)
depends on the availability of non-token-indexical propositional knowledge
about the location of Marble Arch in space.
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ALFRED GELL 28I
itself, it can be used to generate images of Pitcairn seen from all possible points of
view. Thus, suppose we are approaching Pitcairn not from the Bounty Bay side,
but from the opposite side. Consultation of the map will generate an image of
what we should see if we are correct in our supposition that we are approaching
Pitcairn from the south-west. I have drawn this image in fig. 2C.
It is essential to the theory of navigation that I am putting forward here that,
just as images (like landfall sketches) are of no use to the mariner unless he has a
map at his disposal which generates, at specific coordinates, just that token-
indexical image, so non-token-indexical maps are of no use unless they gener-
ate, at any given set of coordinates, a unique image. For it is only in the light of
token-indexical judgements (noticing, for instance, that the world has come to
look like fig. 2b or 2c) that navigational decisions can be formulated. Such
decisions are attended with navigational success only if they are based on a
correct identification of the current position of the navigator. Thus, in fig. 3, it is
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
282 ALFRED GELL
A N
0
O 0
C B
FIGURE 3. Misidentified coordinates.
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ALFRED GELL 283
which I have tacitly assumed is not the case. But readers of Frake's article, and
the accounts of Micronesian navigation given by Gladwin and Lewis will be
inclined to contest this stipulation. Frake's lunar/solar/tidal mental maps of
medieval seamen clearly exist in order to codify a process of systematic change
in the territory-at certain moments in time harbours are full and sandbanks
well covered, at others they are empty and their approaches are made hazardous
by low water. My answer to this would be that the tidal compass described by
Frake is a means of providing temporal indices for a 'file' of maps, maps which are
spatially non-token-indexical but temporally token-indexical, i.e. true at some
times and not at others. The mariner's problem is to decide which of his maps is
true 'now'; that is, to arrive at a token-indexical temporal belief about which set
of non-token-indexical spatial beliefs to entertain, since his beliefs about which
ports are tidally safe or hazardous do not depend on where he is, spatially, in
relation to them. He achieves this by making use of a time-map of lunar/solar
correlations; i.e. he derives a temporal 'image' (a 'now'-fix) from his set of
non-token-indexical temporal map beliefs. The tidal compass is the set of
non-token-indexical temporal beliefs whose token-indexical images determine
which non-token-indexical spatial beliefs he will entertain, spatial beliefs whose
token-indexical images will in turn motivate his final navigational decisions.
What we have is a two-stage process instead of the one-stage process normally
encountered in navigation away from the sea. But the two stages, the first
temporal, the second spatial, have identical logical attributes. In neither case are
the maps themselves 'dynamic', since the truth conditions for the tidal compass
are independent of the passage of time; the mariner's time map is true at all
times, not at particular times. And similarly, the file of temporally indexed
spatial maps as a whole does not change in truth value because of the fact that,
depending on the temporal index, at a given moment only one of the file of maps
is currently true. It is true at all times that a map, indexed as 'true at TI ' according to
the tidal compass, is true at that temporal index. We can therefore rigorously
distinguish between spatial/temporal map beliefs which, true or not in reality, at
least aim at 'timeless' truth, from the dynamic token indexical beliefs which map
users hold about the current truth-value of particular images derived from such
maps.
The same kind of considerations can be applied to the Micronesian etak
system, which has been described over and over again in the psychological
literature, but which may still not be sufficiently familiar to anthropological
readers to make a brief summary of the facts inappropriate. Micronesians have
been accustomed to make voyages in small canoes over distances of 400 miles
and more, aiming at targets not more than a few miles across. These extraordi-
nary feats are achieved by a combination oftechniques involving dead reckoning,
following the stars at night, and making use of a detailed knowledge of
conditions encountered at sea (wave patterns, bird movements, cloud forma-
tions, winds, etc.). Navigational lore is passed on by master navigators as a
theoretical discipline, on land rather than at sea, and the effectiveness of the
system can be gauged by the fact that properly instructed individuals think
nothing of attempting voyages to distant islands where neither they themselves
nor their instructors have ever sailed.
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
284 ALFRED GELL
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ALFRED GELL 285
Pleiades* N
N \
\ \
\\\I II /
/ /
~ I FARAULEP
?o THEETAK (HATAG)
I, / \ N \ \.\\ Aldebaran
/ / /A
i \ \4
\ ~~OLIMARAO~--
N \
WOLEAI /__ 3 6
0 1 2Antares
FIGURE 4. The etak.
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
286 ALFRED GELL
star courses, a system of spatial beliefs which does not alter according to the
location of the canoe.
The etak system, therefore, though of extraordinary refinement, is a system of
images derived from a map and is logically on a par with the cognitive processes
which underly the most elementary kinds of way-finding in everyday contexts.
And this is the general point that I should like to end with. We can distinguish
among navigational techniques from the standpoint of their complexity and the
amount of information they may involve, which in the case of Micronesian
navigation is very great indeed. We can also distinguish between those systems
which rely on published information, such as charts and tables giving the times
of high and low tides, combined with standard algorithms which can be
performed with paper and pencil etc. versus systems which rely on extensive
rote memorisation and involve mental calculations of a greater or lesser degree
of difficulty. There can be no doubt, as Frake suggests, that medieval navi-
gational techniques would weed out the duffers much more effectively than the
systems in use nowadays, and that from the point of view of the intellectual
demands made on them, the mariners of earlier times are in a class apart from
their present-day counterparts. All this should not be allowed to obscure the
fact, however, that the essential logical processes involved in all way-finding,
from the most elementary and subliminal, to the most complex and laborious,
are identical. And it is on these grounds that we should seek to justify the thesis
of the universality of human cognitive processes against opponents, such as
Hallpike, who maintain that there are cognitive sheep and goats. Frake has
shown that there are sheep among the goats: I want to go further and deny the
existence of goats altogether.
REFERENCES
Baker, R. R. I98I. Human navigation and the sixth sense. London: Hodder & Stoughton.
Bateson, G. I972. Steps to an ecology of mind. London: Paladin.
Bourdieu, P. I977. Towards a theory ofpractice. Cambridge: Univ. Press.
Canter, D. I977. The psychology ofplace. London: Architectural Press.
Chomsky, N. I959. Review of'Verbal behavior', by B. F. Skinner. Language. 35, 26-58.
Downs, R. & D. Stea I977. Maps in minds. New York: Harper & Row.
Gould, R. & P. White I974. Mental maps. Harmondsworth: Pelican.
Gladwin, T. I970. Thepast is a big bird. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard Univ. Press.
Hallpike, C. I979. Thefoundations ofprimitive thought. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Lewis, D. I972. We the navigators. Canberra. Australian National Univ. Press.
Observations on route-finding and spatial orientation among the Aboriginal peoples of the
western desert region of central Australia. Oceania, 46 (4), 249-82.
Lynch, K. I960. The image of the city. Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press.
Mellor, D. I98I. Real time. Cambridge. Univ. Press.
Neisser, U. I976. Cognition and reality. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.
Oatley, K. I977. Inference, navigation, and cognitive maps. In Thinking (ed.) P. N. Johnson-
Laird. Cambridge: Univ. Press.
This content downloaded from 143.107.8.30 on Thu, 24 Aug 2017 16:26:19 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms