"Nehruvian Socialism," 1927-1937: Nationalism, Marxism, and The Pursuit Modernity
"Nehruvian Socialism," 1927-1937: Nationalism, Marxism, and The Pursuit Modernity
"Nehruvian Socialism," 1927-1937: Nationalism, Marxism, and The Pursuit Modernity
453-473
Sanjay Seth*
453
Downloaded from alt.sagepub.com at DALHOUSIE UNIV on June 5, 2016
454 “NehruniunSocialism,”1927-1937: Nutionalism, Murrism, and the Pursuit oj Modernity
More than six years later, upon the occasion of his second presidential
address to the Indian National Congress (INC) at Lucknow, Nehru
reaffirmed his commitment: “I am convinced that the only key to the
solution of the world‘s problem and of India’s problem lies in socialism,
and when I use this word I do so not in a vague, humanitarian way
but in the scientific, economic sense.”’
In the intervening years, Nehru had propagated his socialist ideal
at innumerable youth and trade union conferences, peasant gatherings,
and Congress-organizedpublic meetings. He had urged the desirability
and at times the inevitability of socialism in many of his published
writings, most notably the series of newspaper articles published in
October 1933 under the title “Whither India?” and in his acclaimed
An Autobiography, written in jail betweenJune 1934 and February 1935.
Above all, Nehru had propagated socialism within the Indian National
Congress, seeking to educate and persuade the INC’s membership of
its necessity. He constantly urged the Congress to define its goal of
independence more clearly,and to do so by making social and economic
change for the benefit of the “masses” central to that definition. Such
urgings sometimes brought Nehru into conflict with the more
conservative elements that dominated the Congress, but they also
yielded some limited successes. The adoption of a Resolution on
Fundamental Rights by the INC at its Karachi Congress in 1931,which
declared, “This Congress is of the opinion that in order to end the
exploitation of the masses, political freedom must include real economic
freedom of the rnillion~,”~ was the result of Nehru’s persistent efforts.
The emphasis placed by the Congress on economic issues during the
1937 provincial assembly elections had much to do with Nehru’s urgings,
and he was the most energetic and effective campaigner for the Congress
in the lead up to the election. Nehru was also virtually the sole architect
of the anti-imperialist and generally progressive policies on
international issues adopted by the INC.
Nehru’s socialist declarations were frequently delivered from
congressional platforms and were usually couched in the first person,
as in the two passages quoted above. The use of the first person was
a consequence of Nehru’s position-that of a nationalist and a socialist
who pIayed a leading role in a heterogeneous, nonsocialist nationalist
organization. The sometimes president and frequent general secretary
of the Congress could speak only for himselfwhen speakingof socialism.
This “position” was itself an indication of one of the defining features
of Nehru’s socialism-the fact that nationalism, and a commitment
to the Congress, were the foundations upon which his association was
based. Nehru’s conversion to socialism in the 1920s did not compromise
his absolute dedication to the nationalist cause and to the Congress
as the vehicle for its pursuit This did not mean that Nehru’s socialism
amounted to no more than public declarations. It did mean, however,
that Nehru’s various activities in promoting the socialist ideal were
constrained by his commitment to nationalism and to the Congress.
Nehru sought, above all else, to radicalize the Congress-to introduce
socialist elements, step by step, into the program and practice of the
INC, at a pace that would not endanger the unity of an ideologically
diverse organization. The task of promoting socialism therefore became
an essentially ideological one of winning over increasing numbers of
adherents, and thereby facilitating the radicalization of the Congress.
If, as all this suggests, Nehru’s case was one of a nationalist who
The first question Nehru had to address-as indeed did any Indian
nationalist-was “What is India?” In other words, what was this entity
for which “independence” was being sought, and what constituted its
unity and distinguished it from other nations?
This question had become particularly pressing and particularly
difficult to answer with the growth of communalism in the 1920s. Indian
nationalists had to establish not only that the British had no right
to dominion over India but also, in argument and in practice, that
there was an India-a unified collective entity rather than a congerie
of (warring) religions, castes, and princely states.
Part of Nehru’s answer to the question of what constituted the unity
of India was culture. In an article directly addressed to this question,
entitled “The Unity of India,” Nehru wrote that despite the immense
variety of India, “the tremendous or fundamental fact of India is her
essential unity throughout the ages.. . . This Indian background and
unity were essentially cultural.”5
Nehru was only too well aware, however, that Indian civilization
was composed of many religions, languages, and customs-composed,
in short, of many cultures. What allowed for all these to be assimilated
into a single, all-encompassing “culture”? His answer was that Indian
culture was a synthesis. This culture was dominated, it is true, by one
particular strand within it, Hinduism. Hinduism in premodern times,
however, was “vague, amorphous, many sided, all things to all men.
It is hardly possible to define it.’’a Because it could not be defined,
because it was a way of life rather than a religion, it was inclusive
rather than exclusive. Indian culture was Hindu only in the sense that
it was marked by a flexibility and tolerance that enabled it to synthesize
the many cultures of invaders of India into the one culture-one
dominated not by any specific set of beliefs and practices but by the
principle of tolerance.’
Culture, then, was part of Nehru’s answer as to what constituted
the unity of India. Taken by itself, however, this answer did not satisfy
him, for this unity was the combination (or synthesis) of so many
particularities of religion, caste, custom, and so on that it was not an
inner or organic unity. Moreover, as we shall see, Nehru was a vehement
critic of many of these particularities. It was not upon these that he
wished to found an independent nation.
what counted ultimately were the people of India, people like them
and me, who were spread out all over this vast land. Bharat Mala,
Mother India, was essentially these millions of people, and victory
to her meant victory to these people. You are parts of this Bhurut
Mutu, I told them, you are in a manner yourselves Bhrut Mutu.’”
culture, but of history; that they were so closely associated with the
West was a function of the uneven nature of historical development,
not of any essential superiority of Westerners or their culture.
Specifically, these differences were largely a result of the industrial
revolution in the West:
The virtues of the West were in this way acknowledged, but also
immediately historicized, and thereby detached from their Western
origins. Rationalism and nationalism were thereby reconciled with the
aid of historicism. Western science, industry, and even social institutions
could now be praised and emulated by a militant nationalism-precisely
by postulating their sociohistorical origins, rather than their origins
in a specific spirit or culture. Indeed, it was now possible for nationalism
to assume a radical, transformative position, to criticize Indian culture
vigorously from a modern rationalist perspective without ceasing to
be nationalist, Nehru told a student audience:
You have stated somewhere that India has nothing to learn from
the West.. . . I entirely disagree with this viewpoint and I neither
think the so-called Rama Raj was very good in the past, and nor
do I want it back. I think the western or r u t h industrial civilisation
is bound to conquer India.ID(emphasis added)
Nehruvian Socialism
Whither India? Surely to the great human goal of social and economic
equality, to the ending of all exploitation of nation by nation and
class by class, to national freedom within the framework of an
international cooperative socialist world federation?’
Here socialist theory, with its emphasis upon economic equality and
international cooperation, pointed to the direction in which to move
and provided the criteria by which progress was to be measured. It
thus not only made possible a worldview that saw history as the progress
of reason, it was a constitutive part of that rationalism. In fact, in
helping to define the ultimate human goal, socialism was not only
part of, but was the highest point of, rationalist thought.
If this was so of socialist theory, it was also true of socialism as
a social system. The conflict between capitalism and socialism, Nehru
wrote,
How was this possible? If the answer does not lie in Nehru’s
opportunism, in concluding we should perhaps look more closely at
what kind of Marxism it was that Nehru appropriated. Let us do so
first by focusing upon the relationship of Marxism to its intellectual
heritage.
Mam’s thought was at once heir to the Enlightenment, and an attempt
to develop a radical critique of some of the central concepts
Enlightenment thought bequeathed to subsequent intellectual systems.
“Enlightenment” is used here in a very broad sense, to include many
post-Enlightenment intellectual developments: as used here it denotes,
in effect, modernity-a “way of thinking,” embodied in certain notions
and concepts,which was born in the eighteenth century and has shaped
the Western intellectual tradition since.
Prominent in this way of thinking were notions of the paramountcy
of reason; of history as progress, and particularly as a process of the
mergence of reason into its own: of knowledge as science (a conception
of knowledge deeply indebted to the developments in natural science);
an evolutionist view of history and a view not only that history has
order and meaning but that order and meaning reside in history; and
so on. Not all of these notions were “discovered” by the Enlightenment,
and some (certainly historicism) do not, strictly speaking, belong to
it at all. But the Enlightenment sensibility marks the ground in which
such conceptions grew, until they gained a currency that marked them,
precisely, as features not of Enlightenment thought but of “modern”
thought.
Mam, as is obvious at first glance, also accepted many of these
notions. At the same time, he sought to subject this whole intellectual
system to a far-reaching critique, in at least two important senses. He
accepted and developed some of the central categories of bourgeois
thought, thereby revealing their contradictions and limitations-the
method of an ‘immanent critique’. His Economic and Philosophic
hfanuscri)ts and the first part of Capital Z (on value) are particularly
good illustrations of this.
Marx also sought to show that all systems of thought were products
of particular historical and social conditions. Thus the Enlightenment
became the bourgeois Enlightenment, and its most fundamental
was to be done, but Lenin’s dictum that the colonial question was
first and foremost a national question remained virtually
unchallenged.‘*
Thus when a communist politics came to be developed in and for
India-a small Communist Party of India was founded in 1925-
nationalism’was at the heart of it. The “political core” of Marxism
in the colonies-that which distinguished it from others seeking national
liberation-shrank to a series of propositions relating to strategic and
organizational questions. Thus in the East there was this added element
that had the effect of narrowing the gap between Marxism and other
political philosophies and movements, making possible an appropri-
ation of Marxism-the Marxist endorsement of nationalism (and, one
could add, Soviet socialism’s strong emphasis on the state as the
instrument for industrialization).
It was this combination of Marxism’s endorsement of nationalism and
its development into the most consistent form of Enlightenment
rationalism that facilitated its appropriation by a nationalism of the
Nehruvian type, one that was also committed to modernization and
also wedded to notions of science and progress. In the colonies, where
Marxism was not a critique of modernity, and whert it was largely
shorn of a distinctive political core, it could be appropriated by a
rationalist and modernizing nationalism without doing violence to
Marxism-that is, without cynicism and careful selection. Indeed, such
a “fusion,” amounting to the appropriation of Mamism bj nationalism,
would be successful. It would result in the production of a nationalism
that could at once be critical of India yet nationalist, internationalist,
and rationalist-a nationalism that could define progress and identify
its project as representing progress in the very measure that it was
genuine rather than cynical and selective.
This, then, was the meaning of Nehruvian socialism. Marxism was
attractive to it because it helped underwrite a modernist and statist
nationalism; and its appropriation of Marxism was possible because
of the nature of Marxism as it developed after Marx and because of
the position Marxists came to adopt toward colonial nationalism.
Notes
3. SU: 7, p, 180.
4. SU: 4. p. 511
5. J. Nehru, “The Unity of India,” in The Unity of India: Collected Writings
1937-40 (London: 1948), pp. 14-15. (This article was first published January
1938.)
6. Ibid., p. 77.
7. For a discussion of how Nehru sought to avoid essentialist constructions
of India by grounding Indian identity in “history”-and the problems attendant
on this-see SanjaySeth, “Nationalism,National Identity and ‘History’:Nehru’s
Search for India,” Thesis Eleven, no. 32 (1992).
8. Ibid., p. 19.
9. J. Nehru, “Speech at Sultanpur” (June 27,1936). SU: 7, pp. 297-298.
10. J. Nehru, Discovery of India (Calcutta: 1956), p. 63,
11. J. Nehru, “Presidential Address to Bombay PresidencyYouth Conference”
(December 12,1928). SU: 3, p. 205.
12. J. Nehru, “The Past and the Present” (August 1934), SU: 6, p. 439
13. Ibid.. p. 436.
14. J. Nehru, “Address to Indian Science Congress,” in The Unity of India,
note 5, p. 175.
15. J. Nehru, “Whither India” (October 1933). SU: 6, p. 3.
16. Ibid., p. 5.
17. J. Nehru, “Paper Read to International League of Women for Peace and
Liberty” (September 19271, SU: 2, p. 333. Similarly, in a speech to a student
meeting in Bombay (May 20,1928) Nehru declared that “Europe of the Middle
Ages was much the same as Asia of the Middle Ages.” SW 3, p. 185.
18. May 20,1928, SW, 3, pp. 185-186.
19. January 11, 1928, SU: 3, p. 14.
20. Nehru, note 15, p. 26.
21. J. Nehru, “India and the Need for International Contacts” (May 13,1928).
SU: 3, p. 379.
22. Ibid.
23. J. Nehru, “On the Indian Situation” (March 2,1927), SU: 2, p. 297.
24. Nehru, note 15, p. 16.
25. J. Nehru, press interview in Calcutta Uanuary 16, 1934), SU: 6, p. 90.
26. SU: 7, p. 180.
27. J. Nehru, An Autobiography (London, 1936). pp. 362-363
28. J. Nehru, “Address to Congress Socialist Party” (November 7, 1936). SU:
7, p. 542.
29. J. Nehru, “On the Indian Problem” (February 4,1936). SU: 7, p. 92
30. J. Nehru. “On the Indian Situation” (November 12,1935). SU: 7, p. 37.
31. Nehru, note 15, p. 16.
32. Ibid., p. 12.
33. Ibid., p. 8.
34. See, for example, Nehru. note 27, pp. 366,591.
35. I! Chattejee, note 1, p. 145.
36. Ibid., p. 140.
37. Ibid.
38. Ibid., p. 132.
39. Ibid.
40. Ibid., especially p. 140.