The Credit Ratings Game

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 27

THE JOURNAL OF FINANCE • VOL. LXVII, NO.

1 • FEBRUARY 2012

The Credit Ratings Game

PATRICK BOLTON, XAVIER FREIXAS and JOEL SHAPIRO∗

ABSTRACT
The collapse of AAA-rated structured finance products in 2007 to 2008 has brought
renewed attention to conflicts of interest in credit rating agencies (CRAs). We model
competition among CRAs with three sources of conflicts: (1) CRAs conflict of under-
stating risk to attract business, (2) issuers’ ability to purchase only the most favorable
ratings, and (3) the trusting nature of some investor clienteles. These conflicts create
two distortions. First, competition can reduce efficiency, as it facilitates ratings shop-
ping. Second, ratings are more likely to be inflated during booms and when investors
are more trusting. We also discuss efficiency-enhancing regulatory interventions.

[The investment] could be structured by cows and we would rate it


—Analyst at one of the main credit rating agencies in an e-mail referring
to structured finance products, April 5, 2007.1
THE ANALYST IN THE above statement refers to a key dilemma for credit rating
agencies (CRAs): How should they act when their principal source of revenue
comes from the firms whose products they are rating? This potential source of
conflict has repeatedly been brought to the public’s (and regulators’) attention,
particularly following the East Asian Financial Crisis (1997) and in the after-
math of the failures of Enron (2001) and Worldcom (2002), but it has never
been so salient as during the recent financial crisis. Indeed, while CRA prof-
its exploded with the growth of structured finance products (Moody’s profits,
e.g., tripled between 2002 and 20062 ), the large number of downgrades of these

∗ Bolton is with Columbia University; Freixas is with Universitat Pompeu Fabra; and Shapiro

is with University of Oxford. Bolton, Freixas, and Shapiro are also affiliated with CEPR. We
thank Adam Ashcraft, Heski Bar-Isaac, Marco Becht, Bo Becker, Itay Goldstein, Doh-Shin Jeon,
Jens Josephson, Navin Kartik, Marco Pagano, Ailsa Röell, Francesco Sangiorgi, David Skeie,
Chester Spatt, James Vickery, Mungo Wilson, and audiences at AFA 2010, Bank of England,
Bergen, BIS, Bocconi, CEPR conference on Transparency, Disclosure and Market Discipline in
Banking Regulation, FIRS 2009, Hunter, NBER Workshop on the Economics of Credit Rating
Agencies, NBER Securitization Working Group, NY Fed, NYU-Stern, SEC, Tilburg, and UPF for
helpful discussions. We also thank the Editor (Cam Harvey), an Associate Editor, and the referee
for detailed comments and suggestions. Shapiro gratefully acknowledges financial support from
the Spanish government under SEJ2006-09993 and from the Fundacion Ramon Areces. Freixas
acknowledges financial support from The Barcelona GSE Research Network and the Generalitat
de Catalunya.
1 Securities and Exchange Commission (2008, p. 12).
2 “Triple-A-Failure,” by Roger Lowenstein, New York Times Magazine, April 27, 2008. Moody’s

profits are the easiest of the CRAs to measure since they are a public stand-alone company. “Moody’s

85
86 The Journal of FinanceR

securities from 2007 onwards has fostered suspicion that ratings standards had
been relaxed during the boom years. Further along with these allegations of
possible conflicts of interest for CRAs, many commentators have also reproved
(institutional) bond investors for their excessive reliance on ratings, and for
not doing their homework in independently assessing default risk. The combi-
nation of CRA reliance on fees from issuers, investors who were too trusting,
and issuers looking to benefit from the mispricing of their issues could have led
to substantial ratings inflation with important systemic consequences.
In this paper, we combine these elements in a model of credit ratings and CRA
competition to analyze the equilibrium outcome of ratings and the efficiency
consequences of possible equilibrium ratings inflation. The model gives rise
to two fundamental equilibrium distortions. First, competition among CRAs
may reduce market efficiency since it facilitates ratings shopping by issuers
and results in excessively high reported ratings. We show in particular that,
as a result of issuer shopping, efficiency may be higher under a monopoly CRA
than under a duopoly despite the potential for the increased informativeness
of two ratings. Second, CRAs are more prone to inflate ratings during booms,
when there is a larger clientele of investors in the market who take ratings at
face value and when the risks of failure that could damage CRA reputation are
lower.
The key building blocks of our model are as follows:
1. Issuer payments for ratings: In practice, CRA fees involve both a fee at the
time of issuance and an annual fee for as long as the issue is outstanding.
Importantly, while CRAs have list price schedules, they may renegotiate
fees with regular customers (White (2002)).3 In addition, CRAs offer related
consulting services, such as prerating assessments.
2. Issuer shopping for ratings: In practice, as in our model, an issuer pays a
CRA only if it asks the CRA to make the rating public.4 Also, if an issuer
is unhappy with a rating, it may solicit another one.5
3. CRA credit models may vary in precision: We consider CRA credit risk mod-
els that provide imperfect assessments of default risk. As Deven Sharma,

operating margins exceeded 50% for the past 6 years, three to four times those of Exxon Mobil
Corp., the world’s biggest oil company.” “Bringing Down Wall Street as Ratings Let Loose Subprime
Scourge,” by Elliot Blair Smith, www.bloomberg.com, September 24, 2008.
3 The Securities and Exchange Commission found that, in a sample of subprime residential

mortgage-backed security (RMBS) deals, 12 arrangers represented 80% of the business in both
number and dollar volume, while for collateralized debt obligations (CDOs) of subprime deals, 11
arrangers accounted for 92% of the deals and 80% of the dollar volume (Securities and Exchange
Commission (2008, p. 32)).
4 “Typically the rating agency is paid only if the credit rating is issued” (Securities and Exchange

Commission (2008, p. 9)).


5 “Brian Clarkson, then president and chief operating officer of Moody’s Investor’s Service ac-

knowledged that, ‘There is a lot of rating shopping that goes on . . . What the market doesn’t know
is who’s seen certain transactions but wasn’t hired to rate those deals.”’ “Bond-Rating Shifts Loom
in Settlement; N.Y.’s Cuomo Plans Overhaul of How Firms Get Paid,” by Aaron Lucchetti, Wall
Street Journal, June 4, 2008.
The Credit Ratings Game 87

President of Standard & Poor’s (S&P), notes: “Events have demonstrated


that the historical data we used and the assumptions we made significantly
underestimated the severity of what has actually occurred.” 6
4. CRAs can make “adjustments” to their credit risk model outputs: As Griffin
and Tang (2010) show in their study of structured product credit ratings,
CRAs use noisy credit risk models, to which they make frequent adjust-
ments before determining the final rating. Importantly for our analysis,
the authors show that these adjustments tend to shift the rating upwards
relative to the model-predicted rating.
5. Reputation concerns for CRAs: As rating agencies executives often ar-
gue, CRAs are concerned about maintaining their reputation for providing
timely and accurate assessments of (changes in) default risk. Accordingly,
we introduce in our model a reputation cost that CRAs incur in the event
that an issue they rated highly ends up in default. Short-term gains from
inflating an issue’s quality can thus be smaller in our model than long-term
reputation losses from jaded investors.
6. Barriers to entry in the credit rating industry: We confine our analysis to
competition between two CRAs. However, it is possible, although some-
what tedious, to extend our analysis to the case of three CRAs, which
broadly speaking is the current market structure in the credit rating in-
dustry. This high concentration of CRAs is a reflection of large barriers
to entry into this industry. One “artificial” barrier was established by the
Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC), in 1975 when it created the
Nationally Recognized Statistical Rating Organization (NRSRO) designa-
tor, which indicates those CRAs whose ratings the SEC recognizes as being
valuable for investment decisions. Although seven firms initially received
this designation, mergers brought this number down to three (Standard &
Poor’s, Moody’s, and Fitch) and the SEC had not admitted new firms un-
til recently.7 Since Congress, local governments, and regulatory agencies
adopt this designation, White (2002, p. 52) argues that it has resulted in
an “absolute barrier to entry.” The extremely high profit margins of CRAs
are also emblematic of a highly concentrated industry.
7. Sophisticated and “trusting” investor clienteles: Some of the potential in-
vestors in rated issues are sophisticated and understand a CRA’s poten-
tial conflicts of interest; they are thus able to see through ratings infla-
tion. However, a significant fraction (which may vary) of investors are
trusting, in that they take the CRAs’ ratings at face value. This coexis-
tence of trusting and sophisticated investors may be due to different types
of incentives to perform due diligence. Trusting investors, for example,
may be pension fund managers, whose compensation only marginally de-
pends on the ex post return of the assets they manage. Moreover, the more

6 Testimony before the Committee on Oversight and Government Reform, United States House

of Representatives, Deven Sharma, October 22, 2008.


7 Until 2003, when the SEC gave Dominion the NRSRO designation. In 2005, A.M. Best received

the designation, and in 2006 three more designations were given out (White (2010)).
88 The Journal of FinanceR

complex the investments, the more costly it may be to uncover their value.
Sophisticated investors, on the other hand, could be hedge funds, whose
returns depend more directly on the profitability of the investment. Regu-
lation that forces managers to only purchase investments with good ratings
could also provide incentives to be trusting.8 In a study of the CRA credit
watch mechanism, Boot, Milbourn, and Schmeits (2006) model investors
who take ratings at face value, calling them institutional investors. Sim-
ilarly, Hirshleifer and Teoh (2003, p. 338) model investors with “limited
attention and processing power.” More generally, this allows for a rich and
subtle interaction between two different investor clienteles (which seems
of the essence for CRAs) and contributes to the literature on differences of
opinion.9
Incorporating these key features into our model, we demonstrate under what
situations ratings inflation is more likely to occur, what its impact on market
efficiency is likely to be, and what the impact of regulatory proposals is likely
to be. Furthermore, we examine empirical implications of the model and evi-
dence from current studies on CRAs and structured finance products. We now
summarize the main results.
Our most important result is that a duopoly ratings industry is generally less
efficient than a monopoly. The reason is that, although in a duopoly investors
could obtain more information, the issuer has more opportunities to shop for a
good rating and to take advantage of trusting investors by only purchasing the
best ratings. By extending the model to two periods to allow for endogenous
reputation, we further show that the greater efficiency of a monopoly CRA holds
for any parameter constellation. This result is consistent with the findings of
Becker and Milbourn (2011), who show that the greater competitive threat
posed by Fitch in the corporate bond market coincides with a deterioration in
ratings quality.
We next show that CRAs may inflate the quality of the issuer’s investment
when there are more trusting investors in the market and/or when CRA ex-
pected reputation costs are lower. As these features are common to entire
classes of issues of similar characteristics, ratings inflation is not just about
idiosyncratic attributes of a single issuer but rather has systemic effects. In
particular, during boom times, when more investors are trusting and the prob-
ability of getting caught is smaller, more ratings inflation is likely to occur. This
result is consistent with the findings of Ashcraft, Goldsmith-Pinkham, and

8 One might argue that investors were all sophisticated because they both originated and held

these securities. However, this is not true empirically. From Lehman Brothers calculations in
April 2008, we know that U.S. commercial and savings banks represented only 23% of the holders
of nonagency AAA securities. (“Residential Credit Losses—Going into Extra Innings?” Lehman
Brothers Securitized Products Research, 2008.) If we were generous, we might add broker dealers
(who held 6.1%) to the list of possible originators. The main other holders were government-
sponsored enterprises (GSEs) and the Federal Home Loan Bank (FHLB) System (18.8%), money
managers (13.8%), insurance companies (7.6%), and overseas investors (25.2%).
9 We provide a somewhat different (more institution-based) explanation for why differences of

opinion arise (see Harrison and Kreps (1978) and Scheinkman and Xiong (2003)).
The Credit Ratings Game 89

Vickrey (2009), who show that ratings of mortgage-backed securities (MBSs)


were least accurate at the peak of the real estate boom. We also show that
more precise CRA credit risk models enhance CRA payoffs from inflating their
ratings as well as increase their probability of getting caught ex post, so that
their overall effect is ambiguous.
We further show that, when an issuer is more important to a CRA, either
because it is a repeat issuer or because it has larger issues, the CRA is more
prone to inflate that issuer’s ratings. This result is in line with the findings
of He, Qian, and Strahan (2010), who show that CRAs rated large structured
product issuers more favorably, and Faltin-Traeger (2009), who finds that re-
peat issuers are more likely to stick with the same CRA if they received a more
favorable early rating.
Finally, we analyze reforms to the industry in the context of our model. The
Cuomo plan, which is an agreement between New York State Attorney General
Andrew Cuomo and the three main CRAs, requires that issuers pay CRAs for
their rating up-front, not contingent on the report. In our model, this plan
eliminates the incentives for CRAs to inflate ratings, but does not eliminate
shopping. Mandating automatic disclosure of any ratings solicited is therefore
necessary to get rid of the shopping distortion.10 In addition, the up-front fees
may undermine CRA incentives to invest in model accuracy and due diligence,
making oversight on methodology potentially important.
Next, we offer a summary of the related theoretical literature (Section VI is
dedicated to a discussion of the empirical evidence).

Related Theoretical Literature


There is a substantial literature on information intermediaries in both mi-
croeconomics and finance. The paper closest to ours is Mathis, McAndrews, and
Rochet (2009), who examine the incentives of a monopoly CRA to inflate ratings
in a model of endogenous reputation.11 They find that reputation cycles may
exist where a CRA builds up its reputation by relaying information accurately
only to exploit this reputation later by collecting fees for inflated ratings. They
also demonstrate that truth telling incentives are weaker when the CRA has
more business from rating complex products. While their model endogenizes
reputation, it restricts them to analyzing only a monopolist and to define a
complex product simply as one in which the CRA’s reputation is at stake. By
making the large assumption that reputation is exogenous, we are able to ex-
amine the effects of competition and include a wealth of parameters on which
we can perform comparative statics. Nevertheless, we endogenize reputation

10 This regulation can only address explicit shopping. The implicit shopping problem would

remain (see Sangiorgi, Sokobin, and Spatt (2009)).


11 Strausz (2005) and Bar-Isaac and Shapiro (2011) also model endogenous reputation for infor-

mation intermediaries. Strausz (2005) provides interesting insights in line with our findings, as he
argues that honest certification has some of the characteristics of a natural monopoly. Bar-Isaac
and Shapiro (2011) incorporate economic shocks and show that CRA accuracy may be countercycli-
cal, which is also consistent with our results.
90 The Journal of FinanceR

in a simple repeated game in Section VI to show that our results are indeed
robust.
In the microeconomics literature, information intermediaries are modeled
in acquiring and certifying information by committing to disclosure rules, as,
for example, in Biglaiser (1993) and Lizzeri (1999). In contrast, CRAs do not
commit to information disclosure rules and their incentives come from the pos-
sible reputation costs they incur when they provide inaccurate information.
This is akin to the issues financial analysts face when they recommend stocks,
as analyzed by Benabou and Laroque (1992) and Morgan and Stocken (2003).
The model of Morgan and Stocken (2003) also addresses the issue of unverifi-
able information provision, when the certifier can lie but thereby incurs a lying
cost (this problem is examined further in Kartik (2009), Kartik, Ottaviani, and
Squintani (2007), and Ottaviani and Sorensen (2006)).
Although our signaling game is simpler in some respects, we extend the
literature by examining how strategic contracting between the informed party
(the CRA) and an interested party (the issuer in our case) can affect information
revelation. Our problem is also related to the economics literature on strategic
contracting when the information revealed affects a third party, which covers
a wide number of microeconomics issues (see Inderst and Ottaviani (2009),
Durbin and Iyer (2009), and Mariano (2008)). In Pagano and Volpin (2010),
CRAs have no conflicts of interest, but can choose to be more or less opaque
depending on what the issuer asks for. The authors show that, because of the
existence of a winner’s curse, opacity can enhance liquidity in the primary
market but may cause a market freeze in the secondary market.
In Bolton, Freixas, and Shapiro (2007), we analyze a situation of strategic
contracting where the informed parties (banks) set prices for their products
at the same time as they provide recommendations about them to uninformed
investors. We show that competition unambiguously reduces banks’ incentives
to oversell their products. Interestingly, this turns out not to be the case in
our model of conflicts for CRAs. The reason is that CRA ratings are as likely
to be complements as substitutes and issuers may choose to purchase ratings
from both CRAs in equilibrium. Also, the presence of trusting investors distorts
CRA incentives to inflate ratings in the same way, whether in a duopoly or a
monopoly. In contrast, in Bolton et al. (2007), information revelation comes
from the banks’ need to differentiate their products.
Several related papers study other implications of shopping for good ratings.
Faure-Grimaud, Peyrache, and Quesada (2009) look at corporate governance
ratings in a market with truthful CRAs and rational investors. They show that
issuers may prefer to suppress their ratings if they are too noisy. They also
find that competition between rating agencies can result in less information
disclosure. Skreta and Veldkamp (2009) and Sangiorgi et al. (2009) also assume
that CRAs truthfully relay their information and demonstrate how noisier
information creates more opportunity for shopping by issuers to take advantage
of a naive clientele.
Farhi, Lerner, and Tirole (2010) are interested in how certifiers such as
rating agencies or academic journals position themselves with respect to the
The Credit Ratings Game 91

transparency and coarseness of their certifications. While they allow for het-
erogeneity among certifiers, they set aside reputation effects and the incentives
to produce generous ratings or certifications. They examine the strategy of sell-
ers (our issuers) when they face certifiers that differ in their standards. When
a fail for the high-level certification is not disclosed, sellers may opt for an
ambitious certification strategy (approaching certifiers with higher standards
first) provided the nondisclosure of the fail is not transparent. This strategy is
related to ratings shopping, as the result in both cases is that the market does
not observe negative information.
The paper is organized as follows. In Section II, we develop the model and
solve the case for a single CRA. In Section III, we analyze the case of com-
petition between two CRAs. Section IV compares efficiency in the two market
structures. Section V takes the conclusion from Section IV that competition
decreases efficiency and examines its robustness. Section VI investigates dif-
ferent plans to regulate the credit rating industry. Section VII lays out empir-
ical implications of the model and surveys the evidence. Finally, Section VIII
concludes.

I. The Model
We consider three types of risk-neutral agents: issuers, CRAs, and investors
with a measure of one. Funds from investors are sought by issuers for inde-
pendent investments in multiple periods, although we focus primarily on the
analysis of a single issue in the first period.
An investment is characterized by its probability of default: a bad invest-
ment defaults with probability p > 0, and a good investment defaults with
probability zero. Either type of investment yields the same return R when not
in default, and zero in default.12 The investment has constant returns to scale,
so that each unit issued has the same return profile.
All agents believe ex ante that the investment is good with probability 12 . This
creates a role for the CRA, which can use its technology to find out whether the
investment is good or bad. A signal θ ∈ {g, b}, which is the private information
of the CRA, has the following informational content about the true type ω of
the investment:
Pr(θ = g | ω = g) = Pr(θ = b | ω = b) = e.
The variable e measures the quality of the signal received, which we refer to
as the precision of the signal. At e = 12 the signal has revealed no information
and agents retain their ex ante beliefs. For e > 12 , the signal is informative. We
assume that the level of precision is known and lies in the interval ( 21 , 1).
The CRAs post their fee φ at which a rating can be purchased before they
receive the signal. When they are approached by an issuer, CRAs proceed to
12 In the working paper version of this model, we allowed for a positive recovery value conditional

on default. All of the same results continue to hold, so we have chosen this specification for
expositional purposes.
92 The Journal of FinanceR

retrieve the signal θ and produce a credit report. After observing the report, the
issuer chooses either to pay φ to have the CRA’s proposed rating distributed
or to refuse to purchase it. In other words, we allow the issuer to “shop” for
ratings. This timing is meant to capture in a simple way the back-and-forth
negotiations that often go on when CRAs make their ratings reports.13 If the
issuer shops and refuses to buy the CRA’s report, that in itself is a signal, which
conveys information to investors.
The published rating is a message or report of m = G (“Good” ) or m = B
(“Bad”) that is observable to investors. Once the rating is announced, or if it is
not announced due to the issuer’s refusal to purchase it, the issuer sets a uni-
form price T for the investment. Since the cost of the investment’s production
is normalized to zero, we can interpret the price T as a spread. After observing
the rating and the price T , investors finally decide how much of the investment
to purchase.
There are two types of investors, sophisticated and trusting. A fraction 1 − α
of investors is sophisticated. These investors observe the payoffs of the game
for both the CRA and the issuer, and therefore understand the CRA’s and
issuer’s potential conflict of interest. However, they do not know whether the
investment is good or bad, as they do not observe the signal of the CRA and
they only have access to the CRA’s report. Trusting investors assume that CRAs
always truthfully rate the investment and therefore take CRAs’ ratings at face
value. Also, when they don’t observe a rating, these investors simply retain
their ex ante beliefs. Sophisticated investors, in contrast, rationally update
their beliefs.
One way to motivate the coexistence of trusting and sophisticated investors is
to observe that different types of investors have different incentives to perform
due diligence. Trusting investors may be managing third party investments
and their pay may only depend marginally upon the realized return of the
assets they manage14 whereas sophisticated investors may be investing their
personal funds or their pay may be more closely tied to realized returns.
If investors find out that a CRA inflated its rating, they punish the CRA in
future periods by ignoring its reports. At the time the rating is issued, how-
ever, investors cannot determine whether the rating is truthful; more formally,
investors cannot determine whether the rating m ∈ {B, G} is equal to the signal
received by the CRA θ ∈ {b, g}. But investors are able to find out ex post whether
the CRA lied in the event of a default. In practice, it is difficult to determine
whether a CRA misled investors even ex post. Still, it is generally easier to

13 We do not allow for unsolicited ratings. These ratings are rare in practice (see Sangiorgi

et al. (2009)). In the Internet Appendix, we analyze the effects of restructuring an investment
(e.g., a structured financial product). We find this is likely to decrease market efficiency, as the
sole purpose of the restructuring is to offer a better rating to the trusting investor clientele. (An
Internet Appendix for this article is available online in the “Supplements and Datasets” section at
http://www.afajof.org/supplements.asp.)
14 Regulation that forces managers to only purchase investments with good ratings could also

provide these incentives. Lower incentives to perform due diligence could also be exacerbated by
investments that are more complex and difficult to value.
The Credit Ratings Game 93

make that determination ex post rather than ex ante. To simplify the analy-
sis, we make the somewhat extreme assumption that investors can perfectly
identify whether the CRA lied in the event of a default.15 Hence, if the CRA
receives a signal θ = g and reports m = G, then if the investment fails the CRA
will not be punished, as investors can see that it acted in good faith. However,
a CRA who receives a signal θ = b and reports m = G will be punished if the
project fails.
Reputation costs create an incentive for CRAs to tell the truth, since investors
can eventually learn and punish the CRA. We denote the reputation cost by
ρ. This is the discounted sum of future CRA profits, which are available when
the CRA is not caught lying.16 To simplify the analysis, we follow Morgan
and Stocken (2003), Ottaviani and Sorensen (2006), and Bolton et al. (2007)
by assuming that reputation costs are exogenously given. This allows us to
explore policy implications in a tractable manner.
Also for tractability, we also assume that the reputation ρ at stake is slightly
noisy:
ASSUMPTION 1: There is a tiny amount of uncertainty on the part of the CRA
about the actual value of ρ, that is, ρ ∈ [ρ̃ − ε, ρ̃ + ε] such that ε → 0. This
uncertainty is resolved when the CRA receives its signal.
This assumption restricts the CRA’s strategy space since, for any small
amount of uncertainty, however small, it will be unable to set fees exactly at
levels to make itself indifferent between reports. Thus, this small uncertainty
limits the CRA to pure strategies.
Investors can purchase either one unit or two units of the investment. We
assume that they have a reservation utility that is increasing in the size of
their investment; specifically, they need a return of u on the first unit of their
investment and a return of U on the second unit, where U > u.17 One may
think of this in several ways: it could be an investor holding her money in cash
and needing a larger return to invest all of it, a need for a higher return in
order to commit to only one investment vehicle and not diversify, or a form of
risk aversion.
We make the following assumptions on the returns on investment:
ASSUMPTION 2: (1 − p)R > u.
15 Formally, we can motivate this assumption by assuming that the recovery value in default

is a random variable and, even though the expected value is normalized to zero, the realizations
differ depending on the signal θ observed by the CRA ex ante. The economic idea here is that the
issuer also gets a noisy signal θ ex ante and takes greater precautions to salvage some recovery
value when θ = b than when θ = g.
16 This punishment may be more likely in the case of newer financial instruments like structured

finance products where demand for the product may dry up. From a broader perspective, the
punishment imposed may be from a change in the regulatory environment due to public outcry,
such as enforcing liability claims. Finally, although something similar has not occurred in the
recent crisis, the downfall of Arthur Andersen represents a severe punishment to a certification
intermediary.
17 The specific form the reservation utility takes could be modeled in multiple ways and give the

same results; this form is chosen for simplicity.


94 The Journal of FinanceR

ASSUMPTION 3: (1 − (1 − e) p)R > U .


ASSUMPTION 4: (1 − 2p )R < U .
Assumption 2 says that an investor who knows the investment is bad is
willing to purchase one unit. Assumption 3 says that an investor with reli-
able information that the investment is good is willing to purchase two units.
The information problem is explicit in Assumption 4: not knowing whether an
investment is good or bad (and evaluating the investment with the ex ante be-
liefs), an investor is not willing to purchase two units. This implies that, if the
CRA did not exist, the issuer would not be able to sell two units to any investor
since the probability that the issue is bad is too large. The CRA can therefore
potentially improve market efficiency by providing information. These assump-
tions are standard18 and are necessary to create a value-enhancing role for
CRAs through information provision.
To simplify our expressions for payoffs, we introduce the following notation:

V G = (1 − (1 − e) p)R − U

V B = (1 − ep)R − u
 p
V0 = 1 − R − u.
2
The terms V G and V B represent the marginal value19 to sophisticated in-
vestors when the CRA truthfully reports m = G and m = B, respectively. They
also represent the marginal value to trusting investors when the CRA reports
m = G and m = B, whether truthfully or not. The term V 0 is the marginal
value to investors who maintain their ex ante beliefs about the value of the
investment.

A. The Ratings Game with a Single CRA


We begin by examining the game with a monopoly CRA. The timing of moves
in this game is as follows:
1. The CRA posts its fee φ.
2. The CRA receives the signal and then makes a report of m = G or m = B.
3. The issuer observes the report and decides whether to buy and distribute
it. The issuer then sets a price T for a unit of the investment.

18 For example, Mathis et al. (2009) assume that, in the absence of a CRA, the investment will
not be purchased, and the CRA can improve market efficiency by providing information about
which investments are good.
19 We define the marginal value V B with respect to the first unit of investment and its reservation

value u because investors will only purchase one unit of a bad investment. We define the marginal
value V G with respect to the second unit of investment and its reservation value U because
investors will purchase two units of an investment they believe to be good, and since issuers are
assumed to use uniform pricing, the price must be based on the marginal unit.
The Credit Ratings Game 95

4. Investors observe the price T and the CRA rating, if there is any, and decide
how much of the investment to purchase.
5. The investment return is realized.
When the monopoly CRA receives a signal it must decide what to report.
The issuer must decide whether to purchase the report, and subsequently how
much to charge investors. Sophisticated investors must infer how good the
investment is and formulate their willingness to pay.20 We solve the game
backwards, beginning with the CRA decision of what report to issue after
observing the signal.
LEMMA 1: Given the fee φ, the CRA’s reporting strategy is as follows:
For φ > epρ, the CRA inflates ratings (always reports G).
For 0 < φ < epρ, the CRA reports the truth, relaying its signal perfectly.
The proof is in the Internet Appendix.
When the CRA offers a B rating, the issuer responds by not purchasing
this rating, as it only decreases investor valuations. The CRA therefore only
obtains the fee φ when it offers the G rating. There are thus two possible
reporting regimes, one in which the CRA inflates the investment quality (when
the fee is larger than the expected reputation cost) and one in which the CRA
truthfully reveals the investment quality (when the fee is smaller than the
expected reputation cost).
We proceed next to derive the equilibrium fees the CRA sets under each
informational regime.
PROPOSITION 1: The equilibrium of the fee setting game is
1. If α2V G − V 0 > epρ, the CRA inflates ratings, sets φ = α2V G − V 0 , and
has profits
 ep 
α2V G − V 0 + 1 − ρ.
2
2. If α2V G − V 0 < epρ, the CRA reports truthfully, sets φ = min[2V G −
max[αV 0 , V B], epρ], and has profits
1
min[2V G − max[αV 0 , V B], epρ] + ρ.
2
The proof is in the Internet Appendix.
Proposition 1 establishes that the CRA maximizes its profits by choosing
ratings inflation over truth telling whenever the profits from ratings inflation
(α2V G − V 0 ) are larger than the expected reputation cost epρ.21 Overstating

20 There are situations in which a report of “Bad” (m = B) is off the equilibrium path. Because we
employ the concept of Perfect Bayesian Equilibrium, there is no restriction on off-the-equilibrium-
path beliefs. However, we restrict attention to equilibria in which off-equilibrium-path beliefs are
equal to ex ante beliefs (i.e., the investment is expected to be good with probability 12 ).
21 The fee α2V G − V 0 represents selling two units of the investment to each trusting in-

vestor, who believes the G rating. This fee must subtract off V 0 , because the issuer must be
96 The Journal of FinanceR

the quality of the investment is an equilibrium outcome, despite the presence


of reputation costs. This is also a point that Mathis et al. (2009) make.
The cutoff α2V G − V 0 − epρ determines whether the CRA inflates the quality
of the investment. Thus, when reputation costs are smaller and the size of the
trusting audience larger, the CRA is more likely to take advantage of trusting
investors by inflating ratings. Conversely, when reputation costs are larger
and the size of the sophisticated audience larger, the CRA is more likely to tell
the truth and create information for all investors. This suggests that ratings
inflation is more likely in boom times when investors have lower incentives
to perform due diligence, as the ex ante quality of investments is then higher.
Note also that an increase in the precision of the signal e has competing effects.
It raises the expected valuation of trusting investors, giving higher short-term
returns to the CRA. On the other hand, it also increases the likelihood that the
CRA gets caught if it misled investors, decreasing future returns.

II. Competition among Ratings Agencies


We next examine the game where two ratings agencies compete in selling
ratings to issuers. The CRAs can be thought of as having differentiated prod-
ucts since they are receiving imperfect (e < 1) signals about the quality of the
investment. In addition, two ratings provide more information than just one
rating, so the issuer may want to purchase both. The timing of the game with
competition is similar to the game with one CRA:
1. Each CRA posts a fee φk, where k = 1, 2 represents the firm.
2. The CRAs receive their signals and produce reports of m = G or m = B.
3. The issuer observes the reports and decides whether to purchase and dis-
tribute one, both, or neither report. It then sets a price T per unit of the
investment.
4. Investors observe the report(s) purchased by the issuer and decide how
much of the investment to purchase.
5. The return is realized.
Again to simplify our expressions for payoffs, we adopt the following notation:
 
(1 − e)2
V GG = 1 − p R − U,
(1 − e)2 + e2

 
e2
V BB
= 1− p R − u.
(1 − e)2 + e2

The terms V GG and V BB represent the marginal value to sophisticated in-


vestors when both CRAs truthfully report m = G and m = B, respectively. They
also represent the marginal value to trusting investors when both CRAs report

compensated for deciding to do business with the CRA, rather than sell to investors with ex ante
valuations.
The Credit Ratings Game 97

m = G and m = B, respectively, whether truthfully or not. The marginal value


to trusting investors when one CRA reports m = G and the other reports m = B
is V 0 , the ex ante marginal value before any information about the investment
is obtained.
To simplify the analysis, we make the following assumption about the
marginal value of an additional positive report:22
ASSUMPTION 5: α2V G − V 0 > 2(V GG − V G ).
This means that the value of the first G report for trusting investors is
larger than the value of a second G report for all investors. This assumption
is a way of expressing decreasing returns to G reports. It is slightly stronger
than standard decreasing returns. This assumption is always satisfied if the
precision e is sufficiently high (close to one) or sufficiently low (close to one-half),
as in those cases V GG = V G .
We also make the following assumption:
ASSUMPTION 6: α2V G − V 0 − min[2(V GG − V G ), epρ D] < e2 pρ D.
This condition guarantees existence of the truth telling equilibrium by pre-
venting one CRA from unilaterally deviating to inflating its ratings and cater-
ing only to trusting customers. If this condition did not hold, there would be
less truth telling in duopoly, which would only strengthen our results on the
efficiency of monopoly in Sections IV and V.
Finally, we make the following assumption:
V0 V BB
ASSUMPTION 7: 2V G
< V0
.
This is not critical to the results at all, but simplifies the exposition.23
We denote the discounted sum of future profits in a duopoly for each CRA
if it is not caught lying by ρ D. Again this is an exogenous variable as in the
case of monopoly.24 As before, we solve the game backwards, beginning with
the decision of what report to issue after observing the signal.
22 Without Assumption 5, there can still be equilibria in which both CRAs tell the truth and

equilibria in which both CRAs always report G (and there would be no equilibria in which one
CRA tells the truth and one always reports G). However, there would be multiple equilibria for
each informational regime, there would need to be another restriction on parameters to guarantee
existence, and both types of equilibria could coexist. Assumption 5 also places a lower bound on α,
which means some shopping will always occur. This plays a role in our analysis of market efficiency.
23 Assumption 7 fixes the cutoffs for which shopping will occur. When there are two B reports the

issuer must decide between charging V 0 to trusting investors or V BB to everyone. There is then a
BB
cutoff VV 0 for α such that it is best to target trusting investors for α higher than this cutoff (when
there are two B reports), that is, max[αV 0 , V BB] = αV 0 . This will be relevant in the proposition
below and in the section on market efficiency.
24 Note that this is a stronger assumption, since with two CRAs it might be the case that should

one CRA be caught lying, the other CRA gets larger continuation profits. It might also be the case
that a CRA only gets caught if it is lying and the other CRA is telling the truth (Stolper (2009)
examines this type of reputation in a game where a regulator is actively monitoring and punishing
CRAs). Alternatively, it might be the case that both CRAs (the whole industry) get punished when
any CRA is caught. Furthermore, there may be an added difference between monopoly and duopoly
in the sense that when a monopoly CRA gets caught there is nowhere to turn, while when a duopoly
98 The Journal of FinanceR

LEMMA 2: For a given set of fees for both CRAs, CRA k’s reporting strategy is
as follows:
1. If φk > epρ D, the CRA inflates ratings (always reports G ).
2. If φk < epρ D, the CRA reports the truth, relaying its signal perfectly.
The proof is the same as that of Lemma 1. We next solve for the equilibrium
of the fee-setting game.
PROPOSITION 2: The equilibrium of the fee-setting subgame (assuming Assump-
tions 5 to 7 hold) is as follows:
1. If α2(V GG − V G ) > epρ D, both CRAs always report G, φk = α2(V GG − V G )
for k = 1, 2, and CRA profits are given by
 ep  D
α2(V GG − V G ) + 1 − ρ .
2
2. If α2(V GG − V G ) < epρ D, both CRAs report truthfully, φk = min[2(V GG −
V ), epρ D] for k = 1, 2, and CRA profits are given by
G

1
min[2(V GG − V G ), epρ D] + ρ D.
2
The proof is in the Internet Appendix.
There are thus two possible equilibria: one in which both CRAs always
inflate the quality of the investment, and one in which both CRAs truth-
fully reveal their information about the investment. The cutoff determining
which equilibrium prevails is whether the current payoff from inflating ratings
α2(V GG − V G ) is larger or smaller than the expected cost of getting caught
epρ D.
In general, with a larger fraction of sophisticated investors and a larger rep-
utation cost there will be more truth telling. An increase in the precision of the
signal, however, creates a trade-off. The probability of getting caught is rising
in the precision, making truth telling more likely. But the current payoff from
manipulating (α2(V GG − V G )) is increasing for low precision levels, meaning
that truth telling is less likely. However, in contrast to the case of monopoly, for
high precision levels the current payoff is decreasing in the precision, meaning
that current and future incentives are aligned in making truth telling more
likely.
Comparing the outcome under competition to the case of a monopoly CRA—
where the cutoff for truth telling is whether α2V G − V 0 − epρ is larger than
zero or not—we find that, as the marginal value of a positive CRA report is de-
creasing, the payoff to inflating ratings is larger in a monopoly. Still, it is likely
that ρ > ρ D, since the expected loss of business should be larger in monopoly,
which may mitigate the increase in fees available to the monopolist. Note,
however, that if trusting investors were to overestimate the precision of the

CRA gets caught there is a reasonable alternative (the other CRA). This approach is taken in the
context of firms selling goods of varying qualities in Hörner (2002).
The Credit Ratings Game 99

CRAs’ reports, the incentive to inflate would be very strong irrespective of mar-
ket structure (current payoffs increase, future costs do not change). Ashcraft
and Schuermann (2008, p. (ii)) support the idea of overestimation, noting that
“Credit ratings were assigned to subprime MBS with significant error. Even
though the rating agencies publicly disclosed their rating criteria for subprime,
investors lacked the ability to evaluate the efficacy of these models.” Finally,
if we define shopping as taking place when there are less than two G signals
(Pr(Shopping) = 1 − Pr(two G signals)), we find that shopping increases in
duopoly when precision decreases.25 Skreta and Veldkamp (2009) also point
out that less precise signals imply more ratings shopping by issuers.

III. Market Efficiency


We now turn to the evaluation of the efficiency of equilibrium outcomes.
Note that in our model it is not completely obvious what the relevant efficiency
benchmark is, as a fraction of investors are trusting. We consider total ex
ante surplus,26 evaluating expected surplus for all agents from the point of
view of a sophisticated agent, thus adopting a paternalistic point of view. In
other words, we take the view that one role of financial regulation is to protect
trusting investors from mistakes they may make based on faulty information.
The main motivation for this view is that trusting investors would support such
regulations with the benefit of hindsight once their naivete is exposed.
We begin by establishing two benchmarks for total surplus, the first-best and
the market solution when there are no CRAs. The first-best (subscript FB) is
given by
1 1
WFB = (2R − u − U ) + ((1 − p)R − u)
2 2
1
= V + (R − U ).
0
2
This expression is given by the probability that the investment is good mul-
tiplied by the surplus created when investors purchase two units plus the
probability that the investment is bad multiplied by the surplus when only one
unit is purchased.
The market solution when there are no CRAs (subscript 0) is given simply
by
W0 = V 0 ,
25 As Charles Calomiris has argued: “Subprime was a relatively new product, [. . .] Given the

recent origins of the subprime market which postdates the last housing cycle downturn in the
U.S. (1989-1991), how were the rating agencies able to ascertain what the LGD would be on a
subprime mortgage pool?” Thus, the lower precision of CRAs’ information about subprime credit
risk may have been a source of ratings inflation through greater shopping pressure by issuers.
“The Subprime Turmoil: What’s Old, What’s New, and What’s Next,” by Charles Calomiris, Vox:
//www.voxeu.org/index.php?q=node/1561, 2008.
26 In a previous version of the paper, we also used investor surplus to evaluate market efficiency.

The results were the same when comparing truthtelling regimes, but stronger when comparing
ratings inflation regimes (duopoly had strictly lower investor surplus than monopoly).
100 The Journal of FinanceR

since both trusting and sophisticated investors would then only purchase one
unit. The maximum surplus that can be gained through the provision of credit
ratings is therefore given by 12 (R − U ), the extra unit purchased when the
investment is good.
We now analyze the total surplus in each regime for both monopoly and
duopoly. In the total surplus calculations we add the surplus of investors,
CRAs, and issuers. The fees of CRAs and the prices charged by issuers net
out. Note also that we exclude future surplus from our welfare calculations
and look only at efficiency in the short run, as our reputation parameters ρ and
ρ D are exogenous. Finally, note that Assumption 5 implies that α2V G − V 0 > 0,
V0
or α > 2V G . We therefore examine total surplus (and investor surplus) only for
0
the interval α ∈ [ 2V
V
G , 1].

1. Monopoly CRA, ratings inflation regime (α2V G − V 0 > epρ):


Only trusting investors purchase at the high prices, as the rating reveals
no positive information to sophisticated investors. Since trusting investors
believe the investment is good, they invest two units. Total surplus is
then
G
WM = α[V 0 + (V 0 + u − U )] (1)

(where the subscript M refers to the monopoly and the superscript G refers
to the fact that the CRA always reports G).
This expression is positive, although it may be quite small. The first term
in the expression in square brackets is our market solution when there are
no CRAs and is positive, while the second term is negative by Assumption
4. Hence, as intuition suggests, the presence of a CRA reduces surplus in
this scenario.
2. Monopoly CRA, truth telling regime (α2V G − V 0 < epρ):
There are two subcases here, depending on how the issuer prices the in-
vestment when there is no report (interpreted correctly by sophisticated
investors as a B report that was not purchased). First, when αV 0 < V B,
the issuer optimally sets its price low enough to sell the issue to both types
of investors. Total surplus then equals:
1 G
WMT 1 = V 0 + V . (2)
2
As expected, the surplus is higher than when there is no CRA as V G > 0 by
Assumption 3. As the precision approaches e = 1, the surplus approaches
the first-best.
When αV 0 > V B, there is an additional distortion because the issuer then
sets its price high (when there is no report) to cater only to trusting in-
vestors. In this subcase, total surplus is obviously smaller:
1 G 1−α B
WMT 2 = V 0 + V − V . (3)
2 2
The Credit Ratings Game 101

3. Duopoly, ratings inflation regime (α2(V GG − V G ) > epρ D):


Total surplus here is exactly the same as when there is a monopoly CRA who
always reports G. Trusting investors purchase two units and sophisticated
investors purchase nothing. The split of rents between CRAs and the issuer,
however, is different here, as the issuer can earn more than V 0 per investor
due to competition. If there is a fixed operating cost for CRAs, this would be
less efficient than the case of a monopoly CRA. Both an inflating monopoly
and an inflating duopoly are less efficient than a market without CRAs.
4. Duopoly, truth telling regime (α2(V GG − V G ) < epρ D):
V0 V BB
When α ∈ [ 2V G , V 0 ], the issuer sets the price so as to cater to both types of

investors when there is no report. Total surplus then equals


1 2
WDT 1 = (e2 + 2e(1 − e)α + (1 − e)2 )V 0 + (e − (1 − e)2 )(R − U )
2
+ (2e(1 − e)α + (1 − e)2 )(V 0 + u − U ). (4)
BB
In contrast, when the fraction of trusting investors is large (α ∈ [ VV 0 , 1])
and when there are no G reports the issuer sets a high price at which only
trusting investors purchase. Trusting investors are also the only ones to
purchase when there is only one G report. Thus, the total surplus is the
same as in equation (4), minus the surplus lost from the fact that the issuer
targets only trusting investors:
1 2
WDT 2 = (e2 + 2e(1 − e)α + (1 − e)2 )V 0 + (e − (1 − e)2 )(R − U )
2
+ (2e(1 − e)α + (1 − e)2 )(V 0 + u − U ) (5)
1−α  
− (1 − e)2 (R − u) + e2 ((1 − p)R − u) .
2
Comparing these expressions for total surplus in equations (1) to (5), we find
a surprising result: Truth telling in duopoly yields a lower surplus than truth
telling in monopoly. We establish this result in the following proposition:
PROPOSITION 3: Given Assumptions 1 to 7, a truth telling monopoly strictly
dominates a truth telling duopoly.
The proof is in the Internet Appendix.
A duopoly is less efficient because there are more opportunities for the issuer
to take advantage of trusting investors. This can occur when one CRA reports
G and one reports B, or when both report B. In contrast, under a monopoly
CRA there is an opportunity to shop only when the monopoly CRA reports B.
As a result, issuers set high prices that exclude sophisticated investors from
the market when, from an efficiency perspective, they should be participating.
Also, the additional information of the second report is wasted. This is pred-
icated on the fact that Assumption 5 places a lower bound on the number of
trusting investors, since, clearly, shopping doesn’t occur when all investors are
sophisticated.
102 The Journal of FinanceR

This result, taken together with the fact that a duopoly is as efficient as
a monopoly when both are inflating the quality of the investment (and less
efficient if we consider operating costs), suggests that competition among in-
formation intermediaries may be detrimental when shopping is allowed. More
formally, conditional on being in the same informational regime, monopoly in-
creases total surplus. Therefore, policies encouraging entry may not be the
best methods to increase efficiency. This result is in line with the evidence pre-
sented in Becker and Milbourn (2011), who document less accurate ratings in
the corporate bond market due to more competition from Fitch.

A. Are There Any Benefits to Competition?


Our result that competition among CRAs reduces market efficiency is ob-
tained by comparing outcomes under a monopoly and a duopoly for the same
informational regime. A natural question that arises is whether there can be
any benefits to competition when the informational regime differs across mar-
ket structures. Consider first the comparison of monopoly and duopoly under
different information regimes. It is easy to see that a truth telling monopoly
not only dominates a truth telling duopoly but also a duopoly in which CRAs
inflate ratings. But does a monopoly CRA that inflates ratings dominate a truth
telling duopoly? The next lemma establishes that this is not the case.
LEMMA 3: Total surplus for a truth telling duopoly is larger than that of a
monopoly CRA that inflates ratings.
The proof is in the Internet Appendix.
This lemma underscores the harmful effects of CRA ratings inflation rela-
tive to issuer shopping. The parameters for which both scenarios can occur
simultaneously depend on the intersection of the following two inequalities:
(1) α2(V GG − V G ) < epρ D, which guarantees that CRAs in a duopoly prefer to
rate truthfully, and
(2) α2V G − V 0 > epρ, which ensures that a monopoly CRA prefers to inflate
ratings to attract more issuers.
A few observations are worth pointing out. First, these inequalities can only
hold in both market structures if the measure α of trusting investors is small.
Otherwise, the financial rewards for CRAs from inflating their ratings and
overselling the issue to trusting investors are just too high. Second, truth
telling in the duopoly is more likely when the informational value of a second
rating is low (V GG close to V G ). Thus, somewhat paradoxically, a CRA duopoly
dominates a monopoly only in situations in which the marginal value of a
second CRA is small. Moreover, in the following section we demonstrate that
when reputation is endogenized, the CRAs will be in the same information
regime for all parameters, which implies that monopoly is always more efficient.
Finally, note that, even when a duopoly dominates a monopoly, this does not
imply that competition is efficient, as the negative effects from issuer shopping
remain. It is straightforward to show that reducing competition to create a
The Credit Ratings Game 103

regulated duopoly, in which issuers are required to purchase a rating from both
CRAs, would be welfare superior to an unregulated duopoly.27 Indeed, under
such a regulation (1) CRAs would always strictly prefer to rate truthfully, as the
purchase of their rating is then no longer contingent on its content; (2) issuer
shopping would be eliminated; and (3) issues would be rated based on the
maximum available information. In fact, without the CRA conflict of interest
and issuer shopping, total surplus would be equal to the first-best (constrained,
of course, by the precision of the CRAs’ information).28

IV. Endogenous Reputation


We now explore the effect of endogenizing reputation costs in a fully specified
dynamic model. The endogenous reputation cost from being caught inflating
ratings is the cost in forgone future ratings sales. The simplest way of extending
our model to allow for such an endogenous reputation cost is to consider a two-
period version in which the payoff weight attached to the second period is given
by a parameter β (as, e.g., in Laffont and Tirole (1993)), where β may be larger
than one. The size of the parameter β then represents the importance of future
relative to current profits for the CRAs. Thus, for example, at the onset of an
issuance boom future capitalized CRA profits are likely to be large, so that β is
large. In contrast, at the end of an issuance boom and at the onset of a recession
β is small.
Consider first the situation of a monopoly CRA. The simplification obtained
from the two-period formulation is that we can solve the game backwards
starting from the second period (taking as given that the CRA has not been
caught inflating ratings in the first period). As the second period is the last
period, there are no more reputation concerns that discipline the CRA, so that
the CRA always inflates its ratings. From Assumption 5 we know α2V G −
V 0 > 0, so that the CRA’s optimal policy in the second period is to sell the
overrated issue only to trusting investors and thus realize a positive profit of
α2V G − V 0 . In period 1, endogenous reputation costs from forgone future profits
are then given by ρ = β(α2V G − V 0 ). With such an endogenous reputation cost,
the CRA then inflates ratings in period 1 if and only if

(α2V G − V 0 ) > epβ(α2V G − V 0 ),

or
1
β< .
ep
This simple analysis of the dynamic CRA monopoly thus reveals that with
endogenous reputation costs a CRA is more likely to engage in ratings inflation

27 In the model, this means purchasing from two CRAs. In practice, realistically this would

imply purchasing from the big three CRAs (Moody’s, Standard & Poor’s, and Fitch).
28 Issuers may lose out under this regulation if CRAs remain free to set prices since, as under a

monopoly, the entire issuer surplus may be appropriated by the CRAs.


104 The Journal of FinanceR

when future profits matter less, for example, towards the end of an issuance
boom. This result is consistent with both the theoretical results of Mathis et al.
(2009) and the empirical findings of Ashcraft, Goldsmith-Pinkham, and Vickery
(2010).
Consider next the situation of a duopoly CRA. Once again, the two CRAs
inflate ratings in period 2, as there are no costs in being caught inflating ratings.
Each CRA’s best response in the second period is to sell the overrated issue
only to trusting investors and thus realize a positive profit of α2(V GG − V G ).
In period 1, then, endogenous reputation costs from foregone future profits are
given by ρ D = βα2(V GG − V G ). In period 1 a CRA duopoly that inflates ratings,
in which each CRA earns α2(V GG − V G ), is then an equilibrium if and only if
α2(V GG − V G ) > epβα2(V GG − V G ),
or again
1
β< .
ep
This implies the following result:
PROPOSITION 4: In the model with endogenous reputation costs, in the first
period
(1) the CRA(s) report truthfully in both monopoly and duopoly iff β ≥ ep
1
, and
(2) the CRA(s) inflate ratings in both monopoly and duopoly iff β < ep .
1

Thus, with endogenous reputation costs, it is the same condition that deter-
mines whether a monopoly CRA or a duopoly CRA will rate truthfully in period
1 or not. In other words, in our simple dynamic extension with endogenous rep-
utation costs, the equilibrium information regime is the same across market
structures, so that a monopoly always dominates a duopoly in this situation.
This simple analysis thus suggests that making reputation endogenous may
well strengthen our efficiency results rather than weaken them. It would be of
interest (but beyond the scope of this paper) to explore these issues more sys-
tematically in a fully general dynamic game, possibly with an infinite horizon.
There is currently no model of oligopolistic competition over an infinite horizon
in the CRA literature; indeed, there are very few such models in the industrial
organization literature for obvious reasons of tractability.29

V. Regulating the Credit Ratings Industry


The subprime crisis has brought to light the poor performance of CRAs in
rating structured financial products and reminded investors of CRAs’ poor past
performance in predicting the East Asian crisis, the excesses of the dotcom
bubble, and the collapse of Enron. Governmental bodies have been debating
how to regulate CRAs, and some initial rules have thus been issued.
29 See Bar-Isaac and Tadelis (2008) for a review of the literature.
The Credit Ratings Game 105

In this section we discuss the most prominent proposals in the context of our
model. In our view, the key issues that the proposals seek to address are as
follows:
(1) eliminate the CRA conflicts of interest by preventing issuers from influenc-
ing ratings,
(2) prevent issuers from shopping for ratings and disclosing only those ratings
they prefer, and
(3) monitor the quality of the ratings methodology.
New York State Attorney General Andrew Cuomo reached an agreement30
with credit ratings firms to change some features of the rating process in
the summer of 2008. The agreement between Cuomo and Standard & Poor’s,
Moody’s, and Fitch essentially addresses the first point, preventing issuers from
paying for specific ratings and forcing issuers to pay the CRA up front before it
conducts its initial analysis.31 This restriction can eliminate ratings inflation
by CRAs in our model by eliminating the issuer’s ability to provide incentives
for good ratings.32 Importantly, however, it does not eliminate shopping by
an issuer; an issuer may still reach an agreement with a CRA to not publish
a bad rating. In our model, issuer shopping can create distortions even with
unbiased CRA ratings due to the trusting nature of some investors. There have
been several moves to decrease CRA conflicts of interest. The SEC recently
enacted a rule that prohibits consulting activity related to ratings by CRAs. The
Dodd-Frank financial reform bill further states that ratings must be explicitly
separated from sales and marketing.33
Prohibiting shopping by requiring that CRAs automatically disclose any rat-
ing paid for by an issuer would achieve the first-best surplus34 in our model
when combined with the Cuomo plan. The SEC currently has a proposed rule
that would formalize this prohibition. Nevertheless, shopping may be difficult
to eliminate because of informal discussions between issuers and CRAs that
may still take place. This points to a possible need for auditing by a regulator.

30 The agreement is reportedly for 3 years and on structured finance products only, see “Big

Credit-Rating Firms Agree to Reforms,” by Aaron Lucchetti, Wall Street Journal, June 6, 2008.
31 There is a fine point here, namely, the deal specifies up-front payments for initial analysis

but does not prevent subsequent payments. This is obviously an issue, but outside the scope of our
model.
32 It is possible, of course, to dynamically create these incentives through repeated interactions

between an issuer and a CRA. Such analysis is out of the scope of this paper, but the point is
certainly a caveat.
33 An intriguing proposal to diminish conflicts of interest was taken out of the Dodd-Frank bill

at the last minute (and was relegated to be the subject of a formal study by the SEC). The “Franken
Amendment” proposed to set up a body that would randomly assign issuers of structured finance
products to rating agencies. If fees were paid up front to the body, this could eliminate both conflicts
of interest and shopping.
34 While quite intuitive, we prove this formally in the Internet Appendix. An interesting un-

intended consequence of eliminating shopping is to reduce the number of ratings, which occurs
because the rents to an extra rating decrease. This is not a complete surprise, as our model demon-
strates that monopoly is more efficient than duopoly.
106 The Journal of FinanceR

Even by eliminating shopping from the Cuomo plan, there is a risk of effi-
ciency loss due to moral hazard. Suppose the precision of the signal e is a choice
variable of the CRA and larger precision is more costly. If the CRA can choose
this precision after being paid up front35 and it is noncontractible, then the
CRAs would choose the minimum precision of 12 and, knowing this, the issuer
would not hire the CRA in the first place. There would thus be a breakdown in
the market for certification.
Interestingly, our main model with no regulation shows that adding the ob-
servable choice of precision in monopoly will lead to positive investment by the
CRA since the issuer pays contingent fees. Still, our total surplus calculations
show that breakdown of the CRA market could still be a better outcome than
one in which a CRA inflates quality, but worse than an outcome in which a
CRA tells the truth. Consequently, it is crucial that the new regulatory struc-
ture for CRAs be accompanied by oversight of minimum analytical standards
for the CRAs (and that these standards be enforceable), so as to regain the ben-
eficial aspects summarized earlier. The Dodd-Frank bill discusses analytical
standards and mandates that the SEC issue rules regarding both training, ex-
perience, and competence for CRA analysts and procedures and methodologies
for the ratings.
One last approach to improving ratings quality lies in enhancing the market’s
ability to punish CRAs. In our model, this would increase CRA’s reputation cost,
making truth telling more likely. The SEC has issued rules forcing CRAs to dis-
close their track record, making their performance more transparent. More im-
portantly, the Dodd-Frank bill lowers the bar for liability claims against CRAs.
CRAs had been “immune from liability for misstatements . . . under Section 11
of the Securities Act of 1933” and have won most cases against them based
on arguments that credit ratings are free speech and “extensively disclaimed”
(Partnoy (2002, pp. 78, 79)). Eliminating this immunity could therefore impose
serious costs on CRAs for ratings inflation.

VI. Empirical Implications


This paper demonstrates that competition among CRAs can reduce market
efficiency due to the shopping effect and provides a framework for understand-
ing the trade-offs in recent policy proposals regarding the credit rating industry.
In this section we examine evidence surrounding testable implications of the
model. We conclude by discussing systematic evidence related to our assump-
tion that investors are trusting.
The model offers several testable hypotheses:
1. The model shows that poor quality ratings are increasing in the fraction
of trusting investors and current payoffs, and decreasing in the expected
probability of getting caught (the reputation cost). While it is difficult to
35 If precision were not effort in performing the analysis on the investment, but rather quality of

the analytic models used, then the CRAs would choose greater precision, since the level of precision
would entirely be chosen before the fees were paid.
The Credit Ratings Game 107

measure these variables, all three of these factors are more likely to occur
during boom times and less likely to occur during recessions: when times
are good, the probability of defaults is lower, which may decrease due
diligence on the part of investors as well as evidence of ratings bias. As a
follow-on effect, this can increase demand and issuance, generating larger
fees for CRAs. To test this implication of the model, we can examine whether
poor ratings quality is more likely during boom times.
2. As opposed to other theoretical papers, ratings inflation can arise in our
model purely due to conflicts of interest and not shopping. Empirically,
we can attempt to exploit the lack of shopping possibilities in the corpo-
rate bond markets to examine whether conflicts of interest (the trade-off
between higher current profits and expected future profits) have some ex-
planatory power. Variables that affect current and future profits, such as
the degree of competition, can be related to ratings quality.
3. We show in the section on competition that shopping is more likely when
the CRAs’ models are less precise.
4. Shopping is used by issuers to exploit trusting investors. Hence, if shop-
ping occurs, investors are not taking into account the selection effect. These
observations can be used to test two implications of the theory, namely (i)
yields are more dependent on ratings when there is more shopping-type be-
havior, and (ii) fewer published ratings predict worse ex post performance.
We make use of recent empirical papers on CRAs and ratings quality to ex-
amine our hypotheses. To do so, we interpret investment in our model broadly
as applying to both the corporate bond markets and structured finance prod-
ucts (indeed, in the Internet Appendix we explicitly model the restructuring
process). We attempt to point out where institutional details benefit or detract
from the model.
The implication that ratings inflation is more likely to happen during booms
has been documented in several recent papers. Ashcraft et al. (2010) find that
as MBS issuance volume shot up between 2005 and mid-2007, ratings qual-
ity declined. Specifically, subordination levels36 for subprime and Alt-A MBS
deals decreased over this period when conditioning on the overall risk of the
deal.37 Moreover, subsequent ratings downgrades for the 2005 to mid-2007
cohorts were dramatically larger than for previous cohorts. Griffin and Tang
(2010) find that CRA adjustments to their models’ predictions of credit risk in
the CDO market were positively related to future downgrades. These adjust-
ments were overwhelmingly positive and the amount adjusted (the width of
the AAA tranche) increased sharply from 2003 to 2007 (from 6% to 18.2%). The
adjustments are not well explained by natural covariates (such as past deals

36 The subordination level they use is the fraction of the deal that is junior to the AAA tranche.

A smaller fraction means that the AAA tranche is less “protected” from defaults, and therefore less
costly from the issuer’s point of view.
37 Alt-A mortgages, short for Alternative A-paper, are those mortgages that have prime borrow-

ers but a nonstandard characteristic, e.g. regarding documentation. This makes them riskier than
prime mortgages but less risky than subprime ones.
108 The Journal of FinanceR

by collateral manager, credit enhancements, and other modeling techniques).


Furthermore, 98.6% of the AAA tranches in their sample CDOs failed to meet
the CRAs’ reported AAA standard (for their sample from 1997 to 2007). They
also find that adjustments increase CDO value on average by $12.58 million
per CDO.
On the relationship between current payoffs and ratings inflation, He et al.
(2010) find that MBS tranches sold by larger issuers38 performed significantly
worse (market prices decreased) than those sold by small issuers during the
boom period of 2004 to 2006. Faltin-Traeger (2009) shows that when one CRA
rates more deals for an issuer in a half-year period than another CRA, the first
CRA is less likely to be the first to downgrade that issuer’s securities in the
next half-year. He also finds that, if a CRA rates a deal higher, that CRA is
more likely to be chosen by the issuer on the issuer’s next deal. This effect is
strongest for Fitch.
Our model isolates two basic causes of poor ratings quality: conflicts of inter-
est (ratings inflation) and shopping. While it is difficult to isolate these in real-
ity, an interesting comparison arises between the corporate bond market and
the structured finance market. First, in the corporate bond market, Standard
& Poor’s and Moody’s rate virtually every rated issue. This implies that there is
little scope for shopping in that market. Nevertheless, our model suggests that
the trade-off between current profits and future payoff may still influence rat-
ings quality. Becker and Milbourn (2011) find supporting evidence: they show
that increases in market share by Fitch (a proxy for more competition) lead to
higher ratings. Moreover, this evidence suggests that more competition may
not be better, even when shopping is not as much of an issue.
Second, the methodology for rating corporate bonds is more standardized and
the bonds themselves are much less complicated than structured finance prod-
ucts. Our paper suggests that shopping is more likely when the CRAs’ models
are less precise, which is certainly the case comparing corporate bonds to struc-
tured finance. Within the structured finance arena, Ashcraft et al. (2010) find
that the MBS deals that were most likely to underperform were the ones with
more interest-only loans (because of limited performance history) and lower
documentation, that is, loans that were more opaque or difficult to evaluate.
Our paper posits that shopping is used by issuers to exploit trusting in-
vestors. Regarding the dependency of yields on ratings, Adelino (2009) shows
that AAA tranche yields of MBS do not have extra predictive power about
defaults or subsequent rating downgrades outside of the rating itself. How-
ever, it is not obvious from his results that this got worse during the boom
(Table 12, Adelino (2009)). With respect to lower ratings leading to poorer per-
formance, there is mixed evidence. Griffin and Tang (2010) find no evidence
that CDOs rated by multiple rating agencies experience less default. Both
Benmelech and Dlugosz (2009) (for asset-based securities (ABS)) and Ashcraft
et al. (2010) (for RMBS), however, find that ex post downgrades of structured

38They define larger by market share in terms of deals. As a robustness check, they also look
at market share in terms of dollars and find similar results.
The Credit Ratings Game 109

finance products are both more likely and larger in deals rated by a single
CRA.39 In preliminary work, Ashcraft et al. (2009) find that the more issuers
switch among CRAs, the lower is subordination for Alt-A RMBS, indicating
benefits to shopping around.40
While not a prediction, a key part of the paper is our assumption that a
fraction of investors are trusting. While there is substantial anecdotal evidence
to support this assumption, we take this opportunity to describe systematic
evidence. There are two views of trusting investors to explain why they do
not perform proper due diligence and analysis. The first explains such belief
using incentive problems, whereas the second claims that the analysis is too
complex for them. While the second is difficult to measure, two papers in the
literature on corporate bond ratings demonstrate that ratings are important
to some investors solely for regulatory purposes. Kisgen and Strahan (2010)
demonstrate that Dominion Bond Rating Service’s acquisition of NRSRO status
in 2003 changed the impact of its ratings on bond yields only in situations in
which this status was important.41 Bongaerts, Cremers, and Goetzmann (2011)
find that Fitch’s ratings are often used to break ties between S&P and Moody’s.
Focusing on the structured finance market, Adelino (2009) finds intriguing
evidence of naivete. He finds that, while initial yields on tranches below AAA
predict future credit performance (probability of default and future ratings
downgrades), the initial yields on AAA tranches have no predictive power. This
is consistent with the hypothesis that investors in AAA tranches have no other
information beyond the credit ratings themselves.

VII. Conclusion
Our paper analyzes CRAs and their conflicts of interest. The model includes
the critical elements of the industry: Issuer’s payments may influence ratings,
issuers may shop for ratings, CRA models may vary in precision, barriers to
entry create market power for CRAs, reputation considerations affect decision
making, and different clienteles for investments exist. These elements allow us
to provide a simple general framework for analyzing the rating industry and
its efficiency.
Our model yields a surprising result on the adverse effects of competition.
In particular, we find that the presence of more trusting investors or lower
reputation costs gives CRAs incentives to inflate investment quality, while the
precision of the CRAs analysis has dual effects: More precision raises current
payoffs but also increases the probability of paying a reputation cost. Our anal-
ysis of market efficiency makes it clear that, in general, a monopoly is more
efficient than a duopoly. This is because a duopoly provides more opportunities
for the issuer to shop and mislead trusting investors. In terms of regulation,

39 Ashcraft et al. (2009) note, however, that only 1% of their deal sample has just one rating.
40 The sign is the same for subprime deals but the coefficient is not significant.
41 That is, regulations that required investments to use the best or second-best NRSRO rating

and specifically around the investment grade threshold.


110 The Journal of FinanceR

we suggest that up-front fees (as in the Cuomo plan) accompanied by auto-
matic disclosure of ratings and oversight of analytical standards will minimize
distortions from conflicts of interest and shopping.
To present a closed-form model of CRA competition, we abstract away from
several aspects of the industry that would be worth analyzing further. We sim-
plify the ratings process to allow for only two levels of ratings rather than
a finer partition and do not allow for subsequent upgrades and downgrades
that CRAs make while monitoring an investment. In terms of the invest-
ment being issued, we do not model conduits with multiple assets or make
a clear distinction between idiosyncratic and systematic risk. Finally, while we
did extend the model in Section V to two periods to endogenize reputation, a
model of CRA competition over a longer time horizon could yield interesting
results.

REFERENCES
Adelino, Manuel, 2009, Do investors rely only on ratings? The case of mortgage-backed securities,
Working paper, Dartmouth.
Ashcraft, Adam, Paul Goldsmith-Pinkham, and James Vickery, 2009, The role of incentives and
reputation in the rating of mortgage-backed securities, Working paper, Federal Reserve Bank
of New York.
Ashcraft, Adam, Paul Goldsmith-Pinkham, and James Vickery, 2010, MBS ratings and the mort-
gage credit boom, Working paper, Federal Reserve Bank of New York.
Ashcraft, Adam, and Til Schuermann, 2008, Understanding the securitization of subprime mort-
gage credit, Working paper, Federal Reserve Bank of New York.
Bar Isaac, Heski, and Joel Shapiro, 2010, Ratings quality over the business cycle, Working paper,
NYU.
Bar Isaac, Heski, and Steve Tadelis, 2008, Seller reputation, Foundations and Trends in Microe-
conomics 4, 273–351.
Becker, Bo, and Todd Milbourn, 2011, How did increased competition affect credit ratings? Journal
of Financial Economics 101, 493–514.
Benabou, Roland, and Guy Laroque, 1992, Using privileged information to manipulate markets:
Insiders, gurus, and credibility, Quarterly Journal of Economics 107, 921–958.
Benmelech, Efraim, and Jennifer Dlugosz, 2009, The credit rating crisis, NBER Macroeconomics
Annual, 161–207.
Biglaiser, Gary, 1993, Middlemen as experts, RAND Journal of Economics 24, 212–223.
Bolton, Patrick, Xavier Freixas, and Joel Shapiro, 2007, Conflicts of interest, information provi-
sion, and competition in the financial services industry, Journal of Financial Economics 85,
297–330.
Bongaerts, Dion, K.J. Martijn Cremers, and William N. Goetzmann, 2011, Tiebreaker: Certification
and Multiple Credit Ratings, Journal of Finance, forthcoming.
Boot, Arnoud W.A., Todd T. Milbourn, and Anjolein Schmeits, 2006, Credit ratings as coordination
mechanisms, Review of Financial Studies 19, 81–118.
Durbin, Erik, and Ganesh Iyer, 2009, Corruptible advice, American Economic Journal: Microeco-
nomics 1, 220–242.
Faltin-Traeger, Oliver, 2009, Picking the right rating agency: Issuer choice in the ABS Market,
Working paper, Columbia Business School.
Farhi, Emmanuel, Josh Lerner, and Jean Tirole, 2010, Fear of rejection? Tiered certification and
transparency, Working paper, Harvard University.
Faure-Grimaud, Antoine, Eloic Peyrache, and Lucia Quesada, 2009, The ownership of ratings,
Rand Journal of Economics 40, 234–257.
Griffin, John M., and Dragon Y. Tang, 2010, Did subjectivity play a role in CDO credit ratings?
Working paper, UT-Austin.
The Credit Ratings Game 111

Harrison, J. Michael, and David M. Kreps, 1978, Speculative investor behavior in a stock market
with heterogeneous expectations, Quarterly Journal of Economics 92, 323–336.
He, Jie, Jun Qian, and Philip E. Strahan, 2010, Credit ratings and the evolution of the mortgage-
backed securities market, Working paper, Boston College.
Hirshleifer, David, and Siew Hong Teoh, 2003, Limited attention, information disclosure and
financial reporting, Journal of Accounting and Economics 36, 337–386.
Hörner, Johannes, 2002, Reputation and competition, American Economic Review 92, 644–663.
Inderst, Roman, and Marco Ottaviani, 2009, Misselling through agents, American Economic
Review 99, 883–908.
Kartik, Navin, 2009, Strategic communication with lying costs, Review of Economic Studies 76,
1359–1395.
Kartik, Navin,, Marco Ottaviani, and Francesco Squintani, 2007, Credulity, lies, and costly talk,
Journal of Economic Theory 134, 93–116.
Kisgen, Darren J., and Philip E. Strahan, 2010, Do regulations based on credit ratings affect a
firm’s cost of capital? Review of Financial Studies 23, 4324–4347.
Laffont, Jean-Jacques, and Jean Tirole, 1993, A Theory of Incentives in Procurement and Regula-
tion (MIT Press, Cambridge).
Lizzeri, Alessandro, 1999, Information revelation and certification intermediaries, RAND Journal
of Economics 30, 214–231.
Mariano, Beatriz, 2008, Do reputational concerns lead to reliable ratings, Working paper, Univer-
sidad Carlos III.
Mathis, Jerome, Jamie McAndrews, and Jean-Charles Rochet, 2009, Rating the raters: Are reputa-
tional concerns powerful enough to discipline rating agencies? Journal of Monetary Economics
56, 657–674.
Morgan, John, and Philip C. Stocken, 2003, An analysis of stock recommendations, RAND Journal
of Economics 34, 183–203.
Ottaviani, Marco, and Peter Norman Sorensen, 2006, Reputational cheap talk, RAND Journal of
Economics 37, 155–175.
Pagano, Marco, and Paolo Volpin, 2010, Securitization, transparency, and liquidity, Working paper,
Università di Napoli Federico II and London Business School.
Partnoy, Frank, 2002, The paradox of credit ratings, in Richard M. Levich, Giovanni Majnoni, and
Carmen Reinhart, eds.: Ratings, Rating Agencies and the Global Financial System (Kluwer
Academic Publishers, Boston).
Sangiorgi, Francesco, Jonathan Sokobin, and Chester Spatt, 2009, Credit-rating shopping, selec-
tion and equilibrium structure of ratings, Working paper, Carnegie Mellon University.
Scheinkman, Jose, and Wei Xiong, 2003, Overconfidence and speculative bubbles, Journal of
Political Economy 111, 1183–1219.
Securities and Exchange Commission (SEC), 2008, Summary Report of Issues Identified
in the Commission Staff’s Examinations of Select Credit Rating Agencies. Available at
http://sec.gov/news/studies/2008craexamination070808.pdf.
Skreta, Vasiliki, and Laura Veldkamp, 2009, Ratings shopping and asset complexity: A theory of
ratings inflation, Journal of Monetary Economics 56, 678–695.
Stolper, Anno, 2009, Regulation of credit rating agencies, Journal of Banking & Finance 33,
1266–1273.
Strausz, Roland, 2005, Honest certification and the threat of capture, International Journal of
Industrial Organization 23, 45–62.
White, Lawrence J., 2002, The credit rating industry: An industrial organization analysis, in
Richard M. Levich, Giovanni Majnoni, and Carmen Reinhart, eds.: Ratings, Rating Agencies
and the Global Financial System (Kluwer Academic Publishers, Boston).
White, Lawrence J., 2010, Markets: The credit rating agencies, Journal of Economic Perspectives
24, 211–226.

You might also like