Time As An Illusion: PSW - Papers@yahoo - Ca
Time As An Illusion: PSW - Papers@yahoo - Ca
Paul S. Wesson
Abstract We review the idea, due to Einstein, Eddington, Hoyle and Ballard, that time is
dimensional universe. In this approach, all moments in time exist simultaneously, but
they are ordered to create the illusion of an unfolding experience by some physical
world that extends beyond spacetime. Death in such a scenario may be merely a phase
change.
A Paper for the Proceedings Minkowski Spacetime: A Hundred Years Later, edited by V.
mous speech argued that time should be welded to space to form spacetime. The result is
obtain a more complicated expression for the interval, which is the basis of cosmology.
However, between the small systems of quantum theory and the large ones of cosmology,
there are numerous others which can be adequately described by Newtonian mechanics
and also involve time. An ongoing debate, in both philosophy and physics, has to do
with the nature of time in its various applications. Especially: are the various usages of
time in physics and everyday life consistent with a unique definition for it? Alterna-
tively: while time occurs in many guises, what is the most useful way to view it at a
conceptual level? We hope in what follows to answer these and related questions by re-
examining the argument – espoused by Einstein, Eddington, Hoyle, Ballard and others –
In doing this, it will be necessary to debunk certain myths about time, and to clar-
ify statements that have been made about it. Certainly, time has been a puzzling concept
throughout history. For example, Newton in his Principia (Scholium I), stated that “Ab-
solute, true and mathematical time, of itself, and from its own nature, flows equably
without relation to anything external, and by another name is called duration.” This sen-
tence is often quoted in the literature, and is widely regarded as being in opposition to the
nature of time as embodied later in relativity. However, prior to that sentence, Newton
2
also wrote about time and space that “… the common people conceive these quantities
under no other notions but from the relation they bear to sensible objects.” Thus Newton
was aware that the “common” people in the 1700s held a view of time and other physical
concepts which was essentially the same as the one used by Einstein, Minkowski, Poin-
dimensional space. The result is spacetime. In this, the time part involves the product of
t with the speed of light c, which essentially transforms the ‘distance’ along the time axis
to a length ct. Due to this, the interval is also a measure of which points are (or are not)
in contact via the exchange of photons. Those particles with real interval can be in con-
ever, it has a corollary which is not so familiar: particles with zero interval are coincident
in 4D. Einstein realized this, and it is the basis of his definition of simultaneity. But it is
not a situation which most people find easy to picture, so they decompose 4D spacetime
into 3D space and 1D time, and visualize a photon propagating through x y z over time t.
Eddington, the noted contemporary of Einstein, also appreciated the subjective nature of
the situation just described, and went on to argue that much of what is called objective in
physics is in fact subjective or invented. The speed of light was also commented on later
by a few deep thinkers such as McCrea and Hoyle, who regarded it as a mere man-made
constant. From the Eddington viewpoint, one can argue that the decomposition of 4D
3
Minkowski spacetime into separate 3D and 1D parts is a subjective act, so that in effect
the photon has been invented as a consequence of separating space and time.
Below, we will enlarge on the possibly subjective nature of physics, with an em-
phasis on the concept of time. We will in fact suggest that time is a subjective ordering
device, used by humans to make sense of their world. Several workers have expressed
this idea, including Einstein (1955 in Hoffmann 1972), Eddington (1928, 1939), Hoyle
(1963, 1966), Ballard (1984) and Wesson (2001). We hope to show that this approach
makes scientific sense, and from a common-day perspective has certain comforts.
give a critique of other, more mainstream views. This will be short, because good re-
views of the nature of time are available by many workers including Gold (1967), Davies
(1974), Whitrow (1980), McCrea (1986), Hawking (1988), Landsberg (1989), Zeh
(1992), Woodward (1995) and Halpern and Wesson (2006). We will discuss contending
views of the nature of time in Section 2, introduce what seems to be a better approach in
Section 3, and expand on the implications of this in Section 4. Although it is not essen-
tial, it will become apparent that our new approach to time is psychologically most
productive when the world is taken to have more dimensions than the four of spacetime,
The idea that time flows from the past to the future, and that the reason for this
has something to do with the natural world, has become endemic to philosophy and phys-
4
ics. However, this idea is suspect. We will in this section examine briefly the three ways
in which the direction of time’s ‘arrow’ is commonly connected with physical processes,
and argue that they are all deficient. Quite apart from technical arguments, a little
thought will show that a statement such as the “flow of time”, despite being everyday us-
age, is close to nonsensical. For the phrase implies that time itself can be measured with
respect to another quantity of the same kind. This might be given some rational basis in a
multidimensional universe in which there is more than one time axis (see below); but the
everyday usage implies measuring the change of a temporal quantity against itself, which
because there is a widespread belief that the subjective, unidirectional nature of time can
But more specifically, it is a measure of the disorder in a system; and since disorder is
observed to increase in most systems as they evolve, the growth of entropy is commonly
taken as indicative of the passage of time. This connection was made by Eddington, who
also commented on the inverse relationship between information and entropy (Eddington
1928, 1939). However, the connection has been carried to an unreasonable degree by
some subsequent writers, who appear to believe that the passage of time is equivalent to
the increase of entropy. That this is not so can be seen by a simple counter-argument: If
it were true, each person could carry a badge that registered their entropy, and its meas-
urement would correlate with the time on a local clock. This is clearly daft.
5
A more acceptable application of the notion of entropy might be found in the
systems bifurcate, and so define the direction of the future. In principle, this approach is
viable. However, the theory would be better couched in terms of a universe with more
than the four dimensions of spacetime; and interest in the idea of many worlds appears to
have lapsed, because there is no known way to validate or disprove their existence.
Another physical basis for the passage of time which has been much discussed
somewhat indirect, but can be illustrated by a simple case where light propagates from
one point to another. (This is what happens when humans apprehend things by the sense
of sight, and is also how most information is transmitted by modern technology.) Let the
signal be emitted at point P and observed at point O, where the distance between them is
d and is traversed at lightspeed c. Now Maxwell’s equations, which govern the interac-
tion, are symmetric in the time t. (We are assuming that the distance is small enough that
get the physics right, we have to use the electromagnetic potential not at time t but at the
retarded time (t-d/c). This is, of course, the time ‘corrected’ for the travel lag from the
point P of emission to the point O of observation. Such a procedure may appear logical;
but it has been pointed out by many thinkers that it automatically introduces a time
asymmetry into the problem (see Davies 1974 for an extensive review). The use of re-
tarded potentials, while they agree with observations, is made even more puzzling by the
6
fact that Maxwell’s equations are equally valid if use is made instead of the ‘advanced’
potentials defined at (t + d/c). In short, the underlying theory treats negative and positive
increments of time on the same footing, but the real world appears to prefer the solutions
where the past evolves to the future. Studies have been made of the symmetric case,
are allowed. One argument for why we do not experience the signals corresponding to
the advanced potentials is that due to Hoyle and Narlikar (1974). They reasoned that the
with a universe which is apparently asymmetric between the past and future. This expla-
cosmos. On the small scale, it appears that the need for retarded potentials in electrody-
namics leads to a locally-defined arrow of time; though whether this is due to objective
The big bang offers yet another way of accounting for the arrow of time. Accord-
ing to Einstein’s theory of general relativity, everything we observe came into existence
years before the present. This description is familiar to all, and carries with it the impli-
cation that the universe in a dynamical sense has a preferred direction of evolution.
However, closer examination shows that it is really the recession of the galaxies from
each other, rather than the big bang, which identifies the time-sense of the universe’s evo-
lution. This was understood by Bondi (1952), who was one of the founders with Gold
and Hoyle of the steady-state theory. In it, matter is continuously created and condenses
7
to form new galaxies, whose average density is thereby maintained even though the
steady-state theory shows that it is the motions of galaxies which essentially defines a
preferred direction for time, rather than the (still poorly understood) processes by which
they may have formed after the big bang. Let us, in fact, temporarily forget about the lat-
ter event, and consider an ensemble of gravitating galaxies. Then there are in principle
only three modes of evolution: expansion, contraction and being static. The last can be
ruled out, because it is widely acknowledged that such a state, even if it existed, would be
unstable and tip into one of the other two modes. We are thus lead to the realization that
if the arrow of time is dictated by the dynamical evolution of the universe, its sense is
given a priori by a 50/50 choice analogous to flipping a cosmic coin. That is, there is no
dynamical reason for believing that events should go forward rather than backwards in
time. In addition to this, there is also the problem that there is no known physical process
which can transfer a cosmic effect on a lengthscale of 1018 cm down to a human one of
order 102 cm. In order to circumvent this objection, it has been suggested that the hu-
the nucleosynthesis of elements that determines the evolution of the Sun. This process
might, via the notion of entropy as discussed above, be connected to geophysical effects
on the Earth, and so to the biology of its human inhabitants. But it is really obvious,
when we pick apart the argument, that there is no discernable link between the mechanics
of the evolving universe and the sense of the passage of time which is experienced by
people.
8
The preceding issues, to do with entropy, electrodynamics and cosmology, have
the unfortunate smell of speculation. Dispassionate thought reveals little convincing con-
nection between the time coordinate used in physics and the concept of age as used in
human biology. We can certainly imagine possible connections between physical and
human time, as for example in Einstein’s Dreams by Lightman (1993). There, the effects
of relativity such as time dilation are described in sociological contexts. But, there is a
large gap between the fluid manner in which time can be manipulated by the novelist and
the rigid transformations of time permitted to the physicist. Indeed, while the physicist
may be able to handle the “t” symbol in his equations with dexterity, he looks clumsy and
strained when he attempts to extend his theories to the practicality of everyday existence.
That is why the sayings about time by physicists mainly languish in obscurity, while
In the latter category, we can consider the statement of Marcel Proust: “The
world was not created at the beginning of time. The world is created every day.” This
appears to dismiss the big bang, and by implication other parts of physics, as irrelevant to
the human experience of time. However, it is more rewarding to consider statements like
“time” which is compatible with the rather narrow usage of the word in physics, and yet
in agreement with the many ways in which the concept is experienced by people?
9
3. Time as a Subjective Ordering Device
The differing roles which time plays in physics and everyday life has led some
workers to the conclusion that it is a subjective concept. Let us consider the following
quotes:
Einstein (as reported by Hoffman): “For us believing physicists the distinction be-
tween past, present and future is only an illusion, even if a stubborn one.”
Eddington: “General scientific considerations, favour the view that our feeling of
the going on of time is a sensory impression; that is to say, it is as closely connected with
stimuli from the physical world as the sensation of light is. Just as certain physical dis-
turbances entering the brain cells via the optic nerves occasion the sensation of light, so a
change of entropy … occasions the sensation of time succession, the moment of greater
Hoyle: “All moments of time exist together.” “There is no such thing as ‘waiting’
for the future.” “It could be that when we make subjective judgments we’re using con-
nections that are non-local … there is a division, the world divides into two, into two
happened, all the events that will ever happen, are taking place together.” “It’s possible
to imagine that everything is happening at once, all the events ‘past’ and ‘future’ which
constitute the universe are taking place together. Perhaps our sense of time is a primitive
10
The preceding four opinions about time have an uncanny similarity, given that
they apparently originate independently of each other. However, they are all compatible
with Eddington’s view of science, wherein certain concepts of physics are not so much
discovered as invented (see Wesson 2000 for a short review). The subjective nature of
time is also compatible with current views of particle physics and cosmology, wherein
several worlds exist alongside each other (Everett 1957, De Witt 1970, Penrose 1989,
Wesson 2006, Petkov 2007). It is important to realize that there need not be anything
mystical about this approach. For example, Hoyle considers a 4D world of the usual type
with time and space coordinates t and x y z which define a surface φ (t , x y z ) = C . Here
C is a parameter which defines a subset of points in the world. Changing C changes the
subset, and “We could be said to live our lives through changes of C.” In other words,
the life of a person can be regarded as the consequence of some mechanism which picks
What such a mechanism might be is obscure. Hoyle speculated that the mecha-
nism might involve known physical fields such as electromagnetism, which is the basis of
macroscopic levels by the brain in the manner envisaged by Penrose (1989). However,
while the precise mechanism is unknown, some progress can be made in a general way
hypersurface. This is the relation one obtains when one cuts through a higher-
11
in fact quite feasible that the Minkowski spacetime of our local experience is just a slice
In fact, higher dimensions are the currently popular way to unify gravity with the
interactions of particle physics, and reviews of the subject are readily available (e.g.,
Wesson 2006 from the physical side and Petkov 2007 from the philosophical side). Since
we are here mainly interested in the concept of time, let us concentrate on one exact solu-
tion of the theory for the simplest case when there is only a single extra dimension. (See
Wesson 1999 for a compendium of higher-dimensional solutions including the one exam-
ined here.) Let us augment the time (t) and the coordinates of Euclidean space (x y z) by
an extra length (l). Then by solving the analog of Einstein’s equations of general relativ-
ity in 5D, the interval between two nearby points can be written
dS 2 = l 2 dt 2 − l 2 exp i (ωt + k x x )dx 2 − l 2 exp i (ωt + k y y )dy 2 − l 2 exp i (ωt + k z z )dz 2 + L2 dl 2 . (1)
Here ω is a frequency, kx etc. are wave numbers and L measures the size of the extra di-
mension. This equation, while it may look complicated, has some very informative
aspects: (a) it describes a wave, in which parts of what are commonly called space can
come into and go out of existence; (b) it can be transformed by a change of coordinates to
a flat manifold, so what looks like a space with structure is equivalent to one that is fea-
tureless; (c) the signature is + – – – +, so the extra coordinate acts like a second time.
These properties allow of some inferences relevant to the present discussion: (a) even
ordinary 3D space can be ephemeral; (b) a space may have structure which is not intrinsic
but a result of how it is described; (c) there is no unique way to identify time.
12
This last property is striking. It means that in grand-unified theories for the forces
of physics, the definition of time may be ambiguous. This classical result confirms the
inference from quantum theory, where the statistical interaction of particles can lead to
thermodynamic arrows of time for different parts of the universe which are different or
even opposed (Shulman 1997, 2000). It should be noted that the existence of more than
one ‘time’ is not confined to 5D relativity, but also occurs in other N-dimensional ac-
counts such as string theory (Bars et al. 1999). Indeed, there can in principle be many
In addition, the definition of time may be altered even in the standard 4D version
quently called a gauge choice.) The reason is that Einstein’s field equations are set up in
terms of tensors, in order to ensure their applicability to any system of coordinates. This
property, called covariance, is widely regarded as essential for any modern theory of
physics. However, if we wish to have equations which are valid irrespective of how we
choose the coordinates, then we perforce have to accept the fact that time and space are
malleable. Indeed, covariance even allows us to mix the time and space labels. Given the
principle of covariance, it is not hard to see why physicists have abandoned the unique
We are led to the realization that the concept of time is as much a puzzle to the
probably feels more comfortable about the issue than those who attempt to analyse it.
13
However, it is plausible that time in its different guises is a device used by people to or-
In the foregoing, we saw that several deep thinkers have arrived independently at
(Einstein), connected with human sensory impressions (Eddington), so that all moments
of time exist together (Hoyle), with the division between past and future merely a hold-
over from our primitive ancestors (Ballard). Perhaps the most trenchant opinion is that of
Hoyle (1966), who summarizes the situation thus: “There’s one thing quite certain in this
business. The idea of time as a steady progression from past to future is wrong. I know
very well we feel this way about it subjectively. But we’re all victims of a confidence
trick. If there’s one thing we can be sure about in physics, it is that all times exist with
equal reality”
This view of time can be put on a physical basis. We imagine that each person’s
higher-dimensional world, and that a person’s life is represented by the evolution of this
vast ocean whose parts are all connected, but across which a wave runs, its breaking crest
the preceding section as Equation (1). It should be noted that there is nothing very spe-
14
cial about the dimensionality, and that it is unclear how many dimensions are required to
adequately explain all of known physics. The important thing is that if we set the interval
to zero, to define a world whose parts are connected in higher dimensions, then we neces-
sarily obtain the hypersurface which defines experience in the lower-dimensional world.
It is interesting to note that the behaviour of that hypersurface depends critically on the
number of plus and minus signs in the metric (i.e., on the signature). In the canonical ex-
tension of Einstein’s theory of general relativity from four to five dimensions, the
hypersurface has two possible behaviours. Let us express the hypersurface generally as a
call the proper time (which is the time of everyday existence corrected to account for
things like the motion). Then the two possible behaviours for the hypersurface may be
written
Here lo is a fiducial value of the extra coordinate, L is the length which defines the size of
the fifth dimension, and s is the aforementioned interval or proper time. The two noted
behaviours describe, respectively, a growing mode and an oscillating mode. The differ-
ence between the two modes depends on the signature of the metric, and is indicated by
the absence or presence of i ≡ − 1 in the usual manner. So far, the analysis follows the
basic idea about experience due to Hoyle but expressed in the language of hypersurfaces
as discussed by Wesson (see Hoyle and Hoyle 1963, Wesson 2006). However, it is pos-
sible to go further, and extend the analysis into the metaphysical domain for those so
inclined. This by virtue of a change from the growing mode to the oscillatory mode, with
15
the identification of the former with a person’s material life and the latter with a person’s
spiritual life. That is, we obtain a simple model wherein existence is described by a hy-
persurface in a higher-dimensional world, with two modes of which one is growing and is
identified with corporeal life, and one is wave-like and is identified with the soul, the two
Whether one believes in a model like this which straddles physics and spirituality
is up to the individual. (In this regard, the author is steadfastly neutral.) However, it is
remarkable that such a model can even be formulated, bridging as it does realms of ex-
perience which have traditionally been viewed as immutably separate. Even if one stops
part way through the above analysis, it is clear that the concept of time may well be an
illusion. This in itself should be sufficient to comfort those who fear death, which should
5. Conclusion
ways. It can be formalized, using the speed of light, as a coordinate on par with the coor-
dinates of ordinary three-dimensional space. But while spacetime is an effective tool for
the physicist, this treatment of time seems sterile to the average person, and does not ex-
plain the origin of time as a concept. There are shortcomings in purely physical
explanations of time and its apparent flow, be they from entropy, many-worlds, electro-
magnetism or the big bang. Such things seem too abstract and remote to adequately
explain the individual’s everyday experience of time. Hence the suggestion that time is a
16
subjective ordering device, invented by the human mind to make sense of its perceived
world.
This idea, while not mainstream, has occurred to several thinkers. These include
the philosopher Proust, the scientists Einstein, Eddington and Hoyle, and the novelist
Ballard. It is noteworthy that the idea appears to have its genesis independently with
these people. And while basically psychological in nature, it is compatible with certain
approaches in physics, notably Penrose’s suggestion that the human brain may be a kind
macroscopic ones. The idea of time as an ordering device was given a basis in the phys-
ics of relativity by Hoyle, who however only sketched the issue, arguing that the
movement of a hypersurface would effectively provide a model for the progress of a per-
son’s life. This approach can be considerably developed, as outlined above, if we assume
Then it is possible to write down an equation for the hypersurface, which can have an
evolutionary and an oscillatory phase, which might (if a person is so inclined) be identi-
fied with the materialistic and spiritual modes of existence. Perhaps more importantly, in
this 5D approach, the interval (or ‘separation’) between points is zero, so all of the events
in the world are in (5D) causal contact. In other words, everything is occurring simulta-
neously.
That this picture may be difficult to visualize just bolsters the need for something
like the concept of time, which can organize the simultaneous sense data into a compre-
hensible order.
17
Time, viewed in this manner, is akin to the three measures of ordinary space, at
least insofar as how the brain works. Humans have binocular vision, which enables them
to judge distances. This is an evolutionary, biological trait. Certain other hunting ani-
mals, like wolves, share it. By comparison, a rabbit has eyes set into the sides of its head,
so while it can react well to an image that might pose a threat, it cannot judge distance
well. But even a human with good vision finds it increasingly difficult to judge the rela-
appearance, like a photograph, or a landscape painting. In the latter, a good artist will use
differing degrees of shade and detail to give an impression of distance, as for example
when depicting a series of hills and valleys which recede to the horizon. Likewise, the
human brain uses subtle clues to do with illumination and resolution to form an opinion
about the relative spacing of objects at a distance. This process is learned, and not per-
long been aware of the pitfalls of trying to assess the distances of remote objects. Tradi-
tionally, they measured offsets in longitude and latitude by means of two angles indicated
by the telescope, called right ascension and declination. But they had no way of directly
measuring the distances along the line of sight, and so referred to their essentially 2D
maps as being drawn on the surface of an imaginary surface called the celestial sphere.
Given such a limited way of mapping, it was very hard to decide if two galaxies seen
close together on the sky were physically close or by chance juxtaposed along the line of
18
probability arguments to decide (say) if two galaxies near to each other on a photographic
plate were really tied together by gravity, or merely the result of a coincidental proximity
in 2D while being widely separated in 3D. The situation changed drastically when tech-
nological advances made it easier to measure the redshifts of galaxies, since the redshift
of a source could be connected via Hubble’s law to the physical distance along the line of
sight. Thus today, combining angular measurements for longitude and latitude with red-
shifts for outward distance, astronomers have fairly good 3D maps of the distribution of
tially 2D) by the hologram (which provides information in 3D). However, whether this is
done for a cluster of galaxies or a family portrait, the process of evaluating distance is a
relatively complicated one. The human brain evaluates 3D separations routinely, and we
are not usually aware of any conscious effort in doing so. But this apparently mundane
process is also a complicated one. If we take it that the concept of time is similar to the
concept of space, it is hardly surprising that the human brain has evolved its own subtle
Thus the idea of time as a kind of subjective ordering device, by which we make
References
Bars, I., Deliduman, C., Minic, D., 1999. Phys. Rev. D 59, 125004.
19
Bondi, H., 1952. Cosmology. Cambridge University Press. Cambridge.
Davies, P.C.W., 1974. The Physics of Time Asymmetry. University of California Press,
Berkeley.
Eddington, A.S. 1928. The Nature of the Physical World. Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge.
Eddington, A.S., 1939. The Philosophy of Physical Science. Macmillan, New York.
Gold, T. (ed.), 1967. The Nature of Time. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, N.Y.
Halpern, P., Wesson, P.S., 2006. Brave New Universe. J. Henry Press, Washington.
Hawking, S.W., 1988. A Brief History of Time. Bantam Press, New York.
Hoffmann, B., 1972. Albert Einstein, Creator and Rebel. New American Lib., New York.
Hoyle, F., 1966. October the First is Too Late. Fawcett-Crest, Greenwich, Conn.
Hoyle, F., Narlikar, J.V., 1974. Action at a Distance in Physics and Cosmology. Free-
Landsberg, P.T., 1989. In Physics in the Making (Sarlemijn, A., Sparnaay, M. J., eds.).
Petkov, V. (ed.), 2007. Relativity and the Dimensionality of the World. Springer, Berlin.
Penrose, R., 1989. The Emperor’s New Mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford.
20
Shulmann, L.S., 1997. Time’s Arrow and Quantum Measurement. Cambridge Univer-
Wesson, P.S., 2000. Observatory 120 (1154), 59. Ibid., 2001, 121 (1161), 82.
Whitrow, G.J., 1980. The Natural Philosophy of Time. Oxford University Press, Ox-
ford.
21