For A Realistic Logic: Henry Veatch, Indiana University
For A Realistic Logic: Henry Veatch, Indiana University
Nor would the case seem to be otherwise with what throughout the last
few centuries has usually been called Aristotelian logic. Thus one hardly
needs to be reminded of Kant’s celebrated pronouncement concerning this
sort of logic, namely, that “since Aristotle it has not required to retrace a
single step”; indeed, “to the present day this logic has not been able to
advance a single step, and is thus to all appearance a closed and completed
body of doctrine.”1 True, Kant continues, although “some of the moderns
have thought to enlarge it by introducing psychological ..., metaphysical ...,
1
Critique of Pure Reason, trans. by Norman K. Smith (London, Macmillan, 1929),
Preface to 2nd ed., B viii.
2
or anthropological chapters ..., this could only arise from their ignorance of
the peculiar nature of logical science.” For “the sole concern” of logic being
“to give an exhaustive exposition and a strict proof of the formal rules of all
thought,”2 it makes no difference, presumably, what one’s psychology or
metaphysics or anthropology may be; logic must perforce be always the
same and invariant.
2
Ibid.
3
We do not mean to imply that this interpretation of Aristotelian logic is necessarily the
correct one; all we mean is that it is the current and common one. Indeed, for the last
three centuries or so, the term “Aristotelian logic” has tended to signify a purely formal
logic, these “forms” being considered quite apart from any intentional function which
they might happen to have. Rather than attempt to revise this conception of Aristotelian
logic or to consider whether it is just either to Aristotle or to the Aristotelian tradition, we
propose simply to accept it at its face value. For whether genuinely Aristotelian or not,
such a logic, we think, is quite ill-adapted to the purposes of a genuinely realistic
philosophy.
4
It is well known that mathematical logicians do not consider that the new logic is in any
way contradictory to Aristotelian logic. Quite the contrary. it is merely more extensive
and comprehensive, with the result that the older logic can be simply taken up into and
absorbed by, the new. Again (see the preceding note), we do not in this paper wish to
challenge this view of the relation between mathematical logic and so-called Aristotelian
logic. On the contrary, as the latter has generally come to be conceived and understood,
3
1. There are beings that are and are what they are independently of their
being known.
2. Human beings are able to acquire some knowledge of such beings as they
really are in themselves and not merely as they are relatively to their being
known.
Now granting these two theses, the nature and function of logic would
therewith seem determined and defined. For as to its function, logic on such
a basis would be regarded simply as the tool or instrument through which
human beings could acquire precisely this sort of realistic knowledge of
things as they are really and in themselves. And such being the function of
logic, the nature of the logical tools and instruments that are requisite for the
performance of such a function can also be determined.
Thus for one thing, such logical entities as propositions, argument forms,
predicate terms, and so forth would not be ordinary real beings but rather the
sorts of things through which such real beings could come to be known. That
is to say, one would hardly expect that a proposition, for instance, would
exist or would ever be encountered in rerum natura in quite the same
manner as an electron or a jellyfish. No, propositions just do not have that
kind of existence. Instead, they are unmistakably intellectual tools and hence
are quite incapable of existing apart from psychological processes of
cognition or out of the context of human cognitive behavior. In this sense,
indeed, they might be said to be mere beings of reason, or entia rationis, to
use a Scholastic term.
At the same time, they are not mere fictions arbitrarily invented or
conjured up at will. Instead, they have to be wholly fitted and adapted to
their function of disclosing or representing things other than themselves,
precisely as these latter are really and in themselves. Consequently, such
logical entities may be said to have a foundation in reality in the sense that
they cannot be rightly understood save with reference to the real which they
are thus designed to represent.
the mathematical logician is quite correct in supposing that Aristotelian formal logic
represents but an insignificant part of mathematical logic. Our point is rather that a
realistic logic must differ radically from both mathematical logic and Aristotelian logic as
so understood.
4
Or to put the same thing a little differently, we might say that logical
entities are peculiar precisely in that they are nothing but “intentions,” their
whole nature and structure being that of a thing which “tends toward”
something else or which is wholly and completely of or about something
else. It is in this sense that we say they must have such a character as will
render them completely transparent or wholly representative of that which is
other than themselves, or, to use the technical term, will render them
completely intentional.5
Very well, but if such be the criteria of the logical, considered from the
point of view of philosophical realism, can we produce any examples of
such peculiarly logical or intentional entities? We think we can. Indeed, we
think that those very entities — concepts, propositions, and arguments —
which have always been thought to be in some sense or other the proper
concern of logic — these very entities, we think, may be shown to be
capable of functioning as intentions and to meet, when viewed in a certain
way, all the requirements that a realistic philosophy lays down for logical
tools and instruments.
consider the concept “greater than,” anyone would readily recognize that it
is a concept of a certain relation; and yet he would also recognize just as
readily that its own character and structure, just as a concept, is certainly not
one of being greater than something else.
First, with respect to concepts, we may answer briefly that the function
of the concept is to disclose or signify the “what” of things. That is to say,
anything that is or is real in any sense may be presumed to have some sort of
determinate nature or character — an “essence,” in the very broadest sense
of that much abused and misunderstood term. Thus anything whatever, be it
a relation, an event, a quality, a size, an activity, a substance, a sense datum,
or what not, will be or have a certain “what” or essence; it will be something
rather than nothing. Nor can there be any knowledge or understanding of
things, save in so far as we get at their “what’s” or essences.
6
Again, see Parker’s essay, pp. 19 ff. [in Wild, pp. 168 ff.].
7
In this brief essay, we are considering only deductive argument, not induction.
8
LET THIS, THEN, suffice for a very cursory explanation and defense of our
first thesis,8 namely, that there is, or at least can be or should be, such a thing
as a realistic logic; and that the hallmark of such a logic must needs be its
radical and thorough intentionality. But now let us turn to our second thesis.
According to it, it must be recognized that the current types of logic with
which we are particularly familiar nowadays — namely, mathematical logic
and Aristotelian logic as that is ordinarily understood — such types of logic
are not in the nature of a realistic or intentional logic at all. Why not? Well,
we venture to suggest that the reason is that developments in modern
mathematical logic have tended to introduce into logic a type of formalism
which is radically and completely nonintentional.
Indeed, to bring the issue to a head, let us quote a rather striking passage
from Ludwig Wittgenstein: “We make to ourselves pictures of facts. The
picture presents the facts in logical space, the existence and non-existence of
atomic facts. The picture is a model of reality. To the objects correspond in
the picture the elements of the picture. The elements of the picture stand, in
the picture, for the objects. The picture consists in the fact that its elements
are combined with one another in a definite way. The picture is a fact. That
the elements of the picture are combined with one another in a definite way,
represents that the things are so combined with one another. This connexion
of the elements of the picture is called its structure, and the possibility of this
structure is called the form of representation of the picture.”9
8
See above, p. 3 [in Wild, p. 178].
9
Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (London, K. Paul, Trench, Trubner, 1922), p. 39.
10
This word has often been taken in a Pickwickian sense in the context of modern logic.
9
And yet a mathematical logician might well make the rejoinder that in
the passage quoted, Wittgenstein does seem to ascribe a definite
representative function to logic, in so far as it is supposed to “picture” the
facts. And in this sense, it might well be asked whether for Wittgenstein,
quite as much as for us, logic might not be said to be an affair of intentions.
In other words, is not mathematical logic an intentional logic after all?
the symbol for it; and that complexity of the symbol corresponds very
closely with the complexity of the fact symbolized by it.”11
Now from the point of view of a thoroughly realistic logic of the sort we
are defending, what precisely is the import of this basic presupposition of so
many mathematical logicians, that in order for logical relations and
structures to represent real relations, there must be an isomorphism or
structural identity between them?
For one thing, such a view of the nature of representation would seem to
come very close to the discredited “copy theory” of knowledge, according to
which there must always be a correspondence between the thing known and
what is in the mind of the knower. Moreover, quite apart from the usual
difficulties of such a theory according to which it would be impossible for
one ever actually to tell whether there was in fact such a correspondence
between knower and known, there is another difficulty that is somewhat
more immediately germane to our present discussion. For if it be maintained
that in order for one to know a given complex structure, the complexity of
the symbol must correspond to the complexity of the fact symbolized, the
presupposition would seem to be that one can know the fact only by first
knowing the symbol.12
But then the problem of logical intentions has merely been pushed back
one step further. For how, and through what intentional instruments, does
one know the symbol? If the only possible intentional instruments are
symbols which are isomorphic with the thing symbolized, then a regress to
infinity would seem inescapable. And rather than accept this consequence, it
would seem necessary to recognize that representation may well involve
11
The Philosophy of Logical Atomism (lectures delivered in 1918 and published in the
Monist, 1918–19; republished by the Department of Philosophy, Minneapolis, University
of Minnesota, no date), p. 12. See also Russell’s comments on Wittgenstein in his
Introduction to the Tractatus, op. cit., especially pp. 8–11.
12
Otherwise, there would be no point in insisting on the likeness of the symbol to the
thing symbolized. That is to say, on this view it is only through recognizing the likeness
that one comes to recognize that which it is like. Hence one must first come to know the
symbol, and only then does one come to know what is symbolized, on the ground that the
former is like or similar to the latter.
11
Indeed, this same point is even more strikingly borne out when one
considers the theories of those mathematical logicians who would simply
reject the notion that logical forms and structure must somehow correspond
to real forms and structures. Instead, accepting a more Kantian or even
idealistic epistemology, they would question the necessity or even the
meaningfulness of talking about a real to which the logical is somehow
supposed to correspond. And in place of such a correspondence theory, they
would make logic and/or mathematics actually constitutive of reality as
known. Or to put the thing a little differently, logic and mathematics on such
13
On the difficulties of a correspondence theory see Parker’s essay, pp. 5 ff. [in
Wild, pp. 156 ff.].
14
To use more technical language, one might say that white instrumental (in this case.
iconic) signs are entirely proper, one cannot expect them to displace or substitute for so-
called formal signs. See John Wild’s article, “An Introduction to the Phenomenology of
Signs,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, VIII, (Dec. 1947), 217 ff.
12
But clearly here, more than ever, supposedly logical forms and relations
have ceased to be mere intentions through which the real comes to be
known; instead, they are the actual form and relations of the real itself. Or
better, instead of being intentional structures through which the order of
nature comes to be known, these so-called logical structures actually
determine the order of nature as it is for us.
Coming, then, directly to the first question: What precisely is the nature
of an intentional relation? The answer we should like to suggest, albeit with
some diffidence,16 is that this relation is always a relation of identity. Thus,
15
See Professor Lewis’s use of this adjective in Mind and the World-Order. (New York,
Scribner 1929), p. 27.
16
This diffidence proceeds from many sources. In the first place, there are various current
senses of “identity” with which identity in our sense must not be confused, but almost
inevitably will be confused. For instance, the idealistic logicians speak of identity,
apparently thinking of it as connected with the Absolute which absorbs all differences
within itself. Also, the mathematical logicians speak of identity after the analogy of
equality, as if there could be a relation of identity between individuals or classes of
individuals. But clearly, the intentional identity of which we are speaking is of neither of
these two types.
But in the second place, even within the context of realism it would seem necessary to
13
we have already argued that logical entities, on a realistic basis, are ordered
to a disclosure of the “what,” the “that,” and the “why” of things. And such
intentional functions, we think, can only be effected through this peculiar
relation of logical identity.
distinguish between the purely logical relation of identity, with which we are here
concerned, and that real relation of cognitive identity which is basic to any realistic
epistemology (see Parker’s essay, especially pp. 13 ff. [in Wild, pp. 163 ff.]). The latter is
a real relation, the former only a relation of reason. Also, the latter is the end, the former
only the means to the end. For instance, the logical relation of identity between subject
and predicate is a means or instrument of the real relation of cognitive identity between
knower and known.
17
Incidentally, it might be remarked that both nominalism and extreme realism seem to
overlook the relational character of universals. The former sticks simply to the
individuals and refuses to recognize that intellectually it is impossible to abstract their
essence from them and so relate it back to them. On the other hand, extreme realism fixes
upon the abstracted essence but forgets that, as thus abstract, the essence or “what” is
wholly and completely in relation to the individuals from which it has been abstracted.
14
Likewise in the syllogism, where one seeks to get at the “why” of x’s
being y. Thus, in fact and in reality there would certainly have to be some
real cause or real reason why x should be, or should be y. Hence any sort of
knowledge or understanding of why x is, or is y, would seem to require some
insight into, or recognition of, the cause of this fact. Presumably, then, so-
called logical argument is nothing but a device or instrument for getting at
the causes of things, just as the concept is an instrument for getting at
essences and the proposition an instrument for getting at existence.
18
As thus described, the relation of predicate to subject in a proposition would seem to be
no different from the relation of abstracted essence to individuals in a concept. Nor is it to
be denied that a concept, by the very fact that it is abstract and universal, is necessarily
predicable of the individuals to which it is related by a relation of identity. Still, the
concept as such as predicable and identifiable, not actually predicated and identified.
15
So also with the syllogism. What it intends may be the real cause of a
certain fact;20 and yet its own structure as an intending relation is not one of
cause-effect but rather one of triple identity. Thus, for instance, we may say
that the reason towels dry our hands is because of their capillary structure. In
other words, it is because towels are of such a structure, and things of such a
structure are absorbent, that we can say that towels are absorbent. That is to
say, the only way we can understand why x is y is in virtue of something
else that x is. Thus a real causal transaction certainly does not involve any
real relation of identity; and yet it would seem that it can only be intended by
such a relation of identity.
But now let us turn to the mathematical logicians. If we are right in our
view of a realistic logic, concepts, propositions, and arguments are nothing
but relations of identity, through which we are able to get at the “what,” the
“that,” and the “why” of things. Also if we are right, the mathematical
logicians, through their confusion of real forms and relations with properly
logical or intentional forms, are bound to misconstrue such things as
concepts, propositions, and arguments, not recognizing the distinctively
intentional nature of such entities. But is this in fact the case?
19
See below, pp. 17–19 [in Wild, pp. 190–92].
20
It should be apparent that this notion of a syllogism as being an instrument for the
intention of causes presupposes the realistic view of causal transaction (see John Wild,
“Phenomenology and Metaphysics,” in The Return to Reason, op. cit., pp. 36 ff.); see
also his “A Realistic Defense of Causal Efficacy,” Review of Metaphvsics, II, No. 8 (June
1949), 1–14, in contrast to a Humean view of a cause as an atomic event prior in time to
its effect.
16
And yet it might well be urged that what the modern logician calls
“propositional functions” are quite adequate to perform all the functions of
concepts. Indeed, propositional functions, it might be argued, are really
much more adequate than concepts for the very reason that whereas concepts
never can represent anything more than mere properties of things,21
propositional functions are able to represent relations between things. Thus
one can have a function with one argument, and that will represent the
relation of a thing to its property or a substance to its accident; or one can
have a function with two arguments, representing a relation between two
things; or a function of three arguments, representing a relation between
three things; and so forth.
But here, surely, there is a very patent confusion of real relations with
logical relations. For must not such a thing as a propositional function be
regarded as a sort of schema for various types of real relations? Thus, for
instance, let us suppose that John is the brother of Joe. Now quite apart from
the conceptual or propositional form through which this relationship is
intended, the fact simply is that there is in reality a real relationship of John
to Joe. Accordingly, the function f(x,y) would seem to be simply the form of
this real relation, not necessarily the form of the intention in and through
which this relation is apprehended. Or if one wants to say that the function
f(x,y) represents the form of the relation rather than simply is the form of the
relation, then it does so after the manner of an iconic sign — that is, by
being like the relation or by corresponding to it or by being isomorphic with
it.
But a concept is not this sort of thing at all, and functions quite
differently. True, a concept can perfectly well be a concept of a certain
relation — of a many-termed relation, in fact. And yet in such a case the
structure of the concept just as such will not be the same as the structure of
what is thus conceived or intended. For what is conceived will be a many-
termed relation; but the relation through which it is conceived will be a
relation of identity, that is, a concept which is precisely such a relation of
identity between the real relation that is intended and its “what” or essence.
Indeed, any relation whatever, be it one between a thing and its property or
between two things or between three things — any such relation, or for that
21
The distinction between “thing” and “property” here may be taken to be synonymous
with the distinction between substance and accidents. See the essay by Manley H.
Hopkins, Jr., [in Wild], pp. 125 ff.
17
22
In other words, there is no reason why a concept of a relation or relational complex
could not be represented more or less iconically through the symbolic device of the
propositional function. The point would be that the relation of the concept to what it was
a concept of would be a relation of identity, for all that.
18
Nor will any relational form such as x R y suffice for this purpose. Thus
if it is concerning x that one wishes to recognize that it is thus and so, the
only propositional form that will serve is the subject-predicate form: x is in
relation R to y. Or if it is the relation itself that one wishes to say something
23
Here we are using “thing” not in the narrower sense of substance (see above Note 21)
but rather in the broadest sense possible, as synonymous with being itself.
19
about, again the subject-predicate relation of identity is the only one that will
perform the requisite intentional function: “The relation x R y is
symmetrical.” Or if one’s concern be to state something (a “what it is”)
about the whole relational complex, x R y, once more, the only intentional
instrument is that of subject-predicate — “A situation in which a given
thing, x, stands in relation R to y, is also one which involves a counter
relation of y to x.”
All M is P
All S is M
All S is P
24
Nouveaux essais sur l’entendent humain (Paris, Flammarion, n. d.), Liv. IV, Chap. 17,
§4, p. 248.
20
For that matter even the form of the syllogistic argument given above
could be still further formalized and so shown to be structurally or formally
the same as the transitivity of the relation of congruence. One could then set
up the completely general statement: if x R y and y R z, then x R z. And this
completely general theorem could be proved on the basis of the two axioms
about congruence, provided they also be completely generalized. In fact, the
principle underlying all relations of this general type — identity in the
syllogism, congruence in line segments, and so forth — could be summed up
thus: Any relation that is reflexive and that also has the property P26 will
necessarily be a transitive relation.
25
Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of Deductive Sciences (2nd rev. ed., New
York, Oxford University Press, 1946), pp. 121 ff.
26
This is the way Tarski chooses to symbolize that general relational property
exemplified in the relation of equality: Things equal to the same are equal to each other.
21
formalize the relation of triple identity, once he has made it the object of his
intention, still when it functions as an intention, such a relation is radically
and thoroughly intentional: It is simply of or about or discloses something
other than itself. In this respect, it is quite different from all other relations,
even though these may in certain cases appear to be isomorphic with it.
LET US CONSIDER, then, that our second thesis has been sustained and that
modern mathematical logic has been shown to involve a systematic
confusion of real relations with logical relations and hence not to be a
properly realistic or intentional logic at all. Now if this be true, then it would
seem possible for us to provide an explanation of two more or less
unexplained features that would seem to characterize so many current
theories regarding the logic or philosophy of science. For one thing, we refer
to that feature according to which formal logic is held to be something
totally different from, and in a sense only accidentally relevant to, what is
sometimes called the logic of discovery or scientific method. And for
another thing, we have in mind that feature of so many contemporary
philosophies of science according to which no science is considered a really
advanced and developed science unless it be, so to speak, mathematized —
as if the perfect form of a science were presumably a mathematical form.
To take the second feature first, we think that this can be accounted for
as being a direct consequence of the confusion in modern logic of real
relations with properly logical and intentional relations. For supposing that
logic is what so many mathematical logicians seem to think it is, namely, an
investigation of all possible types of order, relation, structure, and forms of
connection in general, then logic itself will be precisely a mathematics and
not a logic (that is, not in our sense of an intentional logic). As a matter of
fact, we do not see why mathematics might not be defined as being simply a
science of relations, these relations being considered not as actually existing
in rerum natura but rather as abstracted from all content and all conditions
of actual concrete existence. In contrast, logic, on our view, is not a science
of relations in this sense at all; rather it is a science only of relations of a
very peculiar sort and kind — namely, the purely intentional relations of
identity.
Very well. Supposing, though, that one does turn logic into mathematics,
and supposing one disregards any properly logical and intentional forms
altogether, then obviously any science which is not fully mathematical in
form and structure will not be fully logical in form and structure either; and
to this extent it will not be logically precise and rigorous. On this basis, then,
sciences other than physics — biology, anthropology, history, economics,
philosophy, and so forth — must be put down as being comparatively crude
and undeveloped sciences.
24
Now all this, of course, is not to be taken as implying that from the point
of view of what we have chosen to call a realistic or intentional logic
mathematics is to be regarded as unimportant and the use of so-called
mathematical methods in the sciences to be discouraged. Quite the contrary,
we should insist that there is nothing wrong with mathematics, our only
contention being that it must not be confused with logic. Nor could there be
any possible objection to introducing mathematics into any and all the
various natural sciences — physiology, archaeology, economics, even
ethics. After all, relations are to be found everywhere in nature. Hence if one
wants to consider particularly the relational aspects of, say, physiological
phenomena, it is only appropriate that he should proceed mathematically.
No, the point is not to decry mathematics but rather to distinguish logic
from it. For the minute one recognizes the intentional character of logic, he
will see that logical forms are in no sense isomorphic with the real forms and
patterns of relation in mathematics. On the contrary, as we suggested earlier,
being purely intentional, logical forms will be purely neutral and transparent:
Through them one can intend anything: mathematical relationships, organic
functions, natural substances, act and potency — anything. For this reason
an intentional and realistic logic, unlike a mathematical logic, never
prejudges the issue as to the kinds of realities there are in the natural world.
Hence, so far from insisting that there can be only one natural science,
namely physics, the realistic logician recognizes that there may be, and
presumably are, many sciences and many “knowledges” — just as many, in
fact, as there are kinds of things to be known.
And now for that other feature of the present intellectual situation that
we proposed to comment upon, namely, that whereas formal logic seems to
be productive of vast systems and a priori constructions, the so-called logic
of discovery or induction or scientific method or what you will seems to be
something entirely different and almost unrelated. But again, we think that
this curious situation is the direct result of the neglect of an intentional logic
and the attempt to replace it by a logic or mathematics of real forms and
relations. For, after all, concepts and propositions and arguments, as we have
described them, are entirely oriented toward the intention of the real world,
and of the real world as that is given in experience. Indeed, the intention of
the empirically given could only be an intention in terms of the “what,” the
“that,” and the “why.”
25
On the other hand, with a logic that concerns itself with nonintentional
forms, the situation would perforce be entirely different. For such forms do
not intend anything else. Hence they are not forms through which the given
comes to be known for what it is in itself. Instead, these are forms which
come to be known purely a priori and without the slightest reference to any
given reality which they might supposedly be designed to intend. Not only
that, but these mathematical structures and types of order having almost
endless properties and ramifications, they can be exhibited a priori in vast
and elaborate systems.
Needless to say, however, all such idealistic tendencies28 are quite alien
to any sort of genuine realism in philosophy. Accordingly, it certainly
behooves realistic philosophers to take logic seriously and to realize that the
development of a genuine realistic or intentional logic is not an
accomplished fact but a crying need, since the sort of mathematical logic
that is prevalent today would seem to be not so much an instrument of
realism as a serious source of confusion and embarrassment.
27
This would actually seem to be Einstein’s view. See the article by Professor A.
Ushenko in Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist (“The Library of Living Philosophers,”
VIII [New York, Tudor, 1949]), p. 636.
28
On these, see again John Wild, “Phenomenology and Metaphysics,” op. cit., pp. 38 ff.