The Dependence Effect, Consumption and Happiness: Galbraith Revisited
The Dependence Effect, Consumption and Happiness: Galbraith Revisited
To cite this article: Amitava Krishna Dutt (2008) The Dependence Effect, Consumption
and Happiness: Galbraith Revisited, Review of Political Economy, 20:4, 527-550, DOI:
10.1080/09538250802308919
ABSTRACT In his analysis of the affluent society, Galbraith argued that advertising and
the sales promotion activities of firms create wants for people, which makes them consume
more without making them better off, because their wants were artificially created. Thus,
in the affluent society, ever-increasing levels of production (and consumption) do not
increase welfare. This paper considers three criticisms of Galbraith’s analysis: first,
firms cannot ‘create’ wants for consumers without their consent, because consumers
are not mere pawns in their hands; second, even if people’s wants are created, they
may be better off by consuming more; and third, that expansion of consumption can
make people better off by expanding aggregate demand. It draws on the recent
literature on consumption, income and happiness, and develops a simple model of
growth and distribution, to argue that Galbraith’s analysis holds up against these
criticisms.
1. Introduction
Half a century ago, John Kenneth Galbraith argued in The Affluent Society that
even when an economy becomes rich according to conventional measures, such
as real production and income, it is beset with many problems. ‘Conventional
wisdom’ in economics (to use Galbraith’s phrase) gives a paramount position to
production and takes it to reflect the wants of the sovereign consumer. In this
view, since consumer wants are never satiated, increasing output of goods and
services is good for society. While this view may be relevant for situations in
which many people are poor and economically insecure, Galbraith argued that
it is inappropriate for affluent societies. In his view, in such societies, since
increases in production create consumer wants, the fulfillment of such artificially
created wants makes consumers no better off. On the contrary, the creation
of wants for private goods reduces people’s willingness to spend on public
goods and services such as education, transportation facilities, and health and
sanitation, which results in a social imbalance – private affluence and public
squalor – leading to social disorder. He also pointed out that the preoccupation
Correspondence Address: Amitava Krishna Dutt, Department of Economics and Policy Studies,
University of Notre Dame, Notre Dame, IN 46556, USA. Email: [email protected]
Galbraith termed the way wants depend on the process by which they are satisfied
‘the Dependence Effect’, and proposed the squirrel wheel as an apt model for the
affluent society, which runs only to stay at the same place.
Galbraith’s claim has been disputed in various ways.2 This paper focuses on
three major criticisms, which are as follows. First, the increases in consumption in
affluent societies that Galbraith observed, and which continue to occur in affluent
and less-affluent societies today, are not due to the advertising and sales-
promotion activities of firms. Firms may try to persuade consumers, but cannot
force them to buy their products. Consumers are the ones who make buying
decisions, and they should not be thought of as passive pawns in the hands of
firms. Moreover, there is no clear evidence that advertising has an effect on
total levels of consumption, and at best it makes specific producers of particular
goods increase their sales at the expense of other producers. Second, even if
firms increase consumption by creating needs, it does not necessarily follow
that welfare is not increased by increases in consumption. The fact that advertising
makes us buy a particular product does not imply that its purchase does not make
us better off, and therefore increase welfare. Third, even if an increase in
consumption does not make us better off directly, it is possible that it has other
1
Both supporters and detractors of Galbraith’s book focus on Chapter XI, entitled ‘The
Dependence Effect’. Hayek (1961, p. 346), a critic, writes: ‘I believe the author would
agree that his argument turns upon the “Dependence Effect” explained in Chapter XI of
the book’, and titles his critique ‘The non sequitur of the “Dependence Effect”’. Stanfield
(1983, pp. 590– 591), in summarizing and pointing out the relevance of Galbraith 25 years
after the appearance of the book comments that nothing else in the book has invited more
controversy.
2
For a discussion of the book and a review of early criticisms and appraisals of it, see
Hession (1972).
The Dependence Effect, Consumption and Happiness 529
consequences that result in increases in welfare. For instance, it can increase the
demand for goods, make firms produce more, and thereby increase employment
and reduce unemployment, improving wellbeing.
The purpose of this paper is to evaluate these three criticisms by examining
some recent theoretical and empirical literature on consumption and happiness
and by examining some simple macroeconomic models of consumption, pro-
duction, employment and growth, and relating them to Galbraith’s analysis in
The Affluent Society. By so doing, it attempts to provide a critical evaluation of
Galbraith’s complaints about the affluent society.
The rest of the paper proceeds as follows. Section 2 examines the criticism
that firms do not actually increase consumption by creating needs, and discusses
it in terms of recent analytical developments in the analysis of consumption
and happiness. It also briefly comments on the empirical argument that advertis-
ing does not increase consumption, merely reallocating sales between firms.
Section 3 turns to the criticism about whether consumption actually increases
welfare by examining recent empirical work on the determinants of happiness
as reported by people themselves, especially on whether increases in consump-
tion and income increase happiness, and by discussing explanations of the empiri-
cal findings. Section 4 examines the argument that advertising has a favorable
impact on the economy because it increases aggregate demand, thereby reducing
unemployment and promoting economic growth. Section 5 concludes.
force them on consumers against their free will.3 To underscore this point, the
American Association of Advertising Agencies put out an advertisement with a
picture of a woman using shaving cream and a razor on her face, stating that
‘[d]espite what some people think, advertising can’t make you buy something
you don’t need’ (see Belch & Belch, 2007, p. 733). It is pointed out that many
expensive advertising and sales promotion campaigns by firms have failed,
which demonstrates that firms cannot manipulate consumers. For instance,
the attempt by Coca-Cola to reformulate Coke in 1985 failed, as did Ford’s
attempt to market a radically new car, called the Edsel, despite expensive adver-
tising campaigns.4
It is argued that although the earlier approach of marketers to advertising
involved trying to make consumers buy whatever firms produce, the more recent
approach is for marketers and firms to find out what consumers really want
(perhaps in a latent manner) and to supply it to them. Firms want to sell by creating
brand loyalty; this cannot happen if consumers are not getting what they really
want and being satisfied with their purchases. A leading principles of marketing
text, by Kotler & Armstrong (2004, p. 5), states that ‘[t]oday, marketing must be
understood not in the old sense of making a sale – ‘telling and selling’ – but in
the new sense of satisfying consumer needs’ (italics in original). The text continues
to point out (p. 6) that ‘[o]utstanding marketing companies go to great lengths to
learn about and understand their customer’s needs, wants and demands. They
conduct consumer research and analyze mountains of consumer sales, warranty
and service data. Their people at all levels – including top management – stay
close to customers.’
Finally, although advertising seems to affect the demand for particular pro-
ducts in some cases and contexts (see Albion & Farris, 1981), it is argued that
there is little evidence to suggest that advertising expenditure causes an increase
in aggregate consumption. Although Taylor & Weiserbs (1972) report that adver-
tising increases consumption, most studies find negligible effects. Simon (1970)
summarizes data collected during newspaper strikes and on the distribution of
advertising expenditures and consumption expenditures that do not find strong
effects, although spending appears to fall during newspaper strikes when people
are less exposed to advertising. Schmalensee (1972) finds that increases in sales
increase advertising, but advertising does not affect the total consumer spending
on goods and is inconsequential in driving aggregate demand. Quarles & Jeffres
(1983) find that increases in disposable income lead to increases in consumption,
which in turn leads to increases in advertising expenditures. The review of the
3
Katona (1960) suggests the image of the powerful consumer in affluent societies, who
makes consumption decisions using discretionary income based on his or her level of con-
fidence. He draws attention to the instability of the consumption function despite high
levels of advertising by large corporations.
4
I mention the case of Edsel here because Galbraith (1998) refers to it in his introduction to
the 40th anniversary edition of the book, saying that earlier, textbooks used to argue this
point with the example of Ford’s Edsel, but later jettisoned it. I return to this case in Note 5,
below.
The Dependence Effect, Consumption and Happiness 531
literature in Luik & Waterson (1996) suggests that advertising positively affects
consumption demand in the early stages of a product’s life cycle, but with the
passage of time primarily affects a brand’s share rather than total consumption.
There are many problems with these arguments. First, the simple ‘proof’,
which points to the failure of some advertising and sales promotion campaigns,
does not hold water. This can be shown with the following analogy: just because
some lies are not believed by people, it does not follow that people never believe
lies or even that the majority of lies are not believed. It would be rather surprising
if such simple proofs could, in fact, resolve the issue.5 Indeed, the simple proof of
the claim that advertising increases sales, with the argument that if advertising
does not work firms would not advertise, is also erroneous. Firms may be adver-
tising not to lose their market share when their rivals advertise; this does not
imply that if there is no advertising by anyone sales would be lower.
Second, the fact that consumers are the ones that ultimately make the pur-
chasing decision does not imply that firms cannot make them buy more than
they would otherwise.6
It can be argued that if consumers are consciously aware that advertise-
ments are trying to persuade or influence them they can employ their cognitive
defenses to protect themselves form going against their own interests. However,
growing evidence suggests that much of human behavior, including consumer
behavior, is not under conscious control but occur automatically without cogni-
tive intervention. This is particularly evident in the writings of behavioral econ-
omists, who have drawn on the findings of cognitive psychologists and decision
theorists.7 The implications of these contributions, including the different types
of cognitive biases of consumers, has been explored by Hanson & Kysar
(1999a), who argue that sellers can make use of the cognitive failures of
buyers to manipulate markets influencing, if not determining, market outcomes
by controlling the format of information, the framing of choices, and the setting
in which purchases are made. Hanson & Kysar (1999b) amass a large body of
empirical evidence, which shows the extent to which such manipulation
5
There are also problems with specific examples. I am grateful to an anonymous referee for
pointing out that the Edsel disaster is actually a complex tale of many shortcomings, and
should not be seen as a failure of advertising in isolation. See, for instance, Brooks (1963)
and Bonsall (2002).
6
Katona’s (1960) argument, noted earlier – that consumer spending is unstable and depen-
dent on consumer confidence despite high advertising expenditures – does not imply that
advertising does not positively affect consumption spending. The fact that, as Katona
argues, consumers use their discretion to replace durable goods long before they must
be replaced because they are completely worn out and beyond repair, implies the possi-
bility that the timing of replacement, and hence the level of consumption, can be affected
by marketing. Moreover, the argument that consumption expenditure is affected by adver-
tising and other forms of marketing does not imply that it is not also affected by consumer
confidence.
7
Some of the relevant literature in economics (and psychology) is surveyed in Earl (1990)
and Rabin (1998).
532 A.K. Dutt
8
See, for instance, Shimp (2007, p. 63).
9
James Vicary created a myth by claiming that consumer choice can be affected by adver-
tisements (using words) superimposed repeatedly in single frames within movies (even
though the eye could not consciously register them). Although this scam has been
subsequently discredited (see Rogers, 1992 – 93), subliminal advertisements involving
the use of symbolic messages that prey on the viewers’ subconscious to affect their con-
sumption behavior is an effective marketing tool.
10
Amazon.com’s practice of providing personalized suggestions based on what other
customers who have bought the item ordered have also purchased, can be thought of as
helping out customers in a world of imperfect information and bounded rationality, but
arguably also promotes, and is designed to promote, impulse buying.
The Dependence Effect, Consumption and Happiness 533
their attention, rather than to reduce search time and other transactions costs for
the optimizing shopper with well-defined preferences.
social scientists have produced empirical studies that question the fact that
increases in consumption and income – at least significantly – affect happiness
as evaluated by the consumers themselves. The pioneering contributions of
Easterlin (1973, 1995, 2001), and subsequent work by Oswald (1997), and Frey
& Stutzer (2002) among others, suggest a number of empirical regularities.11
Time series data for individual countries (such as the US, and Japan, with high
levels of per capita income) do not reflect significant (and in some cases any)
increases in the average level of self-reported happiness over time, despite signifi-
cant increases in income and consumption. Panel data on specific groups of indi-
viduals over their lives suggest that despite large increases in income, these
individuals do not show significant increases in self-reported happiness. Cross-
sectional studies across countries suggest that countries with higher levels of
per capita income and consumption do not have higher average levels of self-
reported happiness beyond a certain level of income that is far below the
income of the rich countries of the world. Even individuals who win lotteries
have been found to report no greater happiness after a few years. To be sure,
there is some support for the income/consumption –happiness connection.
Cross-sectional studies within countries seems consistent with it: people
in higher income groups with higher levels of consumption report higher levels
of self-reported happiness than people in lower income groups; it seems that it
is better to be rich than poor in a particular society at a particular point in time.
Cross-country studies do suggest a positive income–happiness link at low
levels of income. Some studies suggest that people are happier – even if
temporarily – if their consumption and income increases. However, the bulk
of the evidence seems to contradict the consumption– happiness relationship.
What all this suggests is that increases in production and consumption, at least
in affluent societies, may not increase subjective well-being significantly, and in
that sense have a low or zero marginal utility. This holds even in the presence
of advertising and salesmanship, contrary to, but in fact strengthening, Galbraith’s
suggestion!
There are good reasons to believe that increases in consumption caused
by marketing efforts may not result in lasting increases in happiness. If adver-
tising is to be successful it should not only induce people to buy things by
making them believe that they lack something that they need to have, but
by continuing to make them believe that they lack something to make them
buy even more. Thus, to be effective, advertising needs to keep people in a
state of discontent. Moreover, to the extent that advertisements and other
kinds of marketing methods try to increase sales by making people insecure
and fearful, and if the resultant purchases do not actually overcome some nega-
tive feelings (one does not necessarily obtain friends by buying beer, contrary
to what is suggested by commercials!), discontent can actually increase with
increases in consumption.
11
See also Easterlin (2002) for an edited collection of key contributions and Layard (2005)
for a recent overview.
The Dependence Effect, Consumption and Happiness 537
12
This compares with a marginal loss of 3.1% for people with low and middle income,
13.3% for unhealthy people.
The Dependence Effect, Consumption and Happiness 539
Advertising and its related arts . . . help develop the kind of man the goals of the
industrial system require – one that reliably spends his income and works
reliably because he is always in need of more . . . In the absence of the
massive and artful persuasion that accompanies the management of demand,
increasing abundance may well have reduced the interest of people in acquiring
more goods . . . Being not pressed by the needs for these goods, they would have
spent less reliably to get more. The consequence – a lower and less reliable
propensity to consume – would have been awkward for the industrial system
(Galbraith, 1967, p. 219).
However, in The Affluent Society, Galbraith did not discuss this aggregate
demand-creating role of advertising. He seemed to worry, instead, about the
problem of inflation caused by a high level of aggregate demand (due to govern-
ment policies aimed at providing economic security) and the wage-price spiral
(due to the coexistence of oligopolistic firms and strong labor unions). In the
1998 edition, Galbraith states in his introduction that his focus on inflation and
the wage-price spiral was, with hindsight, misplaced because of weakened
unions and technological change. So it is important to take aggregate demand
and unemployment into account in analyzing the consequences of sales pro-
motion. Is it not possible, then, that increases in consumption demand will
increase aggregate demand and growth and reduce unemployment and poverty,
thereby increasing happiness and welfare?
These issues can be examined using the simple textbook aggregate demand-
aggregate supply (AD-AS) model.13 The economy’s position is shown in the usual
way by the intersection of a downward-sloping AD curve and an upward-rising AS
curve on price and real output space. An increase in advertising expenditures (and
other activities of firms and those media that increase sales), which increases the
level of consumption at each price level, shifts the AD curve to the right, increas-
ing real output (as well as the price level). It will therefore have the effect of
increasing employment and reducing unemployment, and the effect on prices
will be small if there are no significant wage pressures when unemployment falls.
The textbooks, however, also point out that these effects of increases in con-
sumption are only valid in the short run, when involuntary unemployment can
exist. If there is such unemployment, wages will fall, which will reduce the
price level, increase real money supply, and increase aggregate demand as
people spend their excess real money balances, or lend it out, which reduces the
interest rate and encourages spending by others. In the medium run, therefore,
the economy will be at the so-called natural rate of unemployment or the
NAIRU. Starting from medium run equilibrium, an expansion in consumption
demand due to the activities of firms will only increase output and reduce unem-
ployment in the short run; wage and price increases will move the economy back
to its medium-run equilibrium. Consumption spending will merely crowd out
investment spending, thereby jeopardizing the expansion of the economy in the
future.
13
See, for instance, Blanchard (2006).
540 A.K. Dutt
The argument that the effect of increases in consumption are only temporary,
and negated in the medium run, while subscribed to by many – in fact most –
mainstream macroeconomists, is neither theoretically persuasive nor empirically
accurate. There is no automatic necessary tendency for the economy to return
to some natural rate of unemployment through wage and price adjustments. For
instance, price reductions can result in debt deflation and an adverse effect on
the financial position of debtor firms, which can reduce investment spending,
and price changes may lead to endogenous changes in money supply with no
(appreciable) effects on interests rates (unless there are policy changes made by
the monetary authorities). Moreover, economic expansion can result in endogen-
ous changes in technology, which increase the so-called natural level of output
(see Dutt, 2006a). There are many empirical studies which suggest that the real
output in many countries does not follow a stationary process, implying that
temporary shocks can have long-term, even permanent, effects (see, for instance,
Dutt & Ros, 2007, for a review).
If aggregate demand changes can have effects beyond the short run, are we to
conclude that the sales promotion activities of firms necessarily reduce unemploy-
ment? It may not do so if such activities increase people’s desire to obtain more
income and work more, increasing the supply of labor.14 Abstracting from this
possibility, we confine attention to the aggregate demand side. That increases in
sales promotion expenditure need not necessarily increase aggregate demand
and reduce unemployment can be seen from a simple explicit version of the
AD-AS model.
Assume that firms set the price level according to the markup-pricing rule,
so that
P ¼ (1 þ z)bW (1)
where P is the price level, W is the money wage, b is the fixed (for simplicity) unit
labor requirement, all other variable inputs are ignored, and z is the level of the
markup, determined by factors such as the level of industrial concentration,
held fixed for now. Firms spend an amount A in real terms on advertising. The
rate of profit of firms is given, using equation (1), by:
z Y A
r¼ (2)
1 þ zK K
where K is the stock of capital. The level of consumption demand is assumed to
depend positively on real income and the level of advertising expenditures. We
write the consumption function in a linear form as:
C ¼ c0 A þ cY (3)
where c is the marginal propensity to consume out of income and c0 the marginal
14
See Schor (1998), for instance, for the argument that an increase in consumption may
increase labor supply, and that unemployment may be reduced if workers decide to
reduce their supply of labor and increase their leisure time, with more people sharing
employment.
The Dependence Effect, Consumption and Happiness 541
Cc ¼ co A þ cc sY (30 )
where cc is the marginal propensity to consume out of profits. In this case, equation
(6) will have to be replaced by:
a0 þ (c0 a1 )a
u¼ (60 )
½(1 cc ) a1 s
where s ¼ z/(1þz) is the share of income going to profits. The stability of short-
run equilibrium requires that cc þ a1 , 1, which implies that the rise in the
markup, by increasing the profit share, will have a tendency to reduce u by redis-
tributing income from profit recipients who save to workers who do not. This
raises the likelihood that an increase in sales promotion activities will reduce
capacity utilization.
One problem with the formulation just discussed is that sales promotion has no
effect on consumption by workers, which follows from the assumption that workers
consume all their income. We can allow sales promotion to have an effect on con-
sumption by workers if we incorporate another feature of the economy highlighted
by Galbraith, that is, consumer debt. To introduce this we allow workers to save and
accumulate wealth, as in models pioneered by Pasinetti (1962), but extend these
models to allow for consumer borrowing and debt.
The income of workers, net of interest payments or receipts, is given by:
where w is the real wage, W/P, i the interest rate, and Kw is the stock of wealth
held by workers, which can be positive (representing assets) or negative (repre-
senting debt). The consolidated income of capitalists and advertising companies
(we refer to the two jointly as capitalists from now on) is given by:
15
Regarding income distribution, the first edition noted that although inequality had faded
as an economic issue because of the emphasis on aggregate output and because it had not
worsened, though still high (Galbraith, 1958, pp. 84– 85). In the 40th anniversary edition,
however, it was stated that the problem of inequality had not only continued, but worsened
(Galbraith, 1998, p. 71).
The Dependence Effect, Consumption and Happiness 543
16
We do not distinguish between the consumption propensities of capitalists and those who
obtain income from advertising for simplicity. Allowing for differences would require us
to keep track of the stock of capital owned by each group separately, adding to the
complexity of the dynamic model developed below.
544 A.K. Dutt
income, while the second term captures the negative effect of an increase in the
profit share, the increase in consumption of capitalists, and the induced increase
in consumption by the workers.
If the expression in equation (19) is positive, the relation between g and kw
satisfying equation (18), and hence implying dkw/dt ¼ 0, is shown as in Figure 1.
The values of g and kw which are the asymptotes for the curve are given by:
(1 cc )(1 cw )i
gþ ¼
L
and
(1 s)(1 cw ) g s cc
kwþ ¼
L
The horizontal arrows, from equations (17) and (11), show how kw changes at differ-
ent points in the figure. The figure shows that the economy, unless it starts from very
low values of kw, tends to its long-run equilibrium at point E. In equilibrium there
will be a positive level of kw, so that workers will own a constant share of total
capital. For the model to be internally consistent the parameters should be such
that kw 1, and that the equilibrium values of g and kw do not imply the full utiliz-
ation of capital or the full employment of labor.
If the expression in (19) is negative, the dkw/dt ¼ 0, will be as shown as in
Figure 2. The values of the asymptotes will be as before, and the horizontal
arrows, showing movements in kw, are as shown. In the configuration shown in
the figure, there is no long-run equilibrium, and it is possible for the economy
to be on a path in which kw and g keep falling, implying greater indebtedness
of workers and lower rates of growth. If the investment parameters are sufficiently
large, it is possible for the dg/dt ¼ 0 line to intersect the dkw/dt ¼ 0 line, and for
there to be a stable long-run equilibrium (at the intersection with the higher growth
rate). Of course, kw cannot take any value. We have to ensure that g and kw do not
fall to such an extent that u becomes negative. Far before that point is reached,
however, some lower bound for kw will be reached at which workers will reach
their credit limits. In that case the equations of this model will cease to apply.17
It can be seen that it is possible the economy may experience a regime shift
due to increases in advertising. Increases in advertising expenditures, by increas-
ing the marginal propensities to consume or the level of g, can move the economy
from the case in which G . 0, so that Figure 1 applies, to the case in which G , 0,
so that Figure 2 applies. Starting from a long-run equilibrium shown in Figure 1,
it may seem that in the short run capacity utilization increases with more adver-
tisement expenditure (although, as discussed earlier, this may not happen).
However, if the economy experiences a regime shift, it will experience a fall in
17
If workers reach their credit constraint – as a fraction of their income net of interest
payments – the evolution of debt will no longer be as analyzed in this model, which
allows workers to borrow any amount they wish, given their income and consumption
plans. With credit constraints, consumption will be determined by how much they can
borrow and the evolution of debt will be as analyzed in Dutt (2006b).
The Dependence Effect, Consumption and Happiness 547
the share of capital owned by workers, and eventually rising worker indebtedness,
which will imply a lower level of economic growth and a less equal distribution of
income and assets. Given an exogenously fixed rate of growth of labor supply,
unemployment will grow (faster) as well. The economy can then be said to be
less ‘happy’.
The intuition behind this effect of increasing advertising (and other market-
ing expenditures) on growth and distribution is straightforward. When workers
save, they obtain income from both wages and interest, and are able to own a
share of the capital in the long run. If advertising expenditures increase workers
consumption, they may experience a rise in income in the short run because of
the expansionary effect of higher spending by both workers and capitalists. But
with increases in capitalist income and the desire by workers to emulate them,
workers become borrowers and eventually net debtors. As their debt increases,
workers experience a decline in their net income, and with a redistribution of
income (from interest payments), there is a contractionary effect on aggregate
demand, because capitalist interest earners have a higher saving propensity than
workers. This contractionary effect reduces capacity utilization and growth,
implying a worsening in both growth and income distribution.
Economic growth may not make people, especially the rich, happier. But it
may do so if it makes the poor have higher levels of income, reduces unemployment,
and reduces inequality. However, our analysis implies that the sales promotion
expenditure of firms is unlikely to lead to this type of growth, and may even lead
to stagnation. There are much better ways of improving the macroeconomic per-
formance of the economy in ways that make people happier, for instance, by
increasing the supply of useful public goods, and improving the distribution of
income.
548 A.K. Dutt
5. Conclusion
This paper has attempted to evaluate Galbraith’s analysis of the affluent society in
which firms create wants and increase consumption without increasing well-being.
It has done so by examining three criticisms of Galbraith’s analysis: firms cannot
manipulate consumers, it is not true that higher levels of consumption induced by
firms do not increase welfare, and higher levels of consumption can result in
improved macroeconomic behavior, which can make people better off.
First, it has argued that even though consumers ultimately decide how much –
and what – to consume, firms affect consumption through their marketing and
related efforts. This argument has drawn on recent research on the determinants
of consumption, especially that which shows that consumption by people depends
on the consumption of other people.
Second, by reviewing empirical evidence and theoretical contributions, it has
argued that increases in consumption and income may not be associated with
increases in well-being even as evaluated by consumers themselves. Although
Galbraith may have oversold the argument that increases in output and consump-
tion will not increase utility since it is brought about by increasing sales
promotion, his argument is supported by empirical data and theoretical analysis.
Third, it has argued, by reviewing standard macroeconomic models and by
developing a new one, that increases in advertising and other sales promoting
expenditures may well have adverse long-run macroeconomic effects by increas-
ing consumer indebtedness and inequality, and reducing growth.
Galbraith’s analysis seems, 50 years later, to be right on the mark even
though, at the time, the argument could not be fully developed and firm empirical
evidence was not yet available.
Acknowledgments
An earlier version was presented at the Eastern Economic Association meetings at
New York, 2007 and at the Analytical Political Economy Workshop at Queen
Mary, London University, 2007. Comments from participants at these presenta-
tions, including Bill Gibson, Gilberto Lima, Simon Mohun, Malcolm Sawyer,
Gil Skillman, Martha Starr, and Roberto Veneziani are gratefully acknowledged.
I am also grateful to Michael Etzel for discussions and for pointing me towards
relevant marketing and advertising textbooks. Finally, I would like to thank the
anonymous referees for this journal for their extremely useful comments and sug-
gestions, and references to the literature.
References
Adorno, T.W. & Horkheimer, M. ([1944] 2000) The culture industry: enlightenment as mass decep-
tion, in: J.B. Schor & D.B. Holt (Eds) The Consumer Society Reader, pp. 3–19 (New York: New
Press).
Albion, M.S. & Farris, P.W. (1981) The Advertising Controversy: Evidence on the Economic Effects
of Advertising (Boston: Auburn House).
Baran, P. & Sweezy, P. (1964) Theses on advertising, Science and Society, 28, pp. 20–30.
Baran, P. & Sweezy, P. (1966) Monopoly Capital (New York: Monthly Review Press).
The Dependence Effect, Consumption and Happiness 549
Belch, G.E. & Belch, M.A. (2007) Advertising and Promotion: An Integrated Marketing Communi-
cations Perspective, 7th edn (New York: McGraw Hill).
Blanchard, O. (2006) Macroeconomics, 4th edn (Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall).
Bonsall, T. (2002) Disaster in Dearborn: The Story of the Edsel (Stanford, CA: Stanford University
Press).
Brooks, J. (1963) The Fate of Edsel and Other Business Adventures (New York: Harper & Row).
Brown, S., Taylor, K. & Price, S.W. (2005) Debt and distress: evaluating the psychological cost of
credit, Journal of Economic Psychology, 26, pp. 642–661.
Carroll, C.D. & Dunn, W.E. (1997) Unemployment expectations, jumping (S,s) triggers, and house-
hold balance sheets, NBER Macroeconomics Annual, Vol. 12, pp. 165–217 (Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press).
Clark, A.E. & Oswald, A.J. (1994) Unhappiness and unemployment, Economic Journal, 104,
pp. 648–699.
de Graaf, J., Wann, D. & Naylor, T.H. (2002) Affluenza: The All-Consuming Society (San Francisco:
Berrett-Koehler Publishers).
Di Tella, R., MacCulloch, R.J. & Oswald, A.J. (2001) Preferences over inflation and unemployment,
American Economic Review, 91(1), pp. 335–341.
Dickinson, R., Herbst, A. & O’Shaugnessy, J. (1986) The marketing concept and customer orien-
tation, European Journal of Marketing, 20(10), pp. 18–23.
Dutt, A.K. (2001) Consumption, happiness and religion, in: A.K. Dutt & K. Jameson (Eds) Crossing
the Mainstream: Ethical and Methodological Issues in Economics, pp. 133–169 (Notre Dame,
IN: University of Notre Dame Press).
Dutt, A.K. (2006a) Aggregate demand, aggregate supply and economic growth, International
Review of Applied Economics, 20(3), pp. 319–336.
Dutt, A.K. (2006b) Maturity, stagnation and consumer debt: a Steindlian approach, Metroecono-
mica, 57(3), pp. 339–364.
Dutt, A.K. & Ros, J. (2007) Aggregate demand shocks and economic growth, Structural Change and
Economic Dynamics, 18(1), pp. 75–99.
Earl, P.E. (1990) Economics and psychology, Economic Journal, 100, pp. 718–755.
Earl, P.E. & Potts, J. (2000) Latent demand and the browsing shopper, Managerial and Decision
Economics, 21, pp. 111–122.
Easterlin, R. (1973) Does economic growth improve the human lot? Some empirical evidence, in:
P. David & M. Reder (Eds) Nations and Households in Economic Growth: Essays in Honor of
Moses Abramovitz, pp. 89–125 (Palo Alto, CA: Stanford University Press).
Easterlin, R. (1995) Will raising the incomes of all increase the happiness of all?, Journal of Econ-
omic Behavior and Organization, 27, pp. 35–47.
Easterlin, R. (2001) Income and happiness: towards a unified theory, Economic Journal, 111,
pp. 465–484.
Easterlin, R. (Ed.) (2002) Happiness in Economics (Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar).
Frank, R. (1999) Luxury Fever: Why Money Fails to Satisfy in an Era of Excess (New York: Free
Press).
Frey, B.S. & Stutzer, A. (2002) Happiness and Economics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press).
Galbraith, J.K. (1958) The Affluent Society (London: Hamilton).
Galbraith, J.K. (1967) The New Industrial State (London: Houghton Mifflin).
Galbraith, J.K. (1998) The Affluent Society, 40th anniversary edn (Boston: Houghton-Mifflin).
Hanson, J.D. & Kysar, D.A. (1990a) Taking behavioralism seriously: the problem of market manipu-
lation, New York University Law Review, 74, pp. 630–749.
Hanson, J.D. & Kysar, D.A. (1990b) Taking behavioralism serious: some evidence of market
manipulation, Harvard Law Review, 112(7), pp. 1420–1572.
Hayek, F. (1961) The non-sequitur of the ‘dependence effect’, Southern Economic Journal, 27(4),
pp. 346–348.
Hession, C.H. (1972) John Kenneth Galbraith and his Critics (New York: New American Library).
Hirsch, F. (1976) Social Limits to Growth (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
Kalecki, M. (1971) Selected Essays on the Dynamics of the Capitalist Economy (Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press).
550 A.K. Dutt