Charting A New Path Toward Gender Equality in India: From Religious Personal Laws To A Uniform Civil Code
Charting A New Path Toward Gender Equality in India: From Religious Personal Laws To A Uniform Civil Code
Charting A New Path Toward Gender Equality in India: From Religious Personal Laws To A Uniform Civil Code
INTRODUCTION
In India, only Muslim men may practice polygamy, 1 and Hindu sons inherit greater
shares of their parents’ estates than their sisters do. 2 While one’s religion determines
which law will apply to him or her regarding marriage, divorce, maintenance,
guardianship, adoption, inheritance, and succession, 3 a common thread woven through
all of India’s religious personal law systems is the patriarchal dominance of men and
the unequal treatment of women. Given the seemingly strong protections of gender
equality in India’s Constitution, however, it is puzzling that the Indian government can
uphold facially discriminatory laws against women, especially when such laws affect
women’s lives so intimately. In the name of protecting the rights of religious
communities, Parliament has thus far skirted its responsibilities to some of the most
vulnerable individuals within those communities—the women.
The religious personal law systems of India have not helped Indian women, nor
have they been effective in protecting the rights of the religious communities in which
Indian women live. Rather, the preservation of these separate laws has served to
deepen the division between the majority Hindu population and minority religions,
particularly Islam. The personal laws have also perpetuated—and arguably enhanced—
tensions between these two groups by reinforcing identities that oppose one another.
India must take care to move away from religious personal laws and toward a
uniform civil code, as envisioned by Article 44 of the Indian Constitution. 4 At present,
the debate over a uniform civil code appears hopelessly divided along both political
and religious lines. However, the turmoil is rooted in concerns over the process—and
who controls that process—much more so than the concept itself. A uniform civil code
constructed by a majority Hindu Parliament will not be accepted as legitimate among
minority groups no matter how fairly it may be drafted. The answer, then, lies with
promoting a process that brings all concerned voices to the table: men and women of
all religious communities must be included. To be successful, a uniform civil code
needs to reflect India’s diversity as well as its commitment to equality.
This Note is divided into four parts. Part I focuses on the equality provisions and
religious protections set forth in the Indian Constitution, their interplay with religious
personal laws, and the significance of Article 44. Part II outlines the three basic
problems created by the religious personal law systems. It argues that the systems
promote the myth of state neutrality at the expense of women’s rights; freeze religious
reform and thereby silence internal dissent; and intensify the connection between
personal law and identity, thus heightening tensions between majority and minority
populations and strengthening prejudices. All of these trends weaken the ability of the
group and its individuals to manage internal change, obtain protection from the state,
and trust the state generally.
Part III details the reasons why the problems caused by religious personal laws
cannot be solved piecemeal by the courts, and why the legislature cannot be trusted to
draft a legitimate uniform civil code under present circumstances. This Part also rejects
as inadequate alternative approaches to a uniform civil code proffered by legal
scholars. Finally, Part IV introduces a multistep plan for religious communities—rather
than Parliament—to move India toward a uniform civil code that addresses each of the
basic problems caused by the religious personal laws. The goal of this gradual process
is to bring about new measures for gender equality without displacing political power
from religious groups to legislators. By facilitating the transition to a uniform civil
code, religious communities will maintain control of the process, thus legitimizing the
results and fulfilling India’s constitutional vision of unity through diversity.
When India’s Constituent Assembly set out to draft the Indian Constitution in the
late 1940s, it was faced with no small task. The country was still recovering from the
violent partition of India and Pakistan following India’s independence from Great
Britain. 5 While many Muslims left India for Pakistan en masse, those who stayed
behind harbored feelings of distrust, rejection, and fear of the majority Hindu
population. 6 Because of the hostility between the Muslim and Hindu populations of
India, this Note focuses particularly on the Muslim personal law system and the
tension between the Muslim minority and Hindu majority regarding the debate over a
uniform civil code.
In the context of this religious turmoil, the Constituent Assembly was especially
concerned with minority and religious rights. 7 On the other hand, the drafters also
sought to provide equality among all individuals regardless of religion, caste, or sex, as
the Constitution’s equality provisions demonstrate. 8 Thus, it has been said that the
genius of the Indian Constitution is its secular ambiguity—in other words, its strength
has been in its ability to pay deference to religious sensitivities in a religiously
5. See ARCHANA PARASHAR, WOMEN AND FAMILY LAW REFORM IN INDIA: UNIFORM CIVIL
CODE AND GENDER EQUALITY 158 (1992) (describing partition as a “communal holocaust” that
“left thousands dead and many thousands displaced, in both countries”).
6. Id.
7. See James Chiriyankandath, ‘Creating a Secular State in a Religious Country’: The
Debate in the Indian Constituent Assembly, COMMONWEALTH & COMP. POL., Jul. 2000, at 1, 1–
2.
8. See INDIA CONST. arts. 14–16.
2008] TOWARD GENDER EQUALITY IN INDIA 697
pluralistic society while still retaining the secular quality of dedication to individual
rights regardless of religion. 9 Jawaharlal Nehru, India’s first prime minister and a key
personality behind the Indian Constitution, supported this nuanced approach,
“declaring in November 1948 that the ‘glory of India has been the way in which it
manages to keep two things going at the same time: . . . infinite variety and . . . unity in
that variety.’” 10
Part I of this Note first considers the constitutional provisions for gender equality
and their effect, if any, on religious personal laws. Second, it argues that the religious
protection that the Constitution affords to minority groups regrettably traded legislative
political power for religious political power, thus strengthening the bond between
Muslim identity and Muslim personal law. Lastly, it discusses the significance of
Article 44’s promotion of a uniform civil code in light of the persistence of religious
personal laws.
The promotion of gender equality in India’s Constitution begins with Article 14,
which provides that “[t]he State shall not deny to any person equality before the law or
the equal protection of the laws within the territory of India.” 11 Article 15 reinforces
this, providing that “[t]he State shall not discriminate against any citizen on grounds
only of religion, race, caste, sex, place of birth or any of them.” 12 With the apparent
purpose to effectuate these equality provisions, Article 13 states that all “laws in force”
in India at the commencement of the Constitution, “in so far as they are inconsistent
with the provisions of this Part, shall, to the extent of such inconsistency, be void.” 13
On their face, Articles 13, 14, and 15 appear to guarantee women’s equality with
men and render religious personal laws, which were in force at the time of the
Constitution’s commencement, void to the extent that they are inconsistent with the
equality provisions. However, the constitutional status of religious personal laws has
not been as clear cut for Indian courts. The Indian Supreme Court has never directly
9. See Chiriyankandath, supra note 7, at 1 (“One reason for [the Indian Constitution’s]
durability has been its deliberate (and necessary) ambiguity in dealing with potentially
explosive issues of religious identity.”). Susanne and Lloyd Rudolph argue that Indian law and
politics have been a contest between legal pluralism, which gives expression to a multicultural
society, and legal universalism, which is concerned with equal and uniform citizenship. Susanne
Hoeber Rudolph & Lloyd I. Rudolph, Living With Difference in India: Legal Pluralism and
Legal Universalism in Historical Context, in RELIGION AND PERSONAL LAW IN SECULAR INDIA,
supra note 2, at 36.
10. Chiriyankandath, supra note 7, at 10 (quoting 7 CONSTITUENT ASSEMBLY DEBATES:
OFFICIAL REPORT 323 (1948)) (alterations in original).
11. INDIA CONST. art. 14. The language of this Article promotes both formal equality and
substantive equality.
12. INDIA CONST. art. 15. The Article also specifically prohibits discrimination on the same
grounds in access to places of public accommodation and further provides for affirmative action
for women, children, and the “socially and educationally backward classes of citizens or for the
Scheduled Castes and the Scheduled Tribes.” Id.
13. INDIA CONST. art. 13. It should be noted that Articles 14 and 15 are in the same “Part”
as Article 13.
698 INDIANA LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 83:695
addressed the issue, while lower courts are split on the Constitution’s applicability to
religious personal laws. 14
At the very least, the neutralizing effect of the case law has delayed the realization
of Articles 14 and 15 for most women. 15 The real disappointment of the courts’
waffling over the treatment of personal laws is that these are the laws that affect Indian
women’s lives most intimately. For example, a Muslim Indian woman may be
unilaterally divorced by her husband without cause, while that same woman may only
obtain a divorce on statutorily specified grounds. 16 Likewise, under Christian law, a
man may obtain a divorce when his wife has committed adultery, while a Christian
woman seeking divorce is required to prove at least two offenses by her husband, such
as adultery with cruelty or adultery with desertion. 17 Under both Hindu and Muslim
law, the father is the natural guardian of legitimate children and a Hindu husband is
also the natural guardian of his wife if she is a minor. 18
What is the benefit of having progressive equality provisions in the Constitution
when they will not apply to a woman’s rights under marriage, including whether she is
allowed custody of her children? All of India’s religious personal law systems suffer
from “gross sex inequalities.” 19 Their shelter, thus far, from real constitutional scrutiny
makes a mockery of India’s constitutional commitment to equality and fails to provide
women with the protection they deserve.
14. Kirsten K. Davis, Equal Protection for Women in India and Canada: An Examination
and Comparison of Sex Equality Provisions in the Indian and Canadian Constitutions, 13 ARIZ.
J. INT’L & COMP. L. 31, 46 n.98 (1996). Compare Kaur v. Choudry, A.I.R. 1984 Del. 66, 75
(India) (resisting application of the Constitution to a Hindu law for restitution of conjugal rights
on the policy of preserving marriage, reasoning that “[i]n the privacy of the home and the
married life neither Art. 21 nor Art. 14 have any place”), and State of Bombay v. Mali, A.I.R.
1952 Bom. 84, 89 (India), abrogated by In re Amina, A.I.R. 1992 Bom. 214, 219 (India)
(holding that a Muslim law permitting bigamous marriages was not a “law in force” and thus
outside the reach of the Constitution and in any case, the law would not be held to discriminate
against gender because the law was based on “vital and compelling” social, economic, and
religious grounds), with In re Amina, A.I.R. 1992 Bom. 214 (India) (overruling Mali and
holding that personal laws are “laws in force” under Article 13 of the Constitution).
15. However, bringing personal laws under the Constitution would still not be the most
optimal solution because the change for women would be a slow, piecemeal process not
conducive to providing justice on a large scale. See infra Part III.A. Still, constitutional scrutiny
of personal laws would provide women with better protection than the current scheme.
16. PARASHAR, supra note 5, at 287.
17. Id.
18. Id. at 292.
19. Martha C. Nussbaum, India: Implementing Sex Equality Through Law, 2 CHI. J. INT’L
L. 35, 40 (2001).
20. INDIA CONST. art. 25(1). It is of note that “this Part” includes Articles 14 and 15.
2008] TOWARD GENDER EQUALITY IN INDIA 699
corporate life was secure.” 29 That reassurance came in the “form of allowing the
Muslim community to preserve and practice their personal law.” 30
The government is under no constitutional obligation to maintain the system of
religious personal laws. 31 However, the Assembly’s decision to strip Muslims and
other minorities of a secured position in the secular framework of government pushed
Muslims further into an outsider role and guaranteed the result that Muslim identity
would become conflated with Muslim personal laws. The nationalists were correct in
seeing a link between group-based norms and inter-group conflict; yet they were
complicit in perpetuating this problem between Muslims and Hindus in India through
the preservation of religious personal laws.
The highly debated Article 44 of the Indian Constitution provides that “[t]he State
shall endeavour to secure for the citizens a uniform civil code throughout the territory
of India.” 32 If ever fulfilled, Article 44 would almost certainly sound the end to
religious personal law, requiring all Indians to be governed by one secular civil code.33
There is, however, no guarantee that this will ever happen because the Article is found
in the Constitution’s Directive Principles and is therefore not judicially enforceable. 34
This designation of the Article as a Directive Principle was driven by the Assembly’s
desire to achieve national unity—and not gender equality—by reassuring Muslims that
their personal laws would not be upset. 35
The Constitution provides no timeline for the implementation of Article 44, nor
does it provide any process by which it should be drafted. Professor Archana Parashar
argues that the benign placement of Article 44 demonstrates that the Constituent
29. Id.
30. Id. at 49. The government maintained all the religious personal law systems, and not
just Muslim law.
31. See PARASHAR, supra note 5, at 160 (quoting the Law Minister of the Constituent
Assembly to say, “I shall hear no argument from any community to say that this Parliament has
no right to interfere in their personal law or any other laws”); Pratibha Jain, Balancing Minority
Rights and Gender Justice: The Impact of Protecting Multiculturalism on Women’s Rights in
India, 23 BERKELEY J. INT’L L. 201, 210 (2005) (relying on the Constitution to argue that all
group rights granted to minorities are subject to state intervention).
32. INDIA CONST. art. 44.
33. See PARASHAR, supra note 5, at 261 (explaining that while a uniform civil code could
technically be created to coexist with religious personal law, an optional code would make it
“almost certain that the majority of women will not be able to take advantage of the enhanced
legal rights which it provides”).
34. INDIA CONST. art. 37 (“The provisions contained in this Part shall not be enforceable by
any court, but the principles therein laid down are nevertheless fundamental in the governance
of the country and it shall be the duty of the State to apply these principles in making laws.”).
35. See PARASHAR, supra note 5, at 235–36 (noting that the drafters understood that a
justiciable uniform civil code would be consistent with the equality provisions of the
Constitution, but that they did not want to alienate the Muslims). Parashar concludes that “[t]he
final shape taken by the article on a [uniform civil code] indicates the greater importance
attached by the (mainly male) Constitution makers to achieving national unity than to ensuring
legal equality for women.” Id. at 236.
2008] TOWARD GENDER EQUALITY IN INDIA 701
Assembly accepted gender equality in the abstract, but was not truly committed to
bringing about concrete legal rights for women. 36 The current Parliament likely has the
same priorities because Muslims—and not women—are a formidable voting bloc. 37
Article 44 has not found much favor within the Muslim community. Indeed, the
Article is sometimes referred to as a “Damocles Sword” dangling over the heads of all
religious groups because its existence serves as a continual threat to their control over
personal laws. 38 Religious minorities have valid reasons to worry that a uniform civil
code would not reflect their values, especially in light of another Directive Principle
that aims toward the eventual ban on cow slaughter throughout India. 39 Such an
obviously Hindu-centric value in a Constitution purporting to be based on secularism40
raises doubts regarding the state’s ability to be impartial in its policy toward religion. 41
The Indian Constitution’s gender equality provisions and its protection of religious
practices subject to those provisions appear to provide Indian women with assurance
that their rights will be equal to those of men. However, the operation of religious
personal laws largely outside the reach of the Constitution has left women vulnerable.
Given the patriarchal bias present in all religious personal laws, Indian women will not
be able to realize their constitutional right to equality until these laws are exchanged
for a uniform civil code that both reflects the values of all groups within India and
adheres to the constitutional commitment to gender equality.
Preservation of the religious personal laws into the post-colonial era may have been
necessary under the circumstances at independence, but their continuation into the
twenty-first century has caused injury to India’s religious minorities as well as to
Indian women of every religion. Failure to implement a uniform civil code has
reinforced differences between Hindus and Muslims and left women more vulnerable
as a result. “Instead of moving toward a secular, equality-based legal system, the
recognition of personal laws under the guise of protecting minorities from a dominant
majority culture helped institutionalize patriarchal traditional practices that
disadvantage Indian women.” 42
This Part focuses on the three main problems that have resulted from maintaining
religious personal law systems in India. First, the laws have perpetuated a myth of state
neutrality, while in reality, the government inevitably takes sides in religion when it
transfers political power to religious leaders. Second, religious personal laws have had
the effect of “freezing” minority religious cultures, thereby silencing internal dissent.
Lastly, the existence of the laws has inflated the importance to Muslims of maintaining
a group identity that is distinct from the state, thus intensifying intergroup distrust and
hostility.
Once religious power within a group is equated with political power outside of it,
the stakes for internal dissent are higher for the entire community. A challenge to
religious leadership is translated into a challenge to the group’s legitimacy in the
political world; those who question become traitors to the faith. 49 Professor Ayelet
Shachar states that “state-sanctioned delegation of jurisdiction to authorities within an
identity group . . . plays right into the hands of power-holders in the group” allowing
leaders to define any challenge to the group’s practices as a corruption. 50 Hence,
within Indian minority groups, religious personal law has resulted in quelling internal
dissent for the sake of the group at the expense of the individual.
Professor Madhavi Sunder describes religious communities as “internally contested,
heterogeneous, and constantly evolving over time through internal debate and
interaction with outsiders.” 51 Muslim religious leaders in India commonly assert that
Muslim personal law cannot be altered by the government because it is based on the
shariat. To the contrary, history shows that the Ulema, the sole interpreter of Islamic
law, has allowed deviations from that law from time to time. 52 Nevertheless, where a
group’s power is based on its distinct identity from the majority, group leaders stress
loyalty and obedience over reform of individual rights that may bring the group’s
identity into closer conformity with the majority. 53
When an individual member of a minority community seeks protection from the
state in opposition to her group’s laws or customs, she is effectively being forced to
choose between her rights and her community. 54 Taking a stand risks the real
possibility that friends and family will turn against her, while remaining silent deprives
her of any meaningful rights. In this way, protection of the individual is pitted against
the autonomy of the group and a zero-sum game arises whenever the interests of the
two are not aligned.
Consider the story of Shah Bano: In 1978, a seventy-three-year-old Muslim woman
named Shah Bano was unilaterally divorced by her affluent lawyer husband after forty-
three years of marriage. 55 After becoming impoverished, she appealed to the courts for
maintenance under section 125 of the Criminal Penal Code—a code that applies to all
49. See SHACHAR, supra note 45, at 39 (“Members who attempt to bring about in-group
changes, by suggesting a less gender-biased reading of its family law practices, for example, are
consequently open to accusations of cultural betrayal.”).
50. Id.
51. Sunder, supra note 44, at 1402–03.
52. See PARASHAR, supra note 5, at 59 (citing examples of when the Ulema has made
adjustments to fit certain circumstances, such as sanctioning the regulations of political rulers
that were not in conformity with religious precepts). Parashar argues “that religious personal
laws have developed to reach their present form due to human endeavour and, just as they have
undergone a change in the past so they can be modified to accord with the changed
circumstances of the present.” Id. at 47.
53. See SHACHAR, supra note 45, at 39 (explaining the pressure that is placed on “women
insiders to relinquish their individual citizenship rights and to demonstrate group loyalty by
accepting the standard interpretation of group doctrine as the only correct reading of their
group’s tradition”).
54. See Sunder, supra note 44, at 1410.
55. See SHACHAR, supra note 45, at 81.
704 INDIANA LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 83:695
Indians regardless of religion. 56 Her husband argued that section 125 did not apply to
him because Muslim law obligated him only to pay maintenance during the period of
iddat. 57 Ruling in Shah Bano’s favor, Chief Justice Chandrachud of the Supreme Court
noted that the Criminal Penal Code overrides personal law when there is conflict, 58 but
the Court ultimately held that no conflict between the laws existed here because
Islamic law obligates husbands to provide maintenance to impoverished wives beyond
the iddat period in certain circumstances. 59
The Shah Bano decision outraged the Muslim community because a “non-Muslim,
secular jurist trained only in secular law interpreted significant Islamic law principles,
upon which there is not even consensus among trained Islamic legal scholars.” 60
Muslims were equally angered over Chandrachud’s disrespectful tone toward Islam. 61
The opinion created further controversy because in dicta, Chandrachud urged the
Parliament to follow through on drafting a uniform civil code, thus reinforcing Muslim
fears about losing group autonomy and identity. 62 The interference with Islamic law
coupled with the threat of a uniform civil code sparked Muslim protests nationwide. 63
In response, the Congress party rushed through Parliament the Muslim Women’s
(Protection of Rights on Divorce) Act. 64 Despite its benign-sounding name, the Act
was intended to reverse the Shah Bano decision by exempting Muslim men from
section 125 of the Criminal Penal Code. 65
After seven years of litigation, Shah Bano renounced any award she may have
received from the favorable decision, stating that she was unaware that what she was
seeking was against Muslim law. 66 In the end, what is surprising is not her
renunciation of the maintenance, but her strength in the face of so much opposition to
fight for it in the first place. There are not many Shah Banos; the majority of the
women in her situation will go unnoticed by the courts. 67
56. Khan v. Begum, A.I.R. 1985 S.C. 945, 946–47 (India) (Shah Bano).
57. Id. at 947. Iddat is an approximately three-month period following a divorce during
which remarriage is prohibited. Jain, supra note 31, at 215.
58. Shah Bano, A.I.R. 1985 S.C. at 949.
59. Id. at 951.
60. Seval Yildirim, Expanding Secularism’s Scope: An Indian Case Study, 52 AM. J. COMP.
L. 901, 914 (2004).
61. See infra Part III.A.
62. See Shah Bano, A.I.R. 1985 S.C. at 954.
63. See Yildirim, supra note 60, at 914. In the aftermath of the Shah Bano decision, Muslim
leaders traveled the country organizing rallies and leading protest marches of hundreds of
thousands of Muslims. This insured that the issue would become a political problem for the
leading Congress party. See PARASHAR, supra note 5, at 174–75.
64. Mody, supra note 37, at 948–49.
65. Id. at 949. However, in Latifi v. Union of India, A.I.R. 2001 S.C. 3958, 3973 (India),
the Supreme Court interpreted the Act as a validation and not a reversal of Shah Bano, by
holding that a Muslim woman was still entitled to relief under section 125 if her ex-husband
failed to provide her reasonable maintenance for life in the iddat period. To hold otherwise, the
Court said, would render the Act unconstitutional. Id. at 3972.
66. See Nussbaum, supra note 19, at 45.
67. See Sylvia Vatuk, “Where Will She Go? What Will She Do?” Paternalism Toward
Women in the Administration of Muslim Personal Law in Contemporary India, in RELIGION AND
PERSONAL LAW IN SECULAR INDIA, supra note 2, at 226, 240 (“Very few Muslim matrimonial
2008] TOWARD GENDER EQUALITY IN INDIA 705
disputes ever reach the courts: they are nearly always dealt with informally at the family and
community level and with the help of various kinds of religious bodies, functionaries, and
private religio-legal experts. . . . [E]ven in situations where they have the same opportunity to
obtain relief under the law, Muslims are less likely to do so than Hindus or Christians.”).
68. For an example of how individual rights are threatened when they are in opposition to
group rights:
[M]uch of the Muslim community, feeling its honor slighted and its civic position
threatened [by the Shah Bano decision], rallied round the cause of denying women
maintenance. Women were barely consulted when statements were made about
what Indian Muslims wished and thought; an impression was created by the
Ulema that all Muslims disagreed with the judgment.
Nussbaum, supra note 19, at 45.
69. Narain, supra note 41, at 50.
70. See Mody, supra note 37, at 946 (“It is increasingly believed that it is important for
Muslims to view their interest as a community, not because they are one, but because they are
perceived as one. This unity would increase their bargaining position in the bread and butter
issues of politics.”).
71. SHACHAR, supra note 45, at 35.
72. Id.
73. See Sunder, supra note 44, at 1462 (arguing that “many in the Muslim world seek to
maintain their religious identity in what appears to be the only place remaining—the past”).
706 INDIANA LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 83:695
life are governed have heightened significance for the group. 74 In India, this point is
evidenced by the Ulema’s history of reforming the personal law so as to have more
control over Muslim women without remedying the legal disparities between men and
women. 75
Granville Austin argues that “[m]odernization, economic progress, and education,
especially for women, are likely to decrease the Muslims’ sense of isolation in society
and their consequently tenacious grip on their personal law as an essential identifier.” 76
In this sense, progress for Muslim women itself threatens Muslim identity by virtue of
weakening support for Muslim personal laws. 77 Thus, both internal change and
external pressures give rise to Muslim reactive culturalism.
Debate over a uniform civil code serves as a constant external threat to Muslim
identity. The three most recent periods of heated debate over a uniform civil code
coincided with the three Supreme Court opinions that have suggested in dicta that
Parliament start working on a code. While Shah Bano may have been the most
explosive of the three, two more recent cases managed to reignite the political fires and
to reinforce minority group opposition to the idea of a uniform civil code.
In Mudgal v. Union of India, the Supreme Court heard a case regarding four Hindu
husbands who converted to Islam for the sole purpose of taking additional wives,
which is allowed under the Muslim personal laws. 78 The Court held that the second
marriage of a Hindu husband after his conversion to Islam is a void marriage and the
converted husband is guilty of bigamy, a practice proscribed under Hindu marriage
laws. 79 In dicta, the Court recited the Shah Bano dicta in favor of a uniform civil code
and added its own reasoning:
Those who preferred to remain in India after the partition, fully knew that the
Indian leaders did not believe in two-nation or three-nation theory and that in the
Indian Republic there was to be only one Nation—Indian nation—and no
community could claim to remain a separate entity on the basis of religion. 80
Such statements reinforced fear among Muslims that their identity was under siege.
In the most recent Supreme Court case advancing a uniform civil code, the Court
examined a section of the Indian Succession Act that affected only the rights of
Christians to make charitable or religious bequests. 81 In declaring that section
74. SHACHAR, supra note 45, at 36. “Religious norms shape the everyday lives of Indian
women in very tangible ways and their replacement by any other value is bound to be resisted,
particularly because, for the majority of women, issues of feminism and equal rights do not have
any reality.” PARASHAR, supra note 5, at 35.
75. See Narain, supra note 41, at 47.
76. Granville Austin, Religion, Personal Law, and Identity in India, in RELIGION AND
PERSONAL LAW IN SECULAR INDIA, supra note 2, at 15, 22–23.
77. See Mody, supra note 37, at 951 (arguing that issues like the Shah Bano controversy
empower Islamic mullahs by improving “their strong hold on the largely illiterate Muslim
population who can easily be swayed by the warning, ‘Islam is in Danger’”).
78. A.I.R. 1995 S.C. 1531, 1533 (India).
79. Id. at 1539.
80. Id.
81. Vallamattom v. Union of India, A.I.R. 2003 S.C. 2902, 2906 (India).
2008] TOWARD GENDER EQUALITY IN INDIA 707
unconstitutional because it violated Article 14, the Court reiterated the sentiment of the
previous two cases:
It is a matter of regret that Art. 44 of the Constitution has not been given effect to.
Parliament is still to step in for framing a common civil code in the country. A
common civil code will help the cause of national integration by removing the
contradictions based on ideologies. 82
The decision sparked political debate and nationwide controversy, and Muslim leaders
have since made clear their rejection of any proposed uniform civil code. 83
The religious personal law system in India has resulted in less justice for women
and more tension between minority and majority religions. At its foundation, the state
violates constitutional secular ideals by validating the ideals of certain members in
religious communities over those of others. This transformation of religious power into
political power freezes internal dissent and further endangers the situation for women
seeking rights that are in conflict with group autonomy. Lastly, both internal reform,
such as women’s education, and external pressure, such as the call for a uniform civil
code, have prompted Muslims to withdraw and cling to traditional notions of gender
and family. Because religious personal law systems fail to secure women’s equality
and exacerbate intergroup tensions, they must find their end in the eventual adoption of
a uniform civil code.
Despite the hostile divide along religious and political lines in India regarding
adoption of a uniform civil code, India must nonetheless work to reframe the debate
and eventually realize its constitutional vision. This Part argues that the Supreme Court
is not capable of solving the problems between religious rights and gender equality
because of the piecemeal fashion under which the laws must change and the Court’s
poor public relationship with Muslims. Likewise, Parliament is unsuited to draft a
uniform civil code, given the damage politicization of the debate has already done and
the distrust minority groups have of the majority Hindu Parliament. Finally, this Part
rejects solutions forwarded by others that are alternatives to a uniform civil code. It
argues that such alternatives are insufficient because they do not address the basic
problems that persist under the religious personal law systems.
Attempting to modify religious personal laws through the court systems of India is
neither ideal nor practical. As noted earlier, relying on the courts for change requires
Inevitably, the role of the reformer has to be assumed by the courts because, it is
beyond the endurance of sensitive minds to allow injustice to be suffered when it
is so palpable. But piecemeal attempts of courts to bridge the gap between
personal laws cannot take the place of a common Civil Code. Justice to all is a far
more satisfactory way of dispensing justice than justice from case to case. 85
The Court should not be called upon to transform personal laws with their multitude of
gender inequalities one case at a time; justice demands uniform action.
Finally, the Supreme Court has failed to show adequate respect for the Muslim
community regarding its personal law, and in some cases, the Court appears to
blatantly favor the majority’s religion and culture. 86 Martha Nussbaum makes the
seemingly obvious statement that “[j]udges should not insult the religions, and they
should be especially cautious in dealing with the affairs of a religious minority.” 87
Chief Justice Chandrachud, writing for the Court in Shah Bano, does not seem to have
had the benefit of Nussbaum’s wisdom because he began the opinion by criticizing
Islam’s treatment of women: “it is alleged that the ‘fatal point in Islam is the
degradation of woman.’” 88 When the Court lacks sensitivity with such a serious issue,
religious minorities are given no reason to feel as though their religious values are
being protected or will be retained. Placing all religious personal law under the scope
of the Constitution would only exacerbate this problem.
The Supreme Court, although eager to see Parliament enact a uniform civil code,
cannot require action from the government, and therefore its ability to effect change in
this arena is minimal. In sum, the Supreme Court cannot adequately remedy the
problems resulting from religious personal laws because even when women are brave
enough to assert their rights, the Court can only right one wrong at a time. And given
the Court’s tendency to offend minority sensitivities, it is possible that this piecemeal
approach is not helping anyone, including women.
The answer to India’s personal laws rests no more with the legislative branch than it
does with the judiciary. Parliament simply cannot be trusted to implement a fair and
legitimate uniform civil code, and any attempt to put forward a draft will only cause
more chaos and strife. The reason that Parliament will not be successful in
implementing a legitimate uniform civil code is twofold: (1) the politicians who most
strongly support a code have overt Hindu-centered aims, making it difficult for
minority groups to accept their ideas; and (2) as a result, any code that the government
creates will merely reflect the brand of patriarchy espoused by the majority, and will
not provide the gender equality required by Article 14 of the Constitution.
Professor Ayelet Shachar argues that no matter how democratic a country is, it “will
always have certain cultural, linguistic, and historical traditions which welcome some
of its members more completely than others, because the institutions of that society
have been largely shaped in their image.” 89 In India, this argument is validated by
right-wing Hindu political parties, such as the Bharatiya Janata Party (BJP), who have
advocated for the establishment of a Hindu state and a return to a sense of Hindu
identity called Hindutva. 90 Given that the BJP is the strongest political proponent of a
uniform civil code, minority groups within India rightly fear that a code presented to
the nation as neutral and secular would in fact be a reflection of Hindu values. 91
The uniform civil code that this Note argues for is one that provides for gender
equality at its foundation. But this is certainly not the only sort of code, nor is it the
probable code, that would result if drafted by Parliament. “The version championed by
the Hindu right, for instance, is based on reforming other personal laws to make them
similar to Hindu law, an eminently unsatisfactory situation given the extreme gender
inequity within present law.” 92 Although the BJP has reformed its proposed uniform
civil code recently, 93 its position has consistently been more focused on national
Given that the prospect for legislation on a uniform civil code is not realistic under
current circumstances, a number of alternative approaches have been proffered by legal
scholars and political theorists. Though not without merit, these methods nonetheless
fail to address some of the core problems caused by the religious personal law system.
1. Option Plans
Any plan that provides Indians with the option to be governed either by a uniform
civil code or by their religious personal laws is wholly incapable of providing women
with real protection. Advocates of this view claim that an opt-in or opt-out provision
respects group rights and protects individual autonomy by allowing people to choose
the law that will govern them. 95 This argument misses two key problems, however.
First, an option plan is facially misleading because “the majority of women in India do
not enjoy the privilege of making choices about their rights.” 96 This “right of exit”
approach thus offers no real solution for women, because it does not furnish an answer
to this question: How does a woman realistically go about choosing between her
community and her rights? 97
This leads to the second problem. It is patently unfair to place the “burden of
resolving conflict upon the individual,” while “relieving the state of any responsibility
for the situation.” 98 If the goal of a uniform civil code is to protect the community’s
most vulnerable members, an option plan completely fails because it merely evades the
power to women, but has failed to say exactly how women will be benefited. BJP MP Stresses
Need for Uniform Civil Code, HINDUSTAN TIMES, Feb. 25, 2006.
94. See Nilanjana Bhaduri Jha, Does India Really Need a Uniform Civil Code?, THE
ECONOMIC TIMES (India), Aug. 3, 2003 (asserting that patriarchy is the basis of personal law,
regardless of community, and that the BJP is less concerned with equality than national
integration).
95. See Jain, supra note 31, at 206. Jain believes a uniform civil code with an opt-out
provision will put pressure on minority groups to take the initiative in reforming their own laws.
Id. She does not, however, address the possibility that those who need the protection of the
secular code most will not have “the privilege to choose” anything at all.
96. PARASHAR, supra note 5, at 261. Parashar supports her argument against an option plan
by noting that the Special Marriage Act of 1954, a secular act under which all Indians have the
“option” of being governed, is only chosen by a small minority of Indians. Even within that
minority, she speculates, the decision was most likely made by the men. Id.
97. See SHACHAR, supra note 45, at 41.
98. Id.
2008] TOWARD GENDER EQUALITY IN INDIA 711
state’s duty to secure women’s rights while doing nothing to ensure that those rights
can ever be exercised.
2. Dual Jurisdiction
Professor Ayelet Shachar advocates a theory of dual jurisdiction that she terms
“transformative accommodation.” 99 The theory gives the minority group and the state
shared authority over personal law by assigning to each party a different aspect of the
law so that neither has a monopoly over the other. 100 Its goal is to promote better
responsiveness on the part of the state and group leaders by allowing individuals the
opportunity to turn to one jurisdiction when dissatisfied with the other. 101 However,
Professor Shachar’s optimistic proposal falls short of resolving the underlying
problems of the personal law system. First, by her own words, exit strategies do not
sufficiently protect women’s rights. 102 Second, dual jurisdiction increases the state’s
lack of neutrality by allowing the state to decide which areas of personal law should be
governed by religion, and which should be governed by the state. Making these kinds
of decisions further violates the secular principles of the Indian Constitution. It also
provides minority groups with new fears of majority encroachment and loss of identity.
Lastly, a dual jurisdiction model ignores the practical consequences of administering
two systems of law to a group of people who already have enough trouble
understanding their rights under the existing system. 103 Thus, maintaining the religious
personal law system alongside a secular jurisdiction cannot remedy the problems
arising from religious personal law. It will only add confusion to a system that
vulnerable women already find difficult to navigate.
IV. THE PROCESS OF BUILDING CONSENSUS: THE ROAD TO A UNIFORM CIVIL CODE
In order to address the reactive culturalism occurring in the Muslim community and
the deepened religious divide over the personal laws, a complete abrogation of the
religious personal law system is necessary. Because this project is so ambitious,
however, the government should proceed in stages that will keep religious groups
involved in the process and on board with the ultimate objective of enacting a uniform
civil code under which all Indians can be governed.
The central goal of the process described in this Part is to provide Indians of all
religious communities a long, but defined, period of time in which (1) to reform their
own personal laws, and (2) to contribute to the creation of a uniform civil code. By
involving both men and women of the different religious groups in the discussion and
final outcome, this plan strives to legitimize the process by encouraging internal
reform. This, in turn, will hopefully de-emphasize the focus placed on majority-
minority tensions by making each group responsible for its own reform and equally a
part of the process of drafting the uniform civil code. The substantive component will
be the requirement that all laws be consistent with the constitutional gender equality
provisions. Ultimately, the result should be a uniform civil code that ensures gender
equality and reflects the values of minority and majority communities alike.
Control over the substance of religious personal laws must be kept in the hands of
the leaders of the religious communities in order to ensure their legitimacy within the
various groups. However, unlike past situations when the state professed neutrality as
it handed power over to the conservative—and all-male—religious leaders, here the
power to revise personal laws would rest in the hands of both male and female leaders
within each community. A committee would be formed for each religion that has its
own distinct personal laws. 108 Each committee would be comprised of its own
religious members, and a quota system would be implemented to require that at least
forty percent of the committee members be female with the same percentage
requirement for males. In this way, neither gender dominates a committee, but a group
need not concern itself with being exactly even.
Members of the committees would be appointed through a system of nomination
and confirmation by Parliament, and requirements would be in place at the national
level to ensure representation from all parts of India. 109 Appointment is preferred over
election because (in rural areas especially) religious leaders such as Muslim clerics
have an incredible amount of control over their uneducated constituents. 110 Under
these circumstances, it is doubtful that an election would produce a committee with
members who are independent of the clerics’ influence. Furthermore, Indians are not
alien to the process of appointing members to committees charged with drafting
personal law, 111 and they should not have trouble accepting the process of appointment
over election. The appointed committees would agree to reformed laws by a
supermajority of two-thirds and the resulting laws would go into effect without
parliamentary interference at this stage. 112
The primary goal of this stage of the process is to open up the debate over personal
laws within religious communities. Rather than the entire debate taking place
externally between bodies such as the BJP and the Muslim Law Board, forcing
religious groups to take control over the substantive changes to their laws will
hopefully “thaw” the internal dissent that is natural to all cultures. 113 Committees
108. Accommodation would have to be made for Sikhs, Buddhists, and Jains, who are
subsumed under Hindu personal law; they would require representation within the Hindu
committees in some reasonable proportion.
109. Because no one religious group in India is so cohesive as to have the same cultural and
religious practices throughout the country, a requirement that committee members come from
geographically diverse areas will assist in getting all concerned voices to the table.
110. See supra note 77.
111. See PARASHAR, supra note 5, at 81 (discussing the Hindu Law Committee, whose
members were appointed by the government).
112. While I think the Parliament should play a role in codifying the uniform civil code, this
interim stage of the process does not warrant its oversight. Nevertheless, the reformed laws will
unequivocally be subject to the Constitution, and the Supreme Court can interpret them
accordingly.
113. See supra Part II.B. This approach will help to empower the marginalized voices in
every religious community and allow those voices “to participate in the processes of cultural
714 INDIANA LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 83:695
would be required to tour communities and solicit input in the form of questionnaires
from lawyers, judges, women’s associations, and ordinary citizens. 114 In this way,
committees can draft revisions to the law that reflect the values of the community
which are consistent with the equality provisions of the Constitution.
The secondary goal of this stage is to change the climate surrounding the future of a
uniform civil code. Most scholars believe that Shah Bano was the turning point of the
Muslim community’s strong feelings regarding a uniform code. 115 As discussed above,
Muslims were angered over the decision because of its insulting tone toward Islam, 116
and not necessarily because of the maintenance order. By guaranteeing Muslims a role
in the transition from personal laws to a uniform civil code, this process should
assuage the Muslims’ fears that a code would only reflect majority values, thus
encouraging them to take ownership of their contribution. 117
If a guaranteed spot at the table is the carrot, a parliamentary committee to reform
any religious law must be the stick in the event that a given group will not comply with
this process. Members of the Constituent Assembly have “conceded that religious
personal laws do not fall outside the competence of the State,” and all religious groups
should be reminded that there is no reason why the government cannot interfere in the
realm of personal law. 118 Ideally, minority groups will see it to their advantage to
engage in reform within their own communities, and as a result, group members will
accept their new laws as legitimate and Indian women will benefit immensely.
Updating the religious personal laws will provide protection both for religious
groups and for the women in those groups, while the next, much slower part of the
process ensues: the drafting of a uniform civil code. Because minority groups’
concerns about a uniform civil code stem from the idea that it will be written by the
Hindu majority, and therefore reflect Hindu values, the committee to draft the uniform
civil code must comprise the entire cross section of religious groups, while maintaining
the same gender quota as in the previous stage. Essentially, equal numbers of members
from each of the personal law revision committees will be appointed to a committee to
draft a uniform civil code—the Drafting Committee.
This stage is designed to provide a comfortably long, but definite, time period for
national debate on a uniform civil code. Adjustment will no doubt take time, and there
is no gain in pushing forward a plan on an unwilling public; the code must be wanted
in order to be ultimately accepted. This stage may further be subdivided into distinct
periods of information gathering, debate, and proposals to aid its transparency and
legitimacy. 119
The primary goal of this stage is to ensure legitimacy in the process by leaving no
concerned voices out of the discussion. 120 The Drafting Committee will have no
majority religion. As long as gender equality is provided for, no single religion’s
values will be given special weight. Therefore, to obtain the required two-thirds
supermajority, the religions will need to work together and form coalitions to achieve
their objectives. Unlike the previous stage, Parliament will play a role in codifying the
Drafting Committee’s uniform civil code. Parliament’s obligation will be more
procedural than substantive, however, and barring obvious inconsistencies with
constitutional gender equality provisions, Parliament will pass the code into law for all
Indians without interference. 121
The secondary goal of this stage is to fulfill Article 44 of the Constitution.
Following through on a uniform civil code will demonstrate that India takes women’s
rights seriously. The uniform civil code should serve as a vehicle for the realization of
women’s equality in India. According to Professor Parashar, when all religious
personal law is replaced by a uniform civil code that prioritizes gender equality over
religious rights, there will be a two-fold effect of easing religious tensions and holding
the state accountable for women’s rights:
For if a civil code enumerates legal rights without reference to the various
religious personal laws, then no community can legitimately argue that its religion
is being superseded by the religion of other communities. At the same time the
State will no longer be able to justify legal inequality for women on the ground
that it does not want to hurt the religious sentiments of some communities. 122
Thus, the creation of a uniform civil code will finally place the state in the position it
has sought since the members of the Constituent Assembly abolished reserved seats for
minorities on the grounds that separate treatment deepens the divide between religious
groups. 123 Furthermore, the government will no longer be able to hide behind the
religious personal laws and shirk its duty to women. Through this process, women’s
119. This idea is borrowed from the European Union’s Convention on the Future of Europe,
held in 2002, which progressed in three stages: the listening stage, the examination stage, and
the proposal stage. PAUL CRAIG & GRÁINNE DE BÚRCA, EU LAW: TEXT, CASES, AND MATERIALS
32 (4th ed. 2007). Proceeding in such stages would allow the Drafting Committee the
opportunity to hear all sides of the debate, while maintaining transparency, and thus would
bolster its legitimacy.
120. This notion is supported by Vrinda Narain, who believes that “the State must strive to
reach a consensus by the construction of dialogue, which includes not just the perspective of the
male-dominated collectivity of Muslims, but one that is also informed by the specificity of
Muslim women.” Narain, supra note 41, at 65.
121. My assumption here is that, in accordance with Article 44, the Parliament itself has set
this proposal into motion. In so doing, it has relinquished much of its role in the substantive
drafting of the code. By exchanging its power to draft the code for greater legitimacy,
Parliament will essentially serve as a “rubber stamp.” Barring extreme results, Parliament will
only perform the procedural function of codifying the bill into law.
122. PARASHAR, supra note 5, at 255.
123. See supra Part I.B.
716 INDIANA LAW JOURNAL [Vol. 83:695
equality will be protected by law, and all religious groups will have played a role in
making that possible.
Once the legal mechanisms for women’s equality are in place in the form of a
uniform civil code, the attention of the Indian government must turn to the reality that
many Indian women are neither aware of their rights nor how to exercise them. 124 A
code that provides women with equality does nothing if women do not know it exists.
Therefore, the final stage in this process is for Parliament to establish a permanent
commission for gender and religious concerns (“the Commission”), which will exist
for the primary purpose of transforming legal equality into actual equality.
The Commission’s composition would be similar to the previous committees in that
it would include all of the religious groups and apply the same gender quota. However,
the members would be elected for limited terms by the populace because by this time,
the traditional leaders will have hopefully lost their grip on their communities. Also,
elections would be preferred to the appointment process previously used because in
order to fulfill their role, it is important that the members of the Commission maintain
their independence from Parliament.
The Commission would be charged with the task of making the law more accessible
to women generally, as well as to women belonging to the various religious groups. In
this way, the Commission will acknowledge that a uniform civil code is not necessarily
the “magic alternative,” 125 and that Muslim women will still face problems particular
to their community, Hindu women will face distinctly Hindu problems, and so forth.
By recognizing that discrimination can be intersectional—that is, it is based on a
combination of two or more legally prohibited grounds 126 —the Commission can more
fully address the problems facing Indian women.
The state must take an affirmative role in “ensuring that women are given access to
educational and economic opportunities so that they will have the critical tools to
challenge received norms and to make the world their own.” 127 The Commission
would serve this function by promoting educational reform and changing underlying
assumptions about women in the various patriarchal religious communities. With the
gender literacy gap in India standing at twenty-five percent, 128 girls are clearly not
given the priority they require, and the Commission would need to make the education
of girls a central issue on its agenda.
The authority of the Commission would be similar to that of the Commission for
Gender Equality in South Africa, which is empowered to “monitor, investigate,
124. In one survey of 200 Hindu rural women, only twelve had any knowledge of the Hindu
Succession Act that governs inheritance rights for Hindus. Baird, supra note 2, at 147.
125. See Basu, supra note 92, at 164.
126. See, e.g., Leland Ware, People of Color in the Academy: Patterns of Discrimination in
Faculty Hiring and Retention, 20 B.C. THIRD WORLD L.J. 55, 69 (explaining “intersectional
discrimination” as the combination of bias based on both race and gender).
127. Sunder, supra note 44, at 1468.
128. Nussbaum, supra note 19, at 35. The literacy rate of men is sixty-five percent, while
women stand at around forty percent. Id.
2008] TOWARD GENDER EQUALITY IN INDIA 717
research, educate, lobby, advise and report on issues concerning gender equality.” 129 It
would also share characteristics of South Africa’s Commission for the Promotion and
Protection of the Rights of Cultural, Religious and Linguistic Communities. 130 Further,
the Commission would explicitly be guaranteed the following: adequate funding to
make nationwide campaigns, access to governmental records for research purposes,
independence from the legislature in order to retain legitimacy, and the right to propose
legislation to Parliament that reflects its findings on the status of women in India.
This plan for the implementation of a uniform civil code aims to allay the fears of
minority groups through its process of including a wide spectrum of voices in the
discussion. It further aims to challenge the patriarchal assumptions about women by
making gender equality the substantive goal of the code. By doing so, the hope is that
the resulting uniform civil code will be accepted by all religious communities, and that
the constitutional promise of gender equality will at last be given effect. Finally, the
continued monitoring of gender and religious concerns by the Commission should
advance reforms that are necessary for women to take advantage of their newly
achieved equality.
CONCLUSION