G V Plekhanov Art and Social Life PDF
G V Plekhanov Art and Social Life PDF
G V Plekhanov Art and Social Life PDF
Plekhanov 1912
1
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 2
I
The relation of art to social life is a question that has always
figured largely in all literatures that have reached a definite stage
of development. Most often, the question has been answered in
one of two directly opposite senses.
Some say: man is not made for the sabbath, but the sabbath for
man; society is not made for the artist, but the artist for society.
The function of art is to assist the development of man’s
consciousness, to improve the social system.
Pushkin set forth his view of the mission of the poet in the much-
quoted words:
Here the so-called theory of art for art’s sake is formulated in the
most striking manner. It was not without reason that Pushkin was
cited so readily and so often by the opponents of the literary
movement of the sixties [9].
There was a time when he did not believe in the theory of art for
art’s sake. There was a time when he did not avoid strife, in fact,
was eager for it. This was in the period of Alexander I. At that
time he did not think that the “people” should be content with the
whip, dungeon and rack. On the contrary, in the ode
called Freedom, he exclaimed with indignation:
writer,” the latter replied: “I fully share your opinion, but in all
fairness it may be said that in him one mourns the future, not the
past.” [12] This means that the never-to-be-forgotten emperor prized
the dead poet not for the great things he had written in his short
lifetime, but for what he might have written under proper police
supervision and guidance. Nicholas had expected him to write
“patriotic” works like Kukolnik’s play The Hand of the All-
Highest Saved Our Fatherland. Even so unworldly a poet as V. A.
Zhukovsky, who was withal a very good courtier, tried to make
him listen to reason and inspire him with respect for conventional
morals. In a letter to him dated April 12, 1826, he wrote: “Our
adolescents (that is, all the ripening generation), poorly educated
as they are, and therefore with nothing to buttress them in life,
have become acquainted with your unruly thoughts clothed in the
charm of poetry; you have already done much harm, incurable
harm. This should cause you to tremble. Talent is nothing. The
chief thing is moral grandeur...” [13] You will agree that, being
in such a situation, wearing the chains of such tutelage, and having
to listen to such instruction, it is quite excusable that he conceived
a hatred for “moral grandeur,” came to loathe the “benefits” which
art might confer, and cried to his counsellors and patrons:
Pisarev would have taken issue with me and said that Pushkin the
poet addressed these vehement words not to his patrons, but to the
“people.” But the real people never came within the purview of the
writers of that time. With Pushkin, the word “people” had the
same meaning as the word which is often to be found in his
poems: “crowd.” And this latter word, of course, does not refer to
the labouring masses. In his Gypsies Pushkin describes the
inhabitants of the stifling cities as follows:
The belief in art for art’s sake arises wherever the artist is
at odds with his social environment.
“No, you fools, no, you goitrous cretins, a book cannot be turned
into gelatine soup, nor a novel into a pair of seamless boots... By
the intestines of all the Popes, future, past and present: No, and a
thousand times no!... I am one of those who consider the
superfluous essential; my love of things and people is in inverse
proportion to the services they may render.” [15]
What was the reason for this attitude of mind of the French
romanticists and Parnassians? Were they also at odds with their
social environment?
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 12
Gautier says: “In those days it was the prevailing fashion in the
romantic school to have as pallid a complexion as possible, even
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 14
writer who was devoid of serious talent could find favour with a
wide circle of readers. Leconte de Lisle held that the popularity of
a writer was proof of his intellectual inferiority (signe d’infériorité
intellectuelle). It need scarcely be added that the Parnassians, like
the romanticists, were staunch believers in the theory of art for
art’s sake.
But in revolting against the old order, David and his friends were
well aware that behind them marched the serried columns of the
third estate, which was soon, in the well-known words of Abbé
Sieyès, to become everything. With them, consequently, the
feeling of disharmony with the prevailing order was supplemented
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 16
The belief in art for art’s sake arises when artists and
people keenly interested in art are hopelessly at odds with
their social environment.
But this is not the whole matter. The example of our “men of the
sixties,” who firmly believed in the early triumph of reason, and
that of David and his friends, who held this belief no less firmly,
show that the so-called utilitarian view of art, that is, the tendency
to impart to its productions the significance of judgements on the
phenomena of life, and the joyful eagerness, which always
accompanies it, to take part in social strife, arises and spreads
wherever there is mutual sympathy between a considerable section
of society and people who have a more or less active interest in
creative art.
come and see him, and “make him understand that the noble and
useful purpose of talent consists not only in the lively depiction of
what is ludicrous or evil, but in justly condemning it; not only in
caricature, but in inculcating lofty moral sentiments; consequently,
in offsetting vice with virtue, the ridiculous and criminal with
thoughts and actions that elevate the soul; lastly, in strengthening
the faith, which is so important to social and private life, that evil
deeds meet with fitting retribution already here on earth.”
Tsar Nicholas I himself looked upon art chiefly from the “moral”
standpoint. As we know, he shared Benkendorf’s opinion that it
would be a good thing to tame Pushkin. He said of Ostrovsky’s
play, Shouldering Another’s Troubles, written at the time when
Ostrovsky had fallen under the influence of the Slavophiles [31] and
was fond of saying at convivial banquets that, with the help of
some of his friends, he would “undo all the work” of Peter [32] – of
this play, which in a certain sense was distinctly didactic, Nicholas
I said with praise: “Ce n’est pas une pièce, c’est une leçon.” [33] Not
to multiply examples, I shall confine myself to the two following
facts. When N. Polevoi’s Moskovsky Telegraf [34] printed an
unfavourable review of Kukolnik’s “patriotic” play, The Hand of
the All-Highest Saved Our Fatherland, the journal became
anathema in the eyes of Nicholas’s ministers and was banned. But
when Polevoi himself wrote patriotic plays – Grandad of the
Russian Navy and Igolkin the Merchant – the tsar, Polevoi’s
brother relates, was delighted with his dramatic talent. “The author
is unusually gifted,” he said. “He should write, write and write.
Yes write (he smiled), not publish magazines.” [35]
literature and all the art of the celebrated era of Louis XIV was
permeated through and through with this conviction. Napoleon I
would similarly have looked upon the theory of art for art’s sake
as a pernicious invention of loathsome “ideologists.” He, too,
wanted literature and art to serve moral purposes. And in this he
largely succeeded, as witnessed for example by the fact that most
of the pictures in the periodical exhibitions (Salons) of the time
were devoted to the warlike feats of the Consulate and the Empire.
His little nephew, Napoleon III, followed in his footsteps, though
with far less success. He, too, tried to make art and literature serve
what he called morality. In November 1852, Professor Laprade of
Lyons scathingly ridiculed this Bonapartist penchant for didactic
art in a satire called Les muses d’Etat. He predicted that the time
would soon come when the state muses would place human reason
under military discipline; then order would reign and not a single
writer would dare to express the slightest dissatisfaction.
I shall remark in passing that for this witty satire Laprade was
deprived of his professorial post. The government of Napoleon III
could not tolerate jibes at the “state muses.”
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 21
II
But let us leave the government “spheres.” Among the French
writers of the Second Empire there were some who rejected the
theory of art for art’s sake from anything but progressive
considerations. Alexandre Dumas fils, for instance, declared
categorically that the words “art for art’s sake” were devoid of
meaning. His plays, Le fils naturel and Le Père prodigue were
devoted to the furtherance of definite social aims. He considered it
necessary to bolster up with his writings the “old society,” which,
in his own words, was crumbling on all sides.
It follows convincingly from all this that the utilitarian view of art
can just as well cohabit with a conservative, as with a
revolutionary attitude of mind. The tendency to adopt this view
necessarily presupposes only one condition: a lively and active
interest in a specific social order or social ideal – no matter which;
and it disappears when, for one reason or another, this interest
evaporates.
Like all questions of social life and social thought, this question
does not permit of an unconditional answer. Everything depends
on the conditions of time and place. Remember Nicholas I and his
servitors. They wanted to turn Pushkin, Ostrovsky and the other
contemporary artists into ministers of morality, as it was
understood by the Corps of Gendarmes. Let us assume for a
moment that they had succeeded in their firm determination. What
would have come of it? This is easily answered. The muses of the
artists who had succumbed to their influence, having become state
muses, would have betrayed the most evident signs of decadence,
and would have diminished exceedingly in truthfulness,
forcefulness and attractiveness.
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 23
Ruskin when he says that a maiden may sing of her lost love, but a
miser cannot sing of his lost money. And he rightly observes that
the merit of an artistic work is determined by the loftiness of the
sentiments it expresses. “Question with yourselves respecting any
feeling that has taken strong possession of your mind. ‘Could this
be sung by a master, and sung nobly, with a true melody and art?’
Then it is a right feeling. Could it not be sung at all, or only sung
ludicrously? It is a base one.” This is true, and it cannot be
otherwise. Art is a means of intellectual communication. And the
loftier the sentiment expressed in an artistic work, the more
effectively, other conditions being equal, can the work serve as
such a means. Why cannot a miser sing of his lost money? Simply
because, if he did sing of his loss, his song would not move
anybody, that is, could not serve as a means of communication
between himself and other people.
What about martial songs, I may be asked; does war, too, serve as
a means of communication between man and man? My reply is
that while martial poetry expresses hatred of the enemy, it at the
same time extols the devoted courage of soldiers, their readiness to
die for their country, their nation, etc. In so far as it expresses this
readiness, it serves as a means of communication between man
and man within confines (tribe, community, nation) whose extent
is determined by the level of cultural development attained by
mankind, or, more exactly, by the given section of mankind.
There are very many people in the world to whom the principles of
1789 are not only “dubitable,” but entirely unknown. Ask a
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 26
because he, like all idealists, had a mistaken notion of the actual
course of man’s aesthetic development.
Who was it, one asks, that tired Gautier’s ears with the assertion
that mankind is capable of self-perfection? The Socialists – more
precisely, the Saint-Simonists, who had been very popular in
France not long before Mademoiselle de Maupin appeared. It was
against the Saint-Simonists that he directed the remarks, quite true
in themselves, about the difficulty of excelling Marshal de
Bassompierre in winebibbing and Milo of Crotona in gluttony. But
these remarks, although quite true in themselves, are entirely
inappropriate when directed against the Saint-Simonists. The self-
perfection of mankind which they were referring to had nothing to
do with enlarging the capacity of the stomach. What the Saint-
Simonists had in mind was improvement of the social organisation
in the interest of the most numerous section of the population, that
is, the working people, the producing section. To call this aim
stupid, and to ask whether it would have the effect of increasing
man’s capacity to over-indulge in wine and meat, was to betray the
very bourgeois narrow-mindedness which was such a thorn in the
flesh to the young romanticists. What was the reason for this?
How could the bourgeois narrow-mindedness have crept into the
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 30
hand in the struggle between the rich and the poor? The relations
between the classes of modern society had become greatly
simplified. All the ideologists of the bourgeoisie now realised that
the point at issue was whether it could succeed in holding the
labouring masses in economic subjection. This realisation also
penetrated to the minds of the advocates of art for the rich. One of
the most remarkable of them in respect to his importance to
science, Ernest Renan, demanded, in his Réforme intellectuelle et
morale, a strong government “which would compel the good
rustics to do our share of the work while we devoted ourselves to
mental speculation” (“qui force de bons rustiques a faire notre part
de travail pendant que nous speculons”). [46]
The fact that the bourgeois ideologists were now infinitely more
cognisant of the import of the struggle between the bourgeoisie
and the proletariat could not but exert a powerful influence on the
nature of their “mental speculations.” Ecclesiastes put it
excellently: “Surely oppression (of others) maketh a wise man
mad.” Having discovered the secret of the struggle between their
class and the proletariat, the bourgeois ideologists gradually lost
the faculty for calm scientific investigation of social phenomena.
And this greatly lowered the inherent value of their more or less
scientific works. Whereas, formerly, bourgeois political economy
was able to produce scientific giants like David Ricardo, now the
tone among its exponents was set by such garrulous dwarfs as
Frédéric Bastiat. Philosophy was increasingly invaded by idealist
reaction, the essence of which was a conservative urge to reconcile
the achievements of modern natural science with the old religious
legends, or, to put it more accurately, to reconcile the chapel with
the laboratory. [47] Nor did art escape the general fate. We shall see
later to what utter absurdities some of the modern painters have
been led under the influence of the present idealist reaction. For
the present I shall say the following.
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 34
An artist who turns mystic does not ignore idea content; he only
lends it a peculiar character. Mysticism is itself an idea, but an
idea which is as obscure and formless as fog, and which is at
mortal enmity with reason. The mystic is quite willing to say
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 36
The belief in art for art’s sake arises and takes root wherever
people engaged in art are hopelessly out of harmony with their
social environment. This disharmony reflects favourably on
artistic production to the extent that it helps the artists to rise
above their environment. Such was the case with Pushkin in the
period of Nicholas I. It was also the case with the romanticists, the
Parnassians and the early realists in France. By multiplying
examples, it might be shown that this has always been the case
wherever such a disharmony existed. But while revolting against
the vulgarity of their social environment, the romanticists, the
Parnassians and the realists had no objection to the social
relationships in which this vulgarity was rooted. On the contrary,
although they cursed the “bourgeois,” they treasured the bourgeois
system – first instinctively, then quite consciously. And the
stronger the movement for liberation from the bourgeois system
became in modern Europe, the more conscious was the attachment
of the French believers in art for art’s sake to this system. And the
more conscious their attachment to this system became, the less
were they able to remain indifferent to the idea content of their
productions. But because of their blindness to the new trend which
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 37
When his poet abuses the “rabble,” we hear much anger in his
words but no vulgarity, whatever Pisarev may have said on the
point. The poet accuses the aristocratic crowd – precisely the
aristocratic crowd, and not the real people who at that time were
entirely outside the purview of Russian literature – of setting
higher store on a cooking pot than on Apollo Belvedere. This only
means that their narrow practical spirit is intolerable to him.
Nothing more. His resolute refusal to instruct the crowd only
testifies that in his opinion they were entirely beyond redemption.
But in this opinion there is not the slightest tinge of reaction. That
is where Pushkin is immensely superior to believers in art for art’s
sake like Gautier. This superiority is conditional. Pushkin did not
jeer at the Saint-Simonists. But he probably never heard of them.
He was an honest and generous soul. But this honest and generous
soul had absorbed certain class prejudices from childhood.
Abolition of the exploitation of one class by another must have
seemed to him an impracticable and even ridiculous utopia. If he
had heard of any practical plans for its abolition, and especially if
these plans had caused such a stir in Russia as the Saint-Simonian
plans had in France, he probably would have campaigned against
them in violent polemical articles and sarcastic epigrams. Some of
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 38
III
I have already said that there is no such thing as a work of art
which is entirely devoid of ideas. And I added that not every idea
can serve as the foundation of a work of art. An artist can be really
inspired only by what is capable of facilitating intercourse among
men. The possible limits of such intercourse are not determined by
the artist, but by the level of culture attained by the social entity to
which he belongs. But in a society divided into classes, they are
also determined by the mutual relations of these classes and,
moreover, by the phase of development in which each of them
happens to be at the time. When the bourgeoisie was still striving
to throw off the aegis of the lay and clerical aristocracy, that is,
when it was itself a revolutionary class, it was the leader of all the
working masses, and together with them constituted a single
“third” estate. And at that time the foremost ideologists of the
bourgeoisie were also the foremost ideologists of “the whole
nation, with the exception of the privileged.” In other words, at
that time the limits of that intercourse of which artistic production
that adhered to the bourgeois standpoint served as the medium,
were relatively very wide. But when the interests of the
bourgeoisie ceased to be the interests of all the labouring masses,
and especially when they came into conflict with the interests of
the proletariat, then the limits of this intercourse considerably
contracted. If Ruskin said that a miser cannot sing of his lost
money, now a time has come when the mental attitude of the
bourgeoisie begins to approximate to that of a miser mourning
over his treasure. The only difference is that the miser mourns
over something already lost, while the bourgeoisie loses its
equanimity at the thought of the loss that menaces it in the future.
“Oppression (of others) maketh a wise man mad,” I would say in
the words of Ecclesiastes. And a wise man (even a wise man!)
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 40
The hero of this play is Ivar Kareno, a young writer who, if not
talented, is at any rate preposterously self-conceited. He calls
himself a man “whose thoughts are as free as a bird.” And what
does this thinker who is as free as a bird write about? About
“resistance,” and about “hate.” And who, in his opinion, must be
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 41
you think they would have more to eat if the lion divided his prey
equally with each of them, leaving only a small portion for
himself? Not at all! Such a kind-hearted lion would cease to be a
lion; he would hardly be fit for the role of a blind man’s dog. At
the first groan of his prey, he would refrain from killing it and
begin licking its wounds instead. A lion is good only as a savage
beast, ravenous for prey, eager only to kill and shed blood. When
such a lion roars, the jackals lick their chops in expectation.”
Clear as this parable is, the eloquent orator explains its moral in
the following, much briefer, but equally expressive words: “The
employer opens up the nourishing springs whose spray falls upon
the workers.”
to secure the lion’s food, part of which goes to satisfy their own
hunger. But who will venture to say that the workers employed in
any given factory contribute nothing to the creation of its product?
It is by their labour, obviously, that it is created, all economic
sophistries notwithstanding. True, the employer participates in the
process of production as its organiser. And as an organiser, he is
himself a worker. But, again, everybody knows that the salary of a
factory manager is one thing, and the entrepreneur profit of the
factory-owner quite another. Deducting the salary from the profit,
we get a balance which goes to the share of capital as such. The
whole question is, why does capital get this balance? And to this
question there is not even a hint of an answer in the eloquent
disquisitions of Jean de Sancy – who, incidentally, does not even
suspect that his own income as a big shareholder in the business
would not have been justified even if his absolutely false
comparison of the entrepreneur to a lion, and the workers to
jackals, had been correct: he himself does absolutely nothing for
the business and is content with receiving a big income from it
annually. And if anybody resembles a jackal who feeds on what is
obtained by the effort of others, it is the shareholder, whose work
consists solely in looking after his shares, and also the ideologist
of the bourgeois system, who does not participate in production
himself, but lives on what is left over from the luxurious: banquet
of capital. With all his talent, de Curel, unfortunately, himself
belongs to this category of ideologists. In the struggle of the wage-
workers against the capitalists, he unreservedly takes the side of
the latter and gives an absolutely false picture of their real attitude
toward those whom they exploit.
exponents can no longer say of themselves that they were not born
for “agitation and strife.” No, they are eager for strife, and do not
shun the agitation that goes with it. But what is it waged for – this
strife in which they are anxious to take part? Alas, for the sake of
self-interest. Not, it is true, for their own personal self-interest – it
would be strange to affirm that men like de Curel or Bourget
defend capitalism in the hope of personal enrichment. The self-
interest which “agitates” them, and for which they are eager to
engage in “strife,” is the self-interest of a whole class. But it is
none the less self-interest. And if this is so, just see what we get.
could not think, feel and – chiefly – act as befits people who hold
the predominant position in society. In the present historical
conditions, this is tantamount to the reproach that they did not
display sufficient energy and consistency in defending the
bourgeois order against the revolutionary attacks of the proletariat.
Witness the anger with which Nietzsche spoke of the Socialists.
But, again, see what we get.
good and evil would mean not being deterred in this struggle even
by the few rights which the working class has succeeded in
winning in bourgeois society. And if his struggle were successful,
its effect would be not to diminish, but to increase the evil in
social life. In his case, therefore, going beyond good and evil
could not be justified, as it generally is when it is done for the
furtherance of reactionary aims. It may be argued in objection that
although Ivar Kareno could find no justification from the
standpoint of the proletariat, he certainly would find justification
from the standpoint of the bourgeoisie. I fully agree. But the
standpoint of the bourgeoisie is in this case the standpoint of a
privileged minority which is anxious to perpetuate its privileges.
The standpoint of the proletariat, on the other hand, is that of a
majority which demands the abolition of all privileges. Hence, to
say that the activity of a particular person is justifiable from the
standpoint of the bourgeoisie, is to say that it is condemnable from
the standpoint of all people who are not inclined to defend the
interests of exploiters. And that is all I need, for the inevitable
march of economic development is my guarantee that the number
of such people will most certainly grow larger and larger.
Hating the “sleepers” from the bottom of their hearts, the neo-
romanticists want movement. But the movement they desire is
a protectivemovement, the very opposite of
the emancipation movement of our time. This is the whole secret
of their psychology. It is also the secret of the fact that even the
most talented of them cannot produce the significant works they
would have produced if their social sympathies ran in a different
direction, and if their attitude of mind were different. We have
already seen how erroneous is the idea on which de Curel based
his play, Le repas du lion. And a false idea is bound to injure an
artistic work, since it gives a false twist to the psychology of its
characters. It would not be difficult to demonstrate how much
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 50
But this slavish heroism has but little appeal for the modern
reader, who probably cannot even conceive how it is possible for a
“vocal tool” [57] to display such devoted loyalty to his owner. Yet
old Gaucherond in Bourget’s play is a sort of Vasily Shibanov
transformed from a serf into a modern proletarian. One must be
purblind indeed to call him the “most likeable figure” in the play.
And one thing is certain at any rate: if Gaucherond really is
likeable, then it shows that, despite Bourget, each of us must side
not with the class to which he belongs, but with that whose cause
he considers more just.
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 51
Bourget’s creation contradicts his own idea. And this is for the
same reason that a wise man who oppresses others becomes mad.
When a talented artist is inspired by a wrong idea, he spoils his
own production. And the modern artist cannot be inspired by a
right idea if he is anxious to defend the bourgeoisie in its struggle
against the proletariat.
“Our morality, our religion, our national sentiment have all gone
to pieces,” he says. “No rules of life can be borrowed from them.
And until such time as our teachers establish authentic truths, there
is naught we can do but cling to the only reality, our ego.” [59]
When in the eyes of a man all has “fallen to pieces” save his own
ego, then there is nothing to prevent him from acting as a calm
chronicler of the great war raging in the bosom of modern society.
But, no! Even then there is something to prevent him doing so.
This something will be precisely that lack of all social interest
which is vividly described in the lines of Barrès I have quoted.
Why should a man act as a chronicler of the social struggle when
he has not the slightest interest either in the struggle, or in society?
He will be irresistibly bored by everything connected with the
struggle. And if he is an artist, he will not even hint at it in his
works. In them, too, he will be concerned with the “only reality” –
his ego. And as his ego may nevertheless be bored when it has no
company but itself, he will invent for it a fantastic, transcendental
world, a world standing high above the earth and all earthly
“questions.” And that is what many present-day artists do. I am
not labelling them. They say so themselves. Here, for example, is
what our countrywoman, Mrs. Zinaida Hippius, says:
Mrs. Hippius continues: “Are we to blame that every ego has now
become separate, lonely and isolated from every other ego, and
therefore incomprehensible and unnecessary to it? We all of us
passionately need, understand and prize our prayer, our verse – the
reflection of an instantaneous fullness of the heart. But to another,
whose cherished ego is different, my prayer is incomprehensible
and alien. The consciousness of loneliness isolates people from
one another still more, makes them separate, compels them to lock
their hearts. We are ashamed of our prayers, and knowing that all
the same we shall not merge in them with anyone, we say them,
compose them, in a whisper, to ourselves, in hints that are clear
only to ourselves.” [61]
But the point is not whether the souls of Mrs. Hippius and of all
who, like her, “love themselves as God” will be saved or not. The
point is that poets who love themselves as God can have no
interest in what is going on in the society around them. Their
ambitions must of necessity be extremely vague. In her poem, A
Song, Mrs. Hippius “sings”:
have said that our soul lies in the transcendental, and yours in the
phenomenal. Nietzsche would have said that you are ruled by
Apollo, and we by Dionysus; your genius consists in moderation,
ours in impulsiveness. You are able to check yourselves in time; if
you come up against a wall, you stop or go round it; we, however,
dash our heads against it (wir rennen uns aber die Köpfe ein). It is
not easy for us to get going, but once we have, we cannot stop. We
do not walk, we run. We do not run, we fly. We do not fly, we
plunge downwards. You are fond of the golden mean; we are fond
of extremes. You are just; for us there are no laws. You are able to
retain your equanimity; we are always striving to lose it. You
possess the kingdom of the present; we seek the kingdom of the
future. You, in the final analysis, always place government
authority higher than the liberties you may secure. We, on the
other hand, remain rebels and anarchists even when fettered in the
chains of slavery. Reason and emotion lead us to the extreme limit
of negation, yet, despite this, deep down at the bottom of our being
and will, we remain mystics.” [66]
Mrs. Hippius, now that she has (at last!) become interested in
social questions, still remains exactly as she appeared to us in the
poems cited above, namely, an extreme individualist of the
decadent type who yearns for a “miracle” only because she has no
serious attitude to real social life. The reader has not forgotten
Leconte de Lisle’s idea that poetry now provides an ideal life for
those who no longer have a real life. And when a man ceases to
have any spiritual intercourse with the people around him, his
ideal life loses all connection with the earth. His imagination then
carries him to heaven, he becomes a mystic. Thoroughly
permeated with mysticism, Mrs. Hippius’s interest in social
questions is absolutely fruitless. [69] But she and her collaborators
are quite mistaken in thinking that the yearning for a “miracle”
and the “mystical” negation of “politics” “as a science” are a
feature peculiar to the Russian decadents. [70] The “sober” West,
before “inebriate” Russia, produced people who revolt against
reason in the name of an irrational aspirations. Przybyszewski’s
Eric Falk abuses the Social-Democrats and “drawing-room
anarchists like John Henry Mackay” solely because, as he claims,
they put too much faith in reason.
From this the authors conclude that we do not know what forms
objects have in themselves. And since these forms are unknown,
they consider they are entitled to portray them at their own will
and pleasure. They make the noteworthy reservation that they do
not find it desirable to confine themselves, as the impressionists
do, to the realm of sensation. “We seek the essential,” they assure
us, “but we seek it in our personality not in an eternity laboriously
fashioned by mathematicians and philosophers.” [76]
In these arguments, as the reader will see, we meet, first of all, the
already well-known idea that our ego is the “only reality.” True,
we meet it here in less rigid guise. Gleizes and Metzinger affirm
that nothing is farther from their thought than to doubt the
existence of external objects. But having granted the existence of
the external world, our authors right there and then declare it to be
unknowable. And this means that, for them too, there is nothing
real except their ego.
The amusing thing about the parody is that in this case the
“exacting artist” is content with the most obvious nonsense.
Incidentally, the appearance of such parodies shows that the
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 66
inherent dialectics of social life have now led the theory of art for
art’s sake to the point of utter absurdity.
poet. The people who composed this “rabble” might without any
exaggeration say of themselves what the rabble say in Pushkin’s
poem:
If you live with the wolves, you must howl with the wolves. The
modern bourgeois aesthetes profess to be warring against
philistinism, but they themselves worship the golden calf no less
than the common or garden philistine. “What they think is a
movement in art,” Mauclair says, “is actually a movement in the
picture mart, where there is also speculation in unlaunched
geniuses.” [83] I would add, in passing, that this speculation in
unlaunched geniuses is due, among other things, to the feverish
hunt for something “new” to which the majority of the present-day
artists are addicted. People always strive for something “new”
when they are not satisfied with the old. But the question
is, why are they not satisfied? Very many contemporary artists are
not satisfied with the old for the sole reason that, so long as the
general public cling to it, their own genius will remain
“unlaunched.” They are driven to revolt against the old by a love
not for some new idea, but for the “only reality,” their own dear
ego. But such a love does not inspire an artist; it only disposes him
to regard even the “idol of Belvedere” from the standpoint of self-
advantage. “The money question is so strongly intertwined with
the question of art,” Mauclair says, “that art criticism is squeezed
in a vice. The best critics cannot say what they think, and the rest
say only what they think is opportune, for, after all, they have to
live by their writing. I do not say this is something to be indignant
about, but it is well to realise the complexity of the problem.” [84]
Thus we find that art for art’s sake has turned into art for money’s
sake. And the whole problem Mauclair is concerned with boils
down to determining the reasons why this has happened. And it is
not very difficult to determine them. “There was a time, as in the
Middle Ages, when only the superfluous, the excess of production
over consumption, was exchanged.
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 72
“There was again a time, when not only the superfluous, but
all products, all industrial existence, had passed into
commerce, when the whole of production depended on
exchange...
on within the ruling class, in fact within the whole range of old
society, assumes such a violent, glaring character, that a small
section of the ruling class cuts itself adrift, and joins the
revolutionary class, the class that holds the future in its hands. Just
as, therefore, at an earlier period, a section of the nobility went
over to the bourgeoisie, so now a portion of the bourgeoisie goes
over to the proletariat, and in particular, a portion of the bourgeois
ideologists, who have raised themselves to the level of
comprehending theoretically the historical movement as a
whole.” [86]
To this I objected, and now object, that I do not think there is, or
can be, an absolute criterion of beauty. [89] People’s notions of
beauty do undoubtedly change in the course of the historical
process. But while there is no absolute criterion of beauty, while
all its criteria are relative, this does not mean that there is
no objective possibility of judging whether a given artistic design
has been well executed or not. Let us suppose that an artist wants
to paint a “woman in blue.” If what he portrays in his picture
really does resemble such a woman, we shall say that he has
succeeded in painting a good picture. But if, instead of a woman
wearing a blue dress, we see on his canvas several stereometric
figures more or less thickly and more or less crudely tinted here
and there with blue colour, we shall say that whatever he has
painted, it certainly is not a good picture. The more the execution
corresponds to the design, or – to use a more general expression –
the more the form of an artistic production corresponds to its idea,
the more successful it is. There you have an objective criterion.
And precisely because there is such a criterion, we are entitled to
say that the drawings of Leonardo da Vinci, for example, are
better than the drawings of some little Themistocles [90] who spoils
good paper for his own distraction. When Leonardo da Vinci, say,
drew an old man with a beard, the result really was an old man
with a beard – so much so that at the sight of him we say: “Why,
he’s alive!” But when Themistocles draws an old man, we would
do well to write underneath: “This is an old man with a beard” –
so that there might be no misunderstanding. In asserting that there
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 75
Notes
[Footnotes are Plekhanov’s own, except additions by subsequent
editor marked “Note by editor"]
37. Form is beautiful, true, when there is thought beneath it! What is the
use of a beautiful forehead, if there is no brain behind it? – Ed.
38. See A. Cassagne’s excellent book, La théorie de l’art pour l’art en
France chez les derniers romantiques et les premiers réalistes, Paris, 1906,
pp. 96-105.
39. Article 2 of the Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen,
adopted by the French Constituent Assembly at its sittings of August 20-
26, 1789, reads: “Le but de toute association politique est la conservation
des droits naturels et imprescriptibles de l’homme. Ces droits sont: la
liberté, la propriété, la sûreté et la résistance a l’oppression.” (“The object
of every civic association is the protection of the natural and
imprescriptible rights of man. These rights are: liberty, property, security
and resistance to oppression.”) The concern for property testifies to the
bourgeois character of the revolution, while the recognition of the right to
“resist oppression” indicates that the revolution had only just taken place
but had not yet been completed, having met with strong resistance from the
lay and clerical aristocracy. In June 1848 the French bourgeoisie no longer
recognised the right of the citizen to resist oppression.
40. Belinsky expressed this opinion in his article “A View of Russian
Literature in 1847.” [Note by editor.]
41. Its exclusiveness, which cannot be denied, only signified that in the
16th century the people who prized art were hopelessly out of harmony
with their social environment. Then, too, this disharmony induced a
gravitation towards pure art, that is, towards art for art’s sake. Previously,
in the time of Giotto, say, there had been no such disharmony and no such
gravitation.
42. It is noteworthy that Perugino himself was suspected by his
contemporaries of being an atheist.
43. Mademoiselle de Maupin, Préface, p. 23.
44. Milo of Crotona – a famous Greek athlete (6th century B.C.). [Note by
editor.]
45. Les Poètes, MDCCCLXXXIX, p. 260. – Ed.
46. Quoted by Cassagne in his La théorie de l’art pour l’art chez les
derniers romantiques et les premiers réalistes, pp. 194-95.
47. “On peut, sans contradiction, aller successivement à son laboratoire et
à son oratoire” (“one can, without contradiction, go successively to one’s
laboratory and one’s chapel”), Grasset, professor of clinical
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 82
Paris, 1910.) Ivar Kareno would probably recognise in these views his own
free-as-a-bird thoughts. But these views were not yet reflected in
Flaubert’s novels directly. The class struggle in modern society had to
advance much further before the ideologists of the ruling class felt the need
to give outright expression in literature to their hatred for the emancipatory
ambitions of the “people.” But those who eventually conceived this need
could no longer advocate the “absolute autonomy” of ideologies. On the
contrary, they demanded that ideologies should consciously serve as
intellectual weapons in the struggle against the proletariat. But of this later.
52. The feudal landlord in Saltykov-Shchedrin’s satirical tale, The Wild
Landlord, who wanted “to solve” the peasant problem by murdering off
the peasants. [Note by editor.]
53. See Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Selected Works in three volumes,
Vol. 1, Moscow, 1969, p. 112. [Note by editor.]
54. “For such is our good pleasure.” – Ed.
55. He says so himself. See La barricade, Paris, 1910, Preface, p. xix.
56. Vasily Shibanov – hero of an historical ballad of the same name by
Count Alexei Tolstoy. [Note by editor.]
57. “Vocal tool” – instrumentum vocale, the name given to slaves in
Ancient Rome. [Note by editor.]
58. La barricade, Preface, p. xxiv.
59. Sous l’oeil des barbares, 1901 ed., p. 18.
60. Collected Verse, Preface, p. ii.
61. Collected Verse, Preface, p. iii.
62. Babayev – a character in Sergeyev-Tsensky’s play of the same name.
[Note by editor.]
63. According to Plekhanov’s opportunist conception, there were no
objective conditions for a socialist revolution in Russia since she had
embarked on the road of industrial development later than other countries
and a conflict between the productive forces and capitalist production
relations was not yet in sight. [Note by editor.]
64. We know, for instance, that the work of Helvetius, De l’homme, was
published in The Hague, in 1772, by a Prince Golitsyn.
65. The infatuation of Russian aristocrats for the French Encyclopaedists
had no practical consequences of any moment. It was however useful, in
the sense that it did clear certain aristocratic minds of some aristocratic
prejudices. On the other hand, the present infatuation of a section of our
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 84
course, are possible even now. But the chances of any such appearing have
drastically diminished. Furthermore, even works of distinction now bear
the impress of the era of decadence. Take, for example, the Russian trio
mentioned above: if Mr. Filosofov is devoid of all talent in any field, Mrs.
Hippius possesses a certain artistic talent and Mr. Merezhkovsky is even a
very talented artist. But it is easy to see that his latest novel Alexander I,
for example, is irretrievably vitiated by religious mania, which, in its turn,
is characteristic of an era of decadence. In such eras even men of very
great talent do not produce what they might have produced under more
favourable social conditions. [
92. A play on lines from Krylov’s fable, The Ass and the Nightingale.
After hearing the nightingale sing, the ass commended her, but thought she
“yet greater praise would earn, if to the farmyard cock she went to learn.”
[Note by editor.]
93. Sovremenny Mir (Contemporary World) – a monthly journal published
in St. Petersburg from 1906 to 1918. [Note by editor.]
Name index
Alexander I (1777-1825) Russian Emperor (1801-25)
Alexinsky, Grigory Alexeyevich (b. 1879) Russian Social-
Democrat; during the period of reaction (1907-10), one of the
organisers of the anti-Party group Vperyod, subsequently a
reactionary
Aristogeiton (6th century B.C.) Athenian who was put to death for
conspiring against the tyrants Hipparchus and Hippias
Aristotle (384-322 B. C.) Great thinker of Ancient Greece
Augier, Emile (1820-1889) French playwright
Banville, Théodore de (1823-1891) French poet
Barbey d’Aurevilly, Jules (1808-1889) French writer,
representative of reactionary romanticism
Barrès, Auguste Maurice (1862-1923) French writer and publicist,
ideologist of Catholicism
Art and Social Life G.V. Plekhanov Halaman 88