SHEPSLE, Keneth - Analyzing Politics - Rationality, Behavior and Institutions PDF
SHEPSLE, Keneth - Analyzing Politics - Rationality, Behavior and Institutions PDF
SHEPSLE, Keneth - Analyzing Politics - Rationality, Behavior and Institutions PDF
"The ideal place for students to cut their teeth on one of the
fields at the heart of modern political science."
- Michael Laver, New York University
The New Institutionalism in
American Politics Series
Also available
•
Analyzing Politics
Rationality, Beh avior, and Institution s
S ECOND ED ITION
Kenneth A. Shepsle
HARVARD UN IVERSITY
'
IMt
W · W • Norton & Company
New York • London
In memory of my parents,
Philip a nd Edythe Shepsle
W. W. Norton & Company, Inc., 500 Fifth Avenue, New York, N.Y. 10110
www.wwnorton.com
W. W. Norton & Company Ltd., Castle House,
75176 Wells Street, London WIT 3Q1'
3 4 5 6 7 8 9 0
Contents
.
Acknowledgments lX
Part I
INTRODUCTION
Part II
GROUP CHOICE
vu
Vlll Contents
Part III
COOPERATION, COLLECTIVE ACTION,
AND PUBLIC GOODS
8 Cooperation 231
9 Collective Action 262
10 P ublic Goods, Externalities, and the Commons 306
Part IV
INSTITUTIONS
Index 535
Acknowledgments for the
Seeond Edition
lX
x Acknowledgments for the Second Edition
A S CIENCE OF P OLITICS?
1 Why else was Profiles in Courage, John F. Kennedy's book about politicians
who sacrificed their own personal well-being for a greater good, so short?
3
4 Analyzing Politics
2 Thick descript ion and political history writing, it should be added , were not
unique to the study of America.n politics of the t ime; they were the primary
methods of political analysis of politics in nearly every country in the world.
3 This is true of quantitative data as well as of qualitative facts. A detailed
Let's pause now and see where we are heading. The main pur-
pose of this book is not to expose students to specific details
about political life-details you undoubtedly study in other
courses in history, political science, and sociology- but rather
to introduce you to some theoretical tools you will find useful
in making sense of these details. We will be intent especially
on becoming acquainted with elementary models. These are
stylizations meant to approximate in very crude fashion some
real situation. Models are purposely stripped-down versions of
the real thing. Events in the real world are complex bundles of
characteristics, often far too complicated to understand di-
rectly. We depend on a stylized model to provide us with in-
sights and guidance that will shape our analysis of these
events. 4
In the next chapter, for example, we construct a simple
model of human choice. It contains no more than a shadow of
any real flesh-and-blood human being. Instead, in an utterly
simple way, it considers a person exclusively in terms of the
things he or she wants and the things he or she believes. We
want to get a feel for how a person makes choices when con-
fronted with alternatives. Since political behavior is often
about making choices, our model will provide us with hunches
and intuitions about how a generic or representative individ-
ual confronts these circumstances in the abstract.
In Chapters 3 and 4, to take another example, we expand
our focus from the individual to a group of individuals. Al-
though politics is often about making choices, only in: the
world of Robinson Crusoe do individuals make choices entirely
in isolation from others, and that is hardly a very political sit-
4 I have described here how I use the term model in this book. A model of
something is (or should be) recognizable as a highly stylized simplification of
the real thing. A sphere to represent a planet or th e nucleus of an atom is a
good example.
8 Analyzing Politics
& Model a nd theory are terms used in various ways depending upon which
philosopher of science you wish to consult. Since there is no unifoi·mity of
usage, I can do no more than s tate clearly my own practice, in no sense
claiming superiority or seeking converts.
10 A nalyzing Politics
P OLITICS
Now that you know where I'm heading, it's time to get on. My
purpose in writing this book is to provide some tools to enable
you to conduct your own analysis of the political events t hat
affect your life. I believe that an understanding and applica-
tion of the concepts contained in this book will help you to pre-
dict a nd explain political events. My job is to present the
concepts clearly and to communicate how they can be a pplied
13
14 Analyzing Politics
what I want, I would not do what she is doing (and she ought
to want what I want). In either case, you are claiming that
what your friend is doing is crazy. Crazy it may well be, but I
shall reserve irrationality for something quite specific.
The term rationality as I shall use it does not mean bril-
liant or all-knowing. The inen and women whose behavior we
wish to understand are not gods, so we certainly do not want
to characterize any deviation from omniscient, godlike behav-
ior as irrational (for then nearly all behavior would fall in this
category). The people we model are neither all-knowing nor
worldly wise; they are ordinary folks. As such they have wants
and beliefs, both of which affect their behavior.
PRELIMINARIES
p. 5.
---------------------
16 Analyzing Politics
5 For r eaders interested in pursuing this theme further, see Geoffrey Brenna n
and Michael Gillespie, eds., "Special Issue: Homo Economicus and Homo
Politicus," Public Choice 137 (2008): 429-524.
18 Analyzing Politics
MOTIVATION
DISPLAY 2.1
Actor E ndowment Objective
consumers budget contentment
producers inputs profits
workers time purchasing power/leisure
investors wealt h long-run return
CASE 2.1
CLAIRE McCASKILL'S E LECTORAL OPTIONS
q Finally, the weak preference relation is trans itive ii x R,y and y R1z imply
x R,z.
26 Analyzing Politics
ity. Suppose we take the population of males and draw two at random. It is
entirely possible, indeed highly probable, that neither one is the father of
the other; thus, not all pairs of alternatives are comparable according to
this relation. On th.e other hand, even if, for three selected males, the first
is the father of the second and the second is the father of the third, it is ob-
vious to any five -year-old that the first is not the father of the third, but
rather is the grandfather. That eliminates transitivity.
Rationality: The Model of Choice 27
T HE MAxlMIZATION P ARADIGM
15
It is the relative numerical values, not their absolute values, that convey
this kind of information. Consequently, it is typical to "normalize" the util-
ity numbers, setting your most·preferred alternative to a utility value of
one, your least· preferred to a value of zero, and intermediate alternatives at
utility levels between zero and one. It would have done just as well to set
most-preferred and least-preferred alternatives at 100 and 0, respectively,
or 1000 and - 1000, respectively. The normalization values are arbitrary. We
report on all this only for the rare reader who wishes to delve more deeply.
A standard, accessible reference for further details is Howard Raiffa, Deci-
sion Analysis (Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1968). Readers will not
need very much detail to digest the materials in the remainder of our book,
so breathe easy!
Rationality: The Model of Choice 33
16 There are many theories of decision under uncertainty that cover the cir·
cumstanccs in whlch choosers cannot assign probabilities of outcomes to
alternative actions. We do not review them here. Still one of the best pre·
sentations of this material is to be found in R. Duncan Luce and Howard
Raiffa, Games and Decisior1s (New York: Wiley, 1957), Chapter 13.
34 Analyzing Politics
CONCLUSION
*6. Imagine that you are confronted with two pairs of lotteries
over the following three outcomes: x = $2.5 million, y = $.5 mil-
lion, and z ~ $0. The first pair pits P 1 against P 2 , where P 1 =
(p 1(x),p 1(y),p 1 (2)) .. (0, l, O) (i.e., you are certain to win
$500,000) and P 2 = (p 2 (x),p 2 (y),p 2 (z)) = (.10, .89, .01). The sec-
ond pair is a choice between P3 = (p3(x),p 3(y),p3(z)) = (O, .11,
.89) and P4 = (pix),p 4 (y),piz)) = (.10, 0, .90). Empirically, most
individuals express a strict preference for P 1 to P 2 , and P 4 to
P 3 . Is this behavior consistent with the theory of expected
utility? In order to solve this problem, rephrase each of the
expressed opinions in terms of expected utility (e.g., EU(Pa) =
. llu(x) + .89u(z)) and then use basic operations on the re-
sulting inequalities to see if a contradiction emerges. No
knowledge of t!he actual utility function is necessary to solve
this problem.
Part II
GROUP CHOICE
3
Getting Started with
Group Choice Analysis
AWARM-UP EXERCISE
Andrew, Bonnie, and Chuck are friends who have decided to
cut class on a pleasant spring afternoon in Boston. Andrew, an
intellectual snob, suggests going to see a fabulous collection of
Impressionist paintings at the M useum of F ine Arts. Bonnie,
a bit more political, wants to go down to the Boston Common
to attend a rally to raise funds and consciousness in support of
preserving Walden P ond, which is threatened by commercial
development. Chuck, a jock, thinks an afternoon at Fenway
P ark watching t he Red Sox would be just fine. Display 3.1
supplies each group member's rank order of the alternatives.
In terms of the notation in Chapter 2, Andrew's preference or-
dering is MFA P_4 WP PA RS. Similar expressions may be writ-
ten down for Bonnie and Chuck. Each member of the group,
{A, B , C}, has preferences over the alternatives, {MFA , WP,
RS}, satisfying completeness a nd tr ansitivity-properties 1
a nd 2 of Chapter 2.
It becomes e vident after the briefest of times that this
group of friends does not have an obvious course of action. It
suffers from a common group affli ction, an affliction with no
known cure short of authoritarian measures-preference
41
42 Analyzing Politics
DISPLAY 3.1
A B c
MFA WP RS
WP RS WP
RS MFA MFA
D ISPLAY 3.2
'
We will explore strategic behavior more systematically
in Chapter 6, but let's briefly and casually examine the
possibilities of strategic behavior in this example. What we
want to determine is whether any of the friends has an incen-
tive to misrepresent his or her preferences by voting strategi-
cally. A person might consider doing this if he or she could
produce a more preferred final outcome. In our example this
is a very real prospect because each outcome in the round-
robin was decided by a single vote. Thus, there are two things
to determine-feasibility and desirability: (1) Can someone
shift the outcome by shifting his or her vote? and (2) Given
the possibility, would such a person want to shift the out-
come?
It is clear that any one in the majority in each pairing
above could, by misrepresenting preferences, change the out-
come in that pairing. This answers the first question about
feasibility. As to desirability, one thing is clear: Bonnie has ab-
solutely no incentive to change her vote in any pairing since
she is the great beneficiary of sincere voting by members of
the group-her first preference wins the round-robin. Poor An-
drew is pivotal only in the comparison between Walden Pond
and Red Sox and, if he were to change his vote to favor RS,
then he would make the latter the overall winner of the round-
robin. But the latter is the worst thing for him, so he certainly
has no incentive to switch votes. This leaves Chuck as the
only one with a possible motive to behave strategically. It is
clear that he could change the result of the pairing between
MFA and RS, but this would not change the overall outcome
so there is not much point to his doing that. 2 However, what if
he voted against WP (his second preference) and for MFA (his
last preference) in the first pairing in Display 3.2? Then the
2 He could simultaneously change his votes in each of the first two ballots, in
which case MFA wo1Uld be the round-robin winner. But this is Chuck's least-
preferred outcome, so he hardly has an incentive to behave strategically in
this fashion.
Getting Started with Group Choice Analysis 45
A R EVISED E XAMPLE
This will not be the last time you hear me say, "Institutions
matter." In this case I want to claim that the institutional pro-
cedure for conducting a vote to resolve a problem of group
choice dramatically affects that group choice. 1b show this, I
alter our "warm-up exercise" slightly. Suppose that Andrew,
Bonnie, and Chuck have the same preferences with which
they were endowed in Display 3.1. But now let us suppose
that, before any votes are taken, there is an intervening stage
of debate a nd deliberation (otherwise known as arguing).
While debate and deliberation may often seem like window
dressing, it is entirely possible that, from time to time at least,
some persuasion, reconsideration, conceivably even coercion,
takes place that r esults in someone changing preferences.
Thus, while our friends are deliberating, suppose Chuck
becomes convinced that a trip to the museum might be brief
and he might, at the very least, catch the last few innings of
Getting Started with Group Choice Analysis 47
D ISPLAY 3.3
A B c
MFA WP RS
WP RS MFA
RS MFA WP
the Red Sox game on the tube afterward. The Walden Pond
rally, on the other hand, would go on all afternoon. As a conse·
quence, suppose he elevates MFA in his preference ordering
(and lowers WP). Thus, before the voting but after delibera·
tion, the preferences of the group members now are as given
in Display 3.3. A round-robin majority rule tournament does
not produce a winner in this new situation (as shown in Dis-
play 3.4). Each alternative is beaten by one of the other alter-
natives: MFA loses to RS, which loses to WP, which loses to
MFA. If we were to write the group majority preference rela-
tion as Pc, then we would have RS Pc MFA Pc WP Pc RS.
But this doesn't look like a preference ordering at all. Indeed,
it is not! 4 Whereas the individuals of the group possessed
coherent-that is, transitive-preferences, the group does not.
The group preference relation is intransitive or, to put it more
colorfully, the group's preferences cycle, with a different ma-
jority coalition supporting the winner in each pairwise com-
panson.
Since round-robin voting doesn't solve our group's problem
in this circumstance, we need to think about other institu-
tional schemes. One arrange1nent that is found in official in-
stitutions is called the agenda procedure. 5 For a given set of
alternatives, some individual (or subcommittee)-called the
agenda setter-is charged with assembling an order of voting
• Notice that RS is simultaneously (!) at the top and bottom of this list-
something not characteristic of an ordering.
6 This procedure is also used in many sports competitions, under the rubric of
single-elimination tournament.
48 Analyzing Politics
DISPLAY 8.4
DISPLAY 3.5
Agenda I Agenda II Agenda III
MFA RS WP
WP MFA RS
RS WP MFA
SUMMARY
I've wandered a bit astray, but I hope the reader has been sen-
sitized to the fact that even when individuals honestly reveal
their preferences, it is nevertheless entirely possible for a
50 Analyzing Politics
7 Rational Man and Irrational Society? (Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage, 1982).
Getting Started with Group Choice Analysis 51
*4. Now using the preferences after k has changed his mind,
show that if player j proposes the agenda tsrq,a then player i
has an incentive to strategically misrepresent her vote if she
assumes the otlhers vote honestly. Now suppose k proposes the
• First t and s are voted on, then the winner of that contest faces r, then the
winner of that contest faces q. The winner of that final contest is the overall
victor.
52 Analyzing Politics
CYCLICAL MAJORITIES
Condorcet's Paradox
We saw in the last chapter that a group of rational individuals
can collectively produce irrational results. Even though each
individual in the group has preferences that are consistent
(complete and tr ansitive), this need not be true of the group's
preferences. This puzzle has come to be known as Condorcet's
paradox, named after the eminent scientist, philosopher, and
mathematician of late eighteenth-century France who (re)dis-
53
54 Analyzing Politics
D ISPLAY 4 .1
CYCLICAL MA.JORITY PnEFE REN CES
1 2 3
a b c
b c a
c a b
1 Por the longest time, Condorcet was credited with inventing this voting para-
dox. Only recently it has come to light that, in fact, he had rediscovered
something that had been known five hundred year s earlier. For a general
historical overview of this subject, see fain McLean and Arnold B. Urken ,
eds., Classics of Social Choice (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press,
1993).
Group Choice and Majority Rule 55
DISPLAY 4.2
ALTERNATIVE PREFERENCE ORDERINGS
OF THREE ALTERNATIVES
(1) (2) (3) (4) (5) (6) (7) (8) (9) (10) (11) (12) (13)
a a b b e e ab ae be a b e
b e a c a b abe
e b e a b a e b a be ac ab
DISPLAY 4.3
ANOTHER SBT OF C YCLI CAL M AJORITY P REFEHENCES
l 2 3
c a b
b c a
a b c
natives. That is, there are 2197 different "societies." 'lb keep
things simpler still, let's focus on the 6 x 6 x 6, or 216, societies
of three persons with strong preferences (preference ordering
1 through 6 in Display 4.2). It is now possible to calculate how
many of these societies are afflicted with Condorcet's paradox.
Notice in Display 4.1 that the cyclical group preferences are
produced by a situation in which each alternative is ranked
first by exactly one person, second by exactly one person, and
third by exactly one person. This produces the "forward cycle"
a Pc b P0 c P0 a. (Recall that Pc means "is preferred by a ma-
jority of the group.") There are actually six different ways to
produce this forward cycle, since Mr. l's preference ordering in
Display 4.1 could be held by any one of the three individuals,
Ms. 2's by any one of the two remaining, and Mr. 3's by who-
ever is left. There arc also six ways to produce the "backward
cycle," c P0 b P0 a P0 c, generated by the individual orderings
given in Display 4.3, as well as by any reassignment of them
among group members. 2 So, taking forward and backward cy-
cles together, there are exactly 12 of 216 (strong-preference)
societies that generate group preference cycles. 3
4 A Condorcet winner is the alternative that can defeat all others in pairwise
majority contests. If three alternatives do not cycle, then it must be the case
that one of them is a Condorcet winner. I t is the one at th e top of the major·
ity preference relation, P0 .
58 Analyzing Politics
TABLE 4.1
P ROBABILITY OF A CYCLICAL MAJORITY, P r(m,n)
Number of Voters (n)
Number of 3 5 7 9 11 limit
Alternatives (m)
3 .056 .069 .075 .078 .080 .088
4 .111 .139 .150 .156 .160 .176
5 .160 .200 .215 .251
6 .202 .315
dis plays. The denomina tor gives the total number of possible
societies, computed as follows: With m alternatives, any in-
dividual in the group may choose any one of m x (m - 1) x
(m - 2) x ... x 3 x ~ x 1 (or m! in mathematical symbols) dif-
ferent ways to order his or her preferences over the alterna-
tives. Since there are n individuals, this means there are
m! x m! x ... x m! (n times), or (m!) 0 different societies. This
number, form= n = 3, is (3 x 2 x 1) 3 • 6 x 6 x 6 = 216, as we also
saw in the discussion of Display 4.2. Fortunately for us, com-
putationally talented scholars have determined Pr(m ,n) from
the formula given above for various values of m and n. A par-
tial summary of their calculations is presented in Table 4.1.5
The columns of this table give groups of different sizes,
ranging from three to some extremely large number (which I
call the "limit"). The rows give sets of alternatives of different
sizes, again ranging from three to a limiting (very large) num-
ber. The entries of the table give the probability that majority
preferences cycle, Pr(m ,n). Thus, if we look at the first row
(m - 3 alternatives), the probability of a cyclical majority rises
slowly from the 12/216 - .056 computed above for three-
member groups to .088 in the limit as the number of group
members becomes very large. Increase the number of alterna-
tives to four and the probability of a cyclical majority roughly
doubles for each group size; that is, it starts at a higher level
and smoothly increases to a limiting probability of .176. As the
number of alternatives grows very large, Pr(m,n) approaches
1.0-it becomes nearly certain that there will be preference
cycles among majorities.
So, the good news of the s mall-group/few-alternatives situ-
ation does not extend to more general situations. As the num-
ber of group members increases, and especially as the number
of alternatives increases, the probability of badly behaved
majority preferences-that is, cycles-grows, becoming nearly
certain as we approach the limit. In general, then, we cannot
rely on the method of majority rule to produce a coherent6
sense of what the group wants, especially if there ar e no
institutional mechanisms for keeping participation restricted
(thereby keeping n small) or weeding out some of the alterna-
tives (thereby keeping m s mall).
This is a troubling state of affairs for anyone trying to ana-
lyze politics. We have just concluded that, most of the time,
when we employ majority rule, we must tolerate either group
incoherence, a highly compressed franchise (small n), or
highly restricted agenda access (small m). That is the gist of
Table 4.1. There is, however, an important qualification.
In computing the entries of Table 4.1, a very specific as-
sumption was made about the likelihood of various preference
configurations. We assumed that, for any size group (n), each
DISPLAY 4.4
MAJORITY CYCLE I N "DMDE THE DOLLARS" GAME
Majority Coalition
Distribution 1 Distribution 2 Preferring 2 to 1
[3331/J, 3331/3, 3331/3] (500, 500, 0) {E,C}
[500, 500, OJ (700, 0, 300) {E,W}
(700, o. 300) [333'h, 333'h, 333'A] {C,W}
[700, 0, 300] (since 333V;i > 0 for C and 333V;i > 300 for W),
thereby producing a majority cycle (Display 4.4).8
I have claimed that "divide the dollars" represents a
generic kind of politics. I have just proved that sharing out
benefits and burdens, or what is known as "distributive poli-
tics,"9 is inherently cyclical in majoritarian settings. Any
proposed distribution is open to amendment as different ma-
jorities jostle with one another for advantage. Final outcomes,
whatever they happen to be, are extremely sensitive to other
institutional features of the group decision-making setting.
They will depend, for example, on someone's exercising
agenda power, on some arbitrary time limit on deliberation,
CASE 4.1
CIVIL W AR T AXES, G REAT D EPRESSION
T AXES, 1980s T AX R EFORM
·The institutional features emphasized here are procedural rules that are
common in most legislatures. They will be discussed more systematically
in the next chapter.
t The organizational problems, known as collective action problems, will be
more fully analyzed in Chapter 9.
Group Choice and Majority Rule 65
t The details are provided in the fine essay by James E. Alt, '"l'he Evolution
of Tax Structures," Public Choice 41 (1983): 181-223.
66 Analyzing Politics
~The politics of the 1986 tax reform process, and the specific quote from
Darman, are found in Alan S. Murray and Jeffrey H. Birnbaum, "Law·
makers, Lobbyists and the Unlikely Triumph of Tax Reform," Congress
and the Presidency 15 (1988).
AR.Row's T HEOREM
I have looked both theoretically and practically at the puzzle
of Condorcet's paradox. The choices of rational individuals
(based on complete and transitive preferences) do not neces-
sar ily tran slate through majority voting into a well-defined
group preference. Condorcet's paradox is problematic for ma-
jority rule in theory because its probability in natural groups
is not trivial and grows both with the size of the group and
with the number of possible alternatives for choice. It is prob-
lematic for majority voting in practice because in very r eal po-
litical settings, especially those dealing with the distribution
of a fixed pie, voting cycles do emer ge.
Nevertheless, it may be that we aren't looking at the prob-
lem properly. Maybe the problem of group incoherence is a pe-
culiarity of round-robin tournaments, or of specific features of
68 Analyzing Politics
CASE 4.2
L EGISLATIVE I NTENT
· While it is often the case that liberals seek broad interpretive principles
and conservatives prefer narrow ones, it does not al ways play out that
way. On matters of "police power," for example, conservatives often in-
cline toward a more permissive reading of a statute to justify greater
state activity.
76 Analyzing Politics
--
May Condition Arrow Condition
A D
-
N I
M p
16
Apparently this was the case on many pirate ships. Arrow's Theorem would
lead one to believe either that there were many revolts aga inst captains, or
that an existing captain managed to control the agenda of s ubsequent votes.
17
The"- " symbol means "logically implies."
80 Analyzing Politics
DISPLAY 4.5
CONDTTTO NS C HARACTERIZTNG GROUP
D ECISION-MAKING M ET HODS
Arrow May
U (Universal Domain) U (Universal Domain)
P (Unanimity) A (Anonymity)
I (Independence from Irrele- N (Neutrality)
vant Alternatives)
D (Nondictatorship) M (Monotonicity)
It is pretty easy t.o see why the first implication in the corol-
lary is true. If there were a dictator, then the condition of
anonymity could hardly hold, since the group preference is
produced by an identifiable individual; consequently if some
procedure is anonymous, then it must be nondictatorial.
The second and third implications are a little trickier to estab-
lish and so I implore the reader either to take the claims
on faith or to consult May's original paper or Riker's discus-
sion of it. 18
Stringing together May's Theorem, Arrow's Theorem, and
May's Corollary :yields the result that MMR is but a special
case of the aggregation mechanisms covered by the Arrow con-
ditions and, therefore, is subject to the same vulnerabilities.
Symbolically, we have:
MMR ++ {U, A, N, ~I} (May's Theorem)
{U, A, N, M} ~ {U, P, I, D} (May's Corollary)
{U, 1, P, D} ~ P 0 violates the Rationality
Assumption (Arrow's Theorem).
1
~ T<enneU1 0. May, "A Set of Indep<'11dcnt Necessary and Sufficient Conditions
for Simple Majority Decision," Econometrica 20 (1952): 680- 84; Riker, Lib-
eralism Against Populism, chapter 3.
Group Choice and Majority Rule 81
Single-Peakedness
This most famous domain restriction was invented, even
before Arrow's Theorem, by the Scottish economist Duncan
Black. He believed that minimal forms of consensus well short
of unanimity might be sufficient to produce coherent group
°
choice.2 For example, consider the abortion issue in American
politics over the last four decades. Opinion is quite polarized
on a woman's options and rights. A sizable bloc of citizens,
calling themselves pro-life, believes abortion should be prohib-
ited in all circumstances (L). Another sizable group of citizens,
20 Black was unable to serve in the British Army during World War II, so he
took on voluntary night-watch duty in Scotland. Spending long nights in a
bunker watching for German aircraft, his curious mind toyed with various
geometric conditions that would enable majority rule to function smoothly.
These ideas appeared in a series of papel's at the end of the war. Their
fullest statement is found in Black, The Theory of Committees and
Elections.
Group Choice and Majority Rule 83
Value Restriction
In a brilliant insight, the economist Amartya Sen asked,
"What's so special about being 'not worst'?" 21 Consider the set
of alternatives A • {a , b, c, d , e}. What if, for {a, b, c}, all the
members of a group agreed that b was "not best"?22 What if
they agreed that c was "not middling"? 23 Indeed, what if for
{a, b, c} there was consensus that alternative a was "not
worst," whereas for {b, c, d} all group members agreed that
d was "not best," and in {c, d, e} the group members agreed
that e was "not middling''? Sen refers to this as the condition
of value restriction. A group's preferences are value restricted
if, for every collection of three alternatives under considera-
tion, all members of the group agree that one of the alterna-
tives in this collection either is not best, not worst, or not
middling (with all members agreeing on which quality the al-
ternative in question was not). He proved a remarkable result,
generalizing Black's Theorem:
Sen,s Value-Restrict ion Theorem. The method of
majority rule yields coherent group preferences if
individual pre fere nces are value restricted .
Both single-peakedness and value restriction circumscribe
Arrow's universal domain condition, U. True enough, majority
rule won't work in all situations. But in a surprisingly large
number of such situations (204 of 216 in the three-person/
three-alternative situation, recall), the kind of consensus re-
quired may, in fact, exist.
*5. For each of the following societies, state whether the pref-
erences satisfy Sen's value-restriction criterion, that is, that
for any three outcomes, all voters agree that at least one of
the outcomes is not first, middle, or last. If not, identify the
tuple(s) of preferences that violate value-restricted prefer-
ences. Assuming that the voting rule is majority rule, are the
group preferences in societies without value-restricted prefer-
ences transitive or intransitive?
Society 1:
yP 1 xP 1 zP 1 w
wP 2 yP 2 xP2 z
z P3 y P3 wP 3 x
Society 2:
y pl w pl z pl x
w P2 x P2 y P2 z
z P3 w P3 y P3 x
Society 3:
y p l w p l z pl x
zP 2 xP 2 yP 2 w
xP 3 yP 3 wP3 z
90
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 91
SPATIAL FORMULATION
The Simple Geometry of Majority Rule
Suppose a group's problem is, in effect, to pick a point on a
line: the group must select some single numerical parameter.
For example, a bank's board of directors must decide each
week on the week's interest rate for thirty-year home mort-
gages. In effect, the relevant interest rates are points on a
line, one endpoint being 0 percent and the other being some
positive number, say 10 percent. This interval is written as
[O, 10). In this and other circumstances, I want the reader to
imagine a group of individuals each of whom has a most-
preferred point on the line and preferences that decline as
points further away in either direction are taken up.
In Figure 5.1 the preferences of the five-person board of
bank directors, G = {l, 2, 3, 4, 5}, are displayed. The board is
meeting on Monday morning to decide the interest rate to
FIGURE 5.1
UTILITY
0 2 10
92 Analyzing Politics
1
Recall that "i E G" means "the element i in the set G," where i stands for any
one of the five bank directors.
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 93
FIGURE 5.2
UTILITY
Ps(Y)
0 4 6 y= 7 8 10
X5 = 8.25
FIGURE 5.3
UTILITY
U5
U4
U3
U2
U1
0 2 4 6 8 10
I
X1 X2 y X3 X4 X5
'----y---1 '--.,--'
P2(Y) P3(y)
P1(Y) P4(y)
Ps(Y)
DISPLAY 5.1
THE MAJORITY COALITIONS OF G= {l,2,3,4,5}
S ize of Coalition Coalitions
3 {1,2,3}, {1,2,4}, {l,2,5},
{1,3,4}, {l,3,5}, {l,4,5}
{2,3,4}, {2,3,5}, {2,4,5}
{3,4,5}
4 {1,2,3,4}, {1,2,3,5}, {1,2,4,5}
{l,3,4,5}, {2,3,4,5}
5 {1,2,3,4,5}
• In Figure 5.3 it turns out that members of only one of the sixteen majorities,
{3,4,5}, has overlapping Pl(y) sets. Members of the r emaining fifteen major·
ities (listed in Display 5.1) cannot agree on any points they jointly prefer to
y. For any one of those fifteen, say, {l,2,4}, some members prefer only points
to the left of y while others prefer only points to the right of y. As a group
they cannot agree. Thus W(y) - · P 3(y) n P 4(y) n P 6(y).
96 Analyzing Politics
place. On the other hand, if the winset of xis not empty (W(x)
"' 0), then it is hard to justify the choice of x. How can you
choose x when some majority of the group clearly wants some
other specific alternative? And if the winset is nonempty for
euery alternative, we have a problem: the group's preferences
are incoherent, since some majority prefers something to
every alternative available.
The question of the moment is whether, or in what circum-
stances, an x possessing an empty winset exists. If any com-
plete and transitive preferences may be held by the
individuals in 0-Arrow's "universal domain" condition-
then, as we have seen, the answer is "not necessarily." Why?
Because under Arrow's condition U, it is possible for majority
preferences to cycle, in which case W(x) = 0 for no alternative.
But if preferences are restricted, then a different answer is
possible.
Black's Median-Voter Theorem. If members of g roup
G have s ing le-p eaked prefe r ences, then the ideal
point of the median voter has an e mpty w inset.
One such group consisting of individuals with single-peaked
preferences is pictured in Figure 5.3'. The median voter ideal
point in this group is x3 of Mr. 3. 5 The claim of Black's Theo-
rem (th·e same Duncan Black, by the way, as in the previous
chapter) is that W(xJ = 0, and that x 3 is the majority choice.
We can prove this theorem using the example of the five
bank board mcmlber s. Consider any arbitrary point in the fea-
sible set of interest rates, [O, 10], to the left of x3-say the
point labeled a i n Figure 5.3'. Notice that a is preferred to
x3 by members 1 and 2. since x3 is not in either P/a) or P/a),
but x3 is preferred to a by members 3, 4 and 5. Thus, x3 is
6
The median of a set ordered from left to right is the point such Lhat at least
half the points are aL or to its right and at least half the points are at or to
its left.
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 97
FIGURE 5.3'
UTILITY
0 2 4 6 8 10
I
x, X2 Ct X3 X4 X5
P2(et) P3(<X)
,------'----, ,-J--.,
Psets --------------------------------------~
P 1( a) P4{ a)
P5(<X)
6 For example, the U.S. Constitution requires the Senate to have an even
number but establishes a tiebreaking procedure. The vice president of the
United States, sitting as the president of the Senate, is allowed to vote only
in case of a tic. Likew~se, the standing rules of the House of Representatives,
which has an odd number, provide a tiebreaking rule, asserting that a mo-
tion fails if it obtains no more yeas than nays-it fails on a tie.
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 99
7 Generally, when dividing a fixed pie among n categories (or people), we need
only n- 1 dimensions to display all outcomes.
100 Analyzing Politics
FIGURE 5.4
UTILITY
u1 BUTIER
,'
-------------~~=-
,, ..
,
9 1Y "---- - ---+
GUNS
8 If the size of the budget were fixed in advance, then by the argument in the
previous paragraph and footnote, only one dimension would be needed, say,
dollars for defense; once this is established, dollars for domestic programs is
strictly determined-it's what is left over. When the budget is not deter-
mined in advance, then we need both dimensions to display all outcomes.
102 Analyzing Politics
FIGURE 5.5
GUNS
0 BUTTER
her ideal, being equidistant from that ideal, are equally pre-
ferred by her. The logic is the same in comparing a point on
one circle to that on a nother. A legislator prefers a point on a
circle with a smalkr radius to one on a circle with a larger ra-
dius, because this 1neans the form er point is closer to her ideal
than is the latter point.9
Notice the point labeled yin Figure 5.5. The circle through
FIGURE 5.6
-W(y)
along the other dimension. Put differently, preference is said in this instance
to decline with weighted distance from the ideal (where the weights reflect
the salience of each dimension to the legislator). In this instance, indiffer·
ence contours will no longer be circles, but will be ellipses instead. I wiJl
stick with the most basic formulation.
104 Analyzing Politics
FIGURE 5.7
,,
,,
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 105
to the dashed line containing all three ideal points, any point
on Ms. 3's side of that line is less preferred than x 2 by 1 a nd 2,
and any point on Ms. l's side of the line is less preferred than
x2 by 2 and 3.
Now let's add two more voters to the picture that are sym-
metrical i.n precisely the same way (Figure 5.8). Voters 2, 4,
and 5 lie on a line , just as 1, 2, and 3 do. It is still the case that
W(x 2) - 0, because any departure from x 2 is opposed by at
least three of the :five voters. You may test this proposition out
for yourself by laying a straightedge through x 2 at any a ngle.
There a re always two voters who would like to move to some
point on one side of the straightedge, two who would like to
move to points on the other side of the straightedge, and
one (Mr. 2) perfectly content to stay at x 2 . Since no majority
favors moving in any direction (there are always three votes
against), the winset of x 2 is empty. Something about distribut-
ing voters symmetrically around a common point seems to be
producing a coherent majority choice.
Indeed, we can be very specific here. Let us consider a set
of m voters (where mis any number, which we will take to be
odd to si mplify the presentation), whose ideal poin ts are xi' x2'
... , x n.. These m ideal points are in a multidimensional policy
space, like the one pictured in Figure 5.8 (although the results
presented below apply to policy spaces of more than two di-
mensions as well). These ideal points are distributed in a radi-
ally symmetric fashion if the following conditions hold:
(1) There is a distinguished ideal point, labeled x*; (2) the n-1
remaining ideal points can be divided into pairs (since n is
odd, n-1 is even and this is possible); and (3) t he two ideal
points in any pair, say X; and xi' plus x* all lie on a line with x*
"between" x; and x;yj. In Figure 5.8, x 2 is the distinguished
point, x 1-x3 and x 4 -x" are t he pairs of remaining ideal points,
and x 2 lies on a line " between" the ideal points in each pair.
Notice that radial symmetry does not require the two ideal
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 107
FIGURE 5.8
°Charles R. Plott, "A Notion of Equilibrium and Its Possibility under Major-
1
11 One result is said to '"generalize" another when the latter is a special case of
the former. Thus, Black's median-voter result is the one-dimensional ver-
sion of Plott's Theorem, in which the median voter 's ideal is the distin-
guished point and pairs of voter ideal points, one from each side of the
median, are distributed arou nd it in a radially sym metric fashion.
12 The sensitivity is not quite so severe wh en the number of voters is even. In
this case the disting uished point is not a voter ideal point. Some shifts in
voter ideal points are possible without disturbing the empty winset prop-
erty of this distinguis hed point.
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 109
APPLICATIONS
14 It should he noted that the members of each majority coalition in this exam-
ple bl indly vote their prefere nces, like la mbs following the judas goat to
slaughte r. The legislators seem like putty in th e hands of the wily agenda
setter, Mr. 3. In the n ext chapter, we will endow "followers" with some so·
phistication by which they might be able to control their "leader."
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 111
FIGURE 5.9
Spatial Elections
The real origins of the spatial model are found in a famous
paper written in 1929 by Harold Hotelling. 15 An economist in-
Row, 1957).
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 113
18 For those too young to remember, Vince Lombardi was the legendary foot-
ball coach of the Green Bay Packers and, at the end of his career, the Wash-
ington Redskins . To Lombardi, nothing was more important than winning.
While not exactly an uplifting imperative, Lombardi's maxim is a pretty
good first approximation for what it takes to succeed in the national politics
of most countries, the business world, and the Na tional Football League.
(By the way, though associated with Lombardi, it is not clear h e really ever
said this!)
114 Analyzing Politics
FIGURE 5.10
0 X1 Xz l 100
sian rule is that each voter votes for the candidate whose loca-
tion is closest to his or her ideal point. 19
We can now answer the questions posed in the previous
paragraph. Candidate R should snuggle up infinitesimally
close to the right-hand side of L. That way, R gets all the votes
to the right of l and, since l is to the left of the midpoint of the
voter distribution, that means that R gets more than half of
all the votes. 20 That is, R gets the 375 votes from voters of
types 3, 4, and 5; L gets the 250 votes of types 1 and 2. Put
more generally, L's location divides the electorate into two
groups: those with ideals less than l and those with ideals
greater than l. K s optimal response is an r just next to l on
the side of the larger group. We have thus figured out how R
will respond to any move made by L . L thus knows that her
position will divide the electorate into two groups and she will
get the smaller group. Given that she, too, wants to maximize
votes, she should try to make this smaller group as large as
possible. She can do this, the reader may have guessed, by set-
ting l equal to the ideal point of the median voter, since the
groups to the left and right would then be equal in size. If l
and r just straddle the ideal point of the median voter, x3, then
each location is optimal against the other's and the election
ends in a virtual tie.
We draw precisely the same conclusion if we fix K s posi-
tion first and let L respond optimally. For any r chosen by R, L
will set l just next to r on the side of the larger group. Under
19
For any two candidate positions, say, a and ti in [O, 100), where a is to the
left of~. the midpoint is (a + ~)/2. The candidate located at a receives the
votes of all voters with ideals to the left of this midpoint, whereas the can·
didate located at ~ gets the votes of all voters with ideals to the right of this
midpoint. Voters at the midpoint are indifferent between the two candi-
dates, since their positions are an identical distance from these voters'
ideals; these vote·rs tlip coins to decide for whom to vote.
20 If l happened to be to the right of the midpoint of the voter distribution,
then R would maximize his votes by squeezing up against Lon its left side,
thereby getting a majority of the votes.
116 Analyzing Politics
23 Notice that the rationale is not that the middle is "where the votes are."
Certainly this may be true; in many circumstances the middle of the spec·
trum is where most persons' preferences lie, with the numbers getting
smaller as one moves toward the more extremist tails of the distribution.
But go back to Figure 5.10 and suppose that the extremists are the more
plentiful. That is, suppose types 1 and 5 have 250 voters each, types 2 and
4 have 62 voters each, and type 3 consists of a single voter. Will the Down·
sian logic recounted above be any different here? No. The centripetal pull is
the same, even though the "center" is least populated wilh voters!
24 It might interest the reader to know that Downs's book originated as a
FIGURE 5.1 1
T gets x votes
L, R get y/2 votes each
T L, R
1 2 3 4 5
o ---~~~~~~~~~~"-~~~~~~~~~~~
100
x m· y
sible, yet it is clear that parties do not converge all the time.
Why n1ight this be? Downs's spatial model is quite user -
friendly as a "discovery tool," so we can vary some of its as-
sumptions and see what happens. Suppose, for example, we
do not foreordain that there are two candidates. What if Leftie
(L) and Rightie (R) are not the only two kids on the block?
There is a third candidate-call her Trey (T)-who may enter
the race if she thinks she has a chance. Well, if L and R locate
at the median (call it m*)- l ~ r ~ m*-an d if, when there are
more than two candidates, the one with the most votes (not
necessarily a m ajority) wins the election, then T certainly
does have a cha nce. She can locate close on one side or the
other of the median, win nearly all the votes on that side, and
thus defeat Land R, who end up splitting the remaining votes
(Figure 5.11 ). On the other hand, if the positions of L and R
are sufficiently widely dispersed. then T can enter between
them at some position t. She will get the votes of voters whose
ideal points lie in the interval [(l + t)/2, (t + r)/2]. T he left
boundary of this interval is the midpoint between the posi-
tions of Land T, whereas the right boundary is the midpoint
between the positions of T and R. By the sa me Downsian r ule
of calculation, L gets all the voters in the interval (0, (l + t)/2],
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 119
and R gets all the voters in [(t + r)/2, 100). If there are more
voters in the first interval than in the second or in the third,
then Twins. So, when there is the possibility of entry, L and R
can locate neither too closely together nor too far apart.
In fact, there may be a set of entry-deterrence locations for
T and R, with tlhese two getting roughly the same number of
votes, and no third candidate able to locate in any place that
would give her a victory (thereby discouraging her from enter-
ing at all). The point here is that when we broaden Downs's
initial model to take account of some factor he had omitted-
the possibility of entry by a third candidate-we discover that
there may be occasions and circumstances in which the estab-
lished parties (T and R) are ill-advised to converge toward the
median.
Research has, in fact, been conducted on precisely the issue
of Downsian candidate competition with (prospective) entry. 25
As noted, it is clearly one extension of the original Downsian
assumptions that produces the possibility of nonconvergent
candidate locations. But there are other possibilities. Candi-
dates, for instance, may have their own policy preferences,
ones often known to the voters. Thus, suppose T and R have
their own policy ideal points at l* and r*, respectively (shown
in Figure 5.12). They may declare policy programs at other lo-
cations, say, l .. l* and r .. r*. But why should the voters
believe these policy declarations? It's not necessary to be alto-
gether cynical to believe that once one of them wins, she or he
will be sorely tempted to implement her or his preferred policy
(l* or r*), not declared policy (l or r); politicians cannot be
trusted to do what they say when they have preferences of
their own. Effectively, then, candidates once again will not
converge, this time because there is no point in doing so (they
FIGURE 5.12
/" I m· r r·
28 In 1968, Wallace entered on the right, thinking "there's not a dime's worth
of difference" between the Democrat Hubert Humphrey and the Republican
Richard Nixon.
29 Both Anderson and Perot sought to capture the center, which they believed
had been conceded by Carter and Reagan in 1980 and Clinton and Bush in
1992, respectively.
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 123
30 This may be proved as follows. Suppose x , x, and y are all points in the di-
mension. and that xms.xsy. Legislator m clearly prefers x to y. But then so
does every legislator t-0 the left of m. Together these legislators constitute a
majority, so xis pl'.'eferred by a majority toy. Likewise, by the same reason-
ing, if ysxsx.,, then both m and a majority (all the legislators to the right of'
m) prefer x to y. So, it has been shown that whenever x and y are on the
same side of the median, a majority a lways agrees with the preferences of
the median voter. Suppose, then, that xsxmsy. and that m prefers x to y.
Consider the legislator just to the left of m. Her ideal is closer to x and far-
ther from y than was m's ideal; so if m prefers x to y, surely she does, too.
But then. so do all the other voters to the left of m's ideal, and once again
they jointly comprise a majority. This establishes that a majority always
agrees with the preferences of the median voter.
31 In some circumstances, the status quo policy does not remain in place, un-
less the legislature takes positive action to keep it in place. If the legisla-
ture fails to do anything, then the status quo reverts to some specific policy
(known, naturally enough, as the reuersion point). This is true, for instance,
in statutes that possess sunset prouisions, an example explored further in
Case 5.1.
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 125
posal. Once the committee has opened the gates and made a
proposal, it concedes its monopoly access to the agenda.
Each of these systems is explored in both the one-
dimensional and the multidimensional setting in order to de-
termine whether there is anything regular or routine that we
can expect from these alternative majority-rule regimes. Some
brief comparative observations on these regimes are offered,
leaving a full-blown consideration for chapters 11 and 12,
where institutions are taken up more systematically.
FIGURE 5.13
0 1
1
EQUILIBRIUM
OUTCOME
mine the content of agenda items and the order in which they
will be taken up. Some legislatures establish a single agenda
committee to decide these matters. However, most legislatures
(certainly in the United States) employ a division-of-labor
comn1ittee system that divides up agenda power by policy
area. Subsets of legislators have disproportionate influence
over the agenda in specific policy jurisdictions. The committee
serves, in its jurisdiction, as a n agenda agent for its parent
legislature.
I will have much more to say about these things in Part IV.
For now, I need focu s only on the fact that what distinguishes
the closed-rule regime from pure majority rule is that ther e is,
in addition to xfJ and xm, a third pa ra meter of interest, namely
the median ideal point of an agenda-setting committee, xc.a4
Many of th e conclusions drawn about this regime depend on
the relative locations of :xfJ, xc, and xm.
The decision-making procedure, as suggested earlier, is for
the committee either to make no proposal at all, in which case
xO remains in place, or to make a motion to change the status
quo, which the parent body must accept or reject as is. What
will such a committee do? To answer this question, we once
again determine P m(x'Y), as in the top panel of Figure 5.13.
This is a set whose boundary points are xfJ itself and x*; it con-
tains the only points a legislative majority prefers to xfJ. The
committee, as personified by its median voter, c, treats these
points as its "opportunity set," picking its favorite as the mo-
tion it makes (if it makes a ny motion at all). We look at three
orderings of the relevant parameters (there are six orderings
in all, but the omitted ones are simply mirror images of the
ones we conside r):
34 Since the one-dimensional model is being elaborated here, we are concerned
with the medjan ideal of only a single committee. In multiilimensional con·
texts, where there arc many jurisdictions into which the dimensions of t he
policy s pace are arranged, we will need to know the policy preferences of
different committees, each responsible for its own bundle of policy dimen-
sions. More on this will be developed in Part IV.
130 Analyzing Politics
would be defeated. So it might as well not bother and s im ply keep the gates
closed (especially if the bother were at all costly). On the other hand, if out-
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 131
side interests took heart in the fact that the committee was at least putting
up a good fight and rewarded the committee accordingly, then the commit-
tee might wish to ''bother" (though the result would be uncbanged-xO
would stay in place).
37
The classic statement of this result, plus a derivation of some of the political
consequences of it, is found in Thomas Romer and Howard Rosenthal, "Po-
litical Resource Allocation, Controlled Agendas, and the Status Quo," Public
Choice 33 (1978): 27-43.
132 Analyzing Politics
CASE 5.1
S UNSET P ROVISIONS AND
Z ERO -BASED B UDGETING
aa The reader might try to see what happens as .t.o changes in cases 2 and 3
above.
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 133
0 B x,,. B* N
outcomes (a fact that may puzzle those not equipped with the
theory developed here). If, for instance, a legislative election
caused massive turnover in incumbents but did so symmetri-
cally so as to leave xm unchanged, then "the more things
change, the more they stay the same." Likewise, if before an
election legislators c and m are at loggerheads, as defined in
case 3 above, then electoral change, no matter how massive,
that leaves the (possibly newly determined) c and m at logger-
heads will simply maintain the status quo ante. The institu-
tional impediments implicit in the closed-rule regime stand in
stark contrast to the hypersensitivity of pure majority rule.
FIGURE 5.14
This procedure looks very much like the pure majority rule
regime, except that the committee has the first move. Once it
opens the gates, we're in the world of pure majority rule. This
means that once a proposal is made, it will be amended and
amended again, with successful amendments converging the
process toward xm. Indeed, it doesn't even matter what the ini-
tial committee proposal is. The reality is:
open the gates :::::> xm
keep gates closed :::::> :xfl
The commit.tee decision is really pretty simple. If the com-
mittee median voter, Ms. e, prefers x"' to x 0 , then she makes a
motion (any motion); if Ms. c prefers xD to xm, then the commit-
tee keeps the gates closed. Thus, all we need to inspect is Ms.
e's preferred-to-x0 set, Pc(:xfl), to see whether xm is in it or not.
Recall th e t hree possible cases in the preceding section.
For the parameter ordering of case 1 (:xflsx"'sx), the commit-
tee clearly prefers xm to x 0 , so it will open the gates. For case 3
(xms:xflsx), the committee clearly has the opposite preference,
so it will keep the gates closed. It is the case 2 ordering
(:xflsxcsxm) that is the interesting one. If e's ideal policy is less
than halfway between x 0 and xm, then she keeps the gates
closed; if it is more than halfway, then she makes a motion.
The first of these case 2 situations is shown in Figure 5.14.
What makes this especially interesting is that it represents a
subject to another amendment. The process continues until no more amend-
ments are forthcoming, after 'which there is a final vote between the alter-
native left standing on the floor and the status quo.
136 Analyzing Politics
CASE 5.2
THE I MPORTANCE OF COMPROMISE AND
STRATEGIC THINKING
•
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 137
c I
Without going into any of the specifics concerning the
way powerful lobbyists exercise their power, suppose that
lobbyist I is in a position to undermine any change in the
status quo if it finds the change not to its liking (perhaps by
"bribing" influential legislators- that is, contributing to
their campaign committees). Under the closed rule, the best
I could hope for is the compromise point, C-a policy just a
little bit closer than :xfJ to xm. If the lobbyist stubbornly
refuses to accept C by seeking something . more extreme,
it loses. Under the open rule, it must be prepared to ac-
cept xm, for Uris is where the process of amendment will
drive the final result. In either of these cases, the lobbyist
must be able to anticipate the best deal it can cut and settle
for it. In particular, it must be especially sensitive to the
fact that "the best deal it can cut" depends upon the proce-
dural rules for amendments. Even though it is powerful
enough to undermine proposed changes in :xfJ, it cannot im-
pose its own "'·ill. It needs a little help from its (legislative)
friends.
Some observers have cited the absence of such strategic
thinking as a reason for the failure of the Equal Rights
138 Analyzing Politics
40 Namely, that everyone votes his or her preference rather than voting strate-
gically (which is taken up in the next chapter).
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 139
FIGURE 5.15
x b2 ~ - - -- - - - - - -- ... xb
''
'
xc 1 x a1 1
day, when all motion-making and voting are said and done,
the final outcome is the multidimensional median, xm=(x/ ,
x0 2), since legislator c is median on the first dimension and
legislator a is median on the second. This does not mean
that W(xm)=0. There are points to its northeast, for instance,
that both a and c prefer to xm. Rather, it means that on any
dimension-say, the first-holding policy fixed on the other di-
mension, no movement away from xc 1 would be supported by a
majority. (For any point on the horizontal line through xm-
the points in which policy on the first dimension changes but
remains fixed on the second-two of the three legislators al-
ways prefer xm to it. The same holds for points on the vertical
line through xm. The only points preferred by a majority to xm
require changes on both dimensions at once.)
Thus, the multidimensional version of pure majority rule
yields one of two possible conclusions, depending upon
whether there is additional institutional structure or not. In
the pure case, the status quo is continuously vulnerable to
change. The group's choices are never very durable, since it is
always in someone's interest to introduce a motion to change
it, and it is always in some majority's interest to comply. In
the case of institutional structure in the form of dimension-by-
dimension decision making, the result is both predictable and
centripetal. The median ideal point on each dimension pre-
vails under the procedure described above (although it need
not be the same median voter on each dimension, of course).
Since I will take up the multidimensional versions of the
open-rule and closed-rule regimes in the chapter on legisla-
tures in Part IV, the discussion will be especially brief on this
subject now. Imagine, in Figure 5.16 (a reproduction of the
spatial positions in Figure 5.13), that Ms. c is an agenda setter
and the status quo is :xfJ. If her proposals are subject to amend-
ment by the parent legislature, then we are back to the wild-
and-woolly open-rule majority system. Under a closed rule,
however, she can make a take-it-or-leave-it proposal, one that
Spatial lvfodels of Majority Rule 141
FIGURE 5.16
~W(x°}
CONCLUSION
The spatial mode l will be used time and ti1ne again in the
analyses of the remainder of the book. I've put forward the
basic ingredients in this chapter and briefly explored majority
rule in electoral and small group settings. But a good deal of
na·ivete characterizes voter/legislators (apparently, only candi-
dates and agenda setters a re wily). I want to relax this unre-
alistic feature in Chapter 6. In Chapter 7 t he a nalysis moves
beyond majority rule to the multitude of ways human creativ-
ity has manifested itself in devising sometimes bizarre and in-
tricate ways for groups to arrive at decisions.
What is exciting about the spatial model to an analytical
political scientist is the opportunity it affords to capture many
of the interesting details of political competition-whether be-
tween candidates in an election or between alternative mo-
tions in a legislative assembly-and, at the same time, to do
so in a fairly clean and simple manner. We appreciate that the
reader may not a gree entirely with the last sentiment, since
this chapter has required your undivided attention and careful
reading. Nevertheless, political scientists over the past fifty or
so years have found the model to serve as the principal build-
ing block for the analysis of political rivalries of all stripes.
A single chapter in a book, of course, can only portray the
spatial model at its simplest. But even the simple formulation
possesses nonobvious implications. In the context of one-
dimensional pure majority rule with single-peaked prefer-
ences, for example, whether in two-party electoral competition
or legislative policy choice, the magnetic attraction of the me-
dian participant's ideal point is powerful. Majoritarian politics
is subjected to centripetal forces, producing outcomes that ob-
servers describe with words such as "compromise," "moder-
ate," or "centrist." At the very least, then, the simple spatial
model provides a rationale or expla nation for the inexorable
movement of majority-rule competition towa rd the center of
.
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 143
EXPERIMENTAL CORNER
Group Choice under Majority Rule
Imagine a group that must make a decision. For example,
suppose a group of five individuals must choose a point in a
two-dimensional space, one that looks like that in Figure
5.8, where each individual values the points in this space
differently. Ms. 1 most likes points in the southwestern part
of the space; Mr. 3 favors points to the northeast; others
prefer points in other regions of the space. In short, there is
conflict among the preferences of the members of this
group. There are many theories of group choice that at-
tempt to analyze and explain situations like this. In a clas-
sic paper, Morris Fiorina and Charles Plott set out to assess
these theories by running experiments with real, live
groups (mainly of college students, but others have experi-
mented with university employees, business people, towns-
people, etc.).8 In this "Experimental Corner," I will focus on
one of their experiments. This is actually a slight variation
that I run with my own students.
Begin with an odd number of group members. Each is
given experimental preferences by the experimenters. For a
five-member group as portrayed in Figure 5.8, member 1
has an ideal or most-preferred point located at x1, member
2 at x 2, and so on. Their preferences are Euclidean, which
means that they prefer the final outcome to be a point
closer to their ideal point than one further away. Thus, 3,
for example, is indifferent among all the points on a circle
center ed on her ideal point (because they are equidistant
from x3) and prefers any point on a circle of smaller radius
to one on a larger radius (because the former is closer to x3
More often than in the previous setting, the time limit de-
termines when the session will end. The final outcome is
somewhere in the middle of the distribution of preferences,
but it does not hone in on a specific point as it did when the
Plott conditions were satisfied. lt is not exactly "chaos," but
outcomes do not display the same regularity they do when
preferences are distributed in a radially symmetric fashion.
As a final exercise, I have added a new twist to the orig-
inal Fiorina-Plott experimental design. In some sessions I
tell subjects not only their own ideal points but also those of
the other subjects. Does this make a difference? Theory
says it shouldn't-either there is a Plott equilibrium point
or there is the wandering around of the McKelvey Theorem.
The additional information does not alter these facts. And,
experimentally, the results are about the same as in the
limited-information context, though the chatter among sub-
jects during the experiments does reveal envy and competi-
tiveness when some approved status quo looks to benefit
the person sitting across the table.
At least in this rather carefully controlled setting, pure
majority rule (with only the most elementary of institu-
tional features) pretty much works the way the theorems of
Plott and McKelvy suggest. Indeed, against a large number
of theoretical competitors, Plott and Fiorina conclude that
this theory of majority rule is superior.
Bobby and Emma: O; Amy: 1500; Cathy: 6000; Frank: 7500; Geri :
10,000; and David: 12,000.
FIGURES.A
1
w
:E
0
()
I-
::i
0
:E
::i
a: M
en
...I
::i
0
w
SQ
ZB=O
ZB=O SQ M 1
COMMITTEE IDEAL POINT, C
Spatial Models of Majority Rule 153
156
Strategic Behavior 157
CASE 6.1
"NEED-BLIND" COLLEGE ADMISSIONS
R ATIONAL FORESIGHT
3 What I mean to say here is that most students implicitly assume that j and
k have already made up their own minds about how to vote. Students do not
appreciate, in general, that the choices j and k will actually make are reac·
tions to i's initial choice, so that i can, in fact, affect the thinking of j and k.
The true strategist, in contrast, appreciates his or her power to inRuence the
thinking of subsequent movers.
Strategic B ehavior 161
will vote nay and this will be the best outcome for her); on the
other hand, if j votes nay, the bill will still pass because k will
be forced to vote yea, and this will be best for j. What we have
figured out so far, then, is that if i votes yea, then j can afford
to vote nay, forcing k to vote yea; the bill will pass, i and k will
get their second-preference outcome, while j gets his first
choice.
But what if i decides to vote nay? He can think ahead,
since he has deduced how the others will react. Legislator i
knows that, foUowing his nay vote, if j votes nay, the bill fails
(no matter what k does). On the other hand, if j votes yea this
will produce a split vote forcing k to vote yea, too. Legislator j
is snookered here, since he will reluctantly vote yea to get his
second choice r ather than vote nay, killing the bill and getting
his third choice. We now know what i should do. By voting
nay, he forces both the other legislators to carry the burden of
passing the pay-raise bill.
CASE 6.2
CONGRESSIONAL PAY R AISE DILEMMAS
•In fact, we are describing what is known as an extensive form game in game
theory. Game-theoretic ideas run all throu gh this volume, though I don't al-
ways take the time to point this out. Political science models are increas-
ingly game-theoretic in spirit if not in fact. A good place to encounter game
theory in the context of politics is the Ordeshook volume cited in footnote 2
above. For an outstandingly clean a nd clear (and brief!) presentation of the
essentials of game theory, nothing competes with David M. Kreps, Game
Theory and Ecol'IOmic Modelling (Oxford, U.K.: Oxford University Press,
1990).
164 Analyzing Politics
FIGURE 6.1
!~ b2
CD
2
(3, 3, 2)
(7, 1, 5)
b, 3 (1, 6, 10)
§1 © (8, 9, 3)
b,
=~
(3, 3, 9)
-= Final out come
~ j(a, 4, s>I
@!] 0 {10, 6, 4)
b2 8 (5, 1, 2)
-
@!]
b2
:®10
(7, 7, 6)
(4, 2, 4)
b, 11 (1, 4, 2)
~ @ (5, 10, 1)
b, 13 (9, 3, 6)
~ ® (3, 8, 2)
....
@!]
b2
:@16
(3, 10, 8)
(7, 4, 2)
@!] @ (6, 2, 5)
b2 18 (10, 1, 8)
Strategic Behavior 165
6 If he chooses a" he knows Mr. Ill will follow with c3 and Ms. II with b2 . Thus
a choice of a 1 yields outcome 6 with a payoff of 8 to Mr. I. If h e chooses a 2 ,
then the other players will choose c~ and b., respectively, yielding Mr. I a
payoff of 7 from outcome 9. Finally, if he chooses a 3 , outcome 15 with a pay-
off of 3 for him results. Of these he prefers outcome 6 and thus chooses a 1•
Strategic Behavior 167
CASE 6.3
P RESIDENTIAL V ETO STORIES
7
When the choice is from a fixed sequence of votes, like a legislative agenda,
most authors refer to "sophisticated" voting. When the choice is made in a
one-shot circumstance, like switching your vote in an election because you
believe your favorite candidate is out of contention, it is called "strategic"
voting. I will tend to use these terms interchangeably.
168 Analyzing Politics
MANIPULATION
SOPHISTICATED V OTING
CASE 6.4
AID TO EDUCATION AND THE POWELL
AMENDMENT
S TRATEGIC VOTING
CASE 6.5
NOT W ASTING O NE'S VOTE
H ERESTHETIC
11 The entire episode is recounted in William H. Riker, The Art of Political Ma-
nipulation, Chapter 10.
182 Analyzing Politics
CONCLUSION
E XPERIMENTAL CORNER
b If, instead of hypothesizing that all group members are of a specific type,
the experimenters assume some distribution of types across the group
members, they can still deduce probabilistic expectations associated with
particular agenda choices.
Strategic Behavior 189
191
192 Analyzing Politics
V OTING M ETHODS
The Problem with Methods of Voting-They Matter!
Getting down to business, suppose we have a group of 55 indi-
viduals, choosing among five alternatives, {a, b, c, d, e}. 1 Of the
120 possible complete and transitive strict preference order-
ings an individual might adopt as his or her own, 2 there are
only six distinct orderings, or "opinions," represented in this
particular group. They are listed in Table 7.1, along with the
number of group members holding each. (The underlining in
Table 7.1 will be explained later.) For the sake of discussion,
six different "reasonable" ways for the group to arrive at a
choice among the five alternatives are considered. The reader
may well be able to devise others and should rest assured
that, in human history, a multitude of alternative methods
have been devised. 3
1
This absolutely evi l example was invented by Joseph Malkevitch and is dis-
played in Figure 2 of his article, "Mathematical Theory of E lections," Annals
of the New York Academy of Sciences 607 (1990): 89-97. For another exa mple
that shows some of the outcome variation that arises in moving from one
voting system to another, even with preferences held fixed, see Donald G.
Saari, "Chaos, But in Voting and Apportionments?" Proceedings of the Na-
tional Academy of Sciences 96 (September 1999): 10568-71.
2 Recall that there are five possible first-preference alternatives, four remain-
ing possibilities for second preferences, and so on-or, 5 x 4 x 3 x 2 x 1 • 120
ways to strictly order five alternatives.
3 A considerably more systematic treatment of alternative voting methods is
found in William H. Riker, Liberalism Against Populism (San Francisco:
Freeman, 1982), Chapter 4. Somewhat more technical, yet quite insightful,
is Peter Fishburn, "A Comparative Analysis of Group Decision Methods," Be-
hauioral Science 16 (1971): 38-44.
Voting Methods and Electoral Systems 193
TABLE 7.1
AN EVIL EXAMPLE
I II III IV v VI
(18) (12) (10) (9) (4) (2)
a b c d e e
d e b c b c
e d e e d d
c c d b c b
b a a a a a
SOURCF.: Joseph Malkevitch, "Mathematical Theory of Elections," Annals
of the New York Academy of Sciences 607 (1990): 89-97 (Figure 2)
over the five alternatives by awarding four poi nts to his or her
first choice, three to the second choice, two to the third, one to
th e fourth , and none to the fifth. These points a re totaled and
the alternative with the most points wins.
Fifth, the Condorcet p rocedu re seeks to determine
whether there is some specific alternative that can secure a
majority agains t each of the others in a pairwise round-robin
tournament. If so, t hat is the winner. If not, then we will need
to provide some a lternative procedure (perhaps one of the
others).
Finally, consider the method of approval voting, invented
by the political scientist Steven Brams and the operations re-
search scholar Peter Fishburn. It puts no limit on the number
of votes an individual can cast. Each individual casts votes for
all those alternat ives she "approves of." This means that if she
wishes, she may cast votes for all the alternatives, none of
them, or any number in between. The winner is the alterna-
tive that receives the most approval votes. 5 All of the methods
are listed in Display 7.1.
With the data of Table 7.1 we can determine how the vari-
ous forms of popular sovereignty listed in Display 7.1 perform.
Voters are assumed to vote sincerely. Display 7 ..2 provides the
results, with the winning alternative given in bold.
The simple plurality method produces a victory for a, since
it has the most first-preference supporters, though a peculiar
victory it is, given that all but the first group hate this alter-
native. This is made all too apparent when we look at the plu-
rality runoff procedure in which b triumphs; indeed, any
alternative that made it to the "finals" against a would have
5
An individual who votes for all the alternatives states that all are "above
threshold," or acceptable. The impact on the final outcome is exactly the
same as the voter who abstains (or, equivalently, states that she approves of
no alternative). What matters in approval voting is that an alternative do
well relative to its competitors; its absolute vote total is less important.
Voting Methods and Electoral Systems 195
6 That is, the voter can either submit a subset of the full set of alternatives
(the "approved of" alternativeis) or, as in Table 7.1, he or she ca n hand in a
preference ordering with a line drawn below the "approved of" alternatives.
Voting Methods and Electoral Systems 199
dures (and any others you can think up) have their peculiari-
ties. Plurality rule, for instance, is especially odd. Alternative
a was the plurality winner in the example above, yet it loses to
every other alternative in pairwise comparison. Additionally,
the Condorcet ·.vinner, e, which many would take as a strong
normative candidate for the group choice, actually got the
fewest votes in the plurality contest. Runoffs, whether simple
or sequential, have the perverse possibility of eliminating an
alternative that can beat every other in a pairwise contest (e
never made it very far in these runoffs). The Borda count
method (indeed, this is true of all the methods) is very vulner-
able to strategic behavior. Notice that the twelve voters of
group II or th e ten voters of group III in Table 7.1, who prefer
e to d, can actually give e a victory by misrepresenting their
preference ranking for d (pretending it is lower in their rank-
ing).7 The Condorcet procedure does not always produce a
winner- and th.en what do you do?
Finally, there is an issue that applies to each of the voting
methods we have described, but we will ruscuss it in terms of
approval voting, since its proponents seem so unperturbed by
it. 8 In the example above there are five alternatives. Those al-
ternatives might be various motions (say, what movie the fra-
ternity house should rent this evening) or candidates (say,
which of the sorority sisters should be the representatives on
the Greek Council). However, which motions are moved or
which candidacies are activated depends intimately on the
voting method, F. You might figure, for example, that The
Hurt Locker would get a lot of second-choice votes from your
ELECTORAL SYSTEMS
General Remarks
One of the leading contemporary students of the theory of
electoral systems, Gary Cox, has defined an electoral system
in terms of five bits of information. 11 For Cox, as for us, the
critical separation is between plurality and proportional sys-
tems, but five bits of information can be used to characterize
10 For an elaboration on this theme, with special reference to the U.S. Con·
gress, see Kenneth A. Shepsle, ''Representation and Governance: The Great
Legislative Tradeoff," Political Science Quarterly 103 (1988): 461-84.
11 'l\vo especially important papers by Cox are mathematically advanced but
well worth examining, if only to get a feel for the kinds of analysis scholars
like Cox are able to do. See his "Electoral Equilibrium under Alternative
Voting Institutions," American Journal of Political Science 31 (1987):
82- 109; and "Centripetal and Centrifugal Incentives in Voti ng Systems,"
American Journal of Political Science 34 (1990): 903-36. These are su mma·
rized and extended in Gary C. Cox, Making \!Otes Count (New York: Cam·
bridge University Press, 1997).
204 Analyzing Politics
12
"Centripetal and Centrifugal Incentives in Voting Systems," 905-906.
Voting Methods and Electoral Systems 205
DISPLAY 7.3
ALTERNATIVE ELECTORAL SYSTEM S
v p c k f
First Past the !Post 1 no no 1 Plurality
(FPP)
Single 1 no no k>l Plurality
Nontransferable
Vote (SNTV)
Limited Vote (LV) <.k yes no k Plurality
Cumulative Vote (CV) s.k yes yes k>l Plurality
each voter is still endowed with only one vote, but now the k
highest vote getters are elected from the district, where h is
given in advance as the district's magnitude.
Just as SNTV is a small alteration of FPP (namely, a
change in di strict magnitude from 1 to some k > 1), the
method of limited vote (LV) is only a slight alteration of SNTV.
Specifically, LV endows each voter with more than one vote
(but fewer than h), still allowing for k winners. If, under FPP,
one representative is to be elected from a district and each
voter casts one vote, and, under SNTV, more than one repre-
sentative is to be elected from a district and each voter (still)
casts one vote, then, under LV, more than one representative is
elected from a district and each voter may cast multiple votes.
Thus, a district m ay elect four legislators under LV by giving
each voter, say, two votes. This method, however, offers an ad-
ditional strategic maneuver to voters-"plumping" (as the
English called it in the eighteenth century), or voting only for
your favorite candidate. 13 Consider the district with k = 4 and
v = 2 as just mentioned. Suppose I am is considering casting
my votes for my two favorites in the field of candidates. The
latest public opinion poll showed my second-choice candidate
running in fourth place and my favorite candidate in fifth. If I
proceed to vote for both candidates, my second choice may
win, but just possibly at the expense of my first choice, who
will finish just ou t of the running. I might be better advised to
cast only a single vote for my first choice, thus foregoing the
support I had planned to give to my second choice, but just
13 In Sa/ire's Political Dictionary (New York: Random House, 1978), the follow-
ing entry is found und er plump:
"One of the English election phrases for which there is no equivalent. in
the United States," wrote the New York 'Jribune in 1880. "is 'plumping.'
Whenever [an English] constituency returns two memhers, each voter ca n
give one vote each to any two ca ndidates but he cannot. give his two votes
to any one candidate. If he chooses he can give one vote to only one can-
didate, and this is t ermed 'plumping."'
Vbting Methoas and Electoral Systems 207
14
Safire, in the entry referred to in the previous footnote, goes on to indicate
that the American usage of the term "plump" differs from the English. In
the United States, "to plump" means to cumulate your votes for a particular
candidate.
15
For various points of view, see Lani Guinier, "The Representation of Minor-
ity Interests," and Kenneth Benoit and Kenneth Shepsle, "Electoral Sys-
tems and Minority Representation," both in Paul Peterson, ed., Classifying
by Race (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1995), pp. 21- 49 and
50-84.
-- ----------------------------
208 Analyzing Politics
16
"Centripetal and Centrifugal Incentives of Electoral Systems," 912. Cox
makes "small enough" and "large enough" precise.
Voting Methods and Electoral Systems 209
17
"Centripetal and Centrifugal Incentives of Electoral Systems," 915.
210 Analyzing Politics
The rule for the single transferable vote method is: For districts
with S seats and m candidates (m ;;,; S), the voters, V in number,
mark ballots for first choice, second choice, ... , and mth choice. A
quota, q, is calculated thus:
q = V/(S + 1) + 1
until all seats are filled. If at any point in the process (including
the beginning) no candidate has q first-place and reassigned
votes, the candidate with the fewest first-place and reass igned
votes is eliminated and all the ballots for her or him are trans-
ferred to candidates in the second (or next) place on those ballots;
and this is repeated until some candidate has q votes. 18
To make all this concrete, suppose there were 100 voters
(V - 100) in a district charged with electing 3 representatives
(S = 3). The quota- known as the Droop quota (Mr. Droop was
a friend of Mr. Hare)-is q = 100/(3 + 1) + 1 "' 26. That is, any
candidate receiving 26 votes can be assured that no more than
two other candidates can get as many as she. 19 If, in fact, a
candidate got in excess of 26 first-preference votes, and all the
remaining candidates did not, then the preference orderings of
the excess voters are consulted for the second preference llsted
and those votes are distributed to them. If this pushes some
other candidate over the 26-vote quota, then he or she is
deemed elected. 'I'his continues until all three candidates have
been elected or until fewer than three have been elected and
no remaining candidate has the quota. In this case, the
process starts eliminating candidates, starting with the one
with the fewest total votes. All of that candidate's votes are
distributed to t he candidates named second on each ballot.
This continues until all seats are filled.
The STV method is used to elect the parliament in Ireland
(called the Dail) and the city council of Cambridge, Massachu-
18
Riker, Liberalism Against Populism, p. 49. Duncan Black refers to STV as a
system of proportional representation because it tends to approximate the
representativeness that many PR systems display. See his famous Theory of
Committees and Electioni; (Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press,
1958). But it is decidedly a plurality system in that election is dependent on
getting more (first-preference plus transfer) votes than other candidates.
19
lf three other candidates got at least 26 votes, then they would jointly have
78 votes, which would mean that, together with the candidate who already
has 26 votes, 104 votes had been cast. But this cannot be, since only
100 votes can be cast. Therefore, it also cannot be that more than three can·
didates receive 26 or more votes each.
212 Analyzing Politics
CASE 7.1
O SCAR NOMINATIONS
20 For those interested in learning more about this system, they should con-
sult Gideon Doron, "The Hare Voting System Is Inconsistent," Political
Studies 27 (1979): 283-86; and Gideon Doron and Richard Kronick, "Single
Transferable Vote: An Example of a Perverse Social Choice Function,"
American Journal of Political Science 21 (1977): 303-11.
Voting Methods and Electoral Systems 213
21 STV is also used to elect members of the Faculty Council of Harvard Uni-
versity. (It is something of a historical irony that it was recommended to the
university by Kenneth Art"OW while he was a member of the faculty!) It runs
smoothly, virtually without controversy, and certainly with no strategic be-
havior, because so few faculty members offer themselves as candidates.
214 Analyzing Politics
Proportional Representation
I will be analytically less precise about PR systems because,
quite frankly, not much work has been done on them. The pur-
pose of a proportional system is to produce a legislature that
mirrors, in some fashion, the larger society. If, for example,
the main cleavages in society are ethnic (as in many of the
democracies in Africa and the Middle East), or religious
(Northern Ireland), or linguistic (Belgium), then a PR system
will tend to reproduce them inside the elected legislature.
Under most such systetns, no stratum, unless especially small
or poorly organized (or just plain stupid) is highly underrepre-
sented.
One would think that the design of a PR system is straight-
forward. Let each citizen cast a single vote for his or her fa-
vorite party (or any other, for that matter). Add up the votes
for each party. Give each party a proportion of legislative seats
exactly equal to its proporLion of the total popular vote. Voila!
Not so fast! First of all, the legislature's size is typically
fixed in advance. For most "reasonably" sized legislatures, it is
typically not possible to translate electoral proportions evenly
into seat proportions. Suppose the Beer Lovers Party (an ac-
tual party in Poland) captured 1 percent of the popular vote.
How many seats should it receive in the 450-seat Sejm (the
Polish House of Representatives)? It cannot be given the 4.5
seats to which it is entitled according to its electoral propor-
tion. Most PR schemes-and there are actually quite a large
number of them-differ primarily on how they handle the
problem of allocating these "fractional seats."
A second issue involves exactly who should get elected to
the legislature in the first place. If the Polish Beer Lovers
Party receives one percent of the popular vote, as in the previ-
ous paragraph, should it get any representation at all? If the
answer is in the affirmative. then at what point does the an-
swer change to negative-0.5 percent? 0.25 percent? 0.10 per-
Voting Methods and Electoral Systems 215
EXPERIMENTAL CORNER
\tbting Rules and Jury Verdicts
Choices over voting methods don't affect only electoral poli-
tics. Indeed, one of the most consequential decisions on a
24 In 2006 Ila ly returned to full PR.
218 Analyzing Politics
•This example and many others are contained in William Poundstone, Cam ·
ing the W>te: Why Elections Aren't Fair (and What We Can Do About It) (New
York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2008).
224 Analyzing Politics
Now suppose the same setup except now each voter has two
votes ( v • 2) which are not cumulable (c = no) (this is one form
of a Limited Vote system). If m ... 3, what is a stable equilib-
rium? Is that same value an equilibrium when m - 4 or 5?
226
Summary of Part II 227
231
232 Analyzing Politics
l A utile is a made-up unit of value or utility. All that matters for our purpose
is that more utiles means more value to a person. If it makes it easier, you
may think of the units as thousands of dollars, so that each farmer values
the drained marsh at $2000.
2 That is, there are increasing returns to marsh-draining effort. One person,
working alone, would end up expending 3 utiles of energy, whereas two
working together would jointly expend only 2 utiles.
a Some readers may recognize this payoff matrix. In game theory it is known
as the Prisoners' Dilemma. 1\vo petty criminals are arrested for a burglary.
Tf both keep quiet, the district attorney has to release them (payoff of 1
utile). If both squeal they get time in the slammer, but with a plea-bargained
reduction (payoff of 0 utiles). But if one squeals and the other keeps quiet,
theu the squealer is given a reward and the book is thrown at the "squealee"
(payoffs of 2 and -1, respectively). This story yields the same payoff matrix
as Display 8.1, so our analysis will be the same.
Cooperation 237
Suppose you are Farmer A (recall that your payoffs are the
left-most number in each cell). If Farmer B chooses to drain
(so we're looking at the left-most column of Display 8.1), then
you get 1 utile if you drain and 2 utiles if you do not. If Far-
mer B chooses not to drain (right column of Display 8.1), then
you get -1 utile if you drain and 0 utiles if you do not. No mat-
ter what Farmer B does, Farmer A always gets a higher payoff
if he chooses not to drain. The reasoning is precisely the same
if you are Farmer B: No matter what Farmer A does, Farmer B
always gets a higher payoff if he chooses not to drain.
From the perspective of either farmer, there is a double
reason to choose not to drain. First, you do better by not drain-
ing no matter what your counterpart chooses to do. But sec-
ond, and perhaps more psychologically compelling (since you
never trusted your neighbor very much anyhow), precisely be-
cause the same payoff profile holds for your counterpart he is
likely not to drain, making it clearly in your interest not to do
so either. That is, the other guy's incentives reinforce your
own inclination not to drain, and vice versa, ad infinitum.
Each farmer has a "dominant" strategy to be uncooperative,
238 Analyzing Politics
4 See David Hme, A Treatise of Human Nature. ed. L.A. Selby-Bigge and P.H.
Nidditch (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975 (1737)). I thank Dr. Mark Yellin for
bringing this to my attention.
Cooperation 239
C ASE 8.1
THE PARADOX OF COOPERATION:
N UCLEAR DISARMAMENT IN THE COLD
WAR AND CONGRESSIONAL
PORK-BARRELING
SOVIET U NION
Maintain Disarm
U NITED Maintain 0,0 100, -100
STATES Disarm - 100, 100 10, 10
Given their incentives, both countries preferred to main-
tain their forces rather than disarm regardless of the other's
actions. Each side considered unilateral disarmament
equivalent to surrender. The specter of this event, indicated
by the -100 payoff above, prevented the mutually preferred
outcome of bilateral disarmament. The dynamics of the co-
operation game kept the nuclear weapons in place despite
intentions and preferences to the contrary. *
Though substantively quite different, the politics of
pork-barreling in the U.S. Congress is theoretically another
instance of the paradox of cooper ation. The term "pork-
barrel politics" r efers to the appropriation of federal funds
for inefficient projects that benefit individual congressional
districts but offer little benefit to the nation as a whole. The
incentive to engage in pork-barrel politics is the opportu-
nity it affords for legislators to claim credit at election time
for prominent, federally subsidized projects in their dis-
tricts. Pork-barrel politics often centers on agricultural sub-
sidies, defense contracts, and transportation projects. A
$180-million-a-year wool and mohair subsidy, the $31-
hillion NASA space station, the mass-transit system in
downtown Buffalo, and the "Big Dig" harbor tunnel con-
necting the city of Boston to its airport have all been ac-
cused of being "pork." Pork-barrel politics has come under
close scrutiny recently as budget pressures force politicians
to reexamine their budget expenditures.
• Interestingly, disarmament has occurred over the last two decades, but it
has not been unilateral and it hail not been all or nothing. It has pro·
ceeded, in a sense, in baby step~: "You get rid of some of your arsenal and
we'll get rid of some of ours." The result has been a reduction in nuclear
weapon stockpiles but not their elimination.
Cooperation 241
6 Robert Alex.rod, The Evolution of Cooperation (New York: Basic Books, 1984).
An earlier and highly influential analysis is Michael Taylor, Anarchy and
Cooperation {New York: Wiley, 1976).
Cooperation 245
ALTERNATIVE M ECHANISMS
I NDUCING COOPERATION
I. Internalized Values
As strongly as I believe that rational responses to ongoing
relationships are responsible for quite a lot of the cooper-
ative dividends most of us ,realize in everyday life, they
clearly aren't the only thing going. Let us look briefly at some
alternatives.
People do, in fact, internalize values that dispose them to
cooperate, if only to cause them to be "nice" at a first en-
counter so that reciprocal norms might develop. But this does
not account for why one set of moral or religious principles
rather than another is internalized. Moreover, we observe
1
This situation is nicely analyzed in Avino.sh Dixit and Barry Nalebuff, Think·
ing Strategically (New York: Norton, 1991), Chapter 9. For the interested
reader, this volume is perhaps the most accessible, and certainly the most
delightful, book on game theory available.
246 Analyzing Politics
8 Clearly, the larger society would be better served if the two prisoners were
not able to capture the dividends of cooperation. But that is not our concern
here; we want to remain neutral for the time being about whether the coop-
eration we're investigating is good or bad in some broader sense.
Cooperation 247
DISPLAY 8.2
THE MAFIOSO (NON) DILEMMA*
9 In a sense, t.hough, there may not be a clear distinction between these two
mech!\nisms all the time. In the presence of external enforcement, individ-
uals will often take this fact on hoard and act as though they had internalized
some value. In effect, they have anticipated the external sanction that would
be forthcoming and have avoided it in advance· by displaying proper behavior.
Cooperation 249
tions) or she may claim that the guarantee does not cover
what the buyer complains about. ("In the fine print we said
only the left widget wouldn't fail, not the right widget.") But if
the incentives for the seller to renege are strong, then the
buyer will probably anticipate that the guarantee is "not
worth the paper it's written on." Thus, guarantees, by them-
selves, may not do the trick.
If, however, a guarantee were enforceable because there
existed a third party prepared to make the guarantor deliver
on her promise, then a buyer might well be prepared to make
the purchase. Both the buyer and the seller would be pleased
by the existence of this enforcement institution. Coerci ng her
to deliver on her promise makes the seller's promise credible.
It is the credibility of her promise that induces the buyer to
buy, after all. So, the institution of thirdparty enforcement al-
lows cooperation (Buyer: "I'll buy your product." Seller: "I'll
guarantee its quality."). The absence of this exogenous en-
forcement institution makes both buyer and seller worse off. 10
In the Mafioso Dilemma, for example, imagine the payoffs
are as they originally were in Display 8.1. Mafioso A says to
mafioso B, "I won't squeal." Mafioso B says to mafioso A, "Nei-
ther will I." These promises are credible because there is a
thjrd-party enforcer, Don Corleone, who imposes sanctions on
those who break their promises. The presence of Don Corleone
effectively transforms Display 8.1 into Display 8.2. What is es-
pecially interesting in this instance is that as long as mafioso
A and mafioso B believe they are playing the game in Display
8.2, the Don never has to display his might. Indeed, to those
ignorant of the Don's existence, the two prisoners might be
thought simply to be honest men who keep their promises! Al-
10 A buyer may still buy under these circumstances, but because the seller
cannot credibly commit to honor b.er guarantee, the buyer will require a
break on the price. This differenc~ between the price a buyer would pay
under a fully enfo:rceable guarantee a nd one that is not enforceable is, in
effect, the insurance premium the buyer requires.
~· -·-=-=-~-=--·~--~
250 Analyzing Politics
'
ternatively, it may be thought that there is "honor among
thieves" (a moral principle) .
By introducing a third-party enforcer, much like Hobbes did
with his invention of Leviathan, we have effectively coerced
people to behave in a manner that yields the m a cooperation
dividend. But our analysis would be woefully incomplete if we
failed to inquire further into the nature of this enforcer. To be
precise, I need to take up three matters: costly enforcement,
- ------
let his brother-in-law off for speeding but nail the town's "radi-
cal lawyer" who has been such a nuisance to the police depart-
ment? Who would doubt that the rabbi, the third-party
enforcer in the little Polish villages that the Nobel laureate
Isaac Bashevis Singer wrote about, would make sure that his
own son got small advantages in village life? What is to pre-
vent a future black government in South Africa from stifling
dissent within the white community? In short, while many
communities-ranging from small-town America to villages in
eastern Europe to the national community in South Africa-
rely on institutions of third-party enforcement, all are vulnera-
ble to difficulties arising from inappropriate incentives. The
traffic officer above responds not only to his official responsibil-
ities but also wants to keep his wife out of his hair and his bud-
dies in the department off his case. We all look after our own.
That third-party enforcers may march to their own drum-
mers is especially troubling when it is offered, as it was by
Hobbes, as a solution to disorder in the state of nature. Third-
party enforcement is often offered as a rationale for the very
existence of the state. The state is seen as the community's
mechanism, first and foremost, for allowing its citizens to
avoid wasting their resources on their own protection and,
more generally, for permitting cooperation to occur. The state,
with its monopoly of force, empowers state officials not only
to provide the assurances that permit cooperation to take
place among citizens but also to use that force for their own
purposes. 12 But, as the saying goes, " Who will guard the
guardians?" Until one can be satisfied that the incentive prob-
Cooperation 253
P RELIMINARY CONCLUSION
E XPERIMENTAL C ORNER
Hunter B:
Hunter A: Stag Hare
Stag 3, 3 0, 1
Hare 1, 0 1, 1
• A's payoff is the left number in each cell; B's is the right number.
Cooperation 261
Friend B:
Friend A: Basketball Movies
Basketball
Movies
I 3. 1
0,0
I o.1, 30 I
Does either player end up doing better with either Basketball
or Movies no matter what his friend chooses to do, as in the
marsh-draining game? What are the outcomes in which nei-
ther player has an incentive to alter his strategy (assuming
the other player's strategy stays fixed)? Explain why this
game illustrates the problem of coordination.
262
Collective Action 263
2
Arthur Bentley, The Process of Government (Evanston, m.: Principia Press,
1908). Its famous midcentury companions were V. 0. Key, Politics, Parties,
and Pressure Groups, 3rd ed. (New York: Crowell, 1952), and David B. Tru-
man, The Governmental Process (New York: Knopf, 1951).
8 Even in these less liberal societies, conflicts were often portrayed in group
terms as struggles between large social aggregates: bourgeosie versus prole-
tariat; aristocracy versus merchant class; various racial, religious, linguistic,
or regional groups in opposition to one another; and so on.
Collective Action 267
C ASE 9.1
WHO l s R EPRESENTED?
• Organized Interests and American Democracy (New York: Harper & Row,
1986), pp. 69-71.
t Of course, the number of organizations is at best only a rough measure of
the extent to which various categories of citizen are represented in the in-
terest group world of Washington.
268 Analyzing Politics
COOPERATION ACCOUNTS
•A more complicated version of this situation, one not pursued here, enriches
each person's behavioral repertoire. Instead of a twofold choice, there is
some continuously variable input, like effort or money, that the individual
may choose to contribute.
6 Surely there are situations in which individuals may actually be denied the
benefits of a group if they do not contribute to its production. If the benefit is
highly valued, then this capacity to deny it makes it easier for the group to
elicit contributions. If you want to ride on the Massachusetts Turnpike, for
example, you must make a contribution, called a toll. If you want to fish on
the Possum Hollow River, then you must pay your club dues. If you want to
hear the Boston Symphony Orchestra play a Beethoven symphony, then you
must purchase a ticket. These activities are not quite public goods, and l
defer further consideration of them to the next chapter. In the present dis-
cussion I take up the polar case of a group good or goal, once produced, being
available to all.
270 Analyzing Politics
6
I could complicate the story by individualizing evaluations, so that Mr. i
values the group goal at B(i) utiles, while Ms. j values it at B(j), where
B(i),. B(j). But this enrichment does not change the thrust of this story, so I
will not employ it here. Conflict of interest among group members-that is,
differential evaluation of group goals-will be explored below.
Collective Action 271
the other hand, if B > C, then every member of the group will
contribute. Why?
Actually, there are two possible outcomes when B > C, but
we argue that only the one in which everyone contributes
makes sense. Suppose everyone has chosen not to contribute,
and, of course, the goal is not attained. Would any group mem-
ber be so unwise as to reconsider her choice? Hardly, for if,
say, Ms. j, decided to contribute, then her payoff would be -C
(the cost she bears) and there would still be no compensating
benefit (since the latter is produced only if everyone con-
tributes). So, it is possible for a group to be stuck in an "equi-
librium trap" in which no one is contributing, even though
everyone would be better off if everyone contributed.
But this outcome is not very likely. Everyone will realize
that everyone else benefits from achieving the group goal, and
that the only way for this to happen is if everyone contributes.
So, Ivls. j, like every other group member, makes the following
calculation:
D IS PLAY 9.1
Ms. J'S N UMBER OF OTHER G ROUP
CHOI CE MEMBERS CONTRIBUTING
less t han k - 1 e xactly k - 1 k or mor e
Cont ribute -C B-C B-C
Do not con tribute 0 0 B
7
This idea was first developed in his famous book, The Strategy of Conflict
(Cambridge, Mass. : Harvard University Press, 1960).
Collective Action 273
would learn to stay to the right quite quickly (and there would
be all manner of Boston drivers to let it know if it did other-
wise). Similarly, I could imagine our social group, after some
trial and error, implicitly coordinating-for example, going to
the opera in even-numbered months and to the ballet in odd-
numbered ones. 9
9 r have said nothing about communication, and the curious reader mny
have begun to wonder why the members of this allegedJy social group
seemed incapable of talking to one another! Communication surely is an op-
tion, but it adds an additional layer of complexity that I'd just as soon not
tackle. For one thing, communication may be costly. For another, it may be
asymmetric (some people having the power to transmit, others to receive,
still others to do both, and finally some poor sods who can do neither). For
yet another, it opens up all kinds of strategic possibilities (one person leav-
ing a voice-mail message for everyone else that he's going to the opera and
will not be able to receive any incoming calls from this point on- a fait ac-
compl i). A rigorous treatment of strategic communication may be found in
Jeffrey Banks, Signaling Games in Political Science (Chur, Switzerland:
Harwood, 1991).
Collective Action 279
C ASE 9.2
T HE LARGE AND THE SMALL
In the case of NATO and the Warsaw Pact, the large partic-
ipants, the United States and the Soviet Union, respec·
tively, subsidized the other members of their alliances.*
Their large size and their belief in the necessity of the al-
liance structure handicapped them in negotiating with
their allies over a more equitable division of alliance costs.
David Marsh's research on corporations in Great Britain
belonging to the Confederation of British Industry (CBI)
suggests a similar exploitation of the large by the small.t
Large firms are more dependent on the group and small
firms are more likely to free-ride. The managing director of
one large firm said, "If the CBI didn't exist we would need
to create it. We: need someone to stand up and talk for in-
dustry" (p. 264). An executive at a small firm said, ''Whether
we were members of the CBI or not we would derive some
benefit from the part it plays for industry. You get that type
of benefit whether you are a member or not" (p. 264). In
s upport of Olson's theory, smaller group members often free
ride on the efforts of larger members whose participation is
more critical to the group's existence.
• Mancur Olson and Richa1·d Zeckhauser, "An Economic Theory of Al·
liances," Review of Economics an.d Statistics 48 (1966): 266-79.
t "On Joining Inter est Groups: An Empirical Consideration of the Work of
Mancur Olson, J r.," British Journal of Political Science 6(1976): 257-71.
Political Entrepreneurs
It is very unusual in the academic world for a book review to
become an important part of the literature on a subject. But
this is precisely what happened to Richard Wagner's review of
Olson's book. 11 Wagner noticed that Olson's arguments about
groups and politics in general, and his by-product theory in
particular, had very little to say about the internal workings
of groups. In Wagner's experience, however, groups often come
into being and then are maintained in good working order not
only because of selective incentives but also because of the ex-
traordinary efforts of specific individuals-leaders, in ordi-
nary language, or political entrepreneurs in Wagner's more
colorful expression.
Wagner was motivated to raise the issue of group leaders
11
Richard Wagner, "Pressure Groups and Political Entrepreneurs," Papers on
Non-Market Decision Making I (1966): 161-70.
Collective Action 287
12 The Wagner Act made it possible for unfons to organize by legalizing the so-
called closed shop. If a worker took a job in a closed shop or plant, he or she
was required to jo~n the union there. "Do not contribute" was no longer an
option, so workers in closed shops could not free-ride on the efforts made by
others to improve wages and working conditions.
288 Analyzing Politics
them-they feel good inside, they feel free of guilt, they take
pleasure in the activity for its own sake. We maintain that this
second view of behavior is entirely compatible with rational
accounts. Instrumental behavior may be thought of as invest-
ment activity, whereas experiential behavior may be thought
of as consumption activity. I still will not have answered the
question of where such beliefs and values originate nor why
they survive. But economists do not tell us where consumer
tastes originate either, and yet they make central use of those
tastes in constructing their theory of price. The key thing to
appreciate here is that we can still make precise statements
about how dispositions toward both investment and consump-
tion affect the prospects of collective action. I shall do this in
more detail when discussing voting, our next topic.
But before leaving this section, let me briefly note one other
aspect of experientially oriented behavior: It is the behavior
itself that generates utility, rather than the consequences pro-
duced by the behavior. To take a specific illustration of collec-
tive action, many people certainly attended the 1963 March
on Washington because they cared about civil rights. But it is
unlikely that many deluded themselves into thinking their in-
dividual participation made a large difference to the fate of
the civil rights legislation in support of which the march was
organized. Rather, they attended because they wanted to be a
part of a social movement, to hear Martin Luther King Jr.
speak, and to identify with the hundreds of thousands of oth-
ers who felt the same way. Also-and this should not be mini-
mized-they participated because they anticipated that the
march would be fun, an adventure of sorts.
So, experiential behavior is consumption-oriented activity
predicated on the belief that the activity in question is fulfill-
ing apart from (or in addition to) its consequences. Individuals,
complicated beings that we are, are bound to be animated both
by the consumption value of a particular behavior that I just
described and its instrumental value, the rational (investment)
Collective Action 291
CASE 9.3
W HAT D OES THE EVIDENCE SAY?
What does the evidence say about these different explana-
tions of collective action: Olson's by-product theory, Wag-
ner's theory of political entrepreneurs, and the rationality
of ideology and experiential behavior? In various studies
group members have been surveyed to determine why they
become members. The survey results indicate that people
join for a combination of reasons. In support of Olson's the-
ory, members of economic groups are more likely to join for
selective, material benefits than for collective benefits. Eco-
nomic groups include unions, farm groups, and business as-
sociations. Members of these groups often disagree with the
political goals of the group, suggesting that the latter are
not the chief reason for joining.*
In opposition to the by-product theory, some studies
have found that members of noneconomic groups are moti-
vated primarily by collective benefits. Individuals often join
noneconomic groups such as Common Cause or the Sierra
Club primarily because they agree with the group's political
goals.t Overall, the evidence indicates that the motivation
for membership in interest groups is a combination of selec-
tive and collective benefits, differing slightly for economic
13 William H. Riker and Peter C. Ordeshook, "A Theory of the Calculus ofVot·
ing," American Political Science Reuiew 62 (1968): 25-42.
294 Analyzing Politics
duces a dead h eat. With S 3 she can break what would other -
wise be a tie. In state S 4 her vote for Kendall would produce a
tie (though why she would ever want to do this is beyond us,
since she prefers J ackson). Finally, if S 5 is the prevailing
state, then, like in S., her vote, however she casts it, will have
no effect since J ackson wins regardless. Display 9.4 gives the
complete picture.
Each cell of the display gives the utility payoff to Ms. j,
which depends both on the state of the world (what everyone
else is doing) and her own choice. Notice that if Ms. j votes,
then her utility for the outcome, whatever it is, is always re-
duced by C, the utility cost of her participation. Of course, if
she abstains, then she does not pay this cost. The only term in
this display requiring further explanation is L , which enter s
once in each row. L stands for " lottery," and reflects the fact
that the election ends in a tie. In this case, we assume that
some random device is used to determine the winner; the lot-
tery is a fifty-fifty chance of either J ackson or Kendall. The ex-
pected utility theorem (see Chapter 2) implies that u(L) •
112 u(J) + 1/2u(K).
A glance at Display 9.4 reveals that Ms. j should never vote
for Kendall, since in each state of the world the payoff to her
in the "vote for Jackson" row is at least as big as its counter-
DISPLAY 9.4
Ms. J'S STATE OF THE W ORLD
CHOICE
81 82 83 8, 86
Vote for u(K)-C u(L )-C u(J)-C u(J)-C u(J)-C
J ackson
Vote for u(K)-C u(K )-C u(K)-C u(L)-C u(J)-C
Kendall
Abstain u(K) u(K ) u(L) u(J) u(J)
296 Analyzing Politics
14 In the first and fiftlh states, the payoffs are identical. In the third state,
since u(J ) > u(K ). the statement in the text holds. The only places in which
there may be some confusion is when L is involved. In the second state, a
fifty·fifty chance of getting your preferred candidate is surely better than
the certainty of getting your worst choice. ln t,he fourth stat,e, the certRinty
of getting your best candidate is surely better than a lottery in which your
chances of getting him are only fifty.fifty. So, the conclusion holds that
Ms. j docs at leas t as well voting for Jackson as she does voting for Kendall.
15
In our discussion of utility funcnon s in Chapter 2, we mentioned that it is
often convenient to "normalize" the analysis, without doing any logical dam-
age, by setting the utility of th<.' most-prefened alternative to unity and
that of the least-preferred to 0.
Collective Action 297
sI 82 Sa 84 86
(p l ) (p 2) (P 3) (p 4) (p 5)
Vote for -C ~-C 1-C 1-C 1-C
J ackson
Abstain 0 0 Yi 1 1
16 The lottery givin.g a fifty-fifty chance of Jackson or Kendall is, given the
normalization, a fifty-fifty chance of getting a utility of 1 or of 0. Thus, the
expected u tility of th is lottery is equal to 1/2.
298 Analyzing Politics
17 The author remembers all too keenly how painful it was to face his children
afer returning home from work on the evening of an election and confessing
that he "just didn't have the time to vote." That experience, seared in his
memory, has factored into all subsequent participation decisions for him!
300 Analyzing Politics
20
Excellent starting points are two books to which I have referred readers be·
fore: Avinash Dixit and Barry Nalebuff, Thinking Strategically and Avinash
Dixit, Susan Skeath, and David H. Reiley, Jr., Games of Strategy.
302 Analyzing Politics
DEFINING T ERMS
1
Of course, there are (politically imposed) limits to your discretion. In most
societies there are laws against squeezing toothpaste into someone else's
iPod without their permission, for example.
306
Public Goods, Externalities, and the Commons 307
•The limits have to do with the degree to which jointness of supply is compro-
mised by crowding. If greater crowding, beyond some limit, actually affects
the quality of the good, then we cannot claim that the good is jointly sup-
plied. We shall pursue this prospect in the next illustration.
Public Goods, Externalities, and the Commons 309
DISPLAY 10.1
P UBLIC AND P RIVATE Goons
Excluda bility
Yes No
Yes :v1adonna concert Public goods: defense,
Joint ness lighthouse services
of
S upply No Priva te goods: Crowded Cape Cod
toothpaste, BMW 320i beach
PUBLIC SUPPLY
market actors will not provide them (at least not in sufficient
quantities) because they cannot be assured of adequate com-
pensation. The state, on the other hand, may use its authority
to require payment, either out of general revenue raised by
taxation or from user charges of vaxious sorts. 8
However, there is a paradox associated with the public pro-
vision of public goods. Public provision does not just happen.
Political pressure must be mobilized to encourage the institu-
tions of government to make this provision a matter of public
policy. Bills must be passed, appropriations enacted, and gov-
ernment agencies created. In short, political actors must be
persuaded to act. But if the provision of a public good distrib-
utes a benefit widely, and if the enjoyment of that benefit is
unrelated to whether a contribution has been made toward
.mobilizing politicians to act, then we may reasonably ask:
Why would any individual or interest group lobby the govern-
ment for public goods? Why wouldn't they, instead, free-ride
on the efforts of others, thereby freeing up thei!' own resources
either to lobby for some other private benefits or to deploy in
the private sector for private gain? That is, if many public
services are like public goods, then therr supply depends upon
individuals and groups successfully engaging in collective ac-
tion to get the government to provide them. Since magic
wands are not available, the "public supply" solution to the
provision of public goods becomes a problem in collective
action.
8 The reader should notice that public goods, as we have defined them, and
publicly provided goods may not be the same. The latter may be public goods,
like lighthouses and national defense; but the state provides lots of other
goodies-like mail delivery, for example-that are sufficiently like other pri-
vate goods that they undoubtedly could be provided reasonably well in the
marketplace. (Indeed, courier services, overnight mail delivery, and package
delivery are provided privately in direct competition with the U.S, Postal
Service.) Publicly provided goods and services- the activities in which gov-
ernments engage-refl ect the political advantages possessed by interests in
the political process t.hat are sufficient to induce the public sector to do their
bidding. Some of these things are public goods, but not all of them.
316 Analyzing Politics
10
If, instead, we were discussing the production of art and culture as financed
by grants from the Nation11l Endowment, for the Arts, merit-based concen-
tration would be even more extreme, with New York and Los Angeles secur-
ing the lion's share of support.
Public Goods, Externalities, and the Commons 321
11 This argument is elaborated in Linda Cohen and Roger Noll, The Technology
Pork Barrel (Washington: Brookings Institution, 1991).
322 Analyzing Politics
CASE 10.1
P UBLIC G OODS, P ROPERTY RIGHTS, AND
THE R ADIO S PECTRUM
E XTERNALITIES
him at the end of the session for each unit of the product pur-
chased during the exper iment. For example, the experimenter
may pay 30 points for the first unit, 28 points for the second
unit, 25 for the third, and so on. A buyer, then, makes a profit
if his first purchase in the market is for less that 30 points,
the second purchase is for less than 28 points, the third for
less than 25, and so on. Each buyer wants to earn as many
points (as much profit) as possible, since these points will be
added to the scor·e of his midterm examination. Similarly, each
seller is given a schedule informing her of the cost of produc-
ing each unit. For example, the first unit may cost 12 points,
the second 15 points, and so on. A seller makes a profit if she
sells each unit for more than its cost (the first unit for more
than 12 points, the second for more than 15, and so on). She,
too, wants to earn as many points as possible--for the same
reason.
The buyers and sellers sit across a table from one another.
When the market opens, bargaining begins with buyers shout-
ing out "bids" and sellers shouting out "asks" in what is
known as a double oral auction. When a buyer and seller come
to an agreement on a price p, the sale of a unit is registered. If
the buyer with the schedule given in the preceding paragraph
is buying his first unit, then his profit is 30 - p; if the seller is
selling her second unit (having already sold one earlier), then
her profit is p - 15. (If p lies between 15 and 30, then both
make a profit.) The market remains open until no one can
agree on a price for consummating any further sales. Since
the experimenters have fixed the schedules so that the "ceil-
ing" on acceptable prices for a buyer gets lower and lower with
each purchase, and the "floor" on acceptable prices for a seller
gets higher and higher with each sale, there will always come
a time when it is no longer possible for a buyer and seller both
to make a profit. 14 The market closes at this point.
14 The seller's floor ultimately becomes higher than the buyer's ceiling.
Public Goods, Externalities, and the Commons 327
16 With no exernality, the bargaining range for pis 15 to 30. With the exernal-
ity, this range becomes 16 to 29.
328 Analyzing Politics
ir. The reader should not think that l am being unfair here in placing the tax
only on the seller, smce some of it will be passed on to the buyer in negoti·
ating a final purchase price.
Public Goods, Externalities, and the Commons 329
17 The reader should note that in taking account of the external effects of
transactions, this solution does not eliminate externalities altogether.
Rather, the damage done by the externality is balanced against the benefit
that accrues from allowing buyers and sellers to capture gains from ex-
change. In general, we typically do not, as a matter of public policy, wanL to
drive negative externalities to zero because this would mean passing up
profitable exchan ges.
330 Analyzing Politics
is Although I will not trouble the reader with details, in the running example
from the experiment., a tax of ten points per sale will still permit some sales
to be consummated, though a smaller number than in the absence of the
tax. If we had not been sure about the damage done by externalities, and
(incorrectly) guessed that instead of one unit per person the damage was
two units per person, the tax (now twenty units per sale) would have com-
pletely shut the market down. No sales would have occurred. Thus, mis-
taken guesses about the right tax or subsidy rate may make matters worse
than no tax or subsidy at all.
Public Goods, Externalities, and the Commons 331
19
The entire story is told in Bruce Ackerman and William Hassler, Clean
Air I Dirty Coal (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1981).
332 Analyzing Politics
Sitting just outside the office in which these words are being
written is the Cambridge Common, a lovely urban public
place most famous for the fact that it was there that General
George Washington mustered the twelve hundred volunteers
of what became the Continental Army in 1776. Publicly owned
parks and land reserves are today the object of great passion
by those who place significant value on "green space." In an
earlier time in Europe (and still today in various parts of the
world), commons were valued for more practical reasons-
notably as places to graze cattle and to forage. 20 Today, exam-
ples of commons include not only green space and sites for
grazing and foraging but also bodies of water utilized for com-
mercial fishing, irrigation systems, urban water supplies, and,
indeed, even the earth's atmosphere. 21
A commons is, by definition, owned by everyone (in com-
mon), and therefore is the responsibility of no one. Consider a
field owned by a village and used by its residents' herds as a
grazing commons. Each villager gets to graze his or her cattle
"for free." If a villager is contemplating adding a head to his
herd, he will take into account his costs of doing so, but this
calculation will not include the cost of grazing. If the commons
is large, and the village demands on it minimal, this will not
pose serious problems. But even if demands on the commons
grow, no villager has an incentive to restrict his use of this
"free" resource, resulting in what Garrett Hardin called "the
20 Several hundred years ago in England and elsewhere, there were political
move ments t hat succeeded in enclosing common lands, that is, dividing
them into parcels and distributing or selling them to individuals as private
property. 'fhe modern co unterpart of this practice is the sale of state-owned
assets (privatization) in both socialist and capitalist economies. '
21 The most insightful discussion of "common pool problems," of which these
are examples, is Elinor Ostrom, Governing the Commons (New York: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1990). Os trom was awa1·ded the Nobel Prize in
Economic Sciences in 2009 for this work.
336 Analyzing Politics
n Garrett Hardin. "The Tragedy of the Commons," Science 162 (1968): 1243-
48. This now cla;;sic paper is must reading for the interested student.
Public Goods, Externalities, and the Commons 337
CASE 10.2
FISHING AND THE
T RAGEDY OF THE COMMONS
----
340 Analyzing Politics
CONCLUSION
DISPLAY 10.2
COOPERATION, COLLECTIVE ACTION, PUBLIC GOODS
SUPPLY, EXTERNALITY CONTROL, COMMONS
GOVERNANCE: COMPARIS ONS
Behavior to Be
Problem Controlled Illustrative Solu t ion
Cooperation Defection Repeat play
Collective Action Free-riding By-products,
political entrepreneur
Public Good Supply Noncontribution Public provision
Externality Control Inattention to Tax/subsidy scheme
external effects
Commons Governance Overutilization Property rights
regime, gover-
nance structure
EXPERIMENTAL C ORNER
Punishing Free-R iders
Public goods, as we have seen, are underproduced because
individual incentives to contribute to their production are
weak. Especially in large anonymous groups, individuals
are strongly tempted to free-ride on the contributions of
others, since they can enjoy whatever public good is pro-
duced while avoiding any of its costs. Indeed, if the group is
large enough and anonymous enough, their failure to con-
tribute will often go unnoticed. Of course, they risk being
punished for their antisocial behavior, but then punishment
itself is costly for others so it is unlikely to be much of a
detriment to free-riding. But what if, despite its cost, people
did punish "irresponsible" behavior?
In a wonderful experiment, Fehr and Gachter demon-
strate that "free riding generally causes very strong nega-
tive emotions among cooperators and that there is a
widespread willingness to punish the free riders ... even if
punishment is costly and does not provide any material
benefits for the punisher."a Moreover, they show that the
punishment increases in severity the more the free riding
deviates from cooperative levels, so that the opportunity
and inclination to punish will have the effect of diminishing
free riding.b
Their public goods experiment has a no-punishment and
a punishment treatment. In the former, theory tells us that
there should be widespread free-riding, possibly undermin-
l. Write out an empty 2x2 chart like that in Display 10.1, and
then for each square develop an original illustrative example
of the type of good, explaining why your example is either ex-
cludable (or not) or jointly supplied (or not). Then, explain
what "problems" arise from nonexcludability and from joint-
ness of supply (or lack thereof!).
355
356 Analyzing Politics
2
The Senate has always prided itself on being "the world's greatest delibera-
tive body," and some defenders of the earlier rule on cloture believed that it
faci litated debate and deliberation by preventing the body from taking a
vote until an extraordinary majority felt there was nothing further to delib·
erate on or debat.e. Detractors, on the other hand, felt that the old cloture
rule was simply a procedural device behind which a disciplined minority
could extract concessions from the majority, if not defeat the majority's objec·
tives altogether. During the civil rights revolution, detractors had the votes
to pull ofJ the procedural coup described in the text (though southerners ac-
tually filibustered duri ng the debate on whether to change the cloture rule!).
The House limited debate in its formal rules more than a century earlier,
corning to the conclusion that no large gro up of politicians could be expected
to keep quiet long enough to take a vote unless forced to by institutional pro-
cedures.
Institutions: General Remarks 361
Specialization of Labor
In an institution, each actor is not a perfect copy of any other
actor. Instead, actors tend to have different talents, interests,
and preferences. Many institutions reflect this fact and make
good use of it, by specializing labor. Some professors, there-
fore, spend disproportionate amounts of time in the classroom;
others spend large amounts of time in the lab or library. Some
legislators specialize in particular policy areas, others special-
ize in different areas of policy, while still others remain gener-
362 Analyzing Politics
8
I have made much of the phenomenon in which a parent body delegates
authority and resources to its subunits because this organizational format is
so pervasive in the real world. Presumably it reflects a gain in the capacity
of an organization to achieve its goals, relative to what it would otherwise
achieve in a more centralized format. Delegation and decentralization, it
should be noted, are instances of a more general principal-agent relation-
ship. I do not have t ime to go into this in detail. Suffice it to say that when-
368 Analyzing Politics
CONCLUSION
1
The reader may wish to return to "Spatial Models of Legislatures" in Chap-
ter 5 for a quick review.
2 Chapters 8 and 9.
369
370 Analyzing Politics
UNDERLYING PROBLEMS
Majority Cycles
Preference heterogeneity and diversity mean, first and fore-
most, that no part icular view on public policy predominates in
the legislature. Were this not true-if, that is, a large propor-
tion of the members were more or less in agreement on how to
proceed- then the problem confronting a legislature would
merely be one of providing expedited procedures to enable this
374 Analyzing Politics
on a subject near and dear to his h eart (or those of his con-
stituents). This is a source of frustration, since, as we have
noted, the premise of instrume ntal behavior mea ns that legis-
lators would, if they could, concentrate whatever resources
they commanded on those subjects of highest priority to them.
In principle, this frustration could be alleviated by a sys-
tem of vote trading. Votes cannot literally be traded, but
promises about casting the m in particular ways can. Our
Philadelphia legislator can promise her Montana colleague to
vote as the latter wishes on an upcoming mining bill if the lat-
ter, in turn, supports the Philadelphian's preference on an up-
coming jobs bill. There are two problems (at least) with this
idea, however. First, can you imagine the negotiating and
bookkeeping complexities of a system of vote trading in any
but the s1nallest of assemblies? It's one thing to think through
an isolated bilateral exchange of votes. The sheer cost of or-
ganizing and sustaining a "market" in votes involving 435
traders across a myriad of issues boggles the mind. Second,
vote-trading agreements, like other deals among politician s,
are not enforceable contracts. If the Philadelphia legislator
casts her vote for the Montanan's mining bill, but the Mon-
tanan then reneges on his promise to vote for her jobs bill,
what can she do? She can certainly refuse to do business with
him in the fu ture, but she can't sue in a court for nonperfor-
mance of a contractual obligation. For both of these reasons, a
market in votes entails very high costs of transacting, and
thus is a very costly way to match legislator influence with
legislator interests.
It is sometimes thought that party leaders act as liaisons
in vote-trading transactions, matching up legislators inter-
ested in making exchanges, and generally facilitating the
making of deals. The problem with this view, indeed with
nearly any highly centralized manner for organizing ex-
change, is the almost superhuman burden on a leader to know
who is willing to trade what at what price. Again, in s mall so-
376 Analyzing Politics
Information
The refrain of many urban legislators in the last few decades,
like our Philadelphia congresswoman above, is "more jobs at a
living wage." This is a response both to the disappearance of
many jobs from most American cities (they gravitate to lower-
wage regions of the country or out of the country altogether to
lower-wage regions of the world) and, of those that remain,
the often unattractive wages, benefits, and career prospects
attached to them. Many legislative solutions to this serious
problem have been proposed. Some urge a higher minimum
wage; some mandate better fringe benefits-health care cover-
age, day care subsidies, pension benefits, parental leave poli-
cies, and so on; some underwrite training programs to
improve the productivity of workers; some advocate all these
things and more. What works? These are very complicated
matters; even those legislators for whom the problems are
most pressing are often quite unsure how to answer this
question.
If legislators voted directly for social outcomes, then this
wouldn't be a problem al all. The Philadelphia legislator could
simply offer a bill "mandating" more jobs at a better wage in
urban areas and, if it passed, then-abracadabral- the man-
dated effects would become a reality. Alas, legislators do not
vote for outcomes directly, but rather for instruments (or poli-
Legislatures 377
Compliance
The legislature is not the only game in town. The promulga-
tion of public policies is a joint undertaking in which courts,
executives, bureaucrats, and others participate alongside leg-
islators . If the legislature develops no means to monitor what
happens after a bill becomes law, then it risks public policies
implemented in ways other than those stipulated in the law.
Cooperation, that is, does not end with the successful passage
of a law. If legislators wish to have an impact on the world
around them, especially on those matters to which their con-
stituents give priority, then it is necessary to attend to policy
378 Analyzing Politics
With the stage thus set, I can now apply our framework for
analyzing institutional politics to legislatures. Throughout I
assume the legis lature consists of n legislators (where n = 435
for the U.S. House, n = 100 for the U.S. Senate, n - 650 for the
British H ouse of Commons, and so on). I maintain as working
premises that legislators are instrumen tal in seeking policies
that will please various of their constituents, that legislator
preferences over policy options arc heterogeneous, and that no
legislator preference is sufficiently numerous in the legisla-
ture as to be decisive. Finally, I assume that legislative policy
may be represented by a spatial formulation, with each di-
mension reflecting a n aspect of public policy salient to at least
some legislators. With these features as background, I argue
that legislators choose a division and specialization of labor,
regular procedure, a jurisdictional arrangement, and delega-
tion a nd monitoring technologies in order to facilitate coopera-
380 Analyzing Politics
tion and other gains from exchange. After making my case for
these claims, I will go on to analyze additional layers of insti-
tutional detail that constitute the operating features of real
legislatures.
3 Actually it is quite all right, and factually accurate in the case of the U.S.
Congress and most of the state legislatui·es, to allow members to serve on
more than one committee. What is normally forbidden is to give a member
no committee assignment.
382 Analyzing Politics
-
Legislatures 383
requirements for the two houses of Congress. But it also permits each house
to set its own rules, thereby giving the parent bodies tremendous discretion
to revise structural and procedural feat ures as they wish.
384 Analyzing Politics
may take them away from, their subunits. In this view, com-
mittees may be thought of as agents of the parent body to
whom jurisdiction-specific authority is provisionally delegated.
Of what does this delegation consist? I describe committee au-
thority in terms of gatekeeping power, proposal power, inter-
chamber bargaining power, and oversight authority.
In all of the dimensions of public policy falling within a
committee's jurisdiction, there is always some status quo policy
in place. It may be that the issue is new, in which case "cur-
rently doing nothing" is the prevailing policy. On other issues
there are well-established laws keeping a bevy of bureaucrats
and other government officials busy at implementation and ad-
ministration. At any time on any of these dimensions, a com-
mittee may choose to "open the gates" by proposing new
legislation to change the status quo ante. Although a slight ex-
aggeration, it is fair to say that 'in many legislatures commit-
tees have, in their jurisdiction, exclusive gatekeeping authority.
That is, it is practically impossible for the full legislature to
consider changes in the status quo in a committee's jurisdic-
tion unless the committee consents to open the gates. This
makes a committee an agenda monopolist in its jurisdiction.
A committee's agenda monopoly should be thought of as
provisional. It is a standing decision by the parent legislature.
At any time, however, the parent legislature can revise that
standing decision. This is the parent legislature's "club behind
the door." A committee, in exercising agenda power, is always
at risk of inducing the parent legislature to revise its agenda
authority. A second mechanism by which the parent legisla-
ture can discipline a committee is the discharge petition. This
is a temporary procedure in which the legislature, upon a ma-
jority of its members signing a petition, removes a particular
bill from the committee and brings it directly to the floor.
Closely related to gatekeeping is a committee's proposal
power. Normally, any member of the legislature can submit a
bill calling for changes in the status quo in some policy area.
Legislatures 385
CASE 12.1
CAMPAIGN CONTRIBUTIONS*
12 There is still controversy among scholars concerning this issue, but it mainly
involves the very thorny problems of measuring preferences of real legisla-
tors. The most committed of legislative jocks who want more on this sub-
ject, may find it for the period through the mid-1970s in Shepsle, 'l'he Giant
Jigsaw Puzzle. A study covering most of the postwar period up through the
early 1990s is Gary W. Cox and Mnthew D. McCubbins, Legislative
Leviathan (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993). Also see their
Setting the Agenda (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2005).
13
I remarked earlier that it would be quite accidental if xm • x, but quipped
that accidents do happen. We now know why. Because generalist commit-
tees have such pervasive policy impacts on the welfare of a large number of
different constituencies, the legislature explicitly stacks these committees
so that the committee median is relatively close to the chamber median.
This is what it means to make these committees "representative."
Legislatures 393
14 The careful reader might note that because their jurisdictions are of rele·
vance to narrow constitutencies, specialist committees really don't need to
be monitored clasely since their policy effects are confined. While this is
true most of the t ime, it is not always true. In particular, whenever propos·
als en tail the expenditure of revenues, they have implications for the activ·
ities of every other committee, since these expenditures draw from the
same common revenue pool from which other committees hope to draw.
Most of the House would not be pleased with an Agriculture Committee, for
example, that proposed a level of price support for agricultural products
that consumed a large proportion of the annual public budget.
394 Analyzing Politics
1
~ (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1991).
Legislatures 395
16 Evidence on this may be found in one of the classics of this literature, John
Ferejohn, Pork Barrel Politics (Stanford, Calif.: Stanfot·d University Press,
1974). For an alternative perspective, see Robert M. Stein and Kenneth N.
Bickers, Perpetuating the Pork Barrel (New York: Cambridge University
Press, 1995). For an excellent recent study, also see Diana Evans, Greasing
the Wheels (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2004).
17 Nevertheless, in the 1960s it was rumored that Charleston, South Carolina,
was sinking under the weight of all the naval installations the chair of the
House Armed Services Committee, Mendel Rivers, had managed to secure
for his district. J\.fore recently, there has been concern that the same fate is
being suffered by the state of West Virginia, whose powerful senior senator,
Robert Byrd, the chair of the Senate Appropriations Committee and former
majority leader, !has managed to entice numerous government agencies to
relocate to his state from Washington, D.C.
396 Analyzing Politics
CASE 12.2
INTEREST GROUP I NFLUENCE
C ONCLUSION
FIGURE 12.1
DIMENSION Y
•7
•4 •5 •6
•3
• •2
1
DIMENSION X
FIGURE 12.2
DIMENSION Y
•2
•p
•1 •q •3
DIMENSION X
FIGURE 12.3
0 p v c f 1
If the status quo lies between c and f, can the Congress secure
implementation of any preferable law? What if it lies between
u and c, or p and u, or to the right off? How does this help us
understand the circumstances that generate gridlock?
407
408 Analyzing Politics
I NTERGOVERNMENTAL R ELATIONS, I :
B UDGET-MAXIMIZING B UREAUCRATS AND
A P ASSIVE L EGISLATIVE SPONSOR
Motivational Considerations
The popular view of bureaucrats as failing to live up to the ex-
pectation that they will serve the public interest is judgmental
and emotionally laden, not analytical. In a now classic treat-
ment, the economist William Niskanen rejected this misbegot-
ten view entirely. 1 Instead, he proposed that we consider a
bureau or depart ment of government as analogous to a divi-
sion of a private firm, and conceive of the bureaucr at just as
Niskanen s Model
Imagine, then, a government bureau whose chief is interested
in eliciting as large a budget as his legislative overseers will
appropriate. The legislature, we assume, is inter ested in the
bureau's output-number of crimes solved, quality of weapons
procured, number of patients served, number of juveniles
counseled, number of high school students graduated. But,
like almost any other good or service, this preference for bu-
reau output increases at a decreasing rate (and may even turn
down after it reaches some level). In pecuniary terms, the leg-
islature (or more precisely, its median voter) is prepared to
pay more for the first unit of output than the tenth, and decid-
edly more for the first than the hundred and tenth. Its
willingness-to-pay curve (labeled B for ''budget") is graphed in
Figure 13.1. The quantity (Q) of the bureau's output is plotted
Bureaucracy and Intergo vernmental Relations 411
FIGURE 13.1
$
TC
"Profit"
L o· H Q
on the horizontal axis. The total budget in dollars that the leg-
islature is prepared to pay for various values of Q is on the
vertical axis. It is assumed that the bureaucrat knows this in-
formation about the legislature. Notice that the curve arcs
down, reflecting the marginally diminishing nature of the leg-
islature's preferences.2
A public bureaucracy, like a private firm, must institute a
production process to enable units of output to be produced. A
public hospital, for instance, looks just like a factory in many
FIGURE 13.2
$
TC
L o0 H o· 0
<= o~>
Variations on Niskanen
Niskanen's model of bureau behavior, although attractive for
a variety of reasons, is certainly not without controversy.
Whether or noit one "likes" the conclusions of a neoclassical
economist intrinsically suspicious of government, Niskanen,
to his credit, has laid all his assumptions out on the table
in full view. It is thus up to the critic to point to specific fea-
tures of the model that, if changed, would produce different
conclusions-not merely to criticize the conclusions. In this
way debate is focused on analytical or empirical features of a
theoretical argument, not on matters of taste and personal
ideology.
I will mention a few changes that might be considered,
though I hardly have the space to elaborate on forty years of
reaction to Niskanen's famous book. The first place to start is
with the matter of motives. I have defended Niskanen's
budget-maximization hypothesis from a variety of perspec-
tives, that should, at the very least, suggest to the reader that
it is not entirely off the mark. Nevertheless, there are alterna-
tives, and they are likely to produce very different views of bu-
reaucratic phenomena.
For example, suppose that bureaucrats cared not a whit for
their bureau's mission but mainly about the perquisites of
bureaucratic life they might enjoy-the so-called on-the-job
consumption that could be financed out of bureau revenues. If
they are able to camouflage their costs of production from the
416 Analyzing Politics
10 A good example is the Federal Trade Commission (F1'C) of the 1950s and
1960s. Today it is a ve1·y activist regulatory commission. But then it was
staffed by political cronies of the chairman of the congressional oversight
committee (the so·called "Tunnessee crowd") and, because it aimed mostly
to keep its head down and not make waves, the FTC was celled, among
other sobriquets, "the gentle matron of Pennsylvania Avenue."
11 Of course, it is likely that no single motivational hypothesis applies every·
where equally well.
418 Analyzing Politics
12
This and other related points are drawn from Gary J . Miller and Terry M.
Moe, "Bureaucrats, Legislators, and the Size of Government," American Po·
litical Science Review, 77 (1983): 297-323.
13
This takes the form in Niskanen's model of the bureau being permitted by
its legislative sponsor to select, from the latter's willingness-to-pay sched·
ule, a budget, B, And associated quantity, Q, of deliverable bureaucratic
product.
' ' Much like the parliamentary ministe r is manipulated by his wily senior
civil servants in the British television series, Yes, Minister.
Bureaucracy and Intergovernmental Relations 419
the alphabet soup agencies of the New Deal and World War II;
subsequent acts of Congress dismantled many of them.
So, while presidential signatures were required on these
congressional enactments and affirming judicial rulings were
needed to keep them alive, Congress can lay claim to pater-
nity (and maternity), birthing, and wet-nursing responsibili-
ties for the structure of the federal bureaucracy. Moreover,
Congress passed various pieces of legislation regarding both
personnel practices and administrative procedures, which
serve to regulate entry into, and advancement through, the
civil service on the one hand, and the official procedures by
which civil servants conduct bureaucratic business on the
other. Finally, as I emphasized in the previous chapter, Con-
gress maintains a constant presence in the affairs of the bu-
reaucracy through
• the drafting of laws revising and extending bureaucratic
authority;
• the approval of appropriations for the various divisions
of government; and
• the subsequent ("continuously watchful") oversight of the
uses to which this authority and these resources are put.
It is difficult to square Niskanen's view of a dominant bu-
reaucracy manipulating its passive legislative masters with
this litany of facts. The bureaucracy is created by Congress
and sustained by Congress. Although there are bound to be oc-
casions in which a bureau chief pulls the wool over a legisla-
tor's eyes, and t here are surely times in which a department's
budget people use "blue smoke and mirrors" to misdirect con-
gressional inspectors, it is unlikely, I believe, for these abuses
to persist for ve·r y long-certainly not without the implicit ap-
proval of congressional players in the bureau's jurisdiction.
In fact, it is even something of a strain to square with
these facts the much more balanced view of Miller and Moe in
422 Analyzing Politics
15
Throughout, I will suppose that these elected politicians are legislators.
There is, in fact, an entire literature, known as the "Congressional Domi-
nance School," that explicitly stipulates that the bureaucracy is a creature
of legislative preferences. I would want to quali fy this, however, by empha-
sizing that other elected and appointed politicians-€specially the president
and judges-influence bureaucratic activity, too.
Bureaucracy and Intergovernmental Relations 423
Principal-Agent Relationships
Most people hire a doctor, lawyer, or contractor to tend to their
health, to draw up their wills and other legal papers, or to
renovate their !kitchen, respectively. In principle we could do
these things our selves, but in practice we find it more satisfac-
tory to spend our time and energy on other things. This is just
another way of saying that most of us reject self-sufficiency
and accept the superiority of market exchange. In effect, we
retain agents to act in our interest, agents whose specialized
knowledge and skills make them more effective in doing our
bidding than we could ourselves. In these relationships, each
of us is a principal, and the problem we face is that of control-
ling our agents.
When we hire a kitchen contractor, agreeing to pay him a
particular sum of money in exchange for renovation services
(typically stipulated in pages and pages of detailed specifica-
tions), we face the problem that we don't know how good he is
and often aren't able to detect the quality of workmanship at
the time it is performed. Suppose he used aluminum wiring
rather than copper wiring, something we unhappily discover
after a fire. Suppose he said he would use copper piping but in
fact used plastic piping (obtained cheaply from his brother-in-
law and hidden out of sight in the walls), something detected
only years later when the less reliable plastic pipe springs a
leak. Suppose he claimed to know how to assemble and install
the extra-fancy gourmet cooking surface we purchased, only to
concede (after our kitchen had been torn apart) that it was
more complicated than he had figured.
There are two broad categories of control mechanism en-
abling a principal to guard against opportunistic or incompe-
tent agent behavior. The first is employed before the fact and
depends upon the reputation an agent possesses. One guards
against selecting an incompetent or corrupt agent (one who
cannot or will not perform with the principal's interests at
424 Analyzing Politics
16 These three authors have now written a large number of papers. The two
that will get the interested reader started are "Administrative Procedures
as Instruments of Political Control," Journal of Law, Economics, a1id Orga-
nization 3 (1987): 243-79; and "Structure and Process, Politics and Policy:
Ad ministrative Arrangements and the Political Control of Agencies," Vir-
ginia Law Review 75 (1989): 431- 83.
426 Analyzing Politics
17 Why, the reader might wonder, would poli ticians care about what happened
after they retired Crom political life? The reason is that the constituencies
they represent, and who reward them in the here and now for "good deeds,"
have long time horizons. Since they care about the long term, they are pre·
pared to reward politicians who attend to the long term. Thus, politicians
will do their bidding, thereby attempting to influence policy even after their
active political life.
Bureaucracy and Intergovernmental Relations 427
FIGURE 13.3
RESOURCES
AUTHORITY
18 If the bureau must observe the financial restraint of not spending more
than has been appropriated (given by the component of x on the vertical di-
mension), then x' will simply slide down the side of the triangle to the point
that is the same height as x.
Bureaucracy and Intergovernmental Relations 429
CASE 13. 1
CONGRESSIONAL O VERSIGHT:
P OLI CE P ATROLS, FIRE ALARMS,
AND FIRE E XTINGUISHERS
A GENCY SLIPPAGE
Budgetary Exploitation
From Niskanen we have seen that specialized bureaucratic
agents are very knowledgeable about the intricate details of
policy making in their jurisdiction, perhaps more so than even
specialists on legislative committees. Even though the latter
are themselves policy specialists, they have many other hats
to wear and roles to fill; they cannot devote the time and en-
ergy necessary to absorb all the arcane minutiae associated
with implementing a specific public policy. For bureaucratic
agents, on the other hand, these details are the core of their
434 Analyzing Politics
Bureaucratic Drift
If, on the other hand, authority and resources are used to pur-
sue other policy objectives, then .we have an instance of bu-
reaucratic drift, as described by McNollgast and depicted in
Figure 13.3. This follows from the ability of the bureaucrat to
exercise discretion in his or her pursuit of policy priorities
that may not have been warranted in statutory authority.
This policy drift, moreover, is protected from after-the-fact ret-
ribution as long as the bureaucrat is crafty enough to protect
against unanimous opposition from the components of the en-
acting coalition. In effect, if the bureaucrat can keep this key
senator or that house committee chair content, he or she may
be home free.
Bureaucracy an,d Intergovernmental Relations 435
Bureaucratic Capture
A third source of tension requires that I make some finer dis-
tinctions than heretofore. The bureaucratic drift that McNoll-
gast describes is the difference between the co1nprornise policy
arived at politically (x in Figure 13.3) and the policy imple-
mented bureaucratically (x'). In that figure, however, the care-
ful reader may have noticed that both the Senate (with ideal
point S) and the president (with ideal point P ) actually like x'
better than x. Only the House (with ideal point H) loses from
the drift in this particular example. If we retreat from the
myth that the Senate and House are unitary and possess ideal
points, instead more appropriately assuming that there are
435 ideal points scattered about H and 100 ideal points scat-
tered about S, then it is very likely that a number of represen-
tatives and senators sympathize more with the bureaucrat's
preferences than they do with either the political preference
arrived at in their legislative chamber (H and S, respectively,
in Figure 13.3) or the policy compromise arrived at among
House, Senate, a nd president (x). To push the argument one
step further, taking on board some of the factors I considered
in the previous chapter, it is likely that the committees with
jurisdiction over this bureaucracy and policy area are popu-
lated precisely with legislators who are more likely to sh ar e
the bureaucrat's preferences for larger bureaucratic output
than the preferences of their political colleagues for more
modest levels (i.e., an outlier committee). -They are in a posi-
tion to protect a drifting bureaucracy (through their gatekeep-
ing and other .agenda-control powers). Finally, behind these
legislators are the interest groups and geographic constituen-
cies whose well-being the legislators pursue; they, too, will be
pleased by the drift. Indeed, the traditional political science
literature makes frequent allusion to "cozy little tria ngles," in-
volving legislat()rs on key committees, bureaucrats, and inter-
est groups, as the dynamos behind policy implementation.
436 Analyzing Politics
Coalitional Drift
At the very outset of this discussion I noted that politicians not
only want the legislative deals they strike to be faithfully im-
plemented, they want those deals to endure-they want "deals
struck to stay stuck," as the inside-the-Beltway pundits put it.
This is especiaJly problematic in American political life with
its shifting alignments and absence of permanent political
cleavages. Today's coalition transforms itself overnight. Oppo-
nents today are partners tomorrow and the reverse. This
makes dealmakers inside the legislature, and their interest-
group backers in the hustings, insecure. A victory today, even
one implemented in a favorable manner by the bureaucracy,
may be undone tomorrow. What is to be done?
To some extent legislative structure leans against undoing
the handiwork of an enacting coalition. If such a coalition
votes handsome subsidies to grain farmers, say, it is very hard
to reverse this policy without the gatekeeping and agenda-
setting resources of members on the House and Senate Agri-
culture Committees; yet their members undoubtedly partici-
pated in the initial deal and are unlikely to turn against it.
But even these structural units are unstable, old politicians
departing and new ones enlisted. The problem, then, is that
CASE 13.2
How TO TEST NISKANEN?
CONCLUSION
1. The idea of term limits for elected legislators and for chairs
of legislative committees has been hotly debated for a quarter
of a century (while, of course, presidents have been term-
limited since ratification of the Twenty-second Amendment in
1951). In light of the principal-agent framework discussed in
this chapter, how might you attack the idea of term limits?
How would you defend it? Do the sa1ne arguments make sense
for bureaucrats?
" See Dennis Mueller, Public Choice III (New York: Cambridge University
Press, 2003), p. 365.
Bureaucracy and Intergovernmental Relations 443
Principal:
Agent: Audit Don't Audit
I o~·- 1 I 3~·-~ I
Work 0
Shirk
1 I also draw on the survey of Morris P. Fiorina and Kenneth A. Shepsle, "For-
mal Theories of Leadership: Agents, Agenda Setters, and Entrepreneurs," in
Bryan D. Jones, eel., Leadership arid Politics (Lawrence: University Press of
Kansas, 1989): 17-41. The interested reader should consult this essay for an
elaborated version of the argument found in this chapter.
445
446 Analyzing Politics
2 Some years ago there was a New Yorker cartoon showing a formation of
geese, minus itis leader at the apex, flying off, with the "lead" goose scram-
bling to get out in front.
Leadership 447
a James Hopkins, ed., The Papers of Henry Clay, volume I (Lexington: Uni-
versity of Kentucky Press, 1959).
448 Analyzing Politics
CASE 14.1
FDR AND W ORLD WAR II
A leader is often placed in the difficult position of choosing
between what lUs or her followers want and what he or she
feels they need. This distinction was made especially clear
by the eighteenth-century English philosopher Edmund
Burke in his famous speech to the electors of Bristol. A
member of Parliament at the time running for reelection,
he made clear to his constituents that he would not go back
to Westminster as a mere delegate- someone who simply
represents and acts as an unreflective agent of constituency
opinion. Rather, he regarded himself as a trustee-someone
whose intelligence and expertise would be deployed in the
service of what he considered to be the best interests of his
constitutents. (Burke was defeated for reelection.) Henry
Clay, on the other hand, cast his role as Speaker as more
that of a delegate: "I obey rather your commands than
my own inclination." (Clay was reelected to that post for
fifteen years.) Should a leader continue to obey, or should
he follow his own inclination? The answer depends to a
large extent on how a leader interprets his mandate as an
agent.
In the years leading up to World War II, Franklin Roo-
sevelt was faced with a difficult dilemma. He followed the
Nazi march through Europe with great alarm. Public opin-
ion in the United States at the time was decidedly isolation-
ist, but Roosevelt saw a need to begin providing aid to
Great Britain a nd to prepare the country for war. He be-
lieved that delaying mobilization until Germany posed an
immediate threat to the United States would be too late.
Leadership 451
6
By "must" I do not mean these things are inviolable laws of nature. like grav·
ity or the first law of thermodynamics. Rather, some things are so fundamen·
tat to a group that its very existence depends upon accomplishing them.
Failure to do so risks having the group replaced or its jurisdiction altered.
Leadership 453
that off the agenda). Since a leader cannot afford to get rolled
too frequently-if this occurs, it becomes increasingly difficult
for an agent to convince her principals that she has their in-
terests at heart- she will want to give careful consideration to
the distribution of preferences among those she leads. Like-
wise, in deciding to exercise an after-the-fact control mecha-
nism like rolling the chair, a follower must determine exactly
how much damage this will inflict on a leader he otherwise
thinks is satisfactory. 6 In short, care must be exercised to de-
tect but not to cross any number of rather fuzzy lines. In the
end the chair can extract some agenda advantages (an un-
avoidable form of agency slippage), but she must be prudent,
not piggish. This problem is normally least serious at the be-
ginning of a chair's term; at the end of a chair's term in office,
especially one who would like to retire to her own work,
agency slippage becomes more problematic (the so-called end-
game problem).
I have developed the interaction over agenda setting be-
tween a chair and her colleagues in a university department,
not only because it is interesting in its own right (at least to
the author, whose life is substantially affected by this agency
relationship), but also because it is an exemplar of the oppor-
tunities possessed by leaders of groups in general to trade off
satisfying the preferences of their followers in order to secure
some of their own objectives. Refining the group's agenda is
one of the standard activities that a group delegates to a
leader (or an agenda committee). In doing so, there is ordinar-
ily an awareness in the group that a "pound of flesh" will be
exacted by the leader-agent. Politically savvy choices, by the
group in selecting the leader and by the leader in exercising
her agenda authority, place limits on this "compensation."
Should those limits be breached, revolt soon follows.
6 He will also have to weigh the consequences of trying, but failing, to roll the
chair. The age-old adage applies: "If you go after the king, you had better get
him."
Leadership 455
7
Th e Speaker is often instrumental, moreover, on exactly who serves on
which committee. Until 1910 in th e House of Representatives, th e Speaker
made all committee assignments. Even after that date, up to the present,
the Speaker's influence is felt in this absolutely crucial institutional process.
In other legisla tures, the Speaker or equivalen t ins titutional officer remains
the pivotal person in terms of committee assignments. And, of course, in
other venues, the leader is often decisive in this respect. In most academic
456 Analyzing Politics
departments, for example, t he chair composes committees. If, from our ear-
lier example, the department chair did not want to promote a junior col-
league to tenure, yet felt constrained from keeping the matter off the agenda
entirely, she could influence the result by having the candidate reviewed by
an artfully crafted committee t hat is likely to reflect her own doubts.
Leadership 457
ordering (so tha t if the first choice were to decline the offer,
she would know to whom to turn next), she could suggest that
each voting faculty member write down a single name-and
candidates would be ranked in terms of the total votes each
got~r that each faculty voter submit a complete rank-
ordering, from which a group rank-ordering would be derived
(see Chapter 4). Indeed, as Chapter 7 makes clear, many dif-
ferent voting systems might be employed in this circumstance,
any one of which the chair could defend by appealing to at-
tractive criteria the voting system satis fied. If she has kept
her ear to the ground, she will be able to make this "sugges·
tion" in an informed strategic fashion. Such are the agenda-
setting opportunities with which a leader is presented.
8
Th e classics in the leadership literature emphasizing entrepreneurs ar e
Rich ard Wagner, "P ressure Groups and Political Entrepreneurs," Papers on
Non-Market Decision Making 1 (1966): 161-70; and Norman Frohlich, J oe
Oppenheimer, and Oran Young, Political Leadership and Collective Goods
(Princeton, N.J. : Pr inceton University Press, 1971).
458 Analyzing Politics
9
The author, while interviewing congressional staff in the early 1980s, ruscov-
ered that it was not uncommon for a legislative staff director to assign
staffers to monitor committee hearings around Capitol Hill with the instruc·
tion, "Find something useful for the boss." Members of Congress, that is,
often shop around for issues that they believe they can convert to some use-
ful purpose for the mselves.
460 Analyzing Politics
CASE 14.2
ONLY N IXON COULD Go TO CHINA
11
'l'his compensation comes in various forms, not the least of which is the op·
portunity for the leader to sq ueeze pr ivate advantage out of her agenda set·
ting powers, something discussed earlier in this chapter.
464 Analyzing Politics
D ISPLAY 14.1
12 This keeps the math manageable while at the same time allowing the ana-
lyst to see what happens to the leader over time.
Leadership 467
CONCLUSIO N
473
474 Analyzing Politics
1
Richard A. Posner, "What Do Judges and Justices Maximize? (The Same
Thing Everybody Else Does)," Supreme Court Economic Review 3 (1993):
1- 41. Quotation on page 2.
2 Of course, in some s.tat es and localities judges are elected at regular inter-
vals, thus making them much more like other elected politicians. However,
judges on higher courts, in both state and federal systems, are typically ap-
pointed to lifetime posts.
Courts and Judges 475
Dispute Resolution
So much of the productive activity that occurs within families,
among friends and associates, even between absolute strang-
ers takes place because the participants do not have to devote
substantial resources to protecting themselves and their prop-
erty or monitoring compliance with agreements.4 For any po-
tential violation of person or property, or defection from an
agreement, a ll parties know in advance that an aggrieved
party may take an alleged violator to court. The court, in turn,
serves as a venue in which the facts of a case are established,
punishment meted out to violators, and compensation
a warded to victims. The court, therefore, is an institution that
engages in fact finding and judgment.
Many disputes are between private parties, so the court
a The term justice is reserved for members of the U.S. Supreme Court. All
other judges are called "judges," although some judges low in the pecking
order are referred to as "magistrates." (However, entirely inconsistent with
this nomenclature, one of the lowest categories of judges is "justice of the
peace.") Throughout we will si mply call all of them, with due respect, judges.
4 Naturally, some resources are devoted to protection and monitoring. How-
Coordination
Dispute resolution occurs after the fact- that is, after a dis-
pute has taken place. In a manner of speaking, it represents
a failure of the legal system, since one function of law and its
judicial institutions is to discourage such disputes in the first
instance. We may also think of courts and judges as before-
the-fact coordination mechanisms inasmuch as the anticipa-
tion of what happens once their services are called upon allows
private parties to form rational expectations and thereby co-
ordinate their actions in advance of possible disputes. A pro-
spective embezzler, estimating the odds of getting caught,
prosecuted, and subsequently punished, may think twice (or
even three or four times) about cheating his partner. Surely,
some prospective embezzlers are deterred from their crimes by
these prospects. Two acquaintances, therefore, may much
more confidently entertain the possibility of going into busi-
ness together because their partnership will flourish (or fail)
"in the shadow of the law." The sword (or is it the scales?) of
justice hangs over their collaboration.
In this sense, the court system (like the dog in Sir Arthur
Conan Doyle's story "Silver Blaze") is as important for what it
doesn't do as for what it does. 5 The system of courts and law
coordinates private behavior by providing incentives and dis-
incentives for specific actions. To the extent that these work,
there are fewer disputes to resolve and thus less after-the-fact
dispute resolution for courts and judges to engage in. What
makes the incentives and disincentives work is their power
(are the rewards and penalties big or small?), their clarity, and
the consistency with which judges administer them. Bright-
line incentives (clearly defined standards that leave little or no
room for varying interpretation), consistently employed, pro-
6 In this Sherlock Holmes adventure, the key to solving the mystery was that
a certain dog did not bark.
478 Analyzing Politics
Rule Interpretation
Dispute resolution and coordination tremendously affect pri-
vate behavior and the daily lives of ordinary citizens. Judges,
however, are not entirely free agents (despite the fact that
some of them are tyrants in their courtrooms). In matching
the facts of a specific case to judicial principles and statutory
guidelines, judges must engage in interpretive activity. They
must determine what particular statutes or judicial principles
mean, which of them fit the facts of a particular case, and
then, having determined all this, the disposition of the case at
hand. Does the statute of 1926 regulating the electronic trans-
mission of radio waves apply to television, cellular phones,
ship-to-shore radios, fax machines, or electronic mail? Does
the law governing the transportation of dangerous substances,
passed in 1937, apply to nuclear fuels, infected animals, or ar-
tificially created biological hazards? Often, the enacting leg-
islative body has not been crystal clear about the scope of the
legislation it passes. Indeed, a legislature acting in 1926 or
1937 hardly could have anticipated technological develop-
ments a half century later. Nevertheless, cases come up on a
regular basis, and judges must make judgment calls, so to
speak, on highly complex issues.
Interpreting thE> rules is probably the single most impor-
tant activity in which higher courts engage. This is because the
court system is hierarchical in the sense that judgments by
higher courts constrain the discretion of judges in lower courts.
If the Supreme Court rules that nuclear fuels are covered
by the 1937 law on transporting dangerous substances, then
Courts and Judges 479
people" in the sense that they do their jobs with an eye at least
partly on advancing in their world (however they conceive of
it). The program manager at the Mellon Foundation hopes to
become a vice president at the Rockefeller Foundation and, be-
yond that, perhaps the president of the Ford Foundation. 'rhe
dean of students at a small liberal arts college may aspire to
be dean of admissions at the state university and, beyond that,
perhaps dean of undergraduate education at an Ivy League
college or university. The local director of United Way may
harbor ambitions to rise through that bureaucracy to regional
and then national office. In this manner, "unter" judges hope
some day to become "ilber" judges. Federal district judges hope
for promotion to one of the Courts of Appeals, and "great men-
tioners" in Washington always have their list of appeals court
judges as candidates for the Supreme Court (The recently con-
firmed Justice Sonia Sotomayor is an apt illustration.)
Ambition for advancement, then, substitutes as a standard
for other forms of performance-based compensation. But, as
Posner notes, ambition cannot be a tremendously strong moti-
vation because the odds of advancement, even for the very
highest performing judges, are remote. It is probably more
likely that a dean of students at a high-quality midwestern
liberal arts college can become admissions dean at an Ivy
League institution than that a federal district judge will move
up the judicial hierarchy to the Supreme Court. My view,
then, is that individual judges, like other nonprofit profession-
als, rationalize the energy and commitment they invest in
their jobs by their desire for popularity, prestige, and reputa-
tion. They value these things partly for their own sake be-
cause standing among one's peers and within one's community
is part of the nature of all human beings, a perspective that
goes back at least to Aristotle. But they also value them be-
cause they conceive of these things as necessary attributes for
advancement, however remote the latter possibility might be.
In their heart of hearts, I suspect, many judges probably ex-
484 Analyzing Politics
draft, why one side or the other should win. Judges vote not
only with ballots but also with ideas-ideas about the facts,
about judicial principles, about legal reasoning, and about
moral values. It is through the opinions they draft, rather
than the ballots they cast, that judges may influence a wider
collection of interests, since these opinions serve to constrain
lower-court judges in similar cases in the future. 7
Legislators in Robes
In many models of legislative politics, legislators are thought
of as policy oriented. In the spatial model (as described in
Chapter 5), for example, a legislator (or, in Chapter 16, a po-
litical party), is characterized by an ideal policy and prefer-
ences that decline as one moves spatiaJly more distant from
that ideal policy. It is often unnecessary for the purposes of
Courts and Judges 487
CASE 15.l
THE B EST JUDGES M ONEY C AN BUY?
8 For a critical review, the reader may consult Jeffrey A. Segal, "Separation-of-
Powers Games in the Positive Theory of Congres and Courts," American Po-
litical Science Reuiew 91 (1997): 28-44. The original paper on which the
preceding is based is Brian A. Marks, "A Model of Judicial Influence on Con-
gressional Policymaking," Working Papers in Political Science, P-88-7,
Hoover Institution, Stanford, Calif., 1988. Unfortunately, it has never been
published.
492 Analyzing Politics
DISPLAY 15.1
Sequ ence of t he Policy Game
Step Player Action
0 xQ in place
FIGURE 15.1
0 100
11
Recall from the analysis of the McNollgast model in Chapter 13 that any
point in the subinterval between xH and x5 (including its endpoints) is an
equilibrium in the sense that any movement away from one of these points
will be opposed by either the House or the Senate (or both). Since a legisla·
tive reaction to an agency decision requires the assent of both the House
and the Senate, these points constitute equilibria.
Courts and Judges 495
CONCLUSION
C ASE 15.2
L EGISLATORS IN R OBES REVISITED
make the rules; they apply them. The role of an umpire and a
judge is critical ... but it is a limited role .... It's my job to
call balls and strikes, and not to pitch or bat." Explain in your
own words Roberts's vision of the role of courts. What judicial
role was he emphasizing, and what others was he implicitly
criticizing? Then, assess Justice Roberts's metaphor overall. Is
it sufficient for a Supreme Court justice to just "call balls and
strikes"?
• For further elaboration on these questions, see David Rohde and Kenneth
Shepsle, "Advising and Consenting in the 60-Vote Senate: Strategic Appoint-
ments to the Supreme Court," Journal of Politics, 69 (2008): 664-77.
b John Ferejohn and Barry Weingast, "A Positive Theory of Statutory Inter-
pretation," International Review of Law and Economics, 12 (1992): 263-79.
502 Analyzing Politics
503
504 Analyzing Politics
Governmental A rrangements
In parliamentary regimes there is a division and specializa-
tion of labor. Tihe House of Commons does not run British
politics. Nor does the Dutch 'Iiveede Kamer, the German
Bundestag, the Japanese Diet, or the Norwegian Starting run
the politics of the Netherlands, Germany, Japan, or Norway,
respectively. Rat her, each parliament "elects" a government to
serve as the executive arm of the regime. I thus need to de-
scribe exactly what a "government" is on the one hand, and
how a country's parliament "elects" one on the other.
The politica] executive in a parliamentary democracy is,
with a few exceptions that I won't stop to consider here, cho-
sen by parliament. This executive is called the government; it
is also known as the cabinet or council of ministers. It is a col-
lection of senior politicians each of whom is the head of a de-
partment or ministry of state. In nearly every parliamentary
regime there is a finance minister, foreign minister, interior
minister, defense minister, justice minister, education minis-
ter, environment minister, and so on.
Thus, there is a division and specialization of labor at two
different levels. The first distinguishes between legislature
and executive. The legislature selects the executive in the first
place; keeps it in place or replaces it with a different one; and
considers various pieces of legislation, the most important of
which is the annual budget. 3 I will discuss these features mo-
3 It should be noted that legislatures in parliamentary regimes are not the
hyperactive lawma king engines we encounter in the American setting. Typi-
cally, parliaments vote a few broad delegations of statutory authority which
are then implemeroted by the government. In the United States, on the other
hand, Congress and the various state legislatures legislate with much
greater frequency and in a much more fine-grained fashion.
506 Analyzing Politics
& In effect, each party may be treated as a unitary actor. Unlike legislative
parties in the United States, which contain within them a wide range of
opinion and whose members are relatively free to pursue their own private
objectives, parliamentary parties are far more homogeneous in terms of pol-
icy preferences, and their leaders have powerful mechanisms by which to
control the rank and file. Parliamentary party leaders, of course, must keep
their followers happy, as I argued more generally in Chapter 14, but they
may proceed in a manner that is best for their party as a whole. In effect,
then, we may think of the parliamentary party as acting as if it had well·
defined preferences, as manifested in the beliefs and choices made by its
leaders.
508 Analyzing Politics
A MENAGERIE OF GOVERNMENTS
8
In Great Britain in 1994, the Conservative government of Prime Minister
John Major was a unified government, but only tenuously so. It had a bare
majority in the House of Commons and thus was potentially vulnerable to
factional blackmail from within its partisan ranks. In parliamentary votes
on expanding the role of the European Union in the spring of 1994, so-called
Euroskeptics inside the Conservative Party threatened to desert the govern-
ment (which favored further European integration). Major called their bluff
and won ... that time.
Cabinet Government and Parliarnentary Democracy 511
TABL E 16.1
P ARLIAMENTARY GOVERNMENT FORMS*
9 If one of the governing parties pulls out, then, as we noted earlier, a n actual
vote of no confidence need not occur. If t he parties remaining in the govern-
ment believe they no longer have the s upport of parliament, the government
may simply resign, triggering a new round of government formation. Alter-
natively, the prime minister may petition the head of state to dissolve parlia-
ment and call for new elections.
512 Analyzing Politics
12 If, as is often the case in the real world, there are more than the four par·
ties in the example (say, p in number), and more than two portfolios (say, q
in number), then there are pq possible ways to divvy the portfolios up
among parties, and thus pq possible governments. Even for moderate values
of p and q, this number can grow rather large. With ten parties (as was ap-
proximately t he case at various times in countries like Belgium or Italy)
and fifteen government ministries, for instance, there are ten million billion
different conceivable governments. We would have to harvest an entire for-
est to print a list like the one in Display 16.1!
516 Analyzing Politics
D ISPLAY 16.1
POSSIBLE P ORTFOLIO ALLOCATIONS IN THE B UNDESTAG
P a r ty holding
Fin ance p ortfolio (F) For e ig n Affa irs po r tfolio (FA)
1. CD CD
2. CD SD
3. CD FD
4. CD G
5. SD CD
6. SD SD
7. SD FD
8. SD G
9. FD CD
10. FD SD
11. FD FD
12. FD G
13. G CD
14. G SD
15. G FD
16. G G
DISPLAY 16.2
OFFICE-SEEKING P ARTY P REFERENCES OVER
ALTERNATIVE G E RMAN G OVERNMENTS*
CD SD FD G
{l} {6} {11} {16}
{2, 3, 4} {5, 7, 8} {9, 10, 12} {13, 14, 15}
{5, 9, 13} {2, 10, 14} {3, 7, 15} {4, 8, 12}
{6, 7, 8, 10, 11, {1, 3, 4, 9, 11, {l, 2, 4, 5, 6, {1, 2, 3, 5, 6,
12, 14, 15, 16} 12, 13, 15, 16} 8, 13, 14, 16} 7, 9, 10, 11}
* The numbers in each column refer to the goverments listed in Display
16.1. A party prefers higher-listed to lower-listed governments and is in-
different among bracketed governments.
-
OFFICE-SEEKING. The first, the office-seeking motivation, as-
sumes that parties care only about getting into office. Thus,
the CDs, in looking over the possibilities in Display 16.1, will
most like government 1, giving them both portfolios. If they
car e more about financial matters than foreign affairs (and I
will assume this, for the sake of argument, for all parties),
they will next prefer governments 2, 3, and 4 (among which
they are indifferent), giving them the Finance portfolio and
some other party the Foreign Affairs portfolio. Next they will
prefer governments 5, 9, and 13 in which they get the Foreign
Affairs portfolio and some other party gets Finance; again,
they are indifferent among these three governments. Finally,
they least prefer (and are indifferent among) governments 6,
7, 8, 10, 11, 12, 14, 15, and 16, in which they are excluded
from government altogether. Display 16.2 gives the office-
seeking preferences of each of the four parties.
Since we know which combinations of parties constitute
Bundestag major ities (the bulleted list above), we can com-
pute majority p1·eferences over the sixteen possible govern-
518 Analyzing Politics
ia I also note that it doesn't matter for our purposes whether a party is "re-
ally" committed to the policies it pursues (ideological parties), or instead
whether it does so only to secure electoral benefits from satisfied con-
stituents (instrumental parties).
520 Analyzing Politics
FIGURE 16.1
FOREIGN
POLICY
ECONOMIC POLICY
16 This evidence is found in Laver and Shepsle, Making and Breaking Govern-
ments, chapters 6-9.
17 Informal proof- Suppose x and y are two lattice points. Logically, either x is
FIGURE 16.2
FOREIGN
POLICY
1 - - - - - - + --
SD
G
ECONOMIC POLICY
CONCLUSION
•See Dennis Mueller, Public Choice III (New York: Cambridge University
Press, 2003), pp. 280-81.
Cabinet Government and Parliamentary Democracy 529
3. Draw two sets of axes ranging from 0 to 10, with one dimen-
sion representing Finance a nd the other Defense, and suppose
that there are three parties (A, B, and C) with ideal points
(1, 2.5), (3.5, 1) and (9, 7). Any coalition of two parties (with
one controlling each portfolio exclusively) is sufficient for a
majority government, but no one party has an outright major-
ity. What is the set of possible minority and majority govern-
ments? Is there a stable majority government coalition (i.e.,
with an empty winset)? Is there a minority government that is
a stable equilbrium (if we assume that no party can be forced
into a government against its will)? Illustrate all of your an-
swers graphically and briefly explain your logic, taking special
care to explain how minority governments come about.
To summar ize this volume in all but the most superficial fash-
ion is more than the reader is likely willing to tolerate. So I do
so superficially. Part I provided the basic building blocks for
political analysis- individuals, their preferences, and their
beliefs. I emphasized there the importance of analysis and,
with the rational choice paradigm, I nailed my colors to the
mast by laying out an analytical approach.
Part II focused on group choice by voting. I demonstrated
that groups, unlike individuals, could not always be treated as
unitary because the aggregated preferences of group members
did not always add up. Neither the method of majority rule
nor, from Arrow's Theorem, any other "reasonable" method of
preference aggregation can guarantee rational group prefer-
ences. This fact, in turn, means that individuals controlling
motion making and other agenda mechanisms can strategi-
cally manipulate things to their advantage. Combine this with
the fact that there are many ways in which to stage an elec-
tion or structure a vote, and the bottom line is that the result
of group deliberation is, in many respects, artifactual. It is de-
pendent on the individual preferences and beliefs of group
members, to be sure. But it also depends upon who makes
motions, in what order motions are made, what the voting
rule is, and many other features besides. One might well want
the outcome of group choice to depend on individual prefer-
ences and beliefs. But it is considerably less clear that it is de-
530
Final Lessons 531
535
536 Index
preference aggregat ion, 73, 77-78, plurality voting systems and, 203-
195 4, 215- l 7
preference diversity, 41-42, 372 proposal power, 384
preference heterogeneity, 371-74, Proposition 174 (CaUfornia), 138
390 Protestant work ethic, 156
preference ordering public goods
Arrow's Theorem on, 69-70 common lands problem, 335- 42
Condorcet's paradox and, 55-56 dcfined,307
defined,25 defining terms, 306-9
society and, 60 excludability, 307, 309
preference revelations, 43 externalities, 325-34
presidential vetoes, 167-69 jointness of supply, 307- 9
PricewaterbouseCoop ers, 213 policy-relevant information and,
prime minister, 506 377
principal-agent relati:onship politics and, 309-14
Congressional oversight, 431-32 property rights and, 323-24
denned, 367n public supply, 314- 23
enacting coalitions. 425 punishing free-riders, 344-48
intergovernmental r elations and, radio spectrum as, 323-24
420- 30 scientific knowledge as, 318-20
leadership and, 448 public supply
parliamentary regimes and, 506 cap-and-trade program, 322-23
Prisoners' Dilemma collective action and, 315
about, 236n deregulation and, 323
altruism and trust in, 253-59 interstate highway system, 316-
common lands problem and, 337 17
Mafioso Dilemma and, 246-47 national defense and, 317- 18
marsh-draining game a nd, 244 politica l intervention and, 314-15
private goods privatization and, 322
defined, 306-7 railio spectrum and, 323- 24
excludability, 307, 309 scientific knowledge, 318-21
jointness of supply, 307-9 time horizons, 321
privatization, 322 Pirate Radio (film), 324
privileged groups pure majority rule, 125-34
agenda power and, 131
Olson on, 292, 318, 429 radio spectrum, 323- 24
privileged motion, 146 rational choice model
problem of order, 234 actors in, 18-19, 30
procedural controls, 429 beliefs in, 16-17, 30- 33
producers in rational choice model, comparability property, 24, 27
18-19 defined, 13
production function, 270 environmental uncertainty and,
Profiles in Courage (Kennedy), Sn 30-33
property rights external environment in, 16
common lands problem, 335-42 maximization paradigm, 29-30
controlling externalities, 332 motivation in, 18-20
public goods and, 323- 24 preference in, 14, 20- 29
proportional representation self-interest in, 15
Cox on, 203- 4 transitivity property, 25- 26, 28,
Duverger's Law and, 6, 216 29n
electoral arrangements, 504 rational foresight, strategic behavior
examples, 214- 15 and, 159-70
546 Index
wor1~ w1:r
8
value restriction condition (Sen's n, 450-51 /
Theorem), 84 Wozniak, Steve, 363n
Verba, Sidney, 150
vetoes, presidential, 167-69 X, Malcolm, 458
vote of investiture, 507
voters, see also sophisticated voting; Yes, Minister (tv series), 4 l8n
strategic voting YouTube.com, 348
collective action and, 293-301
ideal point for, 114 zero-based budgeting, 132-33, 152
PRAISE FOR
Analyzing Politics
"Analyzing Politics is the single best source for
understanding how powerfully rational choice
theory has influenced the study of politics. It does
not dumb down the important core concepts, yet
it remains entertaining, vivid, and accessible. My
students not only read it-they love it!"
-James Fowler, University of California, San Diego
flf°f )