Logical Equivalence
Logical Equivalence
I. Introduction
Statements are materially equivalent when they have the same truth
value. Because two materially equivalent statements are either both true, or
both false, we can readily see that they must (materially) imply one another,
because a false antecedent (materially) implies any statement, and a true
consequent is (materially) implied by any statement. We may therefore read
the three-bar sign, as “if and only if.”
Page 1 of 8
A. Double Negation
B. De Morgan’s Theorem
Page 2 of 8
First, what will serve to deny that a disjunction is true? Any
disjunction p V q asserts no more than that at least one of its two
disjuncts is true. One cannot contradict it by asserting that at least one
is false; one must (to deny it) assert that both disjuncts are false.
Therefore, asserting the negation of the disjunction (p V q) is logically
equivalent to asserting the conjunction of the negations of p and of q. To
show this in a truth table, we may formulate the biconditional ~(p V q)
≡ (~p • ~q) , place it at the top of its own column, and examine its truth
value under all circumstances, that is, in each row.
Page 3 of 8
of p and of q. In symbols, the biconditional, ~(p • q) ≡ (~p V ~q) may
be shown, in a truth table, to be a tautology.
Page 4 of 8
THE THREE LAWS OF THOUGHT
Some early thinkers, after having defined logic as “the science of the
laws of thought,” went on to assert that there are exactly three basic laws of
thought, laws so fundamental that obedience to them is both the necessary
and the sufficient condition of correct thinking. These three have
traditionally been called:
Page 5 of 8
not in the same respect. Whatever portion is blue cannot be red at the
same time, in the same way. Half the car can be red, and the other half
blue. But the whole car can't be both red and blue. These two traits,
blue and red, each have single, particular identities.
Page 6 of 8
made of wood at the same time. In the law of non-contradiction, where
we have a set of statements about a subject, we cannot have any of the
statements in that set negate the truth of any other statement in that
same set. For example, we have a set of two statements about Judas. 1)
Judas hanged himself. 2) Judas fell down, and his bowels spilled out.
Neither statement about Judas contradicts the other. That is, neither
statement makes the other impossible because neither excludes the
possibility of the other. The statements can be harmonized by stating:
Judas hanged himself, then his body fell down, and his bowels spilled
out.
Page 7 of 8
matter what statement we decide p should represent. So the law of
excluded middle tells us that every statement whatsoever must be
either true or false. At first, this might not seem like a very problematic
claim. But before getting too comfortable with this idea, we might
want to consider Bertrand Russell’s famous example: “The present
King of France is bald.” Since the law of excluded middle tells us that
every statement is either true or false, the sentence “The present King
of France is bald” must be either true or false. Which is it?
Page 8 of 8