Arriving at A Strategic Theory of The Firm: Steven E. Phelan and Peter Lewin

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 43

ARRIVING AT A STRATEGIC THEORY OF THE FIRM

Steven E. Phelan
and
Peter Lewin

School of Management

University of Texas at Dallas

Box 830688, Richardson, Texas, 75083

(972) 883 2754

[email protected]

[email protected]

First Draft
January, 1999
Please do not cite or quote without permission.
Comments welcome.

1
ABSTRACT

Several authors have characterized their work as “moving towards” a


strategic theory of the firm (Rumelt, 1984). The authors of this paper
argue that it is time to start “arriving” at a strategic theory of the firm
because a theory of the firm necessarily underlies every decision to enter
a new line of business or outsource a function. Existing strategic theories
of the firm are contrasted with economic theories of the firm and are
found to be weak in explaining the existence of the firm while strong in
their understanding of value creation and the location of firm boundaries.
A distinction is made between firms in general and corporations. It is
concluded that firms exist for a variety of reasons but that corporations
have grown to dominate the business landscape because of their superior
ability to create, and protect, value for their owners.

2
ARRIVING AT A STRATEGIC THEORY OF THE FIRM
INTRODUCTION
As many as half of all transactions in the economy are now conducted within

firms. The theory of the firm sets out to explain the nature and limitations (or boundaries)

of the firm as an economic institution. The theory of the firm can be located within the

broader analysis of economic organization, which attempts to explain the observed

diversity of institutional arrangements in the economy. For instance, why do some

transactions occur in markets, others in firms, and still others in hybrid structures such as

franchises, joint ventures and strategic alliances? The study of economic organization

seeks to understand the conditions that create this diversity.

Ronald Coase’s (1937) observation that “…firms exist because there are costs to

using the market” has been the touchstone for the study of organizations by economists.

Attempts to identify the costs of using the market have led to fruitful developments in

economics such as transaction cost economics (Williamson, 1975; Williamson, 1985),

incomplete contracts theory (Hart, 1995), property rights and measurement costs (Barzel,

1989; Cheung, 1983) and agency theory (Alchian & Demsetz, 1972).

More recently, there has been an explosion of interest in the theory of the firm

among strategy scholars (see Foss, 1998b for a review). Their attention has been caught

by the possibility that there may be benefits to using firms rather than costs to using the

market (Conner, 1991). It is argued that contemporary theories of strategy (particularly

the resource-based view) are well positioned to explain these benefits. Several theories

of the firm have been proposed from a strategic perspective, using a variety of (related)

theoretical lenses, such as resources (Barney, 1996; Rumelt, 1984), knowledge (Conner

3
& Prahalad, 1996; Grant, 1996), competencies (Foss & Knudsen, 1996; Penrose, 1959),

capabilities (Langlois, 1992), and real options (Barney & Lee, 1998; Sanchez, 1998).

To date, there has been a tentative quality to much of the work in strategy, with

several authors characterizing their work as “moving towards” a theory of the firm rather

than forming a definitive theoretical statement. We believe that the field has evolved to

the point where we are ready to start arriving at a strategic theory of the firm by drawing

together the disparate threads of previous discussions into a single coherent theory. This

conviction is the motivation for this paper.

DOES STRATEGY NEED A THEORY OF THE FIRM?

Every time a manager engages in a make-or-buy decision, he or she is utilizing

(either explicitly or implicitly) a theory of the firm. The use of outsourcing, strategic

alliances, joint ventures and franchising has grown markedly during the 1990s and has

been accompanied by an increased scrutiny of all make-or-buy decisions within the firm.

We have already alluded to the fact that the problem of where to set the boundaries of the

firm is one of the central issues in the theory of the firm. A corollary to the question,

“Why do firms exist?” is “Why are all transactions not performed by a single firm?” Any

advance in our understanding of where to draw firm boundaries must ultimately improve

the quality of managerial decision making in this area.

A theory of the firm can also inform the entrepreneurial process because it seeks

to provide the conditions (both necessary and sufficient) for the establishment of a firm.

The decision, by an entrepreneur, to start an enterprise implicitly reflects the belief that

he or she can “beat the market” and produce a product more effectively through a firm

than via a set of market contracts. Similar considerations apply when an existing firm

4
decides to vertically integrate or enter a new line of business. By offering plausible

explanations for the existence and boundaries of the firm, a theory of the firm becomes

capable of offering prescriptions for both the founding of new enterprises and

adjustments to the horizontal and vertical boundaries of existing firms.

Some of the motivation for developing a strategic theory of the firm also emerges

from the dissatisfaction felt by management scholars and practitioners towards existing

economic theories of the firm. As will be discussed in the next section, existing

economic theories of the firm tend to characterize firms as efficient devices for

minimizing information and transaction costs under certain conditions. Williamson

(1991) goes so far as to say that economizing on transaction costs should be far more

important to managers than strategizing.

While we believe that economic theories of the firm have considerable

explanatory power, we do not believe that they provide the whole story (or even half the

story) for the existence and organization of the firm. A definitive theory of the firm must

ultimately blend strategic and economic considerations.

ECONOMIC THEORIES OF THE FIRM

The set of economic theories of the firm is large ranging from neoclassical theory

to industrial organization (Seth & Thomas, 1994) and from Adam Smith to Karl Marx.

The subset of economic theories we are about to review1 currently rank among the most

influential theories of the firm. While there are clear differences between the various

theories within this set, all share a common set of assumptions about: 1) the need for

exchange arising from specialization, 2) the need for coordination and cooperation among

5
economic agents, and 3) the assumption of efficiency in economic organization. Each of

these assumptions will be discussed in turn.

Specialization and Exchange

It is well known that specialization through division of labor increases

productivity (as Adam Smith so clearly discerned over two hundred years ago). It follows

that allowing people to specialize in activities in which they have a comparative

advantage increases the wealth of the society as a whole.

For Demsetz (1995), a ‘firm’ is any individual, or group of individuals, that

undertakes specialized production, that is, producing for others rather than for their own

households. Firms exist because they are able to produce goods more efficiently than

households can. The alternative to the firm is not the market but the household. If firms

are less productive than households, people will become self-sufficient and produce

goods for their own consumption (Demsetz, 1995; Demsetz, 1997).

Specialization, however, is not in itself sufficient to improve economic welfare.

Specialist producers must also be able to exchange their output with others in the

economy. The emergence of money, for instance, greatly facilitated the process of

exchange because it enabled agents with disparate outputs and time preferences to

transact.

Because gains from trade can only be realized after exchange has occurred,

economists have tended to focus on the transaction – the act of negotiating, executing

and enforcing an exchange – as the most appropriate unit of analysis.

1
Foss (1993) refers to them as contractual theories of the firm.

6
This raises the question about what is actually being exchanged in a transaction.

Most economists would now agree that it is the rights to an asset (broadly defined) that

are being exchanged. Common rights that may be transacted include the rights to use,

alter, transfer, alienate, or appropriate income from, an asset. An asset in this case

includes labor, land, capital, or any combination thereof.

Transactions and contracts are closely related (in fact, Cheung (1969) views all

transactions as contracts). It is not surprising that developments in the law of contract

closely correspond with developments in exchange mechanisms (Masten, 1988). Over the

centuries, the common law and statutes have prescribed (and proscribed) the rights that

may be transferred in a transaction. For instance, a person cannot alienate (or sell) his or

her own human capital nor is it possible to own someone else’s human capital (i.e.

slavery is per se illegal). Similarly, under common law, the master-servant principle

ensures that an employer (who has contracted the right to use someone’s human capital in

exchange for wages) is also entitled to any gains or discoveries made by the employee

while in his or her employ.

One may distinguish between specific rights, that are explicit terms in a contract,

and residual rights, which are not. Common law has generally upheld the right of

individuals and firms to make almost any specific provisions they wish in a contract

provided certain basic conditions are met2. The law (i.e. society) also determines the

nature of the default or residual rights that remain after a transaction.

2
Such as both parties being competent when they made the contract, considerations were

exchanged, and nothing specifically illegal was contracted.

7
Ownership can be conceived as the bundle of residual rights that remains after all

specific contractual arrangements. The most important of these residual rights are the

rights to income and control. The owners of a firm, for example, are entitled to any

surplus received after contractual obligations (including wages, rent, and debt payments)

have been met. In lieu of any specific provisions, the owners of a firm are also entitled to

use, alter, divide or sell the firm’s assets in any way they see fit. As we shall see, these

two rights are very important in determining the benefits and costs of organizing

exchange within a firm.

Coordination and Cooperation

In textbook models of comparative advantage, firms produce one discrete

commodity (such as wine) and trade it for another discrete commodity (such as wheat).

This greatly oversimplifies the nature of specialization in a sophisticated economy.

Advanced technologies, such as computer systems or modern jet aircraft, require

the inputs of a multitude of specialists and specialist services. In the case of human

capital, some of these inputs (e.g. a programmer) may be purchased in the market via a

service agreement or, alternatively, employed by the firm using a wage contract. In the

case of physical capital, such as a photocopier, a firm may choose to either hire the

services of a copy bureau, lease a copier machine, purchase the machine outright, or even

build its own copier machine.

This leads to the multifaceted problem of coordination. In the first instance, a

firm (or entrepreneur) must perceive a market demand for a product. Second, a bundle of

specialist inputs (or resources) must be identified that is capable of meeting the perceived

market demand. Third, a firm must ensure that the process of assembling the inputs is

8
undertaken and that all parts are capable of productively working together to form the

final product. Finally, a firm must determine the best form of economic organization for

each input (lease/own, make/buy) to maximize the long-run performance of the

company3.

The cooperation problem follows from the last point. The specialists that provide

the inputs to the final product are assumed to be maximizing their own gains from

exchange. The owner of the firm must therefore organize contractual arrangements in

such a way as to ensure the interests of the agents (specialists) are aligned with the

interest of the principal (owner). This is achieved mainly through the use of monitoring

and incentives.

Problems of coordination and cooperation can be seen as types of information

costs. In an economy with perfect information, there would be no coordination or

cooperation costs. The correct technology to meet consumer needs would be known, and

the effort and level of cooperation of employees could be easily measured. Consumer

needs could also be easily determined. The fact that these things are not easily

determined makes the issues of coordination and cooperation important. In fact, with no

information costs the question of economic organization would be irrelevant. All

resources would be accurately priced and could be costlessly exchanged via market

transactions (Demsetz, 1988).

3
The so-called choice between the firm or the market is really a choice using one firm or two as

all specialization is by firms and hence all exchange is between firms.

9
Economic Efficiency

All of the most influential economic theories of the firm subscribe to the

hypothesis of economic efficiency which assumes that all observed forms of economic

organization are efficient (absent external effects)4. A corollary of this hypothesis is that

all opportunities for gain have been exhausted. If there was a better (i.e. more efficient)

way of organizing production then firms in the economy would have implemented it.

Thus, the task of the organizational economist is not to find ‘better’ ways of

organizing. Rather, it is to understand why certain forms appear in some contexts and not

in others. Workers in the textile industry, for example, are almost always paid on the

basis of piecework rates while college professors are hardly ever paid this way.

Attempting to explain such differences in economic organization is the primary goal of

organizational economics.

The theory of the firm is thus a subset of the overall problem of explaining

economic organization and is focused on the tendency for some sections of the economy

to coordinate transactions within the boundaries of a firm, while others parts of the

economy choose to coordinate their transactions through the market. The goal is to

explain this diversity of organization.

Specific Theories

We are now in a position to review some of the more influential economic

theories of the firm. This will be no more than a brief overview. The goal is to gain an

4
in the sense of Pareto efficiency where no one can be made better off without making someone

else worse off

10
appreciation for the reasoning involved. This will act as an aid in understanding both

how strategists have departed from economic reasoning in their theories of the firm, and

to illustrate the basis of the criticisms that economists have leveled at such theories.

The Coasian Tradition

According to Coase (1937), if all transactions are efficient then firms must exist

because there are costs to using the market (or price mechanism). Coase identified several

of these “transaction costs” including the costs of discovering prices; and searching,

negotiating and concluding contracts. Coase believed a firm could avoid these costs by

negotiating long term contracts with its employees. The fewer contracts signed over a

given period of time the lower the transaction costs.

However, as contract periods lengthened so did the likelihood that business

conditions would change in unforeseeable ways. To counter this effect, he predicted that

employers would want to leave many details of their employment contracts unspecified

so they could be free to direct employees to take different actions as conditions dictated.

For Coase, this ability for owners to (re)direct the work of their employees was the

distinguishing characteristic of the firm5.

He defended his argument by pointing out that the legal definition of a master-

servant relationship (versus a principal-agent agreement) turned on the ability of the

employer to direct the work of the employee whereas such a power did not exist in a

principal-agent agreement.

5
i.e. the firm has residual rights of control over its employees.

11
Coase went on to provide several reasons why all transactions did not occur in

one large firm. He argued that the number, dispersion and dissimilarity of transactions

would negatively impact the ability of management to effectively allocate resources thus

increasing the costs of integration.

Measurement Cost Approach

Cheung (1969; 1983) extended Coase’s analysis by discussing several additional

costs to using the price system. Coase had always discussed transaction costs between

firms, not between firms and consumers. Cheung reasoned that in a world without firms,

consumers (or households) would be forced to coordinate the assembly of complex

products themselves by buying the individual components from specialists. This raised

several problems (i.e. costs) for consumers:

...the determination of prices is costly because of the number of transactions,

because consumers lack detailed information on the use of each component or

contribution to a commodity, because of the difficulty of measuring varied

and changing activities, because of the need to separate contributions

(Cheung, 1983, p.9).

Cheung suggested that all of the difficulties were due to information costs. In a

world of perfect information these difficulties would not arise. Cheung also argued that

firms did not supersede markets. Rather, one form of contract was replaced with another.

Firm as Nexus of Contracts

Alchian and Demsetz (1972) explicitly rejected the notion that authority provided

a justification for the firm. Either side of an employment contract could terminate an

12
agreement just as either side of a market contract could terminate an agreement. An

employee did not have to follow orders he or she did not like, so the firm had no special

authority over its employees. Like Cheung, they believed that the term ‘firm’ was simply

shorthand for a particularly dense nexus of contracts between economic agents.

Alchian and Demsetz’s started with the observation that much of the production

in a firm could be characterized as “team production” in that the services of several

specialists were required to produce an end product. While they viewed the coordination

of production as relatively unproblematic, they felt it was very difficult to monitor the

effort of individual workers in a team. Individual team members had an incentive to shirk

by reducing their effort. Shirking reduced the surplus of everyone in the team prompting

the hiring of a monitor to measure effort. But this created a new problem – monitoring

the monitor.

The solution was to award the residual income of the firm to the monitor (now

called the owner). The incentive to earn an uncapped income would motivate the monitor

to keep a close check on the team. A firm was therefore defined as team production in the

service of a monitor holding residual income rights.

Transaction Cost Approaches

Like Cheung (1983), Williamson (1975; 1985) and Klein, Crawford and Alchian

(1978), hereafter KCA, made major contributions to Coase’s transaction cost framework,

introducing new elements and significantly expanding the explanatory power of the

theory. Whereas Coase had emphasized the ex ante costs of search and contract

negotiation, Williamson and KCA focused on ex post transaction costs arising from an

inability to enforce contracts.

13
Williamson (1975) began his argument by assuming that economic agents were

boundedly rational. This ensured that any contracts written between agents were

incomplete (i.e. agents could not contract for every contingency).

Williamson also introduced the notion of asset specificity. A contract between

two parties invariably created assets specific to the relationship that could not be easily

deployed to alternative uses (i.e. sunk costs). The difference in value between an initial

investment and its salvage value (or its value in its next best use) was termed quasi-rent

(Klein et al., 1978).

By acting opportunistically to renegotiate an (incomplete) contract in the light of

unforeseen contingencies, an unscrupulous party could potentially holdup its partner and

appropriate the quasi-rents. Of course, if the partner firm could foresee this risk, the deal

would not proceed in the first place. Paradoxically, unanticipated holdup never occurs in

Williamson’s world.

The alternative for a firm with substantial quasi-rents was to vertically integrate

into the activity of its partner, thus holding all specific assets itself and removing the

threat of holdup. The extent of a firm’s integration was limited at the margin by the

tradeoff between governance costs and transaction costs.

Property Rights Approaches

The property rights approach (Barzel, 1989; Hart, 1995; Hart & Moore, 1990)

has further extended the transaction cost approach. The focus of the work is on the

distinction between specific and residual rights (discussed earlier). In a world of

incomplete contracts, it is impossible to define specific rights for all contingencies. Firms

will thus spend resources trying to acquire valuable unspecified rights (Barzel, 1989).

14
Ownership of physical assets becomes important because ownership grants

residual rights of income and control (Grossman & Hart, 1986; Hart & Moore, 1990).

When contracts are incomplete, it is the owner that ultimately has the right to decide on

the final disposition of assets. Furthermore, if changing the deployment of an asset

increases the value of the firm then the asset owner is also entitled to any surplus

received. This has prompted Hart (1995) to recommend that the firm with the greatest

potential surplus from an asset should own that asset.

Earlier, we saw that Alchian and Demsetz (1972) claimed that a firm has no right

of fiat (or authority) over its employees. Initially, the property rights approach would

seem to support this position as human capital cannot be owned (i.e. slavery is illegal).

This conclusion has been disputed in the property rights literature. One of the rights of

ownership is the right to exclude others from access to your asset. Many employees are

in their highest valued use only when working for a particular company – their human

capital is relationship specific. Presumably, these employees will be amenable to

directions because the firm has the power to a) appropriate their quasi-rents and b)

remove access to the corporate assets altogether (i.e. fire them).

For example, a commercial pilot is in his or her highest valued use when working

for a commercial airline. During the Australian pilots’ strike of 1989, 85%-90% of

scheduled air services were cancelled for several weeks as pilots pushed for a 30% wage

rise. Buoyed by Federal government support, the commercial airlines simply fired all of

their pilots and hired new pilots from overseas at lower rates than before the strike. Some

15
of the ringleaders of the strike have never flown in Australia again and have suffered a

considerable loss of income and prestige6.

This power inherent in controlling access to physical assets has led property rights

theorists to define the firm in terms of the ownership of physical assets (where ownership

denotes residual rights of control and income). Unlike the nexus of contracts view, this

definition makes the boundaries of the firm relatively easy to determine (Foss, 1997). If

firm X owns, or has residual rights over, asset x then asset x lies within the boundaries of

firm X.

Mahnke (1997) has argued that the power to control access to corporate assets

may also extend to non-physical or intangible assets, such as reputation, information and

brand names. This may explain why top accounting and consulting firms are able to hire

the best students from prestigious colleges at salaries considerably below market rates.

From the students’ perspective, they are enhancing their human capital through exposure

to a leading firm’s reputation, techniques and client base. Thus, recognition of the ability

to appropriate quasi-rents by controlling access to corporate assets may be important in

developing a comprehensive theory of the firm.

STRATEGIC THEORIES OF THE FIRM

As a rule, strategic theories of the firm have been developed by scholars in

strategic management, published in management journals, and have used concepts and

constructs drawn from management and evolutionary economics to support their

arguments.

6
A similar example would be the air traffic controllers strike in the U.S. during the Reagan

administration.

16
Discussions on a strategic theory of the firm are relatively recent, dating from

Rumelt’s (1984) paper “Towards a strategic theory of the firm”. Like the economic

theories surveyed above, there are several core principles that are common to all strategic

theories of the firm. In fact, given the short period of development, these principles are

probably more homogenous among strategic theories than those in economics.

Common Principles

Strategists tend to agree on three broad principles: 1) the resource-based nature of

the firm; 2) the determination of firm boundaries; and 3) bounded rationality

Nature of the Firm

Following Penrose (1959), the firm is seen as a bundle of productive resources

under administrative direction. Resources are defined as inputs into the firm's operations

that are used to produce products or services (Wernerfelt, 1984). Examples of resources

include patents, capital equipment and skilled human resources. A capability (or

competency) is the ability to perform a task or activity that involves complex patterns of

coordination and cooperation between people and other resources (Grant, 1991; Schulze,

1994). Capabilities include research & development, excellent customer service, and high

quality manufacturing.

Strategists are particularly (some would say exclusively) interested in those

resources and capabilities (known collectively as strategic assets) that earn rents, where a

rent is defined as a surplus of revenue over cost (Amit & Schoemaker, 1993). Strategists

seek to create, and protect, rents in order to enhance the value of their firm7. Resources

7
The value of a firm is the sum of its rents discounted at the relevant cost of capital.

17
are known to be more valuable if they are rare, difficult to imitate and non-substitutable

(Barney, 1991). However, in a competitive market, rents can only arise because of luck or

differences in expectations concerning the value of a resource (Barney, 1986). Otherwise,

the supplier of a resource can appropriate its full value.

If the owner of a resource cannot envisage how a firm will use a given resource

then the price of the resource will reflect the next best use (or opportunity cost) that its

owner can find. The strategic value of a given resource is thus likely to depend on the

way a firm combines, coordinates, and deploys that resource with other firm-specific and

firm-addressable8 resources (Sanchez & Heene, 1997). It is in the interest of the firm to

use a new resource in ways that its former owner could not envisage.

Of course, not all resources can be traded. Some resources are developed within

the firm and cannot be bought or sold in factor markets (Dierickx & Cool, 1989).

Examples of these non-tradable assets include reputation, culture, firm-specific know-

how, and values. These assets may be particularly difficult for competitors to imitate

because of time compression diseconomies, asset mass efficiencies, interconnectedness

of asset stocks, asset erosion, and causal ambiguity (Dierickx & Cool, 1989).

Boundaries

According to Penrose (1959), the routinization of the firm’s activities frees up

management resources to explore new opportunities. The indivisibility of certain assets

also creates excess capacity that, although not easily traded (see non-tradable assets

above), can be utilized in new activities. Management’s inability to conceive and control

8
A resource that lies outside the boundaries of the firm but can nevertheless be used by the firm.

18
new activities places limits on the growth of the firm. This ‘cognitive limits to growth’

perspective has found considerable support in the recent strategy literature (Ginsberg,

1994; Prahalad & Bettis, 1986).

Richardson (1972) views the economy as a set of activities each requiring a set of

capabilities (i.e. knowledge, skills, and experience). Similar activities share common

capabilities. Firms can realize gains (through economics of scale, scope and experience)

by expanding into similar activities. Complementary activities lie in the same value chain

but require dissimilar capabilities. The closer the complementarity between stages of

production, the greater the degree of cooperation required between firms. This

cooperation could include any form of joint planning between firms including strategic

alliances, joint ventures or vertical integration.

As rent-seekers, firms are advised to expand only into areas where they have a

competitive advantage. Growth will thus be constrained by the fungibility and

transferability of the firm’s most valuable resources (which are by definition rare and

difficult-to-imitate).

Bounded Rationality

In the neoclassical world of perfect information, differences in expectations

cannot exist (Demsetz, 1988, Demsetz, 1997). Firms are assumed to have the “blueprints”

for all production possibilities (Foss, 1998b). Economic theories of the firm do not move

far beyond their neoclassical roots. The notion that production knowledge may be

difficult to acquire receives little attention in the literature. It is assumed a priori that a

potential gain from exchange exists. Consequently, the theories focus on structuring the

transaction so that the partners to the deal can agree on the division of the expected gains.

19
The assumption that all production possibilities (or gains from exchange) can be

easily discovered is antithetical to strategists. At a given point in time, a firm will never

know whether its particular combination of resources is in the best possible use to

maximize rents. Nor will it know whether its choices reflect the best possible

deployment of resources to meet future contingencies (i.e. to optimize the value of the

firm over its lifetime). Strategic theories problematize the assumption that production

possibilities can be easily discovered.

Why is discovery difficult? Strategists (either implicitly or explicitly) assume that

resource holders are boundedly rational. Managers do not have perfect knowledge of

future states of the world, of alternative actions that may be taken should such states

arise, nor of the payoffs from adopting various alternatives (Newell & Simon, 1972).

Moreover, the way a manager chooses to allocate resources will be a function of that

manager’s past experience, skills, values, biases, and personality. Socio-cognitive

processes, leadership in creating shared visions, imagination, and creativity thus become

important factors in explaining resource allocation decisions (Ginsberg, 1994; Prahalad &

Bettis, 1986).

Accordingly, even if two managers were given identical bundles of resources9,

they would tend to use them in different ways. The result is that, over time, a firm’s stock

of tradable and non-tradable assets will diverge from its competitors, as will its

performance. Managers in competing firms do not face the same set of choices. Rather,

they have different menus with different choices (Teece, Pisano, & Shuen, 1997).

9
Resources are usually assumed to be heterogeneous.

20
For Demsetz (1997), information costs refer to the difference between the real

world and the “perfect” world of neoclassical economics:

This creates a productive role for management where none exists in

neoclassical theory. Imperfect information... makes the judgment of managers

and owners a source of productivity enhancement. The main source of

management's productivity in contemporary theory has been in its response to

agency problems. Shirking, opportunism, and reputation are brought to the

fore. This effort has led to the neglect of information problems that do not

involve agency relationships. These are associated with planning in a world in

which the future is highly uncertain, and they include problems of product

choice, investment and marketing policies, and scope of operations. Neglect

of this class of problems is unfortunate (Demsetz, 1997, p.428).

Strategists are thus uncomfortable with the view that all outcomes are globally

efficient. Global efficiency implies that the future can be discerned, or a superior

production technique discovered, by simply investing in more “information”10.

An alternative is to embrace the assumptions of Austrian and evolutionary

economic theory and assume that the future is, to a greater or lesser degree, uncertain and

unknowable (Hayek, 1945; Nelson & Winter, 1982). Thus, no amount of expenditure on

information gathering will resolve what Knight (1921) calls ‘fundamental uncertainty’.

Firms are only relatively efficient (or inefficient) in reference to other firms. Firms adapt

21
but they do not optimize (or, more correctly, they never know if they have reached an

optimal position).

In the neoclassical approach, inefficient firms do not survive. They are assumed to

fail very rapidly leaving only efficient firms (Friedman, 1951). Diversity in firm

performance can only be explained using ad hoc assumptions such as information costs

or short run adjustment constraints. An evolutionary approach offers a more

parsimonious explanation for the survival of under-performing firms. First, there is

always the chance that a firm will improve its performance by altering its resource

allocations. Liquidating a firm prematurely destroys, or damages, the firm’s stock of non-

tradable assets. Second, the firm may not, in fact, be under-performing. It may be

implementing a strategy with a payoff over an extended time period. In either case, it

may be rational to ‘wait and see’ if performance improves. Consequently, firms strive to

improve performance but survival is also important (Alchian, 1950).

Specific theories

This section briefly discusses several strategic theories of the firm. The goal is to

capture some of the essence of the thinking around these issues. We begin with the

knowledge-based theory of the firm, move on to options-based theory and conclude with

the dynamic transaction costs view.

10
In neoclassical economics, efficient behavior is sometimes synonymous with purposeful

(rational) behavior. This usage reduces “efficiency” to a behavioral postulate with no normative power to

adjudicate outcomes.

22
Knowledge

Knowledge theories of the firm (KTF) form the largest subset of the growing

literature on strategic theories of the firm (Conner, 1991; Conner & Prahalad, 1996;

Grant, 1996; Kogut & Zander, 1992; Liebeskind, 1996). All KTF invariably start from

the premise that knowledge is the most important strategic asset that a firm possesses.

Grant (1996) goes so far as to say that “…all human productivity is knowledge

dependent, and all machines are simply embodiments of knowledge” (p. 112). The

literature, however, makes a strong distinction between explicit knowledge in the public

domain and tacit knowledge.

Tacit knowledge cannot be easily codified and can only be learned through

observation and practice (Kogut & Zander, 1992; Grant, 1996). Riding a bicycle is an oft-

quoted example of tacit knowledge. Tacit knowledge is a valuable resource because it

cannot be directly appropriated and attempts at imitation will be costly in terms of time

(even assuming an instructor can be found). Explicit knowledge, on the other hand, is

extremely easy to transfer and contracts protecting knowledge are difficult to enforce

(Liebeskind, 1996).

Several explanations for the existence of the firm have been offered in the KTF

literature. Liebeskind (1996) argues that the firm exists because it is more efficient at

protecting (explicit) knowledge. For example, employment contracts hinder knowledge

transfer by requiring exclusivity, confidentiality, and restrictions on competitive

behavior. Similarly, the threat of dismissal may also deter attempts to transfer knowledge.

Job design and division of labor within a firm ensure that employees don’t see the ‘whole

23
picture’. Firms can also impose exit costs on employees by deferring compensation in the

form of pension plans, stock options or promotion.

By definition, tacit knowledge resides in individuals but must be integrated to

become useful. Grant (1996) argues that the continuity of association found in a firm

enables the development of common knowledge, a shared language and meaning among

the firm’s specialists. The organization’s rules and routines also assist in facilitating

coordination. Firms are therefore more efficient at integrating knowledge than the

market.

Conner and Prahalad (1996), focus on the advantages that administrative direction

provides over market contracting. They note that a market contract needs to be re-

negotiated if requirements change whereas employees can be more easily directed to new

tasks. As Coase (1937) also noted, this gives the firm flexibility and lowers transaction

costs. Similarly, market contractors often need to be convinced of the merits of a project

before they commit to production. Integrating the activity into the firm removes the need

to educate the supplier or distributor on the merits of the project. Conner and Prahalad

(1996) refer to this as the knowledge- substitution effect.

Dynamic Transaction Costs

The knowledge-substitution effect bears a strong resemblance to the concept of

dynamic transaction costs discussed by Langlois (1991) and Langlois and Robertson

(1995). For these authors:

The boundaries of the firm are determined entirely by the capabilities of the

firm relative to the capability of the market (Langlois & Robertson, 1995,

p.33).

24
Dynamic transaction costs are defined as:

…the costs of persuading, negotiating, coordinating and teaching outside

suppliers…[about your capabilities and strategic architecture]…it is the cost

of not having the capabilities you need when you need them (Langlois &

Robertson, 1995, p.35).

Transferring knowledge to suppliers also runs the risk that the suppliers might

appropriate the gains from innovation (Langlois & Robertson, 1995; Teece, 1986).

Appropriation can occur either in the form of holdup (i.e. higher input prices) or forward

integration. In either case, the firm has an incentive to transcend the market through

integration.

Options

The options-based theory of the firm formalizes Conner & Prahalad’s (1996)

insight that flexibility is valuable to a firm (Barney & Lee, 1998; Foss, 1998b; Sanchez,

1993; Sanchez, 1998). In finance, an option is the right, but not the obligation, to trade a

security at a fixed price (the exercise price) over a given period of time11.

The right is valuable because the market price of the security may rise or fall over

the life of the option contract. The holder of a call (put) option will exercise the option if

the market price rises above (falls below) the exercise price. If the market price moves

contrary to the option holder’s expectations then the loss will only be limited to the

premium (i.e. the initial price of the option contract).

11
The right to buy a security is called a call options, the right to sell a security is known as a put

option.

25
The probability that the market price will differ from the exercise price is, among

other things, a function of the volatility of the underlying security and the length of the

contract. Option pricing will reflect the market’s assessment of the likely gain from these

potential price movements.

As we have argued earlier, the firm is a bundle of resources over which its

owners/managers have residual rights of control. The flexibility to change the allocation

of resources in the firm allows management to design new products, alter the timing of

investment projects, and vary relationships with suppliers and distributors (Phelan, 1997;

Sanchez, 1993). Options theory makes explicit the link between flexibility and value.

Firms provide their owners more flexibility and are thus more valuable (i.e. they are more

effective than markets at providing strategic options).

Options-based theory is also vocal on the issue of determining the boundaries of

the firm:

Firms should internalize only a few inputs that 1) are exceptionally difficult to

obtain through markets and 2) are capable of generating superior options values

for the firm (Foss, 1998, p.7).

This statement hints at the fact that not all resources are capable of generating

options. The decision to acquire a resource must ultimately depend on a) its premium (or

acquisition price), b) its current value to the firm, and c) its ability to be recombined with

other resources to create value – the expected value of future gains represents the

resource’s option value. A commitment to learning about the ways in which resources

may be combined increases the value of options (Barney & Lee, 1998). However, unless

a difference of opinion exists between the seller and acquirer of the resource, in a

26
competitive market the acquisition price will tend to reflect the current and future value

of the asset to the acquirer.

Criticisms of Strategic Theories

Williamson ((1991), p.76) has argued that “…economizing is more fundamental

than strategizing”. However, a close reading of Williamson reveals that he views strategy

as synonymous with market power and economizing as efficiency. Williamson identifies

the resource-based and dynamic capabilities views as the leading efficiency approaches

to business strategy but criticizes their lack of structure and focus. While Williamson

fiercely defends the vital role of transaction cost economics in explaining governance

choices he leaves the door open for resource-based explanations.

Nicolai Foss (1996a; 1996b; 1997) has made some thoughtful criticisms of

strategic approaches to the theory of the firm. According to Foss (1997), the resource-

based theory of the firm cannot easily explain:

• The existence of the firm;

• Why firms are defined by their ownership of [physical] assets;

• When capabilities are important for economic organization and when they are not;

and

• Future firm boundaries or causes of success.

Most importantly, he argues that “co-specialization [carries] no implications for

ownership” (Foss, 1996a, p. 473).

agents…could simply meet under the same factory roof, own their own pieces

of capital equipment or rent it to each other, and develop value-

enhancing…principles among themselves. (Foss, 1996a, p.473)

27
We agree that strategists have often not discerned the need to justify the existence of the

firm in these terms. The next section addresses Foss’s central concerns.

ARRIVING AT A STRATEGIC THEORY OF THE FIRM

The Existence of the Firm

As Demsetz (1995, 1997) has noted, the alternative to the firm is not the market

but the household. Firms exist because they are able to assemble valued goods and

services more efficiently than households can. The source of this efficiency is the

productivity enhancing effects of specialization; comparative advantage; division of

labor; and associated economies of scale, scope and experience.

However, Demsetz’s use of the word ‘firm’ in this context is somewhat unusual.

In everyday speech a ‘firm’ refers to a corporation or cooperative, comprised of a number

of people and other assets, which may have legal status as a company or partnership.

Demsetz’s ‘firm’ could be a sole trader, a specialist who produces for the consumption of

others beyond the needs of his or her own household. The modern theory of the firm is

really seeking to explain the existence of the corporation (in the above sense).

Coordination

As we have already discussed, advanced economies are characterized by a high

degree of specialization. The creation of any consumer good requires the involvement

and coordination of countless specialists each with their own tacit knowledge domain. On

this score alone, the firm can transcend the market by reducing the costs of coordination

by, for example, lowering search costs for consumers and producers (Coase, 1937;

Barzel, 1989) or by providing a common language and set of routines (Grant, 1996).

28
Moreover, coordination is difficult. Resources cannot be assumed to be in their

value-maximizing use at any given point in time. The continuous stream of new

developments and innovations emerging into the public domain further complicates the

problem of finding appropriate resource combinations (Hayek, 1945; Nelson & Winter,

1982; Schumpeter, 1934; Teece, 1986; Witt, 1998). The problems of coordination ensure

that opportunities for gain will always exist.

Behavioral Assumptions

We assume that firms are not formed with the intention of creating social welfare

(or public efficiency). Specialists trade for their own gain or profit (private efficiency).

So, too, do corporations. Firms are profit-seeking entities. Thus, it is reasonable to

assume that all parties to a transaction will act to maximize private gain.

Unlike other strategists (Kogut & Zander, 1992; Conner & Prahalad, 1996) we do

not believe that it is necessary to reject the assumption of opportunism to develop a

strategic theory of the firm. This is not to say that altruism does not occur in corporations.

Rather, we believe that ‘planning for the worst while hoping for the best’ is the path of

least regret. Also, as Axelrod (1984) has demonstrated, it may be in one’s self-interest to

act cooperatively. Cooperation is not beyond our definition of self-interest (Langlois &

Robertson, 1995).

We also assume that managers possess bounded rationality. However, our

conception of bounded rationality goes beyond the lack of ability to detect shirking or to

write complete contracts. In a strategic theory of the firm, bounded rationality is

extended to include differences in expectations among economic agents concerning the

value of production possibilities. These differences in expectation arise because the

29
coordination of production is a highly dynamic and complex task. An entrepreneur is

someone who is able to perceive that a gain can be made by recombining resources in a

novel way and seeks to profit from that perception (Schumpeter, 1931).

The Special Status of the Corporation

The property rights of a corporation are protected by common law, social

convention and the corporation’s own actions (Barzel, 1989). They include the rights to:

• Receive any surplus income generated from its assets;

• Direct, control or transfer non-human assets;

• Alienate (or sell) physical assets;

• Lawfully direct the work of employees; and

• Appropriate any proceeds from the employment relationship.

Discussion

Let us start with an entrepreneur and an existing stock of rare and difficult-to-

imitate resources (land, labor and capital) that are held by other agents in the economy.

Each agent possesses bounded rationality so there is no reason to presume that the

resources are deployed in their most efficient use in some global sense. At some stage, let

us assume that the entrepreneur “discovers” some undervalued resource or resource

combination (or asset co-specialization) that was hitherto unperceived by the other agents

in the economy. For the purposes of this analysis it does not matter how the insight arises

– luck, creativity, imagination, superior information – are all possible explanations.

To make the example more concrete, assume that the resources in their new

combination are estimated to yield a capitalized present value of $100 million. The

marginal contributions from each resource being: land ($20m), labor ($40m), and capital

30
($40m). The resources in their current use are earning a total of $50 million – land

($10m), labor ($20m) and capital ($20m). [All values are prospective estimates.]

Once a profit opportunity has been discovered, the question then arises as to

which organizational arrangement is best suited to its realization. Is the entrepreneur

indifferent to hiring the inputs through market contracts or forming a firm (which would

entail purchasing at least some of the physical assets and placing at least some of the

labor on employment contracts)?

The first point to note is that any contract will be incomplete due to bounded

rationality. In effect, this means that any input owner under contract (including labor)

will have the opportunity to periodically re-negotiate the terms of their contract. Thus,

while the landlord might initially rent the land at a capitalized value slightly above $10m,

the rent is likely to subsequently rise towards $20m (and beyond).

The transaction cost story (Williamson, 1985) is that relationship specific assets

(i.e. those that are generating quasi-rents or returns above their next best use) are always

subject to such holdup or ex post appropriation12. The entrepreneur is strongly advised to

buy the assets outright to protect the gain. The property rights implicit in ownership

enable the entrepreneur to alienate the residual income between the asset’s new use and

its sale price.

How much will the entrepreneur actually pay for the land? This is entirely

negotiable and will lie somewhere between $10m (its value in its current use) and $60m

12
Similarly, the dynamic transaction cost story (Langlois & Robertson, 1995) is that the

entrepreneur might not be able to convince the input holders of the value of the new idea and thus cannot

convince them to shift their resources to a new use.

31
(assuming the entrepreneur is able to obtain the other inputs at their current use value).

However, given that the landlord is ignorant of the entrepreneur’s future plans, the price

could reasonably be expected to lie at the lower end of the range (although we know that

acquiring firms often pay significant premiums to acquired firms).

Once the entrepreneur purchases the specialized land and capital, he or she also

acquires two additional items of value. The first is a strategic option to recombine the

assets in new ways. As we described earlier, even if the input owners appropriate the full

$100m value of the initial plan, the deal would still be valuable because of the underlying

flexibility to redirect resources (itself a function of the property rights inherent in

ownership). The firm will also start to build non-tradable assets like reputation, goodwill,

and a corporate culture. While these assets cannot be acquired on the market they are,

nevertheless, valuable (Dierickx & Cool, 1989).

Both of these facts complement, rather than supplant, transaction cost logic (Barney &

Lee, 1998; Foss & Foss, 1998). The value of the strategic options and non-tradable assets

simply increases the quasi-rent that may potentially be appropriated and further biases the

entrepreneur towards creating a firm to protect the (increasingly) co-specialized

resources.

From the entrepreneur’s viewpoint, the weak link in the arrangement is labor. At

some stage, labor contracts (whether market-based or employment-based) will need to be

re-negotiated. In our previous example, wages are likely to commence at a capitalized

value of $20m. If land and capital were acquired at their opportunity cost of $10m and

$20m respectively then labor has the potential to appropriate the remaining $70m in

future negotiations (and any gains from strategic options and non-tradable assets that may

32
also emerge). Is the firm a better vehicle for protecting the entrepreneur’s gains than the

market?

The answer is no. Both market and employment contracts need to be re-

negotiated. Instead, it is the ownership of physical assets that gives the firm bargaining

power in both cases. Ownership carries with it the right to restrict or deny access to a

resource (Hart, 1990). If labor becomes too strident (as in the Australian airline example),

the owners can exclude their labor force and train a new group. Labor with firm-specific

skills (often built over a lifetime) is more vulnerable to holdup in these circumstances.

The ability to defer compensation also suppresses bargaining power (Liebeskind, 1996).

However, even if labor were to appropriate all gains from the relationship, there would

still be a period of adjustment between the old and new rates from which an entrepreneur

could profit (Rumelt, 1984). Finally, as with the example of professional firms, exposure

to the specialized resources of a reputable firm early in one’s career can enhance lifetime

earnings (by increasing one’s human capital). This can lead employees into a “rat-race”

where current wages are lowered for a winner-take-all prize (Rajan & Zingales, 1998).

There is also another set of reasons the firm may prefer employment contracts. First, as

Coase (1937) first noted, employment contracts provide the flexibility to direct staff into

new assignments. Firms also have the legal right to appropriate inventions and other

assets arising from employment (a residual right they don’t have with market

contracting). In both cases, the option value (and hence quasi-rent) of the firm is

increased. Second, as Grant (1996) points out, an on-going association between

employees creates shared knowledge and a common language, both non-tradable assets

that increase option value.

33
Implications

Two views on the nature of transaction costs have emerged from our discussion.

The first view, attributable to Coase (1937), emphasizes the ex ante costs (in terms of

time, money, and effort) of identifying and negotiating for the exchange of valued inputs

using the price system. Strategists have identified strongly with this theme, making

several contributions concerning the benefits of the firm in coordinating knowledge

(Grant, 1996) and the role of resources in determining boundaries (Penrose, 1959).

The second view of transaction costs, attributable to Williamson (1975; 1985),

emphasizes the ex post costs of holdup when suppliers and distributors appropriate the

gains from asset specificity. Awareness of these ex post costs influences ex ante behavior.

The firm, with its common law property rights, provides a convenient mechanism for

avoiding these costs (or alternatively protecting any gains from specialization). The key

message is that the value realized from entrepreneurship, organizational learning, saving

on ex ante transaction costs, or strategic options is inconsequential if the public gain can

not be translated into a private gain.

The antagonism between the strategic and economic theories of the firm

(Williamson, 1991; Ghoshal & Moran, 1994; Williamson, 1994; Kogut & Zander, 1996)

is thus difficult to explain. Views of the firm that focus on value creation are clearly

complementary to Williamson’s transaction cost view. Perhaps it is because Williamson

has used the term ‘transaction cost’ when talking about ‘appropriability’ that this

misunderstanding has occurred since strategists have long appreciated the link between

shareholder value and appropriability (Porter, 1980; Teece, 1982).

34
However, we disagree with the view that opportunism is either necessary of

sufficient to explain the existence of the firm (Foss, 1996a,1996b). Coase’s ex ante

transaction costs arise solely as a consequence of bounded rationality. There is no holdup

in Coase’s world, simply a problem of finding information that will enable resources to

be allocated to their best use. Thus, whenever the costs of managed coordination are

lower than the costs of price coordination, firms will subsume markets (Demsetz, 1995).

The assumption of opportunism is needed to explain the overwhelming

prevalence of capital-managed firms (KMFs) relative to labor-managed firms (LMFs).

Dow (1993) argues that capital providers would never lease their resources to LMFs

because of their inability to protect fixed assets (i.e. highly specific assets) from

appropriation. LMFs only arise when capital plays a small part in value creation (e.g. in

professional firms). He goes on to argue that the firm should be viewed as a nexus of

[negotiation] strategies rather than a nexus of contracts as the division of income between

labor and capital is highly negotiable. We would add that negotiating to acquire physical

assets also plays a key role in protecting entrepreneurial value.

The threat of appropriation of rents by buyers and suppliers has always played a

large role in the theories of Porter (1980) and Teece (1986). Curiously, the resource-

based literature has always been more concerned with imitation of key resources by

competitors than appropriation of quasi-rents by resource owners. However, increasing a

firm’s value depends as much on obtaining favorable terms from resource providers as it

does on protecting resources from imitation by competitors. Opportunism is not a

necessary condition for the existence of the firm but it would be incorrect to suggest that

it plays no role at all.

35
The Boundaries of the Firm

Strategists have generally had more success in explaining the boundaries of the

firm than they have had in explaining its existence. It was Coase (1937) who first posited

that firms exist because there are costs to using the price system. Similarly, the reason

that all production is not organized in one large firm is because the cost of planned

production will, at the margin, exceed the cost of using the price system.

For Penrose (1959), the number of resources under the firm’s control contributed

to the development of new resources and new opportunities for gain. This was offset by

the inability of management to envision new ways of combining the increasing number of

assets under their control (Coase, 1937; Prahalad & Bettis, 1986). For Coase (1937):

…the cost of losses through mistakes will increase with an increase in the

spatial distribution of transactions organized, in the dissimilarity of

transactions, and in the probability of changes in the relevant prices (25).

Strategists are generally well-informed about the cognitive, social and behavioral

factors that hinder resource allocation in large firms (Bower, 1986; Hoskisson & Hitt,

1994). A discussion of these factors is beyond the scope of this paper but once a limit to

the size (or resources) of a firm has been accepted, the question naturally arises about

which resources should be included within the firm.

The answer to the above question is that the firm should acquire the bundle of

resources that are expected to produce the most value for the firm. Resource-based

theorists (Amit & Schoemaker, 1993; Barney, 1991; Peteraf, 1993) have catalogued

several characteristics of valuable assets including:

• scarcity

36
• inimitability,

• inappropriability,

• durability, and

• flexibility.

Maximizing value entails balancing the current and future (option) value of the

firm. Resources that can be leveraged into new applications or used to develop new

resources are clearly more valuable from an options-based perspective (Sanchez, 1993).

CONCLUSION

According to Kirsten Foss (1998a), economists have tended to work from the

assumption that potential gains from exchange are known to exist and agents simply need

an incentive to realize them (typically an assurance that they will receive some or all of

the potential gains). Strategic management enriches this perspective by pointing out that

opportunities for gain are not readily known and value must be discovered.

Firms (as corporations) exist because they are better at protecting these gains after

they are discovered. Firms are also incubators (or engines) for future value creation. The

property rights associated with ownership play an essential role in creating these benefits

of incorporation. The firm is thus more than a nexus of contracts. It is also more than just

a superior way of coordinating knowledge and resources among cooperative agents.

37
REFERENCES

Alchian, A. A. 1950. Uncertainty, evolution and economic theory. Journal of Political

Economy, 58: 211-221.

Alchian, A. A., & Demsetz, H. 1972. Production, information costs, and economic

organization. American Economic Review, 62: 772-795.

Amit, R., & Schoemaker, P. J. H. 1993. Strategic assets and organizational rents.

Strategic Management Journal, 14: 33-46.

Axelrod, R. 1984. The Evolution of Cooperation. New York: Basic Books.

Barney, J. 1991. Firm resources and sustained competitive advantage. Journal of

Management, 17: 99-120.

Barney, J. B. 1986. Strategic factor markets, expectations, luck and business strategy.

Management Science, 32: 1231-1241.

Barney, J. B. 1996. The resource-based theory of the firm. Organization Science, 7: 469.

Barney, J. B., & Lee, W. 1998. Governance under uncertainty: Transaction costs, real

options, learning, and property rights. Paper presented at the Annual Meeting of the

Academy of Management, San Diego.

Barzel, Y. 1989. Economic Analysis of Property Rights. Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press.

Bower, J. L. 1986. Managing the Resource Allocation Process: A Study of Corporate

Planning and Investment. (Rev. ed.). Boston: Harvard Business School Press.

Cheung, S. N. S. 1969. Transaction costs, risk aversion, and the choice of contractual

arrangements. Journal of Law &Economics, 12: 23-42.

38
Cheung, S. N. S. 1983. The contractual nature of the firm. Journal of Law & Economics,

26: 1-21.

Coase, R. 1937. The nature of the firm. Economica, 4: 386-405.

Conner, K. R. 1991. A historical comparison of resource-based theory and five schools of

thought within industrial organization economics: Do we have a new theory of the

firm? Journal of Management, 17: 121-154.

Conner, K. R., & Prahalad, C. K. 1996. A resource-based theory of the firm: Knowledge

versus opportunism. Organization Science, 7: 477-501.

Demsetz, H. 1988. The theory of the firm revisited. Journal of Law, Economics, and

Organization, 4: 141-162.

Demsetz, H. 1995. The Economics of the Business Firm: Seven Critical Commentaries.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Demsetz, H. 1997. The firm in economic theory: A quiet revolution. American Economic

Review, 87: 426-429.

Dierickx, I., & Cool, K. 1989. Asset stock accumulation and sustainability of competitive

advantage. Management Science, 35: 1504-1511.

Dow, G. K. 1993. Why capital hires labor: A bargaining perspective. American

Economic Review, 83: 118-133.

Foss, K. 1998a. Technological interdependencies, specialization and coordination: A

property rights perspective on the nature of the firm (Working Paper 98-10).

Copenhagen: Danish Research Unit for Industrial Dynamics.

39
Foss, K., & Foss, N. J. 1998. The Knowledge-Based Approach: An Organizational

Economics Perspective (Working Paper WP98-5). Copenhagen Business School:

Department of Industrial Economics and Strategy.

Foss, N. J. 1996a. Knowledge-based approaches to the theory of the firm: Some critical

comments. Organization Science, 7: 470-476.

Foss, N. J. 1996b. More critical comments on knowledge-based theories of the firm.

Organization Science, 7: 519-523.

Foss, N. J. 1997. The resource-based perspective: An assessment and diagnosis of

problems (Working Paper 97-1). Copenhagen Business School: DRUID.

Foss, N. J. 1998b. Real options and the theory of the firm. In R. Sanchez (Ed.), Options

theory in strategic management London: Sage.

Foss, N. J., & Knudsen, C. (Eds.). 1996. Towards a Competence Theory of the Firm.

London: Routledge.

Ginsberg, A. 1994. Minding the competition: From mapping to mastery. Strategic

Management Journal, 15: 153-174.

Grant, R. M. 1991. Contemporary Strategy Analysis. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell.

Grant, R. M. 1996. Toward a knowledge-based theory of the firm. Strategic Management

Journal, 17: 109-122.

Grossman, S. J., & Hart, O. D. 1986. The costs and benefits of ownership: A theory of

vertical and lateral integration. Journal of Political Economy, 94: 691-719.

Hart, O. D. 1995. Firms, Contracts, and Financial Structure. Oxford: Oxford University

Press.

40
Hart, O. D., & Moore, J. 1990. Property rights and the nature of the firm. Journal of

Political Economy, 98: 1119-1158.

Hayek, F. A. 1945. The use of knowledge in society. American Economic Review, 35:

519-530.

Hoskisson, R. E., & Hitt, M. A. 1994. Downscoping: How to Tame the Diversified Firm.

New York: Oxford University Press.

Klein, B., Crawford, R. G., & Alchian, A. 1978. Vertical integration, appropriable rents

and the competitive contracting process. Journal of Law & Economics, 21: 297-326.

Knight, F. 1921. Risk, Uncertainty and Profit. London: London School of Economics.

Kogut, B., & Zander, U. 1992. Knowledge of the firm, combinative capabilities, and the

replication of technology. Organization Science, 3: 383-397.

Langlois, R. N. 1991. Transaction cost economics in real time. Industrial and Corporate

Change, 1: 99-127.

Langlois, R. N. 1992. The capabilities of industrial capitalism. Critical Review, 5: 513-

530.

Langlois, R. N., & Robertson, P. L. 1995. Firms, Markets and Economic Change: A

Dynamic Theory of Business Institutions. London: Routledge.

Liebeskind, J. P. 1996. Knowledge, strategy, and the theory of the firm. Strategic

Management Journal, 17: 93-107.

Mahnke, V. 1997. Can contractual theories of the firm explain the existence of

knowledge-intensive firms (Working Paper ??). Copenhagen: Copenhagen Business

School.

41
Masten, S. E. 1988. A legal basis for the firm. Journal of Law, Economics, and

Organization, 4: 181-198.

Nelson, R. R., & Winter, S. G. 1982. An Evolutionary Theory of Economic Change.

Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

Penrose, E. 1959. The Theory of the Growth of the Firm. London: Basil Blackwell.

Peteraf, M. A. 1993. The cornerstones of competitive advantage: A resource-based view.

Strategic Management Journal, 14: 179-191.

Phelan, S. E. 1997. Exposing the illusion of confidence in financial analysis.

Management Decision, 35: 163-168.

Porter, M. 1980. Competitive Strategy. New York: Free Press.

Prahalad, C. K., & Bettis, R. A. 1986. The dominant logic: The new linkage between firm

diversity and performance. Strategic Managment Journal, 7: 485-501.

Rajan, R. G., & Zingales, L. 1998. Power in a theory of the firm. Quarterly Journal of

Economics, 113: 387-432.

Richardson, G. B. 1972. The organization of industry. Economic Journal, 82: 883-896.

Rumelt, R. P. 1984. Towards a strategic theory of the firm. In R. B. Lamb (Ed.),

Competitive Strategic Management (: 556-570. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

Sanchez, R. 1993. Strategic flexibility, firm organisation, and managerial work in

dynamic markets. Advances in Strategic Management, 9: 251-291.

Sanchez, R. 1998. Uncertainty, flexibility, and economic organization: Foundations for

an options theory of the firm. Paper presented at the DRUID Summer Conference,

Copenhagen Business School.

42
Sanchez, R., & Heene, A. 1997. Reinventing strategic management: New theory and

practice for competence-based competition. European Management Journal, 15: 303-

317.

Schulze, W. S. 1994. The two schools of thought in resource-based theory: Definitions

and implications for research. Advances in Strategic Management, 10A: 127-151.

Schumpeter, J. A. 1934. The Theory of Economic Development (Redvers Opie, Trans.).

(first published 1911 ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Seth, A., & Thomas, H. 1994. Theories of the firm: Implications for strategy research.

Journal of Management Studies, 31: 165-191.

Teece, D. 1986. Profiting from technological innovation. Research Policy, 15: 285-305.

Teece, D. J., Pisano, G., & Shuen, A. 1997. Dynamic capabilities and strategic

management. Strategic Management Journal, 18: 509-533.

Wernerfelt, B. 1984. A resource-based view of the firm. Strategic Management Journal,

5: 171-180.

Williamson, O. E. 1975. Markets and Hierarchies. New York: Free Press.

Williamson, O. E. 1985. The Economic Institutions of Capitalism. New York: Free Press.

Williamson, O. E. 1991. Strategizing, economizing, and economic organization. Strategic

Management Journal, 12: 75-94.

Witt, U. 1998. Imagination and leadership - The neglected dimension of an evolutionary

theory of the firm. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 35: 161-177.

43

You might also like