Jean-Paul Sartre S Notebooks For An Ethi
Jean-Paul Sartre S Notebooks For An Ethi
Jean-Paul Sartre S Notebooks For An Ethi
I
n his 1943 Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology1,
Jean-Paul Sartre concludes that the relationship with the other is always
characterized by conflict. No need to be a Sartre scholar to be familiar
with the quote L'enfer, c'est les autres or Hell is: Other People. In his 1960
Critique of Dialectical Reason 2 , the other is understood as the realm of
alienation: the other is that which can take hold of, control, our freedom. Like
in Being and Nothingness, the existence of the other results in a struggle for
freedom; this implies that the relationship with the other is always
characterized by conflict. In the following, I will focus on a text Sartre wrote
in the period between the publications of the two above-mentioned works,
more precisely on his exploration of the gift in his posthumous Notebooks for
an Ethics.3 Sartre’s interest in the debate on the gift was triggered by Marcel
Mauss, who inspired him to rethink the theme of the other—Sartre was at
that time looking for a way to think about the other as the other, a path, to be
sure, that he abandoned later on.4 I propose to follow this alternative route
by re-reading some passages on the gift as they appear in Notebooks for an
Ethics. Notebooks was written in 1947 and 1948 as an attempt to redeem a
promise formulated near the end of Being and Nothingness, namely to
elaborate on the ethical implications of the work and to publish an ethics in
the future. However Sartre left that project, and the texts remained
unpublished until 1983, three years after his death.5
(Paris: Presses universitaires de France, 2012). Translated as The Gift: The Form and
Reason for Exchange in Archaic Societies (New York: W. W. Norton, 1990).
5 Although the Notebooks is, as the title suggests, a bunch of sketches, it is easy to
read the text as a whole, since new themes are broached and related to each other
within the framework of the text, themes like violence, recognition, the appeal,
conversion and the Apocalypse, all in existentialist terms.
From a historical point of view, it is clear that Sartre like many other French
intellectuals at the time was highly impressed by Mauss’ famous essay on
potlatch and the gift, and by Georges Bataille's reaction to it.7 Sartre was well
Urzone, Inc. 1988). The first volume was originally published in France as La Part
Maudite in 1967. Sartre was acquinted with an article version of Bataille’s comments
on Mauss. It is likely that Sartre's friendship with Michel Leiris, who was friendly
with Bataille, is of crucial importance as well, as it was Leiris’ L’Afrique fantôme that
motivated Sartre to look at people and their relations in a different way and to take
Rousseau coined the term bon sauvage to refer to the primitive that is
uncorrupted by so-called civilization; he represents the anti-colonialist
stance, troubled by the guilt implied by Paul Gauguin’s gazing Tahitian
women. The Rousseauean position considers alienation the result of the
oppression and humiliation imposed by colonialists from a culture that is
alienated itself. Here, it is the Western gaze that violates the authenticity of
the primitive.9 Colonialism from this perspective is the violent oppression of
humanity, as opposed to being supportive of humanity. In retrospect, and
taking into account his political stance in the Algerian war, Sartre is the anti-
colonialist par excellence. However, his argument is entirely different than
the one that equates primitive with authentic. Contrary to Rousseauean noble
savage adepts, Sartre clearly distinguishes between oppression and
alienation.
serious notice of the works of Lévi-Strauss and Leiris’ early 1930 teacher Marcel
Mauss.
8 Lucien Lévy-Bruhl, La mentalité primitive (Paris: Presses universitaires de France,
1922), and Georges Dumézil, Mitra-Varuna – Essai sur deux représentations indo-
européennes de la Souveraineté, (Paris: Presses universitaires de France, 1940).
9 This anti-colonialist position is found in the Western Orientalist gaze as described
Sartre still faces the main problem of Being and Nothingness, the one that
arises from his supposition that the human condition is the ultimate
condition for radical freedom. Notebooks shares the ultimate Marxist goal,
which is to free humanity from oppression, but Sartre rejects the Marxist
argument that consciousness is determined by history and social class. To
Sartre, freedom is the ultimate consequence of being human. It is clear that
alienation and oppression are threatening this freedom, but in what way? In
Being and Nothingness, human reality is already ‘beyond-itself’: ‘Human
reality is in fact always being that is beyond its being there.’10 In Notebooks,
this ‘beyond’ equals the other: alienation is understood as the original quality
of the relation between the other and me.11 In other words: we humans are
not ‘the same,’ but we are alienated from each other. This is why alienation is
understood as the original relation between me and the other: the other is
other insofar as he is alienated from me. The other is other to us, insofar as
we are the other to him.12 Since we cannot but understand ourselves through
the agency—or rather the look, the perspective—of the other, we are
alienated to the depths of our being.13 This follows a line of reasoning Sartre
launched in Being and Nothingness, namely that there is no positive content,
no me-ness or innermost being in subjective being-for-itself anyhow.
Sameness, then, is not understood as same-subjectivity, but as ‘the internal
essence of each person insofar as it is frozen by the other’s look,’ as Sartre
writes in Notebooks.14 Our look constitutes our control over the other, because
through the look, the other is an object among other objects. This is where
oppression begins. Oppression is the use of the look. While alienation is
inherent to being-for-itself, oppression may be one of its effects. Sartre also
believes oppression is in a way contagious: ‘I oppress because I am
oppressed […]An oppressor is someone who transmits to others the
oppression that he undergoes.’15
Nothingness, finds itself ‘nothing’, ‘not being’ the other—hence, the Hegelian
influence. I will come to the role of the look.
14 Sartre, Notebooks, 367.
15 Ibid.
16 Sartre's views on this point are close to those of Lacan: he observes that the
individual is primarily the other, and that the individual’s sameness is actually a
construction of otherness. Clearly, he already recognized Lacan’s congeniality—and
quoted him—at the time he wrote Notebooks.
The gift
Since there are others, and since we live with others, alienation cannot be
overcome. In Being and Nothingness, we saw that it is the other who
annihilates my freedom: not owing to any bad intention, but simply because
the other co-exists with us. As mentioned above, Sartre’s ethics asks whether
it is possible to have a universe inhabited by co-existing being-for-itselfs, a
universe in which the other does not make us and our world into mere
objects—the latter of course implies that the other deprives us of our
freedom. What we need, and what Sartre is looking for in Notebooks, is
recognition of the freedom of the other, recognition that is ethically and
phenomenologically understood as a gift. Let us for a moment return to the
project of Being and Nothingness and reread Sartre’s consideration of the gift.
Mauss describes the role of the gift in a negative, destructive way and
understands the gift as something that is firstly material and secondly
economical.17 Sartre, for his part, rejects the notion of giving as a primitive,
even barbaric practice. He writes: ‘the gift casts a spell over the recipient’ and
‘to give is to appropriate by destruction while utilizing this destruction to
enslave another. Generosity then is a feeling structured by the existence of
the Other and indicates a preference for appropriation by destruction.’ 18
Apparently, generosity enslaves rather than liberates. That is the explicit
though limited part the gift plays in Being and Nothingness.
In the Notebooks, Sartre resumes his analysis more elaborately: ‘So we finally
come to the form of exchange that corresponds in this society to the
circulation of goods and that produces their accumulation in the form of
private property. This is the potlatch or subjugating gift. I indicated earlier
that in an alienated society, all behavior must be alienating, even generosity.
The potlatch is alienating generosity. At the level of the potlatch, the bond of
friendship is indiscriminately that of non-friendship, generosity is
indiscriminately subjugation, the gift of entering into debt, the
indemnification of interest.’19 It is clear that Mauss considers the potlatch an
act of both friendship and violence. According to Sartre, the gift is basically
reciprocal to the extent that it is the basis for an economy. However, he adds,
phenomenologically speaking, the period between the act of giving and the
reaction of the recipient basically mortgages the gift: the recipient is
17 Sartre, Being and Nothingness, 594, ‘Actually the gift is a primitive form of
destruction. We know for example that the potlatch involves the destruction of
enormous quantities of merchandise. These destructions are forbidden to the other;
the gifts enchain him. On this level it is indifferent whether the object is destroyed
or given to another; in any case the potlatch is destruction and enchaining of the
other. I destroy the object by giving it away as well as by annihilating it; I suppress
in it the quality of being mine, which constituted it to the depths of its being; I
remove it from my sight; I constitute it—in relation to my table, to my room—as
absent; I alone shall preserve for it the ghostly, transparent being of past objects,
because I am the one through whom beings pursue an honorary existence after
their annihilation. Thus generosity is above all a destructive function.’
18 Ibid.
19 Sartre, Notebooks, 368.
The look
Let’s take a closer look at Being and Nothingness. At first glance, it appeared
the gift hardly came up at all. But when we reread the famous chapter about
the look—le regard—we notice a striking resemblance between the
phenomenological structure of the gift and that of the look.21 Also, it is in this
chapter that the look first becomes an issue in French phenomenology: the
issue has in no way been prepared, nor can it be traced back to the
phenomenologies of the German masters Husserl and Heidegger, yet it will
have a profound effect on French philosophy and philosophers such as
Levinas, Lacan and Foucault. According to Sartre, it is the look that reveals to
me the fact that the other is a free subject, like me, and this fact deprives me
of my free subjectivity. The look of the other objectifies us: through their
eyes, we are objects. The look of the other is not rooted in my intentionality;
their look is not a background for me to appear against. The look of the other
is irrevocably given to me and it is a gift I cannot reject. The appearance of
the other by the gaze, says Sartre, implies a disintegration of my universe:
‘this relation which I call “being-seen-by-another," far from being merely one
of the relations signified by the word man, represents an irreducible fact
which can not be deduced either from the essence of the Other-as-object, or
from my being-as-subject.’22 In other words, it is the look of the other that
cannot be put between brackets, which the phenomenological reduction
would demand: that look is inalienably given to me. Phenomenologically
speaking, the look is a gift. This generosity is by no means to be understood
as an act of the other who is able to give me something, say, a gift of love.
Thinking that the other initially merely exists, to then subsequently give me
some gift would be a mistake. The look simply informs me of the existence of
the other. This is the phenomenological meaning of the gift as given-ness, yet
this can only be captured in a very special Sartrean way: we are not given an
object, but we are given an awareness, since the world is revealed to us as a
universe of objects, ‘beings-in-themselves,’ not of subjects. This implies that
creation is only possible on the side of the being-for-itself—free
consciousness—and not on the side of the world, or the being-in-itself.
Only now we are able to understand why the gift of the other promises to be
both phenomenological and ethical at the same time. The phenomenological
given-ness of the other is taken for an ethical given-ness by the other, as
generosity.
A question that does not come up in Being and Nothingness but is discussed in
Notebooks is whether it is possible to understand the gift as intentional: can
we shoe-horn the master-slave relation out of our relation with the other?
Not to take, to violate, to colonize, to oppress, but to give away?
Generosity
23 Sartre, Notebooks, 371: ‘…not through violence, but on the contrary through
generosity’.
24 René Descartes, Les passions de l'âme (1649), translation Passions of the Soul
(London: Hackett Pub Co Inc, 1989): ‘So I think that true generosity, which brings it
about that a person’s self-esteem is as great as it legitimately can be, consists only in
(i) his knowing that nothing truly belongs to him except this free control of his
volitions, and that his good or bad use of this freedom is the only valid reason for
him to be praised or blamed…’ (§ 153).
25 Sartre, Notebooks, the passage starts at 368.
same time disengage myself from it.’ And ‘Annihilation through the gift
disengages me as a pure for-itself transcending its situation.’26
The gift implies reciprocity of recognition, which Sartre does not table in
Being and Nothingness and is lacking in Critique of Dialectical Reason, in which
the other is fraternally recognized as equaling the self, as one who shares our
goals: ‘The gift presupposes a reciprocity of recognition. But this reciprocity
is not a reciprocity of gifts. […] It is not the gift as the thing that is given, but
recognition itself. This recognition is first of all the recognition that the gift
was not provoked by some interest, that it is a pure freedom that created the
world for me, thereby setting up an interhuman relation.’27
It now becomes clear why and how Sartre introduces the theme of the gift in
his search for an ethics. It creates a chance of an ethics, but seems to slip out
of his hands as soon as it enters the material world. We have already come
across the problematic role of materiality as a threat to freedom. It is the fact
that a gift is material that enslaves the being-for-itself, which is obliged to
receive and to reciprocate, to counter-give. The being-for-itself is controlled
by the other, through materiality.
This becomes even clearer when we read Mauss on the role of the counter-
gift as pay back, which can only be understood as one half of an economic
exchange. Although Sartre warns that giving and counter-giving may
degenerate into economy, it is only the counter-gift that destroys the gift of
the material object. But as long the counter-gift is expected, the gift is not
This positive structure of creation always takes place on the level of freedom,
of acting. But for this reason, the gift is also an affirmation of our freedom in
the face of the world and the other.30 The gift, even on this level, is a structure
of oppression. The other, according to Sartre, might react with anger and
destroy the situation by refusing to recognize the gift. But in this case, Sartre
continues, ‘he refuses to recognize himself too.’
It is important to note that, thus interpreted, the gift is analogous to the look.
Like the potlatch giving, the look of the other cannot be ignored on a
phenomenological level. The look enslaves, possesses. The look, again, is a
gift.
The only way to demonstrate our freedom is by giving. The gift is evidence
of the fact that we are not enslaved. But at the same time, there is no way to
realize this unless we accept the game of the gift, the potlatch game. We have
to enter that arena to secure the right to give and take. And there can only be
one winner. There is always just one who gives and one who receives. This is
a rite, a game, or, as Sartre calls it: a festival. We have to enter an arena in
which we might lose. Without this game as a context, without a potlatch,
there can be no gift at all. And a potlatch is only possible in the presence of
the other. The potlatch denies the freedom of the other—being obliged to
counter-give means being obliged to submit to the other’s being for itself, to
the other’s freedom. The existence of freedom is established as a fact by the
obligation to counter-give.32
Magic
Above, we touched upon the role of the materiality of the gift. Sartre calls the
part the material plays a ‘magical’ one: the material gift is given by a free
consciousness and this is a magical act. Sartre uses the term magic to refer to
a degenerated form of consciousness in which animate freedom has been
replaced by the inanimate ‘thingness’ of the being-in-itself. In the Sartrean-
Cartesian dualistic universe, magic is the only way for the world and for
things to influence the res cogitans or consciousness of the being-for-itself. In
other words, Sartre uses the term magic to refer to the (self-) deception or
false belief involved in the assumption that there is actually an interface
between the being-in-itself and the being-for-itself. False belief, (self)
deception: Sartre also calls it la mauvaise foi: bad faith. It is also magical,
insofar as the being-in-itself is possessed—seized, forced into submission—
by the other. 33 The material sphere is intrinsically bound up with the
fetishism and object-culture of primitive societies. Put in terms of Being and
Nothingness: there is no freedom in primitive relationships, only thingness,
only being-in-itself, because the being-for-itself permanently understands
itself as a thing.
There is yet another way of putting this in Sartrean terms: the actual gift is
imaginary. We then need to take the crucial role Sartre attributes to the
imaginary into account. 34 The non-material gift is imaginary. It cannot be
reduced to the material present. The thing is not even a representative of the
gift. In other words, it is the gesture that counts, not the material thing itself.
What we give is the gift, is the gesture, independent of the material thing.
Perhaps we have bought something the recipient already owns, or something
they don’t like at all, but that doesn’t really matter. Only children and
‘primitives’ take the material present for the gift—which is why potlatch
We can be under the magical spell of the other as well as under the magical
spell of an object, for instance under the spell of the potlach’s material
presents that oblige me to repay. According to Sartre, this is what alienation
truly is, since my subjectivity is understood as the other’s objectivity. The
soul is understood in a negative way: we do not have a soul—the proposition
Sartre defended in Being and Nothingness—but we are possessed by a soul, for
instance in the form of the totemic ancestor.38 A soul, then, fills the empty
seat of the being-for-itself. In primitive, sedentary societies, mana, soul and
possession go together—or perhaps it would be better to say that they do in
our notion of such societies. 39 It is reminiscent of the mauvaise foi or bad faith
in Being and Nothingness, the attitude towards myself in which we
understand ourselves in terms of thingness, of the being-in-itself.40
Sartre lays the groundwork for his use of the bad faith-concept as early as
1939, in the text Esquisse ds the groundwork for his u in which the term magic
plays a central role.41 The magical discourse is not new to the Sartre reader,
but only through Notebooks does it become clear that the looking described in
Being and Nothingness equals an act of the other that is taking possession of
my freedom. Gift, possession, magic: they are all part of Sartre's dialectical
ontology, connected to the crucial role of the look. Let’s read a long passage
from Notebooks:
‘Yet the Other is also an Other for Others, they look at him while he
is looking at me, they can take his name away from him, etc. In this
moment, the magical power of the Other passes over to another
Other and from there to yet another and finally to me, not as me but
as other than the Other. So there is a circulation of Otherness. It is
always somewhere else, it leaps from one to the Other. This is due
to the fact that it is originally the Look that pierces through me, but
that gets extinguished as soon as I look back. The result is that
the look is always somewhere else than where I am looking. It is
behind me, above me, has left the man I am looking at, etc. It
finally becomes the pure possibility of objectification and
actualization of every subject as Other. It becomes a magical
force or mana. But we need to comprehend that it is not, as for
French sociology, a force immanent in society (which would mean
making society a higher of subjectivity). On the contrary, it is the
potentiality of Otherness as such, it is the form power the Other
has to actualize me as Other.’42
The look of the other is the Sartrean equivalent of Freud’s Uber-Ich, like
Leiris’ mana or soul, because it takes possession of a formerly free
consciousness.44 And, again, it is this ‘primitive mind’ that is reminiscent of
39 Ibid.
40 Sartre, Being and Nothingness, ‘Bad Faith’, 86-116.
41 Jean-Paul Sartre, Esquisse d’une théorie des émotions (Paris: Hermann, 1995) First
edition 1938.
42 Sartre, Notebooks, 362.
43 Quoted by Sartre, Esquisse d’une théorie des émotions, 58.
44 Michel Leiris, La Croyance aux génies ‘zar’ en Ethiopie du Nord (Paris: Librairie Félix
Alcan, 1938).
Concluding remarks
RUUD WELTEN (PhD), is Professor of Philosophy at Erasmus University Rotterdam and Tilburg
University, The Netherlands. He has published many articles and
several books on French phenomenology.
©Ruud Welten
Welten, Ruud. “Jean-Paul Sartre’s Notebooks for an Ethics: the Ontology of the Gift,” in Journal
for Cultural and Religious Theory vol. 15. no. 1. (Fall 2015): 3-15.
45 Sartre, Notebooks: ‘The Christian religion: (...) to see oneself with the eyes of God.’
(16) 'In the first place, we see the importance of the look (le regard). In looking, God
may have the evil eye. The eye is always evil because it fixes things.' (364) '...it is my
soul that possesses me. My soul is created by God, illuminated by God, that is,
assimilable to the eternal truths that it contemplates' (365).
46 Sartre, Notebooks, 439.