Progressivism
Progressivism
John Dewey (1859–1952) was one of the United States’ best known academics, philosophers and public intellectuals.
From humble beginnings in Vermont, he managed to achieve a PhD in philosophy and become a professor at the
University of Chicago. It his here that he began experimenting with educational reform, establishing his famous
‘Laboratory School’ in 1896 to develop and test ‘progressive’ methods of teaching. This is where Dewey’s lifelong
concerns with the social outcomes of education began, and particularly his interest in the ways in which education
could enhance democracy. He moved to Columbia University in 1904, where he was a professor of philosophy,
regularly lecturing in the University’s Teachers’ College. He worked at Columbia for the rest of his life, writing a
number of books on education and making a major contribution to the American philosophical school of ‘Pragmatism’.
By this, Dewey meant that philosophy had to be grounded in the practical conditions of everyday human life, and that
human knowledge should be linked to practical social experience. This philosophy underpinned all his educational
thinking.
Dewey was the American founder of ‘progressive education’, a direct counterpoint to the ‘traditional’ or didactic
education of the schools of the early 20th century:
At present, the opposition, so far as the practical affairs of the school are
concerned, tends to take the form of contrast between traditional and progressive education. If the underlying ideas of
the former are formulated broadly … they are found to be as follows: The subject-matter of education consists of
bodies of information and skills that have been worked out in the past; therefore, the chief business of the school is to
transmit them to a new generation. In the past, there have also been developed standards and rules of conduct;
moral training consists in forming habits of action in conformity with these rules and standards … [T]he general
pattern of school organization (by which I mean the relations of pupils to one another and to the teachers) … [centres
around] time schedules, schemes of classification, of examination and promotion, of rules of order … Since the
subject-matter as well as standards of proper conduct are handed down from the past, the attitude of pupils must,
upon the whole, be one of docility, receptivity, and obedience. Books, especially textbooks, are the chief
representatives of the lore and wisdom of the past, while teachers are the organs through which pupils are brought
into effective connection with the material. Teachers are the agents through which knowledge and skills are
communicated and rules of conduct enforced … The traditional scheme is, in essence, one of imposition from above
and outside … Moreover, that which is taught is thought of as essentially static … It is to a large extent the cultural
product of societies that assumed the future would be much like the past, and yet it is used as educational food in a
society where change is the rule, not the exception …
The school environment of desks, blackboards, a small school yard, was supposed to suffice. There was no demand
that the teacher should become intimately acquainted with the conditions of the local community, physical, historical,
economic, occupational, etc., in order to utilize them as educational resources …
It is no reflection upon the nutritive quality of beefsteak that is not fed to infants. It is not an invidious reflection upon
trigonometry that we do not teach it in the first or fifth grade of school. It is not subject per se that is educative or that
is conducive to growth. There is no subject that in and of itself, or without regard to the state of growth attained by the
learner, such that inherent educational value can be attributed to it. Failure to take into account adaptation to the
needs and capacities of individuals was the source of the idea that certain subjects and certain methods are
intrinsically cultural or intrinsically good for mental discipline. There is no such thing as educational value in the
abstract …
If one attempts to formulate the philosophy of education implicit in the practices of the new education, we may, I think,
discover certain common principles amid the variety of progressive schools now existing. To imposition from above is
opposed expression and cultivation of individuality; to external discipline is opposed free activity; to learning from
texts and teachers, learning from experience; to acquisition of isolated skills and techniques by drill, is opposed
acquisition of them as a means of attaining ends which make direct vital appeal; to preparation for a more or less
remote future is opposed making the most of the opportunities of present life; to static aims and materials is opposed
acquaintance with a changing world …
It is the cardinal precept of the newer school of education that the beginning of instruction shall be made with the
experience learners already have; that this experience and the capacities that have been developed during its course
provide the starting point for all further learning.
[H]ow shall we … introduce into the school … occupations which exact personal responsibilities and which train the
child in relation to the physical realities of life? … [For] such work engages the full spontaneous interest of the
children. It keeps them alert and active, instead of passive and receptive; it makes them more useful, more capable,
and hence more inclined to he helpful at home; it prepares them to some extent for the practical duties of later
life—the girls to be more efficient house managers, if not actually cooks and seamstresses; the boys … for their
future vocations.
We must conceive of [schools] … as agencies for bringing home to the child some of the primal necessities of
community life … as instrumentalities through which the school itself shall be made a genuine form of active
community life, instead of a place set apart in which to learn lessons …
As one enters a busy kitchen in which a group of children are actively engaged in the preparation of food, the
psychological difference, the change from more or less passive and inert recipiency and restraint to one of buoyant
outgoing energy, is so obvious as fairly to strike one in the face …
[By] the introduction into the school of various forms of active occupation … the entire spirit of the school is renewed.
It has a chance to affiliate itself with life, to become the child’s habitat, where he learns through directed learning,
instead of being only a place to learn lessons having an abstract and remote reference to some possible living to be
done in the future. It gets a chance to be a miniature community, and embryonic society. To do this means to make
each one of our schools an embryonic community life, active with the types of occupation that reflect the life of larger
society.
John Broadus Watson, who lived from 1879 to 1958, was an American psychologist who is
considered the father of the psychological school of behaviorism. He was raised in South Carolina
by a mother with strict religious standards and an alcoholic father who abandoned John and his
mother when John was only 13 years old. Watson struggled academically and was arrested twice
during high school. Yet despite these troubles and his own admission that he was a poor student,
Watson entered Furman College at age 16 and emerged with a Master's degree five years later. He
eventually completed a doctorate in Psychology at the University of Chicago in 1903 and went on to
teach at John Hopkins University in 1908.
Behaviorism, according to Watson, was the science of observable behavior. Only behavior that
could be observed, recorded and measured was of any real value for the study of humans or
animals. Watson's thinking was significantly influenced by the earlier classical conditioning
experiments of Russian psychologist Ivan Pavlov and his now infamous dogs.
Watson's behaviorism rejected the concept of the unconscious and the internal mental state of a
person because it was not observable and was subject to the psychologist's subjective
interpretation. For example, Freud would ask his patients to tell him their dreams. He would then
interpret the dreams and analyze what these dreams were indicating in the person's life. Watson
found this emphasis on introspection and subjective interpretation to be very unscientific and
unhelpful in understanding behavior.