004
004
004
National Minority
Rights in Europe
TOVE H. M A LLOY
AC
1
Great Clarendon Street, Oxford OX2 6DP
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
It furthers the University’s objective of excellence in research, scholarship,
and education by publishing worldwide in
Oxford New York
Auckland Cape Town Dar es Salaam Hong Kong Karachi
Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Nairobi
New Delhi Shanghai Taipei Toronto
With offices in
Argentina Austria Brazil Chile Czech Republic France Greece
Guatemala Hungary Italy Japan Poland Portugal Singapore
South Korea Switzerland Thailand Turkey Ukraine Vietnam
Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press
in the UK and in certain other countries
Published in the United States
by Oxford University Press Inc., New York
# Tove H. Malloy
The moral rights of the author have been asserted
Crown copyright material is reproduced under Class Licence
Number C01P0000148 with the permission of HMSO
and the Queen’s Printer for Scotland
Database right Oxford University Press (maker)
First published 2005
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced,
stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means,
without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press,
or as expressly permitted by law, or under terms agreed with the appropriate
reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction
outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department,
Oxford University Press, at the address above
You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover
and you must impose the same condition on any acquirer
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
Data available
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Malloy, Tove H.
National minority rights in Europe / Tove H. Malloy.
p. cm.
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0–19–927443–6 (hbk.: alk. paper) 1. Minorities—Legal status, laws, etc.—
Europe. 2. Minorities—Government policy—Europe. I. Title.
KJC5144.M56M35 2005
342.2408 0 73—dc22
2005003878
Typeset by Newgen Imaging Systems (P) Ltd., Chennai, India
Printed in Great Britain
on acid-free paper by
Biddles Ltd., King’s Lynn
ISBN 0–19–927443–6
1 3 5 7 9 10 8 6 4 2
To Bill
Contents
Acknowledgements xi
Abbreviations xiii
Table of Treaties xv
Table of Documents xvi
Table of Travaux Préparatoires to the FCNM xviii
Table of Cases xx
Introduction 1
I. PROBLEMATIZATION: INDIVIDUALISM
AND COLLECTIVISM
1. Overview: National Minority, or Co-nation? 15
1.1 Who are Europe’s national minorities? 18
1.2 National minorities and the structure of
international law 24
1.2.1 National minority rights prior to 1989 28
1.2.2 National minorities and state nationalism 32
1.3 National minorities and public policy 35
1.4 Ethical terminology 38
1.5 Models of accommodation 40
1.6 Citizenship 44
1.7 Justice 48
I I . I N T H E O R Y : UN I V E R S A L I S M
A N D PA R T I C U L A R I S M
4. Liberalism and Nationalism: The Problem of Co-nation
Inclusion in National Self-Determination 115
4.1 What is state nationalism? 118
4.2 Terminology 126
4.3 Liberal pluralism 128
4.4 National identity 132
4.5 Theorizing national self-determination 137
Bibliography 315
Index 345
Acknowledgements
There are many reasons for writing a book on national minority rights. My reasons
are linked to two personal experiences. First, during my years with the Danish
Foreign Service, I observed the fervour with which seasoned and senior diplomats
dealt with the so-called ‘border region question’. Denmark’s adventure into border
region constitutionalism and her subsequent military and political defeat in 1864
continue to have a remarkably strong impact not only on her foreign policy but
also on the national identity of her subjects. Secondly, when I was assigned to the
Danish Embassy in Budapest, Hungary, I had ample opportunity to observe the
impact of Hungary’s history on the Hungarian national identity. Thus, it was
when I realized the importance to the Hungarian national identity of the large
paintings of extra-territorial ‘possessions’ in the halls of the Hungarian Parliament,
that my ideas of researching a Ph.D. and eventually this book began in earnest.
Of course, I had no idea what was entailed in writing a major work on national
minority rights, nor did I realize as is often said that it is no simple matter to turn a
Ph.D. into a book. It is thus with great humility that I wish first and foremost to
thank Professor Michael Freeman of the Department of Government at Essex, for
the dedication and conscientiousness with which he attended to my many deficits
in the academic disciplines. His attention to detail as well as his untiring readiness
to explain complex matters were the supporting pillars when the structure of my
work was prone to collapse. Most of the material and the arguments in this book
are familiar to him, including the ones where our views did not meet. Some
material and arguments will be new to him, and I hope that he will appreciate
these with the usual healthy criticism and scepticism. One aspect I know that we
have in common is the need to see national minority rights in a multi-disciplinary
perspective. I thank Michael Freeman for three memorable years.
I also wish to thank Professors Geoff Gilbert and Frances Millard as well as
Dr David Howarth for their enthusiastic comments. I am particularly grateful
for the comments I received from Professor Peter Jones of Newcastle as he made
me see a number of issues much more clearly. Any deficiencies or inaccuracies are
of course mine.
The exhilarating experience of researching and writing a book could not have
been accomplished without the continuous support and permission to be absent
which I have been granted by the Danish Foreign Service. I would like to express
my gratitude to Ambassadors Claus Grube, Poul Erik Dam Kristensen, Reimer
Nielsen, and the late William Thune Andersen. My greatest debt of gratitude is
to Ambassador K. Erik Tygesen, whose personal efforts have supported my
pursuits for excellence on more than one occasion.
xii Acknowledgements
This book has taken longer than I expected to reach the publisher. This is
partly due to the months I took off to join Dr George Ulrich and his team at the
European Masters Programme in Human Rights and Democratization. I thank
him as well as Professors Manfred Nowak and Horst Fischer for inviting me to
Venice. The experience of spending those intensive months with 90 dedicated
knowledge-thirsty students was a gift that I will treasure for life.
Another delay was caused by a transatlantic move to join the European Centre
for Minority Issues (ECMI). I would like to thank Director Marc Weller for
inviting me to work with him in Flensburg even though he knew that there
would be times when I might be distracted as the deadline for my book drew
closer. The work at ECMI has greatly enhanced my understanding of national
minority issues. I also thank ECMI Chairman Ambassador Peter Dyvig as well as
my colleagues for support and encouragement, with special thanks to librarian
Wes McKinley for helping me on numerous occasions. It is indeed an irony that
I have completed this book in Flensburg, a town where national minority rights
are seen in action in daily life.
Thanks also to Gwen Booth who first read my proposal at Oxford University
Press. Her assistance in bringing this book to print has been invaluable. I also
wish to thank Louise Kavanagh and Virginia Williams as well as the anonymous
reviewers for valuable comments and support.
As often there is unfortunately one who did not live to see the final product
but who bears great responsibility for setting the author on a course to seek
understanding. In my case this is my late father who was a self-proclaimed
observer of the national minority question of the Danish-German border region
and who taught me how ingrained the ‘lesson of 1864’ is in the self-
consciousness of the Danish ‘nation’. This book is also for him.
Above all, my greatest debt is to Bill, my husband, without whom there
simply would not have been a Ph.D. thesis, let alone a book. Bill has supported
me from the very first moments of my academic pursuits, he has shared all good
as well as bad times, during the preparation of this manuscript. Words cannot
express my desire to thank him, but I hope to be able to pay back my debts in full
in the future.
T.H.M.
Flensburg, October 2004
Abbreviations
EC/EU
Regulation 1612 on the rights of migrant workers and their families (1968) . . . . . . 253 n. 4
Directive 486 on children of migrants (1977) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 253 n. 4
Council Regulation 2052 as regards the European Regional
Development FUND (1988). . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 256 n. 17
Council Regulation 1035 establishing a European Monitoring Centre on Racism and
Xenophobia (1997) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 270 n. 25; 57 n. 22
Declaration on Yugoslavia (1991) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 261 n. 41; 261
Declaration on the guidelines on the Recognition of New States in Eastern
Europe and the Soviet Union (1991) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 261 n. 4
Council Directive 43 ‘Implementing the Principle of Equal Treatment between
Persons Irrespective of Racial or Ethnic Origin’ (2000) . . . . . . . . . . 270 n. 76; 57 n. 22
Council Directive 750 ‘Action Programme to Combat Discrimination’,
2001–2006 (2000)
Laeken Declaration (2001) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 270 n. 76, 278 n. 110
EP
Resolution on ‘the granting of special rights to be citizens of the European
Community in implementation of the decision of the Paris Summit of
December 1974’ (1974) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 253 n. 8
Resolution on a Community Charter of Regional Languages and Cultures and
on a Charter of Rights of Ethnic Minorities (1981) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 257 n. 26; 257
Resolution on Measures in Favour of Minority Languages and
Cultures (1983) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 257 n. 27
Resolution on the languages and cultures of regional and ethnic minorities
in the European Community (1987) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 258 n. 27
Resolution adopting the Declaration of fundamental rights and
freedoms (1989) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 258 n. 28; 85 n. 3
Resolution on the Community Charter of Fundamental Social
Rights (1989) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 258 n. 30; 258; 273 n. 89; 273
Resolution on languages in the Community and the situation of
Catalan (1991). . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 258 n. 27
Resolution on Union citizenship (1991) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 258 n. 32; 258
Resolution on linguistic and cultural minorities in the European
Community (1994) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 258 n. 27, 269 n. 73
Resolution on the Constitution of the European Union (1994) . . . . . . . . . . 269 n. 71; 269
Resolution on the establishment of the Charter of Fundamental
Rights (1999) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 273 n. 89
Resolution on the drafting of a European Union Charter
of Fundamental Rights (2000). . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 273 n. 89
Resolution on measures to promote language learning and
linguistic diversity (2001). . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 276 n. 101
Table of Documents xvii
CoR
Opinion of the Committee of the Regions on the revision of the Treaty on European Union and of
the Treaty establishing the European Community (1995) . . . . . . . . . . . . 271 n. 85; 271
Opinion of the Committee of the Regions on Culture and cultural differences and their significance
for the future of Europe (1998) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 264 n. 54, 265 n. 55, 276 n. 99, 100
PA
Recommendation 1134 on the Rights of Persons Belonging to
National Minorities (1990). . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 218; 236 n. 69
Recommendation 1177 on the Rights of Minorities (1992) . . . . . . . . . . . . 218; 236 n. 69
Recommendation 1201 on the Additional Protocol on the Rights of
National Minorities to the ECHR (1993) . . . . . . 219; 221; 228; 236; 238; 248; 236 n. 69
Recommendation 1231 on the follow-up to the Council of Europe
Vienna Summit (1994) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 235; 236 n. 67
Recommendation 1255 on the Protection of the Rights of National
Minorities of (1995) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 236; 236 n. 69
Recommendation 1285 on the rights of national minorities (1996) . . 236, 236 n. 68; 236 n. 69
Recommendation 1300 on the protection of the rights of minorities (1996). 236, 236 n. 70, 69
Recommendation 1345 on the protection of national
minorities (1997) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 236, 237 n. 71; 236 n. 69
Recommendation 1492 on ‘Rights of national minorities’ (2000) . . . . . . . . . 237, 237 n. 72
Recommendation 1609 on ‘Positive experiences of autonomous regions as a
source of inspiration for conflict resolution in
Europe’ (2003). . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 240; 238; 237, 237 n. 73; 238 n. 74; 248
Recommendation 1623 on ‘The rights of national minorities’ (2003) . . . . . . 238; 238 n. 76
Doc. 9862 ‘Rights of national minorities’ of 9 July
2003. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 239 n. 78, 79; 245 n. 90; 246 n. 92, 93
CLRAE
Resolution 52, CG (4) 5 (1997) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 243; 246; 243 n. 85
Recommendation 43, CG (5) 11 of (1998). . . . . . . . . . . . 241; 242; 245; 248; 241 n. 82;
83; 242 n. 84; 245; 246; 248
Recommendation 70, CG (6) 16 (1999) . . . . . . . . . . . . . 243; 244; 245; 247; 243 n. 87;
244 n. 88, 267 n. 64
CSCE
Vienna Concluding Document (1989) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 68 n. 42
Copenhagen Concluding Document (1990) . . . . . . . . . . . . . 63; 215; 229; 235; 291; 292
Helsinki Summit Declaration . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 65 n. 49
Concluding Document of the Inaugural Conference for a Pact
of Stability in Europe (1994) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 267 n. 64
UN
Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31, 32, 36, 37, 53, 105
Declaration on the Granting of Independence to Colonial Countries
and Peoples, Res. 1514 (XV) (1960) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 30 n. 52
xviii Table of Documents
Declaration of Principles on Friendly Relations between States,
Res. 2526 (XXV) (1970) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31 n. 53
Declaration on the Rights of Persons Belonging to National or Ethnic,
Religious and Linguistic Minorities (1992) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 65 n. 52; 66 n. 56
Draft Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples (1994) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31 n. 55
Capotorti, Francesco, Study on the Rights of Persons Belonging to
Ethnic, Religious and Linguistic Minorities (1977) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 223 n. 21; 18 n. 10
Dechênes, Jules, Proposal concerning a Definition of the
Term ‘Minority’ (1985) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 223 n. 21; 18 n. 10
Eide, A. ‘Final Text of the Commentary to the Declaration on the Rights of
Persons Belonging to National or Ethnic, Religious and Linguistic
Minorities’, UN Doc. E/Cn.4/Sub.2/AC.5/2001/2, 1–21 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 65 n. 55
HRC General comment No. 23(50) on ICCPR Article 27 (1994) . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17 n. 8
HRC General Comment No. 12(21) on Article 1, Compilation of General Comments
and General Recommendations Adopted by Human Rights Treaty Bodies,
Doc. HRI/GEN/1/Rev.1 at 12 (1994) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17 n. 8
HRC Concluding Observations regarding France’s report submitted under Article 40 of the
ICCPR, CCPR/C/79/Add. 80 (1997) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
OTHE R DO CUMENTS
Collier, Paul et al., Breaking the Conflict Trap: Civil War and Development
Policy (Washington: IBRD/World Bank, 2003) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 198 n. 80
T HE CO U NCI L O F EU R OPE
CM grouped reply to PA Recommendations 1134 (1990), 1177 (1992), 1201 (1993),
1255 (1995), 1285 (1996), 1300 (1996), and 1345 (1997) of
19 January 1999 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 236 n. 69
CM reply to PA Recommendatioin 1609 (2003) adopted on 3 June 2004 . . . . . . 238 n. 75
CM reply to CLRAE Recommendations 43 (1998) and 70 (1999) of
29 May 2002 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 245 n. 89
ILO
Convention No 169 concerning Indigenous Peoples in Independent
Counrtries (1989) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 31 n. 55
Table of Travaux Préparatoires
to the FCNM
Final Activity Report on the protection of national minorities for the attention of the Committee of
Ministers, CDDH(92)9 Addendum of 16 April 1992 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 226 n. 32
Meeting Report, Committee of Experts for the Protection of National Minorities, DH- MIN(92)7
of 30 November 1992
Proposal for a European Convention for the Protection of Minorities, CDL-MIN(93)6 of
22 February 1993 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 219 n. 10
Explanatory Report on the Proposal for a European Convention for the
Protection of Minorities, CDL-MIN(93)7 of
22 February 1993 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 220 n. 11, 13; 221 n. 14; 229 n. 44; 232 n. 54
Report to the CDDH, DH-MIN(93)4 of 28 July 1993 . . . . . . . . 222 n. 17, 19; 223 n. 22
Final Activity Report of the CDDH for the attention of the Committee of Ministers, CDDH(93)
of 22 August 1993
Terms of Reference for the CAHMIN on the drawing up of a framework convention and a protocol
complementing the European Convention on Human Rights (ECHR), CAHMIN(94)1 of
10 October 1993
Meeting Report, CAHMIN(94)5 of 01 February 1994 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 223 n. 23
Preliminary draft Preamble and opening provisions containing certain principles of the framework
Convention, CAHMIN/GR (94)1 misc. of 17 February 1994
Report of the first meeting of the CAHMIN Drafting Group, CAHMIN/GR(94)2 rev. of
04 March 1994
Meeting Report, CAHMIN(94)9 of 23 March 1994
Study of control and monitoring system in international conventions. Proposals for a control
or monitoring system under a framework convention on the protection of minorities,
CAHMIN(94)7 of 12 April 1994
Meeting Report, CAHMIN(94)13 of 15 April 1994 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 231 n. 52
Preliminary Draft Framework Convention for the Protection of National Minorities prepared by
the Chairman and the Vice-Chairman of the CAHMIN with the assistance of the Secretariat,
CAHMIN(94)12 of 10 May 1994 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 227 n. 34, 35
Contribution of the CDCC to the work of the Ad Hoc Committee on the Protection of National
Minorities (CAHMIN), CDCC-BU(94)7 rev. of 16 May 1994
Proposals concerning the Preliminary Draft Framework Convention for the Protection of National
Minorities, CAHMIN(94)14 rev. of 10 June 1994 . . . . . . . . . . . . . 224 n 25; 228 n. 43
Meeting Report, CAHMIN(94)16 of 13 June 1994. . . . . . . 227 n. 36; 230 n. 46; 231 n. 53
Control of the Implementation of the Framework Convention for the Protection of National
Minorities, CAHMIN(94)17 prov. of 20 June 1994
Meeting Report, CAHMIN(94)19 of 07 July 1994
Informal proposal for further discussion in the CAHMIN submitted by the delegation of the
Netherlands in co-ordination with Belgium, Germany, Hungary, Norway, and Portugal,
CAHMIN(94)24 of 18 August 1994
Summary of the main points raised by the opinion of the Directorate of Legal Affairs on the Draft
Framework Convention, CAHMIN(94)25 of 18 August 1994
Decisions of the Committee of Ministers concerning the work of the CAHMIN at the 516th
meeting of the Ministers’ Deputies, CAHMIN(94)27 of 08 September 1994
xx Table of Travaux Préparatoires to the FCNM
Meeting Report, CAHMIN(94)28 of 19 September 1994
Meeting Report, CAHMIN(94)32 of
14 October 1994 . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 223 n. 24; 227 n. 37; 230 n. 47
Meeting Report, CAHMIN(94)33 of 15 November 1994
Meeting Report, CAHMIN(94)35 of 09 December 1994
Meeting Report, CAHMIN(95)9 of 08 March 1995
Meeting Report, CAHMIN(95)16 of 23 May 1995
Meeting Report, CAHMIN(95)21 of 19 September 1995
Meeting Report, CAHMIN(95)22 of 24 January 1996
Table of Cases
ECtHR
Isop v Austria (1962) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 89
X and Y v Belgium (1966) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 89
Certain Aspects of the Laws on the Use of Languages in Education in Belgium (1968) . . . 76 n. 89
K v France (1984) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 89
Bideault v France (1986). . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 89
Loisidou v Turkey (1996) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 91
The Socialist Party v Turkey (1998). . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 91
The United Communist Party v Turkey (1998) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 91
Sidiropoulos and others v Greece (1998) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 91
Sheffield and Horsham v UK (1998) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 91
Özdep v Turkey (1999) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 91
Okçnoglu v Turkey (1999) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 91
Sürek and Özdemir v Turkey (1999) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 91
Sener v Turkey (2000) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 91
HR C
Sandra Lovelace v Canada (1977) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 90
Kitok v Sweden (1985) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 90
AD v Canada (Mikmaq Tribal Society) (1986). . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 90
Dominique Guesdon v France (1986) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 51 n.2, 76 n. 89
SG v France (1988). . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 89
GB v France (1989) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 76 n. 89
ICJ
Asylum case (1950) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 226 n. 31
Morocco case (1952) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 226 n. 31
E CJ
Casagrande v Landeshauptstadt München (1963) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 253 n. 6
Klöckner Werke AG and others v High Authority (1962) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 253 n. 6
Nold v Commission (1974). . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 253 n. 6
Defrenne v Sabena (1976) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 253 n. 6
Prais v Council (1976) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 253 n. 6
Hauer v Land Rheinland-Pfalz (1979) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 253 n. 6
National Panasonic v Commission (1980) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 253 n. 6
Mutsch v Belgium (1985) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 273 n. 92
Friedrich Kremzow v Austria (1997) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 273 n. 92
Bickel and Franz (1998) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 273 n. 92
Angonese v Cassa de Risparmio di Bolzano SpA (2000) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 273 n. 92
PART I
PROBLEMATIZATION
Individualism and Collectivism
1
Overview: National Minority,
or Co-nation?
Protection rather than ethical consideration has been the focus of the post-1989
national minority rights discourse. Protection refers here to the responsibility of
the state to protect individuals against injury committed either by the state or
third parties and thus also implies the right to humanitarian intervention on
behalf of citizens belonging to a state. Ethical consideration refers to the act of
moral and social recognition of constitutive communities.1 A constitutive
community is usually one’s ethnic, linguistic, or national group but race, gender,
and sexual orientation have also been suggested as constitutive.2 Usually ethical
consideration brings ethical standing. Ethical standing refers to the individual’s
feeling of moral and social worth achieved and afforded through the recognition
of one’s constitutive community. In international law ethical standing is usually
afforded individuals through the moral recognition of their communities to
independence as states and through a national self-determination test.3 The 1933
Montevideo Convention on Rights and Duties of States holds that communities
have the right to moral recognition as states if they fulfil four criteria.4 These are
a permanent population, a defined territory, a government, and the capacity to
enter into relations with other states. The way in which these are verified is
through the test of the right of national self-determination, which determines the
right to state sovereignty. Thus, to have state sovereignty, both internal and
external self-determination must exist. Moreover, external self-determination is
legitimized by the existence of internal self-determination. Where both exist,
there may be statehood. However, a number of states or state-like communities
1 Honneth, Axel, The Struggle for Recognition: The Moral Grammar of Social Conflicts, trans. Joel
Harvard University Press, 1989) and Young, Iris Marion, Justice and the Politics of Difference
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1990).
3 Malanczuk, Peter, Akehurst’s Modern Introduction to International Law, 7th rev. edn. (London:
possess the following qualifications: (a) a permanent population; (b) a defined territory; (c)
government; and (d) capacity to enter into relations with other States’. Quoted in Brownlie, Ian,
Principles of Public International Law, 5th edn. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998), 70.
16 Individualism and Collectivism
recognized before 1933 could not fulfil the Montevideo criteria today. The
Vatican City, for instance, does not have a permanent population,5 and it could
be argued that present-day Colombia does not control its territory as the drug
cartels have created a virtual state within the state. Similarly, in post-Milosevic
Yugoslavia, now Serbia, the UN is currently administering the province of
Kosovo, and in Afghanistan large parts of the south are not controlled by the
government in Kabul and its international protection forces. Nevertheless, these
entities have ethical standing in terms of moral recognition as independent
states. The Montevideo criteria were expanded when the UN was founded in
1944. The Charter of the UN stipulates that states wishing to become members
must be peace-loving, be ready to accept obligations contained in the Charter,
be ready and able to carry out these obligations, as well as willing to do so.6
Certainly, it is questionable how many members of the UN take all these
obligations seriously.
Partial ethical standing is also possible in international law. The Palestinian
Authority has been given recognition, albeit not yet as a state but as an inter-
national player, even though it does not have power over an independent
territory.7 This is because the Palestinians are seen as a people with the right of self-
determination. Likewise, self-determination for indigenous groups, who like the
Palestinians possess a certain degree of social and political cohesion as well as
state-like collective agency, is currently under consideration in the UN system. In
these cases internal self-determination has been established but external self-
determination remains problematic. Internal self-determination may here be seen
as a tool of protection. But even though a number of European national
minorities are socially and politically cohesive and show evidence of state-like
collective agency like the Palestinians and indigenous groups, and inasmuch as
some national minorities needed protection as they were subjected to ethnic
cleansing in the 1990s, they have not earned the right to ethical standing through
the test of self-determination let alone national self-determination. Instead the
international society has focused on protecting national minorities in terms of
human rights. But if internal self-determination ensures protection and partial
ethical standing, one must ask why do national minorities not enjoy the right of
some form of self-determination?
The reason for the differentiation in the national minority rights discourse
between national minorities and other constitutive communities is that,
according to international law and the prevailing view in European international
politics, states are seen as nations and therefore nations equate with states, and
only those nations that equate with states have moral recognition and national
1995), 247.
National Minority, or Co-nation? 17
self-determination. But in reality nations and states rarely coincide. Like
indigenous groups, national minorities consider themselves nations even though
they do not wish to become independent states. Certainly, many national
minorities like the Palestinians and indigenous groups consider themselves a
‘people’. However, international law and politics see national minorities as
cultural groups. This has resulted in national minority rights being categorized
primarily as cultural rights rather than political rights. Hence, inasmuch as the
right of national self-determination is a political right, national minorities are
not eligible for national self-determination. Furthermore, inasmuch as political
rights for groups such as states are usually institutional rights, these fall into the
category of particular rights. In contradistinction, cultural rights are considered
universal human rights. Thus, as the system of international law categorizes
national minority rights as cultural human rights, it leaves the enduring question
of self-determination for national minorities unresolved.8 This is the issue that
Part I will problematize.
To elucidate the problematic relation between protection and national self-
determination in international law one must problematize the discourse of
national minority rights not solely in terms of international law but also in terms
of social idealism. This is why political theorists have been forced to search for
solutions outside international law, within theories of democratization, cit-
izenship, and justice. Theories of democratization, citizenship, and justice merit
attention inasmuch as they relate to the issue of social recognition of national
minorities. Whereas law affords moral recognition in terms of granting rights to
national minorities and their members, democratic institutions, citizenship, and
justice help national minorities and their members achieve social recognition and
the feeling of moral and social worth. First, democratic institutions that include
national minorities in the political process provide them with the opportunity
for individual and collective self-determination. Secondly, citizenship not in
terms of rights but in terms of individual reasoning about action affords
members as well as non-members of national minorities the opportunity to learn
to be self-critical and critical about issues, thus feeling social inclusion. Thirdly,
justice in a form that is acceptable to all members of society and which is
negotiated through democratic institutions affords national minorities the
opportunity to achieve a sense of social worth inasmuch as they are socially and
morally recognized as equal members of society.
However, democratic institutions are often more exclusive than inclusive.
Designing inclusive institutions is a delicate matter in politics, especially in
societies where citizenship is cast in a narrow mould of rights and entitlements.
Citizenship in terms of action is difficult to foster; it requires individual
8 However, see the Human Rights Committee’s General Comment 12(21): ‘The right to self-
9 O’Neill, Onora, Towards Justice and Virtue: A Constructive Account of Practical Reasoning
Linguistic Minorities (New York: United Nations, 1979); Dechênes, Jules, ‘Proposal concerning a
Definition of the term ‘‘Minority’’ ’, UN Doc. E/CN.4/Sub.2/1985/31 and Packer, John, ‘On the
Definition of Minorities’, in John Packer and Kristian Myntti (eds.), The Protection of Ethnic and
Linguistic Minorities in Europe (Åbo: Institute for Human Rights, Åbo Akademi University, 1993),
23–65 as well as Packer, ‘Problems in Defining Minorities’, in Deirdre Fottrell and Bill Bowring,
(eds.), Minority and Group Rights in the New Millennium (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1999), 223.
National Minority, or Co-nation? 19
international law instruments must apply to a wide range of states, a definition
would have to be broad and general. But that is an impossibility in contemporary
circumstances where each national minority may be defined according to par-
ticular and diverse characteristics. Moreover, seeking a definition runs into the
quandary of whether to use objective or subjective criteria.11 Objective criteria
may result in discrimination; subjective criteria could lead to segregation. The
view that national minorities are voluntary associations has also been suggested.12
Over the years, scholars outside the realm of law have volunteered definitions
combining objective and subjective criteria;13 most recently Jennifer Jackson
Preece has put forth a detailed definition which holds that a national minority is
a group numerically inferior to the rest of the population of a state, in a non-dominant
position, well-defined and historically established on the territory of the state, whose
members—being nationals of the state—possess ethnic, religious, linguistic or cultural
characteristics differing from those of the rest of the population and show, if only
implicitly, a sense of solidarity, directed towards preserving their culture, traditions,
religion, or language. (emphasis added)14
As a working tool, this definition is helpful although I would suggest substituting
‘citizens’ for nationals inasmuch as the term national is misleading when
discussing national minorities in relation to national majorities, and because at
the European level national minority protection is viewed as a right of citizens.15
This latter issue is clearly seen in the codification of the term ‘national’ meaning
citizenship, recently introduced in the Council of Europe’s 1997 European
Convention on Nationality, which has only exacerbated matters as members
of national minorities are now demanding the right to dual citizenship.16
Will Kymlicka has suggested a shorthand version holding that national minor-
ities are ‘groups who formed functioning societies on their historical homelands
prior to being incorporated into a larger state’.17 The problem of objective
11 For a good discussion see Pentassuglia, Gaetano, Minorities in International Law (Strasbourg
University Press, 1955), 2; Laponce, J. A., The Protection of Minorities (Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1960), 6. See also in general Macartney, C. A., National States and National
Minorities (London: Oxford University Press, 1934) and Modeen, T., The International Protection
of Minorities in Europe (Åbo: Åbo Akademi, 1969).
14 Jackson Preece, National Minorities and the European Nation-States System (Oxford:
Part II, 6 August 2003; ‘Vojvodina Hungarians Angry at Budapest’ and ‘Hungarian Foreign
Minister Willing to Discuss Dual Citizenship’, RFE/RL Newsline 7/146, Part II, 4 August
2003; ‘Bishop Tokes’s Supporters in Transylvania Back Request for Dual Citizenship’, RFE/RL
Newsline, 7/154, Part II, 14 August 2003.
17 Kymlicka, Politics in the Vernacular: Nationalism, Multiculturalism, and Citizenship (Oxford:
Sharing Systems’, in Will Kymlicka (ed.), The Rights of Minority Cultures (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1995), 275–88 at 275.
19 Tully, James, Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in an Age of Diversity (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1995), 10. See also William E. Connolly, The Ethos of Pluralization
(Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1995), ch. 3.
National Minority, or Co-nation? 21
units, and it is still debated whether they have received international recogni-
tion.20 These national minorities fulfil the third Montevideo criterion because
they often have collective autonomy in terms of self-government or self-
administration. They do not however fulfil the fourth Montevideo criterion, the
capacity to enter into relations with other states. Although this criterion may
come under pressure in the integration of the EU where federal units are
increasingly networking across the European Continent, the capacity to enter
into relations with other states is of course linked to the issues of sovereign
territory inasmuch as it is the centrally held power over territory which deter-
mines recognition. Power over sovereign territory thus seems to be the issue
separating national minorities from being recognized in international law. The
notion of power over sovereign territory will be discussed in detail in Chapter 7;
suffice it to note that the notion is exclusionary not because of the value of
sovereign territory but because of the sentiment of power which excludes some
identities from the territory while not others.21 It would appear that the question
of a scientific definition is fraught with problems. Yet, some might argue that it
is still desirable to define national minorities scientifically, especially if we are
to consider claims by national minorities for special status in international law.
An approach that establishes who and where these groups exist in factual terms
may therefore be more helpful.
Applying the method of elimination may be useful here. Thus, it has been
argued that national minorities are not the religious and immigrant minority
groups that exist in most multicultural states.22 On the contrary, national
minorities are a specific type of minority; they are autochthonous.23 While not
entirely uncontroversial,24 the term autochthonous refers to a minority that is
native to a particular region, in this case certain regions of Europe that were once
either independent or belonged to a neighbouring state. The autochthonous
minority’s present minority status is a result of incorporation into a larger
political unit or the change of borders after major conflicts in modern times.
Most notably this has happened after major bellicose conflicts, such as the
20 The case of the Åland Islands, where there has been a debate as to the status of this
archipelago, is recognized in international law. See Åkermark, Athanasia Spiliopoulou, ‘The Åland
Islands in International Law and Cooperation: The Legal Capacity of an Autonomous Region’, in
Lauri Hannikainen and Frank Horn (eds.), Autonomy and Demilitarisation in International Law:
The Åland Islands in a Changing Europe (The Hague: Kluwer International Law, 1997).
21 Connolly, The Ethos of Pluralization, pp. xxii–xxiii.
22 Smith, Anthony D., Nationalism: Theory, Ideology, History (Cambridge: Polity, 2001), 10–13
and Kymlicka, Multicultural Citizenship: A Liberal Theory of Minority Rights (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1995), 10–11.
23 I borrow the term autochthonous from Silvo Devetak who uses it in ‘Autonomy as One of the
Means of Minorities’ Protection: The Case of Slovenia’, in A. Klinke et al. (eds.), Ethnic Conflicts
and Civil Society (Aldershot: Ashgate, 1997), 99–115.
24 The concept autochthonous if not well defined could lead to discrimination. See ‘Consti-
tution Watch’ of Slovenia in East European Constitutional Review, 102/3 (2001), 41–4, reporting
that the Constitutional Court of Slovenia has ruled the lack of an official definition a cause for
concern, arbitrary and discriminatory.
22 Individualism and Collectivism
Napoleonic Wars, World Wars I and II, but also after the break up of
the USSR.25
National minorities of autochthonous status in Europe are in essence the
groups that have inadvertently found themselves ‘on the wrong side of the border’.
They include, but are not limited to, Hungarians in Slovakia, Romania, Slovenia,
Serbia, and the Ukraine; Turks in Bulgaria and the Balkans; Albanians in Kosovo
and Macedonia; Rusyns, Russians, Romanians, Slovaks, and Belarussians in the
Ukraine; Moravians in the Czech Republic; German-speaking Austrians in
northern Italy; Italians in southern Austria and Slovenia; Germans in southern
Denmark; Danes in northern Germany, and Russians in the Baltic states. While
the territorial criterion for the autochthonous status of most of these groups is
usually quite clear, the criterion of time is less so. Whereas the Hungarians had
been in the Danube basin for many centuries prior to the demise of the Austro-
Hungarian Empire, the Russians in the Baltic states have migrated fairly recently.
But they were migrating within the territory of their own state in much the same
way as the Turkish people had migrated into Bulgaria and other parts of the
Balkans. Hence, the elimination of empires resulted in national groups residing
away from what became their ‘nation-state’ due to the change of borders within
which they had at some point migrated. Autochthonous national minorities also
include other ‘old’ minorities, such as the Bretons in France, the Basques and
the Catalans in Spain, the Welsh, the Scots, and the Irish in the United Kingdom.
In fact, these autochthonous national minorities might well be seen as auto-
chthonous in a stronger sense inasmuch as they have been national groups
attached to territory over an even longer period and some of which have held
independence at one time. Except perhaps for the Scots, most of these national
minorities did not choose to become minorities. Moreover, their members did
not choose to belong to their respective minority.26 Certainly, the view that
national minorities are voluntary associations is out of place here. A good
description of the phenomenon of chance membership as opposed to voluntary
membership is provided by Philip Allott when he argues that
We are born into societies. The first consequence of this fact is that we do not choose
the societies we are born into. The second consequence is that we cannot know what
we would have been, had we been born into other societies. The third consequence is that
we enter at once into a relationship of mutual interaction with societies, an interaction
which we do not leave until we die. The fourth consequence is that our participation
in every other society is conditioned by our participation in the societies into which we
are born.27
opening up of borders after 1989 they began to migrate throughout Europe. They
are by definition nomads, and a defining feature is precisely that they do not wish to
hold power over territory. Nevertheless, most have today become citizens of a legally
recognized state. Some of the new states in Central and Eastern Europe have decided
to recognize Roma and Sinti as autochthonous national minorities thus recently
causing problems of legal definition.30 For the present purpose the Roma and Sinti
will not be considered autochthonous national minorities inasmuch as the problems
that governments face in incorporating these groups are considerably different from
the ones posed by national minorities. In my mind, the problem of integrating
Roma and Sinti groups is largely an economic one akin to the problem of ending the
exclusion of African Americans in North America. The Sami people who live in the
northern parts of Scandinavia, in Norway, Sweden, and Finland, do have autoch-
thonous characteristics, but they are considered indigenous groups rather than
minorities. There is a debate in international law as to whether indigenous peoples
are minorities or not. In my mind, both indigenous groups and national minorities
are nations. But as the issue of indigenous peoples’ self-determination is different
from that of national minorities, given that indigenous peoples do not evidence
strong ‘nation-state’ identities or specific sentiments of nationalism, I will exclude
them from this discussion.31 Finally, refugees who have been forced to flee their
national state and territory against their will and who sometimes settle in host-states
virtually permanently are not considered autochthonous.
Ideally, any one of these groups mentioned needs specific public policies to
address their grievances but these are public policies different from those per-
taining to autochthonous national minorities. As we shall see, Roma, Sinti, and
Sami, as well as refugees, differ from autochthonous national minorities inas-
much as their rights are not linked to the key components that define the
structure of international law.
Slovenia are defined according to two different definitions. Those Romani people who have been in
Slovenia for more than a century have autochthonous status, whereas those that have immigrated
recently do not. East European Constitutional Review, 10/2/3 (2001), 41–4.
31 See Crawford, James, The Rights of Peoples (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988); Aukerman,
Miriam J., ‘Definitions and Justifications: Minority and Indigenous Rights in a Central/East
European Context’, Human Rights Quarterly, 22 (2000), 1011–50, and Brölmann, C. M., and
Zieck, M., ‘Indigenous Peoples’, in Brölmann et al. (eds.), Peoples and Minorities in International
Law (Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, 1993). See also, Kymlicka, Will, Politics in the
Vernacular: Nationalism, Multiculturalism and Citizenship (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2001), ch. 6.
National Minority, or Co-nation? 25
state nationalism. State sovereignty, as noted above, is dependent on fulfilling
the criteria laid out in the Montevideo Convention and the UN Charter as
well as passing the test of national self-determination. State nationalism refers
to the prevailing view of nationalism promoted by the state. When verifying
if recognition, and thus state sovereignty, can be had in international law,
not only power over sovereign territory and population must be verified but
the test of national self-determination must also be passed. National self-
determination is exercised through the power of a population to give its con-
sent. National self-determination being informed by the nationalism of the
state therefore assumes that the entire population adheres to the nationalism of
the state. Thus, for national self-determination and state nationalism to act
together, they presuppose a neat fit between the state and the nation. However,
as noted above, in reality nations and states rarely coincide. This conflation of
state and nation has ramifications for autochthonous national minorities
because state nationalism usually derives its legitimacy from being the
foundation of an independent state based on the assumption of one autoch-
thonous national group to one state. When state nationalism informs national
self-determination, the national self-determination test must presuppose one
autochthonous national group to one state. This results in national self-
determination being exclusionary, as autochthonous national minorities are not
members of the autochthonous national group constituting the majority of the
population. Inasmuch as international law recognizes state sovereignty based on
the national self-determination of one autochthonous national group, it would
appear that even if autochthonous national minorities fulfilled the Montevideo
and UN Charter criteria of power over sovereign territory and population, they
could not have recognition because they represent one nationalism too many
within a sovereign state. Surely, the argument that autochthonous national
minorities are not recognized in international law because they are not con-
sidered a ‘people’ is ambiguous.
How has international law arrived at this confusing situation? First, the history
of the concept of a minority predates the notion of the ‘nation-state’ as it became
known in the Westphalian era. As I will discuss below, prior to the so-called
Westphalian states system, whose inception is usually dated to 1648, the
problem of minority groups was still largely seen in terms of religion.32 It was
not until after the French Revolution in 1789 and the settlement after the
Napoleonic Wars in 1815 at the Congress of Vienna that the concept of a
national minority first came into being.33 The phenomena of national minor-
ities and national minority rights were to some extent also the result of the
32 For an excellent survey of the religio-national minorities see Gilbert, Geoff, ‘Religio-
nationalist Minorities and the Development of Minority Rights Law’, in Review of International
Studies, 25 (1999), 389–410.
33 Thornberry, Patrick, International Law and the Rights of Minorities (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1991), 29.
26 Individualism and Collectivism
international law’, which is the system of law in terms of adherence to treaties, custom, and general
principles and which usually refers to the adjudication of the relationships between states. The term
‘positive international law’ is sometimes used interchangeably with public international law.
Secondly, the term ‘public international human rights law’ refers to the post-World War II regime
of universal human rights law which is also enshrined in treaties but which usually refers to the
relationship between state governments and individuals. Both systems of law originated in the
modern era of history. Henceforth the term ‘modern international law’ will refer also to both these
systems, but when discussing issues prior to World War II, it will refer to ‘public international law’.
See also Chapter 3. In addition, there is the term ‘classic law’, which usually refers to law and legal
theory before the Westphalian system of modern states.
35 See the recent study by Evans, Garreth, and Sahnoun, Mohamed (eds.), The Responsibility to
Protect: Report of the International Commission on Intervention and State Sovereignty and its Sup-
plementary Volume (Ottawa: International Development Research Centre, 2001).
36 Carty, Anthony, The Decay of International Law? (Manchester: Manchester University Press,
1986), 2.
National Minority, or Co-nation? 27
was a concept little defined and only God was considered morally eligible to hold
the rights of a sovereign as defended in the writings of one of the early theorists
of sovereignty, Jean Bodin (1530–96). Later the rights of the sovereign were
transferred to monarchs inasmuch as a need had emerged to explain the concept
of sovereignty as well as the right of sovereignty held by kings and princes when
states began to form in Europe. The need for conceptualization of the natural
right of sovereignty resulted in a transposition of the right from God to mon-
archs as a derivative divine right. This was also the beginning of the idea of
Hobbesian state sovereignty.37 On this conception, each state has a natural right
to self-preservation. Hence the relations of states in modern international rela-
tions were that of the state of nature, of all states against all.38 This outlook,
which renders the state the only sovereign, therefore leaves no room for any other
sovereign entity within the state. As we will see, this is one of the core conceptual
problems that the existence of national minorities challenges in law.
Secondly, with the rise of the doctrine of state sovereignty in modern inter-
national law, state sovereignty became equated with jurisdiction over a defined
territory and population. In terms of international law codification, in so far as
we agree with the view that international law is codified, the codification of state
sovereignty began with the 1648 Peace of Westphalia and the formation of a
system of treaty relationships among modern states in Europe. And it survived
into the twentieth century, exemplified in the 1933 Montevideo Convention
and the UN Charter. In modern international law, territory and borders are fixed
to the concept of state sovereignty and remain the jurisdiction of states only. This
became a firm principle in modern international law in the nineteenth century
by the edict laid out in the doctrine of uti possidetis iuris. This doctrine was
first articulated in Latin America after Spanish rule was overthrown and was
reconfirmed by the Montevideo Convention.39 Basically, it refers to ‘the prin-
ciple involving the preservation of the demarcations under the colonial regimes
corresponding to each of the colonial entities that was constituted as a state’.40
During the decolonization of Africa it was preserved, and in 1986, the Inter-
national Court of Justice (ICJ) acknowledged it in the Frontier dispute case
between Burkina Faso and Mali.41 Most recently, the principle of uti possidetis
has been upheld in the conflict over territories in the Balkans and thus expanded
beyond the colonial context. While the principle is currently under pressure in
the debate over the right to independence for Kosovo, there appears little pos-
sibility that it will be redefined. The artificiality of state borders seems set in
37 Hinsley, F. H., Sovereignty (London: C. A. Watts & Co. Ltd., 1966), 142.
38 Carty, The Decay of International Law? at 2.
39 Klabbers, J. and Lefeber, R., ‘Africa: Lost between Self-Determination and Uti Possidetis’, in
1997), 236.
28 Individualism and Collectivism
concrete.42 State sovereignty therefore is not only a right that belongs uniquely to
states but also a codified de jure right that stipulates the border jurisdiction over
territory and population.
the Post-communist Era: A Historical Perspective’, in Nations and Nationalism, 9/3 (2003), 433–50.
43 Gilbert, ‘Religio-nationalist Minorities and the Development of Minority Rights Law’, 389.
See also Jackson Preece, National Minorities and the European Nation-States System, ch. 4.
44 Vieytez, Eduardo Ruiz, The History of Legal Protection of Minorities in Europe, XVIIth–XXth
Centuries (Derby: University of Derby, Working Papers in International Law and Relations, 1,
1999), 29.
National Minority, or Co-nation? 29
Poland, the Serb-Croat-Slovene State as well as Czecho-Slovakia, the states that
had been on the losing side of the war.45 These Treaties were the first attempt in
modern international law to codify the rights of autochthonous national
minorities per se. However, as the Council of the League of Nations disintegrated
and the Nazi regime employed its deceitful rhetoric of autochthonous national
minority protection, the Treaties system suffered the unusual fate of disap-
pearance from international law. Today, it is largely held that the establishment
of the UN has replaced not only the League of Nations but also the Minorities
Treaties system. In this post-war system of modern international law, by some
termed ‘liberal’ international law or ‘pacifist’ international law46 the regime of
autochthonous national minority rights suffered the same fate as its parent
system. Autochthonous national minority rights as a legal concept surfaced again
only after 1989. This eclipse was in large part due to the fact that Lockean
individual natural rights, by now termed human rights, had gained hegemonic
power in modern international law and created the system of public interna-
tional human rights law as distinct from public international law.
The Minorities Treaties as well as a number of parallel and specific treaties and
unilateral declarations had established a common model of rights that protected
the rights of autochthonous national minorities. This model ensured for
members the right to adopt the citizenship of the state in which they lived and
full civil and political rights, including the freedom to access public office and
full equality before the law. The model also entitled individual members of
autochthonous national minorities to basic education in their native language,
freedom to receive tutoring in their mother tongue, and most importantly,
financial support from the state when necessary for the maintenance of their
native language and culture.47 In addition to these individual rights, certain
treaties established the right to autonomy for specific autochthonous national
minorities. The right to local autonomy was secured for the Saxons and
Hungarians in Transylvania and the regions of Transcarpathia and Ruthenia
were given territorial autonomy. Unfortunately, Czechoslovakia never fulfilled
its obligations to the latter two regions. Hence, as could be expected, the general
tenor of these treaties, as well as their procedural framework within the Council
of the League of Nations, were primarily propelled by the urge to protect the
status quo of borders in Europe.48 However, the concept of autochthonous
45 Treaty of Peace between the Allied and Associated Powers and Austria, Poland, the Serb-
although this concept remains disputed. With respect to the legal system of this period, David Held
during a seminar at the University of Essex, 7 February 2001 termed this ‘liberal’ international law.
Siegfried Schieder has termed it ‘pacifist’ international law in ‘Pragmatism as a Path towards a
Discursive and Open Theory of International Law’, European Journal of International Law, 11/3
(2000), 663–98. 47 Vieytez, The History of Legal Protection of Minorities in Europe, 32.
48 See the discussion of the Tittioni Report in Eppstein, John, Ten Years’ Life of the League of
Friendly Relations and Co-operation among States in accordance with the Charter of the United
Nations’.
54 See Jackson Preece, National Minorities and the European Nation-States Systems, 9.
55 ‘Draft Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous Peoples’, UN Doc. E/CN. 4/Sub.2/1994/2/
Add.1; International Labour Organization (ILO) Convention No. 169 of 1989, ‘Convention
concerning Indigenous and Tribal Peoples in Independent Countries’. See also the Martinez Cobo
Report in UN Doc. E/CN.4/Sub.2/1983/21/Add.8.
32 Individualism and Collectivism
Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (ICCPR), adopted in 1966. This time
the international community agreed on the inclusion of a minority clause, but
not a national minority clause. Article 27 of the ICCPR granted the individual
members of minorities the right to enjoy their ethnic, religious, or linguistic
culture. The Article reads as follows:
In those States in which ethnic, religious or linguistic minorities exist, persons belonging
to such minorities shall not be denied the right, in community with the other members of
their group, to enjoy their own culture, to profess and practice their own religion, or to
use their own language.
This article thus established the right to minority culture as a norm in public
international human rights law. However, conceptually these rights followed the
norm of the UDHR and the ECHR as well as the other articles of the ICCPR
inasmuch as it established these rights as individual human rights. It remains an
argument among scholars whether Article 27 should be interpreted as conferring
rights on a group notion.56 Moreover, not only was the notion of group rights
eclipsed in the post-World War II regime, the adjective national which had been
introduced after World War I was entirely dropped from the post-war language
of autochthonous national minority protection in public international human
rights law. This was on the supposition that if linguistic minorities considered
themselves autochthonous national minorities, the cultural right to language in
Article 27 would protect their rights. By the time that sub-state nationalisms
jetted out from the break-up of the former Communist bloc and back onto the
European political horizon in 1989, autochthonous national minority rights
were non-existing in modern international law.
60 Canovan, Margaret, ‘Sleeping Dogs, Prowling Cats and Soaring Doves: Three Paradoxes in
University Press, 1994). See also, Moynihan, Daniel Patrick, Pandaemonium: Ethnicity in
International Politics (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1993).
62 Smith, Nationalism. See also Smith, Nations and Nationalism in a Global Era (Cambridge:
Enlargement’, in Jan Zielonka (ed.), Europe Unbound: Enlarging and Reshaping the Boundaries of the
European Union (London: Routledge, 2002).
National Minority, or Co-nation? 35
their lives. The differences between the autochthonous national minorities and
the majority population representing the state are likely to be fairly well pro-
nounced and may create not only differences as to what constitutes the good life
but may also bring about clashes of rights and entitlements. Although such
practical issues are not the only reasons for clashes, they are certainly an over-
whelming reason and cause for day-to-day disputes.65 If the assumption is that
all human beings including members of national minorities wish to lead a good
life and feel respected, public policies that are conducive to the well-being and
respect of members of autochthonous national minorities are therefore vital to
the stability and peace of divided states.
Public policies are a way in which state governments can show that they want
to include national minorities that are not members of the majority national
group in the affairs and management of society. Public policies that are not
conducive to the well-being and respect of autochthonous national minorities or
are discriminating in favour of the majority may lead autochthonous national
minorities in the direction of separatism. This could force autochthonous
national minorities to face the problem of whether they wish to accept the
public policies or reject them and seek some form of separation either through
partition or secession. However, if state governments forge inclusive citizenship
for members of autochthonous national minorities that emphasizes ongoing
constructive relations and negotiations between the governments and the
autochthonous national minority groups, there may be a basis for honourable
accommodation if not democratic cohabitation. The major link between the
majority and autochthonous national minorities being public policies, problems
in this relationship usually arise when the substantive content of the public
policies has to be determined.
Given that autochthonous national minorities most often speak a foreign
language, language policies are usually the most prominent issue and frequently
the most contentious. In the Ukraine the question of the status of the Russian
language has had ramifications for the bilateral relations between the Ukraine
and Russia, and in Croatia the issue of minority languages has reached the
highest court.66 It appears to be one of those ‘damned if you do, and damned if
you don’t’ issues. Speaking one’s mother tongue is more than just a habit and
65 Kymlicka, Politics in the Vernacular, 61.
66 For an assessment of the situation in the Ukraine see, Kuzio, Taras, ‘Status of Russian
Language again Threatens Ukrainian–Russian Relations’, RFE/RL 5/2, part II, 10 January 2001.
See also ‘Croatian Bilingualism on Ice’ and ‘Istria to Appeal Decision on Bilingualism’, RFE/RL
5/79, Part II, 24 April 2001; ‘Croatian Government sends Istrian Language Law to Constitutional
Court’, RFE/RL 5/98, Part II, 23 May 2001, and ‘Istrian Party leaves Croatian Government’,
RFE/RL 5/105, Part II, 4 June 2001.
36 Individualism and Collectivism
68 See ‘Report on the Situation of Hungarians in Slovakia’ issued by the Government Office of
Hungarian Minorities Abroad (GOHMA) and Hungarian Ministry of Foreign Affairs, Budapest,
December 1997 available at www.htmh.hu, and Daftary, Farimah, ‘NGO Roundtable on
Inter-ethnic Relations in the FYR of Macedonia, First Meeting’, in ECMI Report, No. 7 (Flensburg:
ECMI, 2001).
69 See Crawford, Leslie, ‘Nation Fights for Recognition’, Financial Times, Spain Annual Report,
71 See Craiutu, Aurelian, ‘A Dilemma of Dual Identity: The Democratic Alliance of Hungarians
Typology’, delivered at the Bratislava Symposium II, 13–16 November 1991, published in
Jena Plichtova (ed.), Minorities in Politics Bratislava Symposium II(Bratislava: European Cultural
Foundation, 1992).
73 See ‘Romanian Opposition Party Opposes Hungarian Demand’, RFE/RL 5/27, Part II, 8
February 2001.
74 I am grateful to Peter Jones for pointing this out to me and in general for engaging very
79 See X and Y v Belgium (1966) and the Belgian Linguistic case (1968).
National Minority, or Co-nation? 43
problems have been cited as probably the most intractable issues of the Canadian
federal state.80 Although not a European state, Canada has been grappling with
the same problems as many European states are now experiencing, especially the
new democracies in Central and Eastern Europe. The problems in Canada have
caused frictions in the relationship between the French co-nation of the federal
unit of Québec and the Anglophone people who are not members of the French
co-nation. Moreover, linguistic federalism may not in fact provide co-nations
with power at the central level that they had hoped for. This is the problem that is
particularly acute in those states in Central and Eastern Europe where co-nations
are small in numbers compared to the French in Canada. While Macedonia and
Romania are both wary of tensions that have resulted from federation, such as the
break-up of the Czech and Slovak republics, Moldova has recently taken steps to
institutionalize federalism. Bosnia and Herzegovina, although a federal state, has
in fact been founded on a rather more complex model of power sharing.
A third and much more complex model of power sharing seen in Europe is
consociationalism in terms of groups that are not territorially defined.81 This
model, successful in the Netherlands between 1917 and 1967, is struggling to
come into existence in Northern Ireland, Bosnia and Herzegovina, as well as
Kosovo and exists to some extent in Switzerland.82 It is a model which has had
little success outside Europe, collapsing in Lebanon but it still exists in Malaysia.
Like federalism, this system promises a great deal to co-nations in terms of the
right to power over their own affairs and guaranteed inclusion in decision-making
processes. While it is not a model designed specifically for co-nation accom-
modation, it might work with some adjustment and fine-tuning. One of the
problems with consociationalism, however, is that it is not clear whether it can
overcome the problem of undemocratic results, such as discrimination against
minorities within co-nations.83 Moreover, inasmuch as the powers that it would
decentralize to co-nations might be far-reaching in terms of self-administration,
this might result in undemocratic rules within the co-nation, such as forced
homogenizing of co-nation identities. In a time of multi-contextual identities
this seems implausible. However, it is also possible that the human interaction
across co-nation lines that consociationalism requires might overcome this.
In fact, greater human interaction might promote non-discrimination through
the sharing of problems and knowledge.84 The political institutionalization of
and Post-Communism’ in W. Kymlicka and M. Opalski, (eds.), Can Liberal Pluralism be Exported?
Western Political Theory and Ethnic Relations in Eastern Europe (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2001), 109–25 at 112.
83 McGarry and O’Leary (eds.), The Politics of Ethnic Conflict Regulation.
84 Connolly, The Ethos of Pluralization, 97–104.
44 Individualism and Collectivism
1.6 Citizenship
Philip Pettit (eds.), Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Anthology (Oxford: Blackwell, 1997),
291–319.
National Minority, or Co-nation? 45
the second, the political, and the third, the social notions, refer to individual
power in terms of political participation and welfare. These distinctions should
not be seen as absolutes because, arguably, in many cases they overlap. Indeed,
twenty-first-century citizenship is considerably more complex, and the thematic
aspects are intertwined and change constantly with the evolutions of globaliza-
tion and technology. Moreover, as it has been argued that there is a danger of
conflating ‘citizenship-as-desirable-activity’ with ‘citizenship-as-legal-status’,88 a
concentration on the latter has often resulted in neglect of the former. Certainly,
citizenship refers to the right of political participation, duties to other citizens,
and responsibility for the welfare of the community as a whole.89 In theorizing
the accommodation of co-nations one must take into account all three themes of
citizenship as well as rights and activity. One should also ideally go beyond these
to include a co-nation dimension.
The co-nation dimension is important inasmuch as co-nations have at times
become adversaries to the ruling co-nation, and at other times they have even
become enemies owing to their co-nation identity invoking an ‘us–them’ rela-
tionship with the ruling co-nation. Even if recognized legally as citizens of
their state, members of co-nations rarely identify with the nationalism of the
ruling co-nation. Moreover, as they cannot be expected to shed their co-nation
identity just because they live in a different national state, problems of loyalty are
posed, loyalty towards the co-nation and loyalty towards the state. This creates
the problem of what Philip Allott calls ‘two forms of energy’ within one sov-
ereign state.90 In terms of identity, rather than fostering dual identities, this has
resulted in members of many co-nations feeling like and actually at times
becoming second-class citizens.91 Feeling like a second-class citizen is of course
not a problem only experienced by members of co-nations; women, blacks, poor,
and homosexuals, to mention a few, have also claimed to feel like second-class
citizens in their respective societies. However, when members of co-nations
have been excluded from public administration on the basis of their lack of
language abilities, it seems plausible to consider their complaints. After an official
language law was adopted in Slovakia recently, members of the Hungarian
co-nation were excluded from public service due to lack of language abilities.
Similarly, Albanians in Macedonia have integrated poorly due to lack of edu-
cation and language abilities. Kosovo-Albanians, on the other hand, were
excluded during Milosevic’s regime simply on the basis of their membership
of the ‘wrong’ co-nation. It would seem that co-nations are discriminated
88 Kymlicka and Norman make this distinction in Kymlicka, Will, and Norman, Wayne,
‘Return of the Citizen: A Survey of Recent Work on Citizenship Theory’, Ethics, 104 (1994)
352–81 at 353.
89 Linklater, Andrew, The Transformation of Political Community: Ethical Foundations of the Post-
against both in terms of social injustice and historical misfortune. Either way
recognition seems an ethical approach to reconciliation. This does not mean that
all complaints are valid nor that other groups in society, such as ethnic or cultural
groups, do not suffer similar discrimination. They often do, and their problems
should also be addressed. But unlike co-nations, these groups do not pose any
apparent threat to peace and stability. In the name of not only peace and social
unity but also human dignity and respect, it would seem that responsibility for
seeking to alleviate discrimination against members of non-ruling co-nations lies
with the ruling co-nation.
Addressing the problem of second-class citizenship requires not only a con-
cern for opportunities; it is also necessary to value such groups equally with
other people. Although this might in practice be utopian, it should at least be
regarded as an honourable ideal for which people have the right to strive. To
co-nations, individual worth in terms of having ethical standing is linked
to moral and social recognition. The idea of recognition and status is a
decidedly modern and primarily a European concept. It is best known in
European philosophical thought from the writings of the German philosopher
G. W. F. Hegel, who pointed out that the individual’s constant striving for
recognition is not a good basis for social relationships.92 Charles Taylor has
picked up on this and argued that lack of recognition is a serious matter because
it may deprive the individual of recognition. Mis-recognition, he argues, can
result in individuals feeling
real damage, real distortion, if the people or society around them mirror back to them a
confining or demeaning or contemptible picture of themselves. Nonrecognition or
misrecognition can inflict harm, can be a form of oppression, imprisoning someone in a
false, distorted, and reduced mode of being.93
Thus, when co-nations are concerned with recognition, one must take it that
they are concerned with the well-being and respect of their members. This means
that they are concerned with the exact same issues with which most members of
ruling co-nations are concerned, namely the freedom to self-identify with their
peers, to speak and learn their mother tongue both in the public and the private
spheres, and to preserve their national heritage and pass it on to their offspring
through community life, to mention a few. Recognition for co-nations is a
question of desiring respect, not only in terms of being left alone, but also in
terms of self-esteem and moral and social worth. However, recognition of
people’s worth is a highly subjective matter; we all harbour some feelings of
prejudice within us.94 This is why philosophers such as Taylor and Axel
92 See Hegel, G. W. F., The Phenomenology of Spirit, trans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Oxford
Examining the Politics of Recognition (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994), 25–74 at 25.
94 Connolly, The Ethos of Pluralization, chs. 1 and 4.
National Minority, or Co-nation? 47
Honneth have identified the constant need for struggles of recognition as a major
component of human interaction and subsequently a prerequisite for developing
democratic societies. Hence, recognition also becomes a very arbitrary matter.
But when we decide that we cannot give recognition to an individual or a group
of people because of our subjective dislike of them, we may not always have
factual reasons for doing so. This is why in liberal ideology toleration is such an
important virtue.
To political theorists toleration comes in different shades but two meanings
have emerged as general knowledge. Susan Mendus in paraphrasing Lord
Scarman argues that on a narrow scope toleration refers to the act of disapproval
of somebody morally, meaning the ‘non-act’ of letting someone alone.95 On a
more positive notion, Karl-Otto Apel, Sheldon Leader, and Michael Walzer have
argued for a form of acceptance of the opponent’s right to existence that builds
on a sentiment of respect.96 While on the narrow scope toleration makes social
interaction difficult, the positive notion would promote the virtue of showing
respect. However, it is not entirely clear that the positive notion will help
individuals to foster self-esteem and self-respect inasmuch as it does not require
interaction with the people who are the object of this toleration. The problem
with both types of toleration is that they do not go far enough to support an
ethical theory of citizenship.
Citizenship theory is a large topic in political theory. The positive conception
of toleration coupled with rights is generally the conception of citizenship that is
fostered in liberal democracies. Stephen Macedo describes this in terms of a set of
liberal virtues and responsibilities that are required to make human interaction
function in liberal societies.97 But there are limits to this liberal citizenship as it
presupposes neutrality in terms of commitments to nation, region, or tribe.
David Miller has proposed a citizenship that takes into consideration national
identity and nationality but considers the ‘nation-state’ as the locus of people’s
identity.98 Kymlicka has argued for a multicultural citizenship based on liberal
pluralism that takes in the notions of both nationality and regionality.99
However, in addition to focusing on how to incorporate nationalism into a model
of citizenship, it is also important to theorize how people should act to one
another. This is an approach that is particularly helpful to theorizing citizenship
for diverse societies and which has been championed by William Galston.100
Unfortunately, he does not address the problem of how citizens achieve the
ability to act in an ethical way. Indeed, few theorists concern themselves with the
way in which individuals might reason in order to achieve and promote the goal
of recognition. Individual practical reasoning determines how we reason about
the values that guide actions, our own as well as those of others. A recent
reinterpretation of Immanuel Kant’s model of individual practical reasoning
proposed by Onora O’Neill as a critical mode of reasoning seeks to alleviate
some of these problems.101 This is a model that is highly idealized, and it may be
argued that it is difficult to implement in terms of public policy. William
Connolly has suggested a comparable, non-Kantian, post-Nietzschean critical
responsiveness mode to social interaction in a democratic ethos.102 While
respecting each philosopher’s ideological leanings, both O’Neill and Connolly
theorize, in my mind, a critical citizenship approach and in doing so question the
assumption that it is desirable to seek a fixed model of justice.
1.7 Justice
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991). 101 O’Neill, Towards Justice and Virtue.
102 Connolly, The Ethos of Pluralization. 103 Tully, Strange Multiplicity, 24.
National Minority, or Co-nation? 49
into account all voices in society. In fact, if rules are to be found as to how voices
are to be heard, the discursive system suggests these rules be defined by all rather
than by the few. Essentially, this approach seeks to return the space for virtues
and ethics in terms of rules of conduct to the activities of human interaction.
Disagreements and divergences about the good life are not however easily settled.
Relying on law alone to settle disputes risks excluding those co-nations which
are not capable of bringing their cause to the courts. And allowing disputes to
be settled through bargaining is even more likely to exclude co-nations as
bargaining often results in the overriding of less forceful arguments. Of course,
there might be co-nations who opt not to participate in the management of their
society. They may not have the political will or leadership required. However, a
healthy political debate that allows for all voices to be heard, irrespective of the
languages and modes used, could possibly bring together both strong and weak
voices. The debate should ideally go beyond the view that adversaries in the
discussion are enemies. That is why a healthy debate is signified by its ability to
produce respect and consideration of the other. The healthy debate that pro-
duces participation across the board is nevertheless very difficult to achieve. This
is why the discursive approach proposes a return to virtues and ethics.
Ethics here means a set of rules constituting a defined sphere, and virtues refer
to the way in which human beings interact. While the discursive approach needs
an account of ethics in terms of both action and guidelines for dialogue, most
accounts of human interaction stop short of establishing what virtues are needed
when individuals and groups reason with each other during the discursive
approach to justice and democracy. This may in part be due to the fact that it is
often argued that ethics and politics should be kept apart, and that, inasmuch as
ethics are not seen as part of politics, an account of virtues is not deemed
necessary.104 However, theorizing co-nation relations in divided societies is
impossible without taking into account virtues and ethics. The expansion of the
Lockean ideal of toleration as reworked by Kant in the ethics of virtue and duty is
found in much of European life today. But while both Locke and Kant are
considered liberal philosophers, the ethics of virtue defended in liberalism has
recently been put under scrutiny and a revisionary conception of Kantian ethics
has emerged.
Revisionary Kantian ethics argues that virtues and liberalism used to com-
plement each other but have become severed in modern times because liberalism
diverged.105 On this view, liberalism developed into an ethos of freedom and
choice, which suppressed the importance of virtues. Moreover, liberalism divided
into two different strands of liberalism.106 One, the European version, retained a
strong ethos of virtues and settled into the European tradition of republicanism
104 Bellamy, Richard, Rethinking Liberalism (London: Pinter, 2000), 103.
105 O’Neill, Towards Justice and Virtue, 37.
106 Onuf, Nicholas Greenwood, The Republican Legacy in International Thought (Cambridge:
that was descended from the Roman Republic and Nicolò Machiavelli’s political
theory. The other liberalism, the Atlantic version, adjusted to the expansive
commercialism of laissez-faire policies and the economic changes of the Industrial
Revolution in the nineteenth century and became the Anglo-American tradition
of liberal justice. The revisionary theory of Kantian ethics retains the strong link
between the virtues of the European version and the justice of the Anglo-
American version. Thus, it appears to have the potential to support the need in
the discursive approach for individual virtuous action as it builds on the critical
practical reasoning model and seeks to provide the science of human interaction
with a mode of ethical consideration. Ethical consideration, as stated above, refers
to the act of moral and social recognition of constitutive communities. But more
importantly, it refers to the ability to be able to foster a notion of individualism
that enables the individual to de-emphasize her own needs and desires when
required and show regard for those of others. This means that the individual
should be capable of going beyond positive toleration and simple respect to foster
cosmopolitan consideration. In a sense this theory of ethical consideration would
promote a cosmopolitan environment of mutual respect as well as a mutual desire
for the other’s self-esteem to grow. It is of course a highly idealized theory and it is
questionable whether it would work in every state where co-nations are seeking
ethical standing. It is a theoretical model that requires much in terms not only of
political will but also civic education and transparency. Indeed, it is a model that
is mainly action guiding and should not be expected to determine action. But in
those societies in Europe where co-nation conflicts have festered and are escal-
ating, it should be investigated whether ethical cosmopolitan consideration might
be fostered through critical individual practical reasoning. If not, its imple-
mentation should be sought across the board to promote a productive environ-
ment for discursive agreement about justice. This may further a desire on behalf
of all members of society for reconciliation, for willingness to show cosmopolitan
consideration, and, most of all, for a flexible model of justice that is relevant to
and accepted by the people it touches.
Inasmuch as the vocabulary of reconciliation, willingness, and consideration is
not as yet part of the legal discourse of co-nation rights and accommodation, a
journey that embarks on elucidating this problem might be worthwhile. More-
over, to attain the purpose of assessing the influence of the post-1989 co-nation
rights discourse on European international ‘politics of accommodation’, the
theoretical approaches to institutionalization of cohabitation and accommodation
that inform the political discourse need scrutinizing. The remainder of Part I will
focus on the post-1989 discourse within the realm of modern international law
and legal theory. Part II will analyse theoretical approaches to accommodation,
citizenship, and justice that dominate the theoretical debate and will seek to
develop an alternative framework of co-nation accommodation. And Part III will
seek to assess the extent to which the post-1989 discourse has informed European
international politics, specifically in the Council of Europe and the EU.