The Quest For Evolutionary Socialism - Eduard Bernstein and Social Democracy (1997)
The Quest For Evolutionary Socialism - Eduard Bernstein and Social Democracy (1997)
The Quest For Evolutionary Socialism - Eduard Bernstein and Social Democracy (1997)
I CAMBRIDGE
UNIVERSITY PRESS
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, Sao Paulo
Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521582001
© Manfred B. Steger 1997
Acknowledgments xi
List of abbreviations xiii
Part 1: Preparation
1. The making of a social democrat 19
2. Persecution and exile 41
3. The "Revisionist Controversy" 66
Part 2: Vision
4. The meaning of socialism 89
5. Evolutionary socialism as "organized liberalism": rethinking
economics, state, and democracy 120
Part 3: Disappointment
6. Facing the critics 151
7. The revisionist debate extended 176
8. The dawn of a new era 205
9. Bernstein's final battle: confronting socialist instrumentalism 230
The research and writing of this book would not have been possible
without a large number of institutions and individuals to whom I feel
greatly indebted. I am deeply grateful to the librarians of Rutgers
University, Princeton University, University of Hawaii-Manoa, and
Whitman College for extending to me the privilege of borrowing books. In
addition, I have used the collections of the New York Public Library,
Harvard University, University of Washington, the University of Munich,
the University of Amsterdam, and the Universities of Vienna and Graz.
Furthermore, I want to thank Dr. Wolfgang Maderthaner, Director of the
Austrian Association for the History of the Austrian Labor Movement in
Vienna; and Ms. Mieke Yzermans of the International Institute of Social
History in Amsterdam, for allowing me to use the extensive archives of
their respective institutions. In addition, the International Institute of
Social History has graciously permitted me to quote from its Bernstein
Archive.
My dear friend and teacher, Stephen Eric Bronner of Rutgers University,
and his wife, Anne Burns, have been of immense help in all stages of this
project; without Steve's erudite criticism and Anne's kind words of
encouragement, this study would have never been written. I am also
indebted to P. Dennis Bathory, W. Carey McWilliams, and William
Solomon, who offered important comments. Terrell Carver, Henry
Tudor, and John H. Kautsky read the entire typescript and offered
invaluable suggestions; I owe them special acknowledgments. I also
would like to thank my colleagues Michael Curtis, Gordon Schochet,
Edward Rhodes, Lawrence Besserman, Scott McLean, Manfred Hennin-
gsen, Peter Manicas, Eldon Kenworthy, Philip Brick, Mary Hanna, and
Timothy Kaufman-Osborn, for their general advice and support, and
wish to extend my gratitude to Michael Forman, Walter Jimenez,
Christine Kelly, Benjamin Peck, Susan Craig, Matt Reed, F. Peter
Wagner, and Stuart MacNiven for offering me the benefit of their comments.
Richard Fisher, my editor at Cambridge University Press, deserves
special recognition. His patience, attention to detail, and professional
xi
xii Acknowledgments
competence turned my typescript into a much better book. Finally, I
would like to express my deepest gratitude to my wife, Dr. Perle
Besserman, whose immense support and expertise enabled me to complete
this project.
Abbreviations
More than thirty years ago, Sidney Hook, the late historian of socialist
thought, lamented the fact that "Eduard Bernstein has not yet come into
his own."1 Though Bernstein, the "Father of Marxist Revisionism,"
escaped the cruel fate of many of his socialist contemporaries who fell prey
to historical oblivion, Hook's lucid observation continued to remain true,
at least in the Anglo-American context, until the late 1980s.
When I began my study of Bernstein's life and political thought in
1989, Peter Gay's important, but dated volume still represented the only
full-scale Bernstein biography available in English.2 Within the next three
years, however, monumental historical changes gave my scholarly efforts
new significance: the Berlin Wall crumbled, the Iron Curtain disap-
peared, and the Soviet Union dissolved. Indeed, the death of Marxism-
Leninism rekindled lively discussions on the fate of socialism in general,
including the ailing Western European model of social democracy.3
Critical questions abounded regarding the feasibility of any radically
egalitarian reforms in our era of globally integrated capitalism. A century
after the famous "Revisionist Controversy" of German social democracy,
1
Sidney Hook, "Introduction," in Eduard Bernstein, Evolutionary Socialism, trans. Edith
C. Harvey (New York: Schocken, 1961), p. xx.
2
DDS.
3
See, for example, William K. Tabb, ed. The Future of Socialism (New York: Monthly
Review Press, 1990); Thomas Meyer, Was bleibt vom Sozialismus? (Reinbeck: Rowohlt,
1991); and Demokratischer Sozialismus - Soziale Demokratie (Berlin: Dietz, 1991); Robin
Blackburn, "Fin de Siecle: Socialism after the Crash," in New Left Review 185 (1991), pp.
5-66; Stephen Eric Bronner Socialism Unbound (New York: Routledge, 1990); and
Moments of Decision (New York: Routledge, 1992); Christiane Lemke and Gary Marks,
eds. The Crisis of Socialism in Europe (Durham, NC: Duke UP, 1992); Alex Callinicos, The
Revenge of History: Marxism and the East European Revolutions (University Park, PA: Penn
State University Press, 1993); Joseph V. Femia, Marxism and Democracy (Oxford: Oxford
UP, 1993); John Roemer, A Future for Socialism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1994);
Ronald Aronson, After Marxism (New York: Guilford,1994); Peter Beilharz, Postmodern
Socialism (Melbourne: Melbourne UP, 1994); and Antonio Callari, Stephen Cullenberg,
and Carole Biewener, Marxism in the Postmodern Age (New York: Guilford, 1994); and
Michael Waller, Bruno Coppieters, and Kris Deschouwer, eds. Social Democracy in a
Post-Communist Europe (Portland, OR: F. Cass, 1994).
1
2 Introduction
Bernstein's model of "evolutionary socialism" became once again the
focus of heated debates.
Indeed, a number of new publications made accessible translations of
both Bernstein's early and later writings.4 Other authors revisited the
historical connections between the Wilhelmine Empire and the rise of
German social democracy, as well as scrutinizing the various intellectual
currents within revisionist Marxist thought;5 and still others probed the
extent to which Bernstein's theoretical framework might provide badly
needed impulses for the survival of a distinct political tradition stretching
back 150 years.6
My study addresses these current debates on socialism arising from
both the sudden collapse of Marxism-Leninism and the crisis of European
social democracy. As I see it, Bernstein's neglected contribution to
socialist theory speaks directly to the current process of rethinking the
traditional project of the democratic Left. At the same time, this book
seeks to answer the urgent need for a new Bernstein biography that
incorporates recent scholarly developments on the topic. As a result, my
study represents neither a conventional political history nor a traditional
"historiography of political ideas," but an examination of the past and
4
See, for example, MS; PS, Till Schelz-Brandenburg, Eduard Bernstein und Karl Kautsky:
Entstehung und Wandlung des sozialdemokratischen Parteimarxismus im Spiegel ihrer Korres-
pondenz 1879-1932 (Koln: Bohlau, 1992). See also my Selected Writings of Eduard
Bernstein, 1900-1921 (Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities International Press, 1996).
5
See, for example, Veli-Matti Rautio, Die Bernstein Debatte: die politisch-ideologischen
Stromungen und die Parteiideologie der Sozialdemokratischen Partei Deutschlands 1898-1903
(Helsinki: Suomen Historiallinen Seura, 1994); Nicholas Stargardt, The German Idea of
Militarism: Radical and Socialist Critics, 1866-1914 (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1994);
John H. Kautsky, Karl Kautsky: Marxism, Revolution & Democracy (New Brunswick, NJ:
Transaction, 1994); EB; Moira Donald, Marxism and Revolution: Karl Kautsky and the
Russian Marxists (New Haven: Yale UP, 1993); Jack Jacobs, On Socialism and the Jewish
Question after Marx (New York: NYU Press, 1993); Stanley Pierson, Marxist Intellectuals
and the Working-Class Mentality in Germany 1887-1912 (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP,
1993); H. Kendall Rogers, Before the Revisionist Controversy: Kautsky, Bernstein, and the
Meaning of Marxism 1895-1898 (New York: Garland, 1992); Peter Beilharz, Labour's
Utopias: Bolshevism, Fabianism, Social Democracy (London: Routledge, 1992); Gary P.
Steenson, After Marx, Before Lenin: Marxism and Socialist Working-Class Parties in Europe,
1884-1914 (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1991).
6
See, for example, Giles Radice, "The Case for Revisionism," in The Political Quarterly 59
(1988), pp. 404-415; Heinz Kleger, "Evolutionarer Sozialismus. Oder: warum noch
einmal Bernstein lesen?," in Widerspruch 19/90 (1990), pp. 38-52; Stephen Eric Bronner,
"Eduard Bernstein and the Logic of Revisionism," in Socialism Unbound, pp. 53-75; Horst
Heimann, Die Voraussetzungen des Demokratischen Sozialismus und die Aufgaben der
Sozialdemokratie (Bonn: Dietz, 1991); Doug Brown, "Thorstein Veblen Meets Eduard
Bernstein: Toward an Institutionalist Theory of Mobilization Politics," in Journal of
Economic Issues 25.3 (September 1991), pp. 689-708; and Peter Beilharz, "The Life and
Times of Social Democracy," in Peter Beilharz, Gillian Robinson, and John Rundell, eds.
Between Totalitarianism andPostmodernity (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1992), pp. 54-68. See
also my "Historical Materialism and Ethics: Eduard Bernstein's Revisionist Perspective,"
in History of European Ideas 14.5 (1992), pp. 647-663.
Introduction 3
present interaction between the world of European social democratic
politics and socialist political ideas. Indeed, my concerns are just as much
hermeneutical, political, and normative as they are historical.
No doubt, German social democracy provides the inseparable social
context of Bernstein's political theory. Torn from its historical soil, our
understanding of his "evolutionary socialism" would remain woefully
abstract, sterile, and clouded. Indeed, one might look upon Bernstein's
life and thought as a microcosmic reflection of the first hundred years in
the history of the German labor movement: he and his party underwent
the same ideological development leading from a Lassallean socialist
eclecticism to a Marxist purism, which, ultimately, culminated in a new
eclecticism enriched by both traditions.
The natural starting point for an interpretation of Bernstein's political
thought is his early critique of orthodox German Marxism, presented in
his 1896-8 essays in the socialist journals NeueZeit and Vorwdrts, as well as
in his more comprehensive 1899 study, The Preconditions of Socialism.
However, it would be a grave mistake to neglect Bernstein's instructive
later writings. Overlooking the fact that he himself repeatedly stressed the
"theoretical progress," reflected in his later work,7 most scholars of
European social democracy have often either trivialized his later oeuvre as
"political journalism," or bypassed it altogether.8 "By 1900," so goes the
verdict of his most prominent biographer, "Bernstein had done his
theoretical work."9 This judgment is echoed in the comments of a recent
observer who noted that, "[Bernstein] added nothing significant to the
position he had developed in the 1890s."10 Such hasty pronouncements
leave the reader with the erroneous impression that, besides his role as a
vociferous critic of orthodox Marxism, Bernstein failed to provide new
impulses to socialist theory. Nothing can be further from the truth. In fact,
the more "constructive" dimension of Bernstein's political thought,
concentrating on problems of democratization, political morality, inter-
national relations, and social reform, emerged in more detail only after his
return from his London exile in 1901.
Therefore, my study seeks to provide a more balanced assessment of
Bernstein's political theory by giving equal weight to his two equally
important creative periods. First, there is his early revisionism, dominated
by his 1895-9 critique of the young, "Hegelian" Marx and his allegedly
7
ES, p. 41.
8
Susanne Miller, "Bernstein's Political Position 1914-1920," in Roger Fletcher, ed.
Bernstein to Brandt: A Short History of German Social Democracy (London: Edward Arnold,
1987), p. 101.
9
DDS, p. 255. See also Thomas Meyer's similar assessment, Bernsteins konstruktiver
Sozialismus (Berlin: Dietz, 1977), pp. 5, 33-34.
10
Tudor, "Introduction," in PS, p. xxxv.
4 Introduction
"Blanquist" tendencies. During this phase, Bernstein sought to reveal the
fundamental weaknesses of orthodox Marxism while introducing the
basic elements of his ethical reformism. Clinging to the idea that Marxist
doctrine could be simply "revised" by "developing the evolutionary
principle" inherent in the mature writings of Marx and Engels,11 Bern-
stein actually ended up changing the entire Gestalt of Marxist socialism.
Second, in his more constructive later phase, Bernstein endeavored to
expand and refine his evolutionary socialism by advocating an ethical
social reformism which was designed to prepare and guide concrete
political initiatives. Moreover, in his capacity as member of the German
Reichstag for more than two decades, Bernstein was in the unique
position to explore the crucial interface between theory and practice from
both ends; an opportunity denied to most prominent socialist theorists,
including Karl Marx, Friedrich Engels, Karl Kautsky, Georg Plekhanov,
and Rosa Luxemburg.
Yet, party theorists - particularly Kautsky and Luxemburg - played
leading roles in questioning the "feasibility" of Bernstein's evolutionary
socialism. Indeed, there are but few figures in the history of socialist
thought who have been more criticized than Eduard Bernstein. An
autodidact, social historian, elected representative to the German Reich-
stag, editor, journalist, political thinker, and theoretical "heir apparent"
to Friedrich Engels, Bernstein exchanged his early reputation as a
committed Marxist socialist for far less noble distinctions, among them,
"traitor of the working class" (Lenin) and "opportunistic philistine"
(Luxemburg). Advancing an extensive critique of Marx's and Engels'
"scientific socialism," Bernstein forfeited his potential claim to socialist
leadership by setting off the famousfin-de-siecle"Revisionist Contro-
versy" in the German Social Democratic Party (SPD).
To the ears of his former friends and German party leaders August Bebel
and Karl Kautsky, Bernstein's liberal-sounding arguments not only recast
their decidedly Marxist libretto, but clearly rang with the sentimental,
ethical tones of "bourgeois" social reformists like Friedrich Albert Lange,
John Stuart Mill, and Sidney Webb. Such "revisionist talk" bolstered their
suspicion that Bernstein, living in his London exile for more than a decade,
had acquired the insidious "British liberal disease" from his new Fabian
and radical-liberal company. Mocking his model of "evolutionary social-
ism" and flatly rejecting his repeated calls for a class-transcending,
left-liberal democratic alliance against Kaiser Wilhelm's authoritarianism,
the orthodox Marxist SPD leadership instead set out to create the
damaging image of Eduard Bernstein, the "petty-bourgeois opportunist."
11
PS, p. 28.
Introduction 5
On the other hand, social-minded German intellectuals of various
liberal shades, like Friedrich Naumann, Eugen Richter, Franz Oppen-
heimer, Lujo Brentano, Theodor Mommsen, and Max Weber, resented
both Bernstein's suspicion of their market-based economics and his
seemingly "exaggerated" commitment to "radical" forms of egalitarian-
ism. Moreover, Bernstein's Kantian ethical ideals appeared to them to be
far too flimsy for a Realpolitik based on more tangible values such as the
defense of "national community" and "German national interests."
Sacrificing genuine conceptual commonalities that could have well been
translated into valuable political capital against the Imperial Government,
national-liberal leaders instead chose to highlight their philosophical
differences with Bernstein.
As a result of this ideological inflexibility toward Bernstein's political
vision in both socialist and liberal camps, decades passed without the
formation of afirmdemocratic alliance against the autocratic rule of "Iron
and Rye" in Germany. Sporadic attempts to reach out across the political
spectrum (like Naumann's courageous rallying cry for a united liberal-
socialist bloc with decidedly nationalist leanings) foundered on the
perpetual factionalism among German liberals and the SPD leadership's
rigid adherence to a "well-tested strategy of splendid isolation" - its refusal
to form political coalitions with any parts of the German "bourgeoisie."12
In the meantime, Bernstein's theoretical model of "evolutionary
socialism," or "liberal socialism,"13 languished in a political no-man's
land. Yet, largely atheoretical SPD Praktiker ("pragmatists") shrewdly
used his initiative in their efforts to link his attack on orthodox Marxism
with their own instrumentalist agenda. Thanks to their skillful tactical
manoeuvers, Bernstein's "revisionism" acquired even more negative
connotations, eventually becoming synonymous with "socialist imperial-
ism" and a form of "philosophical eclecticism," which Rosa Luxemburg
seethingly characterized as "a pile of rubbish, in which the debris of all
systems, the pieces of thought of various great and small minds, find a
common resting place."14 The echoes of such assessments can still be
heard today in Cornel West's equally sharp criticism that "Bernstein .. .
12
For an excellent discussion of this topic, see Beverly Heckart, From Bassermann to Bebel:
The Grand Bloc's Quest for Reform in the Kaiserreich, 1900-1914 (New Haven: Yale UP,
1974).
13
Bernstein's definition of socialism as "organized liberalism," and his general fondness for
the liberal ideals he expressed on many occasions, permits such wording without violating
his theoretical design. Expanding on Bernstein's arguments, the Italian socialist Carlo
Rosselli used the term "liberal socialism" as the title of his 1930 book. See Carlo Roselli,
Liberal Socialism, ed. by Nadia Urbinati (Princeton: Princeton UP, 1994). Throughout
this book, the terms "evolutionary socialism" and "liberal socialism" will be used
interchangeably.
14
Rosa Luxemburg, Reform or Revolution? (New York: Pathfinder, 1973), p. 57.
6 Introduction
neither formulated a philosophical justification for socialist ethical ideals
nor gave these ideals any substantive content."15
While Marxists of various schools have been instrumental in setting the
framework for downplaying Bernstein's contribution to socialist theory,
many non-Marxists scholars, too, have not been much kinder in their
respective appraisals. Criticizing the "eclectic nature of his theoretical
enterprise,"16 such observers point to Bernstein's allegedly "insufficient
grasp of basic philosophical principles" as the underlying reason for his
"negligible theoretical contribution to socialist thought."17 Save for a few
exceptions,18 it seems that most historians of German social democracy
have tacitly agreed that Bernstein's political theory does not warrant
extensive research efforts. As a result, his central role in German social
democracy has received only scant attention, and the exploration of
Bernstein's life and thought as a whole has suffered neglect.
Contrary to this dominant line of argument, my study does not consider
the degree of Bernstein's philosophical sophistication as the key variable in
evaluating his significance as a political thinker and politician. Rather, as
the main thesis of this work, I argue for Bernstein's pivotal role in the
history of socialist thought on the grounds of his model of "evolutionary
socialism" - his pioneering reconceptualization of the relationship be-
tween liberal and socialist political theory. I seek to both illuminate and
critically evaluate Bernstein's attempts to change his party's theoretical
self-understanding in order to facilitate a greater degree of cooperation
with liberal progressives and thus mobilize German society in the name of
democracy. Seen from Bernstein's perspective, the official acknowledg-
ment and appreciation of existing theoretical and political points of contact
between socialists and liberals was the indispensable precondition for the
creation of a new, more democratic (and thus more "socialist") Germany.
In this sense, Bernstein's attempted synthesis of liberalism and social-
ism remains relevant for ongoing discussions on the "end of socialism,"
for it illuminates the central predicament of socialist theory which
continued to haunt the socialist project throughout the twentieth century:
its inability consciously to embrace the libertarian legacy of the Enlighten-
ment. As the normative preconditions for any socialist society, Bernstein
15
Cornel West, The Ethical Dimensions of Marxist Thought (New York: Monthly Review
Press, 1991), p. 176.
16
See, for example, Leszek Kolakowski, "Bernstein and Revisionism," in The Main Currents
of Marxism, Vol. II: The Golden Age (Oxford: Oxford UP, 1978), p. I l l ; and Roger
Fletcher, "The Life and Work of Eduard Bernstein," in Fletcher, Bernstein to Brandt, p.
52.
17
DDS, p. 298.
18
For example, Heimann, Die Voraussetzungen des Demokratischen Sozialismus und die
Aufgaben der Sozialdemokratie\ and Michael Harrington, Socialism Past & Future (New
York: Arcade, 1989), p. 276.
Introduction 7
emphasized above all the establishment of political democracy. Insurrec-
tionary departures from the evolutionary mode of liberal social change
were not only viewed as the dangerous excesses of "romantic Utopians,"
but represented outright threats to the survival of personal liberty. In fact,
Bernstein never failed to emphasize the idea of "democracy" in his party's
self-identification with the label "social democracy," thereby propound-
ing the notion of an "evolving liberalism" guided by basic rational and
humanitarian ideals.
Bernstein encountered such ethically motivated forms of liberalism in
the writings of German neo-Kantians like Johann Jacoby, Friedrich Albert
Lange, Eugen Duhring, Karl Vorlander, and Conrad Schmidt. Moreover,
he showed great sympathy for the British tradition of radical liberalism
stretching from Jeremy Bentham, J. S. Mill, and Richard Cobden to
late-nineteenth-century Fabians like Sidney and Beatrice Webb and
George Bernard Shaw.19 Exiled in London for twelve years, Bernstein
gradually appropriated England's rights-based political language, empha-
sized the primacy of individual self-realization, and praised personal
liberty as the paramount ingredient of any democratic social order.
Though partially supporting Marx's radically egalitarian scheme for a
rational regulation of economic production, Bernstein regarded socialism
as an "heir" to Kant's and Mill's political tradition rather than a
completely new model fundamentally opposed to liberalism.
Like the "New Liberals" L.T. Hobhouse and J. A. Hobson, who sought
to instill a new social-liberal ethos in a young generation of British
reformers, Bernstein provided strong arguments for the necessary "mod-
ernization" of existing liberal doctrine. Yet as a German social democrat,
Bernstein's task was infinitely more difficult, for he had to address
German socialists who had barely escaped Bismarck's political repression
19
See, for example, Erika Rikli, Der Revisionismus: Ein Revisionsversuch der deutschen
marxistischen Theorie, 1890-1914 (Zurich: Girsberger Verlag, 1936); Helmut Hirsch, ed.
Ein revisionistisches Sozialismusbild, 2nd edn. (Berlin: Dietz, 1976); Pierre Angel, Eduard
Bernstein et L'Evolution du Socialisme Allemand (Paris: Didier, 1961); DDS; Hans-Josef
Steinberg, Sozialismus und deutsche Sozialdemokratie 4th ed. (Berlin: Dietz, 1976); Erika
Konig, Vom Revisionismus zum "Demokratischen Sozialismus" (Berlin: Akademie, 1964);
Hans-Jorg Sandkuhler and Rafael de la Vega, eds. Marxismus und Ethik (Frankfurt:
Suhrkamp, 1974); Meyer, Bernsteins konstruktiverSozialismus', Detlef Lehnert, Reform und
Revolution in den Strategiediskusionen der klassischen Sozialdemokratie (Bonn: Verlag Neue
Gesellschaft, 1977); Helga Grebing, Der Revisionismus: Von Bernstein bis zum "Prager
Friihling" (Munich: Beck, 1977); Bo Gustafsson, Marxismus und Revisionismus (Frank-
furt: Europaische Verlagsanstalt, 1972); Helmut Hirsch, Der "Fabier" Eduard Bernstein
(Berlin: Dietz, 1977); Herbert Frei, Fabianismus und Bernstein'scher Revisionismus
1884-1900 (Bern: Peter Lang, 1979); Roger Fletcher, Revisionism and Empire: Socialist
Imperialism in Germany 1897-1914 (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1984); and James
Kloppenberg, Uncertain Victory: Social Democracy and Progressivism in European and
American Thought 1870-1920 (New York: Oxford UP, 1986).
8 Introduction
and were thus understandably suspicious of any "socialist" theory that
implied some form of cooperation with the unreliable German bour-
geoisie. Still, Bernstein insisted that the only path to democracy lay in
uniting the ambitions of a politically dissatisfied "new Mittelstand"
(middle class) offin-de-siecleGermany with the working class' traditional
demands for profound constitutional, administrative, fiscal, and econ-
omic reforms. But if it was to happen at all, such a class-transcending
alliance could not be achieved without first synchronizing the SPD's
theoretical guidelines with a concrete program of action.
For Bernstein, it was the primary task of the socialist intellectual to
complement the necessary "modernization" of liberalism with the long
overdue "modernization" of Marxist socialism - a project aimed at
anchoring the labor movement in the altered socioeconomic conditions of
the new century. Hence, Bernstein's evolutionary socialism started as a
theoretical enterprise: the untiring, empirically driven criticism of the
"outmoded parts" of Marx's model.20 According to Bernstein, such
criticism would actually facilitate the modernization of liberalism, since
Marxism, too, was a fundamentally "evolutionary doctrine." However,
revising Marxist socialism also meant junking its remaining "utopian
strains," throwing out its metaphysical Hegelianism, and eliminating the
"unscientific dogmatism" of Marxist popularizers.21 In other words, if
Marxism was truly the historical science it claimed to be, then its represent-
atives ought to acknowledge that changing empirical conditions necessi-
tated periodic revisions of its theoretical assumptions and predictions.
Ultimately, Bernstein was bound to arrive at conclusions that put him
squarely at odds with the founders. He disapproved of the priority of
economics over politics; he rejected Marx's celebrated dissociation of
socialism from liberalism; and he parted with Engels' contempt for
"bourgeois" morality. Instead, Bernstein praised the "eternal ideals" of
liberalism- the cultivation of refined tastes, the benefits of moral conduct,
and the virtues of piecemeal reformism. Thus, long before most of his party
comrades, he recognized both the obsolescence of certain Marxist ideas
and the inadequacy of Marx's method. He realized that revolutionary
Marxism was a poor vehicle for eliminating the existing democratic deficit
between Germany's semi-feudal nexus of authoritarian social structures,
values, and political attitudes and its accelerated process of economic
modernization. Indeed, Bernstein was among the first nineteenth-century
observers of industrial society who saw both the political importance of the
20
See, for example, Bernstein's conviction that "the first task of revisionism is theoretical,
not practical" (Protokoll iiber die Verhandlungen des Parteitages der Sozialdemokratischen
Partei Deutschland, abgehalten zu Dresden 1903> Berlin, p.397).
21
PS, p. 28.
Introduction 9
rise of white-collar employees and state officials, and the increasing social
differentiation within the proletariat.22 Moreover, he insisted that Marxist
doctrine could neither fully explain the remarkable adaptability of liberal
capitalism nor make sense of the fact that the leaders of European social
democracy were clearly more concerned with the organizational growth of
the labor movement and the outcomes of the next elections than with the
revolutionary overthrow of the ruling elites. Contrary to the ominous
predictions of The Communist Manifesto^ scores of ordinary workers and
most of their representatives seemed to prefer the occasional "crumbs"
from the capitalist table to the perils of an all-out class war.
Not hesitating to turn his skepticism on the proletariat itself, Bernstein
offered a more empiricist assessment of advanced capitalist society, of the
sort we have come to associate with the work of Max Weber. Indeed,
Weber's famous 1918 essay on socialism reiterates many "revisionist"
arguments made by Bernstein twenty years earlier.23 Both Bernstein and
Weber emphasized the central importance of politics and parliamentary
democracy in adjusting society to the forces of modernity. In their view,
such a process was neither a ruptural event in the Marxist sense, nor a
return to the organic bonds of the traditional Gemeinschaft. Insisting that
the Utopias of the past could not be salvaged from the process of
modernization - not even as the scientistic-romantic idyll of "free
associations of free producers" - Bernstein anticipated a future society in
which liberal and socialist currents would be forced to coexist for a very
long time within the framework of an "organized liberalism."24
The articulation of this new vision represented no small theoretical
feat. Despite his fervent rejection of Hegel's dialectical method, Bern-
stein's quest for evolutionary socialism assumed an almost Hegelian
character in its desire simultaneously to "modernize" Marxist socialism
and bourgeois liberalism through their mutual Aufhebung ("uplifting") in
a new theoretical synthesis. Inherently open-ended, Bernstein's model
was critically shaped by the concrete political problems of more than
three decades. In good Aristotelian fashion, he sought to locate the
slippery "middle way" of avoiding both an illiberal utopianism that leaves
no room for doubt, error, and correction, and the empty pragmatism of
cynical careerists whose social reformism had become devoured by cold
instrumental concerns. Over and over again, Bernstein struggled to
provide a more timely version of the old Marxist search for "some rational
22
Gerhard A. Ritter and Klaus Tenfelde, Arbeiter im Deutschen Kaiserreich, 1871 bis 1914
(Berlin: Dietz, 1992), p. 426.
23
Max Weber, Political Writings, eds. Peter Lassman and Ronald Speirs (Cambridge:
Cambridge UP, 1994), pp. 272-303.
24
PS, p. 150.
10 Introduction
criterion for drawing the line between the visionary dreamer at one end
and the petty bourgeois at the other."25 In many instances, however, his
theoretical synthesis translated into politically unpopular compromises
which failed to satisfy the main socialist and liberal players of conflict-
ridden Germany.
Yet, there - in the midst of the concrete political dilemmas of both
Wilhelmine and Weimar Germany, and not limned by the serene poetics
of a purely philosophical enterprise - we encounter again the central
theme of Bernstein's quest: "What must social democrats do to make
possible, and cautiously extend, democracy in industrially advanced
countries?" Applied to the illiberal conditions of his homeland, Be-
rnstein's leitmotif represents an early socialist variant of the vexing
"German Question," so persuasively rendered by Ralf Dahrendorf as
"Germany's persistent failure to give a home to democracy in its liberal
sense."26 By rejecting Bernstein's theoretical blueprint, nationalist revi-
sionists, orthodox Marxists, and radical revolutionaries missed a great
opportunity to make Germany's political culture more hospitable to
liberty and democracy. Ultimately, both socialists and liberals failed to
resolve the painful discordance between their classical doctrine and the
demands of advanced capitalism. From the Left, Eduard Bernstein
offered such a necessary theoretical vision of ideological modernization;
this road not taken points to the implication of social democracy in the
ensuing twentieth-century tragedy of German politics.
Having set the stage for the ensuing arguments, it might be useful first to
offer the reader a short chapter outline of my study. For the sake of
maintaining a lively narrative, I decided to divide Bernstein's life and
thought along more or less chronological lines into three main parts.
The initial three chapters of Part 1 furnish the basic features of
Bernstein's life, set against the historical and political background of
German liberalism and social democracy. I focus mainly on events that
contributed to the formation of Bernstein's personality and his political
outlook- the broad scope of his intellectual interests and his remarkable
early party career as an editor and political journalist. Concurring with
Austrian social historian Julius Braunthal, who pointed out that Bernstein
was "much more of an intellectual than a politician,"27 I contend that
Bernstein's theoretical achievements far outshine his abilities as a party
25
Ibid., p. 35.
26
Ralf Dahrendorf, Society and Democracy in Germany (New York: Doubleday, 1967), p. 14.
See also Fritz Stern, The Failure of Illiberalism (New York: Columbia UP, 1992).
27
Julius Braunthal, History of the International 1864-1914, trans. Henry Collins and Kenneth
Mitchell (London: Thomas Nelson and Sons Ltd., 1966), p. 262.
Introduction 11
28
strategist and political tactician. Though an autodidact, Bernstein's
personal interactions with the most brilliant minds of European social
democracy helped him to develop into a genuine "public intellectual." At
the same time, however, by serving as editor-in-chief of the SPD's most
influential periodical, he never lost contact with the less illustrious world
of the ordinary party member. Hence, the opening chapters offer an
interpretation of Bernstein's intellectual achievements which stands in
strong opposition to frequently raised arguments belittling his contribu-
tion as a political thinker.
In Part 2, I examine in greater detail the main theoretical pillars of
Bernstein's evolutionary socialism. Chapter 4 looks at his attempt to
modernize Marxist theory by clarifying the meaning of socialism for a new
era of advanced capitalism. True to the critical spirit of Kant, he openly
disavowed historicist determinism, acknowledging the inability of any
political solution to overcome wholly the gulf between necessity and
freedom. Discussing his version of historical materialism, I assert that
Bernstein realized the impotence of Marxian socialism in the face of
problems of liberty and morality which were being continuously con-
fronted on the empirical level. Thus, he cut the dialectical connection
between immanence and transcendence which Marx had always presup-
posed. For Bernstein, Marx's teleology had been completely undermined
by the actual course of modern capitalism. While maintaining the
importance of structural economic forces for social development, Bern-
stein's epistemological framework nonetheless resurrects the role of
(Kantian) ethical ideals in a moral critique of capitalism.
Chapter 5 explores Bernstein's efforts to reconceptualize the connec-
tion between state, civil society, and the economy. Rejecting the illiberal-
ism of Marxist doctrine and embracing basic liberal views concerning the
nature of society, Bernstein considered the liberal language of "rights" the
most appropriate vehicle for expressing socialist demands, thus under-
scoring the importance of civil society as a public sphere where citizenship
ought to be universalized. At the same time, however, he remained
opposed to classical liberals who, after the defeat of feudalism, trans-
formed their universalist principles into a defense of privilege against the
rising Fourth Estate. In keeping with Kant and Mill, Bernstein denned
28
For a different view on this, see, for example, George Lichtheim, "The Revisionists," in
Marxism: An Historical and Critical Study > 2nd edn. (New York: Praeger, 1965), pp.
278-300; Kolakowski, The Main Currents of Marxism, pp. 98-114; David McLellan,
Marxism after Marx (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1979), pp. 20-41. See also, Christian
Gneuss, "The Precursor: Eduard Bernstein," in Leopold Labedz, ed. Revisionism: Essays
in the History of Marxist Ideas (New York: Praeger, 1962), pp. 31-41; and Susanne Miller
and Heinrich PothorT, A History of German Social Democracy: From 1848 to the Present
(Lexington/Spa: Berg, 1986), pp. 38-54.
12 Introduction
liberty not purely negatively as the absence of coercion, but chose instead
to emphasize the substantive nature of freedom: political demands for
universal suffrage, equality of opportunity, and a more equitable distribu-
tion of the social product. By shifting his focus from an analysis of
inequalities on the level of production to the level of distribution,
Bernstein again betrayed his liberal bias in favor of pursuing social justice
through redistributive measures, thus endowing the state with the crucial
task of initiating and supervising piecemeal reforms.
Once the essential features of his ethical-liberal interpretation of
Marxist socialism have become apparent, Part 3 explores the main
political problems Bernstein encountered on his quest for evolutionary
socialism. Searching for the origins of the practical defeat of his vision,
chapter 6 first identifies the main arguments advanced by Bernstein's
liberal and socialist opponents. Orthodox Marxist critics like Kautsky and
radicals like Luxemburg charged with good reason that Bernstein had
actually broken with the founders' economic-materialist conception of
history. Bernstein was, in fact, fooling himself by thinking that the essence
of Marx's theory could be preserved in spite of his revisionist "amend-
ments." Without the Marxist idea that capitalism's inner laws of develop-
ment would, with natural necessity, eventually lead to a general "break-
down" of society and open a new chapter in human history, socialism lost
the powerful combination of "scientific" analysis and romantic prophecy
that had made it so attractive to millions of followers.
On the other hand, the response from Bernstein's liberal critics
indicated that the German bourgeoisie was far more national-liberal than
ethical-liberal. His principled reformism often struck them as too moralis-
tic in tone and too idealistic in design - a disarmingly decent, but
infeasible and perhaps even dangerous enterprise in a Germany supposed-
ly surrounded by expansionist enemies. Liberals were also quick to add a
good dose of their "realism" to the vital question of political leadership.
Who would effectively represent and market an "evolutionary" brand of
socialism in Germany? Aside from lacking personal "charisma,"
Bernstein possessed only moderate public-speaking abilities. Moreover,
his stubborn insistence on ethical principles would burden the crucial
tasks of political bargaining. As a mediator between opposing factions,
Bernstein was simply not in the same league with, say, Friedrich Ebert,
Friedrich Naumann, or Gustav Stresemann. In fact, when Bernstein
rejected forthcoming offers from left-liberals to leave the SPD and join
them, and, in addition, disappointed the hopes of the nationalistic Party
Praktiker to spearhead a nationalist faction, his liberal brand of socialism
was sentenced to an assured political death.
As opposed to most accounts that put the end of the SPD's "Revisionist
Introduction 13
Controversy" at around 1903, I argue in chapters 7 and 8 that the old
dispute heated up once again between 1905 and 1914, during the great
theoretical debates on the use of the political mass strike and the role of
nationalism. Set within a general assessment of the cultural assumptions
underlying his views on patriotism and colonialism, I present the numer-
ous political obstacles Bernstein encountered as he struggled to maintain
his Aristotelian "middle way" between political realism and ethical
idealism, particularly in his attempt to furnish alternatives to German
nationalism and imperialism. Moreover, I discuss the intimate link
between the political fate of Bernstein's intellectual quest and the
accelerated process of bureaucratization in German social democracy.
Bernstein's activities during the Great War and the German Revolution,
as well as his pivotal role in drafting the new Gorlitz Party Program, round
out the themes of this chapter. Ultimately, along with Carl Schorske, I
argue that the revolutionary events of 1918 and 1919 merely formalized
the factional divisions that were already present within the pre-war
international labor movement.29
With the arrival of a new Weimar republican order, it appeared as though
Bernstein's quest for evolutionary socialism was to be given a new lease on
life, but the sputtering German economy and an increasingly technocratic
SPD contributed to the remarkable success of radicalisms of both the Right
and the Left. Chapter 9 traces the tensions between Bernstein's ethical
ideals and the various strands of socialist instrumentalism exemplified in
the rise of Bolshevism and the widely discussed issue of German war guilt.
In the end, his theoretical vision was smothered between a state socialism
based on industrial productivity and the rise of extremist political parties.
While Bernstein established the theoretical desirability for a liberal social-
ism, he could not guarantee that actual political practice would honor his
ethical ideals. In other words, without the Marxist dogma of history itself
assuring the coming of the classless society, socialism once again became
an uncertain enterprise, merely striving to approximate a moral order that
must forever elude the full grasp of positivity.
In light of this, Bernstein's attempt to merge the two great progressive
traditions ran a high risk of strengthening a utilitarian conception of
politics as the arena for political bargaining and compromises whose
outcomes would be judged in strictly instrumental terms. The fulfillment
of an ethical duty in the application of socialist principles thus became a
weak counterforce to the satisfaction of infinite material needs. Accepting
the political rules of representative democracy, Bernstein had a poor eye
for the tendency of reformism to breed technocrats who, following
29
Carl E. Schorske, German Social Democracy 1905-1917: The Development of the Great
Schism (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP, 1955).
14 Introduction
omnipresent electoral imperatives, let their political activities be guided
chiefly by their own self-interest and the immediate material concerns of
their constituencies.30
Hence, it has been suggested that Bernstein's evolutionary socialism
represents a "dilemma of principles and power" emerging from the clash
of reform and revolution - two different strategies of advancing social
change.31 While it is true that this predicament pertains to all political
theories intent on changing a given political order, a formulation of
"dilemmas" in such general terms pays insufficient attention to
Bernstein's specific "revisionist" concerns. As thefirstprominent Marxist
theorist of reform, Bernstein assumed that the increasing complexity of
modern society made the large-scale revolutions of the old days obsolete.
Thus, the main question addressed by his evolutionary socialism was not
the old Platonic dilemma of whether reformers will ever gain the political
power they must have to put their theories into practice;32 rather, he
sought to motivate social reformists not to jettison ethical principles on
their assured way to political power.
Given the nature of the regime that overthrew the Weimar Republic,
must we conclude that Bernstein's quest ended in total failure? At first
glance, there seems to be sufficient evidence to confirm such a view.
Indeed, seen from a realist perspective, one might conclude that
Bernstein's vision failed to overcome the fatal combination of Germany's
illiberal sociopolitical order, its widespread nationalist resentment, and its
policy of foreign aggression.33 Moreover, his theoretical synthesis not only
failed to save the integrity of Marxism, but, conversely, provided the basis
for the politically and ideologically devastating struggles of the Left over
the "correct" meaning of "Marxism" and "socialism."
However, looking at the astonishing rebirth of European social democ-
racy following the end of World War II, one can alsofindsome compelling
arguments to the contrary. In the epilogue of this study, however, I go
beyond merely recounting the "golden years of democratic socialism" of
the 1960s and 1970s. Instead, I make the far more difficult case for the
contemporary relevance of Bernstein's evolutionary socialism. First, of
course, there is his admonition to retain the crucial process of critical
self-reflection as the indispensable catalyst that drives the evolution of any
democratic socialism. Second, Bernstein's appreciation of liberalism
contests the deeply engrained equation of "socialism" with "Marxism"
based on the alleged antithesis in principle between liberalism and
socialism. At the supposed "end of socialism," Bernstein's embryonic
30
For an excellent analysis of this "electoral dilemma," see Adam Przeworski, Capitalism
and Social Democracy (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1985).
31
This is the thesis of DDS, pp. 7-8; 298-310.
32 33
Ibid., p. 302. Roger Fletcher, Revisionism and Empire, pp. 184-185.
Introduction 15
model of a "liberal socialism" represents the logical point of departure for
the sole viable progressive project remaining in our post-Soviet and
(perhaps) post-Keynesian era: a new focus on the role of civil society and a
conception of democracy that favors the extension of personal rights over
property rights.34
It is for this reason that I decline to evaluate Bernstein's political thought
solely by applying philosophical standards. What makes his intellectual
quest a worthwhile subject of academic inquiry is neither its degree of
philosophical sophistication nor its lack of methodological purity. Rather,
it is Bernstein's highly original attempt to formulate a coherent synthesis of
two great political traditions that stand for individual self-realization and
distributive justice. In a time when old assumptions about the meaning of
socialism no longer hold and liberal notions of universalism fall under
attack from a multitude of new intellectual forces, a fundamental
reconsideration of the theoretical and historical ties between these two
time-honored traditions serves an important purpose. Herein lies what is
today worth re-examining in Bernstein's political thought.
A final word on the guiding metaphor of the book: in an attempt to
capture the peculiar spirit of Bernstein's political enterprise, I struck upon
the term "quest," for it suggests not only a thorough investigation of the
subject matter at hand, but also connotes an almost romantic, adventur-
ous journey with no fixed destination, yet guided by a noble vision.35 It is
no coincidence that Bernstein's most famous statement should be his
much misinterpreted comment that a static "final goal" of socialism, no
matter how perfect, had no meaning to him; while the concrete social
struggle of the labor movement meant "everything." His willingness to
sacrifice the Marxist dogmas of a future telos for the open-ended quality of
an uncertain present reappears in his love for the political essay as a
stylistic vehicle of inherently unfinished quality and the logical device for
fostering the crucial exercise of critical reflectivity.
Hence, one should not expect to find the "essence" of Bernstein's life
work in a single book or a series of volumes. Rather, one must duplicate
Bernstein's intricate quest leading through a diffuse collection of writings
that span more than three decades. They are comprised of a dozen books
and literally hundreds of book reviews, published lectures, essays, and
monographs that, to this day, defy systematic arrangement. Ranging from
highly theoretical discussions of Marx's labor theory of value to journalis-
tic observations regarding political events of the day, the leitmotive of
Bernstein's intellectual quest only reveal themselves when situated within
the details of his personal life and the history of German social democracy.
34
See Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis, Democracy and Capitalism: Property, Community,
and the Contradictions of Modern Social Thought (New York: Basic Books, 1987).
35
I am greatly indebted to Stephen Eric Bronner for this formulation.
Part 1
Preparation
1 The making of a social democrat
Prologue
At first glance, an assessment of Eduard Bernstein's life and thought
seems to be a fairly straightforward project. Hannah Arendt has put the
matter succinctly: "Bernstein was honest, analyzed what he saw, was loyal
to reality and critical of Marx."1 Sir Isaiah Berlin concurs: "Eduard
Bernstein pointed out more clearly than any one before him the apparent
non-fulfillment of various Marxist prophesies."2 Yet, two entirely differ-
ent images of the "Father of Revisionism" emerge from the descriptions
of his contemporaries. The first, characterized by the relentless criticism
of his political and ideological opponents, presents a weak, theoretically
confused man who repaid the kindness of his mentor, Friedrich Engels, by
attempting to destroy the "communist world outlook" of "scientific
socialism" and betraying the cause of the proletariat.3 The second
account, conjured up by those sympathetic to Bernstein's revisionist
cause, is one of exaggerated praise, depicting a political thinker ahead of
his time who, dedicated to improving the lot of the working classes,
fearlessly attacked an antiquated theory which proved to be out of step
with auspicious sociopolitical developments.4
Not only do both images fail to do justice to the actual person, but
they also fall woefully short of accurately presenting Bernstein's long and
prolific career as a socialist theorist, political journalist, national
19
20 Preparation
politician, political economist, and historian of the labor movement. Like
all controversial figures in political history, Bernstein's name has elicited
powerful emotional responses; among the socialist leaders of the early
twentieth century, we rarely find representatives in any country who did
not form a strong opinion about "Ede" Bernstein. Though they clashed
over the value of Bernstein's intellectual production, a close reading of the
less polemical accounts of his contemporary critics reveals unanimity
regarding two qualities of Bernstein's character: his personal integrity and
his wide-ranging intellectual interests.
His closest political friend and vehement theoretical opponent, Karl
Kautsky, captured the essence of Bernstein's personality when he wrote in
1920: "I admire both Bernstein's honesty and straightforwardness, which
always spurned mere posing and demagoguery, and his great sense of
justice."5 Even at the height of the Revisionist Controversy, when he
fundamentally disagreed with Bernstein, the legendary German party
leader, August Bebel, attested to "Bernstein's zeal for truth and consider-
able astuteness."6 Victor Adler, the founder of Austrian social democracy,
went even further:
Forcibly removed from practical party work, a sharp theoretical mind with
encyclopaedic knowledge, a fanatic for justice, and a skeptic of that most refined
breed which turns its skepticism upon itself and has an insatiable desire for
self-criticism, Bernstein has not only produced a series of excellent theoretical and
historical works but has also assumed one of the most important party functions,
that of criticizing its principles and tactics.7
Paul Lobe, the first social democratic Reichstag president, also acknowl-
edged the breadth of Bernstein's intellect when he noted that, "within the
limited framework of an essay, it is impossible to address all the policy
fields that Bernstein covered in the course of his long parliamentary
career."8 The prominent Kant biographer, Karl Vorlander, though
critical of Bernstein's epistemology and philosophy of science, still
admitted that it was "Bernstein's non-dogmatic intellectual engagement
that made possible a renewed discussion about the philosophical founda-
tions of socialism even beyond the borders of Germany." 9 Finally, in The
Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, Max Weber openly acknowl-
edged his intellectual debt to Bernstein by drawing on arguments from his
1895 book, History of Socialism, which definitively linked the secular
5
Karl Kautsky, "Eduard Bernstein," in Die Weltbiihne 16.2 (1920), p. 44.
6
Bebel to Bernstein (October 16, 1898) in MS, p. 320.
7
Victor Adler, "The Party Conference at Stuttgart," in ibid., p. 313.
8
Paul Lobe, "Eduard Bernstein als Breslauer Abgeordneter," in Helmut Hirsch, Der
"Fabier" Eduard Bernstein (Berlin: Dietz, 1977), p. 153.
9
Karl Vorlander, Kant und Marx: Ein Beitrag zur Philosophie des Sozialismus (Tubingen: J. C.
B. Mohr, 1926), p. 185.
The making of a social democrat 21
asceticism of Protestantism and the accumulation process of capital:
"[Bernstein's] discussion is the first which has suggested these important
relationships."10
Most promising German intellectuals born in the middle of the
nineteenth century were assisted in their theoretical development by
privileged family backgrounds, the church, or the support of wealthy
mentors. This rule does not hold in Bernstein's case. Raising their son in
relative poverty, his parents lacked both the social connections and the
funds to send him to college. It was only because of the professional
opportunities represented in the rising nineteenth-century European
labor movement that Bernstein was afforded the chance to develop his
intellectual capacities.
12
Einstein cited in Julius Schops, Burgerliche Aufkldrung und liberates Freiheitsdenken: A.
Bernstein in seiner Zeit (Stuttgart: Burg, 1992), p. 247.
13
See, for example, Leonhard Krieger, The German Idea of Freedom (Boston: Beacon, 1957);
Dahrendorf, Society and Democracy in Germany; Lothar Gall, Geschichte des deutschen
Liberalismus (Koln: Kohlhammer, 1966); Barrington Moore Jr., Social Origins of Dictator-
ship and Democracy: Lord and Peasant in the Making of the Modern World (Boston: Beacon,
1966); Stern, The Failure of Illiberalism; James Sheehan, German Liberalism in the
Nineteenth Century (Chicago: Chicago UP, 1978); Heinrich August Winkler, Liberalismus
und Antiliberalismus (Gottingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1979); David Blackbourn
and Geoff Ely, The Pecularities of German History (New York: Oxford UP, 1984); Dieter
Langewiesche, Liberalismus in Deutschland (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1988); David Black-
bourn and Richard J. Evans, eds. The German Bourgeoisie (London: Routledge, 1991).
14
For conflicting views in the ongoing debate over the compatibility of German and British
forms of liberalism, see, for example, Geoff Eley, "Liberalism, Europe, and the
Bourgeoisie 1860- 1914," in ibid., pp. 293-317; Wolfgang J. Mommsen, Britain and
Germany 1800-1914. Two Developmental Paths towards Industrial Society (London, 1986);
Liah Greenfeld, Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity (Cambridge: Harvard U P , 1992);
and John Breuilly, Labour and Liberalism in Nineteenth-Century Europe: Essays in
Comparative History (Manchester: Manchester UP, 1992).
15
Schops, Burgerliche Aufkldrung und liberates Freiheitsdenken: A. Bernstein in seiner Zeit, pp.
277-278.
The making of a social democrat 23
clear distaste for dogmatic doctrine and extreme forms of political
radicalism."16
The so-called "Jewish Residence Laws" requiring Jews who had not
been born in Berlin to depart the city after a year of residence, were still in
force in 1838, the year Jakob Bernstein settled in Berlin. Each year,
Eduard's father was officially obliged to "leave" the city of Berlin through
one city gate, only to return hours later through another one and present
himself to a different Prussian "gate official" who was unaware of his
recent "departure." At the time Eduard was born, the situation had only
slightly improved. Although Article 12 of the revised 1850 Prussian
Constitution established freedom of religion, a later article of the same
document established Christianity as the basis for "those institutions of
the state which deal with the practice of religion." In other words, Jews
were robbed of their religious equality by the very same document that
supposedly guaranteed it.17 Indeed, anti-Semitism was widespread in
Prussia, and Jews were barred from holding state office or pursuing higher
ranks in the military.
Like many German Jews at the time, Jakob Bernstein was not observ-
ant. He and his family rapidly assimilated, considering themselves
"Prussian-German patriots," refusing to speak Yiddish, and celebrating
Christian holidays like Christmas alongside the traditional Jewish High
Holidays. Rarely attending even the Reform Jewish synagogue, Jakob
extended to his children the rare privilege of choosing their own degree of
religious involvement.
In 1843, Jakob Bernstein joined Prussia's newly founded Berlin-Anhalt
Railroad Company, and soon distinguished himself as an employee with
an extraordinary sense of professional responsibility. In thirty years of
service as an engine driver, he never called in sick or missed even one day
of work! Though Jakob excelled at his job, he was nonetheless inept at
handling the family finances, which forced his wife Johanna to stretch the
food reserves in order to get by. This meant that meat dishes were a rarity
in the Bernstein household. When meat did appear on the table, most of it
went to Jakob, the family "provider," to sustain him in his physically
demanding labors. Most meals consisted of Eintopf, a thick stew made of
bread, potatoes, and green vegetables.
Both Jakob and Johanna were gentle parents with liberal views who -
unheard of in mid-nineteenth-century Prussia - only very rarely physically
disciplined their children. Little "Ede" learned early on that indulging in
coarse language was unacceptable to his parents. Unlike her husband,
Johanna Bernstein, nee Rosenberg, was a fragile woman who, weakened
16 17
Ibid., p. 278. EBy p. 9.
24 Preparation
by frequent childbirth, further sacrificed her physical health to demanding
housework and the exhausting care of her ten surviving children. More-
over, she was solely responsible for running the Bernstein household
affairs, which, given the family size, turned out to be more than a full-time
job. Calculating expenses, chopping wood, and keeping the fire going in
the stove alone were extremely demanding tasks for a woman who was
often too weak to climb the stairs at the end of the day.
Born in 1820, Johanna had lost her parents while still a child and gone
to live with relatives in Magdeburg, Saxony. Her aunt, a callous,
mean-spirited woman, saw in the girl a welcome object for exploitation
and frequently forced her to do housework to the point of physical
collapse. As soon as Johanna was old enough to find work on her own, she
left the Magdeburg household for good. Not long after her departure, she
met and fell in love with Jakob Bernstein. Like her husband, Johanna
showed some interest in politics, and took a strong liberal position during
the 1848 revolution. Indeed, it was she who kept a prized picture of her
revolutionary hero, Johann Jacoby, a liberal democrat who was later to
become a socialist and one of Eduard's great idols. Showing the litho-
graph to her son, Johanna impressed upon the boy that Jacoby was "a
great man and a champion of the people." 18
Yet, by the 1850s, the high political hopes of radical democrats like
Johann Jacobi had all but vanished. The main political objective of a
German revolution - the creation of a liberal constitution for a unified
German nation state - foundered in 1849 on the refusal of the Prussian
king to accept the crown of a constitutional German Empire that
drastically limited his powers. Unwilling to call for open resistance, the
delegates of the 1849 Frankfurt National Assembly returned home
empty-handed. Germany remained divided, and its aristocratic authori-
tarianism regained most of its former status in the ensuing decade of
reaction. In Prussia, where the conservative reaction was most successful,
liberalism was severely curtailed in the new 1850 Constitution. Espousing
"monarchical constitutionalism," the document permitted the hegemony
of the Crown independent of the consent of the people. In fact, the
patrimonial Prussian Staatsidea ("idea of the state") personified in the
monarch, precluded the legitimation of a politically constituted civil
society removed from the will of the king, making Prussian citizens once
again powerless subjects of an authoritarian military state.
Jacoby's liberal demands for universal suffrage were only partly fulfilled
in the unequal Prussian "Three-Class Suffrage" system, based solely on
the criterion of taxable wealth. In addition, government ministers were
18
Ibid., p. 3.
The making of a social democrat 25
entirely responsible to the king, who appointed them without consulting
the Diet; the parliament's right to veto the budget rested on shaky
constitutional grounds; and the 1854 creation of an aristocratic Upper
House further weakened the powers of elected representatives. With liberal
democrats boycotting the "sham elections" of the late 1850s, conservative
political forces once again succeeded in dominating the political scene.
Disillusioned with politics and aging fast under the blows of her hard
life, Johanna Bernstein would succumb to tuberculosis at age forty-eight.
Like his mother, Eduard was a sickly child who, though intellectually
gifted, never received appropriate educational guidance from his parents.
Stunted in his physical growth, Eduard was referred to by neighbors and
family friends as "the small and weak boy." Doctors gave him only a few
years to live, even going so far as to refuse prescribing proper medication;
for, as they saw it, such expenses would be "nothing but waste." When
Johanna Bernstein asked one of them whether there might be some special
treatment that did not require medication and could still prolong her son's
life, the doctor replied: "Well, perhaps nature itself might help in the end
but, most of all, I'd recommend a sip of good Bavarian beer."19
Obviously, the doctor's advice must have been excellent, for "the small
and weak boy" ultimately reached the blessed age of eighty-two.
School years
Young Ede's school years seem to have been like those of most gifted, but
financially disadvantaged children. Tutored by his older brother Max,
Eduard was already able to read and write by the time he entered the first
grade. His pleasant character, honesty, and intellectual gifts soon caught
the attention of his teachers, who pressured Jakob Bernstein to provide his
son with an education beyond elementary school. One of Ede's teachers,
an ardent anti-Semitic Christian conservative, even attempted to per-
suade "das brave Kind" (the well-behaved child) to convert to Christian-
ity. Never considering religious matters a burning issue, the young
Bernstein refused the honor. As a teenager, Eduard came to doubt all
religious dogma, and he was particularly skeptical about the existence of a
personal god. When his mother died in 1868, his atheism became a
life-long conviction. Tormented by the idea that, since there was no
ultimate "beyond," he would never see his mother again, the young
Bernsteinfinallyresolved his mental anguish in the belief that his mother
would still live on in his memory.
Young Ede soon received a further taste of the power of religious
19
Bernstein, Von 1850-1872, p. 29.
26 Preparation
prejudice in the form of the common Prussian contempt for Judaism.
When his non-Jewish classmates found themselves intellectually sur-
passed by the gifted Eduard, they did not hesitate to vent their anger by
taunting him with cries of "Jew!" and "Dirty Jew!" Deeply distressed, Ede
sought after-school refuge in the arms of his father, who told the boy that
such insults were characteristic of the low intellectual abilities of his
friends, and advised him not take them seriously. In the long run,
however, there was no way for Eduard to escape his origins. Even words of
praise, like those of a well-meaning neighbor, served as forceful reminders
of his despised ethnic identity: "You Bernsteins aren't like 'real' Jews."20
Like most German Jews, the young Ede soon learned to put up with, and
accommodate to, a largely anti-Semitic society.
Eduard's continued academic success prompted his parents to make
great financial sacrifices in order to send him to Gymnasium, the
highest-level secondary school in Germany preparing students for univer-
sity study. In the course of his intellectual development, the boy soon
discovered that he had a penchant for pragmatic problem-solving and
analytical thinking, excelling particularly in mathematics, science, and
languages. In accord with his analytical gifts, Eduard also became a master
of chess, which he loved to play both with his peers and even with
interested adults. At the age of fourteen, he developed a great fondness for
theater, dance, and poetry almost overnight, and, much to the astonish-
ment of his uneducated working-class neighbors, took to reciting publicly
the long ballads of his beloved German poets, Schiller and Goethe.
Bernstein's love for Schiller would later strengthen his friendship with
Friedrich Engels, the one-time president of the "Schiller Association" in
Manchester, England. Drawn to the circus and amusement parks, Ede
spent long hours admiring intricate historical panoramas of great battles
through a spectroscope.
When funds for his son's education were finally exhausted, Jakob
Bernstein pleaded with the sixteen-year-old Eduard to leave Gymnasium
and pursue a lucrative trade. His dreams of becoming an eloquent poet
shattered, the good-natured boy obliged his father by entering the bank of
the brothers Guttentag in Berlin as an apprentice-clerk. Here, in a rather
lighthearted fashion, Bernstein grasped the intricacies of the bank and
insurance business. His considerable salary not only permitted him to
maintain himself, but also went a long way in helping to support his family.
But the novelty of learning the banking profession would soon be
dwarfed by far greater attractions. Having for a long time resisted the
influence of the numerous prostitutes crowding the night-time streets of
20
Ibid., p . 6 5 .
The making of a social democrat 27
Berlin's red-light district, the prudish young Bernstein finally succumbed
to his curiosity. After his initial hesitancy, he came to enjoy his regular
visits. In this he was not unlike other young Prussian men whose "sexual
education" in the bordellos was regarded as a necessary preparation for
marriage.
The socialist
Rising nationalist sentiments in the wake of the 1859 Austro-Italian War,
and the accession to the throne of the less autocratic Prince Wilhelm,
facilitated an impressive resurgence of liberalism and its nationalist vision
in state and local elections. The newly founded "National Association"
{Nationalverein) reunited liberals and democrats along a broad consensus
program chiefly aimed at German unification. A few years later, Prussia's
successful 1866 war against the Austrian Empire again fanned national-
istic flames and enhanced popular support for a kleindeutsche German
unification under Prussian leadership.
No doubt, nationalism formed the sociopolitical context of Bernstein's
first political impressions. Already as a boy, Eduard had shown a mild
interest in war, but the 1866 military endeavor awakened in him the first
stirrings of a powerful patriotic sentiment. Hence, it is not surprising that
in 1870, at the outbreak of the Franco-Prussian War, Bernstein was
immediately swept away by the public expression of anti-French feeling
pervading the Berlin streets. His Prussian chauvinism, however, quickly
gave way to more characteristic promptings of objective analysis and
tolerance, and he was soon arguing that his country's propaganda be
directed against the authoritarian governments of both Emperor Napo-
leon III and the Prussian king, not the "ordinary French people." For
publicly announcing his unpopular views, Bernstein was ejected from a
raucous Berlin tavern by a patriotic bouncer. But the encounter only
strengthened his disgust for extreme forms of nationalism in general, and
for the uncompromising militarism of Bismarck's government in particu-
lar. Once having grasped the dimensions of human suffering imposed by
war, Bernstein gradually moved toward a more detached and interna-
tionalist stance, no longer heeding the nationalistic articles of the German
press, and barely noticing the events surrounding the short-lived socialist
experiment of the 1871 Paris Commune.
At the same time, however, he developed an interest in Prussian
politics, following the shifting fortunes of the liberal forces in particular. In
the early 1860s, the Prussian Lower House, dominated by the German
Progress Party {Deutsche Fortschrittspartei), had been strong enough to
challenge the most blatant authoritarian features of monarchical constitu-
28 Preparation
tionalism. For a while it seemed that history had afforded the revolution-
ary forces of 1848 a second chance; King Wilhelm I was even ready to
abdicate. But instead of sweeping constitutional reforms came the "Blood
and Iron" tactics of the new Prussian Minister President, Prince Otto von
Bismarck.
Though insisting on the right of parliament to detail the hotly disputed
military budget, the Progress Party encountered in Bismarck a vigorous
opponent who did not hesitate to take considerable political risks by
suspending most constitutional rights and dissolving parliament for
lengthy periods.21 During the next four years, the Prussian Minister
President's repressive domestic tactics aimed at retaining undisputed
control for the Christian-monarchical-aristocratic order with its conser-
vative ideal of an authoritarian Stdndestaat ("corporate state"). At the
same time, Bismarck used the new mood of militaristic expansionism to
appeal for support from both anti-aristocratic industrialists and national-
istic liberals. Eventually, his extremely popular campaign against Den-
mark intimidated the majority of liberal deputies into accepting the 1866
Indemnity Bill, which formally ended the constitutional conflict in
Bismarck's favor.
This divisive vote marked the decline of German liberalism: in 1867, it
split into a progressive minority party and the right-wing "national-liberal
Party," which, in order to remain politically viable, was forced to continue
its cooperation with Bismarck during the next decade. The fact that the
national-liberals remained Germany's dominant "liberal" party until
1918 speaks for the pervasiveness of a conservative Weltanschauung22
Further secessionist movements split the liberals in 1880, 1884, and
1893, amplifying the political divisions then plaguing the liberal camp. Its
numerous factions remained hopelessly at odds with each other on issues
of constitutional reform, nationalism, and, most of all, on how to deal with
the rising working class.
Ever more identified with democratic liberalism, Bernstein founded a
small discussion circle of like-minded friends, naming it "Utopia" after
Thomas More's ideal Utopian society. The creation of "Utopia" co-
incided with Bismarck's 1871 establishment of the German Empire under
Prussian hegemony. Though formally a "constitutional monarchy," the
Reich's Prussian legal foundations gave the Imperial Government, ap-
pointed by the Kaiser, far greater powers than the elected Reichstag. The
key positions in the Empire's vast state bureaucracy and the powerful
21
See Giinther Roth, The Social Democrats in Imperial Germany (Totowa, NJ: The
Bedminster Press, 1963), pp. 21-22.
22
See James F. Harris, A Study in the Theory and Practice of German Liberalism: Eduard
Lasker, 1829-1884 (Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 1984).
The making of a social democrat 29
imperial army tended to be occupied by aristocratic Junkers and conserva-
tive civil servants who stalwartly defend their privileges against liberal
pressures for reform. Maintaining the discriminatory electoral system in
Prussia, Bismarck used hisfirstyears as Imperial chancellor to spearhead
the founding of a "new" German Conservative Party based on the alliance
of agriculture and industry- the famous marriage of "Iron and Rye." This
renewed turn to conservatism, known as "konservative Sammlungspolitik"
solidified the reactionary mood of "illiberalism" which dominated the
Wilhelmine Empire and, according to Max Weber, permitted "an
economically sinking class" to retain its power and authority.23
Bernstein's left-leaning association soon explored the political possibili-
ties for fighting this powerful combination of surviving feudal elements,
civil servants, and a nationalist-conservative upper bourgeoisie. Ede's
interest in the industrial proletariat as an agent of social change was
kindled during a "Utopia" lecture on socialism given by Friedrich
Fritzsche, a seasoned political agitator and social democrat. Fritzsche
spoke eloquently on the "social question," conveying to his young
listeners the sentiments of a battle-tested worker who had been bitterly
disappointed by the inaction of German liberal parties, particularly on the
important issue of "workers' rights."
Already the 1848/49 constitutional debates over the social component
of the "catalogue of basic civil rights" (Grundrechte) had foreshadowed the
main ideological faultlines that would separate liberal forces for decades
to come. At the center of the dispute was the question of whether the Bill
of Rights should be extended to deal with the most visible social ills of a
rapidly industrializing society. In the years following, liberal attitudes
toward the social question began to crystallize around three distinct
positions. Center-right "classical" Manchester liberals argued for strict
adherence to laissez-faire economic policies, thus strongly denying the
state a major role in addressing existing social inequalities. The center-left
faction envisaged significant state regulations and moderate protectionist
policies for the sake of maintaining social and economic harmony. Finally,
the small left-liberal group of republicans and democrats not only
approved of state interference with the economy, but also demanded
universal, equal suffrage as the critical instrument in solving the social
question in a democratically constituted Germany of the future.24
In the 1860s, the social question expanded into the "workers" ques-
tion," with liberal intellectuals passionately debating the proper political
role of the proletariat. While the organizational distinctions between
23
Max Weber, Gesammelte Politische Schriften (Munich: Drei Mosken Verlag, 1921), p. 24.
On the topic of German "illiberalism," see Stern, The Failure of Illiberalism.
24
See Langewiesche, Liberalismus in Deutschland, p. 63.
30 Preparation
liberal and working-class associations were often blurred, many liberal
intellectuals warned against a "proletarization" of their movement. 25
Mostly restricting themselves to endorsing the formation of "liberal
interest coalitions" to bridge their internal differences, they maintained a
largely hostile posture toward the working class. Liberal political organiz-
ations like the Nationalverein refused membership to workers' associ-
ations, claiming that "workers should first think about raising their
economic status before demanding political rights." 26 Indeed, they were
reluctant to accede to the Fourth Estate's principal demand - the
abolition of unequal suffrage.27
Refusing to integrate working-class concerns into his liberal agenda, the
influential national liberal Johannes von Miquel appealed instead to a
class-transcending humanism, lecturing the proletariat on its duty to live
up to the social expectations of a "generous fatherland" which had
bestowed upon it the privilege of "allowing" it to vote at all.28 Even more
progressive liberal intellectuals like Hermann Schulze-Delitzsch and
Julius Vahlteich, who dedicated their energy to founding and supporting
workers' self-help and educational organizations, remained skeptical of
the desirability of political coalitions between liberals and workers, thus
driving sensitive and intelligent young "protoliberals" with a working-
class background like Bernstein into the hands of proletarian agitators.
As a result of Fritzsche's talk, Bernstein resolved to keep a close watch
on workers' organizations. The government's well-publicized 1872
"Leipzig High Treason Trials" against Wilhelm Liebknecht, 29 August
Bebel,30 and other leading members of the so-called "Eisenacher" faction
of German social democracy afforded Bernstein a fine opportunity to
observe working-class politics in action. At the time of the trial, Bebel's
small socialist party was a fast-growing organization with its own party
organ, called Der Volksstaat.
Bebel and his comrades were charged with the "crimes" of publicly
25
Jiirgen Kocka, "Problems of Working-Class Formation in Germany," in Ira Katznelson
and Aristide Zolberg, eds. Working-Class Formation: Nineteenth Century Patterns in Western
Europe and the United States (Princeton: Princeton UP, 1986), pp. 333-336.
26
Hermann Schulze-Delitzsch cited in Langewiesche, Liberalismus in Deutschland, p. 115.
27
Gregory M. Luebbert, Liberalism, Fascism, or Social Democracy (New York: Oxford UP,
1991), p. 116.
28
M i q u e l cited in L a n g e w i e s c h e , Liberalismus in Deutschland, p . 1 1 8 .
29
For biographical material on Liebknecht, see Raymond H. Dominick III, Wilhelm
Liebknecht and the Founding of the German Social Democratic Party (Chapel Hill: University
of North Carolina Press, 1982).
30
For literature on and by Bebel, see, for example, August Bebel, Aus meinem Leben, 3 vols.
(Berlin: Dietz, 1953); Helmut Hirsch, August Bebel. Sein Leben in Dokumenten, Reden und
Schriften (Koln-Berlin: Dietz, 1968); W. H. Maehl, August Bebel: Shadow Emperor of the
German Workers (Philadelphia: American Philosophical Society, 1980); and Francis L.
Carsten, August Bebel und die Organisation der Massen (Berlin: Siedler, 1991).
The making of a social democrat 31
supporting a quick end to the Franco-Prussian War and daring to vote
against the Prussian annexation of Alsace-Lorraine. As the trial unfolded,
Bernstein's natural sense of justice was evoked by Bebel's and Lieb-
knecht's breathtaking defense speeches - true masterpieces of romantic
rhetoric - which almost invariably ended with their professed "readiness
to die for the noble goals of social democracy."31 The defendants' ethical
convictions and internationalist stance so kindled Bernstein's interest in
socialism that it took him only a short time to acquaint himself with the
main writings of the great working-class thinkers, Ferdinand Lassalle,
Eugen Diihring, and Karl Marx.
August Bebel was released from his brief prison term a few months after
the trial. Eager to meet the young, charismatic party leader in person,
Bernstein decided to attend a lecture on socialism which Bebel was
presenting to the North-Berlin Workers' Association. Once again, the
combination of Bebel's extraordinary abilities as a public speaker and his
modest working-class appearance proved immensely appealing to the
budding radical. Openly criticizing Bismarck's conservative "oppressor
state," Bebel fearlessly reinforced his reputation among the Junkers who
had dubbed him "the shameless loud-mouth" (der unverschdmte
Schreier).32 Yet, Bebel also turned his wrath against liberals who had
suggested that the best way to improve the lot of the industrial proletariat
was both to increase the national budget's social expenditures and to
challenge wealthy philanthropists to ease their social conscience by means
of charitable donations.33 In fact, Bebel was referring to those more
enlightened liberals who realized that the process of industrialization,
which had unfolded in Germany with such extraordinary speed, was
continuing to sharpen class divisions and might provoke a social revolution
which would prevent their desired course of gradual political liberalization.
In 1872, such socially conscious liberal academics under the leadership
of the renowned economist Gustav Schmoller, founded the influential
Vereinfur Sozialpolitik, whose members became known by the pejorative
label of their working-class opponents - the "socialists of the lectern"
(Kathedersozialisteri) ,34 The Verein was a non-party organization that had
provided an intellectual home to two generations of progressive aca-
demics like Lujo Brentano and Max Weber. Its members disavowed
31
Liebknecht cited in Beatrix W. Bouvier, Franzosische Revolution und deutsche Arbeiter-
bewegung (Bonn: Verlag Neue Gesellschaft, 1982), p. 250.
32
This nickname was coined by the Prince Hohenlohe.
33
See, for example, Georg Fesser, Linksliberalismus und Arbeiterbezvegung: Die Stellung der
Deutschen Fortschrittspartei zur Arbeiterbewegung 1861-1866 (Berlin: Akademie Verlag,
1976).
34
The term was coined in 1871 by Heinrich Oppenheim, a "Manchesterite" writing for the
influential liberal newspaper Nationalzeitung.
32 Preparation
extreme laissez-faire Manchesterism and increasingly sought to address
the social question with a combination of state regulations, the establish-
ment of binding collective bargaining procedures, and the strengthening
of workers' self-help cooperatives.
Finding himself wholeheartedly agreeing with Bebel's skeptical posi-
tion on the Verein liberals, Bernstein decided to join the "Eisenacher"
party on the spot. Presented to the party leader as the nephew of the
prominent liberal publisher Aaron Bernstein, and thus a "special catch,"
the young Bernstein was duly impressed when, during their brief conver-
sation, Bebel boldly and confidently predicted that capitalism would
inevitably "collapse" in "at the latest, twenty years." 35 Only a year later,
Europe was hit by the 1873 Great Depression, which continued to
smolder for two economically difficult decades. This event contributed
much to the almost religious belief of many social democrats that Bebel's
great Kladderadatsch - the breakdown of bourgeois society as predicted in
Marx's and Engels The Communist Manifesto - was just around the
corner. On the other hand, with the onset of the Great Depression most
liberal advocates of social reform found themselves caught between the
contempt of an independent, democratic labor movement and Bis-
marck's increasing scorn of liberal principles, particularly his increasing
disenchantment with free-trade policies. No longer politically dependent
on their support for helping to forge a German Reich, Bismarck could
now return to his natural inclination of maintaining a semi-feudal
authoritarian rule amidst the dynamics of a modern industrial state. The
destruction of a small remaining liberal-democratic political force could
now be completed, signalling the end of a short-lived liberal age in
Germany.36
Facing the equally dismal options of either risking a continued cooption
of their movement by Bismarck or their likely political defeat, the
national-liberals chose the former. Even the Catholic Center Party,
weakened by the years of Bismarck's Kulturkampf, caved in. By the end of
the 1870s, the remarkable realignment of German political forces was
under way. The conservative "Black-Blue Alliance" which included
heavy industry, large landowners, parts of the conservative peasantry, the
military, and most of the state bureaucracy, began to fall into place. Beset
by internal division and self-doubt, and finding themselves outman-
oeuvered by a shrewd chancellor who had appropriated their liberal
kleindeutsch dream for his own conservative constituency, progressives
conceded defeat and abandoned their demands for constitutional reform.
35
ES, p. 6.
36
See Abraham J. Peck, Radicals and Reactionaries: The Crisis of Conservatism in Wilhelmine
Germany (Washington, D. C : University Press of America, 1978), p. 4.
The making of a social democrat 33
Increasingly disillusioned with domestic politics, the Kathedersozialist
Lujo Brentano summed up the hopeless position of liberalism:
How sad are our current affairs. I would prepare a critique of Bismarck if I thought
it would do any good, but after careful consideration I am convinced that I should
keep my resolution not to concern myself with contemporary affairs any longer. If I
could read Assyrian, I'd start a book on the ancient Assyrian economy, if only to
forget the economic policies of modern Germany.37
Moreover, liberalism's inability to reach the working class, and the failure
to cross confessional lines prevented the liberals from consolidating
political power at a crucial historical juncture. As a result, the German
bourgeoisie remained woefully divided into separate reform movements
throughout the Wilhelmine Era. Unable to match its Catholic and
socialist counterparts in developing a fairly solid political subculture
based on a coherent Weltanschauung, German liberalism continued its
decline as a major political force.38
Having moved on to a new and better paid job as a bank clerk at S. & L.
Rothschild in Berlin, Bernstein, the new socialist convert, could now
afford to engage in extensive volunteer work on behalf of the party.
Though his talents as an agitator and public speaker were not overwhelm-
ing, his committed work ethic helped him to rise quickly through the party
ranks. Ignaz Auer, the future SPD secretary, took an immediate liking to
his fellow Berliner. Standing in for Bernstein's older brother Max, who
did not share Ede's enthusiasm for working-class politics, Auer imparted
to his protege the ancient arts of rhetoric and public speaking. Eventually,
Bernstein was placed on the party's "lecturer list," which guaranteed him
several speaking engagements each month. Bernstein never forgot the
kindness shown to him by his first mentor, and he published a touching
eulogy after Auer's premature death in 1907.39
Gradually initiated into the intricacies of party life, Bernstein spent
entire weekends on the stump, often forced to defend his socialist
convictions against thefistsand stones of reactionary small-town crowds.
Prussian police laws made it easy for local authorities to use the flimsiest
excuses to close down public gatherings organized by the labor move-
ment. Yet, despite such hardships, the young orator persevered, gradually
emerging as a leadingfigurein a growing political movement that offered
industrial workers more than simple membership in a voluntary associ-
ation. Indeed, an increasingly self-conscious and confident German
Social Democratic Party was preaching a new and all-encompassing
37
Brentano cited in James J. Sheehan, The Career of Lujo Brentano: A Study of Liberalism and
Social Reform in Imperial Germany (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1966), p. 94.
38
See Langewiesche, Liberalismus in Deutschland, p. 164.
39
Eduard Bernstein, Ignaz Auer, Eine Gedenkschrift (Berlin: Vorwarts, 1907).
34 Preparation
Weltanschauung that was consciously set apart from liberalism, its rival
progressive tradition.
Reisland, 1925).
53
Eugen Duhring, Kritische Geschichte der Nationalokonomie und des Sozialismus, 4th ed.
(Leipzig: Naumann, 1900).
54
Bebel cited in Bernstein, ES, p. 10.
55
Gustav Mayer, Friedrich Engels (New York: Howard Fertig, 1969), p. 237.
40 Preparation
Engels' Anti-Duhring, entitled Socialism: Utopian and Scientific, created,
almost overnight, a simplified, easily understandable version of the
Marxist "communist world outlook."56 Besides giving the German labor
movement a firm ideological foundation, Anti-Duhring imparted to
socialist theorists like Kautsky and Bernstein a strong sense of mission,
which would be invaluable for their connection to the movement and the
further popularization of Marxist thought. Before long, scores of new
party pamphlets appeared, simplifying Engels' arguments even further.
Indeed, the "General" (as Engels was called by his followers) had
manged to condense the rather obscure themes in Capital into a few main
points: the inevitable breakdown of capitalism; the vengeance of history;
and the end of all class struggles in the coming rule of the proletariat. To
those workers who readily embraced its deterministic logic, Engels'
"communist world outlook" offered a distinct sense of class solidarity and
a common political language upon which to build institutional support.
Most importantly, however, it helped eclipse the philosophical eclecti-
cism, as well as any remaining vestiges of "Lassalleanism," in the German
labor movement.
56
Engels, Anti-Duhring, in MECW25, p. 8. For an insightful analysis of the "theological"
aspects of Marxism, see George Lichtheim, "The Concept of Ideology," History and
Theory 4.2 (1965), pp. 172-173; and Pierson, Marxist Intellectuals and the Working-Class
Mentality in Germany, 1887-1912.
Persecution and exile
41
42 Preparation
technique of "negative integration/' Bismarck developed a strategy of
political rule that made use of a sociopsychic opposition between
"in-groups" and "out-groups" and thus stylised internal conflicts so as to
lead a majority of elements "loyal to the Empire" against a minority of
"enemies of the Empire." As Hans-Ulrich Wehler noted, the "latter had
to be made to appear a 'serious danger' without ever posing any real threat
to the system" and "the various coalitions of groups loyal to the Empire
were held together primarily by their enmity towards a common foe - in
other words, on a negative basis."2
Wisely judging their constituency as too small in number to challenge
the governmental reprisals on the streets, the leaders of the German labor
movement chose to dissolve "officially" their centralized party organiz-
ation while continuing illegal underground meetings. Emboldened by the
lack of resistance, the police stepped up their activities and began to exile
prominent social democrats from their home towns. The full breadth of
the social ramifications of Bismarck's initiative on the lives of socialist
activists was gradually revealed within the next twelve months. Under
immense police pressure, even small local party organizations were forced
to dissolve. Hundreds of party functionaries, members, and sympathizers
lost their jobs, and, as Bebel reported angrily, many "comrades were
driven from their homes like mangy dogs." 3
Until the lapse of the anti-socialist laws twelve years later, some 352
political associations were dissolved and 1,229 publications, including
104 newspapers and periodicals, were banned.4 The few remaining
socialist publications had to endure constant governmental interference
and heavy censorship. Crippled in its ability to recruit new members, the
SPD leadership nonetheless secretly founded a central "illegal" party
organ, Der Sozialdemokrat. The journal's main task consisted of reporting
on the repressive situation in Germany, thus keeping socialist under-
ground networks informed and defiant. To ease the pressure on editors
and contributors, Bebel suggested the editorship of the paper be moved to
politically safe Switzerland, where it was put together and printed. Scores
of socialist volunteers smuggled thousands of copies out of Switzerland
and distributed them illegally among members of the German working
class and their bourgeois sympathizers.
Although Bismarck had shrewdly resisted the temptation to revoke the
Reichstag mandates of the social democratic representatives for fear of
2
Hans-Wehler, The German Empire 1871-1918 (Dover, NH: Berg, 1985), p. 91.
3
August Bebel cited in Julius Braunthal, History of the International, 3 vols., trans. Henry
Collins, Peter Ford, and Kenneth Mitchell (New York: Praeger, 1980), vol. I, p. 260.
4
Alex Hall, Scandal, Sensation and Social Democracy: The SPD Press and Wilhelmine Germany
1890-1914 (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1977), p. 14.
Persecution and exile 43
turning them into political "martyrs," the party leadership quickly
grasped that their "official" meetings in parliament were ill suited for a
discussion of the party's internal affairs. In order to prevent the alienation
of the parliamentarian Fraktion from the party base, the SPD leadership
resolved to conduct secret party congresses on foreign soil. During the
years of persecution, the party managed to organize three such meetings
in Switzerland and Denmark, which proved to be invaluable for con-
solidating and boosting morale of the German labor movement. All
prominent members of the SPD - some living abroad in exile - were
reunited and could therefore develop a coordinated strategy of under-
ground resistance.
Already at their first secret party conference, held in the romantic
surroundings of Castle Wyden in Switzerland, the delegates had the
unpleasant task of debating the fate of two prominent members who had
repeatedly challenged the party's resolution to protect its remaining
Reichstag mandates by sticking to a "policy of strict legality" in Germany.
Johann Most and Wilhelm Hasselmann dismissed the party's strategy as
"cowardice" and presented themselves as the only genuine revolutionary
opposition to Bismarck's rule of the "iron fist." As Henry Tudor
emphasizes, the debate over these two "renegades" afforded Bernstein
one of his first opportunities to spell out a carefully "genuine" Marxist
position in print.5
Ultimately, the SPD delegates in Wyden recognized that it was better to
react to the anarchist challenge with drastic measures than to engage in a
drawn-out discussion that would give Most and Hasselmann the oppor-
tunity to propagate their views even further. Expelled from the party at the
Wyden Congress, Most emigrated to London and founded his own
journal, Die Freiheit (Liberty), which wedded the demands of The Commu-
nist Manifesto with anarchist calls for extraparliamentary, revolutionary
action. Hasselmann, a previously well-respected SPD member of parlia-
ment, shared Most's fate, and soon began openly to disavow his former
party by aligning himself with obscure Russian Nihilists.6
Bernstein managed to attend all three underground party meetings as a
delegate - the 1883 party congress in Copenhagen only after a long and
dangerous trip under a false name. There is no doubt that his political and
early editorial activities benefited enormously from these opportunities to
meet and personally interact with the most dedicated and brilliant
representatives of German social democracy. Moreover, these travels also
allowed him to establish personal contacts with other leading European
social democrats, like Jules Guesde, Benoit Malon, Paul Lafargue, and
5
Tudor, "Introduction," in MS, pp. 4-5.
6
DDS, p. 49.
44 Preparation
William Morris. Most of all, the young socialist energies thrived on the
genuine atmosphere of solidarity and cooperation displayed at these
memorable underground meetings: "All were filled with the thought, 'We
belong together and must support each other.'" 7
Bismarck quickly adapted to the continued political agitation of the
labor movement. He was successful in planting Prussian police informers
at the SPD's "illegal" conferences, while at the same time undermining
the appeal of social democracy by buying its cooperation.8 Throughout
the 1880s, he introduced several remarkable pieces of social legislation,
supposedly for the "benefit of the German working class": health
insurance (1883), accident insurance (1884), and old age and disability
insurance (1889).
His double-pronged strategy of persecution and reform did indeed
contribute to the increasing polarization of the SPD into a "moderate"
and a "radical" wing. The former, attached to the party's "parliamentary
road," interpreted the chancellor's social policies as small tokens of his
willingness to compromise on major social issues. Led by most of the
social democratic Fraktion of the Reichstag, the moderates tended to play
down the class nature of the movement and emphasized piecemeal
reform. Though they were genuinely critical of Bismarck's autocratic
state, moderates like Bruno Geiser, Wilhelm Bios, Wilhelm Hasenclever,
and Franz Grillenberger were willing to work within the confines of the
anti-socialist laws, concentrating on expanding the party's appeal to
sectors of the population other than the industrial working class.9 In fact,
Bismarck's double-pronged strategy produced another unintended side
effect that, almost unnoticed, was to impact the overall political strategy of
the SPD. By leaving the weak Reichstag as the only "legal" avenue for
social democratic agitation, the chancellor forced the movement to link its
remaining political identity to parliamentarianism. An early article of
Bernstein's encapsulates this new significance of the Reichstag: "Our
deputies are sent to the Reichstag to raise the voice of the proletariat, the
voice of suffering, the persecuted, the oppressed . . . they are the
representatives of the disinherited and the outlawed."10
At the same time, members of the "radical" faction represented by
Bebel and the ideological firebrand Liebknecht continued to emphasize
the class-based nature of the SPD and denounced Bismarck's systematic
violations of basic liberties. Yet, though they identified themselves in
7
Bernstein, Sozialdemokratische Lehrjahre (Berlin: Dietz, 1991), p. 110.
8
EB, p. 21.
9
Gary P. Steenson, Karl Kautsky, 1854-1938: Marxism in the Classical Years (Pittsburgh,
PA: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1978), p. 51.
10
Bernstein cited in Vernon Lidtke, The Outlawed Party. Social Democracy in Germany
1878-1890 (Princeton: Princeton UP, 1966), p. 132.
Persecution and exile 45
varying degrees as followers of Marx and Engels, radicals would have been
hard-put if asked to define what constituted "genuine Marxism."11 On
the other hand, even a very simplistic understanding of Marxist doctrine
was enough to realize that social reality in Germany seemed to bear out the
Marxist message: the chancellor's stubborn refusal to let the anti-socialist
laws lapse highlighted the conservative stance of the bourgeoisie; and, by
voting for the anti-socialist laws, Liberals had betrayed the working class,
thus giving political expression to the underlying antagonistic nature of
Wilhelmine class structures.
Exile in Switzerland
In 1878, the same fateful year that brought German social democracy
Engels' Anti-Duhring and Bismarck's anti-socialist laws, Eduard
Bernstein quit his secure bank job and accepted a position as private
secretary to Dr. Karl Hochberg, a wealthy young patron of the SPD.
Suffering from the tuberculosis which eventually caused his premature
death in 1885, Hochberg was advised to live in Switzerland. Making their
residence at first in Lugano and later in Zurich, the two men launched
several important publications, among them the socialist journals Die
Zukunfty and Jahrbuch fur Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik, which
devoted much space to matters of theoretical inquiry. Soon after their
arrival in Switzerland, however, the Prussian authorities back in Germany
added Bernstein's name to a substantial list of violators of the anti-
socialist laws, thereby blocking his return to Berlin. Bernstein's long years
of exile had begun.
In spite of the bad news from back home, Bernstein enjoyed working for
his employer. Hochberg was a gifted intellectual who considered himself a
committed socialist and appreciated Marxist theory for its contribution to
the critique of bourgeois political economy; ultimately, however, he
preferred the left-liberal outlook evident in the ethical socialism of
Friedrich Albert Lange.12 It is not surprising that Marx and Engels saw in
their party patron Hochberg a naive "social philanthropist" with little
theoretical understanding of economics who embarrassed their young
11
Steenson, Karl Kautsky, p. 51.
12
Friedrich Albert Lange's (1828-1875) most important works are: Geschichte des Material-
ismus undKritik seiner Bedeutung in der Gegenwart (Iserlohn: Baedeker, 1866; translated by
Ernest Chester Thomas as History of Materialism [New York: Humanities Press, 1950]);
Die Arbeiterfrage in ihrer Bedeutung fur Gegenwart und Zukunft (Duisburg: Falk & Lange,
1865); and John Stuart Mills Ansichten u'ber die soziale Frage und die angebliche Umwa'lzung
der Sozialwissenschaft durch Carey (Duisburg: Falk & Lange, 1866). For the influence of
Lange's neo-Kantianism on Bernstein, see chapter 4; Knoll and Schops, Friedrich Albert
Lange: Leben and Werk\ Rikli, Der Revisionisms; DDS, pp. 152-155; see also my
"Historical Materialism and Ethics: Eduard Bernstein's Revisionist Perspective."
46 Preparation
party with his idealistic reveries.13 In fact, Engels' only reason for
personally receiving Hochberg in his London residence was his monetary
support. Although Bebel assured the "General" that the young patron
exerted no real influence in the party, Engels thought it would be best for
the SPD to detach itself from this "good but appallingly naive fellow."14
During their long debates, Bernstein sought to win Hochberg over to the
more Marxist perspective which he had himself only recently acquired
from his study of Engels' Anti-Duhring.
In spite of his newly found distaste for the seductive grip of "German
ideologies," it took Bernstein only a year to get himself embroiled in yet
another theoretical controversy - one that would cause the severe
consternation of Marx and Engels in London. The new dispute involved
the anonymous 1879 "Three-Star Article" in Hochberg's Jahrbuch fiir
Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik. Allegedly composed by Hochberg and
some of his close socialist friends, this ill-conceived essay criticized at
length the purported errors committed by German social democracy. In
particular, its authors accused the movement of an "exaggerated class
bias" which unneccessarily "fanned the hatred of the bourgeoisie",
thereby leading to the creation of the anti-socialist laws. In other words,
they identified Marxism's alleged penchant for "romanticizing the work-
ing class" as the underlying reason for the labor movement's unwilling-
ness to entertain possible alliances with the liberal bourgeoisie.15
Marx and Engels forcefully repudiated the article in an open letter to the
SPD, touching off wild speculations as to the identity of the author(s).
While the division of labor remains a mystery, it appears that the essay's
main authors were Karl Hochberg, C. A. Schramm, and Karl Flesch.
Bernstein's personal involvement in this unfortunate piece of rhetoric was
only minimal.16 At the time, however, Marx and Engels suspected
Bernstein of more active participation, and hence came to doubt his
loyalty to Marxist socialism. Already displeased with his role in the recent
"Duhring Affair," the London exiles hinted that Bernstein's career in the
SPD had become more than tenuous.
Around the same time, Georg von Vollmar decided to relinquish his
position as acting editor of Der Sozialdemokrat, the party's recently
established chief organ. Party leader Bebel, who felt that Bernstein's
occasional "lapses" ought to be attributed to his youthful inexperience
and not to his lack of loyalty to the cause, recommended that Bernstein
13
BebelBWE,p. 40.
14
DDS, p. 45.
15
"Ruckblicke auf die sozialistische Bewegung in Deutschland," in Jahrbuch fiir Sozialwis-
senschaft and Sozialpolitik I (1879), pp. 75-96.
16
Peter Gay (DDS, p. 44) speculates that the article was actually written by Karl Flesch,
who later became a well-known liberal reformer and city councillor of Frankfurt.
Persecution and exile 47
succeed the Bavarian party leader as the paper's new permanent editor-in-
chief. In order to rehabilitate Bernstein's reputation with Marx and
Engels, Bebel was personally prepared to accompany the young penitent
on his December 1880 "Canossa Pilgrimage" to England. He was
convinced that his endorsement would persuade the elders that
Bernstein's Marxist roots were indeed strong enough to warrant such a
responsible position. As Bebel expected, the trip proved extremely
successful. Not only did Bernstein meet the two theoretical fathers of
German social democracy, but he also made hisfirstcontacts with various
leaders of the British labor movement. Marx received the young "sinner"
in a friendly manner at his home and engaged him in a long political
debate which was later continued in the famous Cafe Royal in Piccadilly
Circus. Bernstein's rapport with Engels was even better. Over several
glasses of fine Bordeaux, the "General"became convinced of the young
man's sincere dedication to Marxist socialism.17 In the ensuing years,
their mutual sympathies expanded into an intimate friendship that lasted
until Engels' death in 1895.18
Soon, the intimate network of Bernstein-Bebel-Engels was expanded
to include the Austrian socialist Karl Kautsky. Already a year before his
trip to London, Bernstein had made the acquaintance of this young
intellectual firebrand in Zurich. Working toward a PhD degree in the
history of philosophy and anthropology at the University of Vienna,
Kautsky had been raised on a steady diet of positivism and evolutionary
materialism, counting among his favorite thinkers Charles Darwin, Ernst
Haeckel, and Ludwig Buchner. Having joined the newly established
Austrian Social Democratic Workers' Party in 1875, the young Viennese
soon established himself as a regular contributor to the most prestigious
German and Austrian socialist journals, Vorwarts, Volkstaat, Die Gleich-
heity and Der Sozialist. Preoccupied with bringing natural science and
Darwinism to the service of socialism, Kautsky's early articles sought to
connect the evolutionary notion of the "struggle for survival" to "instinc-
tive solidarity rules," allegedly operating in all human societies.19 Per-
vaded by a good dose of Blichner's naturalism, while at the same time not
adverse to Thomas Henry Buckle's heroic idealism or George Sand's
17
Bernstein, My Years of Exile, p. 153.
18
For the correspondence between Bernstein and Engels, see Bernstein B WE. The literature
on the relationship between Bernstein and Engels is vast; the following is only a short
selection: Gustav Mayer, Friedrich Engels, 2 vols. (Hie Hague: Nijhoff, 1934); Angel,
EduardBernstein etUEvolution du Socialisme Allemand, pp. 99-176; Lichtheim, Marxism:
An Historical and Critical Study, pp. 203-300; Bo Gustafsson, Marxismus und Revisionis-
mus (Frankfurt/Main: Europaische Verlagsanstalt, 1972), pp. 35-88; Lehnert, Reform
und Revolution in der Strategiediskussionen der klassischen Sozialdemokratie, pp. 106-205;
MS, pp. 1-37.
19
Steenson, Karl Kautsky, pp. 31-32.
48 Preparation
romanticism, Kautsky's early social theory was a contradictory maze of
pseudo-materialism and ethical idealism - a peculiar mixture reflected in
his political engagement which oscillated between the romantic radical-
ism of the Austrian anarchists Josef and Andreas Scheu and the more
moderate "Austrian Lassalleanism" of Heinrich Oberwinder.
However, Kautsky's theoretical outlook fundamentally changed in the
winter of 1879-80 when he finally completed his study of Engels'
Anti-Duhring. His jubilant praise for the book's main theses corresponded
with the more sobering recognition that he had learned nothing but a
"frightful mass of nonsense at the university."20 In fact, Kautsky was
ready to give up his future academic plans, and he barely hesitated to
abandon his dissertation research. Having firmly resolved to pursue a
career as a socialist journalist, the young Viennese was pleased to accepted
Hochberg's offer to work as his second editorial assistant alongside
Bernstein. Although Kautsky remained in Zurich for only six months, the
two "young Turks" immediately embarked upon one of the most
remarkable friendships in socialist history.21
Between the years 1879 and 1932, "Ede" and the "Baron" (as Kautsky
was called after his weakness for exquisite clothes) exchanged more than a
thousand letters, making their correspondence one of the most volumi-
nous in the history of the European labor movement.22 Aside from being
emotionally rewarding, Bernstein's and Kautsky's common activities in
Zurich set the stage for their future stellar careers in the SPD. Kautsky
assisted his slightly older friend with difficult theoretical problems in the
fields of anthropology, biology, and sociology, while Bernstein's editorial
experience and his practical understanding of organizational party mat-
ters proved to be immensely beneficial to the abstract Viennese intellec-
tual. Moreover, Bernstein introduced his friend to the various circles of
socialist emigres - Russians, Italians, and Germans - who had found a
home in the politically liberal Zurich of the early 1880s. Over the next
months the two young socialists became inseparable - a "sort of red
Orestes and Pylades."23 Together, they established a Stammiisch ("regu-
20
Ibid., p . 1 5 .
21
See Kautsky, Erinnerungen und Erorterungen. Important intellectual biographies of Karl
Kautsky include: Walter Holzheuer, Karl Kautskys Werk als Weltanschauung. Beitrag zur
Ideologie der Sozialdemokratie vor dent Ersten Weltkrieg (Munich: Beck, 1972); Steenson,
Karl Kautsky, Massimo Salvadori, Karl Kautsky and the Socialist Revolution, 1880-1938,
trans. Jon Rothschild (London: New Left Books, 1979); Reinhold Hunlich, Karl Kautsky
und der Marxismus der II Internationale (Marburg: Verlag Arbeiterbewegung und Gesel-
lschaftswissenschaft, 1981); Ingrid Gilcher-Holtey, Das Mandat des Intellektuellen: Karl
Kautsky und die Sozialdemokratie (Berlin: Siedler, 1986); Dick Geary, Karl Kautsky
(Manchester: Manchester UP, 1987); and John H. Kautsky, Karl Kautsky: Marxism,
Revolution & Democracy (New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction, 1994).
22
F o r a discussion of these letters, see S c h e l z - B r a n d e n b u r g , Eduard Bernstein und Karl
Kautsky.
23
Steenson, Karl Kautsky, p. 46.
Persecution and exile 49
lar drinking table") in their favorite beer pubs, where, under the direction
of fellow-exile Julius Motteler, they composed and sang sarcastic verses
mocking the repressive political conditions in Germany. Together, the
"Marxist twins" drew up letters of inquiry to Engels in London, and
engaged in a host of other literary endeavors. One of their first common
intellectual projects was a collection of Marx's writings which led to the
1886/87 establishment of an "International Socialist Library," a series
that started with The Economic Doctrines of Karl Marx.24
Indeed, Bernstein and Kautsky formulated their common Marxist
position from a joint study of primary sources, often commencing early in
the morning and, interrupted only by lunch and a brief walk, continuing
late into the night. 25 Their increasingly sophisticated Marxist analyses
speculated on the eventual outcome of the long period of economic
stagnation and high unemployment that followed the Great Depression of
1873 and lingered on in Germany throughout the 1880s. Together with
August Bebel, both men represented the party's radical "Marxist" wing,
accepting and defending Marx's predictions that economic crises of such
an extent as then prevailed would eventually lead to a general collapse of
capitalist society.26 Many of Bernstein's political articles written between
1882 and 1888 under the pseudonyms "Leo" or "Vitellius," reflect this
gloomy outlook and the concomitant hope for a swift revolutionary
seizure of power by the proletariat. 27
In addition to drawing a regular paycheck as a full-time party employee,
Bernstein's new position as editor-in-chief of Der Sozialdemokrat afforded
him the opportunity to establish himself as a leading theoretical voice
within German social democracy. Initially, however, Bernstein doubted
whether he was experienced enough to handle this challenging position.
Confiding his qualms to Engels, the young editor asked outright whether
it might not be better if he were replaced by a more "seasoned" comrade.
Engels' reassuring response came swiftly:
You have directed our paper with much skill, found the right tone, and developed
a fine sense of humor. For the editorship of a newspaper one does not need to
display one's scholasticism; what matters is one's ability to grasp the political
situation in an instant. This you have proven almost every single time. Kautsky, on
the other hand, has failed in this regard, because he always loses himself in endless
elaborations of minor points. 28
In a letter to Bebel, Engels was even more explicit in his criticism of
Kautsky, expressing severe reservations about what he perceived to be
24
Karl Kautsky, Karl Marx' okonomische Lehren (Stuttgart: Dietz, 1887).
25
Karl Kautsky, "Eduard Bernstein," p. 44.
26
C /, p. 20.
27
Three of these articles have been translated by Tudor and Tudor in MS, pp. 38-50.
28
Engels to Bernstein (April 14, 1881) in Bernstein BWE, p. 25.
50 Preparation
Kautsky's lingering dogmatism: "I believe that Bernstein fits the job much
better than Kautsky . . . Recently, Kautsky spent some time here [in
London] and I had a serious clash with him. This leads me to believe that
in the future, significant differences of opinion between him and us
[Engels and Bebel] could easily arise." 29 Following Marx, who regarded
Kautsky as a "talented drinker," "superwise," and a "mediocre character
with a small-minded outlook," 30 the "General" believed the underlying
reasons for his own problems with the young hothead lay in Kautsky's
"innate pedantry and obvious tendency to split hairs... For a newspaper,
such a dogmatist is truly a disaster." 31 On the other hand, Bernstein's
rather detached objectivism, his ability to mediate between different sides,
and his keen political eye made him an excellent choice.
Seeking to teach the "Baron" a lesson, Engels published his own
articles in Bernstein's Der Sozialdemokrat, politely but firmly turning
down Kautsky's repeated requests to work with him on his more
theoretical Neue Zeit> a journal which Kautsky had proudly founded in
1883 with the help of the German socialist publisher J. H. W. Dietz. Given
that the journal's expressed purpose was to continue the theoretical
tradition of Marx's Neue Rheinische Zeitung?2 the fledgling Marxist
intellectual must have been especially pained by Engels' reservations. In
fact, it was rather ironic that Kautsky, the editor-in-chief of the SPD's sole
"legal" publication, remained on the editorial fringes of the party, while
Bernstein, editing the party's "illegal" organ in Switzerland, found
himself at the ideological center of the movement. But Kautsky soon
realized that a smooth working relationship with Engels was an indispens-
able precondition for his future theoretical career. Dutifully, he swallowed
his youthful pride and embarked on a series of "study trips" to England,
receiving "private lessons" in Marxist theory from the "General" himself.
By 1887, the aging tutor could take great pride in the intellectual
"progress"of his earnest pupil, confiding to a friend that he had begun to
trust in Kautsky's theoretical abilities "like my own." 33
Bernstein, on the other hand, soon found himself in the midst of a nasty
dispute over his "orthodox Marxist" editorial style. Moderates in the
Reichstag Fraktion were beginning to criticize what they considered the
increasingly "radical" and "one-sided" tone of Der Sozialdemokrat. Led
by Wilhelm Bios, Wilhelm Hasenclever, and Ernst Breuel, a number of
29
Engels to Bebel (February 11, 1881) in Bebel BWE, p. 102.
30
Marx cited in Steenson, Karl Kautsky> p. 47.
31
Engels to Bebel (August 25, 1881) in Bebel BWE, p. 114.
32
Engels to Kautsky (November 15,1882) in MEW 35, p. 399. Even two years later, Engels
still refused to acknowledge Kautsky's Neue Zeit as one of several "official" SPD party
organs.
33
Engels to F. A. Sorge (April 6, 1887) in MEW36, p. 635.
Persecution and exile 51
German representatives publicly disavowed any responsibility for the
content of the journal's articles. Bernstein retaliated with a sharp attack on
Breuel, and soon accusation followed accusation.34 Supported by
Kautsky and Bebel, Bernstein doggedly fought against the moderates'
efforts to muzzle the Marxist rhetoric of his paper, bravely resisting their
attempts to bring Der Sozialdemokrat more directly under their control.
While the conflicting attitude of German socialists toward Bismarck's
social legislation often lay at the core of the dispute, the ongoing
controversy between moderates and radicals assumed a particularly
heated character when Bernstein permitted the publication of two articles
which identified all social democrats as "true communists, revolutiona-
ries, and enemies of the state" and openly endorsed the "use of violence
against state-supported violence."35 Fearing a new round of repressive
measures against German socialist leaders, even Bebel was outraged.
Engels, who secretly enjoyed the paper's militancy, nonetheless warned
his pupil in Switzerland against permitting "an exaggerated rhetoric of
violence." Bernstein's response once again illustrated his remarkable
ability to consider the advice of his more experienced comrades: in
typically straightforward fashion, he assumed full responsibility for the
unfortunate episode, apologized, and emphasized his "willingness to
correct his mistakes."36 Despite the long and stressful period of severe
criticism to which he and his paper were subjected by it, Bernstein
appreciated the iron discipline of the labor movement, particularly its
repeated refusal to give in to the temptation to break up into different
political organizations: "To the honor of Hasenclever, I must sincerely
attest that he has throughout stood up for the *S[oziaI\-D[emokratY -
despite all our differences. The same goes for Grillenberger. Discipline is
truly the strength of our party."37 Little did Bernstein know that the apex
of his battle with the SPD moderates was still ahead.
Late in 1884, the Imperial Government proposed a steamship subsidy
bill that would grant German steamship lines a subsidy of 5.4 million
marks for the creation and extension of existing routes to Africa, Australia,
East Asia, and the South Sea Islands. A latecomer to the nineteenth-
century European scramble for colonies, Germany obviously sought to
catch up with France and England, and thus used public funds to support
a big industry which was growing monopolistic in structure.38 Disagree-
ments in the SPD over support for protective tariffs were not new.
34
For a detailed account of this dispute, see EB, pp. 25-34.
35
Georg von Vollmar, Reden und Schriften zur Sozialpolitik, edited by Willy Albrecht
(Berlin-Bonn: Dietz, 1977), p. 84.
36
Bernstein cited in EB, p. 28.
37
Bernstein to Engels Qune 20, 1884), Bernstein BWE, p. 277.
38
DDS, p. 55.
52 Preparation
Moderates tended to argue that governmental subsidies for domestic
industrial production were in the interest of the working class, since such
subsidies led, in almost every case, to the creation of new industrial jobs.
On the other side, radicals frequently refused to give blanket endorsement
to such "job creation measures" without the inclusion of social demands
like a reduction in work hours, higher safety standards, and standardized
minimum wage laws. As Gary Steenson has pointed out, back in 1879
Engels had worked out a set of "guidelines for positive parliamentary
behavior" which counselled the SPD Reichstag representatives to grant
Bismarck nothing "which will increase the power of the government
vis-a-vis the people." 39
Obviously, a case could easily be made for the rejection of the proposed
steamship subsidy bill, since it implicitly linked public funds to repressive
colonial policies that not only failed to advance the power of the German
people by one iota, but, through the method of indirect taxation, made
"the workers carry the lion's share of the subsidies."40 Yet SPD moder-
ates used the nebulous argument of Germany's alleged "duty" to "further
world communication" to suggest the endorsement of the subsidy bill,
with the exception of the portion that was earmarked for African ships.
The radical minority faction led by Bebel and Liebknecht was vigorously
opposed to all subsidies, contending that steamship subsidies could not be
separated from imperialism and the undermining of world peace. While
Bernstein openly sided with Bebel's views, he made sure that the ensuing
issues of Der Sozialdemokrat included articles and letters to the editor from
both proponents and opponents of the bill.41
Still, most members of the moderate Fraktion felt that he had given more
space to the radical perspective, and they issued an official declaration
criticizing Bernstein's editorial policy: "The paper does not determine the
attitude of the parliamentary party, it is the parliamentary party which
must control the attitude of the paper." 42 When Bernstein received this
statement with the "order" to publish it without comment in the next
issue, he bristled at the moderates' complete disregard for his genuine
attempts to permit a balanced discussion of the matter. In response, he
refused to insert the statement in the paper and, citing the incident as a
threat to his editorial independence, offered to resign on the spot.43 Once
again, his professional future in the labor movement hung in the balance.
Fortunately for Bernstein, the "General" stepped in and facilitated a
39
Steenson, After Marx, Before Lenin, p. 93.
40
Bebel to Engels (December 28, 1884), Bebel BWE, p. 206.
41
EB, p. 36.
42
DDS, p. 55.
43
Ibid., pp. 55-56.
Persecution and exile 53
compromise that ended the crisis and saved his pupil's job. Following
Engels' advice, the Fraktion moderates agreed to offer amendments to the
bill that would cut the subsidies to 3.7 million marks and explicitly link the
release of the funds to their demands that all ships would have to be built
in German shipyards. When the Reichstag Conservatives predictably
rejected all socialist amendments, even the moderates were frustrated
enough to vote unanimously against the bill. Although the act easily
passed the final vote in parliament, the unified action of the SPD
parliamentarians "officially" restored the peace within the party. Though
Bernstein continued in his editorial position and could thus claim an
important personal victory, some irritation between the two wings of
German social democracy remained - a mutual sense of alienation that
harkened back to the original opposition between the "Marxist"
Eisenachers and the "Lassallean" state socialists.44
Bernstein unflinchingly continued to edit Der Sozialdemokrat along
Marxist lines, often drawing the ire of the pro-German "Lassalleans" for
his support of a "proletarian internationalism" over the chauvinistic
conception of a "nationalist" socialism. Identifying capitalism as the
major source for nationalism and war, Bernstein's paper consciously
aimed at disseminating Marxist arguments among its socialist readership:
"As long as the class state exists, there is no way to eliminate wars of nation
against nation. Wherever we find economic exploitation, wefindwar - at
home between the exploiters and the exploited and abroad among the
exploiters' struggle over territories for exploitation."45 Lassalleans de-
murred; the colonial expansion of the German Empire not only appealed
to their nationalistic pride, but, as they saw it, it also contributed to the
steady rise of the German worker's living standard.
As Henry Tudor has noted, it was perhaps the most complicated part of
Bernstein's task as editor-in-chief to help win the arguments against the
remaining Lassalleanism without jeopardizing party unity.46 In this
difficult enterprise, Bernstein's hand was significantly strengthened by
Engels' advice and support. While the "General's" specific advice to the
leaders of European labor movements sometimes fell on deaf ears, his
unique position as the "legitimate voice of Marxist socialism" frequently
gave him the necessary bully pulpit from which to preach the pursuit of a
"Marxist politics." In fact, as the Conservative-dominated Reichstag kept
renewing Bismarck's Anti-Socialist Laws, Engels came up with the
ingenious "Marxist" suggestion that the party adopt a tactic of "intransi-
gent opposition." Marrying revolutionary Marxist rhetoric with the
44
EB, pp. 36-37.
45
Der Sozialdemokrat (December 23, 1888).
46
Tudor, "Introduction," in MS, p. 5.
54 Preparation
"realistic" tactic of maintaining the "parliamentary road," Engels pro-
nounced that the party had the duty of actively participating in the
parliamentary process in order to increase its strength and secure its
survival. However, parliamentary activity should not be seen as an end in
itself, but as an instrumental means within a long-term struggle that would
"inevitably" culminate in revolution. 47 Confirmed in their cherished roles
within parliamentarian "legality," moderates were willing to pay lip
service to the "revolutionary final goal," and could even occasionally be
counted on to support radical slogans directed against the "repressive
enemies of the working class."
But nobody grasped the propagandistic opportunities hidden in Engels'
"solution" better than August Bebel. Again and again, he encouraged
Bernstein and his other literary comrades to show in their articles how
existing repressive political conditions had in fact borne out the radical
message of Marx and Engels. Raising Marxist principles to the status of
"prophetic" pronouncements, Bebel promised workers that the time of
their trials and tribulations was merely a necessary "overture" to a heroic
future. Ultimately, the socialist opera would end triumphantly with the
avenging angel of history brandishing his sword, clearing the stage for the
final socialist goal - the revolutionary seizure of political power by the
proletariat and the establishment of a just economic and social order. In
particular, Bebel's renewed sanguine predictions of an impending col-
lapse of capitalist society - "at the latest in 1889" - gave his popular
underground speeches the force of unshakable commandments. 48
Backed by their two powerful mentors, Bernstein and Kautsky gradual-
ly emerged as the leading theoretical voices of the SPD, their respective
editorial activities proving instrumental in imparting orthodox Marxist
theory to the young German labor movement. Yet, each man saw his role
as Marxist theorist in a different light. As Gary Steenson emphasizes,
Kautsky's early role in the Austrian party was a model for all his later
participation in various socialist organizations: he took no part in
administration, and neither held nor ran for public or party offices, seeing
himself exclusively as a propagandist, teacher, and very occasional
speaker. 49 Thus, he viewed the socialist intellectual, first and foremost, as
a Marxist popularizer and fierce guardian of "correct" Marxist theory.
Striving to fulfill Engels' ambitions to elevate Marxist doctrine as the only
"genuine" Weltanschauung of the proletariat, Kautsky denned the para-
mount task of the Marxist theorist as that of keeping watch over the
separation of "true" social theories from "false" ones.
47
Ibid., pp. 3-4.
48
See Bernstein, My Years of Exile, p. 96.
49
Steenson, Karl Kautsky, p. 38.
Persecution and exile 55
Consequently, Kautsky and his Neue Zeit concentrated on highlighting
the disparities between the "scientific character of Marxism" and the
ideological distortions of "bourgeois" social theory or other "non-
scientific," i.e., "non-Marxist" forms of socialism. Hoping to rid the party
entirely of its remaining philosophical "eclecticism," he preached the
superiority of Marx's method as a tool for analyzing society by focusing
primarily on the development of the mode of production. Over and over
again, Kautsky insisted on the importance of a "proletarian vantage point"
which, by its very nature, could not tolerate "spurious compromises and
syntheses" in the realm of theory: "The bridging and balancing of
opposites - a significant task of practical politics - is the death of theory. " 50
At the same time, Kautsky legitimized the party's gap between
revolutionary theory and reformist practice - inherent in Engels' tactics of
"intransigent opposition" - by readily accepting the existence of crucial
functional differences between socialist theorists and the Praktiker ("prag-
matists") of the labor movement. It is clear that Kautsky's objective was to
secure the intellectual autonomy of the former while leaving the latter
sufficient latitude for shifting political tactics. Ultimately, the power of
this conception was reflected in the realities of party life: the formation of
an enduring "Kautsky-Bebel axis" around which most items of the SPD's
political and theoretical agenda would turn for almost two decades.
On the other hand, Bernstein's conception of theoretical leadership
differed in many important respects from Kautsky's "evangelical" exer-
cises aimed at "spreading the Marxist word to the masses." Directing a
primarily policy-oriented party organ, Bernstein was more interested in
the difficult task of testing the applicability of socialist ideas in the complex
realm of political and economic practice. Unlike Kautsky, who felt that
the socialist intellectual's talents were wasted on the "detail work of the
day,"51 Bernstein enjoyed analyzing intricate policy questions from a
Marxist point of view, and never sought to free the theorist from practical
matters. He grew increasingly engaged in a struggle with what he saw as a
widening of the theory-practice deficit in the SPD, hoping to provide both
a "realistic" and a value-oriented framework for successful socialist
action. Despite his genuine affection for Engels and the theoretical
outlook he stood for, Bernstein's understanding of the role of the socialist
intellectual more closely approached the commonsensical convictions
expressed in Liebknecht's famous dictum: "I cherish Marx; still, party
matters are paramount."52
50
Karl Kautsky, "Der Parteitag in Liibeck," in NZ 20.1 (1901-2), pp. 19-20.
51
Karl Kautsky, "Akademiker und Proletarier," in NZ 19.2 (1900-1), pp. 90-91.
52
Protokoll tiber die Verhandlungen des Parteitages der Sozialdemokratischen Partei Deutsch-
lands, abgehalten zu Erfurt vom 14-20 Oktober 1891 (Berlin, 1891), p. 327.
56 Preparation
But Bernstein's apprenticeship years in his Swiss exile were not
exclusively dedicated to matters of socialist politics. In 1887, in a quiet
ceremony, he married Regine Zadek-Schattner, a widow with two young
children. Superficial acquaintances of the Bernsteins, "Gine" Zadek's
Berlin family was also Jewish and Polish in origin. Young Ede had been an
occasional guest at the Zadek home in the early 1870s, when the quiet and
well-educated Gine married Carl Schattner, a Serbian industrialist whose
business failed a few years after the wedding. Given to alcohol abuse and
occasional violent outbursts, Carl Schattner showed little interest in his
two children and frequently mistreated his young wife. His sudden death
almost came as a relief for Gine. Accompanied by her mother, son Ernst
and daughter Kate, she moved to Switzerland, where she again met
Eduard Bernstein. But unable to make ends meet, Gine and her children
were forced to return to Berlin and move in with her brother, Ignaz Zadek,
a successful medical doctor with strong sympathies for the labor move-
ment. Aware that his friend had fallen in love with the young widow,
Kautsky suggested that Bernstein invite her back to Zurich for an
extended stay - a recommendation that ultimately led to Ede and Gine's
marriage. 53
The couple's relationship was extremely close, and although they
remained childless, Bernstein proved himself a kind stepfather, treating
his wife's children as his own. Throughout the years, Ede remained
extremely private about his family life, and even his very revealing
autobiographical books deal only very sparingly with his marital relation-
ship. In fact, his announcement of his impending wedding barely
comprises two paragraphs. After reassuring Engels that Gine was a "good
comrade willing to shoulder all obligations which my position imposes on
me," Bernstein ended his brief note with a rather detached remark: "Well,
that's off my chest, and now back to more general matters . . ," 54
Herself drawn to socialism, Gine was more than willing to share her
husband's professional burden. She single-handedly translated Sidney
and Beatrice Webb's voluminous History of British Trade Unions into
German, with Ede supplying the introduction. 55 There is, however, no
evidence to support the suggestion that Gine influenced her husband to
break with orthodox Marxism. 56 Quite the contrary. She struck up a deep
53
Florian Tennstedt, "Arbeiterbewegung und Familiengeschichte bei Eduard Bernstein
und Ignaz Zadek," in Internationale wissenschaftliche Korrespondenz zur Geschichte der
deutschen Arbeiterbewegung 18.4 (1982), p. 474; and Eduard Bernstein, Sozialdemok-
ratische Lehrjahre, pp. 157-160.
54
Bernstein cited in DDS, p. 56.
55
Sidney and Beatrice Webb, Die Geschichte des Britischen Trade Unionismus, translated by
Regine Bernstein and introduced by Eduard Bernstein (Stuttgart: Dietz, 1895).
56
See Angel, Eduard Bernstein et L'Evolution du Socialisme Allemand^ p. 71.
Persecution and exile 57
friendship with the aging Engels, engaged him on political topics, and
helped him carry out his personal errands, especially as his health began to
fail. When Gine died in 1923, Bernstein fell into despair. Unable to
overcome his loss, he retreated to his home and remained there for several
months. Unwilling to receive visitors for a long time, he buried himself in
work and became something of a social recluse.
Bernstein's political exile in Zurich also afforded him the opportunity of
expanding his education beyond the immediate demands of his editorial
position. He embarked on an intensive study of languages and European
history, and within three years was able to speak and write fluently in
Italian and French. By 1883, his French was so good, in fact, that Engels
entrusted him with the German translation of Misere de la Philosophie -
Marx's famous critique of Proudhon's decentralized, communal social-
ism. Upon moving to London, Bernstein immersed himself in the study of
English, a language with which he grew so comfortable that he continued
to correspond in it throughout his life. As Bernstein's intellectual horizons
expanded and his journalistic experience grew, so did the circulation of
Der Sozialdemokrat, already surpassing 10,000 in 1884. Evincing his
enthusiasm for his protege's editorial performance, Engels wrote to
Bernstein approvingly: "I believe that a young man like you who has
proven himself so brilliantly should continue at the job indefinitely."57
59
Eduard Bernstein, Cromwell and Communism (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1930).
60
Bernstein to Kautsky (September 30, 1890), Kautsky Archives, International Institute for
Social History, Amsterdam (IISH), DV131.
61
Eduard Bernstein, Ferdinand Lassalle As a Social Reformer, translated by Eleanor Marx
Aveling (New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, 1893).
Persecution and exile 59
it with its initial sense of its "great socialist ideals," Bernstein went on to
lambast most of Lassalle's political and economic schemes, particularly
his incipient nationalism and his reliance on strong state support for the
creation of workers' producer cooperatives.
Indeed, he most resented Lassalle's "narcissistic grandiosity" and the
"compulsive social climbing" which led the self-proclaimed "leader of the
proletariat" to "flirt with the forces of reaction which he wanted to use to
his advantage . . . instead of trusting the innate strength of the labor
movement."62 It should not come as a surprise that such passages aroused
vehement protests from the remaining German Lassalleans. For them,
Bernstein was engaged in an "unfair strategy" of connecting distinctive
traits of Lassalle's allegedly "flawed" personality to his "failed" political
initiatives. Engels, however, applauded Bernstein's efforts and did his best
to shield his sensitive pupil from the contents of the numerous protest
letters he received from German Lassalleans. Unfazed by the bombard-
ment, the "General" told Bernstein to disregard his "misguided critics."
At the same time, he encouraged him to use the powerful "iron fist" of the
critic encased in a "velvet glove," in continuing to smash the popular
"Lassalle Legend."63
62
Ibid., p . 1 2 5 .
63
Engels cited in EB, p. 50.
60 Preparation
all of German society.64 Indeed, many Praktiker in the SPD openly
revealed that they considered themselves "Marxists" only to the extent
that they accepted the steady flow of communication between the party
leadership and Engels in London. With the lapse of the Anti-Socialist
Laws, they emphasized a reformist model of social transformation, and
even proposed maintaining some form of "constructive interaction" with
the government and bourgeois parties on particular issues.65
Predictably, their vision of "reform socialism" encouraged a number of
radical voices openly to question the wisdom of the "phoney" coexistence
of revolutionary Marxist ideology and reformist political practice. Known
as the "Youngsters," these self-proclaimed "revolutionary Marxists"
exercised considerable influence over a number of socialist newspapers,
and fiercely attacked Bebel and the SPD leadership for not opposing the
Praktiker more firmly. Calling the party's parliamentarianism "despicable
petty-bourgeois opportunism,"66 the Youngsters faction resembled to
some extent the British "Social Democratic Federation" (SDF) whose
"Marxist" leaders combined their insurrectionary reading of The Commu-
nist Manifesto with incessant calls for "radical measures."
As moderates began to strike back at the Youngsters, Bebel recognized
the impending danger to party unity and turned to Engels for advice. After
a short exchange of letters, both men reaffirmed their conviction that the
post-1890 political situation in Germany demanded a change in agita-
tional tactics without an abandonment of radical tenets. Engels continued
to argue that the principles of representative democracy were only an
intermediate step on the way toward the Marxist revolutionary "final
goal." However, the Kaiser's "New Course" cried out for a fundamental
re-evaluation of party tactics built on the old political realities of state
oppression, marginalization, rigid opposition, and underground resis-
tance. While both Engels and Bebel scorned the moderates' call for
absolute reformism, they agreed on a temporary strategy endorsing
"gradualist" tactics. In their opinion, the rapid growth of the labor
movement could only be maintained under conditions of legality and
without launching radical provocations against the Kaiser's government.
Nothing would be more devastating for German social democracy than a
new round of oppressive measures before the SPD was strong enough to
muster a decisive revolutionary response.
64
For a recent evaluation of the role of Bavarian socialist reformists and their leader, Georg
von Vollmar, see Francis L. Carsten, "Georg von Vollmar: A Bavarian Social Democrat,"
in Journal of Contemporary History 25 (1990), pp. 317-335.
65
Gilcher-Holtey, Das Mandat des Intellektuellen: KarlKautsky und die Sozialdemokratie, pp.
54- 55.
66
For a detailed summary of the Youngsters' activities, see Pierson, Marxist Intellectuals and
the Working-Class Mentality in Germany 1887-1912, pp. 19-34.
Persecution and exile 61
Reacting as a mere "tactician/' Engels repeatedly warned party radicals
against premature forms of direct action. For example, pointing to the
volatile political climate in Germany, he counselled against SPD-led
demonstrations in celebration of "Labor Day." In addition, he dismissed
the Youngsters' calls for a general strike on that day as "horrendous
stupidity."67 Indeed, throughout the 1890s, Engels upheld, "for the time
being," "peacefulness, legality, and restraint."68 It is ironic that Engels,
who had formulated the classical Marxist definition of "opportunism"
and mercilessly exposed every kind of opportunism in the international
labor movement, was prepared to "give the SPD enormous latitude in this
regard - as long as it contributed to its smooth growth."69
Having found common ground on party tactics, Engels and Bebel
pronounced their final "verdict" on the Youngsters' rebellion. To the
radicals' great dismay, the co-author of The Communist Manifesto scorn-
fully dismissed their proposals as "frantically distorting Marxism," and
blamed it on the "present rush of students and literary types into the
party."70 While firing his verbal salvos against these "arrogant upstarts,"
Engels did not hesitate to turn his fury against the moderates as well,
calling them "petty bourgeois socialists" who would soon "bite the
dust."71 Leaning on Bebel's ability to execute his proposals, Engels
suggested drastic measures to keep the party from losing its ideological
unity, and thus its political effectiveness: the anarchist leaders of the
"Youngsters" were expelled, and leading Praktiker were pressured into
renewing their token recognition of revolutionary Marxist principles.
In this spirit of "house-cleaning," an enthusiastic Engels announced to
Laura Marx-Lafargue that "February 20, 1890" was the "day of the
beginning of the German revolution."72 Polling almost 1.5 million votes
out of 9.5 million in this triumphant election of 1890, German social
democracy had finally made the transition from a small movement to a
well-organized mass party - the second strongest in the Reich. Engels even
went so far as to calculate with "mathematical certainty" the coming
electoral victory of the SPD. In his opinion, a majority of the military's
personnel would vote social democratic by 1900, thus opening up the
possibility of a quick and relatively bloodless takeover by the proletariat.73
67
Engels to Adolph Sorge (April 19, 1890), MEW37, p. 395.
68
MEW 37, pp. 366, 381.
69
Hans-J. Steinberg, "Friedrich Engels' revolutionare Strategie nach dem Fall des
Sozialistengesetzes," in H. Pelger, ed. Friedrich Engels 1820-1970 (Hannover: Verlag fur
Literatur und Zeitgeschehen, 1971), p. 126.
70
Engels to Otto von Bonigk (August 21, 1890), MEW 37, p. 444.
71
Engels to Kautsky (September 4, 1893), MEW 38, p. 448.
72
Engels to Laura Lafargue (February 26, 1890) in MEW 37, p. 359.
73
Engels in MEW 22, p. 251.
62 Preparation
While Bebel agreed with Engels' tactical moderation and shared his
confidence in the ultimate victory of the proletariat, their overall concep-
tual blueprint of the coming socialist revolution differed significantly.
Bebel expected the working class to take power after a general economic
breakdown, thus in effect endorsing what Dieter Groh refers to as
"revolutionary attentisme" - a combination of fatalism and formal radical-
ism.74 In other words, the collapse of capitalism and revolution was an
inevitable "natural process." In the meantime, the task of the party
consisted in organizing the proletariat and preparing it for the decisive
moment. Liebknecht shared neither Engels' nor Bebel's ideas: he identifi-
ed as the goal of the SPD's gradualism the assumption of an absolute
majority in parliament, and the subsequent hineinwachsen ("growing
into") of the current society into socialism. It was this vaguely expressed
conception of an "evolutionary socialism" which Bernstein would ulti-
mately supply with a more sophisticated theoretical foundation. Yet, these
incompatible assumptions regarding the party's "gradualism" go to show
that while Engels, Bebel, Liebknecht, and even the moderates agreed on
peaceful party tactics, each clearly subscribed to different conceptual
models of what a "socialist transformation of society" in the German
context really meant.
But in the early 1890s, these diverging theoretical visions signified very
little. The party continued engaging in the "reformist" practice of
pursuing immediate improvements of workers' conditions, which some-
times involved informal "deals" and compromises with bourgeois parties
and the Kaiser's authoritarian government. In fact, party secretary Ignaz
Auer later claimed that even from the time of its inception, the German
social democracy stood for a thorough reformism, for "How could it be
otherwise for a party that counts on mass support?"75 Though ingenious
in its theoretical design, Engels' strategy of endorsing "short-term"
reformist tactics that were not at odds with a revolutionary "final goal"
merely postponed the emergence of voices critical of this widening chasm
between theory and practice. Future "revisionists" like Bernstein would
eventually ask the crucial question: if Marxist theory depended on
practice and vice versa, and if the military did not overwhelmingly support
social democracy by the turn of the century, didn't Engels' endorsement
of legality and electoral concerns ultimately have to translate into a
"revision" of theory as well?
Already a year later, the rupture between theory and practice became
painfully obvious when the SPD leadership decided to draft the new 1891
74
Dieter Groh, Negative Integration und revolutiondrer Attentismus: Die deutsche Sozialdemok-
ratie am Vorabend des Ersten Weltkrieges (Frankfurt: Propylaen, 1973).
75
Auer cited in Bernstein, Ignaz Auer, p. 63.
Persecution and exile 63
Erfurt Party Program. In addition, the events leading up to the adoption of
the new program significantly changed the existing power relations within
the SPD. Determined to purge social democracy of its last Lassallean
remnants, Engels, against the wishes expressed in Marx's last will and
testament, resolved to publish the latter's private notes criticizing the
party's 1875 Gotha Program. Engels' surprising initiative, undertaken
without informing the party leadership, had two important objectives.
First, in line with Bernstein's literary efforts, he sought to shatter the
persistent "Lassalle Legend." Engels hoped that the publication of
Marx's private opinions would help to reveal a historical truth: the
existence of "deep antagonisms between Marx and Lassalle."76
But Engels' calculated manoeuvre had a second target: Wilhelm
Liebknecht. Realizing that his aging comrade's intellectual ability to
spread Marx's gospel to a new generation of workers had reached its
limits, the "General" wanted to see him replaced by two more sophisti-
cated Marxist theorists, namely Kautsky and Bernstein. Engels knew only
too well that Marx's marginal notes would reveal not only the latter's
disapproval of Lassallean ideas but also his low esteem for Liebknecht, the
theoretical "architect" of the "eclectic" 1875 Gotha Program. Hence, he
was ready to weather the unpleasant storm of party criticism hurled at him
for his indiscretion.
Engels' plan worked to perfection. Once the initial wave of outrage had
passed, Engels' scheme succeeded in producing the desired effects. While
the SPD leadership offically commissioned Liebknecht with drawing up
the new program, Bebel's confidence in his old comrade-in-arms waned
quickly in the light of Engels' revelations.77 When Liebknecht's internal
draft was made accessible for review to leaders of both the social
democratic parliamentary faction and local party chapters, Bebel eagerly
joined the growing chorus of its critics, allowing Kautsky to launch an
all-out assault on Liebknecht's version. In fact, Kautsky's alternative
proposal, based on the 1880 French "Minimalist Program" drafted by
Marx and two leading French socialists, soon emerged as the leading draft
proposal.
Readily agreeing to minor changes suggested by Bebel, Kautsky
managed to gather the entire political weight of the powerful party leader
behind his proposal. The "hands-on politician" (Bebel) and the "Marxist
ideologist" (Kautsky) had coordinated their mutually beneficial career
76
Engels BWK, pp. 282, 283.
77
The belated publication also revealed that Liebknecht had managed to hide from Bebel
Marx's Critique of the Gotha Program, which he had sent to the party leadership. Had Bebel
read Marx's remarks, he probably would not have given his approval to Liebknecht's
draft.
64 Preparation
interests, a phenomenon that was to leave its indelible mark on the history
of German social democracy. With Kautsky on board, Bebel was even
strong enough to send the "General" a clear sign of his independent
political leadership. Warning against the dangerous political conse-
quences of incorporating Engels' radical-democratic demands for "the
concentration of all political power in the hands of a people's representa-
tive body," 78 Bebel instead suggested a reformulation of this passage that
would blunt its radical edge. Against Engels' protest, the party leadership
overwhelmingly adopted Bebel's motion. Having reached the zenith of his
power, Bebel could now afford to soothe Engels' anger by recommending
that Kautsky write the standard commentary to the new program. Despite
Bebel's show of force, Engels' plan had worked: Lassallean phrases were
omitted, Liebknecht had been demoted, and his pupil Kautsky had been
installed as the "official" party theorist in Germany.
As adopted, the 1891 Erfurt Program consisted of two major parts: a
"theoretical-Marxist" portion based on Kautsky's amended proposal;
and a "practical part," drafted jointly by Bernstein and Engels. The
theoretical portion enshrined the Marxist doctrine of class struggle with
its "inevitable" socialist telos. Time was on the side of the proletariat, for as
capitalist society moved ever closer to its revolutionary demise, the "final
goal" of social democracy would take shape in the "transformation of
capitalist private ownership of the means of production into social
ownership, and the transformation of the commodity production into one
for and by society- a socialist form of production." Hence, the task of the
party was defined as "enlightening the proletariat about both its historical
role in the revolutionary class struggle" and its "inevitable goal."79
Bearing the fingerprints of Bernstein, the "practical" part of the Erfurt
Program represented a "social democratic program of action," and
consisted of concrete demands like reform of discriminatory electoral
laws, the establishment of popular self-government, education, and social
policy.80 Calling for both the extension of political democracy and the
implementation of fair labor laws, Bernstein's rather moderate portion of
the Erfurt Program stood in marked contrast to the radical language of its
"theoretical" part. Reflecting Engels' solution of endorsing tactical
reformism "on the way" to revolution, the document did little to bridge
the party's growing gap between radical theory and gradualist practice.
Thus, German social democracy missed an early historical chance to
remedy this ultimately fatal dualism.
78
MEW 22, p. 235.
79
Karl Kautsky, Das Erfurter Programm, 20th ed. (Berlin: Dietz, 1980), pp. 106, 125-127,
129-140, 222-223.
80
Ibid., pp. 255-258.
Persecution and exile 65
In the end, Engels revealed that his overall concerns with the program's
"Marxist character" outweighed his political instincts. Still, there is
evidence that he remained aware of the potential harm that the widening
theory-practice gap could do to the future unity of the labor movement.81
While invoking a spurious ideological unity in the name of "Marxism,"
the incompatibility of the Erfurt Program's two main portions nonetheless
signalled a renewal of the 1875 Gotha compromise between radical theory
and reformist practice within the authoritarian political framework of
Wilhelmine Germany. But it also gave expression to the party's growing
theoretical fatigue and its lack of critical self-reflection. These ominious
developments increasingly impacted Bernstein's intellectual evolvement,
providing the context of his emerging quest for "evolutionary socialism."
81
Engels in MEW 38, p. 183.
The "Revisionist Controversy5
1
Leo (Bernstein), "Klippen," Der Sozialdemokrat (April 12, 1890; May 3 and 24, 1890).
2
See Henry Tudor, "Introduction," in MS, p. 7.
3
See, for example, DDS', Hirsch, Der "Fabier" Eduard Bernstein; Frei, Fabianismus und
Bernstein'scher Revisionisms 1884-1900.
66
The "Revisionist Controversy" 67
At first glance, it indeed appears that Bernstein's revisionism heavily
relied on Sidney Webb's organicist and scientistic claims regarding the
importance of "objective social criteria" that allowed for a prescriptive
science of politics.4 Largely a middle-class movement of socialist intellec-
tuals, the Fabians, too, argued for a democratic, "evolutionary" recon-
struction of society on the basis of universalist, ethical imperatives.
Bernstein, however, vehemently denied strong Fabian influences on his
political thought. While conceding the favorable impression made on him
by Fabians like the Webbs and George Bernard Shaw, and even admit-
ting on occasion that their evolutionary model had "expanded his
theoretical horizon," he nonetheless insisted that Fabian arguments did
not serve as the main intellectual source of his own "revisionist"
enterprise.5 As he was known for always scrupulously acknowledging his
theoretical influences, Bernstein's claim ought to be taken seriously.
Moreover, there is indeed some evidence for his assertion: as late as 1896,
he assailed the "confused nature of Fabian eclecticism," criticizing
Fabian utilitarian, visionless pragmatism for its lack of core principles.6 In
fact, the Fabian tendency toward atheoretical instrumentalism and
administrative bureaucratism forced the German exile to explore in more
detail the inherent tension in reformism between ethical ideals and
political expedience.7 Granting Bernstein some theoretical detachment
from Fabianism, the fact remairs that he openly admired Sidney Webb's
intellectual stature and his almost encyclopedic memory. On several
occasions, he praised Webb's remarkable talents in parrying the some-
times openly hostile questions posed by his learned lecture audience.8
Bernstein himself was a regular lecturer at meetings of the Fabian society,
and he occasionally dined at the homes of the Webbs, George Bernard
Shaw, and Edward Pease. So, undoubtedly, some "Fabianism" must have
rubbed off on him.
But even if we concede that Bernstein was not a fully fledged "Fabian
convert," what about the claim that he spoke with the eclectic voice of a
Benthamite Philosophic Radical?9 There is no doubt that his later views on
foreign policy and internationalism resembled the ethical and political
positions held by British Radicals like Richard Cobden, the early apostle of
4
C. E. Hill, "Sidney Webb and the Common Good: 1887-1889/' in History of Political
Thought 14.4 (Winter 1993), pp. 593-594.
5
Eduard Bernstein, "Zur Geschichte des Revisionisms," n. d., in Bernstein A, A43.
6
Eduard Bernstein, "General Observations on Utopianism and Eclecticism," MS, p. 77.
7
Bernstein, My Years of Exile, pp. 274-276.
8
Ibid., p. 242.
9
Fletcher, Revisionism and Empire, p. 184; "British Radicalism and German Revisionism:
The Case of Eduard Bernstein," in TJie International History Review 4.3 (1982), pp.
339-370; and Markku Hyrkkanen, Sozialistische Kolonialpolitik: Eduard Bernsteins Stellung
zur Kolonialpolitik und zum Imperialismus 1882-1914 (Helsinki: SHS, 1986).
68 Preparation
Free Trade and founder of the Anti-Corn Law League. 10 Bernstein, who
could never quite warm up to the ascetic Fabian conception of a Puritan
socialism built mainly on administrative efficiency and sound bookkeep-
ing, may have aligned himself instead with the refined aestheticism of the
Philosophic Radicals - a clear departure from Beatrice Webb's puritan
suspicion of the pleasures of material consumption and high culture.
But the intellectual influences on Bernstein during his London exile
were not confined to the principles of Philosophic Radicalism alone.
Wide-ranging in his tastes, he read any radical pamphlet he could lay his
hands on, and frequently attended the political speeches of British trade
union leaders, atheistic free-thinkers, and Christian socialists, 11 thus
absorbing many features of the British "Common Weal" tradition derived
from Coleridge, Owen, Kingsley, Ruskin, and J. S. Mill.12 Bernstein also
made the acquaintance of renowned poet and Socialist Leaguer, William
Morris (who, in 1883, had published his best-selling Utopian novel, News
From Nowhere), and struck a lasting friendship with the Laborite Ramsay
MacDonald, the future British prime minister. Indeed, at the 1893
Bradford Founding Conference of MacDonald's Independent Labour
Party, organized with the help of Keir Hardie, Bernstein was a noted
guest-of-honor.
In sum, then, establishing a single, definite link between Bernstein's
later revisionism and a distinct intellectual source within Britain's radical
tradition would appear to be an impossible enterprise. Suffice it to say that
he did catch the "British disease," and hence, to some extent, absorbed
the left-liberal "virus." As will be shown below, many features of
Bernstein's evolutionary socialism were nourished by the same all-
embracing scientific and ethical Victorian evolutionary intellectual cli-
mate that in the last years of the century gave birth to the "New
Liberalism" of progressive political thinkers like L. T. Hobhouse and J. A.
Hobson. Indeed, Bernstein became a personal friend of H. W. Massing-
ham and other prominent members of the New Liberal "Rainbow
Circle," 13 and he frequently contributed articles to the group's literary
outgrowths, the Progressive Review and The Nation.1*
10
See Roger Fletcher, "Cobden as Educator: The Free-Trade Internationalism of Eduard
Bernstein," in The American Historical Review 83 (1983), pp. 561-578; "Bernstein in
Britain: Revisionism and Foreign Affairs," in The International History Review 1 (1979),
pp. 349-375; and "British Radicalism and German Revisionism: The Case of Eduard
Bernstein," in The International History Review 4 (1982), pp. 339-370.
11
Bernstein, My Years of Exile, pp. 230-249.
12
See Peter Beilharz, Labour's Utopias (London: Routledge, 1992).
13
Later, Bernstein personally revised and prefaced the German edition of Wallas' Human
Nature in Politics. See Peter Clarke, Liberals and Social Democrats (Cambridge: Cambridge
UP, 1978), p. 152.
14
David Blaazer, The Popular Front and the Progressive Tradition: Socialists, Liberals, and the
Quest for Unity, 1884-1939 (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1992), p. 58.
The "Revisionist Controversy" 69
It was the combination of Bernstein's tight progressive network of social
acquaintances, his regular visits to left-liberal societies like the national
liberal club, and his long discussions with a variety of "social reformers"
that facilitated the reawakening of the old liberal ideals of his youth.15 The
evolutionary language of ethical perfectability and rational self-control of
late-Victorian liberalism became the much-cherished standard for his
own cultural and social values. He began to speak favorably of the
"urbane tone of British literature" with its air of cultural superiority, its
dry humor, and its Humean fondness for the proper "refinement of
tastes."16 At the same time, Bernstein appreciated that the English
language had remained "far more colloquial than German," allowing for
a "directness and natural power of expression the want of which is often
felt in German."17 Identifying with Britain's long political tradition of free
expression and public agitation, Bernstein admired the diversity of
opinions expressed in British periodicals and journals.
Most of all, however, he noted the social achievements made possible
by the English workers' practical, utilitarian point of view.18 He spoke in
glowing terms of the good relationship between British labor leaders and
representatives of the liberal bourgeoisie, arguing that "such a marriage of
convenience" had contributed to the success of English piecemeal
reformism.19 For Bernstein, the evolving British model proved the
possibility of mutually agreeable pacts between capital and labor, inspir-
ing him to communicate his observations to his German party comrades.
Nonetheless, interpretations of Bernstein's Wende as a wholesale
"product of his British exile," push too far.20 Rather than "turning him
into a British liberal," Bernstein's twelve years of British exile helped him
to perceive the possible theoretical compatibility of a left-liberalism and
(Marxist) socialist conceptions, and thereby prompted the start of his
lifelong quest for the realization of an evolutionary socialism- in Germany.
Even years after his arrival in London, he confided to Engels that his
greatest wish remained an eventual return to his home country, for
"working abroad" ultimately remained for him "an aimless enterprise."21
Indeed, not everything British turned out to be pleasant for Bernstein.
Soon after his arrival in England, he found his articles attacked by Henry
Hyndman and Ernest Belfort Bax of the dogmatic Social Democratic
Federation (SDF). Both "Marxists" had previously provoked a number
15
Bernstein, My Years of Exile, pp. 253-254.
16
Ibid., p. 204.
17
Ibid., p. 269.
18
Ibid., pp. 276-278.
19
See, for example, Eduard Bernstein, "Briefe aus England," in NZ 9 (1890/91), p. 25.
20
See, for example, Luxemburg, Reform and Revolution; and Hirsch, Der "Fabier" Eduard
Bernstein.
21
Bernstein cited in EB, p. 64.
70 Preparation
of nasty clashes with the founders of scientific socialism themselves. Bax,
who eventually emerged as the first outspoken critic of Bernstein's
"revisionist" views, was an eccentric personality even by British stan-
dards. An outspoken atheist and wild-eyed republican, he had adopted
the French revolutionary hero Marat as his romantic patron saint in his
declared mission of bringing "real socialism" to England. Taking delight
in controversial debates that frequently ended in shouting matches, and
never embarrassed about contradicting his previous arguments, Bax
enjoyed antagonizing his "radical" company. For example, he deliberate-
ly touched off a lengthy discussion in left circles on the question of the
status of women in British society. Arguing that in England "men actually
constitute the downtrodden sex," Bax objected fiercely to the pro-
feminist legislative proposals of his leftist friends.22 No surprise, then, that
his social romanticism clashed with Bernstein's empiricist progressivism,
often culminating in Bax's acerbic attacks on the German exile's "dried-
up" and "soulless" socialism.
As the members of Britain's "official Marxist party" continued their
verbal broadsides against the new exile, both Engels and Kautsky
encouraged Bernstein to strike back. Seemingly rattled by events, and
severely overworked, Bernstein suffered a nervous breakdown that inter-
rupted his daily routine for months. Increasingly aware that the vulgar-
Marxist slogans of the SDF resembled those of the SPD, his anger at such
"misrepresentations of Marxist theory" gave way to a general uneasiness
about some Marxist principles. Slowly, he began to retreat behind a stone
wall of skepticism. More and more, Bernstein's letters and articles came to
reflect his displeasure with "certain formulas of dogmatic Marxists."23
Engels quickly discovered his protege's growing liberal sympathies,
intimating to Kautsky that Bernstein seemed to have lost his fine political
instincts and was becoming increasingly "academic" in his approach.24 In
a letter to Bebel, the "General" complained that Ede sometimes displayed
"the manner of a small shopkeeper . . . At times, I think the old Aaron
[Bernstein's liberal uncle] is standing in front of me." 25 Still, despite his
students' lingering "pessimism," Engels continued to insist that there was
no need to worry about Bernstein's apparent seduction by liberal and
Fabian ideas. On several occasions, Engels reassured his German com-
rades that the situation was definitely "manageable."26
22
Bernstein, My Years of Exile.
23
Bernstein to Kautsky Qune 26, 1891), cited in Steinberg, "Herausbildungdes Revisionis-
mus von Eduard Bernstein," in Horst Heimann and Thomas Meyer, eds. Bernstein und
der demokratische Sozialismus (Berlin, Bonn: Dietz, 1978), p. 44.
24
Engels to Kautsky (November 3, 1893), MEW 39, p. 161.
25
Engels to Bebel (October 12, 1893), Bebel BWE, p. 718.
26
Bernstein to Kautsky, (November 9, 1898), Adler A. See also, PS, p. 7.
The "Revisionist Controversy" 71
In fact, all of Bernstein's major studies written during this period
found Engels' lavish praise and full approval.27 Even in 1894, when
Engels privately called Bernstein's critical review of Marx's posthum-
ously published volume III of Capital "highly confused," he never
attacked his pupil in public. Bernstein remained a regular at Engels'
private Sunday night social gatherings which allowed him to engage in
a series of political debates with Engels' many progressive guests. It
was a time when Bernstein could rub shoulders with a whole range of
thinkers along the political spectrum, from democratic republicans like
Eugen Oswald to Marx's shady son-in-law Edward Aveling, and
Charles Kingsley, the English "Father of Christian Socialism." These
conversations, occurring under Engels' watchful eye, proved to be
immensely important for developing Bernstein's increasingly critical
socialist theory.28
Engels' unwavering confidence in his Berliner friend remained firm to
the last; this was reflected by his will, in which he appointed Bernstein and
Bebel as joint executors of his literary estate. On August 27, 1895,
seventeen days after Engels' secular funeral, Bernstein, accompanied by
Marx's daughter Eleanor and other close friends of the extended "fam-
ily," committed his ashes to the ocean waves offshore of Eastbourne.29
Engels' death left the German labor movement without a single authori-
tative voice in theoretical matters - a dire predicament accurately
captured by SPD party secretary Ignaz Auer: "The Old Man is irreplace-
able in questions of scriptural interpretation. With all due respect for the
younger Church Fathers, the rich experience and authority of Engels is
absent.. . Accordingly, we'll have to do without a 'Source of Truth' for a
while, which may turn out to be a quite unpleasant experience."30 Auer's
fears were borne out within only three years.
38
Protokoll iiber die Verhandlungen des Parteitages der Sozialdemokratischen Partei Deutsch-
lands3 abgehalten zu Frankfurt vom 21-27 Oktober 1894 (Berlin, 1894), p. 152.
39
A recent structuralist argument for the emergence of Bernstein's revisionism has been
advanced by Hyrkkanen, Sozialistische Kolonialpolitik, pp. 190-195. However, as pointed
out by Woodruff D. Smith's review of Hyrkkanen's study (1988), limiting Bernstein's
theory to purely "objective social forces" misses the impact of particular ideas and
thinkers on Bernstein's thought (American Historical Review 93 A, p. 1,071).
40
For a comprehensive "influence analysis" of Bernstein's political thought, see Gustaf-
sson, Marxismus und Revisionismus.
41
ES, p. 20.
42
Schelz-Brandenburg, EduardBernstein undKarlKautsky,p. 292; and Gilcher-Holtey, Das
Mandat des Intellektuellen, p p . 1 2 0 - 1 2 1 .
43
Bernstein to Bebel (October 20, 1898) in MS, p. 325.
The "Revisionist Controversy" 75
Taught/' he saw that he could no longer accept certain Marxist prin-
ciples:
I told myself secretly that this could not go on. It is idle to attempt to reconcile the
irreconcilable. The vital thing is to be clear as to where Marx is still right and where
he is not. If we jettison the latter, we serve Marx's memory better than when (as I
did and as many still do) we stretch his theory until it will prove anything. Because
then it proves nothing.44
Between 1890 and 1891 3 Bernstein reviewed a number of new studies on
political economy for Neue Zeit, including Gerhard von Schulze-Gaver-
nitz's On Social Peace, and Julius Wolfs Socialism and the Capitalist
Economic Order. Both books focused on the likely course of future
economic development and severely criticized the Marxist "theory of
breakdown" - the conception that inherent contradictions at the econ-
omic base would inevitably lead to ever-widening economic crises
culminating in a general collapse of capitalist society. Although his review
skillfully employed Marx's method to modify Wolf and von Gavernitz's
analysis, Bernstein secretly came to agree with the general drift of their
arguments.45
A year later, Bernstein turned his attention to the writings of the
neo-Kantian socialist philosopher F. A. Lange, the radical-liberal hero of
his ex-employer Hochberg. Impressed with the logic of its Kantian ethics
and pleasantly surprised by its author's familiarity with J. S. Mill and the
British liberal tradition, Bernstein approved of Lange's important 1865
study, The Labor Question. Calling it a "progressive program of action
which has removed Lassalle's ambiguities,"46 Bernstein's overall favor-
able analysis of Lange's social theory resulted in a lengthy three-part
article in Neue Zeit, entitled "In Honor of Friedrich Albert Lange."47
Lauding the Duisburg scholar for both his theoretical sophistication and
his role as mediator between progressive parts of the bourgeoisie and the
proletariat, Bernstein was unaware that he would soon share Lange's
desire to link liberalism and socialism.48 He also came to adopt Lange's
critical stance toward G. W. F. Hegel's philosophy of "dialectical
44
Ibid. For a translation of this essay, see H. Kendall Rogers, "Eduard Bernstein Speaks to
the Fabians: A Turning-Point in Social Democratic Thought?," in International Review of
Social History 28 (1983), pp. 320-338.
45
ES, p. 21.
46
Eduard Bernstein, "Zur Wurdigung Friedrich Albert Langes," in NZ 10.2 (1892), p.
108.
47
Ibid., pp. 68-78, 101-109, 132-141. Bernstein's renewed interest in Lange was sparked
in early 1892, while reading Lange's major works in the British Museum. He also wrote a
review of O. A. Ellisen's Lange biography, Friedrich Albert Lange. Bine Lebensbeschreibung
(Leipzig, 1891).
48
I n t h e wake of the 1866 Prussian victory over Austria, t h e frustrated L a n g e left G e r m a n
labor politics a n d accepted a chair in philosophy at Zurich University.
76 Preparation
pitfalls," expressing for the first time in public his Lange-influenced
methodological doubts about Marxist doctrine. In particular, Bernstein
began to share Lange's conviction that Marxism could not lay a priori
claims to absolute "truths," since, as a science, it was inherently open to
future refutations by the new findings of scientific enquiries.49 Finally, the
1894 posthumous publication of the disappointing volume III of Marx's
Capital also seemed to support Lange's earlier warning that actual social
development never proceeded with the "same precision and symmetry as
it does in speculative construction."50 The negative reactions to volume
III of Capital by outstanding political economists from both within and
without social democracy enhanced Bernstein's own suspicion that Marx,
in typically Hegelian "dialectical fashion," had engaged in a "conceptual
stretching" of his main categories in order to correct obvious theoretical
problems in his labor theory of value.
And there was yet another important indication of existing holes in
Marx's theory. The cumulative effects of the end of the long economic
stagnation in Germany and the implementation of the government's
social policies showed positive effects on the living standard of the
working class.51 Moreover, between 1882 and 1895 alone, the German
industrial working class had grown by almost two million. Much faster
than its European neighbors, the German Empire had become an
industrialized country, soon surpassing the coal and steel production of its
closest rivals, France and Britain.52 The rapid economic development in
Germany seemed to bolster what Bernstein had observed in England on a
daily basis: industrialization breeds political and economic reformism,
which, in turn, strengthens the expansion of democratic rights and
weakens old, class-based privileges. Relating the path of industrializing
countries to a general "evolutionary progress," Bernstein felt that the
revolutionary road of 1789 and 1848 had ceased to be a realistic option.
The strong anti-insurrectionary language of his 1895 afterword to Louis
Heretier's History of the 1848 French Revolution^3 and his 1897 review
article on Scipio Sighele's Crowd Psychology and Mass Crime, show that he
began to doubt the applicability of early nineteenth-century revolutionary
principles tofin-de-sieclesocial conditions.
The repeated warnings of his late friend and mentor, Karl Hochberg,
49
Eduard Bernstein, "Zum zehnjahrigen Bestand der Neuen Zeit," in NZ 11.1 (1892/93),
p. 10.
50
PS, p. 31.
51
Georg Fiilberth, "Zur Genese des Revisionismus in der deutschen Sozialdemokratie vor
1914," in Das Argument 13.1-2 (March 1971), p. 3.
52
EB, p. 46.
53
For both Bo Gustafsson (1972, p. 90) and Thomas Meyer (1977, p. 137), Bernstein's
1895 afterword to Heretier's study represents the "decisive break with Marxism."
The "Revisionist Controversy" 77
that "capitalist society may turn out to be much more adaptable than you
think," which, in 1882, Bernstein had simply shrugged off as "regrettable
bourgeois hesitancy," had come back to haunt him.54 In the end,
Bernstein abandoned his belief in the eventual "collapse" of capitalism,
the core principle of revolutionary attentisme which he had held since
Bebel's memorable 1872 Berlin speech. Instead, he began to suspect that
Marx's and Engels' "scientific socialism" was, in fact, a sophisticated
form of dogmatism which assailed the scientific integrity of socialism.
"[T]he party's responsibilities increase with its power, and so does the
need to be completely clear about where one stands. For this reason, a
close examination of our [Marxist] theory is more vital today than ever
before."55
However, Bernstein's theoretical qualms blinded him to the practical
consequences that might ensue from such a thorough "revision" of
Marxist theory. He recognized only later that, "In the midst of my
theoretical struggle, I allowed myself to be carried away and burden my
party with more than it could handle. This was undoubtedly a significant
political mistake."56 Indeed, over the decades of its existence, the party
leadership - exemplified by August Bebel - had fought hard to reap the
benefits of an ideologically unified labor movement. Empirical evidence
contrary to Marxist expectations would punch holes in its economic
determinism and thus weaken the powerful eschatological expectations of
the masses, who had been encouraged to place an almost religious faith in
the beneficial workings of Marx's "objective, historical laws."57
With his characteristic intellectual honesty that bordered on political
naivete, Bernstein displayed the heart of a dedicated theorist who was
ready to blame the party's Marxist rhetoric for the existing theory-practice
gap, and not its socialist reformism. Ignaz Auer, who did not mind the
beneficial political effects of a quasi-theological "Marxist faith," could
only marvel at Bernstein's "strategical blunder" at calling the party's
bluff: "Do you really think that a party, resting onfiftyyears of literature
and forty years of organization, can reverse its theory at the snap of your
fingers? What you demand, my dear Ede, one does neither openly admit
nor formally vote on; one simply does it."58 Undeterred, Bernstein put his
spotless reputation on the line and, only two years after Engels' death,
took the first steps toward "revising Marxism."
Throughout this early revisionist period, he was engaged in a precarious
54
ES, pp. 23-24.
55
Bernstein to Bebel (October 20, 1898) in MS, p. 327.
56
ES, p. 37.
57
Kautsky to Bernstein (February 26, 1898), Kautsky Archive, IISH, C181.
58
Ignaz Auer cited in Bernstein, Ignaz Auer•, p. 63.
78 Preparation
balancing act, desperately seeking to avoid the dangers of both endanger-
ing party unity and losing his theoretical influence. Thus, with the threat
of expulsion permanently hanging over him, Bernstein cautiously reassur-
ed Kautsky that he was neither fighting "the basic principles of historical
materialism, nor the doctrine of class struggle, nor the character of social
democracy as the party of the proletariat."59 Similarly, he declared that he
had no intention of revising the practical portion of the party program.
Rather, his goal was theoretical revision: the effort "to create unity of theory
and reality, of formulation and action."60 Differing fundamentally from
Kautsky's defensive conception of the theorist as guardian of the doctrinal
purity of theory, Bernstein formulated a Kant-influenced "critique of
socialist reason" 61 which profoundly questioned the main theoretical
assumptions and predictions of Engels' "scientific socialism."
Yet he did not set out to modify Marxist theory simply in order to fit the
atheoretical reformism of the party Praktiker. For Bernstein, political
theory was neither an edifying afterthought nor a justification for instru-
mentalist political practice. Rather, he considered the organic link
between theory and practice as one in which theory preceded practice, not
the other way around.62 Insisting that the party's revolutionary language
was deliberately designed to "fudge categories,"63 Bernstein castigated
Bebel's and Kautsky's "supramarxist cant." 64 In his opinion, Kautsky
stifled the all-important process of open "social scientific inquiry" by
consecrating a vulgarized Marxism of metaphysical categories devoid of
any empirical validity. Bernstein frequently shored up his own arguments
by skillfully combining his harsh critique of the "existing gaps and
contradictions in Marxist theory" with timely invocations of carefully
selected passages from Engels' later writings.65
In particular, he loved to cite Engels' "final testament" - his 1895
preface to Marx's The Class Struggles in France - without mentioning that
Liebknecht had trimmed it in such a fashion that Engels was made to
appear "a peaceful worshipper of legality at any price." 66 It is difficult to
come to a final judgment on why Bernstein chose to disregard the
remaining revolutionary core underlying his mentor's mantle of tactical
moderation. Did he need the aura of Marxism to be taken seriously as a
59
Bernstein to Kautsky (October 27, 1898), AdlerA.
60
Bernstein to Bebel (October 20, 1898) in MS, p. 324.
61
Bernstein to Kautsky (November 9, 1898), AdlerA.
62
Eduard Bernstein, "Ein Vorwort zur Programmrevision," in SM 8 (1904), p. 24.
63
Bernstein to Bebel (October 20, 1898) in MS, p. 324.
64
Eduard Bernstein, "Vom deutschen Arbeiter einst und jetzt" SM 10 (1904), p. 175.
65
PS, p. 28.
66
Engels to Karl Kautsky, in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Selected Correspondence
(Moscow: Progress Publishers, n. d.), p. 461.
The "Revisionist Controversy" 79
theorist? Was he truly convinced that Engels had moved closer to the
kind of evolutionary socialism he had gradually come to espouse himself?
Henry Tudor notes that one important reason for his misreading of
Engels was Bernstein's reconceptualization of the relationship between
means and ends.67 For Engels, switching political tactics was but a sober
act of calculation designed to find the most effective mode of action for
the SPD. There were no ethical principles involved in calculating the
revolutionary coming of socialism along "strict mathematical laws":
"Setting the moral question aside, as a revolutionary I welcome any
means - both the most violent one and the seemingly most restrained -
that will lead to the end . . . In my opinion, you [Gerson Trier] are
mistaken to turn a purely tactical question into one involving prin-
ciples."68 Bernstein, on the other hand, had begun to reject revolutionary
violence as a means of social change in complex, modern societies,
seeking to escape the amoral, instrumentalist means-end calculations of
the political realist. Sympathetic to Kant's celebrated Enlightenment
notion of the "moral politician," he refused to separate means and ends
for purely tactical advantage.
Emphasizing what he called the "evolutionary side of Marx and
Engels," Bernstein claimed that the adoption of his critical stance would
liberate the party from its dualism and actually lead to a "further
development and elaboration of Marxist doctrine."69 Making Marxist
theory fair game to critical assessments, he validated new forms of socialist
eclecticism which were not only legitimate but, as he saw it, even
preferable. After all, for Bernstein, evolutionism and philosophical eclec-
ticism were part of the socialist heritage. To justify his claim, he again
cited his late mentor Friedrich Engels, who had reminded his comrades
that, "[W]e German socialists are proud to descend from not only Saint-
Simon, Fourier, and Owen, but also from Kant, Fichte, and Hegel."70
Believing that he was working out a coherent view consistent with
"evolutionary" Marxist principles, Bernstein rarely entertained the
thought that he might have irretrievably broken with Marxist doctrine.71
Ultimately, Bernstein formulated three concrete revisionist claims,
published in Neue Zeit and Vorwdrts between 1896 and 1899, in both his
famous series of articles, entitled "Problems of Socialism," and in
67
Tudor, "Introduction," in MS, p. 35.
68
Engels to Gerson Trier (December 18, 1889), MEW37, p. 327.
69
PS, p. 28.
70
Friedrich Engels, Socialism: Utopian and Scientific (Beijing: Foreign Language Press,
1975), pp. 7-8.
71
For example, during the 1903 Dresden Party Conference he admitted to his "heretical
views" regarding "certain aspects of Marx's thought" (Protokoll 1903 Dresden, pp.
391-396).
80 Preparation
subsequent responses to socialist critics like the Russian emigres George
Plekhanov and Alexander Helphand ("Parvus"), editor of Sdchsische
Arbeiter-Zeitung.12 First, Bernstein directed the brunt of his argument
against the widespread Marxist rhetoric of Bebel's great "Kladderadatsch"
- the inevitable and sudden collapse of bourgeois society due to the
fundamental contradictions in the capitalist mode of production.73 While
he explicitly allowed for the possibility of future "political catastrophes"
like large-scale wars or sustained civil unrest, Bernstein rejected the Erfurt
Program's economic determinism inherent in the idea of terminal
capitalist crises. While there might well be limited crises, empirical
evidence suggested that "we shall no longer be dealing with the old kind of
trade crisis" and, therefore, "[we] will have to throw overboard all
speculations that such a crisis will bring about the great social up-
heaval."74 Suggesting that capitalism was getting better at containing its
own contradictions, Bernstein pointed to the stabilizing role of cartels,
trusts, modern communication, and the international expansion of the
credit system as the main reasons for the unexpected flexibility of
late-nineteenth-century capitalism.
Second, and counterfactually, he argued that, even if Marx was right in
his assertion that economic crises were to become ever more cata-
strophic, and that the SPD would gain power under conditions of a
capitalist breakdown, the party was not prepared to govern without the
bourgeoisie.75 "Social democracy should neither expect nor desire the
imminent collapse of the existing economic system . . . What social
democracy should be doing, and doing for a long time to come, is
organize the working class politically, train it for democracy, and fight for
any and all reforms in the state which are designed to raise the working
class and make the state more democratic."76 Like Engels in his later
work, Bernstein focused on the central importance of what might be
called the "transition problem" in socialist theory.77 But contrary to
Engels, Bernstein turned against the dominant Marxist view that, once
72
The most important of these essays are translated in MS.
73
Bernstein to Kautsky, (October 10, 1898), Adler A.
74
Bernstein, "The Struggle of Social Democracy and Revolution," in MS, p. 166. For an
excellent account of the history of the "breakdown theory" within German social
democracy, see Rudolf Walther, ". . . aber nach der Siindflut kommen wir und nur wir":
"Zusammenbruchstheorie", Marxismus und politisches Defizit in der SPD, 1890-1914
(Frankfurt/Main: Ullstein, 1981); and F. R. Hansen, The Breakdown of Capitalism: A
History of the Idea in Western Marxism, 1883-1983 (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul,
1985).
75
Bernstein, "The Conquest of Political Power," in MS, p. 306; and Bernstein, "Critical
Interlude," in ibid., p. 220. See also, PS, pp. 45, 206.
76
Eduard Bernstein, "The Struggle of Social Democracy and the Social Revolution: 2. The
Theory of Collapse and Colonial Policy," in MS, p. 169.
77
Bernstein to Kautsky (June 29, 1896), Kautsky Archive, IISH, DV375.
The "Revisionist Controversy" 81
5
the economic conditions had sufficiently "matured/ the transition to a
"new society" was, in essence, a political problem that would be solved
by a single act of seizure of political power by the proletariat.78 Rather
than arguing for the wholesale liquidation of the existing capitalist
system, Bernstein opted for "evolution": its gradual democratization via
the extension of political rights. In fact, he believed that "[N]owadays
social democracy can do more as an opposition party than it could if it
suddenly gained control through some catastrophe."79 In his opinion, it
was foolish to tell the working class simply to wait for the "right
moment" in the development of the mode of production and then, in one
blow, seize political power and immediately build the "new socialist
society." Rather, the desired transformation of capitalist society into
socialism would prove to be a painfully slow, evolutionary process, to be
guided by ethical ideals.
No doubt, Bernstein resurrected the old liberal-reformist thesis of
"society growing into socialism," an idea popular with non-Marxist social
democrats in the 1860s, but harshly condemned by Engels as "the old
image of the unencumbered 'evolution' of the existing mess into a socialist
society."80 Here, Bernstein obviously disagreed with his late mentor:
The steady expansion of the sphere of social obligations (i.e. the obligations of the
individual towards society, his corresponding rights, and the obligations of society
towards the individual), the extension of the right of society, as organized in the
nation or the state, to regulate economic life; the growth of democratic self-
government in municipality, district, and province, and the extended responsibili-
ties of these bodies - for me all these things mean development toward socialism,
or, if you will, piecemeal realization of socialism.81
While continuing to reject the "simplistic belief in the creative power of
revolutionary force," Bernstein equally sharply refused to accede to the
political passivity and opportunism of accepting a regime that denied its
subjects basic political rights. As the first necessary "precondition" of
socialism, he called for a "radical break" from the authoritarian political
order of the German Empire - a demand he reiterated throughout the
Wilhelmine Era.82
78
See also Pracht, Parlamentarismus und deutsche Sozialdemokratie 1867-1914, p. 240.
79
Ibid., p . 2 2 1 .
80
Engels to Kautsky (July 29, 1891) MEW38, p. 125.
81
Bernstein, "The Struggle of Social Democracy and the Social Revolution: 2. The Theory
of Collapse and Colonial Policy," in MS, p. 168.
82
See, for example, Eduard Bernstein, "Der Stil des Reformismus," in SM 15 (1909), p.
1,225; and Die deutsche Revolution, vol. I (Berlin, 1921), p. 8. For an analysis of
Bernstein's arguments in favor of a thorough democratization of the German Empire as a
premise for a socialist foreign policy, see Hyrkkanen, Sozialistische Kolonialpolitik, pp.
301-334.
82 Preparation
Third, as the result of quantitative research done in connection with the
hotly disputed "Agrarian Question" at the 1894 and 1895 party conferen-
ces, Bernstein threw out Marx's so-called "immiseration thesis." He
denied the existence of a gigantic social simplification process that would
lead to the disappearance of both the middle classes and the peasantry,
leaving the working class more and more impoverished in an ever-
widening process of capital concentration, cartelization, and monopoliz-
ation. Using statistical data drawn from the 1895 Prussian Census,
Bernstein argued that his findings did not support a "polarization" of
society into a small class of capitalists and the proletarian masses.
Contrary to Marxist assumptions, he maintained that the social spectrum
in Prussia had expanded during the 1880s, thus clearly contradicting
Marx's predictions about the "disappearing" middle classes.83 Under the
modern conditions of late-nineteenth-century capitalism, the middle
class was changing in composition and actually growing in complexity. This
insight was especially important, since it served Bernstein as both a
practical criterion for his piecemeal reformism and an empirical base from
which to attack "scientific socialism."
In a famous statement which he later qualified, Bernstein spoke of the
revolutionary "final goal" as bearing no meaning for him, while the daily
struggle of the "movement" was "everything."84 Eager to draw a thick
line through all "imagined final goals," Bernstein asserted that there was
"more socialism in a good factory act than in the nationalization of a whole
group of factories."85 In elevating radical liberal demands to the "far-
reaching general principle of society, the fulfillment of which will be
socialism," Bernstein sought to synthesize socialist and liberal demands:
"For Social Democracy, the defence of civil liberty has always taken
precedence over the fulfillment of any economic postulate. The aim of all
socialist measures, even those that outwardly appear to be coercive
measures, is the development and protection of the free personality."86
"What makes us socialists," Bernstein wrote to the Austrian labor leader
Victor Adler, "is neither a hypothetical future state nor the prospect of the
great general expropriation, but our sense of justice . .. [T]he striving for
equality and justice is . . . the lasting element in our movement which
survives all changes in doctrine."87
83
Eduard Bernstein, "Statement to the 1898 Stuttgart Party Conference," in MS, p. 288.
84
Bernstein, "The Struggle of Social Democracy and the Social Revolution: 2. The Theory
of Collapse and Colonial Policy," in ibid., pp. 168-169.
85
Ibid., p. 168.
86
Ibid., p. 147.
87
Bernstein to Adler, (March 3, 1899), Adler BW, p. 289.
The "Revisionist Controversy" 83
At the height of the Revisionist Controversy
By 1898, Bernstein's forceful critique of "socialist reason" had, predict-
ably, managed to infuriate the Marxist leadership of the SPD. As the
dispute wore on, Bebel realized that Bernstein had left Marxist grounds
altogether, making more severe future clashes inevitable.88 Although he
commanded great respect in the SPD, Bebel's leadership in the party did
not always go unquestioned. More often than he cared to, he had to
muster his entire political repertoire of persuasion, threats, promises, and
compromises to rally the needed majority behind his decisions. His
outstanding political instincts and charismatic personality notwithstand-
ing, Bebel was in need of theoretical allies who neither encroached on his
political sphere nor caused fractious ideological debates that might
endanger the political unity and effectiveness of the SPD.89
Since the 1891 Erfurt Program, Bebel had relied on Kautsky to play this
role, but their partnership had barely been tested. The unfolding Revi-
sionist Controversy gave them a chance to prove their loyalty to each other
in a genuine crisis situation. Both men realized from the very beginning
that the "Bernstein Affair" constituted an enormous threat to the
ideological hegemony of Marxist theory - and by extension, to their own
leadership posts. In a number of private meetings in the summer of 1898,
Bebel and Kautsky managed to work out a common anti-Bernstein
strategy for the upcoming party conference in Stuttgart.
In the meantime, Bernstein, too, had found a handful of prominent
allies for his cause. Most of them were "PraktikerWixh principles" who
showed some interest in weakening Marxist ideology without jettisoning
socialist theory altogether: Eduard David, a future Interior Minister in the
Weimar Republic; Konrad Schmidt, one of the party's leading social
philosophers and political economists; the influential lawyer, Wolfgang
Heine; and the powerful Reichstag representative, Heinrich Peus. At the
same time, however, the party's extreme left wing led by Parvus and
Luxemburg vowed to use the Stuttgart Party Conference as an arena to
put an end to any form of "bourgeois revisionism," and perhaps even
force Bernstein's expulsion from the SPD.
When the conference opened in October 1898, Kautsky assumed the
role of the party's "chief ideologist," while Bebel kept a watchful eye over
"proper" speaking assignments and the course of the proceedings. At an
opportune moment, he decided to force the issue by reading aloud a
written defense statement that Bernstein - still unable to enter Germany
88
Bebel to Kautsky (September 24, 1898) BebelBWK, p. 111; Bebel to Bernstein (October
22, 1898) MS, p. 330.
89
See Gilcher-Holtey, Das Mandat des Intellektuellen, pp. 263-264.
84 Preparation
without risking arrest - had sent from his London exile. Frequently citing
his mentor Engels, Bernstein's note provided an eloquent summary of his
liberal-socialist views: "The taking of political power cannot be achieved
without political rights, and the most important tactical problem which
social democracy has to solve at the present is, it seems to me, the best way
to extend the political and industrial rights of the German working man." 9 0
Paul Kampffmeyer, a young fellow-revisionist, later wrote that Be-
rnstein's "Stuttgart Letter" showed the orthodox Marxists what they
"really were" but had not dared to admit.91 Bebel saw things differently.
Noting that he fundamentally disagreed with the content of the statement,
he left it to Kautsky to dismantle Bernstein's substantive arguments.
Kautsky's speech, seconded by Liebknecht, turned out to be a great
success with a majority of those conference delegates who soundly
rejected Bernstein's irksome "revisionism." Bernstein's few vocal de-
fenders managed to make themselves heard, but they were too weak and
disorganized to challenge Kautsky's "official" interpretation.
In the end, the conference participants stopped short of following Rosa
Luxemburg's radical call for Bernstein's expulsion. Nevertheless, the
"Bernstein Affaire" provided the twenty-seven-year-old "Red Rosa" with
an opportunity to show her considerable talents. With her sharp intellect
and fiery oratory, she awed the delegates by turning her first major
political appearance into a brilliant defense of Marxist theory from a
radical-left point of view.92 When the dust of the conference finally
settled, most delegates agreed that the debates had fallen far short of
settling the theoretical problems raised by the revisionists. But they also
agreed that revisionism was no cause for serious concern, since, as the
Austrian labor leader Victor Adler put it so aptly, " [T]here is not a single
point ofpolitical practice>, of concrete party tactics, on which Bebel and Auer,
Kautsky and Bernstein would not agree."93
Yet, the theoretical problems raised during the party conference would
soon afford the atheoretical Praktikerin the SPD the excellent opportunity
of questioning the utility of theory altogether. For the time being,
however, Kautsky and Bernstein continued their sharp ideological battles
with seemingly inexhaustible energy in the pages of Vorwdrts and Neue
Zeit. Finally, Kautsky and Adler succeeded in pressuring Bernstein to
write a longer synopsis of his revisionist views. Hastily, Bernstein obliged,
and, in less than twelve weeks, finished his famous "Revisionist Mani-
90
Bernstein, "Statement" in MS, p. 291.
91
Paul Kampffmeyer, "Historisches und Theoretisches zur Sozialdemokratie Revisionis-
mus Bewegung," in SM 8 (1902), p. 354.
92
See Rosa Luxemburg cited in MS, pp. 249-269, 276-305.
93
Adler, "The Party Conference at Stuttgart," in ibid., pp. 316, 319.
The "Revisionist Controversy" 85
festo," entitled The Preconditions of Socialism. Published in early 1899 and
eventually translated into more than thirty languages, the book contained
the main arguments of Bernstein's early revisionist period. While regard-
ing it as a crucial milestone in his career, Bernstein openly acknowledged
the book's rather narrow conceptual framework. "[The] desire to keep
within reasonable bounds a book primarily intended for workers, together
with the need to finish it within a few weeks, should explain why an
exhaustive treatment of the subject has not even been attempted."94
Contrary to the assessment of later commentators, he explicitly warned
that The Preconditions of Socialism should not be interpreted as "a
programmatic work on a large scale."95 Indeed, the full features of
Bernstein's evolutionary socialism emerged in the form of essays, mono-
graphs, and book reviews, drawn out over two decades. Representing only
the beginnings of his theoretical quest, The Preconditions of Socialism
awaited further detailed explorations of the relationship between social-
ism, social science, liberalism, and ethics.
94
PS, p. 28.
95
ES, p. 30.
Part 2
Vision
The meaning of socialism
89
90 Vision
their more scientific and technological orientation, which championed
working-class interests with reference to an ultimate, comprehensive
world view based on supposedly "objective" causal laws.4 Thus, they
frequently found themselves caught in a tension-filled conjunction pitting
science against politics, theory against practice, determinism against
voluntarism, empiricism against speculative metaphysics, and necessity
against freedom. Marx's own relationship to the empirical method and the
"scientific enterprise" in general, had always been ambiguous: on one
hand, he criticized the "uncritical use of statistics in catalogue-like
eruditions,"5 while on the other, he had praised his own theories as
"essential laws,"6 their truths depending on empirical data, since "facts
furnish the test of theories."7
Bernstein never made a secret of the fact that he preferred the
"scientific" tracts of the mature Marx over the passionate essays of the
youthful Hegelian philosopher of praxis.8 Yet, he was also quick to note
that those theoretical tensions even appeared in Capital, which, despite its
impressive theoretical achievement, ultimately amounted to a "piece of
propaganda . . . that remained unfinished, because the conflict between
propaganda and science made the task more and more difficult for
Marx." 9
Such direct attacks on his mentors' writings, however, were usually
sandwiched between long, reassuring paragraphs signalling Bernstein's
intense loyalty to a "Marxism understood as a general program, a
principle, or an idea of justice."10 Obviously, Bernstein disagreed with
fashionable liberal claims that Marxism had no moral components at all. l!
Ultimately, he developed his revisionism from a historically anchored
perspective which allowed him to employ the detached language of
empiricism against the growing disjuncture between theoretical principles
conceived in the middle of the century and the fundamentally changed
socioeconomic conditions offin-de-siecle Germany: "[T]he standards of
Marx-Engels' theory, which were developed under entirely different
4
See Gouldner, The Two Marxisms, pp. 34-36; and Pierson, Marxist Intellectuals and the
Working-Class Mentality in Germany, pp. 4-7.
5
Karl Marx, Grundrisse (New York: International, 1973), p. 888.
6
Karl Marx, Capital vol. III. (New York: International, 1967), p. 831.
7
Marx, Grundrisse, p. 119.
8
PS, pp. 28-46.
9
Bernstein to Bebel (October 20, 1898) MS, p. 326.
10
Eduard Bernstein, "Dialektik und Entwicklung," in NZ 17 (1898/99), p. 360.
1!
Recently, R. G. Peffer has offered a particularly sophisticated defense of Marx's moral
perspective in Marxism, Morality, and Social Justice (Princeton: Princeton UP, 1990). His
study particularly contributes to the ongoing discussion on Marxist epistemology, ethics,
and ontology by showing with great clarity the way relevant philosophical positions are set
out. Peffer also provides a useful list of recent participants in the Anglo-American debate
on Marxism and morality (pp. 9-10).
The meaning of socialism 91
premisses and conditions than today's, are not only insufficient but even
misleading."12 But Bernstein's tone became noticeably more impas-
sioned when he turned against contemporary British and German
"scientific socialists" whose dogmatic interpretation of Marxist doctrine
conflicted with "empirical reality."13
For the purposes of this study, then, it is not necessary to engage in a
detailed textual exegesis outlining intricate comparisons between the
principles of revisionism and the conflicting attributes of the two different
Marxisms.14 Since Bernstein's critique emerged as a clear protest against
the Marxist orthodoxy reigning in the 1890s, we must instead focus on the
principal theoretical works that gave Marxist theory its definitive expres-
sion in the 1891 Erfurt Program. For better or worse, socialism came to be
understood in terms of Kautsky's popular Das Erfurter Programm - a book
that drew its intellectual inspiration from Engels' Anti-Duhring, Marx's
Capital, and, of course, The Communist Manifesto. Kautsky, Bernstein,
and all other prominent Marxist theorists assumed that the teleological
and scientistic language of the Manifesto formed the core of "orthodox"
Marxism. As the "Baron" untiringly reminded his revisionist opponents,
"true socialism" was a science embodied in the founders' systematic
writings. There, they had explained their discovery of the "natural laws of
capitalist production," which unfolded with "iron necessity" toward the
"inevitable socialist goal."15 The hallmark of modern, scientific socialism
was the disclosure of the objective-teleological, historical process finding
its necessary, subjective expression in the revolutionary consciousness of
the proletariat.
But for the "revisionist" Bernstein, the meaning of socialism was no
longer accurately captured in Kautsky's "orthodox" Marxism. Since its
theoretical vision needed correction, Bernstein set out to reconceptualize
socialism along revisionist lines which involved, first and foremost, the
rejection of Kautsky's determinism and the complete deletion of the
Erfurt Program's theoretical claims.16 While the critique of the party
program represented the first step toward a new understanding of
12
Bernstein, "Drei Antworten auf ein Inquisitorium," in Zur Geschichte und Theorie des
Sozialismus: Teil III: Sozialistische Controversen, 4th ed. (Berlin: Dummler, 1904), p. 14.
13
Bernstein to Kautsky (February 16, 1898), Adler A.
14
Recently, Gary Steenson has offered useful criteria for a broader conception of Marxism:
see After Marx, Before Lenin, pp. 261-267.
15
CI, pp. 10,761-763.
16
Bernstein, "An meine socialistischen Kritiker," pp. 5-7; "Vom Wesen des Socialismus,"
in Zur Geschichte und Theorie des Sozialismus, pp. 39-56; "Ein Vorwort zur Programmrevi-
sion," SM 10 (1904), pp. 19-26; and "Der Revisionismus in der Sozialdemokratie," in
Helmut Hirsch, ed. Ein revisionistisches Sozialismusbild, 2nd ed. (Berlin-Bonn: Dietz,
1976), p. 132. Indeed, Bernstein's own blueprint for the 1921 Gorlitz Program includes
virtually no references to his philosophy of science.
92 Vision
socialism, the full consequences of Bernstein's disagreement with the
"orthodox" Marxists became apparent only with the publication of Rosa
Luxemburg's Reform or Revolution? Distributed in 1899, this brilliant
pamphlet offered an admirably succinct exposition of "scientific social-
ism," packing the theoretical core of Engels' and Kautsky's arguments
into a few precisely formulated pages. Consequently, our brief reconsider-
ation offin-de-siecle"Marxist orthodoxy," which Bernstein fought tooth
and claw for more than two decades, will begin with an exposition of the
crucial features of Engels' comprehensive Weltanschauung, it will then
move on to an analysis of Kautsky's commentary on the Erfurt Program;
and will conclude with a review of Luxemburg's famous essay.
Long-standing arguments to the contrary notwithstanding, Marx and
Engels agreed on all fundamental matters of socialist theory.17 Marx
wrote a favorable forward to his friend's Socialism: Utopian and Scientific,
explicitly giving his nod of approval to the use of the term "scientific
socialism" in the context of their social theory.18 Having repeatedly
discussed with Engels the main outline of Anti-Duhring, Marx even
provided his intellectual alter ego with a critical compendium of Duhr-
ing's views on the history of political economy.19 The cooperative
character of Marx and Engels' theoretical development has been amply
documented in their voluminous correspondence and by the testimonies
of contemporary observers. The quality of such evidence should be
sufficient finally to lay to rest groundless notions that Marx did not share
his collaborator's views, particularly his philosophy of science.20
In general terms, Engels' account of "scientific socialism" amounted to
a sophisticated apology for Hegel's method of dialectics with the help of
novel insights drawn from modern natural science. According to the
"General," a closer observation of simple cause-effect relationships
furnished irrefutable proof for nature's evolution according to dialectical
laws, thus belying the mechanical method of "metaphysical" materialists
who considered their objects of investigation "fixed, rigid, given once for
17
For the "dichotomist" argument, see, for example, Lichtheim, Marxism: A Historical and
Critical Study; Shlomo Avineri, The Social and Political Thought of Karl Marx (Cambridge:
Cambridge UP, 1968); Robert C. Tucker, Philosophy and Myth in Karl Marx, 2nd ed.
(Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1972); Norman Levine, The Tragic Deception: Marx contra
Engels (Oxford: Clio, 1975); Frederick Bender, ed. The Betrayal of Marx (New York:
Harper and Row, 1976); and Terrell Carver, Marx and Engels: The Intellectual Relationship
(Bloomington: Indiana UP, 1983).
18
Karl Marx, "Foreword to the French Edition," in Engels, Socialism: Utopian and
Scientific, pp. 1-4.
19
MECW25, p. xiii.
20
This view is shared by Helena Sheehan, Marxism and the Philosophy of Science (Atlantic
Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1993), pp. 48-64; and J. D. Hunley, The Life and
Thought of Friedrich Engels: A Reinterpretation (New Haven: Yale UP, 1991).
The meaning of socialism 93
21
all." At the same time, Marx and Engels realized that Hegel's "funda-
mental laws of dialectical reasoning" needed to be separated from their
idealist content and given a "real basis" in a materialist conception of
history., based on developing contradictions in the economic mode of
production.22 In other words, Engels understood the study of the laws of
dialectics as "the science of the general laws of motion and development
of nature, human society, and thought," thus marrying a Hegelian
philosophical framework to the natural sciences. To a greater degree than
Marx, Engels was quite keen on Darwin's groundbreaking 1859 Origin of
Species, which - although non-predictive, non-determinist, and non-
teleological - served him as the prime example for such a "new materialist
science," linking the dialectical development of class society with evol-
utionary biology.23
Seeking to bridge the gap between rationalism and empiricism, as well
as humanism and naturalism, Engels' Anti-Duhring represented the
ambitious attempt to create an integral world view combining politics,
science, and philosophy as an interdependent social "totality." This
allowed Engels simultaneously to defend the sociohistorical character of
all scientific knowledge and to promulgate "scientific socialism" as the
only possible theoretical expression of the proletarian movement. In fact,
the fusing of natural laws with social development within the framework
of a socialist Weltanschauung even strengthened the legitimacy of a
"dialectical science" by making theory "real" in the concrete, historical
struggles of a proletariat that, in potentia, already bore the final socialist
goal.
Popularizing the insights of Marx's dense Capital, Engels' Anti-Duhring
dedicated an entire section to the exposition of political economy as an
essentially historical science whose modes of production and relations of
material exchange develop in dialectical fashion with the regularity of laws
of nature. Equipped with the dialectical key capable of breaking the secret
code of capitalist social relations, Engels could claim to offer a genuinely
"scientific" critique of classical political economy. In his opinion, the
Marxist method far surpassed previous "eclectic" forms of socialism by
providing the modern proletariat with a powerful analytical tool. "Bour-
geois" notions of "eternal truth," "original sin," and "divine justice"
21
Engels, Anti-Duhring, in MECW 25, p. 22.
22
Ibid., p p . 2 1 , 2 5 .
23
Terrell Carver, Friedrich Engels: His Life and Thought (London: Macmillan, 1989), pp.
238, 245- 246.1 am indebted to Terrell Carver for pointing out to me that Marx was not
rushing to dedicate Capital to Darwin; he merely sent Darwin a copy of the second
German edition of Capital at the request of his son-in-law Edward Aveling. For an
excellent article on this issue, see Terence Ball, "Marx and Darwin: A Reconsideration,"
in Reappraising Political Theory (Oxford: Oxford UP, 1995), pp. 229-249.
94 Vision
could finally be debunked as ideological distortions hiding repressive
social relations.24 By revealing existing contradictions at the economic base
of society - the disjunctive between the dynamic forces of production and
stagnant relations of production - socialist theory assumed in praxis the
status of an objective social movement struggling against oppressive
conditions, independent of the individual's ethical ideals: "Modern
socialism is nothing but a reflex, in thought, of this [class] conflict in fact;
its ideal reflection in the minds, first, of the class directly suffering under it,
the working class."25 Thus, Engels' socialism provided the scientific
explanation of the proletariat's historical role as the social force that was
bound to complete the transition from capitalism to socialism. Indeed,
only scientific socialism harbored the appropriate conceptual means for
the working class to comprehend its historical condition and consciously
transform society with the "final goal" of establishing rational control of
material production.26
Kautsky's 1891 commentary on the Erfurt Program, entitled Das
Erfurter Programm, was hailed by Engels as an "exemplary piece of work"
which elaborated in less philosophical language on the founders' convic-
tion that "scientific socialism" was indeed possible as a cognitive activity
carried on within the framework of a comprehensive world view. Seeking
to simplify Engels' arguments even further, Kautsky provided the German
labor movement with a theory of social totality that emphasized the
alleged connection between Darwinian natural science and Marxist
sociohistorical arguments. Pushing Engels' "nomological" approach to
new extremes, Kautsky viewed human history as a natural process taking
place according to definite laws. Designed to create the propagandistic
effect of an "exact" science revealing the "immanent laws of the capitalist
mode of production," a "theory of collapse" featured prominently in
Kautsky's scheme.
We consider the collapse of our current society inevitable, since we know that the
economic development, with natural necessity [Naturnotwendigkeit], will create
conditions which force the exploited to fight against private property; we also
know that the number and the strength of the exploited is increasing while the
number and strength of the reactionary exploiters decreases;finally,we know that
it [the economic development] will lead to unbearable hardship for the masses,
which will force the people to choose between passive immiseration or the active
overthrow of the existing property relations.27
Over and over again, Kautsky praised the unique ability of "scientific
24
Engels, Anti-Duhring, in MECW 25, p. 255.
25
Ibid.
26
Ibid., pp. 254, 270.
27
Kautsky, Das Erfurter Programm, p. 102. See also ibid. pp. 106, 253.
The meaning of socialism 95
socialists" to identify socialism's "natural and necessary goal" - the
seizure of political power in the state and the transformation of the
capitalist mode of production.28 Neither relying on the "beautiful dream"
of socialist Utopians like Owen, Fourier, and Weitling, nor on the ethical
voluntarism of neo-Kantian moral philosophers, Kautsky characterized
Marx's method as "penetrating deeply into the social tendencies of its
time," ultimately revealing the "coming of a fundamentally different
social order" as the "inevitable consequence of an objectively necessary
process."29
The correspondence of objective sociohistorical conditions and the
subjective moment was to be accomplished in the self-constitution of
social democracy, the political party of the revolutionary proletariat.
Capitalist economic development fostered strong solidaristic bonds
among members of the working class, leading to the formation of a
proletarian "ecdesia miliians" - the concrete political expression of
"maturing" inner contradictions of capitalism.30 Thus, the ultimate
victory of the working class and the realization of its "final goal" were
based upon an objective-teleological, historical process.31
Rosa Luxemburg affirmed Kautsky's nomological interpretation and
further strengthened the notion of the scientific character of Marxist
socialism by identifying three "objectively necessary" consequences of
capitalist development. Firstly, there was the growing disorganization and
"anarchy" of the capitalist economy, a tendency "inevitably leading to its
ruin." Secondly, the progressive socialization of the process of production
created "the germ of the future social order." Thirdly, there was the
increased organization and consciousness of the proletarian class, which
constituted "the active factor in the coming revolution."32 Thus, the
socialist revolution was the inevitable consequence of both "the growing
contradictions of capitalist economy," and "the comprehension by the
working class of the unavoidability of the suppression of these contradic-
tions through a social transformation."33
Rejecting with Engels the "metaphysical viewpoint" of the undialecti-
cal bourgeois scientist, Luxemburg argued that Marx's accurate predic-
tion of the "inevitability of capitalism's collapse" was only possible
because he had looked at the "hieroglyphics of capitalist economy" from
a partisan perspective: "And it is precisely because he took the socialist
viewpoint as a point of departure for his analysis of bourgeois society
28
Ibid., pp. 125-126, 190, 222.
29
Ibid., pp. 130-133, 137, 253.
30
Ibid., pp. 185, 207.
31
Ibid., pp. 219, 230-231.
32
Luxemburg, Reform Or Revolution?, p. 11.
33
Ibid., pp. 31,35.
96 Vision
that he was in the position to give a scientific base to the socialist
movement."34 Hence, socialism was not only possible as a proletarian
science, but it was indeed the sole social theory which corresponded
directly to objective, empirical developments in society.
Like Engels and Kautsky, Luxemburg fully recognized the importance
of sharply separating the "scientific character" of Marx's socialism from
the voluntarism of an "ethical socialism" based upon "the millenarian
dreams of humanity." 35 Relying on the method of historical materialism,
she explained the developmental course of socialist theory from these
"insufficient seven-league boots of the childhood of the proletariat" to
Marx's "correct elaboration of the principles of scientific socialism." 36
Defining the meaning of socialism in exclusively Marxist terms, Luxem-
burg's pamphlet convincingly illustrates the hegemony of orthodox
Marxism infin-de-sieclesocialist theory: " [T]here could be no socialism -
at least in Germany - outside of Marxist socialism, and there could be no
socialist class struggle outside of social democracy. From then on [the
emergence of Marx's theory], socialism and Marxism, the proletarian
struggle for emancipation, and social democracy were identical." 37
Having asserted the complete identity of Marxism and socialism,
Luxemburg was in a position to point to the philosophical core of
Bernstein's "revisionist misreading of Marx" in his famous statement,
"The final goal, whatever it may be, is nothing to me, the movement is
everything." By denying the central significance of the "final goal" in
socialist theory, Bernstein had abandoned Marxist teleology - the theor-
etical basis of "scientific socialism, because, for a proletarian party
standing on the firm grounds of the daily struggle," there existed "no
more practical question than that of the final goal." 38 Kautsky concurred
wholeheartedly: "What could be more depressing than such gross
misinterpretations [of Marx] from a man who himself defended historical
materialism for more than two decades?" 39 Consequently, both Kautsky
and Luxemburg excoriated Bernstein for his "flawed" philosophy of
science, which had abandoned Hegelian dialectics in favor of Kant's
philosophical dualism: "We have here, in brief, the explanation of the
socialist program by means of'pure reason.' We have here, to use simpler
language, an idealist explanation of socialism. The objective necessity of
34
Ibid., p. 40.
35
Ibid., p. 35.
36
Ibid., p. 60.
37
Ibid.
38
Luxemburg cited in Protokoll iXber die Verhandlungen des Parteitages der Sozialdemokratis-
chen Partei Deutschlands, abgehalten zu Stuttgart vom 3-8. Oktober 1898 (Berlin, 1898), p.
99.
39
Kautsky, Bernstein und das Sozialdemokratische Programm, p. 47.
The meaning of socialism 97
socialism, the explanation of socialism as the result of the material
development of society, falls to the ground." 40
Luxemburg's and Kautsky's assessment was shared by the Russian
"Father of Marxism,"George Plekhanov, who in a brief, but intense
philosophical dispute with Bernstein and Konrad Schmidt in Neue Zeit>
had targeted their underlying neo-Kantian philosophy: "The bourgeoisie
hopes to find in Kant's philosophy the 'opium' by which it seeks to lull the
recalcitrant proletariat to sleep. Neo-Kantianism has become rather
fashionable among members of the ruling class because it furnishes the
mental weapon with which to fight for their existence." 41 Unlike most of
his German comrades, Plekhanov's background in Hegelian philosophy
was impeccable; he skillfully fought against what he considered the
repulsive "revisionist infiltration" of Humean and Kantian skepticism
into the socialist movement:
Surely this is a complete break with revolutionary tactics and communism . . . I
almost took sickfromthese [Bernstein's] articles; what is most vexing of all is that
Bernstein is partly right: for instance, it is impossible to count upon the realization
of the socialist ideal in the near future. But truth may be employed for different
ends; Bernstein uses it the sooner to filch the Philistine nightcap. Or is the
Philistine to be the Normalmensch of the future? With this question, a shudder runs
through me and I want to say with Gogol: How tedious is this world, sirs!42
In a letter to Kautsky, Plekhanov went even further: "If Bernstein is right
in his critical endeavors, one may ask what remains of the philosophical
and socialist ideas of our teachers? . . . And in truth, one would have to
reply: not very much!" 43
Indeed, Plekhanov's and Luxemburg's critique struck at the heart of
the matter. Scrambling to bridge the tension between skeptical empiri-
cism and Kantian ethical idealism, Bernstein had fundamentally
changed the meaning of socialism. True, by turning against the
nomological rhetoric of his comrades, he made room for human volition,
morality, and historical contingency. At the same time, however, his
ethical socialism shattered the unity and explanatory power of the
Marxist-Hegelian system. What began as a spark of Kantian doubt
directed against the "dogmatism" of Marxist orthodoxy ended in total
theoretical "subversion."
40
Luxemburg, Reform Or Revolution?, p. 13.
41
George Plekhanov, "Konrad Schmidt gegen Karl Marx und Friedrich Engels," in NZ
16.1 (1898/99), p. 145. See also "Bernstein und der Materialismus," in NZ 16.2
(1897/98), pp. 546-555, and "Materialismus oder Kantianismus," in NZ 17.1
(1898/99), pp. 589-596, 626-632.
42
P l e k h a n o v cited i n S a m u e l H . B a r o n , Plekhanov: The Father of Russian Marxism
(Stanford: Stanford UP, 1963), pp. 172-173.
43
Plekhanov cited in ibid., p. 176.
98 Vision
Socialism and science
Bernstein never fully acknowledged the enormous ramifications of his
revisionist initiative. Though he openly argued for the importance of
"modernizing Marxism" - the critical revision of Marxist theory from a
fin-de-siecle perpective - he also claimed to have remained "within the
bounds of the founders' system." But was it possible simply to "correct"
Kautsky's and Bebel's orthodoxy by letting the "evolutionary Marx"
carry the point against the "dogmatic Marx?"44 What exactly did
Bernstein mean when he spoke of his efforts "to separate the vital parts of
[Marx's] theory from its outdated accessories"?45 Struggling tofinda firm
criterion that would help him identify these "vital parts/' Bernstein began
to vacillate. At times., he asserted that he was "merely" engaged in a
project of "cutting a few branches from an otherwise healthy [Marxist]
tree."46 On other occasions, he admitted to be involved in generating
"self-criticism of... not just a few superficialities but of very substantial
components of Marxism's theoretical structure."47 Once Bernstein had
assumed the posture of the Cartesian rationalist who attacks all dogmatic
claims, his doubts led to more doubts. And, most importantly, why
exactly was the "new" theoretical foundation for an "evolutionary
socialism" more in step with modern social conditions?
Bernstein embarked on his critical enterprise by first exploring the
"new" meaning of "socialism" and "science" itself. All goals and
activities of a "scientifically based" socialist movement, he claimed, could
only be determined in accordance with "knowledge capable of objective
proof, that is, knowledge which refers to, and conforms with, nothing but
empirical experience and logic."48 Therefore, he insisted on the distinc-
tion between "pure" and "applied" scientific theories. Whereas pure
theory was "constant" in its universally valid, "cognitive principles which
are derived from the sum total of the relevant data," applied science was
based on the application of these universalist principles to particular
phenomena or cases, thus yielding provisional, or "variable" knowl-
edge.49 This analytic distinction spilled over into Bernstein's separation of
natural and social sciences: the former sought to uncover purely causal
relationships between natural objects, and the latter dealt in addition with
"products of artifice, based on plan, intention, and acts of will."50
44
Eduard Bernstein, "Bildung, Wissenschaft und Partei" in SM 11 (1907), p. 711; "Der
Sozialismus als sozialwissenschaftliche Entwicklungslehre," in Der Sozialismus Einst und
Jetzt (Berlin: Dietz, 1923), pp. 5-10; and Was ist der Marxismus: Antwort aufeine Hetze
(Berlin: Vorwarts, 1924), pp. 1-8.
45
Bernstein, "Idealismus, Kampftheorie, und Wissenschaft," in SM 5 (1901), p. 606.
46
Bernstein, "Dialektik und Entwicklung," p. 333.
47
PS, pp. 11,46.
48
Ibid., p . 9 .
49
Ibid.
The meaning of socialism 99
Situated in the complex realm of human intersubjectivity, social science
yielded less precise results in its search for universal patterns. Conse-
quently, Bernstein defended the primacy of natural science and the
validity of its categories for social scientific analysis, for in their attempt to
formulate general social theories, social scientists were dependent on
empirically verifiable "facts." They could not rely on purely deductive
operations from first principles in the manner of mathematics or ge-
ometry, but were forced to employ a "positivist-inductive method"
characterized by falsifiability and contingency. 51 Based on these prelimi-
nary distinctions, Bernstein proceeded to provide a "systematic extrac-
tion of the pure science of Marxist socialism from its applied part." 52 This
procedure would allow him to specify which parts of Marx's system could
be revised or removed without any damage to its "pure" theoretical
foundation:
Everything that is unconditional in the Marxist characterization of bourgeois
society and its course of development, that is, everything whose validity is free
from national and local peculiarities, would accordingly belong to the domain of
pure science. But everything which refers to facts and hypotheses which are
conditional on a particular time or place, that is, particular forms of development,
would belong to applied science.53
The problem with this formulation was two-fold: firstly, Bernstein
ultimately criticized not only the "applied parts" of Marxist theory, but
attacked its "pure" parts (e.g., historical materialism and the theory of
surplus value) as well, thus defeating the very purpose of this troubling
distinction. Secondly, his analytic investigations betrayed the "uncritical"
(in a Marxist sense) character of his enterprise - his closeness to the
undialectical, "bourgeois" epistemology of the British empiricists. Ortho-
dox Marxists immediately claimed that Bernstein had foresaken Marx's
emphasis on dynamism and sociohistorical totality - a unifying theory of
modern society and its development - in favor of what Marx had once
derided as Comte's "shit-positivism." Although he was aware of such
criticism, Bernstein nonetheless defended his project as "critical," under-
stood as providing the necessary bulwark against the rigid dogmatism of
Marxist orthodoxy. 54 By implication, however, this meant that his
revisionist position no longer corresponded to the Marxist-Hegelian
philosophical universe - a politically dangerous conclusion for anybody
belonging to a "Marxist" party.
50
Eduard Bernstein, "Naturprinzipien und Wirtschaftsfragen," in SM 4 (1900), p. 320.
51
Bernstein, "Idealismus, Kampftheorie, und Wissenschaft," p. 602; Bernstein to Kautsky
(December 23, 1897) Kautsky Archive, IISH, DV427.
52
PS, p. 10.
53
Ibid., p . 1 1 .
54
Ibid.
100 Vision
Pointing out that the "predictions" of the Erfurt Program were clearly
built on the particularity of space and time - backed up by "variable"
hypotheses and facts - Bernstein found the program's theoretical asser-
tions to be "unscientific" in their claim to present "inevitable" laws of
social development. Ossified into party dogma, Kautsky's "pseudo-
scientific deductions" damaged what Bernstein considered the "critical"
heritage of the socialist (and liberal!) enterprise - its persistent subversion
of dogma of any kind. Any socialism based on "science" had to remain
open to new theoretical propositions and empirical developments derived
from actual political and social practice.55 For Bernstein, Kautsky's
dogmatism was but the latest manifestation of a trend that could be traced
back to the influence Hegel's speculative philosophy had exerted on the
young Marx.
Indeed, Bernstein charged Marx and Engels with having built their
social theory on Hegel's fatal "metaphysical blunder" of "subordinating]
any claim to scientific status to a preconceived tendency."56 By implica-
tion, Bernstein accused the founders of remaining the prisoners of a
metaphysical doctrine, which, in deductive fashion, constructed social
developments from a priori formulas: "[Marxist theory] aims at being a
scientific investigation and also proving a thesis laid down long before its
conception, that is based on a formula in which the result to which the
exposition ought to lead is laid down beforehand."57 Spinning out the
"logical somersaults of Hegelianism," Marx and Engels had overlooked
the "concrete facts" of specific economic developments which would
have provided the necessary empirical correction to "the self-deceptions
they entertained about the actual course of [current] events."58 Thereby,
Bernstein not only questioned the scientific integrity of Marxism, but he
also parted with Engels' notion of a social "totality," expressed in the
compatibility of a socialist Weltanschauung and "proletarian" (i.e., "dia-
lectical") scientific research. In a letter to the Italian socialist Antonio
Labriola, Bernstein openly admitted that he no longer considered
Marxism such an all-encompassing "system," but a particular "way of
seeing things" which, first and foremost, needed to "maintain its
character as a free, open science."59
Undoubtedly, Engels would have attacked his pupil's philosophy of
science as a sophisticated brand of "bourgeois metaphysics," overly
indulgent and undialectically reifying rigid distinctions between science
55
Bernstein, "Ein Vorwort zur Programmrevision," in SM 8 (1904), pp. 9-11.
56
PS, pp. 46, 35.
57
Ibid., p . 1 9 8 .
58
Ibid., pp. 46, 36.
59
Bernstein, "Idealismus, Kampftheorie, und Wissenschaft," p. 606.
The meaning of socialism 101
and world view. Ironically, Bernstein, too, polemicized against the
"pitfalls of metaphysics;" but unlike his mentor, he employed the term in
a Kantian sense, referring to the "speculative dogmatism" of a metaphys-
ics of totality. Indeed, Bernstein's critique of "socialist reason" meticu-
lously separated knowledge from speculation, science from world view,
fact from value, and necessity from freedom. Yet, affirming the validity of
an empiricist epistemology for his own intellectual enterprise, Bernstein
robbed socialism of its presumed immanence, underscoring that its
declared "final goal cannot be constructed a priori in abstract fashion,"
but had to be formed "from within the practical struggles of the
movement itself."60
103
Bernstein, "Wissenschaft, Werturteil und Partei," p. 1,419.
104
Ibid., pp. 1,411, 1,415.
105
Ibid., p. 1,411; "Bildung, Wissenschaft und Partei," p. 707; and "Idealismus, Kam-
pftheorie und Wissenschaft," p. 606.
The meaning of socialism 109
106
justice." Thus, by elevating morality and law/right (Recht) to more than
mere historical categories reflecting primary processes at their economic
base, Bernstein was implicitly attacking what R. G. Peffer calls "moral
historicism" - the view that "whatever social structures have evolved or
whatever social structures will evolve are, ipso facto, morally justified."107
In fact, Bernstein's philosophy of science blended seamlessly into his
critique of Marx's economic determinism: "No one will deny that the
most important part in the foundation of Marxism, the basic law that, so
to speak, penetrates the whole system is . . . the materialist conception of
history. In principle, Marxism stands or falls with this theory; and insofar
as it suffers modification, the relationship of the other parts to each other
will be affected."108
At the height of the revisionist controversy, Bernstein left no doubt that
he considered Marx's method faulty and in need of repair: "The formula
of historical materialism, as passed down by Marx and Engels, is not really
up to task and needs supplementation."109 In particular, he objected to its
"obvious lack of subtlety," which was responsible for the "one-sided
emphasis on economic elements" that had misled the founders into
"making a variety of social prognoses which, in their old form, are simply
out of touch with our time."110 Here, Bernstein's critique approaches that
of Karl Popper, who has pointed out that, "it is clear enough that the
theory [of historical materialism] depends largely on the possibility of
correct historical prophecy."111
But as was the case in his philosophy of science, Bernstein denied that
his reinterpretation of historical materialism amounted to a wholesale
refutation of Marxism. Arguing that his theoretical initiative was consist-
ent with a "consequential development of Marx's scientific work,"112 he
once again refused to draw the full consequences of his revisionist
critique. For example, he never owned up to the fact that his comprehen-
sive proposals aimed at the "modernization of Marxist socialism" were
bound to lead to an outright abandonment of crucial elements in Marxist
106
Bernstein, "Der Kernpunkt des Streites," p. 782.
107
Peffer, Marxismy Morality, and Social Justice, p. 212.
108
PS, p. 12.
109
Eduard Bernstein, "Der Marx-Cult und das Recht der Revision," in SM 9 (1903), p.
258.
110
Ibid.
111
Karl Popper, The Open Society and Its Enemies, vol. II (Princeton: Princeton UP, 1971),
p. 205. Several authors have elaborated on the close relationship between Bernstein's
philosophy of science and Karl Popper's "Critical Rationalism." See, for example,
Frithjof Spreer, "Bernstein, Max Weber und das Verhaltnis von Wissenschaft und
Politik in der Gegenwartsdiskussion," in Heiman and Meyer, Bernstein und der
Demokratische Sozialismus, pp. 274-290; and Robert Steigerwald, Biirgerliche Philosophie
und Revisionismus im imperialistischen Deutschland (Berlin: Akademie, 1980).
112
Bernstein, "An meine sozialistischen Kritiker," p. 4.
110 Vision
theory. There are some obvious reasons for why he hesitated to acknowl-
edge his decisive break with Marxism. For one, he had convinced himself
of the legitimacy of his selective, "evolutionary" reading of Marxist
socialism - a perspective that corresponded more closely to the changing
conditions of modernity. Secondly, having dedicated his life entirely to the
political cause of the labor movement, he realized that afinalbreak with its
dominant ideology would leave him without a viable political base.
Finally, there was also the frequently neglected personal factor: his strong
feelings of "filial piety" toward Marx and Engels, which made it extremely
difficult for him to push his arguments to their logical conclusion.113
Repeatedly asserting that he was simply working out a revision of Marxist
theory already begun years ago by Friedrich Engels, Bernstein produced
what he considered to be "convincing evidence" to support his case.
Had not Engels redefined his understanding of "revolution" by
insisting that the "so-called socialist society" was not afixedconcept, but
a constantly changing and evolving social phenomenon, making "us
[socialists] all evolutionists"?114 Moreover, in his harsh condemnation of
the SPD's "Youngsters" faction, had Engels not explicitly stated that
dogmatic applications of the 1848 Communist Manifesto principles to any
historical context were rooted in an overly simplistic understanding of
Marx's method?115 Likewise, didn't the "General" temper the revol-
utionary fervor of the French Labor Party by warning them against
"moving too close to the antiquated principles of Blanquism"?116 Indeed
sounding thoroughly "revisionist," Engels had contested a rigid concep-
tion of Marxism: " [T]he whole Marxist conception is not a doctrine, but a
method. There are no instant dogmas, only points of reference for further
investigation and the method for this investigation."117
Moreover, Bernstein didn't overlook the fact that Engels was ultimately
forced to admit that overly "deterministic" interpretations of Marx's
method offered by the "Youngsters" were actually made possible by the
existing unstable compromise in Marxist theory between the alleged
primacy of causal determination and the efficacy of human volition. Given
the explosive growth of the German labor movement in the years after
Marx's death, Engels realized the importance of working out a more
precise exposition of the historical-materialist method. At the very core of
113
Bernstein to Kautsky (November 9, 1898), Adler A. Here, Bernstein openly admitted
that his "filial piety" toward Marx and Engels often prevented him from giving free rein
to his criticism. Hence, his complaint: "How is such an [outspoken] critique possible
without injury to the elders?"
114
Engels, "Interview with Le Figaro" (May 8, 1893), MEW22, p. 542.
115
Engels to Schmidt (August 5, 1890), MEW 37, pp. 436-437.
116
Engels to Paul Lafargue (June 27, 1893), MEW 39, p. 89.
117
Engels to Sombart (March 11, 1895), MEW39, p. 428.
The meaning of socialism 111
his efforts lurked the vexing philosophical problem of human "free will."
In his influential 1886 study, Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical
German Philosophy, Engels implicitly raised this pivotal question: if the
ultimate causes of historical events were neither found in philosophical
ideology (Hegel) nor in the undialectical "old materialism" of Duhring
and Buchner, then how could one conceptualize the primary historical
structures in terms of which humans have motives and act?
Responding in "dialectical" fashion, Engels had argued that it was
impossible to explain what happened in history by appealing exclusively to
personal motives which often seemed to account for the actions of
individuals: "The many individual wills active in history produce, for the
most part, results other than those intended . . . Their motives in relation
to the total result are therefore likely [to be] only of secondary signifi-
cance."118 While this explanation successfully set limits to sheer voluntar-
ism and the idealist credo of an "autonomy of human consciousness," the
exact relationship between ultimate causation operating at the economic
base and human will remained unresolved.
In order to defend his model of historical materialism more effectively
against both idealist and materialist critics, Engels was forced to enhance
the causal significance of the ideological superstructure. However, this
meant that he had to "revise" Marx's powerful model of monocausal
determination in a more idealist direction, acknowledging the presence of
"substantial holes" in his old conception of history: "[W]e [Marx and
Engels] have neglected the formal side in favor of the content: the mode in
which mental representations arise."119 Suddenly, in Engels' famous
letters of the 1890s on historical materialism, Marx's method became a far
more complicated model of explaining social change than previously
depicted: "According to the materialist conception of history, the produc-
tion and reproduction of real life are the determining factors only in the
last instance . . . If somebody twists it into meaning that the economic
factor is the only determining factor, then the previous sentence is turned
into a meaningless, abstract, and absurd phrase."120 Despite Engels'
reaffirmation of "economic necessity," it is clear that he enhanced the
significance of the ideological and legal superstructure.
Yet, Engels probably wouldn't have accepted the charge that he was
"revising" historical materialism; in his mind, he was simply defining his
and Marx's earlier views with "more clarity and greater precision."121
1 x8
Friedrich Engels, Ludwig Feuerbach and the Outcome of Classical German Philosophy (New
York: International, 1935), p. 62.
119
Engels to Mehring (July 14, 1893), MEW39, p. 96.
120
Engels to Joseph Bloch (September 21, 1890), MEW37, p. 463.
121
Ibid., p. 463. This is also the thesis of S. D. Bailey, "The Revision of Marxism," in The
Review of Politics 16 (1954), p. 452.
112 Vision
Still, it is not difficult to see that it took Bernstein only a small change in
emphasis to move from Engels' model of "infinite groups of contradicting
forces" producing a "definite historical result that wasn't willed by
anybody,"122 to his revisionist proposition asserting that it was "neither
possible nor necessary to give socialism a purely materialistic basis."123 In
other words, Bernstein readmitted political and ideological forces along-
side purely economic factors, thereby turning Engels' determining "last
instance" into the pluralism of parallel acting forces, all potentially
capable of causing significant social effects.124 In Bernstein's new concep-
tion, economic causes created the structural presuppositions for the
acceptance of certain ideas, but how they rose to prominence and what
particular forms they took depended on a vast number of interacting
tendencies:
Whoever employs the materialist conception of history nowadays is duty bound to
use it in its most developed and not in its original form. This means that, in
addition to the development and the influence of the forces of production and the
relations of production, he is duty bound to take full account of the legal and moral
concepts, the historical and religious traditions of every epoch, geographical and
other natural influences, which include the nature of man himself and his
intellectual dispositions.125
Although economic "laws" were the theoretical and methodological
preconditions for a consequent materialist-dialectical explanation of
sociohistorical processes, they coexisted with consciousness and human
will. The latter were powerful causal factors in their own right, which, at
certain historical junctures, could even eclipse the force of economic
tendencies.126 Again, Bernstein's model resembles Karl Popper's critical
rationalism worked out decades later. Like Popper, Bernstein objected to
the historicist mistake of confusing unconditional prophesies with condi-
tional scientific predictions. Popper put it well: " . . . historicists overlook
the dependence of trends on initial conditions. They operate with trends as if
they were unconditional, like laws. Their confusion of laws with trends
makes them believe in trends which are unconditional (and therefore
general); or, as we may say, in 'absolute trends'"121
Likewise, Bernstein insisted that the study of capitalist development
required a historically specific assessment of existing relations between
subjective factors and economic forces, based on exact data drawn from
22
Engels to Bloch (September 2 1 , 1890), MEW 37, p. 464.
23
PS, p. 200.
24
See Grebing, Der Revisionismus: Von Bernstein bis zum "Prager Friihling", p. 41.
25
PS, p. 16.
26
Ibid., p. 14.
27
Karl Popper, The Poverty of Historicism (New York: Harper and Row, 1957), p. 128.
The meaning of socialism 113
empirical research. Following his own statistical model situated within a
general evolutionist framework, Bernstein suggested that modern capital-
ist society was "far richer than earlier societies in ideologies which are not
determined by economics or by nature working as an economic force."128
As the growing productive capabilities of society fulfilled immediate
economic needs to an ever greater extent, ethical factors widened their
"scope for independent activity/' thus dramatically gaining in causal
significance.129
Given the proletariat's material position in the capitalist order, Bern-
stein could not ignore the importance of economic factors. Yet, he
consciously resisted the materialist reductionism of orthodox Marxists.
Instead, he sought to connect interests and ideas as the "opposing, but
interdependent poles" of a wide array of historical driving forces.130
Offering a subtle interpretation of "emancipatory interests," Bernstein
claimed that the interests guiding the working class' political actions were
always mediated by individual and collective forms of "consciousness,"
thus representing "thought reflexes, conclusions erected on mental
syntheses of mediated facts and therefore inevitably colored by ideol-
ogy."131 The very existence of mentally mediated "common interests" as
the spring of political action implied that, at times, the proletariat
sacrificed its "selfish, material interests" directed at economic advantage
to a "moral ideal" like solidarity, or other "feeling [s] of common
humanity and the recognition of social interdependence."132 Thus,
Bernstein concluded, "The interest which Marxist socialism presupposes
is, from the outset, furnished with a social or ethical element, and to that
extent it is not only a rationalbut also a moral interest, so that ideality in the
moral sense of the term is inherent in it.133
Here, Bernstein explicitly recognized the active role of a system of values
in relation to the scientific means-end chain. The realization of ultimate
socialist values was not simply dictated by economic necessity, but was
also a matter of active imagination, moral will, and conscious choice. In
short, superstructural elements - Lange's "regulative ideals" - proved to
be of great significance for the social democratic project of social change.
The daily struggle of the labor movement for social betterment gave rise to
128
PS, p. 19.
129
Ibid., p. 20.
130
Eduard Bernstein, Wesen und Ansichten des burgerlichen Radikalismus (Munich: Duncker
& Humblot, 1915), pp. 5-6, 32.
131
Bernstein, "The Realistic and Ideological Moments in Socialism," in MS, p. 234.
132
Eduard Bernstein, "Idee und Interesse in der Geschichte" (1924), in Bernstein A, A53;
"Was ist Sozialismus" (1918), in Hirsch, Ein revisionistisches Sozialismusbild, p. 157. See
also, Eduard Bernstein, Von der Sekte zur Partei: Die deutsche Sozialdemokratie Einst und
Jetzt (Jena: Diederichs, 1911), pp. 44-45.
133
Bernstein, "The Realistic and Ideological Moments of Socialism," in MS, p. 233.
114 Vision
An economic conception of history need not mean that only economic forces, only
economic motives, are recognized. It need only mean that economics constitute
the ever-recurring decisive form, the pivot on which the great movements in
history turn. To the words "materialist conception of history" cling all the
misunderstandings which are attached to the concept of materialism.140
From a Kautsky-Luxemburg orthodox perspective, of course, Bernstein
had entirely failed to grasp the vital connection between the weltan-
134
Bernstein, "Drei Antworten auf ein Inquisitorium," in Zur Theorie und Geschichte des
Sozialismus, pp. 10-11.
135
Bernstein, "The Realistic and Ideological Moments in Socialism," in MS, p. 240.
136
Eduard Bernstein, Die heutige Sozialdemokratie in Theorie und Praxis (Munich: Birk,
1906), pp. 6-7.
137
Eduard Bernstein, "Tugan Baranowsky als Sozialist," in Archiv fur Sozialwissenschaft
und Sozialpolitik 28 (1909), p. 786.
138
Bernstein, "Der Marx-Cultus und das Recht zur Revision," p. 257.
139
Bernstein, "Der Revisionismus in der Sozialdemokratie," in Hirsch, Ein revisionistisches
Sozialismusbild, p. 100; and PS, p . 22.
140
Ibid.
The meaning of socialism 115
sc/zaw/zc/z-philosophical and political-economic explanation of the
sociohistorical process, thus "reverting" to the fuzzy "eclecticism" of the
pre-Marxist "petit bourgeois socialist" who defined socialism from within
the confines of an "uncritical" positivism. In their opinion, Bernstein's
philosophy of science restored the autonomy of the subject at the expense
of a Hegelian subject-object identity which emphasized the historicity of
all social structures. According to Kautsky and Luxemburg, Bernstein's
empiricist bird's-eye view depersonalized and dehistoricized the social
observer, while at the same time reducing objects to petrified "facts" that
veiled the dialectical processes of historical becoming.
A few decades later, Georg Lukacs, too, would charge Bernstein with
"flattening the Marxist method," by displaying the empiricist's inability
to grasp the speculative totality of social phenomena. If "facts" were
excluded from social totality, they became "inflexible" and "dead."141 In
Bernstein's blueprint, the nature of man's relationship to the material
world was no longer accurately captured. Marx's celebrated notion of a
dynamic "ensemble of social relations" had but turned into a pathetic
"ensemble of facts."142 As his Marxist critics saw it, Bernstein had slipped
back into a static Cartesianism that accepted empirical data at face value
and allowed him to anchor socialism in the "eternal" moral values of
liberalism, while transforming historically conditioned categories into
timeless expressions of ethical "truth." 143 Luxemburg acerbically noted
that the "Father of Revisionism" had exhibited the same "false conscious-
ness" as those "ethical socialists" whose bourgeois attachment to Kant's
liberalism had blinded them to the philosophical superiority of Hegelian
dialectics. As far as "Red Rosa" was concerned, Bernstein and his
"anxious ethical comrades should drown in the moral absolutes of their
beloved Critique of Practical Reason."144
145
For an excellent overview of neo-Kantian socialism, see Timothy Keck, "The Marburg
School and Ethical Socialism," in The Social Science Journal 14.3 (1977), pp. 105-119;
Thomas Willey, Back to Kant (Detroit: Wayne State UP, 1978); Helmut Holthey, Cohen
and Natorp, 2 vols. (Basel: Schwabe & Co., 1986); and Harry van der Linden, Kantian
Ethics and Socialism (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1988).
146
See, for example, Kurt Eisner, "Kant" in Kurt Eisners Gesammelte Schriften, 2 vols.
(Berlin, 1919); Franz Staudinger (a. k. a. "Sadi Gunter"), "Bernstein und die
Wissenschaft," in NZ17.2 (1898/99), pp. 644-653, and "Kant und der Socialismus: Ein
Gedenkwort zu Kants Todestage," in SM 8 (1904), pp. 103-114; Konrad Schmidt,
"Uber die geschichtsphilosophischen Ansichten Kants," in SM 7 (1903), pp. 683-691;
Karl Vorlander, Kant und Marx: Ein Beitrag zur Philosophic des Sozialismus (Tubingen: J.
C. B. Mohr, 1926); Max Adler, Marxistische Probleme (Berlin: Dietz, 1922).
147
Eduard Bernstein, "Tugan Baranowskys Marx-Kritik," in Dokumente des Sozialismus 5
(1905), p. 421.
148
Bernstein, "Wie ist wissenschaftlicher Sozialimus moglich?," p. 64.
The meaning of socialism 117
149
of empiricism. Unlike the Marburgers, who anchored their socialism
exclusively in the categorical imperative, Lange and Bernstein rejected
any methodological foundation of ethical idealism. This was reflected in
their positivistic interpretation of Kant's "critical method/' which strictly
limited science to the establishment of regularities between empirically
observable entities. Following Lange's theory, Bernstein's brand of
"neo-Kantianism" was not the source of his empiricist skepticism, but its
consequence.150
There were indeed a number of crucial differences between Lange's
philosophy and Marburger neo-Kantianism.151 For example, Lange
denied the a priori existence of ideas, thus agnostically rejecting any
"scientific" grounding of ideal factors like will or ethics. Interpreting
Kant's categories of the understanding as constituents of the human
brain, Lange's physiologism avoided Kant's transcendental explanation
of the categories as necessary, "rational" or "logical" constructs. Indeed,
there was no "systemic" connection between Lange's philosophy and his
conception of socialism other than his ad hoc stipulation of "noble
[socialist] personalities filled with pure idealism."152
But Lange and the Marburger socialists reached common ground in
their political reformism, interpreting the rise of the labor movement
within a general Enlightenment framework that emphasized unilinear
progress. Although he lauded Capital as an "excellent piece of work,"
Lange proceeded to separate "Marx's political perspectives and predic-
tions from his theory."153 For one, he rejected the Hegelian dialectics at
the core of Marx's method as having provided the basis for "the
bottomless ocean of metaphysical errors." In addition, Lange insisted that
Marx's "dogmatic materialism" needed to be refined from the "stand-
point of the ideal."154 Based on his strict separation of the world into a
"realm of science" and a "realm of ideas," Lange claimed that such
ethical "ideals" didn't serve to extend one's knowledge but to counteract
149
PS, p. 210.
150
See also Robert A. Gorman, "Empirical Marxism," in History and Theory 20 A (1981), p.
409.
151
Van der Linden, Kantian Ethics and Socialism, pp. 294-295. See also Klaus Christian
Kohnke, Entstehung und Aufstieg des Neukantianismus: Die deutsche Philosophic zwischen
Idealismus und Positivismus (Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, 1986); and Hans Martin Sass,
"Der Standpunkt des Ideals als kritische Uberwindung materialistischer und idealistis-
cher Metaphysik" in Knoll and Schops, Friedrich Albert Lange, Leben und Werk. These
authors argue convincingly that by offering a fundamental critique of basic neo-Kantian
assumptions, Lange cannot be seen as the precursor or founder of neo-Kantianism, but
as an alternative to it (pp. 188-206, 256).
152
Vorlander cited in Van der Linden, Kantian Ethics and Socialism, p. 294.
153
F. A. Lange, Die Arbeiterfrage, 5th ed. (Winterthur: Ziegler, 1894), p. 348.
154
Lange, Geschichte des Materialismus, p. 54.
118 Vision
materialistic, deterministic assumptions, thereby making room for moral-
ity.155 By now, it should not be difficult to recognize Bernstein's own
philosophical position in Lange's epistemology and moral theory.
Soon after his death in 1875, Lange's views were fiercely attacked by his
former students, led by the well-known Hermann Cohen.156 Twenty-five
years later, the Marburger socialists battled Bernstein's philosophical
"eclecticism" with the same arguments Cohen used against Lange.
Stressing the prior role of the knowing subject in the structuring of
knowledge, Karl Vorlander vehemently rejected Bernstein's separation of
science and ethics. For the Marburgers, Bernstein had obviously been
influenced by the "misguided English empiricists and eudaemonistic
philosophers" who reduced science to a "crude empiricism" which
surrendered the systemic coherence of transcendental standards of ethical
judgment, and erroneously defined the end of morality as "the greatest
amount of material and moral well-being."157 Though Vorlander and
other social liberals agreed with Bernstein that a universalistic ethics ought
to serve as the guide for any socialist politics, they nonetheless insisted that
"scientific socialism" was indeed possible and desirable in the form of a
socialist ethic constructing and explicating the moral law. In other words,
a priori principles of reason were revealed in scientific and moral progress
in history.
Seen from the perspective of the Marburger socialists, the tension
between empiricism and idealism in Bernstein's epistemology was indeed
troubling. But this does not mean that Bernstein failed to grasp Kantian
philosophical principles.158 Though an autodidact, he had accumulated
basic philosophical knowledge through long years of private study.
Obviously, his intellectual efforts hardly made him the equivalent of
academically trained philosophers or social scientists. But neither was
Friedrich Engels - nor, for that matter, were other prominent party
leaders like Wilhelm Liebknecht, August Bebel, and Ignaz Auer. Victor
Adler, the Austrian party boss, was a medical doctor who readily admitted
to his "ignorance in matters of theory;" V. I. Lenin never finished his
academic studies, and even Karl Kautsky openly acknowledged that
philosophy had never been his "strong suit."159 With the exception of
Luxemburg and Plekhanov, German social democracy at the turn of the
155
See Kohnke, Entstehung und Aufstieg des Neukantianismus, p. 253.
156
Hermann Cohen, "Friedrich Albert Lange," in Philosophie Journal 37 (1876), p. 378.
157
Vorlander, Kant und Marx, p. 185.
158
For example, Fletcher (1984) asserts that "it is doubtful whether Bernstein ever acquired
a solid grasp of Kant" (p. 131). But as Walther (1981, p. 129), Grebing, (1977, p. 40),
and Gustafsson (1972, pp. 113-115) emphasize, Bernstein explicitly linked his critique
not to Kant but to F.A. Lange's Die Arbeiterfrage.
159
Karl Kautsky, "Ein Brief iiber Bernstein an Plechanow," in DerKampf 18 (1925), p. 2.
The meaning of socialism 119
century was characterized by the weak philosophical background of its
main theorists, and, in particular, by a remarkable ignorance regarding
Hegelian philosophy. 160
Bernstein's pivotal intellectual achievement - the innovative reconcep-
tualization of the relationship between socialism, ethics, and science that
created the theoretical precondition for reconnecting the socialist tradi-
tion with its liberal origins - required no more than the acceptance of
certain basic Kantian and Fabian philosophical assumptions, and their
logical juxtaposition with his political theses. 161 Throughout his life,
Bernstein, first and foremost, emphasized the political ramifications of his
theoretical enterprise: the strengthening of an ethical reformism, which, in
his opinion, could only be achieved by sacrificing philosophical "system-
thinking" to a less coherent but more applicable "eclecticism":
Eclecticism - selecting from different explanations and ways of dealing with
phenomena - is often only the natural reaction against the doctrinaire desire to
derive everything from one thing and to treat everything according to one and the
same method. Whenever this desire gets out of hand, eclecticism breaks through
again and again with elemental force. It is the rebellion of sober reason against the
inbuilt tendency of every doctrine to confine thought in a straitjacket.162
More than anything, it was his commitment to the liberal paradigm that
led to Luxemburg's and Kautsky's charges against Bernstein's "petty-
bourgeois opportunism." In their opinion, he had clearly "betrayed"
Marxism by resurrecting precisely the kind of pre-Marxian socialist
"eclecticism" against which Kautsky had fought so bitterly his entire
life.163
No doubt, Bernstein had crossed the fundamental divide separating
Marxian socialism and "bourgeois reformism." He no longer regarded
the dichotomy between "liberalism" and "socialism" as useful. Consist-
ent with his philosophical position, Bernstein continued publicly to
announce his sympathies for the liberal tradition with its emphasis on
freedom, individual autonomy, and human rights.
160
Steinberg, Sozialismus und Deutsche Sozialdemokratie, pp. 56-60.
161
See also, Sheehan, Marxism and the Philosophy of Science, p. 75.
162
PS, p. 18.
163
Karl Kautsky, "Karl Kautsky," in Meiner, Die Volkswirtschaftslehre, pp. 19-21.
Evolutionary socialism as "organized
liberalism55: rethinking economics^ state,
and democracy
120
Evolutionary socialism as "organized liberalism" 121
approach, then, by extension, he also had to reject the main arguments of
Marx's analysis of capitalist social relations in Capital. If one does this,
then the crucial Marxist distinction between liberalism and socialism has
indeed lost its theoretical justification.
The obvious starting point from which to unravel Bernstein's revisionist
arguments is the examination of the relationship among the following
critical ideas: value, surplus value, and abstract labor. Like the classical
British political economists Adam Smith and David Ricardo, Marx
considered the value of commodities to be determined by the human labor
incorporated in them. Although Marx accepted some subjective, utilitar-
ian assessments - like those expressed in the idea that a product's "use
value" (utility) partially determined its exchange value - he still insisted
that the determining factor of a commodity's value was the human labor
"encapsulated" in the finished product.4 The exchange value of a
commodity, understood as the "center of gravity for the commodity's
oscillating market price," ultimately determined the price of the product.
Thus, Marx's value theory clearly made the case for an "objectivist"
determination of prices based on production costs; "subjective" or
"psychological" factors were a necessary, but not sufficient, condition for
price determinations.5
But Marx's economic theory differed from classical political economy
in another respect. Ricardo had never asked the question which most
interested Marx: under which sociohistorical conditions does the product
of labor assume the form of a "commodity?"6 In other words, Marx set
out to investigate why - under the current capitalist mode of production -
unique, subjective human labor appeared as the "value" of exchangeable
"things" called commodities.
Therefore, Marx did not regard "value" merely as a quantitative
economic category, but also as the expression of underlying social
relations. Known as "commodity fetishism," this problem denotes the
process through which social labor is represented in the form of an
intrinsic quality of things, which, in turn, appear to be endowed with
independent, "subjective" qualities as though they were "persons,"
impacting on and interacting with "real" people.7 Hence, the phenom-
enon of "commodity fetishism" could be employed as a powerful
analytical tool to reveal the alienating character of the essentially "in-
4
Ibid., pp. 36-41.
5
See also Lothar F. Neumann, "Die Werttheorie und der Sozialismus bei Marx, Bernstein
und in der heutigen Diskussion," in Heimann and Meyer, Bernstein und der demokratische
Sozialismus, pp. 293-299.
6
C /, p. 80.
7
See Lucio Coletti, "Bernstein and the Marxism of the Second International," in From
Rousseau to Lenin (London: Monthly Review Press, 1974).
122 Vision
verted" capitalist world where "things" rule over "people." Unlike the
classical economists, Marx linked the sociohistorical aspect of value
formation to the corresponding "bourgeois" ideological expression based
upon the capitalist mode of production. Whereas Smith and Ricardo
"wrongly" equated the human process of production with "commodity
production" - a self-evident necessity imposed by nature itself- Marx's
critique of political economy (the subtitle of Capitall) identified various
modes of production as limited sociohistorical phenomena which were
always associated with particular forms of ideology and class domination.
Next, Marx analyzed the process of commodity exchange, an operation
that obviously required an abstract common denominator rendering the
"values" of two different commodities commensurable. In other words,
concrete human labor- calculated on the basis of "abstract" equivalents-
had to take on the form of "abstract human labor," otherwise they would
lose their exchangeability. This crucial abstraction allowed Marx to
explain "value" as "mere homogeneous congelations of undifferentiated
human labor" - objective, quantitative units standing in for a purely
subjective, qualitative process.8 Nonetheless, "abstract human labor"
was based on real, concrete value, created by real, concrete human labor
power. Marx insisted that, despite this necessary "abstraction," he had
staked his analytical claims on empirical grounds.
Equipped with his crucial concepts of "value" and "abstract labor,"
Marx took the final step in uncovering the "secret" of the capitalist
production process: the exploitation of the working class in the name of
"commutative justice." Put simply, his main argument went as follows:
although commodities appeared to be freely exchanged as equivalents in a
non-coercive manner, the owners of the means of production were still
able to extract "surplus value" from their workers in the form of unpaid
labor time. This "hidden exploitation," occurring within the framework
of a "fair exchange" on the "free market" was made possible because
material needs forced workers to sell, as quickly as possible, their sole
exchangeable "commodity" - their ability to perform labor for any
capitalist who would hire them for a wage. As R. G. Peffer notes, Marx
never gave a clear-cut definition or explication of his concept of exploita-
tion. While he sometimes employed the term in a morally condemnatory
fashion, there is considerable debate among the interpreters of his work as
to whether this negative moral import is a necessary characteristic of
exploitation.9
Usually, Marx simply observed that capitalists were in the position of
owning enough material goods to sustain themselves without the crucial
8
CIy p. 38.
9
Peffer, Marxism, Morality, and Social Justice, p. 137.
Evolutionary socialism as "organized liberalism" 123
labor-power-wage exchange for longer periods of time, a significant
advantage which put them in control of the labor market. Their possession
of private property allowed them to enter into a contract with workers that
purchased labor power at its value - the minimum time necessary to
"reproduce workers as workers." Paying them such a "minimum wage/'
the employers then used their "legal control" of the working place and
working conditions to compel laborers to produce more. As the crucial
political-legal instrument of class domination, the bourgeois state secured
the enforcement of the wage contract.
In this way, capital exploited labor while maintaining the appearance of
commutative justice on the basis of "equivalent exchange" according to
the bourgeois-capitalist ideology of "individual liberty." But Marx placed
the origins of workers' exploitation at the level of production, advancing
beyond the old mercantilist conceptions of early-nineteenth-century
socialists. For example, Pierre-Joseph Proudhon had supported the
notion of "profit upon alienation," thereby locating the origin of profit in
the difference between selling and buying prices. Equating exploitation
with "theft," Proudhon's arguments revealed a conflict between exploita-
tion and justice/legality. Conversely, Marx considered modern social
inequality in the form of capitalist exploitation occurring as the "logical
consequence" of the political-economic system as such, and in accord-
ance with the development of juridical-political "equality." His occa-
sional moralistic tone notwithstanding, Marx sought to explain exploita-
tion in a descriptive, "scientific" manner. In fact, he deliberately made his
theory of exploitation dependent on the "objective" relationship between
economic variables operating on the level of production in order to avoid
"unscientific" value judgments.10
Marx's economic theory thus provided a conceptual framework for
explaining exploitation in the "legitimate" scientistic language of the
nineteenth century: in spite of the existence of liberal-bourgeois institu-
tions guaranteeing formal equality, social injustice continued in the form
of coerced, unpaid labor (surplus labor) - disguised exploitation based
upon actualpov/QT differentials between classes. Hence, only the abolition
of the commodity form - the revolutionary transformation of the source of
exploitation on the level ofproduction - would lead to subsequent alteration
of the ideological-legal state apparatus and the socialist supersession of the
ideological principles of "capitalist justice."
However, as the century drew to a close, Marx's economic objectivism
explaining value as arising solely from productive labor, came under fire
from a number of social-liberal and neo-classical liberal economists who
10
C/, p. 194.
124 Vision
had fallen under the spell of rising "subjectivist" marginal utility theories
in England and Austria. Regarding the subjective preferences of con-
sumers expressed in utilitarian psychological considerations like "desire"
as the crucial element in determining the value of a commodity, marginal-
ists attacked Marx's "objectivist" labor theory of value, including his
highly complex and "faulty" conclusions regarding price formation and
falling rates of profit.
Briefly, Marx had argued that surplus value could only be extracted
from "variable capital" - labor power - and not from "constant capital"
(the means of production).11 As a result, the rate of profit (the ratio of the
total sum of the invested capital over surplus-value) should fall as
technological innovation caused the share of variable capital in the
invested capital to decrease. However, Marx and Engels could not close
their eyes to the overwhelming empirical evidence indicating that the
average rates of profit in all developed capitalist countries were roughly
equal, regardless of specific industry sectors and their concurrent dif-
ferences regarding their share of variable capital. This vexing problem
indicated a serious contradiction between Marx's fundamental theoreti-
cal assumptions and empirical reality. Despite new "solutions" offered in
subsequent volumes of Capital, this conceptual dilemma remained
unresolvable within the confines of a labor theory of value. For example,
Bernstein charged that Marx's new lack of emphasis on the significance
of value in the exchange of commodities apparent in volume 3 of Capital
had led to the formulation of a price theory which undermined the role of
labor in price formation, and thus the very raison d'etre of his economic
theory.12
The German economist Werner Sombart best expressed the growing
concerns of Marx's liberal critics by concluding that Marx's concept of
value was a purely theoretical construct which did not correspond to any
observable sociohistorical formation.13 Building on Sombart's argu-
ments, the well-respected Austrian neo-classical economist, Eugen von
Bohm-Bawerk, published a long essay which attempted to show that
neither a deductive nor an empirical proof of the labor theory of value
could be successfully sustained.14 For marginalists, Marx provided a
phenomenology of value whose indeterminate relation to price constitu-
tion was never fully acknowledged. In this spirit, Bohm-Bawerk referred
11
Ibid., pp. 199-211.
12
Eduard Bernstein, "Vorfragen einer Sozialistischen Theorie der Gewerkschaf-
tsbewegung," in SM 10 (1906), p. 843.
13
For a detailed discussion of these problems, see Howard and King, A History of Marxian
Economics, pp. 46-55.
14
Eugen von Bohm-Bawerk, "Karl Marx and the Close of his System," in Paul Sweezy, ed.
Karl Marx and the Close of his System (New York: Kelley, 1966).
Evolutionary socialism as "organized liberalism" 125
to Marx's system as a shaky "house of cards/' mired in the speculative
categories of Hegelian philosophy. 15 Conversely, marginalists chose to
remain within the limits of "price theories/' claiming that discussions
centered on the "metaphysical concept of value" yielded but "unscien-
tific" conclusions.
However, whether, as Colletti asserts, the origin of this dispute between
Marxist economic theorists and their neo-classical and revisionist critics
derived from the latters' profound misunderstanding of Marx's concept of
"abstract labor," 16 or whether it reflected legitimate disagreements over
the epistemological and empirical foundations of "value" itself, has
remained the subject of long theoretical debates that originated with
Sombart's and Bohm-Bawerk's critiques. Such controversies over the
analytic merit of the concept of "value" were carried on throughout the
twentieth century by socialist economic theorists like Paul Sweezy,17 Joan
Robinson, 18 and their more recent counterparts, Alec Nove, G. A. Cohen,
John Roemer, Jon Elster, and other representatives of "analytical
Marxism." 19
Seeking to mediate between the two opposing camps, Bernstein
questioned the usefulness of developing a new theories of value. He
argued that some arguments of both schools were pertinent to the more
important political discussion of how to challenge capitalist conditions of
economic exploitation. 20 He illustrated this eclectic approach to value
theory by means of an oft-cited allegory:
Peter and Paul stand before a shop window filled with minerals.
"These are parallel-planed hemihedral crystals/' says Peter.
"These are pyrites," says Paul.
Which of the two is right?
"Both are right," says the mineralogist. "Peter's statement refers to form, Paul's
to substance." .. . Translated into the language of political economy, the same can
be said about the long quarrel over value theory.21
Bernstein believed that Marxist and marginalist concepts of value
15
Bohm-Bawerk cited in ibid., pp. 51-52.
16
Colletti, From Rousseau to Lenin, pp. 79-81.
17
Paul Sweezy, The Theory of Capitalist Development (New York: Oxford UP, 1946).
18
Joan Robinson, An Essay on Marxian Economics (London: Macmillan, 1949).
19
See, for example, G. A. Cohen, Karl Marx's Theory of History (Princeton: Princeton UP,
1978); Alec Nove, The Economics of Feasible Socialism (London: G. Allen & Unwin, 1982);
John Roemer, A General Theory of Exploitation and Class (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP,
1982); Jon Elster, Making Sense of Marx (New York: Cambridge UP, 1985); and Ian
Steedman, ed. The Value Controversy (London: New Left Books, 1981).
20
Bernstein, "Allerhand Werttheoretisches,"pp. 558-559. For Bernstein, the search for an
absolute concept of value that would include all determining factors would prove to be a
fruitless enterprise.
21
Bernstein, "Arbeitswert oder Nutzwert," pp. 101-102.
126 Vision
addressed two different dimensions of the same problem: "Economic
value is androgynous: it contains the element of utility (use-value,
demand) and cost of production (labor power). Which of these two
aspects determines value? Surely, not one without the other."22 Thus he
argued for maintaining Marx's emphasis on human labor as the "sub-
stance" of commodities while also accepting the role of marginal utility
theory in explaining the "form," or the "magnitude" of value. Standing
on their own, however, both theories seemed to Bernstein to be fraught
with serious shortcomings. For example, he accused the marginalists of
focusing exclusively on utility, thus abstractly treating price formation as a
"mathematical operation" removed from the "real conditions" of empiri-
cal complexity, which added non-calculable factors to the capitalist's
decision to sell his commodity at a certain price.23
Along the same line of argument, Bernstein charged that Marx's theory
of value - relying on productive labor in determining a commodity's value
- also involved itself in a number of misleading abstractions and
reductions. For one, Marx incorrectly abstracted from use value, which
led to the identification of exchange value with "abstract human labor,"
and ultimately reduced various concrete forms of labor to a "metaphysical
concept" which failed to take into consideration more tangible factors like
productivity, diligence, and skill.24 This is not to say that Bernstein did not
acknowledge that any scientific analysis of complex social phenomena
required a certain degree of abstraction which was an unavoidable
operation for the specific purposes of demonstration. Echoing Sombart's
and Bohm-Bawerk's arguments, however, Bernstein claimed that Marx
had gone too far, reducing value to a "purely abstract entity" devoid of
"scientific validity."25 Though Marx had masterfully employed these
"mental constructions" for the purpose of exposing the workings of the
capitalist economy, he had ultimately failed to develop a truly scientific
theory.26
The implications of Bernstein's empiricist judgment were obvious: if
Marx's value theory lacked proper scientific grounding, then his crucial
understanding of "surplus value" was flawed as well. For Bernstein,
"surplus value" amounted to a "metaphysical image of which we have no
example in reality," for exploitation could not be calculated in a "purely
economic fashion."27 Standing with one foot on subjectivist grounds,
22
Ibid., p. 102.
23
Bernstein, "Allerhand Werttheoretisches," p. 371.
24
See Gerhard Himmelmann, "Die Rolle der Werttheorie in Bernsteins Konzept der
politischen Okonomie des Sozialismus," in Heimann and Meyer, Bernstein und der
demokratische Sozialismus, p. 313.
25 26
PS, p . 5 2 . Ibid., p . 5 5 .
27
Bernstein, "Allerhand Werttheoretisches," p. 558.
Evolutionary socialism as "organized liberalism" 127
Bernstein was bound to question the alleged objectivism of Marx's theory
of surplus value, with its core claim to provide an exact standard for the
actual degree of exploitation in concrete cases. Having thus robbed
Marx's theory of its scientific status, Bernstein emphasized the political
function of the notion of exploitation: it contributed to social democracy's
educational task of showing the proletariat the social injustice connected
with the generation of profit. However, Bernstein's interpretation de-
prived Marx's theory of its central claim, because early socialist theorists
like Proudhon had already provided the working class with ethical
ammunition against capitalist exploitation. Consistent with his epi-
stemological arguments against "scientific socialism," Bernstein dis-
avowed Engels' claim that Marx's economic theory represented a major
"scientific" achievement.
Once again, Bernstein's empiricist skepticism had triumphed over the
need for dogmatic security. Considering exploitation an empirical condi-
tion manifested in the worker's low living standard, capitalist injustice was
"demonstrable from experience" and required "no deductive proof."
Hence, he denied that the case for a "scientific socialism" could be made
"just on the fact that the wage laborer does not receive the full value of the
product of his labor."28 According to Bernstein, workers had always been
aware of the conditions of inequality underlying the economic and
political subjugation which forced them to produce more than they
received in wages. But as far as the concrete political practice of the labor
movement was concerned, it was "unimportant whether or not one
accepts the development of the theory of surplus value according to
Marx."29 The point was to educate workers to see that their wages did not
reflect the full value of their labor, thus appealing to their sense of justice
and strengthening their will to organize effective forms of political and
social resistance.
Bernstein did not see as the true test of "socialist" economic theories
whether they "correctly" interpreted the myriad aspects of value forma-
tion, but how they helped to advance perennial union demands for a closer
correspondence between wages and performance and price formation
according to rational principles of cost coverage. In this regard, Bernstein
revealed his sympathies for the pragmatic discourse of labor unionists and
SPD Praktiker. What made him different, however, was his unwillingness
to compromise on the core ethical principles of socialism. In other words,
applied to the real conditions of advanced capitalism, any theory of
surplus value was politically translatable only as an ethically motivated
28
PS, p. 52, 56.
29
Bernstein, "Wie ist wissenschaftlicher Sozialismus moglich?," p. 60.
128 Vision
theory of workers' emancipation, designed to strengthen the proletariat's
resolve to fight "not against the fact of surplus labor but the extent of it." 30
Bernstein therefore insisted that any theory of value ought to emphasize its
moral components - transcendental principles of equality and justice,
which Marx and Engels had woefully neglected in favor of their histori-
cism. Though Marxist economic theory illustrated the structural linkages
between production and exploitation, the latter was not simply an
objective relationship between economic variables, but, most important-
ly, expressed a violation of moral standards based on "eternal" liberal
principles of justice. 31
Today, the struggle of the working class is not directed against the wage form itself,
but against the economic dependency relations which depress wages and prevent
their rise according to the general increase of social wealth. The wage form is
simply one part of an economic system that must be changed through the creation
of a democratic-cooperative collectivism. It is only for symbolic reasons that we
refer to this desired change of the wage system as a "struggle against wage labor."
In reality, it is a struggle against the system of wage determination.34
30
Bernstein, "The Realistic and Ideological Moments in Socialism," in MS, pp. 239-240.
31
Bernstein, "Tugan Baranovsky als Sozialist," in Archiv fur Sozialwissenschaft und
Sozialpolitik 28 (1909), pp. 789-790.
32
Bernstein, "Wie ist wissenschaftlicher Sozialismus moglich?," p. 71.
33
Bernstein, "Vorfragen einer Sozialistischen Theorie der Gewerkschaftsbewegung," pp.
844-845.
34
Bernstein, "Zur Frage des ehernen Lohngesetzes: Nachwort," in Zur Theorie und
Geschichte des Sozialismus, pp. 11-IS.
Evolutionary socialism as "organized liberalism" 129
Marx, of course, had insisted that the social inequality between capital and
labor reflected in the class character of capitalist society would always
reassert itself as long as the economic base of society remained unalter-
ed.35 This meant that the reproduction of both exploitation and repressive
class relations occurred on the level of economic production. Reformist-
redistributive policies implemented by a democratically elected socialist
government operating within the old economic framework would never
escape the biased logic of capitalist accumulation. Political measures
aimed at eliminating social inequality would prove themselves incapable
of moving capitalist society even an inch closer to its socialist telos. After
all, the proper functioning of capitalism - the production and distribution
of commodities - depended on the existence of a liberal political system
that guaranteed the survival of the free-market system. The "bourgeois-
liberal state" could therefore hardly be more than a "committee for
managing the common affairs of the whole bourgeoisie," whose external
form and mechanisms of repression would only disappear as the era of
commodity-producing societies came to an end in a genuine socialist
revolution.
Diverging from Marx, Bernstein returned at least partially to the
subjectivism of the marginalists, thereby supporting the general liberal
view of society as composed of equal and independent individual
proprietors - categories of "bourgeois ideology" which Marx had
criticized in both The Jewish Question and Critique of the Gotha Program,
and which he further ridiculed in his famous allusion to bourgeois
"Robinson Crusoe economists."36 Shattering Marx's economic interpre-
tation of social totality, Bernstein considered the state as no longer a
secondary structure dependent on more primary class relations on the
level of production, but as a semi-independent sphere capable of aggres-
sive intervention, and thus critical for evolutionary socialism understood
as ethical reformism.37
Consequently, he put his faith in the ability of liberal-democratic
institutions to accommodate the interests of the working class. In this
context, we must remember that Marxist theorists writing at the turn of
the century still had not offered a comprehensive formal treatise on the
state. Marx's own discussion consisted of a number of scattered and
inconsistent general observations on the role and the character of
the "bourgeois state," usually couched in terms of his analysis of
particular historical situations like the 1848 revolutions and the 1871
35
C/,pp. 617-621.
36
Ibid., pp. 76-83.
37
Eduard Bernstein, "Die Staatstheorien und der Sozialismus," in Sozialismus Etnst und
Jetzt, pp. 75-90.
130 Vision
Paris Commune. 38 Criticizing Engels' anti-statist "utopianism" culmina-
ting in his famous notion of the "withering away of the state," Bernstein
emphasized instead the state's flexible character and predicted its trans-
formative potential from an arbitrary "power above the nation," into a
"legal body of democratic self-administration." 39 Though he agreed with
Marx on the coercive nature of the nineteenth-century state, particularly the
German state, Bernstein considered instrumentalist interpretations of the
state exclusively as an "organ of bourgeois oppression" as "too nar-
row." 40
If Marx de-emphasized the value of the state in bringing about lasting
social reforms, then Ferdinand Lassalle's exaggeration of the state's role in
facilitating a socialist transformation of society represented the other
extreme. Though Bernstein shared Lassalle's emphasis on universal
suffrage as the crucial precondition for social democracy, he nonetheless
rejected the latter's Hegelian idealized collectivism, which, in the name of
a proletarianized "general will," demanded the transformation of the
liberal "night watchman state" into the prime instrument of working-class
rule. Maintaining his long-standing suspicion of Lassallean state socialism
and its "foggy notion of an all-encompassing nationalization of produc-
tion," 41 Bernstein rejected the notion of a patronizing state indiscrimi-
nately dispensing social benefits to its citizens. He stressed the individual's
responsibility for his or her own economic welfare, adding that there was
no prospect for it to be "abolished" in any future socialist order:
Socialism can only facilitate the discharge of this duty. Anything more than that
would be undesirable. We all know that the responsibility for oneself is only one
side of a social principle, the obverse of which is personal freedom. The one is
inconceivable without the other. However contradictory it may sound, the notion
of abolishing the individual's responsibility for his own economic welfare is
thoroughly anti-socialist.42
Hence, the state's power in the economic realm needed to be limited, for
self-directed economic initiative in certain areas remained an important
element guaranteeing individual freedom.43
38
For a discussion of Marxist state theory, see, for example, Graeme Duncan, "The Marxist
Theory of the State," in G. H. R. Parkinson, ed. Marx and Marxisms (Cambridge:
Cambridge UP, 1982), pp. 129-144; Nicos Poulantzas, State, Power, Socialism (London:
Verso, 1980); Ralph Miliband, The State in Capitalist Society (London: Weidenfeld and
Nicolson, 1969); Claus Offe, "Thesis on the Theory of State," in New German Critique 6
(Fall, 1975), pp. 137-147; and Hal Draper, Karl Marx's Theory of Revolution, vol. I. (New
York: Monthly Review Press, 1977).
39
Eduard Bernstein, "The Social and Political Significance of Space and Number," in MS,
40
p. 97. Bernstein, Der Sozialismus Einst undjetzt, p. 88.
41
Bernstein, "Zum Thema Socialliberalismus und Collectivismus," p. 181.
42
Bernstein, "The Social and Political Significance of Space and Number," in MS, p. 94.
43
Ibid., pp. 91-92.
Evolutionary socialism as "organized liberalism" 131
Bernstein looked upon the state in the more balanced manner of L. T.
Hobhouse, J. A. Hobson, and other British "New Liberals." Emerging on
the political scene in full force in the first decade of the new century, the
New Liberals linked demands for greater economic equality with their
traditional support for individual freedom by positing an activist, but
democratic state as the possible site of a more harmonious association of
citizens collectively and consciously regulating the terms of their mutual
interactions.44 This new liberal vision saw capitalism harboring at its core
structural-political and economic inequalities which could be reduced
with the help of an interventionist state apparatus anchored in concrete
social institutions that guaranteed political equality, universal suffrage,
and a democratic representation of societal interests.45
However, this did not mean that Bernstein assumed the complete
eradication of diverging social interests. By arguing that modernity had
put an end to earlier forms of homogeneous social action based on strong
solidaristic bonds among members of small communities - including
idealized ethical relationships of harmony, like ancient forms of "direct
democracy" -he was able to make an even stronger case for the survival of
centralized adminstrative structures. The fact that modern states were
characterized by extensive territories and a large citizenry fostered the
emergence of ever more complex and differentiated group interests, thus
increasing the need for a "coordinated regulation of social and economic
matters."46 That is, the persistence of conflicting interests in modernity
corresponded to the emergence of a pluralist society, making it both
impossible and undesirable to "simply leave the state behind."47
The complexity of modern society increased the pressure on the state to
produce legislation reflecting the "common good" as the outcome of
rational and democratic negotiations across class lines. Though Bernstein
conceded that overlapping class interests rarely went beyond general
policies like education, health care, and national defense, he nonetheless
saw in the liberal-functionalist ideal of the "common good" the ideologi-
cal expression of persisting forms of social cohesion, which could serve as
a powerful regulative idea and common normative matrix connecting all
social classes. According to Bernstein, the true function of the state as the
44
See, for example, L. T. Hobhouse, "Liberalism/' in James Meadowcroft, ed. Liberalism
and Other Writings (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1994), pp. 1-120.
45
F o r a discussion of t h e " N e w L i b e r a l s , " see Blaazer, The Popular Front and the Progressive
Tradition; R i c h a r d Bellamy, Liberalism and Modern Society (University Park, P A : P e n n
State U P , 1 9 9 2 ) ; M . F r e e d e n , The New Liberalism: An Ideology of Social Reform (Oxford:
Oxford U P , 1 9 7 8 ) ; a n d S. Collini, Liberalism and Sociology: L . T. Hobhouse and Political
Argument in England 1880-1914 (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1979).
46
B e r n s t e i n , Der Sozialismus Einst und Jetzt, p . 8 7 .
47
Ibid., p . 9 0 .
132 Vision
"appointed guardian of the common good," was its representation of
society as a whole.48 Therefore, a "liberal" socialism ought to acknowl-
edge both existing forms of class conflict and class consensus expressed as
communal interests (political cooperation) and special interests (compe-
tition).
Underlying this vision was Bernstein's sanguine assessment of the
sustainability of a "democratic evolution" even in the Wilhelmine
Empire, which, he thought, would eventually culminate in a state
reflecting the political will of all its citizens. Once in the hands of liberal
socialists, such representative democracies could gradually abolish both
political privileges and the "strong tendency of the dominant classes to
burden other classes with the costs of public welfare."49 Kautsky and his
orthodox comrades begged to differ with Bernstein's "evolutionism;" not
so much on the desirability or even the possibility of reform and
gradualism in general, but about the prospects for a peaceful democratiz-
ation and for socialist cooperation with a liberal bourgeoisie specifically in
the German Empire.
Overall, then, Bernstein perceived the state in pluralist terms as a
potentially "autonomous" arena which regulated the "common affairs"
of individuals. With unshakable optimism, he emphasized the gradual
realization of the "contractarian idea" as the ontological underpinnings
of his progressive belief in the "organic evolution" of solidarity and
socialism.50 Sharing the utilitarian creed which saw society develop
unilinearly from inscribed forms of social status to the rule of voluntary
contracts fostering the expansion of equality, reciprocity, and legality,
Bernstein underscored the significance of "advancing legal concepts and
institutions which facilitate the mediation of class conflicts without
resorting to force."51 Hence, he reiterated the importance of the politi-
cal sphere for both easing the external relationship among different
states, and "institutionalizing" - and thus harnessing - domestic class
conflict.52
Viewing the modern state as an increasingly autonomous site also
allowed him to define class inequalities in terms of differences in income
and privileges, rather than as systemic contradictions rooted in the process
48
B e r n s t e i n , " W a s ist S o z i a l i s m u s ? , " i n H e i m a n n , Ein revisionistisches Sozialismusbild, p .
157.
49
Bernstein, "Die Notwendigkeit in Natur und Geschichte," in Zur Theorie und Geschichte
des Sozialismus, p. 68.
50
Bernstein, Von der Sekte zur Parted pp. 44-45.
51
Bernstein, "Idee und Interesse in der Geschichte/' in Bernstein A, A53.
52
Bernstein's call for mediating class conflicts found its full expression in neo-corporatist
"social partnerships" between employers and labor in post-World War II European
countries like Austria, Germany, and Sweden.
Evolutionary socialism as "organized liberalism" 133
53
of production. Bernstein therefore implicitly challenged the Marxist
thesis of "irreconcilable class conflicts" emerging from the contradictions
at the economic base. This meant contesting the Marxist dichotomy
between liberalism and socialism: "The term 'social-liberalism' indicates
in no way a fundamental opposition to 'social democracy.'"54
Once the Marxian connection between economic production and social
structure was cut, Bernstein was in the position to restore politics, the
state, and democratic theory to the center of socialist thought. It allowed
the evolutionary project of socialist transformation to originate in a
distinct "political" realm where the general will of citizens was represen-
ted in a democratically accountable parliament. Further strategic ramifi-
cations of Bernstein's theory of state were obvious: liberal democracy was
flexible enough to permit genuine political participation as well as
significant social control of economic institutions.
However, without the concurrent expansion of labor unions and
economic cooperatives, a socialist control of the state apparatus alone
would not be enough to bring about a perfectly egalitarian society. Still,
the democratic legitimacy emanating from fair, comprehensive elections
would give the state a major role in mediating class conflict and regulating
disruptive forms of free-market competition. Revolution was not "inevi-
table" because class conflicts were not irreconcilable. Social democracy,
understood as a "people's party," adhering to democratic reformism and
willing to entertain alliances wirh other liberal-democratic parties, could
spearhead the creation of a "socialist republic." The political institutions
of such a state would implement legally binding rules for a more just
distribution of the social product and the gradual elimination of surviving
political and economic privileges of the bourgeoisie.55 Thus, without the
pernicious social dislocations brought about by revolutionary upheavals,
modern, complex societies - including the German authoritarian-capital-
ist system - could slowly grow into a democratic socialism. This
"evolutionary vision," in a nutshell, constituted the core of Bernstein's
liberal socialism.
In summary, then, we can say that Bernstein's return to Lange's
epistemology led to his idealist reinterpretation of historical materialism
and his critique of Marx's labor theory of value, which, in turn, formed the
theoretical foundation for his pluralist theory of state. The latter allowed
him to not only contest Marx's dichotomy between liberalism and
53
See Freudenthal, "Otto Neurath: From Authoritarian Liberalism to Empiricism," in
Dascal and Griingard, Knowledge and Politics, pp. 218-219. My discussion in this chapter
owes much to the excellent contributions of Freudenthal, Himmelmann, and Coletti.
54
Bernstein, "Zum Thema Socialliberalismus und Collectivismus," p. 183.
55
PS, pp. 143-144; Sozialismus Einst und Jetzt, pp. 59-90.
134 Vision
socialism but arrive at a "constructive" theoretical alternative- evolution-
ary socialism. Hence, before turning to a more detailed discussion of
Bernstein's theory of socialist transformation, we must closely examine
the theoretical link between Bernstein's liberal political framework and his
understanding of socialism.
Indeed, Bernstein did not share Marx's scorn for bourgeois "civil
society" and its egoistic, "so-called rights of man," which reflected the
fundamental capitalist disjunctive between the alienated individual and
59
Luxemburg, in ibid., called Bernstein a "simpleton" with a "poor understanding of
Marxian economics;" a man whose theory amounted to a "passive betrayal" of the
working class (pp. 39, 53). See also Alex Callinicos, Marxism and Philosophy (New York:
Oxford UP, 1985), pp. 65-66.
60
This understanding is most clearly revealed in the SPD's 1959 Godesberg Program:
"Socialism is a continuous task - to fight for freedom and justice, to keep those values, and
to persevere with them . . . Socialism is realized only through democracy, democracy is
fulfilled through socialism." Cited in Wolfgang Abendroth, Aufstieg und Krise der
deutschen Sozialdemokratie (Frankfurt: Stimme Verlag, 1964), pp. 129-130. Although
Kolakowski (1978), noticing this synthesis, calls Bernstein's revisionism a "socialist
variant of liberalism" (p. 114), nobody has properly articulated the theoretical and
political components of Bernstein's evolutionary socialism. See, for example, Meyer,
Bernstein's konstruktiver Sozialismus; Heimann, Texte zum Revisionisms; Lehnert, Reform
und Revolution in den Strategiediskussionen der klassischen Sozialdemokratie; Steinberg,
Sozialismus und deutsche Sozialdemokratie; Grebing, Der Revisionismus: Von Bernstein bis
zum "Prager Fruhling"; Steenson, KarlKautsky 1854-1938; and Pachter, "The Ambigu-
ous Legacy of Eduard Bernstein," in Bronner, Socialism in History: The Political Essays of
Henry Pachter, pp. 256-283.
61
Bernstein, Von der Sekte zur Partei, p. 9.
136 Vision
the community.62 Instead, "evolutionary socialism" was rooted in its
departure from the sphere of production and the corresponding Marxist
reduction of man to a homofaber, whose "human nature" was determined
by his particular mode of productive activity.63 As pointed out in the
previous chapter, Bernstein's empiricist analysis of society tended to treat
socioeconomic entities as though they were indisputable entities, the
"givens" of objective reality. As a result, he viewed personal rights as
moral entitlements based on abstractly defined human qualities and
capacities. This meant, to put it in less favorable Marxist terms, to confuse
"bourgeois man" with "man-in-general."
While he acknowledged the importance of Marx's famous "Sixth
Thesis" on Feuerbach, which characterized humans as a fluid "ensemble
of social relationships," Bernstein nonetheless insisted that the social
environment did not fully determine "human nature."64 Obviously, he
was referring to transhistorical moral standards inherent in "reason" itself
- a rational morality of Recht traditionally expressed in the natural law
concepts of liberal thinkers from Locke to Kant and Mill. In fact, Bernstein
did not hesitate to praise the historically progressive role of natural law
precepts as providing a rational check on limited positive law, thus
inspiring generations of "radical spirits to protest against the domination
of tradition with its antiquated social institutions, political conditions, and
ideology."65 This moral foundation in Recht provided him with a
conceptual framework to encourage his fellow socialists to drop their
dogmatic Marxist slogans denouncing appeals to human rights as signs of
"false consciousness" and defeatism, and to frame their political demands
within a rights-centered discourse of liberal democracy instead.66 Success-
fully appropriating the liberal language of the radical citoyen of the French
Revolution for social democracy, Bernstein clearly subscribed to a
non-Marxist conception of "civil society," which, for him, meant less an
alienated sphere of self-centered individuals than a voluntary association
of individuals according to the ethos of the Enlightenment.
Regretting that the German word "burgerlich" did not allow for the
crucial distinction between the progressive "citoyen" and the conservative
62
Marx's seminal texts in this regard are: On the Jewish Question, Contribution to the Critique
ofHegeVs Philosophy of Right, The German Ideology, and Critique of the Gotha Program, all in
Robert C. Tucker, ed. The Marx-Engels Reader, 2nd ed. (New York: W. W. Norton,
1978).
63
See also Freudenthal, "Otto Neurath: From Authoritarian Liberalism to Empiricism," in
Dascal and Griingard, Knowledge and Politics, pp. 219-221.
64
PS, p. 17.
65
Bernstein, "Die naturrechtliche Begriindung des Sozialism," in Der Sozialismus Einst und
Jetzt,p. 21.
66
Eduard Bernstein, Parlamentarismus und Sozialdemokratie (Berlin: Pan, 1906), p. 13; and
PS, pp. 149, 160.
Evolutionary socialism as "organized liberalism" 137
"bourgeois," Bernstein insisted that it was only the property owners' claim
for special privileges vis-a-vis the state that made them "bourgeois" in
their ideological outlook. 67 Consequently., he showed great sympathy for
Friedrich Schiller's optimism regarding the possible transformation of
Germany's burgerliche Gesellschaft into a vibrant public sphere, whose
paramount task it was to restore an ethical society which would protect the
moral and economic autonomy of individuals from the atomizing and
dehumanizing tendencies of bourgeois capitalism.^ However, this did not
mean that Bernstein failed to recognize the bourgeoisie's ideological and
social hold on civil society. Still, the permeation of modern society by
bourgeois culture only highlighted the critical role of civil society in the
political project of social democracy, which aimed at imbuing political
associations with democratic principles and, ultimately, at transforming
public institutions. Bernstein felt that the working class should utilize the
critical potential of civil society by claiming the "public sphere" as a forum
for the open exchange of emancipatory ideas amongst equal citizens.
As the first prominent spokesman of modern social democracy, Bern-
stein reversed Marx's romantic holism, which looked down upon civil
society as the French Revolution's short-lived experiment in political
emancipation. For Bernstein, civil society could not be reduced to selfish,
independent individuals, released from their communal obligations and
left to their egotistical wishes and desires:
No one thinks of destroying civil society as a community ordered in a civilized way.
Quite to the contrary, Social Democracy does not want to break up civil society
and make all its members proletarians together; rather, it ceaselessly labors to raise
the worker from the social position of a proletarian to that of a citizen and thus
make citizenship universal. It does not want to replace civil society with a
proletarian society but a capitalist order of society with a socialist one.69
Bernstein's notion of creating an equal partnership of all citoyens in a
commonwealth within a socialist (i.e., redistributive) framework required
him to lower the standards of Marx's totalistic demands for "human
emancipation" and a rational control of production. Settling for the more
modest role of mediator between differing systems of thought, and
remaining loyal to the liberal enterprise of "political emancipation,"
Bernstein's evolutionary socialism approached the humanist vision of
Enlightenment thinkers like Kant and Schiller, who argued that the
existence of civil society and abstract human rights protected individual
67
Eduard Bernstein, "Randbemerkungen," in SM 13 (1909), p. 883; and PS, p . 146.
68
Friedrich von Schiller, Sdmtliche Werke: Sdkular Ausgabe, vol. V (Berlin: Cotta, 1904), p.
593. For a discussion on Schiller and modernity, see Jiirgen Habermas, Derphilosophische
Diskurs der Moderne (Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp, 1985), pp. 59-65.
69
PS, p. 146.
138 Vision
liberty institutionalized as the liberal distinction between private and
public. Most of all, Bernstein's approach liberated the political subject
from the smothering objectivity of Marx's historicism, thus encouraging
individual responsibility and permanent self-criticism as the springs for a
socialist action understood as the never-ending, "constructive" task of
transforming political and socioeconomic structures within the frame-
work of liberal democracy.70
Like the British "New Liberals/' Bernstein understood individual
liberty not "in the metaphysical sense dreamed of by the anarchists - that
is, free from all duties toward the community - but free from any
economic compulsion in [one's] actions and choice of vocation."71
Defining freedom as the "highest possible degree of individual self-
determination," he supported legal equality and equality of opportunity
as the organizing principles for the social implementation of liberty. At the
same time, however, he firmly rejected "communist" demands for
absolute equality as "abstract" and even dangerous: "Even if we cherish
equality as our social principle, we cannot posit it as the ethical goal of
human development, for it represents a desired social objective only when
applied to certain cases. Or, to put it differently: equality is a sporadic
human ideal; freedom, however, is an eternal one."72
Applied to the concrete politics of the labor movement, Bernstein's
primacy of liberty translated as an ethical appeal to workers' solidarity.
The extension of their civil rights and political and economic forms of
self-determination were only possible through the institutionalization of
effective workers' organizations.
For Social Democracy, the defense of civil liberty has always taken precedence
over the fullfilment of any economic postulate. The aim of all socialist measures,
even of those that outwardly appear to be coercive measures, is the development
and protection of the free personality. A closer examination of such measures
always shows that the coercion in question will increase the sum total of liberty in
society, and will give more freedom over a more extended area than it takes away. For
instance, the legally enforced maximum working day is actually a delimitation of
minimum freedom, a prohibition against selling your freedom for longer than a
certain number of hours daily, and as such it stands, in principle, on the same
ground as the prohibition, accepted by all liberals, against selling oneself
permanently into personal servitude.73
It is hardly surprising that Bernstein ultimately acknowledged socialism as
70
Thomas Meyer (1977) refers to Bernstein's reformist strategy as a "constructive
socialism" aiming to reformulate socialist theory under modern conditions of highly
complex social structures (p. 386).
71
PS, p. 150.
72
Eduard Bernstein, Die Arbeiterbewegung (Frankfurt: Riitten & Loning, 1910), p. 135.
73
PS, pp. 147-148.
Evolutionary socialism as "organized liberalism" 139
the "legitimate heir" to a liberalism defined not in terms of the incomplete
agenda of existing German liberal parties, but as an historical movement
fighting in the name of the universalist principles of the French Revol-
ution, aiming to liberate the citoyen from his dependency on the church,
the repressive state, and the capitalist economy. 74 Bernstein discerned
even in the flawed "bourgeois" version of liberalism an "evolutionary
principle" that was noticeably absent in feudalism: a universalist logic and
a libertarian discourse that provided the basis for the inclusionary
demands of marginalized social groups. 75 If the rising bourgeoisie,
reflected in a vitalized public sphere with its ability to generate critical
debate and popular activity, was able to contest authoritarianism, then the
succeeding progressive social movements led by social democracy could
use the same liberal logic to further extend representative democracy as
well as civil and economic rights.
Nearly everywhere it took force to destroy feudalism with its rigid corporate
institutions. The liberal institutions of modern society differ from these precisely
in being flexible and capable of change and development. They do not need to be
destroyed; they only need to be further developed. For that we require organiz-
ation and energetic action, but not necessarily a revolutionary dictatorship.76
Yet, this benign vision did not forestall Bernstein's strong disapproval of
classical liberals who sought to limit citizenship to members of the first
three estates. Referring to them as "destroyers of solidarity and commu-
nity," he attacked their "phoney universalism" as nothing more than an
illiberal defense of existing political privilege and economic inequality.77
In order to evolve according to its own core principles, traditional liberal
theory had to be "modernized," that is, complemented with the principles
of solidarity and distributive justice, which, under mature capitalism,
found its most powerful objective expression in the demands of working
class.78 Organized around the ideals of cooperation, liberty, and distribu-
tive justice, the labor movement was therefore the logical successor of
classical liberalism.79
Derived from the Latin word socius (equal associate), "socialism"
meant for Bernstein "organized liberalism." 80 Socialism "evolved" from
liberalism in accordance with the principle of cooperation, offering its
"equally associated" members the same right in participating in socially
Ibid.
5
Bernstein to Bebel (October 20, 1898) in MS, p. 326; and PS, p. 150.
Ibid., p. 158.
Bernstein, "Hat der Liberalismus eine Zukunft in Deutschland?", Bernstein A, El 12; and
PS, p. 148.
Ibid.
9
Bernstein, Wesen und Aussichten des burgerlichen Radikalismus, pp. 42^15.
10
PS, p. 150.
140 Vision
consequential decision-making processes.81 This definition contains the
essence of Bernstein's evolutionary socialism understood as a worker-led
movement pervaded by humanitarian ethics, objectivity and scientific
openness, and reliance on principles of legality which defended individual
liberty against oppressive social conditions and institutions.82 Far from
needing to be destroyed, liberal democracy actually represented the
indispensable foundation of the socialist political project towards extend-
ing political and economic democracy: "[I]n the last instance, for me,
socialism means democracy, self-administration."83
In the end, Bernstein reached a position that echoed many concerns raised
in our contemporary debate on "economic democracy." 115 Ironically, in
the late 1920s these "Bernsteinian economics" resurfaced in the theories
of the Weimar socialist Fritz Naphtali, who urged the expansion of state
control over economic life through both anti-monopoly legislation and
counter-cyclical credit and public investment policy.116 Bernstein's and
Naphtali's blueprints for economic democracy were further developed
during the 1970s as part of a large-scale "Bernstein Renaissance" in
Germany spearheaded by the young faction of "Democratic Socialists" in
theSPD. 1 1 7
The theoretical foundation of these subsequent elaborations on "econ-
112
Eduard Bernstein, Die Sozialisierung der Betriebe (Basel, 1919), p. 19.
113
Bernstein, Der Sozialismus Einst undjetzt, p. 135.
114
Bernstein, "Critical Interlude," in MS, pp. 218-219.
115
See, for example, Robert A. Dahl, A Preface to Economic Democracy (Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press, 1985); and Roemer, A Future for Socialism.
116
Fritz Naphtali, Wirtschaftsdemokratie: Ihr Wesen, Weg, und Ziel (Frankfurt: Europaische
Verlagsanstalt, 1977).
117
See, for example, Peter Glotz, Der Weg der Sozialdemokratie: Der historische Auftrag des
Reformismus (Vienna/Munich: Molden, 1975); David W. Morgan, "The Father of
Revisionism Revisited: Eduard Bernstein," in Journal of Modern History 51 (September
1979), pp. 525-532; RobertS. Wistrich, "Back to Bernstein?", in Ewcowwrer 50.6 (1978),
pp. 75-80; Lehnert, Reform und Revolution in den Strategiediskusionen der klassischen
Sozialdemokratie', Grebing, Der Revisionismus: Von Bernstein bis zum "Prager Friihling";
Heimann, "Die Aktualitat Eduard Bernsteins," in Bernstein, Texte zum Revisionismus;
Sven Papcke, Der Revisionismusstreit und die politische Theorie der Reform (Stuttgart: W.
Kohlhammer, 1979); C. Butterwegge, "Der Bernstein-Boom in der SPD. Grundlagen,
Geschichte und Funktionen der gegenwartigen Revisionismus-Renaissance," in Blatter
fur deutsche und Internationale Politik 5 (1978); and the editorial in Der Spiegel (October
17, 1977). See also the special section on the "Bernstein Debates" in Die Neue
Gesellschaft 24.12 (1977), pp. 1,002-1,025; and H. Krehmendahl, "Renaissance des
Revisionismus. Ein Kongress der Friedrich Ebert Stiftung kniipft an das theoretische
Erbe Eduard Bernsteins an," in Vorwdrts (October 6, 1977).
Evolutionary socialism as "organized liberalism" 147
omic democracy" was Bernstein's conviction that socialism could indeed
be reconciled with the core principles of liberal democracy, including the
right to private property: "We [social democrats] do not abolish private
property, we limit its rights. The total abolition of property is impossi-
ble." 118 As was the case in his theory of political democracy, Bernstein
embedded his vision of economic democracy within a liberal discourse of
rights: "The decisive point is not the fact that property is being acknowl-
edged, but what kind of property is acknowledged and what rights are
connected with property. Protection of acknowledged property is one of
the conditions of a regulated social life and its socially regulated condi-
tions of production. The opposite is not socialism, but anarchism."119
Bernstein's theoretical synthesis of liberalism and socialism understood
as "evolutionary socialism" clearly employed liberal concepts not as
"alien elements" intruding on the doctrinal purity of "real socialism," but
as essential features of any democratic socialism. Unfortunately, the SPD
leadership took an ambivalent, and even hostile position toward his
(re)vision until 1959, when it finally passed the non-Marxist Bad
Godesberg Program. It will be the task of the following chapters to show
why, during his lifetime, Bernstein's quest for evolutionary socialism
remained largely unfulfilled.
118
Bernstein, "Hat der Liberalismus eine Zukunft in Deutschland?," Bernstein A, El 12.
119
Eduard Bernstein, "Zwei politische Programm-Symphonien," in NZ 15.2 (1896/97),
pp. 334-335.
Part 3
Disappointment
Facing the critics
151
152 Disappointment
Kant's Critique of Pure Reason - a subject Bernstein supposedly did not
understand.2 Many party functionaries knew that the late "General"
himself had sung the praises of Bernstein's grasp of theoretical matters,
calling him "one of the best of the younger generation/'3 proudly
presenting him and Kautsky as the "true pearls of German social
democracy/'4 and the "most reliable representatives of Marxist theory."5
In fact, Kautsky, too, had repeatedly defended Bernstein's wit, referring
to him as one of the major proponents of "true Marxism." As late as 1897,
Kautsky had sided with his friend against a charge mounted by British
Marxist Belfort Bax, who had accused Bernstein of having "unconscious-
ly ceased to be a social democrat."6
Eventually, Bebel and Kautsky agreed to "contain" the causa Be-
rnstein by affording his revisionist ideas a "safe" and open forum at
national party conferences where Bebel could counterattack with bind-
ing anti-Bernstein resolutions, thereby preventing the uncontrolled
spread of "wild debates" to local party organizations. Although some
prominent party members secretly pressured Bernstein to resign his
SPD membership for the sake of the "movement," Bebel and Kautsky
initially refused to meet Luxemburg's radical demands for his public
expulsion for fear of pushing Bernstein into forming a new party of
"reformist socialism." When Bernstein signalled his firm resolve to
remain in the SPD, Bebel and Kautsky were forced to go full steam
ahead with their potentially self-defeating anti-Bernstein crusade. Bebel
suddenly "confessed" that he had never regarded his former friend as a
man of exceptional intellectual abilities, conveniently "forgetting" that,
less than twenty years before, he had himself recommended his "young,
bright Berliner comrade" to serve as editor-in-chief of the main party
organ. By openly denouncing Bernstein's credentials as a party theorist
and by questioning his political loyalty, Bebel and Kautsky gave other
2
Eduard Bernstein, "Immanuel Kant's Kritik der reinen Vernunft," in Neue Zeit 18.1
(1899/1900), p. 255-260. For a critique of Bernstein's "neo-Kantianism" by his socialist
contemporaries, see, for example, Wolfgang Heine, "Eduard Bernstein und die politische
Frage der Sozialdemokratie," in SM 3.10 (October 1899), pp. 478-493; George
Plekhanov, "Materialismus oder Kantianismus," in NZ 17.1 (1898-1899), pp. 589-596;
626-632; and Karl Kautsky, "Problematisches gegen wissenschaftlichen Sozialismus," in
NZ 19.3 (1900/1901), pp. 355-364.
3
Engels to Sorge (October 4, 1890) MEW 37, p. 479.
4
Engels to Bebel (June 22, 1885) Bebel BWE, p. 228.
5
Engels BWK, p. 90. See also Engels's remark that "Bebel and Bernstein are the only leaders
who fully grasp the [political] situation" (Engels cited in EB, p. 32).
6
Karl Kautsky, "Was will und kann die materialistische Geschichtsauffassung leisten?" NZ
15.1(1896/97), pp. 269-270. For an excellent account of Kautsky's defense of Bernstein's
theoretical abilities, see Steenson, Karl Kautsky: 1854-1938: Marxism in the Classical Years,
pp. 116-117.
Facing the critics 153
prominent European social democrats the green light to follow their
example.7
Their plan worked to perfection. Within three years, most Marxist
theorists of some stature had published their own "Anti-Bernstein"
tirades, defending the principles of "scientific socialism" against the
"opportunistic attacks" of the "petty-bourgeois turncoat." A greatly
reduced list of contributors to these early efforts aimed at exorcizing the
spectre of revisionism from European social democracy would include
such prominent names as Ernest Belfort Bax, H. M. Hyndman, the
French socialist leader Jean Jaures, Parvus, George Plekhanov, Karl
Kautsky, Rosa Luxemburg, V. I. Lenin, the Dutch theorist, Anton
Pannekoek, the Austrian socialist philosopher, Max Adler, and the SPD
historian, Franz Mehring.
Appearing in the form of short essays or book-length monographs, this
polemical avalanche gradually succeeded in undermining Bernstein's
spotless former reputation as a gifted political thinker and deserving heir
to Friedrich Engels. In its place, the orthodox tracts raised an almost
grotesque effigy of Bernstein as a "theoretical simpleton" with a shallow
grasp of philosophical matters and an "inadequate understanding of
Marxian political economy."8 Aimed at saving orthodox Marxism from
the potentially devastating effects of Bernstein's intervention, these early
commentators pieced together a Bernstein portrait which, at least par-
tially, survived until our time.
Kautsky started the onslaught on Bernstein's evolutionary socialism
with his somewhat disappointing Bernstein and the Social Democratic
Program: An Anti-Critique. Seeking to discredit both Bernstein's empirical
findings and his theoretical conclusions, Kautsky made the surprising
claim that Marxism had always officially rejected concepts such as the
thesis of the inevitable collapse of capitalism or a "general theory of
immiseration." For Kautsky, Bernstein was simply battling his own
inventions.9 Altogether ignoring the source of these concepts - The
Communist Manifesto -Kautsky also conveniently overlooked the fact that
official party ideology had persistently fed the working class with catch-
phrases like "necessary collapse" and "inevitable immiseration," thus
presenting the communist demands of 1848 in afin-de-sieclecontext.10
But no essay contributed more to Bernstein's poor reputation than
Rosa Luxemburg's monograph, Reform or Revolution? Lambasting
7
See, for example, Ernest Belfort Bax, "Our German Fabian Convert; or Socialism
According to Bernstein," in MS, pp. 61-65.
8
Luxemburg, Reform and Revolution?', p. 39.
9
Kautsky, Bernstein und das sozialdemokratische Program, p. 42.
10
Kautsky, Das Erfurter Programm, pp. 106, 136.
154 Disappointment
Bernstein for his "poor statistical skills" and his "childish" arguments,
"Red Rosa" shrewdly mixed the quasi-religious, emotive force of Marx's
early writings with her own insightful structuralist explanation of revision-
ism. Employing Marx's method of social analysis against Bernstein's
idealist "heresies," Luxemburg presented revisionism as an "epiph-
enomenal reflection" of the current "opportunism in social democ-
racy."11 In other words, she skillfully portrayed Bernstein's intervention
as the "superstructural effect" of a more profound problem at the
economic base.12 For Luxemburg, Bernstein's revisionism was related to
the old dispute between Marxists and opportunistic Praktiker. Evolution-
ary socialism amounted to nothing more than an unfortunate, but passing
"petty-bourgeois vulgarization of Marxism,"13 caused by the worsening
tensions and contradictions in the capitalist mode of production.
Heightening her structuralist account, Luxemburg asserted that Be-
rnstein, living in British exile, was incapable of judging the political
situation in Germany by simply gazing through his "tinted English
spectacles." Luxemburg thus appropriated the language of Ernest Belfort
Bax, the British Marxist who had made similar claims three years earlier in
the pages of the SDF journal Justice.14 Of course, there was neither
mention that Marx had developed his own theory as the result of a
life-long study of the economic history and conditions in England,15 nor
that Engels had made his well-received comments on the German
political situation from his comfortable house in London. Luxemburg's
wrath proved to be extremely selective, chiding only a particular London
exile for serving as capitalism's "unconscious predestined instrument,"
thereby manifesting the mode "by means of which the rising working class
expresses its momentary weakness."16
In the end, however, Rosa Luxemburg proved to be too politically
sophisticated simply to write off revisionism as an insignificant, short-
lived historical phenomenon. Although she frequently emphasized the
supposedly unoriginal, eclectic character of Bernstein's "groundless
critique," a few less polemical passages clearly reveal her fear that
Bernstein's theory might give the "opportunistic current" in the SPD its
"general theoretical expression; an attempt to elaborate its own theoreti-
cal conditions and to break with scientific socialism."17 In other words,
Luxemburg implicitly acknowledged that Bernstein, even in his early
11
Luxemburg, Reform or Revolution?, pp. 58-59.
12
Ibid., pp. 35-37, 58-60.
13
Ibid., p. 45.
14
Bax, "Our German Fabian Convert; or Socialism According to Bernstein," in MS, p. 64.
15
Friedrich Engels, "Preface" to the English edition of Marx, C I, p. 6.
16
Luxemburg, Reform or Revolution?, p. 62.
17
Ibid., p. 59.
Facing the critics 155
revisionist phase, went beyond a purely negative project of simply
"deconstructing" Marxism by offering at least the bare outlines of his own
constructive socialist theory.
Though lacking Luxemburg's formal education (she had obtained a
doctorate in political economy from the University of Zurich), Bernstein,
like most leading socialist thinkers of his time, was perfectly capable of
discussing broadly conceived philosophical issues and matters of political
theory in the context of the pressing practical demands of the labor
movement. Obviously, the motive behind the flood of pamphlets and
books that questioned his intellectual ability was not a sudden qualitative
drop in Bernstein's own writings, but their threat to the ideological
authority of "Marxist scriptures." Nonetheless, one must concede that
Bernstein failed to carry his critique to its logical end, completing his break
with Marxism, and perhaps even found a new social-liberal party.18 For a
variety of reasons, he seemed to waver in his criticism in the months
following the publication of The Preconditions of Socialism - a tactic that
often resulted in deliberately vague theoretical formulations.19 Bern-
stein's hesitancy translated into his vexing theoretical oscillation between
rejecting and revising Marxist doctrine, thus making him deserv-
edly vulnerable to harsh judgments regarding his ideological position.
At the 1899 Hannover Party Conference, Bernstein's "heresies"
dominated the proceedings even more than they had the year before.
Moreover, the French "Millerand Affair" added some spice to the
ensuing theoretical debates over the nature of Bernstein's revisionism.
Only a few months preceding the party conference, Alexandre Millerand,
a prominent member of the French Independent Socialist Party, had
decided to join the "bourgeois" cabinet of France's liberal Prime Minister
Waldeck-Rousseau, taking this unprecedented step without seeking prior
consultation with his party's leadership. While a number of French party
leaders and other small reformist workers' groups openly supported
Millerand's move, the anarchist Left and the Jules Guesde's revolutionary
Marxists protested against Millerand's violation of the "basic socialist
tradition," which prohibited any committed socialist from joining a
non-socialist government. Ultimately, the 1900 Paris Congress of the
Second International "resolved" the dilemma by merging Guesde's
demands with the rather vague language drafted by Kautsky, which
permitted exceptions to this rule only under poorly specified conditions
relating to the "protection of the achievements of the working class."
18
See, for example, Eduard Bernstein, "An meine sozialistischen Kritiker," p. 4; and "Der
Marx- Cultus und das Recht der Revision," p. 255.
19
See also Pachter, "The Ambiguous Legacy of Eduard Bernstein," in Bronner, Socialism in
History, p. 258.
156 Disappointment
Eager to avoid a similar conflict in the SPD, Kautsky and Bebel
refrained from raising the "Millerand Case" at the Hannover Conference,
thus foregoing the opportunity to challenge Bernstein's public approval of
the French minister's decision. In his memorable opening speech lasting
more than six hours, Bebel brilliantly displayed his double-pronged
strategy vis-a-vis the lingering "Bernstein Question." Pandering to the
atheoretical Praktiker and a small group of theoretically committed
"revisionists," he spent the first hour extolling the virtues of free speech
and socialist self-criticism. But he soon began to elaborate on the "pitfalls
of reformism," clearly regurgitating Kautsky's arguments designed to
undermine Bernstein's intellectual ability.20 Bebel indicated that any
attempt to rob social democracy of its revolutionary tradition was a blow
to the heart of his own staunch opposition to the existing system. Those
who abandoned "revolution" in favor of "evolution" had allowed
themselves to be coopted by the bourgeoisie and displayed their willing-
ness to compromise with the existing authoritarian state of Kaiser
Wilhelm. To the enthusiastic applause of almost 200 delegates, Bebel
closed his rhetorical tour deforce with a characteristicallyfieryadmonition:
"Let's stick with our goal of [capitalist] expropriation. This we'll never
give up!"21
Bernstein's pending arrest warrant prevented him once again from
defending himself in person. But as in Stuttgart the year before, his
position was well represented by a group of prominent revisionists led by
Eduard David and Heinrich Peus. Both men emphasized the importance
of synchronizing the party's theory and its practice without abandoning
the theoretical and ethical concerns of a committed socialism. According
to David, Bernstein's main contribution was to remind the party of the
fundamental importance of its present-day tasks (Gegenwartsarbeit), its
growing parliamentary activities, and its ethical responsibilities to its
constituency. According to Peus, Bernstein was to be commended for
formulating an evolutionary socialism that might well serve as "a means
for the organic construction of a socialist future."22
In the ensuing confrontations between the two camps which lasted for
almostfivedays, Bernstein's theoretical position was alternately condem-
ned and defended. Ultimately, however, Bebel used his central position in
the party's "old boy network," along with his conciliatory demeanor and
"commonsensical" calls for party unity, to appear as the peacemaker.
Thanking Bernstein for his "bold initiative" and firmly rejecting radical
20
Protokoll iiber die Verhandlungen des Parteitages des Sozialdemokratischen Partei Deutsch-
lands, abgehalten in Hannover vom 9-14 Oktober 1899 (Berlin, 1899), pp. 94-127.
21
Ibid., p . 1 2 1 .
22
Ibid., pp. 144, 186.
Facing the critics 157
calls for his expulsion, Bebel offered a final resolution that affirmed the
Marxist principles of the Erfurt Program. The document also emphasized
the proletarian-class character of the party and rejected any "revisionist"
attempts to turn the SPD into a "social democratic party of reform."23
The measure carried by an overwhelming margin.
In the end, Kautsky and Bebel had achieved a hard-fought victory, but
the war was not yet won. Undeterred, Bernstein would further develop his
revisionist arguments and challenge Kautsky's narrowly interpreted
proletarian Weltanschauung. Ultimately, Kautsky lost his strategic moder-
ation and ask Bernstein to leave the party, since he obviously "never really
understood Marxism."24 A deep personal friendship and remarkable
intellectual kinship of twenty years had come to a bitter end. This was the
moment for which a small number of left-liberals sympathetic to the
workers' cause had waited. Could Bernstein be recruited for a new,
worker-based national-liberal party of reform?
Liberal overtures
Already before the publication of The Preconditions of Socialism, Bernstein
had been inundated with congratulatory letters from left-liberals like the
neo-Kantian philosopher Karl Vorlander who praised his "courageous
initiative." Though disagreeing with Bernstein's epistemology, many
neo-Kantian socialists saw the London exile as a potential ally in their
mounting efforts to replace the party's orthodox Marxist doctrine with
their own ethical brand of socialism based upon Kant's Critical Ideal-
ism.25 Indeed, the powerful surge of neo-Kantian socialism in the first
decades of the new century owed much to Bernstein's revisionist interven-
tion.
Likewise, prominent social-liberal economists like Franz Oppenheimer
began to quote Bernstein in support of their cause, flooding him with
attractive offers for closer intellectual and organizational cooperation.
Politically, Oppenheimer was close to a relatively disorganized group of
small parties collectively called the left-liberals. Theodor Barth, a Bremen
delegate to the Bundesraty and charismatic leader of the most progressive
left liberal party - the Freisinnige Vereinigung (Liberal Association) - had in
the past unsuccessfully called for the formation of a "red" Kartell: a loose
electoral alliance between the left-liberals and the social democrats.26
Indeed, the left-liberals shared with the social democrats their strong
23
Ibid., pp. 244, 294.
24
Kautsky to Adler (May 6, 1901) Adler BW, p. 355.
25
See Steinberg, Sozialismus und deutsche Sozialdemokratie, p. 99.
26
Heckart, From Bassermann to Bebel, pp. 28-29.
158 Disappointment
interest in organizing workers and artisans in trade unions., called the
Hirsch-Duncker Gewerkvereine. Though one of the oldest unions in
Germany, the liberal Gewerkvereine were clearly outmuscled in size and
political power by the social democratic "free" trade unions. Moreover,
left-liberal members of the Reichstag frequently voted with the social
democrats against military and colonial bills that failed to benefit their
constituency.
While the political platform of left-liberal parties traditionally attracted
small businessmen, teachers, lawyers, and lower civil servants, their
membership also included traditional opponents of socialism: representa-
tives of large-scale commerce and finance. These members of the German
Grossburgertum (upper bourgeoisie) vigorously opposed the Conserva-
tive/Junker strategy of maintaining political power by turning against
industrialism. In particular, left-liberals emerged as strong critics of
establishing artificial economic measures such as protective tariffs, export
premiums, and agricultural subsidies, which were hurting the commercial
communities in the large northern German cities and small businessmen
in Saxony, Schleswig-Holstein, and Oldenburg.27
Aware of their respective parties' common roots in opposing the
authoritarianism and militarism of the Empire, Bernstein at first seemed
to reciprocate Oppenheimer's overtures by explicitly welcoming a stron-
ger emphasis on the "liberal element" in socialism. In fact, he conceded
that some theoretical principles of Oppenheimer's left liberalism were not
in contradiction to social democratic tenets as he understood them.28
However, Bernstein was unwilling to go along with Oppenheimer's
undiluted enthusiasm for economic laissez-faire policies and his neo-
Smithian supposition that the free play of economic competition itself
would eventually bring about both greater national wealth and a more
"cooperative" variant of capitalism. Rejecting the economic extremes of
Oppenheimer's left liberalism, Bernstein's liberal socialism instead stood
for significant state interventionist policies for sizeable sectors of the
economy.29 Ultimately, the two men were unable to overcome their
fundamental philosophical differences on this issue, and their correspon-
dence ceased abruptly.
Friedrich Naumann, the powerful leader of the center-left German
National-Social Association (Nationalsoziale Verein), also showed some
interest in moving the progressive parts of the German bourgeoisie closer
to Bernstein's evolutionary socialism. Greatly influenced by Max Weber,
27
Ibid., pp. 26-27.
28
Eduard Bernstein, "Zum Thema Socialliberalismus und Collectivismus," in SM 4
(1900), p. 183.
29
Ibid., p. 181.
Facing the critics 159
Naumann emerged as one of the most prominent non-socialist advocates
for the "modernization" and democratization of the Empire. With a
strong background in the Protestant Christian Social movement for social
reform, he was a keen observer and critic of the social dislocation and
economic hardship connected with Germany's rapid process of modern-
ization and industrialization. In his magnum opus, Demokratie und Kaiser-
tum, published in 1900, Naumann had laid out his comprehensive
theoretical vision for challenging the domination of the Conservatives and
affecting a reconciliation between democracy and Empire.30 Noting that
the agriculturally based Junkers were a formidable obstacle in Germany's
"assured" way to global greatness, Naumann put his faith in the growing
"modern" commercial and industrial classes which, he felt, had to be
rallied around an anti-Conservative political agenda. Naumann's innova-
tive political scheme involved combining the forces of liberal nationalism
and democracy in a progressive, class-transcending alliance "From
Basserman to Bebel" - a policy he officially announced at the 1901 party
congress of his Naiionalsozialer Verein.31
However, unlike Barth and other left-liberals, Naumann shared Max
Weber's overriding concern with Weltpolitik: a politics that subordinated
all domestic goals to "national interest" and the increase of Germany's
power on the international stage. Thus, Naumann saw it as his main task
to appeal to the "internationalist" left-liberals and social democrats to
give up their "unrealistic" opposition to a "national" politics, while at the
same time pressuring the center-right national-liberals to ease their
hostility to both the social democrats and a democratic framework for a
future German Reich. And indeed, it appeared as though both parties
were slowly moving in that direction. The national-liberals elected as their
chairman the moderate Ernst Bassermann, who was socially progressive
and tried to reinvoke the grand old liberal tradition of his party. His efforts
were supported by scores of so-called Young Liberal Clubs which sprang
up throughout the country and were led by young, liberal-thinking
activists like Gustav Stresemann.32
Even some social democratic Praktiker appeared to be attracted to
Naumann's ideas: Otto Hue, the powerful leader of the Ruhr area miners'
union, found himself so enthralled with Naumann's arguments in
Demokratie und Kaisertum, that he organized a well-attended lecture tour
through the Ruhr for the author.33 With Bernstein's The Preconditions of
30
Heckart, From Bassermann to Bebel, p. 13.
31
Ibid., pp. 16,22.
32
Ibid., pp. 33-43. See also Karola Bassermann, Ernst Bassermann (Mannheim: Dr Haas,
1919); and J. Alden Nichols, Germany after Bismarck (Cambridge, MA: Harvard UP,
1958).
33
Heckart, From Bassermann to Bebel, p. 20.
160 Disappointment
Socialism appearing roughly around the same time as Demokratie und
Kaisertum, Naumann assumed that the full transformation of social
democracy along reformist lines was only a matter of time and interpreted
the unfolding Revisionist Controversy as a clear sign of socialism's
willingness to drop its "old revolutionary phraseology."34 Triumphantly
announcing to his readers that "Bernstein is our farthest advanced post in
the camp of social democracy/' he enthusiastically welcomed Bernstein's
study as the "new political ideal of a democratic Left."35 Sending
Bernstein the galley proofs of his Demokratie und Kaisertum with the polite
request for a favorable review, Naumann saw their correspondence as the
beginning of a new era of cooperation between liberalism and the
reformist camp within social democracy.
There was indeed some reason for Naumann's optimism. Bernstein
shared his advocacy for a closer cooperation between liberals and
socialists in order to achieve various democratic goals, and he had
pressured the social democratic leadership to espouse such a "policy of
cooperation" as a matter of principle. In that sense, Bernstein's evolution-
ary socialism corresponded to a certain degree with Naumann's scheme to
create a "grand bloc" from Bassermann to Bebel. However, the socialist
revisionist clearly disappointed Naumann's Weltpolitik ambitions by
failing to warm up to his nationalist arguments. In his overall critical
review of Demokratie und Kaisertum^ Bernstein condemned Naumann for
his "anglophobia" and brought him up for his lack of understanding of
British trade policy. Disappointed and humiliated, Naumann retreated
and decided to drop Bernstein for the time being.36 But it should be noted
that Bernstein's article was aimed as much against those "revisionists" in
his own party who were using his arguments to justify their nationalistic
ambitions, as it was against Naumann's brand of German nationalism.
By far the most serious attempt to win Bernstein over to the liberal camp
came from Heinrich Braun, a sympathizer with social democracy, and
editor of the influential left-liberal political journals Archiv fur Soziale
Gesetzgebung und Statistik and Centralblatt. Braun hoped that Bernstein's
soft spot for liberalism would finally provide the necessary impetus to a
34
Friedrich Naumann, Demokratie und Kaisertum (Berlin: Hilfe Verlag, 1900), p. 7. For
Naumann's relationship with Max Weber, see Michael Panzer, Der Einfluss Max Webers
auf Friedrich Naumann (Wurzburg: Creator, 1986).
35
Friedrich Naumann's review of Bernstein's The Preconditions of Socialism in Hilfe 5.4
(1899), p. 4. See also Karl Korsch, "The Passing of Marxist Orthodoxy: Bernstein -
Kautsky-Luxemburg-Lenin," in Douglas Kellner, ed. Revolutionary Theory (Austin:
University of Texas Press, 1977), p. 176.
36
Eduard Bernstein, "Socialdemokratie und Imperialisms," in SM 4 (1900), pp.
238-251. See also Peter Theiner, Sozialer Liberalismus und deutsche Weltpolitik: Friedrich
Naumann im WilhelminischenDeutschland, 1860-1919 (Baden-Baden: Nomos, 1983), pp.
102-105.
Facing the critics 161
37
"far-reaching internal transformation of the [socialist] party." Seeking
to give Bernstein's revisionism a greater forum, Braun contacted the
London exile, unveiling his plan for a new journal which would employ
social-scientific research in analyzing the practical problems of the labor
movement. Hoping his new project would provide the dynamic spark
required to light the fires of a broad-based reformist socialism, Braun
wrote to Bernstein: "It is not only important that you personally speak to
our audience but that a whole current of scientific expression and practical
influence be represented. We must take positions on the problems of the
day,... [hence] the idea of a new journal, in which all the adherents of the
new direction come together."38
When Braun failed to secure the necessary funds for his new project, he
invited Bernstein to contribute to his Archiv on a regular basis in order to
give the publication a "clearer socialist direction." Before Bernstein was
able to come to afinaldecision on this matter, Braun managed to win over
a number of influential left-liberal editors for another project involving the
creation of a social-liberal weekly. As a theoretical "organ of battle," the
paper was designed to help "free social democracy from its rigid Marxist
dogmatism" and contribute to the "great expansion and deepening of
socialist ideas."39 Considering his publication as the crucial bridge
between left-liberal activists and "evolutionary socialists," Braun suc-
ceeded in securing the necessary funds from Charles Hallgarten, a wealthy
sympathizer. Predictably, Bebel and Kautsky strongly criticized Braun's
initiative, while revisionists like Paul Gohre - an influential religious
socialist and regular contributor to the "revisionist" journal Sozialistische
Monatshefte - and Wolfgang Heine promised their support.40
Initially, Bernstein endorsed the project, but upon returning to Ger-
many, he realized that his enthusiasm for Braun and his ideas had been
misguided. Recognizing that Braun's plan was deliberately designed to
enhance intra-party tensions which could lead to a split in the labor
movement, he distanced himself from the proposed project.41 Bernstein's
decision clearly shows that while he was prepared to provide the crucial
theoretical foundation for a liberal-socialist current within social democ-
racy, he was unwilling to play any role in Braun's separatist political
agenda. In the end, the "Braun episode" helped Bernstein to clarify his
own political plans and strengthen his commitment to his new theoretical
37
Braun to Sombart (December 13, 1900) in Julie Braun-Vogelstein, Heinrich Braun
(Stuttgart: Deutsche Verlagsanstalt, 1967), p. 134.
38
Braun cited in Pierson, Marxist Intellectuals and the Working Class Mentality in Germany
1887- 1912, pp. 151-152.
39
Braun cited in ibid., p. 152.
40
Ibid.
41
Ibid.
162 Disappointment
role as a revisionist thinker within the confines of the German labor
movement. Disappointed in Bernstein's surprising turnabout, Braun
complained about the latter's "lacking character and insight/' and vowed
to carry his struggle against Marxist orthodoxy straight into the lion's den.
Within a matter of weeks, Braun joined the SPD in the hope of mobilizing
other revisionist intellectuals.42
By 1900, it became clear that the combination of Bernstein's hesitancy
and sense of loyalty to his party had prevented him from fulfilling the
expectations of a small faction of intellectual revisionists who had looked
to him to lead their offensive against the orthodox party leadership. Auer's
assessment of Bernstein's weakness as a political leader and his willingness
to subordinate personal ambitions to party interests, proved to be right on
the mark: "Good OP Ede is a loyal comrade with whom I've fought
shoulder to shoulder; but he surely is no new messiah. As long as he
remains the leader of the so-called 'revisionists' we can all rest in peace, for
he will make sure that they never hit the jackpot."43 Two decades later,
Gustav Mayer, a prominent historian of the German labor movement,
concurred with Auer's semi-facetious observations:
Even in his young years, Bernstein lacked the qualities of a statesman . .. He is too
unpragmatic, too thoughtful; he has never been an homme d'action. He is not a
charismatic speaker of Bebel's or Jaures's caliber who can excite the masses; and
even less does he make afinediplomat who must be a master of hiding his true
intentions.44
The logical outcome of all that Bernstein stands for should be a break with the
principles of Marxism - the materialist conception of history, the theory of surplus
value, and the principles and strategy of the SPD. However, for understandable
tactical reasons, Bernstein refuses to finish this break by tearing apart the whole
Marxist edifice. Instead, he shrewdly pretends that his theory helps "evolving"
Marxism. In other words, Bernstein ultimately proclaims that it is after all Marx
who reasserts himself against Marx.51
49
Eduard Bernstein, Die heutige Sozialdemokratie in Theorie und Praxis (Munich: Birk,
1905).
50
Max Lorenz, "Marx-Bernstein-Kautsky," in Preussische Jahrbucher 96 (1899), p. 344.
51
Ibid., p. 330.
52
Austin Harrison, "Socialism and Bernstein," in Fortnightly Review 71 (1902), p. 137.
Facing the critics 165
example of the new wave of negative assessments of Bernstein's theoreti-
cal model from bourgeois journalists who had often unwittingly entangled
themselves in the terminology of Bernstein's radical opponents: "Where
Marx is fatalistic, Bernstein is opportunist."53 Moreover, Harrison
developed an argument which was to become a common feature of the
dominant interpretation of Bernstein's evolutionary socialism. Claiming
that Bernstein's important essays on scientific socialism "contained little
that had not already been suggested in his previous work," the British
writer assumed an early closure on Bernstein's contribution to socialist
thought.54 Writing in 1902, Harrison mistakenly considered Bernstein's
theoretical achievements already a thing of the past.
Yet, like Rosa Luxemburg, the British observer could not help but
acknowledge the obvious constructive ramifications emerging from Bern-
stein's attack on Marxist historicism and economic determinism. Indeed,
Harrison referred to Bernstein's theoretical efforts as instrumental in
creating an attractive "vista of purified rational socialism" which ac-
knowledged the role of the individual and the importance of free agency in
the realm of politics.55 Finding Bernstein's "valiant efforts" to combat
Marxist dogmatism "worthwhile," Harrison added that revisionism
might turn out to be just as Utopian in its vision as Marxism. While
Marxism glorified insurrectionary violence, Bernstein's evolutionary
socialism might eventually disintegrate into pure opportunism.56
To his credit, Harrison's conclusion proved to be extremely prophetic.
He managed to touch upon the three fundamental predicaments of
twentieth-century socialist theory which were brought into sharper focus
by Bernstein's new perspective: the faltering Marxist monopoly on the
meaning of socialism; the necessary clarification of the relationship
between liberalism and socialism; and the problem of the instrumentalist
("opportunist") impulse inherent in any reformism.
53 54 55 56
Ibid., p . 1 2 9 . Ibid., p . 1 3 3 . Ibid., p . 137. Ibid.
166 Disappointment
excellent position with the burgeoning journal., Sozialistische Monatshefte
(The Socialist Monthly), edited by his party comrade Joseph Bloch, an
open sympathizer with the revisionist cause.57 A few years later, Bernstein
expanded his journalistic activities by assuming the position of Berlin
correspondent of the left-liberal London weekly, The Nation.
Bernstein's professional relationship to Sozialistische Monatshefte and its
various "revisionist" contributors, ranging in ideology from "nationalist
socialists" to "ethical socialists," signified the beginning of a new phase in
his intellectual development: the formulation of his "mature" revision-
ism, refined in the course of many years in response to both theoretical
challenges and practical problems arising from the daily business of
observing, organizing, and coordinating the activities of a mass move-
ment. Though not recognized by the SPD as an "official party organ,"
Bloch's journal was widely read by party members and soon surpassed the
circulation of Kautsky's Neue Zeit. Over the next fifteen years, Bernstein
published some of his most important theoretical essays in Sozialistische
Monatshefte. No doubt, Bloch and his staff provided Bernstein with an
appropriate public forum for his political ideas.
Soon after Bernstein joined Sozialistische Monatshefte, his ideological
Wende found its external expression in a dramatic change in his private
life. Paul Nathan, a left-liberal editor, and his old friend, party secretary
Ignaz Auer (who had both worked secretly for years on getting his arrest
warrant repealed), managed to orchestrate Bernstein's return to Ger-
many. Their extensive lobbying efforts finally paid off when German
Chancellor Prince Bernhard von Biilow reluctantly agreed to let Be-
rnstein's arrest warrant lapse in the hope that his return to Germany
would continue to test the organizational strength of the labor movement.
Conservative journalists praised von Billow's shrewd move, and, in
seeking to intensify the SPD's predicament, demanded that Bernstein be
given a teaching post at a major university.58 However, the suggestion that
a "socialist autodidact" should receive preferential treatment so aroused
the wrath of the academic establishment, that serious negotiations
regarding a possible appointment were never initiated. It was not until
after World War I that Bernstein would be invited to give extensive guest
lectures at the University of Berlin.
Having grown deeply attached to their life in England as well as their
57
Sozialistische Monatshefte proclaimed itself "an independent organ for all viewpoints
based on the common ground of socialism." Originating as a periodical of socialist
academics, SM ultimately advanced to become one of the most significant journals of
pre-World War I German social democracy. For a more detailed history of SM, see
Fletcher, Revisionism and Empire; and Pierson, Marxist Intellectuals and the Working Class
Mentality in Germany, 1887-1912.
58
Helmuth von Gerlach in Welt am Montag (May 20, 1901).
Facing the critics 167
numerous social acquaintances in London, the first reaction of the
Bernsteins to the "good news" from Germany was "less joy than dismay,
and the subsequent farewell to London was truly grievous to both of
us." 59 Bernstein clearly was of two minds on this issue: on one hand, he
cherished the thought of becoming actively involved in the German labor
movement again, while on the other, he felt a genuine affection for the flair
of late-Victorian Britain. After a lavish farewell dinner organized in
Bernstein's honor by labor leader Ramsay MacDonald, Ede and Gine set
out for an uncertain future in their home country, eventually settling in a
sleepy Berlin suburb.
Although the SPD leadership officially welcomed back their "battle-
tested comrade," Bernstein's new role in the party was far from clear.
After all, he had not been a major player on the domestic scene for over
twenty years. Deprived of his valuable contacts with the major party
publications and shunned by most of his former friends, the fifty-year-
old socialist veteran did not even hold an official position within the
party. What would his future role be? Could he afford to continue his
criticism without facing still more serious sanctions from Bebel and
Kautsky?
One thing was certain: during these first months of the new century,
Bernstein expressed nofixedplans or clear intentions, choosing instead to
adopt a cautious strategy of responding to developments as they unfolded.
And indeed, within two years of his return, Bernstein slipped into his dual
role in the German labor movement: leading revisionist theorist and
elected Reichstag representative.
Obviously, from close up, the masses look very differentfromwhat a well-meaning
romantic takes them to be. But how can it be otherwise after centuries of
mistreatment under slave holders, feudal domination, and industrial exploitation?
It is the declared purpose of our movement to improve this situation. But whoever
71
See Eduard Bernstein, Der politische Massenstreik und die politische Lage der Sozialdemok-
ratie in Deutschland (Berlin, 1906); Der Streik (Frankfurt: Riitten & Loning, 1906); and
"Politischer Massenstreik und Revolutionsromantik," in SM 10 (1906), pp. 12-20.
72
PS, p. 35.
174 Disappointment
sees this task naively as that of a noble prince who simply has to awaken the
prodigal sleeping beauty called "the people," is gravely mistaken about the task
ahead of us.73
While Bernstein refused to abandon "class" as a critical analytic concept,
his evolutionary "revision" of the Marxist theory of class struggle actually
predates some important insights offered by Max Weber and Robert
Michels a few years later. Reacting against Marx's narrow conceptual
scheme, which reduced the sociological complexity of reality to compre-
hensive terms like "class struggle/' Bernstein claimed that "class/' as a
sociological genus, needed more defining elements than purely economic
categories like the "ownership of the means of production." Observing
the rapid growth of the "middle class," he argued strongly in favor of
including social characteristics like "status," "education," and "pres-
tige" as well. Moreover, he felt that the increasing diversification of the
class structure under modern conditions facilitated a "gradual lifting of
the general cultural level," making class struggles of the future very
different from those of the past. Formulated in a liberal language of rights
and waged in formal political institutions like the legislature and the
courts, "class struggles" themselves would "evolve," becoming less
violent and more "civilized" in character.
At the same time, Bernstein was careful not to turn his evolutionary
socialism into another deterministic Weltanschauung by emphasizing that
there was no absolute guarantee for a steady progressive development,
since unforeseen "social conditions might emerge that could throw us
back into a time of barbarism and struggle."74 Although he reaffirmed the
basic character of the SPD as a "proletarian party," he also emphasized its
potential to transform itself gradually into a more inclusive "people's
party" with an inherent responsibility to welcome all those elements who
acknowledged the social needs of the working class as the crucial red
thread connecting the political demands of social democracy. For Bern-
stein, "class" therefore entailed an ideal component which served as an
organizing principle for all members of society who subscribed to a
socialist ethic. Whoever rejected the universalism expressed in the
concrete demands of the working class should stay outside social democ-
racy.75 Following Bernstein's lead, contemporary political theorist
Stephen Eric Bronner highlights the importance of such a "class ideal," a
"revisionist" notion that is once again receiving new consideration in
current socialist theory.76
73
Auer cited in Bernstein, Ignaz Auer, p. 72.
74
Bernstein, Zur Geschichte und Theorie des Sozialismus III, pp. 50-51.
75
Bernstein, "Hat der Liberalismus eine Zukunft in Deutschland," in Bernstein A, El 12.
76
See, for example, Bronner, Socialism Unbound, pp. 161-168.
Facing the critics 175
Though ultimately incapable of convincing the party leadership to
endorse the formation of promising temporary coalitions on the state
level, Bernstein's calls for a "consequent reformism" nonetheless began
to take concrete shape in a series of constructive critiques of the theoretical
portion of the 1891 Erfurt Program.77 These efforts culminated in a
well-attended 1909 Amsterdam lecture on the principles of revisionism
whose published version includes a fairly detailed blueprint for a new,
"reformist" party program. Entitled "Guiding Principles for the Theor-
etical Portion of a Social Democratic Party Program," the tract suggests,
among other things, the removal of "unscientific passages" dogmatically
predicting the doom of capitalist society.78 Instead, Bernstein's own draft
defined any party program as merely reflecting the movement's "socialist
ill": i.e., the theoretical expression of the ethical principles and concrete
demands of social democracy.79 Arguing that "revisionism translated into
the political realm means consequent reformism," Bernstein's proposals
represent the blueprint of an evolutionary socialism that consciously
confined the party's programmatic language to the task of linking socialist
ideals with concrete political demands. However, in the decades ahead,
Bernstein's "principled reformism" would fare just as badly as Engels'
scientific-socialist Weltanschauung, which Bernstein had helped to demol-
ish. Increasingly subordinating ethical principles to instrumentalist and
nationalist concerns, German social democrats would begin to lose its
interest in any theoretical blueprint at all.
77
See chapter 7 for more on this topic.
78
Eduard Bernstein, "Der Revisionismus in der Sozialdemokratie," in Heimann, Ein
revisionistisches Sozialismusbild, pp. 91-136.
79
Ibid., p. 132.
The revisionist debate extended
176
The revisionist debate extended 177
Yet, ever the social optimist, Bernstein refused to abandon his conviction
that German political forces of democracy would eventually find common
parliamentary strategies.
As he saw it, economic growth, the formation of genuinely left-liberal
bourgeois parties, and the evolutionary logic of parliamentary democracy
were intrinsically connected, pulling Gemany towards liberal democracy.
This overall Gestalt of his evolutionary socialism was also reflected in his
historical studies. With little time to spare from his onerous task as a
Reichstag representative, Bernstein used every spare hour to complete his
cherished literary project on the history of the German labor movement,
From Sect to Party: German Social Democracy Past and Present, the popular
version of his more scholarly volume, The Labor Movement.2 These studies
represent impressive examples of Bernstein's remarkable talents as a
social historian. Emphasizing the German labor movement's role in the
struggle for political and social rights, Bernstein recounted the slow
evolution of social democracy. Starting with the abstract ideology of
small, sectarian labor Utopias that relied upon emancipatory schemes
designed to liberate "humanity" from "wage slavery," he quickly moved
to a discussion of the concrete political objectives of a growing industrial
working class, "not bound to rules passed down by tradition, but
increasingly choosing its own social forms according to the ever-changing
conditions of political and economic life."3
Praising the educational function of parliamentary activity for the
"organic development of a proletarian civic consciousness," Bernstein
indulged in a rather optimistic assessment of the "democratic process" in
the German Empire, an evaluation that recurred two years later in his
extensive historical volume detailing the experience of the German tailors'
movement.4 Some passages in these studies suggest that he was more
concerned with keeping alive his hopes for social progress via the
parliamentary road, than with an accurate description of recalcitrant
Prussian authoritarianism and the political rule of the Junkers. On the
other hand, political and economic conditions did seem to improve in the
first years of the new century. Foremost were the record-breaking results
of the 1903 general elections, in which the SPD captured more than three
million votes and eighty-one seats in the Reichstag. Bernstein read the
elections as an encouraging sign that, even under the repressive conditions
of a military state, the rudimentary liberalism manifest in Germany's
political system could gradually be developed in British fashion.
2
Bernstein, Die Arbeiterbewegung.
3
Bernstein, Von der Sekte zur Partei, p. 5.
4
Bernstein, Die Arbeiterbewegung, p. 169; and Geschichte der deutschen Schneiderbewegung
(Berlin: Verband der Schneider, 1913).
178 Disappointment
Emerging as the second strongest party in the country, the SPD was
entitled to place one of its own in the post of First Vice-President of the
Reichstag, an office that would force the social democrats to abandon
their traditional refusal to pay an official courtesy visit to the emperor.
Bebel, anticipating a favorable proposal from his party's right-wing
faction, made abundantly clear his strong opposition to even such
"symbolic" gestures of socialist "integration" into the authoritarian
German "system." Predictably, Bernstein not only disagreed, but once
again emerged as spokesman for the revisionist dissenters. Insisting that
attending a purely formal ceremony with no political consequences
should not be interpreted as a "glorification of the monarchist principle,"
he went on to compare some aspects of the emperor's status with the office
of a republican president.5 Although he was obviously referring to the
symbolism of representation rather than the representative principle,
Bernstein's arguments could be taken as a call to compromise the SPD's
principled stand for democracy. The ensuing bitter debate over a possible
socialist vice-presidency was another impressive example of Bernstein's
ability to cause "trouble" within the party ranks. This time, however, the
roles were reversed: Bebel refused to separate his principles from political
expediency, while Bernstein, the fervent adherent to Kantian ethics, fell
prey to the shallow instrumentalism of tactical compromise.
Even worse, Bernstein inadvertently emboldened brash Praktiker like
Georg von Vollmar to use his revisionist arguments to further their own
political careers. With an eye on the Bavarian state parliament, Vollmar
proposed that the party also permit the immediate candidacy of social
democrats for all leading offices in state Diets. Refusing to accept Bebel's
guidelines, the feisty Bavarian also demanded an official SPD resolution
in favor of claiming the office of Reichstag president in case of a future
all-out electoral victory. Vollmar's incendiary style, and the considerable
political skills he exhibited in orchestrating support for his position alerted
Bebel to the seriousness of the new conflict. Realizing that revisionism
could no longer be "contained" by focusing on Bernstein alone, he agreed
with Kautsky on the need for a firmer response. It was clear that
revisionisms - ranging from Bernstein's evolutionary socialism to Voll-
mar's atheoretical reformism - had burgeoned into a powerful threat to
orthodox Marxist theory, and thereby to Bebel's and Kautsky's own
leadership positions in the SPD hierarchy. For his part, Kautsky believed
that only a swift and aggressive counterattack led by the charismatic Bebel
himself would stop the further rise of "petty-bourgeois socialism."
Deliberately employing Vollmar's challenge as an opportunity to set a
5
Eduard Bernstein, "Was folgt aus dem Ergebnisder Reichstagswahlen?," in SM 7 (1903),
p. 479.
The revisionist debate extended 179
warning example for future revisionist incursions, Bebel rose to the
occasion and demanded from his party the unambiguous condemnation
of all forms of revisionism.
Confident that "the tables could be cleared once and for all," he chose
the upcoming 1903 Dresden Party Conference as the ideal forum in which
to deal revisionists a decisive blow. Kautsky, having taken a verbal beating
at the previous party conference from Heine and Bernstein for his
"narrow dogmatism" and his "authoritarian leadership-style as editor of
Neue Zeit,"6 claimed he was "sick and tired of continuing to fight
revisionism for the next five years behind closed doors" and eagerly
awaited Bebel's "clear marching orders."7 Ready to issue those orders,
the party leader opened the Dresden proceedings with unusually blunt
demands for greater ideological conformity. In order to illustrate his case,
Bebel cited "disturbances" caused by various "opportunist" literary
contributions of "revisionist authors" to bourgeois publications. Coming
down hard on the "detached intellectualism" of those "abstract ma-
rauders" who had fallen on "the back of the party," Bebel employed his
battle-tested rhetoric of "proper class origins" in preparation for his
attack on Vollmar's "opportunism."8
Despite a determined fight put up by Bernstein and other revisionist
intellectuals who pleaded for "freedom of expression," Bebel's strategy
evinced its desired effects.9 Most delegates agreed with their leader that
"too much openness" could severely undermine party unity as well as
hurt the SPD's ability to expand its vital working-class base. Scenting total
victory, the agile party leader quickly turned against Bernstein's and
Vollmar's political demands for a possible SPD vice-presidency. To his
surprise, however, Bebel ran into a series of determined defense speeches
led by Vollmar, who minced no words in accusing him and Kautsky of
using the "dictatorial language of fanaticism and authoritarianism," and
of "trampling on the sacred right of freedom of speech and criticism."10
Several delegates verbally supported Vollmar, and the atmosphere in the
conference hall turned suddenly hostile. For the first time since the 1875
Gotha Unification Conference, the party found itself on the brink of a
politically disastrous split.
Counting on his personal reputation in the labor movement, Bebel
6
Protokoll uber die Verhandlungen des Parteitages der Sozialdemokratischen Partei Deutschlands,
abgehalten zu Miinchen, abgehaltenvom 14-20September 1902 (Berlin, 1902), pp. 121-126.
7
Kautsky cited in EB, p. 92.
8
Bebel quoted in Pierson, Marxist Intellectuals and the Working-Class Mentality in Germany,
1887-1912, p. 165.
9
See, for example, Georg Bernhard, "Parteimoral," in DieZukunft (January 10,1903), pp.
79-80.
10
Vollmar cited in Protokoll 1903 Dresden Party Conference, pp. 334-339.
180 Disappointment
responded with an emotional appeal for support while at the same time
attacking Bernstein's "bourgeois" language of rights. Now it became clear
why Bebel had opened his remarks with a consideration of "proper class
origins." In their constant appeals for the "right to free expression,"
Bernstein and his revisionist comrades had opened themselves up to the
orthodox Marxist charge that they had deserted "socialist" principles in
favor of "bourgeois" liberalism.11 In the end, Vollmar's speech was not
enough to rally the party behind his proposals. Shamed into a pro forma
affirmation of Bebel's class criteria, most delegates expressed their
support of his leadership and resoundingly approved two separate
resolutions: one condemning future contributions of SPD members to the
bourgeois press without "proper reflection"; the other emphatically
rejecting "the various revisionist strategies to alter our sound and
victorious principle of class struggle."12 On the surface, at least, it seemed
that Bebel and Kautsky had decisively defeated their old nemesis. The
delegates to the Dresden Conference declared the Revisionist Contro-
versy ended; Bernstein's and Vollmar's "heresies" were pronounced
dead. Orthodox Marxists had salvaged the old Erfurt dogma of increasing
class antagonisms while reaffirming their oppositional politics of "splen-
did isolation" - the fundamental rejection of social democratic participa-
tion in any non-socialist government.13 With only eleven delegates
objecting, it was easy for Kautsky to fill various party papers with
triumphant articles about the "final demise" of revisionism.
Encouraged by the results of their "hardline tactics," Kautsky and
Bebel were eager to narrow further the parameters of acceptable dissent,
and thus continued their battle aimed at the systematic isolation of
revisionists.14 For example, they supported the demotion of the promi-
nent neo-Kantian ethical socialist, Kurt Eisner, who, along with some of
his like-minded comrades, was removed from his influential position as
editor of Vorwarts for purely ideological reasons.15 A few years later,
Gerhard Hildebrand, a revisionist expert on international relations,
suffered an even worse fate from Bebel's and Kautsky's internal "party
purge."
Hildebrand had argued that the rapid internationalization of business
and trade was preventing the socialization of the entire production
11
See Schorske, German Social Democracy 1905-1917, p. 25.
12
Protokoll, 1903 Dresden Party Conference, pp. 300-345.
13
Dieter Dowe and Kurt Klotzbach, eds. Programmatische Dokumente der deutschen
Sozialdemokratie (Berlin: Dietz, 1973), pp. 182-183.
14
See John L. Snell, The Democratic Movement in Germany 1789-1914 (Chapel Hill:
University of North Carolina Press, 1976), p. 291.
15
SeePierson, Marxist Intellectuals and the Working-Class Mentality in Germany, 1887-1912,
pp. 176-185.
The revisionist debate extended 181
process. Like Bernstein, Hildebrand foresaw the co-existence of "mixed
forms of economy" for many years to come. Moreover, he publicly
defended Germany's "right to colonies." Publishing the results of his
statistical analysis in various revisionist party papers, he pointed to the
rapid emergence of an intense international struggle over shrinking global
economic resources.16 Championing the interests of the "German
workers" at the expense of the party's "abstract internationalism,"
Hildebrand seemed to subscribe to a new version of Naumann's national-
ist coalition between social democracy and the German bourgeoisie.
Greeted with sharp rebukes from the orthodox party press and lacking
Bernstein's prominent stature, Hildebrand was summarily expelled from
the SPD, after being cited by the Executive Committee for his "flagrant
violation of the party program's principles." Though strongly disapprov-
ing of Hildebrand's ethnonationalism and his vocal support of German
Weltpolitik, Bernstein was unable to suppress his own "liberal" outrage at
the breach of procedural justice and came to Hildebrand's defense. He
chided the party for compromising the most basic demands for openness
in scientific research, and for violating the "cherished principle" of
a broad representation of diverse opinions in the SPD.17 Encouraged
by Bernstein's statement of support, Hildebrand appealed his expulsion
and earned the right to another hearing at the 1912 Chemnitz Party
Conference.
In the meantime, however, after long discussions with his more
orthodox comrades, Bernstein arrived at the conclusion that Hildebrand
had indeed gone beyond the results of his own "scientific analysis" and
was actually disavowing the very socialist ideals that constituted the
partisan core of the international labor movement. True to his method-
ological dualism, which separated "sciencific statements of fact" from
"legitimate party directives to demand from its members the strict
adherence to the ethical ideals of the movement," Bernstein reversed his
opinion on the "Hildebrand Affair" and openly supported the expulsion
verdict of the party court.
However, in these last few years of the Wilhelmine Empire, orthodox
Marxists increasingly found their "ideological victories" being under-
mined by the growing need to tolerate the Praktiker so as to maintain party
unity. As Stanley Pierson has noted, this dilemma ultimately pushed
Marxist doctrine into theoretical exhaustion, giving it a purely "defens-
ive" and "apologetic" function.18 As the labor movement grew, the
16
Gerhard Hildebrand, Sozialistische Aussenpolitik (Jena: Diederichs, 1911).
17
Eduard Bernstein, "Darf Hildebrand ausgeschlossen werden?," in SM 16 (1912), pp.
1,147-1,150.
18
Pierson, Marxist Intellectuals and the Working-Class Mentality in Germany, p. 227.
182 Disappointment
ideological purity of Kautsky's Marxism had to be sacrificed on the cold
altar of political expediency. Social democracy began to speak in many
different tongues, giving credence to Bebel's complaint that the ideologi-
cal and tactical differences in the party had never been greater.19 The
orthodox rhetoric at the Dresden Party Conference and the "Hildebrand
Affair" notwithstanding, Bernstein's arguments were still alive and the
"Revisionist Controversy" was far from over.
"Noble patriotism"
Bernstein rejected any strategy which would elevate German nationalism
and make it attractive to a working class searching to fill the ideological
void left behind by an increasingly ossified Marxism.67 Still, it was clear
that in the decades following Engels' death, Bernstein had moved away
from the orthodox Marxist internationalism he had espoused in his early
articles in Der Sozialdemokrat. For example, he criticized Marx for his
lacking understanding of the powerful influence of nationalism on all
social classes, including the proletariat.68 Seeking to address better this
powerful phenomenon, Bernstein included in his own theory of national-
ism psychological and ideological elements like "ethnic resentment" and
the desire for the "satisfaction of an ethnic sense of superiority"in
addition to economic factors.69 Most of all, he objected to BebePs and
Kautsky's defeatist strategy of dealing with the national question by
invoking a "meaningless" Marxist Utopia in an "internationalist socialist
future" which would make the issue of nationalism irrelevant.70 In a series
of essays, Bernstein outlined his views on nationalism in his characteristic
"moderate" fashion: "It is necessary to avoid both the Scylla of eth-
nonationalism and the Charybdis of an amorphous internationalism."71
He began his arguments by reminding his comrades that the formation
of the post-eighteenth-century modern nation state depended on its
citizens' "natural feelings of love for their own country and their
people."72 Yet, unlike the pure sentiments of primordial solidarity
observed in tribal societies during earlier cultural stages, modern national-
67
Eduard Bernstein, "Die Massen werden irre," in SM 13 (1909), pp. 1,012-1,018.
68
Eduard Bernstein, "Einige Klippen der Internationalist," in SM 5 (1901), p. 255.
69
Eduard Bernstein, "Handelspolitik und Volkerbeziehung," in Sozialdemokratische Vol-
kerpolitik, pp. 167-178.
70
Eduard Bernstein, "Die deutsche Sozialdemokratie und die tiirkischen Wirren," in NZ
15.1 (1896/97), p. 110.
71
Eduard Bernstein, "Geburtenriickgang, Nationalist, und Kultur," SM 17 (1913), p.
1,497. For an excellent discussion of Bernstein's nationalist perspective, see Hans
Mommsen, "Nationalismus und die nationale Frage im Denken Eduard Bernsteins," in
H e i m a n n a n d M e y e r , Bernstein und der demokratische Sozialismus, p p . 1 3 1 - 1 4 8 .
72
Eduard Bernstein, "Patriotismus und Klassenkampf," in Sozialistische Volkerpolitik, p.
134.
198 Disappointment
ism also harbored a progressive element manifested in the sociological
function of modern "organically developed social organisms" to defend
their integrity, independence, and cultural distinctiveness without im-
peding each others' drive toward higher forms of social complexity.73 In
other words, Bernstein identified an "evolutionary," sociological function
of nationalism, which he called "noble patriotism," as opposed to
"anachronistic," pre-modern forms of solidarity. The former was anchor-
ed in his general acceptance of the nation state as the most approporiate
form of modern social organization and in optimistic assumptions
regarding the steady growth of economic and political interdependence
through international commerce, the rising importance of international
law, and the expected evolution of democratic socialism.
As expressions of the "spirit of the modern age," these modern
developments were bound to strengthen the citizens' "noble patriotic
sentiments" as well as their cosmopolitan feelings of respect for, and
cooperation with other nations.74 "Noble patriotism" was the highest
expression of the "civic impulse" that would ultimately connect all groups
of society under the leadership of the working class. This definition
resembles "Constitutional Patriotism," a concept coined by the contem-
porary German philosopher Jurgen Habermas: only in this sense did
Bernstein expect socialism to be "nationalist."75
But in order to fulfill their civic duty to defend their nation state against
natural and social threats, citizens were entitled to full political liberty.
Most importantly, genuine forms of popular sovereignty had to be
introduced through universal and equal suffrage. As long as the German
government prevented the extension of the democratic principle to all
social classes, it pandered to the power interests of the Junkers in the name
of the "fatherland," while stifling social democratic efforts to establish an
international community of civilized peoples.76 As soon as the logic of
representative democracy was reflected in political institutions, the
proletariat gradually began to acquire legitimate "national interests" in
the form of "national rights and duties." Far from merely "tolerating"
nationalism, Bernstein saw it as the duty of the party to strengthen such
nationalist principles like "the maintenance of the nation's effective
self-defense against aggressors."77
73
Eduard Bernstein, "Patriotismus, Militarismus und Sozialdemokratie," in SM 11
(1907), pp. 435-437.
74
Eduard Bernstein, "Wie Fichte und Lassalle national waren," in Archiv fiir die Geschichte
des Sozialismus und der Arbeiterbewegung 5 (1915), p. 161; and Bernstein, "Patriotismus
und Klassenkampf," pp. 130-136.
75
Bernstein, "Patriotismus, Militarismus und Sozialdemokratie," p. 437.
76
Ibid.
77
Ibid., pp. 439^140.
The revisionist debate extended 199
For Bernstein, "nationalism" was not an ideological ploy "invented"
by the bourgeoisie in order to perpetuate exploitative economic relations.
Any efforts aimed at indoctrinating the proletariat with abstract interna-
tionalist principles would run aground on the workers' natural emotional
attachment to Germany. The Marxist slogan of the "proletariat without a
fatherland" was only valid as long as some segments of the population
were systematically denied access to political power. The retention of the
SPD's "mushy cosmopolitanism" would result in pushing the proletariat
into the arms of nationalist fanatics while also failing to attract progressive
segments of the bourgeoisie.78 As the 1907 elections showed, the SPD
could no longer ignore the formation of a proletarian "nationalist
consciousness;" the point was to keep it from turning toward exclusivist
notions of race and ethnicity.79
Thus, Bernstein also acknowledged the existence of a second, "per-
verted" form of nationalism, which he called volkischer Nationalisms, or
"ethnonationalism."80 As Bernstein saw it, the latter was built on
scientifically questionable categories that essentialized language, race,
and heredity, and supported a politically reactionary turn to pre-industrial
forms of solidarity. The justification of nation states on the basis of ethnic
purity not only contradicted Bernstein's cherished humanitarian ideals,
but also harbored a dangerous logic of exclusivism that remained blind to
the ethical purpose of the national idea as ultimately serving the ends of
humanity.81
On this issue, however, Bernstein ran into a serious conceptual
dilemma: how could he be so sure that the German proletariat would cling
to the "healthy, noble" brand of nationalism and not its pernicious ethnic
cousin? Unfortunately, he never clarified this crucial theme. Instead, with
his characteristic evolutionary optimism, Bernstein declared eth-
nonationalism as a merely "artificial and pathological aberration" - a
relatively short-lived phenomenon that would find its certain demise in
the hands of the "noble patriotism" championed by the working class. On
this issue, Bernstein seems to have forsaken his empiricist skepticism for
an almost "Marxian" determinism by closing his eyes to the fact that
ethnonationalism, both within and without the SPD, was rapidly acquir-
ing strength. Were not his frequent literary battles with ultranationalist
revisionists and his increasing alienation from the chauvinistic circle
around Sozialistische Monatshefte editors like Bloch and Leuthner a clear
reminder of the growing attraction of the supposed "aberration?"
78
Bernstein, "Die internationale Politik der Sozialdemokratie," in SM 13 (1909), p. 615.
79
Ibid., pp. 614-615.
80
Bernstein, "Patriotismus, Militarismus, und Sozialdemokratie," p. 437.
81
Bernstein, "Wie Fichte und Lassalle national waren," p. 150.
200 Disappointment
Bernstein remained far too sanguine about the supposed demise of
ethnonationalism in the long run: "In all countries where the working class
assumes political significance, it develops a new, socialist variant of
patriotism. This patriotism can never legitimate the domination of one
nationality by another; rather, it leads to the realization of equal,
democratic rights."82 In fact, he could not produce empirical evidence for
such evolutionary assumptions. Exchanging Marx's internationalist-rev-
olutionary dogmatism for his own equally mechanistic-evolutionary
Utopia of a "noble patriotism," Bernstein displayed a rationalist optimism
which assumed that the ethical appeal to "practical reason" would
ultimately be reciprocated by the masses. He was overly confident that the
working class had the capacity to weigh rationally the arguments of both
sides and ultimately sanction the "middle way" he had found, one that
viewed the German nation as a "link in the organic chain of international
civilization; independent vis-a-vis other nations on the basis of an
international democratic equality of rights and duties."83
As far as the short-term consequences of ethnonationalism were con-
cerned, however, Bernstein did grasp its ominous consequences, includ-
ing the possibility of an impending war of unknown proportions: "There
is today no reaction so dangerous as the exuberance of the national spirit.
Without exaggeration, one might call this phenomenon the mother of all
reactionisms, for all are incorporated in it."84 In the same vein, he
condemned the imperialist policies of the "Prussian militaristic elite,
detached from its own people" as a backward step in cultural develop-
ment.85
Overall, the practical consequences of Bernstein's "noble nationalism"
were unmistakably clear: it surely played into the hands of nationalist
revisionists who had long demanded an adjustment of "abstract interna-
tionalism" to the "concrete patriotic sentiments of the ordinary German
worker." The German liberals ridiculed his "noble patriotism," embrac-
ing instead at least parts of the government's ethnonationalist propaganda
with its anti-Semitic undertones. Only when directly confronted with
their aggressive rhetoric couched within the framework of German
Weltpolitik did Bernstein seem to recognize the magnitude of the problem:
"But what disheartens one with the German Liberals is that they are
opportunists in their ways of thinking and arguing. One can hardlyfinda
82
Bernstein, "Patriotismus, Militarismus, und Sozialdemokratie," p. 438.
83
Bernstein, "Die internationale Politik der Sozialdemokratie," p. 615.
84
Bernstein, "Geburtenriickgang, Nationalist, und Kultur," p. 1,497. See also Bernstein's
critique of the arms race that might end in a "terrible catastrophe" (Bernstein cited in EB,
p. 128).
85
Bernstein, "Patriotismus, Militarismus und Sozialdemokratie," p. 439.
The revisionist debate extended 201
consistent Free Trader amongst them. How can one expect to find a
consistent peace politician?"86
In particular, Bernstein was referring to the national-liberals as well as
Friedrich Naumann's resistance to a German-British disarmament pact.
Retreating to a classical Marxist position, he began to argue that the
increasing jingoism of upper-class German liberalism was not merely
ideological but practical, because of its material connection to the rapidly
growing German military-industrial complex.87 Only in such lonely
moments of bitter disappointment, did Bernstein allow himself to see
some wisdom in Kautsky's long-held conviction that Germany's only way
out of political authoritarianism and the escalating arms race might be,
after all, a proletarian-based "revolutionary upheaval."88
In the long run, however, such sentiments passed, and Bernstein
returned to his more fitting role of the optimistic apostle of gradualism
and evolutionary socialism. Despite the depressing fact that even moder-
ate academics and public intellectuals were beginning to preach eth-
nonationalism, he refused to let go of his Enlightenment rationalism.
Surely, German people would "come to their senses" once the chauvin-
istic distortions and lies of the mainstream press were unmasked,
wouldn't they? True to his ethical ideals, Bernstein kicked off an
"educational campaign for political enlightenment," urging his British
and French political friends to join his cause and speak out against
ethnonationalism - especially now that the German Liberals had so
"cowardly abandoned this task."89 With unusual vehemence, he un-
leashed parliamentarian broadsides against the government's discrimina-
tory ethnic policies toward, for example, Polish minorities in Silesia.
Bernstein's impassioned indictments of the Crown Prince's hyper-
nationalist speeches brought vitriolic calls to order by the Conservative
President of the Reichstag.
When Erich von Falkenhayn, the popular German Secretary of War,
skillfully employed his ethnonationalist interpretation of J. G. Fichte's
famous Addresses to the German Nation in support of the government's
imperialist policies, Bernstein answered with a speech emphasizing the
liberal principles of the French Revolution embedded in Fichte's notion
of national self-determination: "Fichte's patriotism purported to educate
his people to liberty, to champion freedom. He was hostile to all
chauvinism, to all exaggerated nationalism. Fichte was a democrat, Fichte
86
Eduard Bernstein, "How the New Reichstag Will Look," in The Nation 10 (December
30, 1911), p. 551.
87
Eduard Bernstein, "The Marauders," in The Nation 13 (April 26, 1913), p. 142.
88
Eduard Bernstein, "Almighty, All-devouring Militarism," in The Nation 13 (April 5,
1913), p. 16.
89
Eduard Bernstein, "Social Insanity," in The Nation 10 (October 14, 1911), p. 94.
202 Disappointment
was a republican, and, insofar as the era allowed, Fichte was a socialist."90
Expanding his arguments, Bernstein published a lengthy essay, entitled
"The Nationalism of Fichte and Lassalle," in which he challenged the
Conservative minister's influential interpretation.91
In fact, it is likely that Bernstein's own basic assumption that patriotic
sentiments could coexist with a humanistic commitment to cosmopolitan
values emerged from an extremely sympathetic reading of Fichte's
political thought.92 Altogether bypassing the marked differences in the
radical writings of the young admirer of the French Revolution from the
more conservative essays of the anti-French defender of the "German
Idea" composed after Napoleon's 1806 victory at Jena, Bernstein readily
offered his own idiosyncratic translation of Fichte's seemingly paradoxical
concept of a "patriotic cosmopolitanism": "[It is] the sense of a noble
patriotism which seeks for its own people a respected status in a republic
of peoples without losing sight of the idea of a greater, composite
republic."93 Like Fichte's "dialectical" equation of "patriotism" with
"internationalism," Bernstein's "noble patriotism" differed markedly
from the Enlightenment understanding of cosmopolitanism proposed by
Kant and Schiller. By failing to acknowledge Fichte's questionable
dialectical reinterpretation of these key concepts, Bernstein remained
unaware that the Fichtean notion of a "cosmopolitan patriotism" was
sufficiently ambivalent to permit Minister Falkenhayn's ethnonationalist
demands for a "Greater Germany" based on Volkstum and linguistic
superiority.
When international tensions rose once again in the wake of Germany's
bellicose posture during the Second Moroccan Crisis of 1911, Bernstein
reacted sharply to the anti-British propaganda of those nationalists who
were equating the foreign policy objectives of his admired English system
with those of "Czarist despotism." As early as the 1890s, the German
government had commenced a gigantic naval buildup with the declared
goal of challenging the long-standing hegemony of the British navy.
Exploding its defense budget by nearly 400 percent in twelve years, Kaiser
Wilhelm's government encouraged the formation of a notoriously chau-
vinistic navy officer corps whose members took pride in contributing to
the government's highly effective public smear campaign against the
allegedly "anti-German politics of Great Britain." As one of the foremost
90
Bernstein cited in Roger Fletcher, "Revisionism and Nationalism: Eduard Bernstein's
Views on the National Question, 1900-1914," in Canadian Review of Studies in
Nationalism 11.1 (1984), p. 106.
91
Bernstein, "Wie Fichte und Lassalle national waren," pp. 143-162.
92
Ibid., p . 151; see also Eduard Bernstein, Von der Aufgabe der Juden im Weltkriege (Berlin:
Reiss, 1917), pp. 46-47.
93
Bernstein, "Wie Fichte und Lassalle national waren," p. 161.
The revisionist debate extended 203
experts on British politics in the Reichstag, Bernstein used the parliamen-
tary stage to warn publicly against the emperor's militaristic "politics of
the iron fist" against England. Reminding his socialist and bourgeois
colleagues of the beneficial trade relations between the two nations,
Bernstein emphasized that it would be "the most myopic and idiotic
politics to turn the great English nation into Germany's enemy."94
But since most ordinary German workers knew very little about British
culture or British politics, Bernstein's denouncements of the govern-
ment's vicious propaganda campaign fell on deaf ears. Even his short
1911 monograph, The English Peril and the German People, published by
the party press with Bebel's full support, remained too limited in its
outreach. From the very first lines, Bernstein attacked both Germany's
aggressive foreign policy and the ethnonationalist hardliners within his
own party. He condemned what he called the "irresponsible strategy of
Hetzpatrioten [hate patriots]" whose "criminal agitation" could lead to a
world-wide war.95 Only in his closing remarks did he return to a more
conciliatory attitude, suggesting the creation of a "Covenant of Peace
among the Nations," which, following Kant's call for the establishment of
"Perpetual Peace among Nations," would culminate in the application of
international law within the context of a "great European republic of
peoples."96
As might be expected, Bernstein's theory of "noble patriotism" turned
out to be too broadminded for most of his comrades, and he found himself
squeezed between Kautsky's abstract Marxist internationalism and the
aggressive ethnonationalism of his nationalist revisionist comrades. The
battle lines between Marxism and revisionism were drawn: Bernstein's
Aristotelian "middle position" on the national question drew nothing but
ridicule and contempt. Even his strong endorsement of the famous
resolution of the 1912 International Basle Conference, which called for a
coordinated revolutionary strategy among the European proletariat in the
case of war, failed to improve his tainted reputation in Left party circles
whose members regarded him as a "half-and-half supporter of German
imperialism."97 Neither did his pronounced anti-Russian sentiments
(occasionally even approaching Leuthner's slavophobic hysteria) increase
his influence on the nationalist-revisionist Weltpolitiker of the movement
which sought to wed German power politics with the imperialist goals of a
"socialist world policy."
94
Eduard Bernstein, Die englische Gefahr und das deutsche Volk (Berlin: Vorwdrts, 1911), p.
47.
95
Ibid., p . 4 5 .
96
Ibid., p. 48.
97
Georg Ledebour quoted in Fletcher, "Revisionism and Nationalism: Eduard Bernstein's
Views on the National Question, 1900-1914," p. 111.
204 Disappointment
Even his well-meaning symbolic gestures in favor of massive disarma-
ment and world peace provided ammunition for his critics. When
Bernstein helped to organize the Carnegie Endowment-sponsored
"Berne International Conference for the Facilitation of International
Peace/' he was immediately attacked by orthodox Marxists for letting
himself be coopted by "dirty imperialist money." Conversely, nationalist
revisionists ridiculed his mediating role as the deed of a sentimental
"Anglophile," oblivious to "legitimate German national interests." In the
end, Bernstein's search for alternatives to the rising tide of ethnonational-
ism left him with a theoretical model incapable of convincing either side
that internationalism and patriotism should, or even could, be reconciled.
In these last years before the outbreak of the Great War, it had become
clear that what had begun as the SPD's "Revisionist Controversy" had
turned into the "Nationalist Controversy" of German social democracy.
8 The dawn of a new era
1
Eduard Bernstein, "Vorwort des Herausgebers," in David Koigen, Die Kultur der
Demokratie (Jena: Diederichs, 1912), pp. iii-x.
2
For the development of various socialist views on colonial policy, see Hans-Christoph
Schroder, Sozialismus und Imperialismus (Bonn-Bad Godesberg: Verlag Neue Gesel-
lschaft, 1975); "Eduard Bernsteins Stellung zum Imperialismus vor dem Ersten Wel-
tkrieg," in Heimann and Meyer, Bernstein und der demokratische Sozialismus, pp. 166-212;
Fletcher, Revisionism and Empire, and Hyrkkanen, Sozialistische Kolonialpolitik.
3
Neue Rheinische Zeitung (September 10, 1848), in MEW 5, p. 395.
205
206 Disappointment
likelihood of colonial wars - a view shared by the "orthodox Bernstein" of
the early 1880s.4 For example, in 1884 Bernstein sharply denounced
Germany's participation in the scramble for colonies, arguing that
powerful trading companies would make huge profits on the backs of
indigenous populations and disadvantaged German workers. Moving to
London and falling under the influence of both Engels and the British
free-trade tradition, however, caused the young socialist to change his
perspective. He became acquainted with the "liberal imperialism" of
Lord Rosebury and Sir Edward Grey who speculated that the formation of
"white, democratic, and self-governing colonies" abroad might serve as a
catalyst for the expansion of the desired democratization process at home.
Increasingly affected by their arguments and impressed by the efficient
performance of the British colonial administration, Bernstein soon began
to distinguish among a "variety of quite different forms of imperialism,"
ultimately acknowledging the "positive cultural, political, and economic
effects" in its more "benign" manifestations.5 Having taken this initial
step, he could now proceed to develop the necessary theoretical argu-
ments in favor of an "acceptable socialist colonial policy."6
His change of heart swiftly drew the attention of the British Marxist
Belfort Bax, who, in his famous 1896-97 exchanges with the German
exile had condemned colonialism in any form. Indeed, the Bax-Bernstein
debates on foreign affairs marked the beginnings of what would explode
into the "Revisionist Controversy" of German social democracy. Bax
strongly endorsed a mild form of cultural relativism, stressing native
peoples' rights to maintain their traditional folkways and their own
cultural forms of expression, adding that European colonialist practices
would merely prolong capitalism's lease on life by exporting it around the
globe.7 Bernstein response was quick and harsh. He ridiculed Bax's
"naive Rousseauian ideal of the 'noble savage'" and shrewdly invoked the
authority of the "fathers of modern socialism" in support of his thesis
celebrating the "civilizing effects" of capitalist expansion.8 But unlike his
mentors, Bernstein employed economic arguments only as the final
element in a long chain of reasoning that originated in his Victorian
naturalism. In particular, his "socialist colonialism" was indissolubly
4
See, for example, Anonymous, "Marx iiber das Kolonialsystem," in Der Sozialdemokrat 28
(July 10, 1884).
5
Schroder, "Eduard Bernsteins Stellung zum Imperialismus vor dem Ersten Weltkrieg," in
Heimann and Meyer, Bernstein und der demokratische Sozialismus, p. 169.
6
See also Gerhard A. Ritter, Die Arbeiterbewegung im Wilhelminischen Reich (Berlin:
Colloquium, 1959), p. 194.
7
Bax, "Our German Fabian Convert; or, Socialism According to Bernstein;"and "The
Socialism of Bernstein," in MS, pp. 61-64, 69-74.
8
Eduard Bernstein, "Amongst the Philistines: A Rejoinder to Belfort Bax," in ibid., pp.
65-69.
The dawn of a new era 207
linked with his rather reductionistic biological-anthropological views on
sexuality and instincts.9
For Bernstein, human sexual behavior evolved from "animallike"
stages of "uncontrolled desires" to higher forms, where emerging econ-
omic, legal, and ethical impulses joined together to subject sexuality to
social rules, thus making it less driven by "natural necessity" and hence
more "rational" or "cultured."10 In the course of their evolution, humans
were moving through ever more pronounced cultural levels, emerging
from preliminary stages of "savagery," "barbarism," and "half-civiliza-
tion," to "advanced stages" of "civilization" where they supposedly
learned "to let their sensuality be sublimated by such activities and tastes
as intellectual training, physical self-discipline, and mental self-con-
trol."11 As a direct consequence of their uncontrolled sex drive, "sav-
ages" remained prisoners of non-rational forms of social interaction,
manifested as "superstition, vanity, and primitive play."12 Moreover,
they subscribed to a limited tribal ethic that conflicted with rational
universalism, the rule of secular law, and individual choice. Although he
underscored that "proper cultural development" manifested itself in the
"control of drives, not in their suppression" Bernstein nonetheless recom-
mended that (heterosexual) couples ought to subordinate sexual pleas-
ures to intellectual endeavors and the aesthetic refinement of taste,
thereby contributing to a "general uplifting" and thus the "evolution" of
their society's culture.13
With such a theory of cultural evolution as its theoretical foundation,
Bernstein's defense of "appropriate forms of socialist colonialism"
focused on the alleged "right of higher civilizations over that of lower
cultures," which he defended as a "hard-earned privilege" of societies
whose rationalism was reflected in advanced forms of economic
9
Eduard Bernstein's Victorian views on sexuality and sexual hygiene were obviously so
highly esteemed in the SPD that he was asked to put together an official SPD pamphlet on
sexuality and sexual hygiene, Der Geschlechtstrieb (Berlin: Vorwarts, 1920). In this
monograph, Bernstein naturalizes gender relations on the basis of sexual behavior: "The
male sexual drive is much stronger than that of the female" (pp. 13-15). Moreover, he
discusses, among other things, "abnormalities and perverted forms of sexuality," like
masturbation, homosexuality, sodomy, and sadism/masochism. In spite of his negative
judgment on homosexuality, Bernstein anticipated Wilhelm Reich's argument that
homosexuality was only partly pathological; mostly it was the product of "unhygienic
social conditions" which would disappear in the course of a "healthy" social development
toward heterosexuality. See, Eduard Bernstein, Bernstein on Homosexuality (London:
Athol Books, 1977), a translation of Bernstein's 1895 Neue Zeit essays on homosexuality in
the context of Oscar Wilde's famous trial.
10
Eduard Bernstein, Der Geschlechtstrieb, p. 9.
11
Ibid., p. 17.
12
Bernstein, "Materialistische Geschichtsauffassung und modernes Geschlechtsleben," n.
d., in Bernstein A, El20.
13
Bernstein, Der Geschlechtstrieb, pp. 17-18.
208 Disappointment
organization as well.14 Such "cultural rights" also implied the "moral
duty" of Western cultures to colonize the Third World, and - echoing the
famous provision in Locke's Second Treatise on Government - their
economic obligation to "improve the productivity of the land, lift its
population density, and advance technology."15 "Indolent savages"
lacked the cultural legitimacy to deny "more advanced peoples" access to
the dormant economic resources of their territories. Technological know-
how was the indispensable precondition for the "healthy evolution of the
forces of production" and thus the spread of civilization, "gradually"
leading to the socialization of the capitalist system. Indeed, Bernstein's
cultural Darwinism even justified the existence of violent struggles
between different cultures, which, no doubt, would end with the "self-
assertion of the higher civilization." The lesson for social democracy was
clear: "Socialists should finally accept the higher culture's ensuing
guardianship over the vanquished peoples and stop their romantic fight
against windmills." After all, Bernstein noted, "even the proletariat has
a legitimate interest in a reasonable geographical expansion of the
nation."16
The familiar Enlightenment theme endorsing the rational attainment of
human freedom through the subjugation of nature reappeared in Bern-
stein's theory of socialist colonialism as a "self-evident" cultural
injunction, for "culture" itself was defined as "the conscious dominance
of man over nature; the manifestation of the principle of individual
personality; and the refinement and diversification of proper tastes."17
Only by transcending the mechanical cause-effect operations of "blind
nature" in cooperative social arrangements could humans ultimately
approach the "socialist ideal."18 Similar to Marx's theory, Bernstein's
evolutionary socialism retained the crucial concept of rational economic
planning.
However, Bernstein's "right of the higher civilization" did not trans-
late into the realist paradigm of his nationalist-revisionist comrades,
who, literally, offered carte blanche for the vigorous pursuit of German
colonial interests by any means necessary. Rather, Bernstein made
colonialist expansion dependent on a number of specific social and
14
Eduard Bernstein, "Der Socialismus und die Kolonialfrage," in SM 4 (1900), p. 559;
"Die Kolonialfrage und der Klassenkampf," p. 989; and "Der Klassenkampf und der
Fortschritt der Kultur," in SM 15 (1911), pp. 1,165-1,169.
15
Eduard Bernstein, "Der Sozialismus und die Colonialfrage," pp. 549-554.
16
Bernstein, "Die Kolonialfrage und der Klassenkampf," pp. 989, 996.
17
Eduard Bernstein, "Materialistische Geschichtsauffassung und modernes Geschlech-
tsleben."
18
Eduard Bernstein, "Arbeiterbewegungund Kultur," Dokumente des Fortschritts 1 (1908),
pp. 523- 530.
The dawn of a new era 209
political preconditions. Most importantly, he sought to connect the
legitimacy of colonial policies with the degree of political democracy
established in the colonializing country. Given the underdeveloped
democratic structure of the Wilhelmine Empire in which parliament
lacked any control of foreign policy, the very existence of "colonial
policies" devoid of working-class input was highly objectionable. As
noted above, Bernstein employed this argument not only against his own
nationalist-revisionist comrades, but also against Friedrich Naumann's
and Max Weber's national-liberal vision of a German Weltpolitik, com-
paring it unfavorably with the more democratic and libertarian forms of
British and French colonial policy.19
In addition, Bernstein sought to link his support of colonialism to the
modus operandiby which indigenous people were "civilized." Insisting on
a proper application of "ethical methods" vis-d-vis the native population,
he echoed Kant's reservations against the ill-treatment of primal societies
by European powers. On many occasions, Bernstein condemned the
"unspeakable atrocities" committed by Western imperialist forces and
demanded that colonial powers "humanize their actions."20 At the 1907
Stuttgart Congress of the Socialist International, for example, he and his
revisionist comrade Eduard David, pressed hard to make such an ethical
proviso part of an official pro-colonialist resolution: "The expansion of
the capitalist economy will continue, regardless of whether we like it or
not, or whether we pass resolutions for or against it. We cannot prevent its
occurrence, but we can influence its forms and methods in favor of a more
humanitarian society."21 Yet by endorsing colonialist practices in prin-
ciple, both men could merely "deplore" the amount of human suffering
connected with this process without being able to guarantee the imple-
mentation of politically binding moral resolutions or an effective system
for monitoring frequently occurring violations and atrocities.
Finally, Bernstein argued for the establishment of international institu-
tions to settle disputes among "cultured nations" arising from their
colonial endeavors in a peaceful manner. Following the proposal of British
Secretary Grey to press for a full institutionalization of global principles of
conflict resolution through a neutral international court, he suggested the
coordination of international policies that would curb the escalation of
militarism, the menacing naval build-up on both sides of the Channel, and
the most flagrant forms of economic protectionism.22 Abandoning his
19
Eduard Bernstein, "Socialdemokratie und Imperialismus," in SM 4 (1900), pp.
238-251.
20
Immanuel Kant, "Perpetual Peace," in Hans Reis, ed., Kant: Political Writings (Cam-
bridge: Cambridge UP, 1991), p. 106.
21
Eduard Bernstein, "Kulturrecht und Kulturfrage," in Vorwdrts 23.2 (October 4, 1907).
22
Bernstein, Sozialdemokratische Volkerpolitik, pp. 54-58.
210 Disappointment
reserved demeanor, he scolded the nationalist protectionists in the SPD,
demanding that they modify their "myopic" position.23
Indeed, Bernstein's passionate commitment to the principles of free
trade and his sharp denunciation of protective tariffs became one of the
hallmarks of his liberal socialism.24 On these important issues, Bernstein
once again found himself profoundly inspired by the British liberal
tradition. In particular, he seemed to warm up to Richard Cobden's and
Herbert Spencer's economic evolutionism which postulated a positive
correlation between increased international trade relations and the
preservation of world peace.25
But the powerful protectionists in the German labor movement did not
even bother to contemplate what they considered Bernstein's "British
hogwash." Their rejection of free-trade policies provided an important
ideological focus for nationalist revisionists like Max Schippel and
Wolfgang Heine, who felt that protective tariffs best supported the
domestic industrial base, and thus ultimately secured Germany's position
of power in the world. The issue of protectionism soon came to a head in a
major dispute involving Bernstein and his employer, Joseph Bloch.
Bernstein's aggressive article in Sozialistische Monatshefte condemned
Bloch's categorical rejection of free-trade principles as "a deplorable
regression from sophisticated theoretical considerations to coarse empiri-
cal arguments."26 When Bloch demanded an apology, Bernstein refused;
he merely provided a symbolic gesture of reconciliation in his qualified
approval of very moderate protectionistic measures like targeted state
subventions of certain industrial and agricultural sectors.
The SPD's growing internal differences regarding the issues of nation-
alism, colonialism, and culture made painfully apparent that Bernstein's
model of evolutionary socialism had only inadequately addressed the
party's emerging instrumentalism - its willingness to separate ethical
means from political ends. Increasingly, this inclination to abandon
ethical principles at the expense of the organizational expansion of social
democracy surfaced in the "realist" speeches of both party Praktiker and
left-wing radicals. Even Kautsky's orthodox-Marxist faction showed itself
increasingly willing to support reformism as long as the party paid lip
23
Eduard Bernstein, Volkerrecht und Volkerpolitik (Berlin: 1919), p. 184.
24
See, for example, Eduard Bernstein, "Die Britischen Arbeiter und der zollpolitische
Imperialismus," in Archiv fur Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik 19 (1904); "Germany
and the Limitation of Armaments," in The Nation 1 (April 6, 1907); "Die Internationale
Politik der Sozialdemokratie," in SM 13 (1909); "How the New Reichstag will look," in
TheNation 10 (December 30, 1911); "A Sacrifice to Folly," in The Nation 12 (March 15,
1913).
25
See Schroder, "Eduard Bernsteins Stellung zum Imperialismus vor dem Ersten Wel-
tkrieg," in H e i m a n n a n d M e y e r , Bernstein und der Demokratische Sozialismus, p . 1 8 3 .
26
Eduard Bernstein, "Zollfreier Internationaler Verkehr," in SM 15 (1911), p. 831.
The dawn of a new era 211
service to the ultimate "transformation of capitalism." Once again,
Bernstein found himself without a reliable and sizeable base of support in
the party which made the practical translation of his socialist colonialism a
purely academic issue.27 Torn between moral imperatives for the estab-
lishment of a "just" international institutional framework and the
necessary realism of a consequentialist political agenda, Bernstein's pitch
for a "more humane theory of colonialism" went unheeded. The whole
episode represented just another variant of the precarious theoretical
balancing act so typical of his entire political thought.28
Indeed, Bernstein's simultaneous acknowledgment of Germany's "cul-
tural right" to pull even with other colonial powers and his ethical
criticism of the connection between Germany's aggressive foreign policy
and its colonial policy must have sounded rather confused in the ears of
both Marxist internationalists and nationalist revisionists.29 Moreover,
his liberal-evolutionist approach to issues of foreign policy must have
struck them as being theoretically inconsistent, practically unworkable,
and politically out of touch with existing conditions in Germany.
Unwilling to follow Bernstein's theoretical quest, orthodox Marxists,
nationalist revisionists, and atheoretical Praktiker alike distanced them-
selves even further from his evolutionary socialism, fearing that Bern-
stein's "excessive self-reflection" would "hurt" their "cause" in the long
run.30 As a result, his waning capital with the main players in the SPD was
even further depleted. Still, this was only the beginning of a long series of
political disappointments.
58
Eduard Bernstein, Karl Kausky, and Hugo Haase, "Das Gebot der Stunde," in Leipziger
Volkszeitung (June 19, 1915).
59
Kautsky, "Eduard Bernstein," p. 47.
60
See, for example, Eduard Bernstein, Die Internationale derArbeiterklasse und der europdische
Krieg (Tubingen: Mohr, 1915); Sozialdemokratische Volkerpolitik; and Von der Aufgabe der
Juden im Weltkriege (Berlin: Reiss, 1917).
61
Eduard Bernstein, "Der Schulstreit in Palastina," in NZ 32.1 (1913/14), p. 752.
222 Disappointment
displays of anti-Semitism which were raised in the context of the war, led
Bernstein to support the concept of national autonomy for Jews in
individual European countries, and to consider a "civic" Jewish national-
ism as reconcilable with modern democratic ideas of self-determina-
tion.62 But while he continued to disavow the strongly exclusivist streak
running through the Zionist cause, he also argued that the history of
European Jewry had made them "born pacifists" and the true mediators
among the peoples of the world.63 On this point, he held fast to his earlier
idealistic belief that the truest and noblest mission of the Jewish people
consisted in working for the universalist goals of peace and international
cooperation.
Although he began to cultivate a relationship with the Labor Zionist
Movement during the war, it was only in the late 1920s - after his niece,
Lily Zadek, had emigrated to Palestine - that Bernstein became openly
sympathetic to Zionist settlers in the Middle East, admiring their
cooperative social framework and their pioneering zeal.64 Joining several
Zionist labor organizations, he attempted to use his influence to have
pro-Zionist material published in the German social democratic press.65
Gradually he gained a favorable reputation among Zionist activists, and
was even approached by prominent Jewish leaders like David Ben-Gurion
to use his political clout with English politicians to prevent the British
Government from suspending Jewish immigration to Palestine.66
In 1916, the increasingly chauvinistic and anti-Semitic SPD leadership
drew the ultimate consequences of worsening intra-party disputes by
expelling Hugo Haase and his "pacifist Jewish Gang" from the parliamen-
tary Fraktion. Almost immediately, Haase embarked on the creation of a
separate socialist organization - the "Social Democratic Association" -
which ultimately led to the founding of a new "Independent" Social
Democratic Party (USPD), a curious mix of left-wing revolutionaries,
Marxist internationalists, anti-war centrists, and a few ethical socialists.
Though he had always supported party unity, Bernstein arrived at a
decision he hoped he would never have to make. After agonizing weeks of
fruitless mediation efforts, he hesitantly joined the breakaway party.
Though opposing a number of revolutionary principles in the USPD
platform, he fully agreed with its peace aims and felt that the new party
62
See Robert S. Wistrich, Revolutionary Jews from Marx to Trotsky (New York: Barnes and
Noble, 1976), p. 72; and Jacobs, On Socialists and "The Jewish Question" after Marx, pp.
44-70.
63
Eduard Bernstein, "Vom Patriotismus der Juden," Die Friedenswarte 18 (1916), p. 248;
Von den Aufgaben der Juden im Weltkriege, p. 8.
64
Bernstein A, BIO.
65
S e e J a c o b , On Socialists and e<The Jewish Question" after Marx, p . 6 5 .
66
Wistrich, Revolutionary Jews from Marx to Trotsky, p. 74.
The dawn of a new era 223
offered him a more appropriate political context for propagating his
anti-war stance.
In March 1918, Bernstein risked his personal freedom by delivering one
of his most memorable speeches in the Reichstag, a sharp rebuke against
the government's repugnant war policies that included massive violations
of international law, the engagment in an unprecedented series of
submarine attacks on civilian vessels, and the unwillingness to consider
comprehensive peace proposals.67 Repeatedly interrupted and shouted
down by nationalist social democrats, Liberals, and Conservative parlia-
mentarians, an unfazed Bernstein calmly finished his denunciation of
"official" German war policy. Unfortunately, it would take another eight
months and millions of lost lives before the Great War wouldfinallycome
to an end.
1
For a brief introduction to the main ideas of these theorists, see Thomas Meyer,
"Elemente einer Gesamttheorie des Demokratischen Sozialismus und Hinderung ihrer
Durchsetzung in der Weimarer Republik," in Horst Heimann and Thomas Meyer, eds.
Reformsozialismus und Sozialdemokratie (Berlin: Dietz, 1982), pp. 413-440.
230
Bernstein'sfinalbattle 231
While the Weimar SPD could present itself as the chief defender of the
country's new democratic system, it failed miserably in the necessary task
of weakening the powerful influence of the army, state bureaucrats, and
large-scale industrialists on German society. Already before the end of the
war, Friedrich Ebert, the First Chairman of the Majority Socialists
(MSPD), concluded an informal alliance with General Wilhelm Groener,
who represented the army and the old ruling elites. The leading industrial-
ist, Hugo Stinnes, and trade-union boss, Carl Legien, proceeded to create
the "Central Working Alliance" with the obvious goal of keeping
organized labor in its place.2 These pacts were designed to provide the
new social democratic government with some legitimacy by creating the
appearance of the maintenance of "public order" in the critical period
preceding the first elections. Many social democrats considered these
deals unavoidable, fearing that returning soldiers and mass unemploy-
ment might otherwise lead to widespread disorder and a possible
Bolshevik-style take-over.
As Hans-Ulrich Wehler notes, the entire "socialist" leadership of the
MSPD perceived "the liberating discontinuity of the revolution mainly as
a threat."3 With this glaring handicap of failure to carry out a radical
reform of the state, its personnel and its institutions, the likelihood that a
functioning democratic system would emerge in Germany was extremely
low. These powerful continuities at work in German political history were
also apparent in the blueprint of the new Weimar Constitution, which
reintroduced the old constitutional dualism in the form of a mixed
parliamentary-presidential system of rule, thus predisposing the new
republic to a spirit of political contentiousness and instability.
Finally, falling short of a comprehensive overhaul of its old theoretical
edifice along the lines of a genuine "liberal socialism" that might have
breathed new life into its increasingly bureaucratized pragmatism, Ger-
man social democracy proved itself incapable of generating the necessary
emotional drive and mass support for its fragile "socialist republic." The
long-overdue 1921 revision of the old Erfurt Party Program had merely
amounted to a necessary, but not sufficient, first instalment. In fact, the
SPD took a step backward when it replaced the Gorlitz Program with the
more Marxist 1925 Heidelberg Program.
To be sure, the task of ideological renewal was not an easy undertaking
for a German labor movement which in some crucial respects resembled
Plato's fabled many-headed creature. Sharing governing responsibility
and thus forced to occupy itself with the most immediate problems of the
day, the SPD found itself enmeshed in the chronic woes of Germany's
2
Wehler, The German Empire, pp. 224-225.
3
Ibid., p. 226.
232 Disappointment
war-torn, sputtering economy. The persisting intra-labor conflicts dra-
matically worsened after the founding of the Moscow-oriented German
Communist Party, and soon an openly anti-democratic, catch-all
"people's party" of the Right began to capture the nationalist resentment
of a vanquished nation. Caught between the undemocratic extremism of
both the Left and the Right, the party's theoretical manoeuverability was
additionally curtailed by a public mood identifying parliamentarism with
humility and defeat - a phenomenon that retarded the much-needed
reorientation of socialist theory. To a large degree, these developments
explain why the leaders of the Weimar SPD regarded fundamental
theoretical debates as an ill-affordable luxury that, in addition,
threatened to expose the political heterogeneity of the German labor
movement.
Though the immediate political effects of Bernstein's post-war contri-
butions to socialist theory were fairly modest, the ageing revisionist
remained a vociferous critic of the fatigued Weimar socialism.4 His
perceptive commentaries on the politics of the SPD centered on the
party's confusing plans regarding the overall direction and pace of social
change in Germany. While his previously unsuccessful calls for temporary
alliances with various bourgeois parties were finally heeded, the old Left's
resistance against "opportunist" coalitions with the Liberals - like the
newly organized German Democratic Party - remained too strong to
overcome the old climate of mutual distrust.
However, there was indeed some tactical merit in the arguments of
those orthodox voices that warned against the dangers of a wholesale
abandonment of Marxist theory. After all, how could the SPD retain both
its circumscribed self-image of a working class party and its ideological
commitment to end capitalism within a new pluralist framework of
competitive interest-group politics? Putting their fingers on the Left's
persisting divergence of theory and practice, Marxist critics could also
provide a powerful explanation for the impotence of Bernstein's evol-
utionary socialism in the face of an increasingly instrumental tendency in
the party. Most importantly, they grasped why his pioneering reconcep-
tualization of socialism had become the pragmatic foundation of the cross
on which his admirable ethical principles were crucified. Deprived of its
teleological guarantees and its emphasis on seeing the capitalist produc-
tion process replaced by a "liberaP'ethic of redistribution, socialism was
transformed into a merely regulative idea designed to guide reformist
practice toward the uncertain achievement of greater social justice within
the existing capitalist order. Losing the absoluteness of Marx's historicist
4
See Heinrich August Winkler, "Eduard Bernstein as Critic of Weimar Social Democ-
racy," in Fletcher, Bernstein to Brandt, pp. 167-183.
Bernstein's final battle 233
objectivism, meant that social democracy was forced to rely upon its
leadership's subjectivist "will to socialism" for the implementation of its
sociopolitical objectives.
But as the history of the Weimar Republic shows, the reformist logic
emerging from Bernstein's discreditation of Marx's metaphysical telos did
not automatically translate into his ethical socialism; reformism was also
perfectly compatible with the instrumental intentions of the party Prak-
tiker. In the name of Bernstein's non-metaphysical, "level-headed prag-
matism" oriented toward the "daily tasks of the movement," the Praktiker
continued in their pre-war course, determined to support a process of
political decision-making defined solely by political exigency. Without so
much as a peremptory nod toward Bernstein's ethical criticism, their
one-dimensional critique subordinated the "abstract principles" of politi-
cal morality to the instrumental concerns of dispensing immediate
material benefits to constituencies, thus furthering the SPD's organiza-
tional expansion.5
The celebrated achievement of representative democracy in Weimar
was therefore a double-edged sword: while ushering in an unprecedented
era of political freedom in Germany, it also bound social democracy even
closer to the electoral concerns of modern political parties operating in
competitive environments. Though the rapid socioeconomic changes
occurring in the 1920s clearly confirmed Bernstein's early revisionist
theses regarding the increasingly stratified and complex social structure of
advanced capitalism, the working class represented only a minority of the
electorate, its share steadily declining after 1912.6 Conversely, members
of the "new middle classes" increased their political influence. The only
problem was that they hardly conceived of themselves as oppressed
members of the industrial proletariat. Caught in the dynamics of social
change, the German labor movement faced the strategic dilemma of
either maintaining its class appeal by satisfying the needs of its core
constituents, or playing to the different interests of a diverse middle class.
What was to be done? One option was a full-scale retreat to a purist
Marxist position which would have led to a further fragmentation of the
labor movement (Luxemburg). The second option would have demanded
the party's assent to Bolshevik insurrectionism based on the conception of
"Soviet socialism" (Klara Zetkin, August Thalheimer). The third alterna-
tive would have been the party's unambiguous acknowledgment of the
binding character of a non-Marxist program of democratic socialism for a
reformist political practice (Bernstein). No matter which option the SPD
would ultimately select, the choice was between remaining a relatively
5
See Bronner, "Bernstein and the Logic of Revisionism," in Socialism Unbound^ pp. 53-75.
6
Przeworski, Capitalism and Social Democracy', pp. 23-24.
234 Disappointment
small, homogeneous labor party with great internal cohesion facing
perpetual electoral defeats or broadening the party's electoral appeal at
the cost of watering down traditional socialist principles, be they Marxist-
revolutionary or Bernsteinian-evolutionary. After all, if socialist strategy
was reduced to pure electoral tactics, social democracy risked the survival
of its very political identity, reflected in its long-term objectives aimed at
transforming the existing capitalistic system.
Having long hitched its political practice to the logic of parliamentary
democracy, the SPD remained passive, thus trying to play it both ways. As
a result, it lost both its principles (the only weapon with which instrumen-
talism and bureaucratic rigidification could be fought) and its core
constituency. This meant that the most formidable challenge facing
Weimar social democracy was not the stark choice between total revol-
ution and piecemeal reforms, but how to balance the inescapable tactical
imperatives with socialist principles. The party's passivity also under-
mined further the crucial role of theory to serve as the indispensible means
of critical self-reflection. Despite the drafting of two new party programs,
Weimar social democracy witnessed but few fundamental debates on the
continued validity of old meaning structures. Rudolf Hilferding, the
SPD's new rising star, had made it abundantly clear that some Marxist
categories - including outdated expectations of a general capitalist
breakdown - were still very much part of the party's self-understanding,
albeit in a clearly ritualized form.7 At the same time, even Hilferding
realized that the youthful Marxist dreams of the labor movement had
given way to the harsh responsibilities of adulthood reflected in the party's
mature role as the republic's guardian of democracy and civil rights.
Unwilling to bear the risks involved in touching off new theoretical
debates, the party leadership tacitly agreed on ignoring social democracy's
many conflicting objectives deriving from the fundamental disjuncture
between ideological commitment and practical electoral concerns. As a
result, a good number of outdated Marxist slogans survived in the Weimar
SPD not because they commanded widespread support, but because
socialist theory no longer mattered. Suspending the binding force of
socialist principles for concrete political practice, the party leadership
seemed to be willing to risk drowning in its own short-term-oriented
instrumentalism.
Whether it was its conscious unwillingness to act upon any of these
options or sheer bureaucratic inertia, the fact remains that the SPD
condoned its rudderless drift on the stormy sea of Weimar politics, thus
alienating a good number of socialist intellectuals and activists. It quickly
7
Rudolf Hilferding in Protokolldes 1925 Heidelberg Parteitages (Berlin, 1925), pp. 273-279.
Bernstein's final battle 235
eroded social democracy's remaining ideological appeal even within its
own constituency, not to speak of its failure to attract the "new middle
classes." The party's lack of conceptual clarity regarding the direction and
pace of social change explains its inability to strengthen the foothold of
political democracy in Weimar Germany.
Using Bernstein's evolutionary socialism for the liquidation of the
theoretical concerns under which an ethical political judgment becomes
possible,8 the Praktiker pursued a myopic course of "muddling through
the problems/' and remained mired in their characteristic political
half-measures, tactical reversals, and ideological ambiguities. Their in-
strumentalism poured oil onto the propagandistic fires unleashed by
Hitler to convince the electorate of the "inherent weakness" of parliamen-
tary democracy. Bernstein himself never agreed with their impoverished
notion of socialism as nothing more than a set of discrete reforms decided
upon by a self-serving elite of party technocrats. Criticizing the SPD's
"disquieting tendency to fall prey to the spirit of routine," he emphasized
that the socialist movement was depriving itself of the crucial theoretical
framework necessary for a consistent program of constructive reform.
Hence, he berated his party's tendency to forsake "larger, far-reaching
interests in favor of short-term advantages."9 Indeed, Bernstein's fre-
quent calls for a politics of compromise with the bourgeoisie were not
predicated simply on achieving the "best possible deal" for the SPD's
electoral constituency, but remained wedded to a coherent theoretical
edifice - evolutionary socialism - that emphasized the power of ideological
and ethical concerns:
The question of political tactics ... is in the last resort the eternal conflict between
the absolute and the relative method, which reveals itself in its countless
modifications throughout the history of the human race, in religion and politics, as
a constant source of intellectual estrangement. Absolutism is . . . the rejection of
compromise, the rigid consideration of questions from a strictly limited point of
view, whether they concern the omnipotence of a dynasty, the rule of an oligarchy
or the multitude, the interests of different classes, the validity of dogma, or the
principles of ethics. But for relativism one might just as well say liberalism,
inasmuch as this conception does not denote a party, but the tendency to
toleration and mediation, which means, if it is abused, vagueness, eagerness to
compromise, and opportunism. 10
Two years later, Bernstein wrote the "The Bolshevist Brand of Social-
ism," an essay that represents his most coherent attempt to discredit
Marxism-Leninism by contrasting it with selected passages that showed
strong "evolutionary" inclinations in the political thought of Marx.
Critically unpacking some crucial passages from the writings of Lenin,
Trotsky, Bukharin and other leading Bolsheviks, he argued that their
instrumental understanding of the socialist transformation culminating in
the "revolutionary seizure of political power" failed to translate into a
socioeconomic framework that reflected ethical socialist principles. In
particular, Bernstein resented Trotsky and Bukharin's "idiotic" and
"dangerous" methods of "socialist education." Convinced that the
revolutionary end justified their ethically questionable means, the Bolshe-
vik leaders frequently familiarized uneducated Russian workers with a
version of "revolutionary Marxist socialism" replete with "simplistic
deductions and riddled with odd assertions regarding the causes and the
lasting consequences of the World War."28 Repeatedly, Bernstein warned
that coercive measures and the imposition of a subjectivist "will to
communism" on history would ultimately fail because Lenin's Russia
lacked the necessary political and economic preconditions for a demo-
cratic transition to social democracy.
Shuddering at the amount of human suffering involved in the Bolshevik
experiment, Bernstein expressed his solidarity with ordinary Russians,
"who already had to pay the price with the wanton sacrifice of countless
victims."29 Indeed, Bernstein's final rejection of Marxist-Leninist instru-
mentalism was based on a remarkable combination of economic consider-
ations and ethical conviction. In Kantian fashion, he refused to sacrifice
his moral principles to a Bolshevik socialism of "fantastic social plans and
speculative goals," insisting that: "Above all, even for the socialist
reformer or revolutionary, there is a categorical imperative!"30 By violat-
ing basic human rights, Lenin's political scheme had actually continued
the "old Russian tradition of Czarist despotism," for his political
methods, too, relied on the "unbridled terror of suppressing and silencing
dissent, a method commonly employed by Asian despots and African
27
Bernstein cited in John Riddell, ed. The German Revolution and the Debate on Soviet Power.
Documents: 1918-1919 (New York: Pathfinder, 1986), pp. 425-426.
28
Bernstein, "Die bolschewistische Abart des Sozialismus," in Der Sozialismus Einst und
Jetzt,, p. 120.
29
Ibid., p. 122.
30
Ibid., pp. 123, 121.
240 Disappointment
sultans."31 Thus, Bernstein's harsh final judgment on Soviet commu-
nism: "Bolshevism is the prime example of the baneful effects of an
erroneous theory, manifested as belief in the omnipotence of brute force,
blindness to fundamental social laws, and disregard for the evolutionary
principle guiding human beings from barbarism to civilization."32
But Bernstein's opposition to Marxism-Leninism was not confined to
debunking itsflawedtheoretical and moral foundations. In what might be
considered a masterpiece of investigative journalism, Bernstein - who as
Under-Secretary of the Treasury had had access to top-secret war
documents of the Imperial German government - unravelled the hidden
skein of German monetary support for the Russian Bolshevik party. In
1921, he published two short articles in Vorwdrts on this subject,
reporting that Lenin and his comrades had received vast sums of money
from the Kaiser's government for their destructive agitation.33 Though he
could not pin down the exact amounts involved or the full extent of the
interactions between Lenin and German government officials, Bernstein
was able to provide sufficiently specific details to make his reports
credible:
From absolutely reliable sources I have now ascertained that the sum was large,
certainly more than fifty million Gold marks, a sum about the source of which
Lenin and his comrades could be in no doubt. One result of all this was the
Brest-Litowsk Treaty. General Hoffmann, who negotiated with Trotsky and other
members of the Bolshevik delegation in Brest, held the Bolsheviks in his hands in
two senses, and he made sure they felt it.34
Bernstein openly challenged the German Communists and the Russian
Bolsheviks to take him to court if they thought he had libeled Lenin.
Predictably, however, the Central Committees of both parties maintained
their silence, virtually confirming Bernstein's assertions.35
In addition, Bernstein used his regained SPD seat in the Reichstag to
denounce Bolshevism publicly and its "German sister party." Pointing to
persistent and massive human rights violations committed by the Red
Army, which included mass executions without fair trial, he barked
angrily at his radical comrades on the Left: "Would you suggest we imitate
such policies in Germany?"36 When the Red Army marched into Georgia
in 1921, Bernstein drafted the SPD's official protest resolution demand-
ing the retreat of the Bolshevik troops and the release of Georgian social
31
Ibid., p. 124.
32
Ibid., p. 125.
33
Eduard Bernstein, "Ein dunkles Kapitel," in Vorwdrts (January 11, 1921).
34
Bernstein cited in Dmitri Volkagonov, Lenin (New York: The Free Press, 1994), pp.
122-123.
35
Ibid., p. 123.
36
Bernstein cited in EB, p. 176.
Bernstein'sfinalbattle 241
37
democratic prisoners. The annexation of Georgia, together with the
Bolshevik misuse of funds provided by the USPD and SPD for the
catastrophic Russian famines in the summer of 1921, further contributed
to the increasing disillusion of German socialists with Lenin's authoritar-
ian regime.
In spite of his relentless opposition to Bolshevism, however, Bernstein
did not support the ugly Communist-baiting of his comrades
Scheidemann and Ebert.38 Indiscriminately labeling all left-wing social
democrats who disagreed with them "sympathizers of Bolshevism," the
two men reiterated throughout the early Weimar period that they hated all
"unpatriotic social revolutionaries like sin."39 Bernstein's criticism of
their persisting nationalist agenda remained equally harsh, reaching its
highest pitch during the hotly debated question of Germany's responsibil-
ity for the outbreak of the Great War.
Conclusion
The various academic assessments of Bernstein's contribution to socialist
theory range from enthusiastic pronouncements that his approach "has
won on all fronts,"61 to lessflatteringattributes that describe his political
thought as fatallyflawedand "inchoate."62 This study has argued that the
truth lies somewhere in between. Both the greatest strength and the most
obvious weakness in Bernstein's revisionism was the unshakable evol-
utionary optimism that helped him identify the vital connections between
socialism and liberalism, ethics and politics, and democracy and social
reform. At the same time, his evolutionism also led to the glaring
shortcomings of his linear notion of political and ethical progress in the
West.
58
Bernstein cited in Schelz-Brandenburg, Eduard Bernstein and Karl Kautsky, p. 393.
59
Winkler, Der Schein der Normalitat, p. 630.
60
Bernstein frequently described socialism using this quotation from Heraclitus. See, for
example, Eduard Bernstein, "Was ist Sozialismus?," in Hirsch, Ein revisionistisches
Sozialismusbild, p. 157.
61
Carlo Schmid cited in ibid., p. 13.
62
Fletcher, Revisionism and Empire, pp. 165, 183-188.
248 Disappointment
Although he clearly recognized that the development of a genuinely
liberal socialism called for major revisions, and even the abandonment, of
major portions of Marx's theory, the rationalist spirit of the old master
continued to hover over Bernstein's pen. Marxism and the universalist
discourse of the Enlightenment were the significant intellectual forces
dominating his conceptual landscape. Even though he wrote against the
"dogmatism of scientific socialism," he often felt forced to justify his
critical intervention by showing that an "evolutionary-liberal" interpreta-
tion of Marxist socialism might be employed against its doctrinal cousin.
But in the end, Marx's and Engels' theoretical influence on him turned
out to be a mixed blessing at best, for it prevented Bernstein from
formulating an unambiguous repudiation of the Marxist Weltanschauung.
This is not to say that any serious socialist thinker can afford to overlook
Marx's lasting insights. However, the evolutionary optimism driving
Bernstein's liberal-socialist vision at times sounded just as deterministic
and dogmatic as Marx's socialism. Convinced that modernity was
"inexorably" moving toward increasing social complexity and nobler
forms of "socialist culture," Bernstein clung to a liberal-Victorian
conceptual universe which retarded his realization that the mode of
political compromise and reformist gradualism could easily degenerate
into a political instrumentalism that might reverse previous social gains
and strengthen new forms of authoritarianism. Consequently, as Stephen
Eric Bronner has pointed out, there remain major theoretical inconsisten-
cies in Bernstein's assumption that the cumulative impact of a steady
reformism would eventually produce a systemic transformation of capital-
ist society.63 Yet, it is equally important to acknowledge that, by
reinserting moral subjectivity and human agency into socialist theory,
Bernstein at least took the important first steps toward the necessary
process of disentangling the socialist tradition from the ideological grip of
the founders of scientific socialism.
Though his talent for historical interpretation made minor classics of
works like Ferdinand Lassalle As a Social Reformer, and Cromwell and
Communism, Bernstein was hardly in the same league with academic
historians like Wilhelm Dilthey, Friedrich Meinecke, or Oswald Spengler.
The same can be said of his philosophical contribution, which certainly
exhibits the author's firm grasp of general theoretical problems, but
nonetheless lacks the polished features and in-depth understanding of
academically trained socialist philosophers like Karl Marx, Georg Lukacs,
Jean Jaures, or Max Adler. To be fair, however, it must be emphasized that
Bernstein never laid claim to advancing path-breaking philosophical
63
Bronner, Socialism Unbound, p. 73.
Bernstein's final battle 249
theses. Rather, he approached political and social philosophy with the
caution of an experienced social observer who knows that theoretical
analysis captures only a fraction of real-life complexity. His enormous
range of intellectual interests provided the necessary foundation for
his astute commentaries on the ethical implications of public policy
decisions.
As a commentator on current political affairs, Bernstein takes his place
as the genuine successor of Friedrich Engels who, as J. D. Hunley has
recently pointed out, also possessed a vast knowledge of "such a diversity
of disciplines as science, philosophy, history, anthropology, languages,
economics, current events, and business matters . . . without falling into
the pit of dilettantism."64 Eminently successful in his career as a political
journalist, Bernstein's numerous articles appeared not only in socialist
publications, but were frequently picked up by the bourgeois press or
given prominent space in first-rate social-science journals like Max
Weber's Archives for Social Science. Bernstein possessed an intuitive grasp
of emerging sociopolitical trends and rendered his political judgment in a
language that was free of the partisan prejudice of many of his Marxist
comrades.
It is in the field of political science - spanning from political theory to
political economy; from international relations to comparative politics;
and from public policy to political sociology - that Bernstein can truly lay
claim to distinction. While holding fast to the humanist ideals of the
Enlightenment and stressing the liberal tenets of individual responsibility
and ethical engagement, Bernstein's new socialist vision was informed by
real social interdependence rather than by Hegel's speculative totality.
Evolutionary socialism aimed, first and foremost, at developing an
empirically informed, normative foundation for the realization of concrete
socialist demands. Bernstein's self-critical political discourse sought to
leave the necessary space for serious debates with political opponents,
while at the same time retaining the ethical ideals that comprise the basis
of a liberal-egalitarian vision of society. Indeed, such attempts to marry
the "demon of politics" with the "god of love" (Weber) never fully escape
the eternal conflict between the expediency of the political moralist and
the conviction of the moral politician, so well described in Immanuel
Kant's Perpetual Peace.65 At the same time, a theory of ethical socialism
refuses habitually to subordinate theoretical concerns to instrumental
considerations, be it in the name of "rationality," "realism," or "national
self-interest." Taking into consideration both the material and ideal
interests of disadvantaged groups in society, Bernstein's evolutionary
64
J. D. Hunley, The Life and Thought of Friedrich Engels (New Haven: Yale UP, 1991), p. 46.
65
Kant, Political Writings, pp. 121-125.
250 Disappointment
socialism insisted on a synchronization of means and ends, of moral
integrity and political objectives.
For Bernstein, the ultimate task of the socialist thinker was the
seemingly impossible duty of nursing the steady flame of theory and
political morality without either allowing it to turn into an all-consuming
bushfire of sectarian purity or letting it be extinguished by the cold breath
of unprincipled instrumentalism. Hence, he neither shied away from the
onerous obligation of the socialist intellectual to both "explain the
movement and show the way," nor did he fall into the philosophical hubris
of maintaining that correct theory alone can create or destroy a political
movement.66 Indeed, Bernstein maintained that the concerns of the
socialist intellectual could not be divorced from matters of practice
understood as Kleinarbeit: they entailed not only the scientific investiga-
tion of empirical tendencies, but, most importantly, the organization and
education of the public, and the continuous solving of concrete problems
on the path toward a more libertarian and egalitarian society.67 Thus, he
insisted that socialist theorists maintain the open attitude of the social
scientist who sought to understand (verstehen in the Weberian sense) his
sociohistorical context. Without preserving the detached posture of a
"value-free" inquiry into social reality, Bernstein argued, social democ-
racy as a political movement deprived itself of examining the shifting
tendencies, possibilities, and preconditions for the desired transformation
of capitalist society.
Only after this crucial first cognitive step was taken could the social
scientist turn into a partisan "socialist theorist," who, developing eman-
cipatory strategies for linking scientific knowledge and particular inter-
ests, was engaged in the formulation of indispensable "categorical
imperatives binding political parties."68 Thus, it was within the concrete
world of the marginalized and oppressed that the socialist theorist could
complete his function, since progressive political parties were the "cham-
pions of specific interests which it is their duty to foster in every possible
way."69 Bernstein provided an important response to Kautsky's dominant
view that the primary role of political theory was not to initiate politics but
to analyze and explain social phenomena according to the "correct"
Marxist method. More than anything, Bernstein wanted to combine the
traditional role of a social scientist with that of the "thinker of the
movement" who provided the ethical principles for concrete political
action as well as analyzing its empirical presuppositions.
66
Bernstein to Antonio Labriola, n. d., Bernstein A> C20.
67
Bernstein, "Was ist Sozialismus?," in Hirsch, Ein revisionismches Sozialismusbild, p. 148.
68
Eduard Bernstein, "The Conquest of Political Power," in MS, pp. 306-307.
69
Ibid.
Bernstein'sfinalbattle 251
For these reasons, it is difficult to ignore the significance of Bernstein's
constructive efforts in providing thefirstcoherent theoretical blueprint for
an evolutionary socialism whose liberal-socialist principles became even
more important in the course of this century. Indeed, Bernstein's
challenge to orthodox Marxism fertilized the vast field of twentieth-
century progressive political thought. To this very day, the full scope of
the historical consequences following his crucial intervention has not been
properly recognized. The emerging rifts within Marxist socialism opened
the gates to a flood of new "revisionisms," as well as to new theoretical
attempts at restoring unity. Considering himself a "thinker in the Marxist
tradition" despite his rejection of Hegelian categories and his obvious
liberal predilections for neo-Kantian critical theory, Bernstein set an
important first example for succeeding generations of socialist thinkers
who added their neo-Hegelian, Freudian, and Heideggerian inclinations
(among others) to a "Marxism" that had begun to investigate previously
neglected dimensions.
For example, V. I. Lenin, in his famous pamphlet What is to Be Done?,
directly responded to Bernstein's "heresies" by developing his own
voluntaristic-Blanquist brand of Marxism. Georges Sorel's irrationalist
syndicalism, which in turn spawned new radical socialisms of the Left and
Right, was deeply influenced by Bernstein's revisionism. Max Hor-
kheimer, Theodor W. Adorno, Karl Korsch, Georg Lukacs, and other
members of the "Frankfurt School of Social Research" reacted to
Bernstein's "return to the critical moment" in socialist theory with a
revival of the Hegelianized socialism of the young Marx, combined with
Freud's psychological insights - a "Marxist eclecticism" celebrated in
their vision of "Critical Theory."
At the same time, Bernstein's intellectual initiative also helped
legitimize the growing neo-Kantian school within social democracy
comprised of noted social philosophers like Karl Vorlander, Conrad
Schmidt, Franz Staudinger, Max Adler, and Paul Natorp. Otto
Neurath, consciously building on the epistemological premisses of
Bernstein's evolutionary socialism, decisively influenced the formulation
of Karl Popper's critical rationalism and the logical positivism of the
Vienna Circle.70 Finally, contemporary forms of "liberal socialism,"
perhaps best articulated in the works of Norberto Bobbio and Luc Ferry
and Alan Renaut, can be traced back to Carlo Rosselli, Jean Jaures, and
Leon Blum - socialist thinkers heavily influenced by the "Father of
Revisionism."
70
For the connection between Bernstein's revisionism and Otto Neurath's theories, see
Freudenthal, "Otto Neurath: From Authoritarian Liberalism to Empiricism," in Dascal
and Griingard, Knowledge and Politics, pp. 207-240.
252 Disappointment
Perhaps it is most appropriate to leave the last word on the evaluation of
Eduard Bernstein's contribution to socialist theory to the Austrian party
journalist, Karl Leuthner, one of his fiercest nationalist opponents in the
"revisionist" camp:
[T]here is something touching about Bernstein's solicitude in analyzing, categor-
izing, and developing theoretical problems. People say he's hardly creative; he
never managed a genuine philosophical breakthrough. Yet, he succeeded in
dissolving ossified concepts, in the process endowing them with new life. He may
have lacked the sudden flashes of a true genius, but steadily holding up his lamp,
he moved inexorably toward new ground, illuminating a good many dark spots
and uncovering previously unrecognized connections.71
71
Karl Leuthner cited in Hyrkkanen, Sozialistische Kolonialpolitik, p. 282.
Epilogue: evolutionary socialism at the
"end of socialism53
253
254 Epilogue
that socialism, understood as a distinct ideology, or "set of ideologies and
its accompanying social movements," has seen its day.2 Toying with the
post-modern relativism of our times, they have called for the transform-
ation of the socialist tradition into a "cultural project." Suspicious of any
universalist "metanarrative," they reject the essentialist Enlightenment
themes of both Marx and Kant, seeking instead to deconstruct and
unmask modernity's "disciplinary" and "policing" modes of "subjuga-
tion."
Portraying socialism as part of the problem of modernity, academic
"post-modernists" like Jean-Francois Lyotard, Jean Baudrillard, and
Judith Butler have struggled to make the "cultural Left" aware of a
"politics of identity." "Difference" and "subjectivity" are "activated" at
the expense of "solidarity" and "universality";3 deontological ethical
"grand narratives" are met with stern disapproval; and Western,
"logocentric" thought is perpetually "deconstructed."4 While it is true
that the relentless philosophical critique of Cartesian rationality has
drawn due attention to the persisting relations of domination in modern-
ity, the linguistic acrobatics of postmodernity haven't advanced by one
iota the political task of constructing social institutions capable of
answering the cries of real human suffering. The denouncement of the
"subject" as "fiction" has contributed to dangerous forms of aesthetic
withdrawal and political detachment while privileging the ontic world of
Heidegger's "Das Man" Politics degenerates into a "perpetual withhol-
ding gesture,"5 and theoretical assumptions are continuously "inter-
rogated," but never enacted or tested. Indeed, more than sixty years after
Bernstein's death, the post-modern "ontology of discord"6 has not been
able to offer concrete sociopolitical alternatives to his evolutionary
Enlightenment project of radically democratizing society through reform-
ist measures.
The utter discreditation of Soviet-style communism and the shortcom-
2
See, for example, Peter Beilharz, Postmodern Socialism: Romanticism, City and State
(Melbourne: University of Melbourne Press, 1994), p. 105; Norman Rush, "What was
Socialism?," in The Nation (January 24, 1994) and various responses to Rush's article in
"Socialism: An Exchange," The Nation (March 7, 1994); Frederic Jameson, Postmodern-
ism (London: Verso, 1991); Ernesto Laclau, Reflections on the Revolution of Our Time
(London: Verso, 1991); and Ralf Dahrendorf, Reflections on the Revolution in Europe (New
York: Times Books, 1990).
3
Jean-Francois Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1984), p. 82.
4
Jacques Derrida, "The Principle of Reason: The University in the Eyes of Its Pupils," in
Diacritics 19 (Fall, 1983).
5
Stephen K. White, Political Theory and Postmodernism (Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1991),
p. 18.
6
William Connolly, "Taylor, Foucault, and Otherness," in Political Theory 12 (May 1984),
p. 371.
Epilogue 255
ings of the theoretically impoverished and bureaucratized social demo-
cratic model notwithstanding, there seems to be plenty of unfinished
business left in the "evolutionary" enterprise of extending the political
ideals of the French Revolution. The "Social Question" has not disap-
peared; contesting the vast disparities in wealth and well-being produced
by liberal capitalism remains an important political agenda.7 As Jiirgen
Habermas recently noted, there is still much to say for Bernstein's
"socialist ideal" of taming "capitalism to some point where it becomes
unrecognizable as such."8 Similarly, Michael Walzer emphasized that,
"The best name for... the political creed that defends the framework and
supports the necessary forms of state action for both groups and
individuals, is social democracy."9
Yet, the public contestation of social injustice must no longer be
translated into the Marxist dream of riding the wave of history into the
Utopia of a unitary social whole. Socialism, understood as the complete
"abolition of the commodity form" - a romantic "other" to some form of
market economy - has indeed come to an end.10 If anything, the harsh
lessons of the twentieth century have taught social democrats that
socialism is neither forced collectivization plus planned economy nor the
automatic gradualism of an evolutionary one-way street. As the Polish
dissident Adam Michnik put it, "We are what we were thirty years ago,
except that we have lost our illusions and gained in humility."11 Hence,
the continued viability of any socialism lies both in its capacity for
ideological renewal, that is, its ability to reconnect political practice to the
core principles of social democracy.
Ideological renewal can only occur through critical self-reflection.
Bernstein elevated such sincere forms of self-criticism to the modus
operandi of his evolutionary socialism. A thorough and permanent revision
of socialist theory should therefore no longer be interpreted as a disgrace-
ful "betrayal" of the (Marxist) cause, but as an ongoing effort to forestall
ideological petrification. Less exclusive, more moderate, and more
eclectic than its Marxist ancestor, any viable "socialism" of the future
must provide a comfortable home for the democratic critic who questions
total social solutions and calls for an ethically motivated struggle against
structurally embedded forms of injustice and social irresponsibility - be it
7
For the welter of contemporary counter-Enlightenment and post-Enlightenment theor-
izing see, for example, Axel Honneth, Thomas McCarthy, Claus Offe, and Albrecht
Wellmer, eds. Philosophical Interventions in the Unfinished Project of Enlightenment (Cam-
bridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992).
8
Jiirgen Habermas cited in The New York Review of Books (March 24, 1994), p. 26.
9
Michael Walzer, "Political Liberalism," in Dissent (Spring, 1994), p. 191.
10
See also Bronner, Socialism Unbound.
11
Adam Michnik cited in The New York Review of Books (March 24, 1994), p. 26.
256 Epilogue
on the basis of class, race, ethnicity, gender, age, or sexual orientation.
Like Bernstein, such a critic rejects all forms of dogmatism, including that
of turning evolutionary-liberal socialism into a rigid system. In our rapidly
changing world, even the "revisionists" themselves must be subject to
internal and external review.
By abandoning its critical character and lowering its moral sights in the
name of "prudence" (also known as instrumentalism), European social
democracy eventually became too affirmative - a development culmina-
ting in Chancellor Helmut Schmidt's credo: "Each citizen must be
capable of consenting to an orderly procedure of conflict settlement by
compromise. He must be prepared to accept the loss of stringency and
consistency that goes with that."12 While it is true that "democracy is the
school of compromise,"13 the process of political bargaining ought not
overlook the fundamental question of how to reconcile liberty, accounta-
bility, and democracy while maintaining the highest possible degree of
individual freedom and economic equality. In order to prevent a fatal
compromise of principles, the core ethical ideals of social democracy must
be defended even at the risk of electoral defeat. This means that the
question of socialism can never disappear into the state just as the state
cannotbe jettisoned in favor of a nebulous idea of "communism." For this
reason, concrete problems like authority, distributive justice, and per-
sonal liberty ought to remain the most pressing issues debated in both
socialist theory and mainstream political theory.14
Indeed, the viability of social democracy depends on the institutional-
ized enactment of its progressive agenda, that is, its ability to reconnect
political practice to the core principles of social democracy. However, this
step cannot be taken without rejecting reductionistic Marxist concepts
that severely curtail the vision of a genuine liberal socialism. Though
European labor movements have long followed the example of the SPD in
replacing Marxism as their official ideology with a theoretical pluralism
that bases socialist principles equally on "Christian ethics, humanism,
and classical philosophy," many socialist intellectuals have refused to let
12
Schmidt cited in Bronner, Socialism Unbound, p. 63.
13
PS, p. 144.
14
Among the vast literature on this topic, important studies include: John Rawls, A
Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard, 1971); Jiirgen Habermas, Knowledge and
Human Interest (Boston: Beacon, 1971); Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia
(New York: Basic Books, 1974); Alasdair Maclntyre, After Virtue (South Bend, IN:
University of Notre Dame Press, 1981); Michael Walzer, Spheres of Justice (New York:
Basic Books, 1983); Robert Dahl, A Preface to Economic Democracy (New Haven: Yale
UP, 1984); Benjamin R. Barber, Strong Democracy (Berkeley, CA: University of
California Press, 1984); Alan Gilbert, Democratic Individuality (New York: Cambridge
UP, 1990); and Charles Taylor, The Ethics of Authenticity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
UP, 1992).
Epilogue 257
15
go of the Marxist framework. Ridiculing "ethical foundations" for
socialist theory, these stale voices of the old "New Left" continue to view
socialist theory through glasses colored by decades of hegemonic Marxist
conceptual categories. Though perhaps philosophically more demanding
than more eclectic forms of liberal socialism, Marxist doctrine nonethe-
less has failed in its self-imposed task of transforming the less abstract
political arena where concrete material interests compete with aesthetic
ideals, cultural biases, and moral dilemmas.
Twentieth-century Marxism is guilty of what Benjamin Barber calls
"The Law of Incomplete Realization."16 Barber's law demands that
philosophical principles are to be tested against their capacity to operate
when they are incompletely realized. Following this logic, Marxists can
not simultaneously defend the demands of The Communist Manifesto, and
wash their hands of the Bolshevik cult of personality and the despotism of
Chinese party bureaucrats. Despite its tendency to degenerate into
instrumentalism, Bernstein's "evolutionary socialism" achieves much
higher marks on Barber's scale.
Consequently, Bernstein's quest should be seen as the finest vision
social democracy has to offer: a consequent reformism aimed at extending
democracy understood as a "cooperative ideal." Challenging the antith-
esis between liberalism and socialism proclaimed by generations of
Marxist thinkers, the modern descendants of Bernstein's evolutionary
socialism call for an ideological renewal of social democracy based on the
re-evaluation of non-Marxist socialist currents and their historical con-
nections to liberal thought.
Indeed, the future of socialism seems now to hang in the balance of its
reorientation towards the liberal tradition and its renewed emphasis on
democratic and civic practices.17 As Jeremy Rifkin points out, the
profound technological and social changes brought on by the unfolding
Information Age revolution will force every country to rethink long-held
assumptions about the nature of politics, work, and citizenship.18 In our
15
1959 SPD Godesberg Program, cited in Meyer, Demokratischer Sozialismus - Soziale
Demokratie, p. 86.
16
Benjamin R. Barber, "An Epitaph for Marxism," in Social Science and Modern Society33.1
(November/December 1995), p. 24.
17
See ibid., p. 26; Peter Osborne, ed. Socialism and the Limits of Liberalism (London: Verso,
1991); Chantal Mouffe, "Toward a Liberal Socialism?," in Dissent (Winter, 1993), pp.
81-87; and Luc Ferry and Alain Renault, Political Philosophy, vol III: From the Rights of
Man to the Republican Idea, trans. Franklin Philip (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1992).
18
Jeremy Rifkin, "Civil Society in the Information Age," in The Nation (February 26,
1996),pp. 1 1 - 16; and The End of Work: The Decline of the Global Labor Force and the Dawn
of the Post- Market Era (New York: Tarcher/Putnam, 1995). See also Andrew Arato and
Joshua Cohen, Civil Society and Political Theory (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992).
258 Epilogue
era of government and corporate downsizing, special attention ought to be
paid to the central role of civil society as the rapidly growing "Third
Sector" between the market and government spheres which harbors the
opportunity to create millions of new jobs. While the goal of ideological
renewal should certainly not be the abandonment of social egalitarianism
in favor of abstract notions of liberty, it is imperative that twenty-first-
century social democrats re-envision politics, economics, and society in
accordance with some of the radical-liberal premises from which Marxism
departed in the second half of the nineteenth century. A new politics of
evolutionary socialism must firmly commit itself to intersystemic stra-
tegies aimed at advancing political and economic democracy and civil
rights, enhancing the social choices of the disadvantaged, and pursuing
deliberative, rational forms of public discourse.
Therefore, the most appropriate vehicle for liberal-socialist demands
remains the liberal language of rights which, as Bernstein argued so
forcefully, best articulates progressive principles: the expansion of per-
sonal rights at the expense of property rights, thus making socially
consequential power accountable to the will of all citizens.19 Social
democracy cannot simply jettison the specific institutional form of
modern liberal democracy without risking the reunification of state and
society in a totalizing way and thus the surrender of representative
democracy as such.20
The central tasks of extending political and economic democracy and
reconstructing the sphere of civil society between the market and the state
means that the old socialist goal of "overcoming the capitalist system"
must be abandoned. Here, Bernstein needs just as much revision as Marx,
for the post-World War II era has clearly indicated the limits of a
piecemeal reformism in a capitalist system which produces both social
inequality and the revenues needed for redistributive welfare measures.21
This appreciation of the market as intrinsically connected to liberal
democracy may strike inveterate Marxists (some of whom still advocate
political control by workers' councils) as "defeatist."22 So be it. Michael
Harrington has put it best when he insisted that modern social democracy
19
This is the thesis of Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis in Democracy and Capitalism:
Property, Community, and the Contradictions of Modern Social Thought, a study that argues
in favor of "post-liberal democracy."
20
See Agnes Heller, "On Formal Democracy," in John Keane, ed. Civil Society and the State
(London: Verso, 1988), pp. 131-133.
21
This point has been made in great detail by Noberto Bobbio, Which Socialism?
(Cambridge: Cambridge UP, 1986), pp. 100-101.
22
See, for example, Alex Callinicos, The Revenge of History: Marxism and the East European
Revolutions (University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press, 1991), pp.
109-113.
Epilogue 259
must understand itself "on the basis of ethical values and not simply in
terms of the material interests of a single class."23
Is therefore the tension between ethical socialist principles and the
necessary instrumentalism that comes from accepting some form of
market economy unresolvable? Stated in such absolute terms, the answer
is yes. But the inescapability from some instrumentalism under conditions
of advanced capitalism does not mean that there isn't significant room for
change and improvement. In fact, ethical socialists fulfill the important
task of reminding Praktiker who separate values from political activities of
the importance of ideals guiding practice. At the same time, ethical
idealists must be made to recognize the necessity of pragmatic strategies in
democratic politics. Without relying on absolute assurances, progressives
are called upon to issue political judgments under ever-changing social
conditions that may encourage a variety of competing and conflicting
maxims of choice.
The celebration of the quest for this elusive "middle way" is Bernstein's
legacy to socialist theory. Necessary instrumental considerations of
proficient means must be balanced with core principles of "responsive-
ness to individual will, non-arbitrariness, social efficiency and economy,
fairness in distributions and in distinctions of recognition and reward."24
The transcendental character of a socialist ethic prescribes the moral duty
of striving for the realization of the Enlightenment ideals while making
their full implementation impossible. As Charles W. Anderson has
pointed out, the justification for such a "middle way" lies not in its appeal
to considerations of first philosophy, but in its search for the best fit
between theory and practice, continuously taking stock and reappraising
its convictions and commitments to the ideals of good practice, "in the
light of the intrinsic aims of the enterprise itself."25 Rather than furnishing
all-encompassing philosophical systems or dogmatic truths, Bernstein
defined the task of the socialist theorist as supplying the "theoretical
outline of a fundamentally reformist social democratic politics."26
True, Bernstein's delicate balancing act of principles and political
effectiveness could neither prevent the growth of social democratic
instrumentalism nor the birth of a soviet-style voluntarist fanaticism.
There is no doubt, however, that these extreme positions have weakened
the critical impulse in socialism and engulfed the entire socialist project in
a profound sense of disillusionment. In addition, social democracy's lack
23
Harrington, Socialism Past and Future, p. 276.
24
Charles W. Anderson, Pragmatic Liberalism (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1990), pp. x-xi.
25
Ibid., pp. 180, 189.
26
B e r n s t e i n , Wie eine Revolution zu Ende ging, p . 9.
260 Epilogue
of vision has led to its poor theoretical response vis-a-vis the rising
"post-material" forces of the ecological Left and the New Right. Without
the theoretical and institutional renewal of socialism, the 150-year
paradigm of social democracy is in grave danger of slipping into historical
insignificance.
Thus, there is no closure on Bernstein's quest for evolutionary social-
ism. It will continue in those political thinkers and social reformers who
understand their task as a permanent balancing act aimed at increasing the
correspondence of ethical principles and political praxis. Like Bernstein,
they will reject the intellectual hubris of Marxism and settle for the more
modest role of mediating between different systems of thought in the
name of a fundamental reformist politics which seeks to approximate the
great ideal of social justice. As Benjamin Barber put it, "[PJatience and
humility remain the chief democratic virtues, especially for social demo-
crats."27 Evolutionary socialism presupposes tolerance, the willingness to
engage with political opponents, and, above all, the willingness to change.
"After all," Bernstein once noted, "time is the greatest revisionist."28
27
Barber, " A n Epitaph for M a r x i s m , " p . 2 6 .
28
Bernstein, "Der Marx-Cultus und das Recht der Revision," p. 18.
Select bibliography
PRIMARY SOURCES
ARCHIVAL MATERIALS
Periodical literature
A rbeiter-Zeitung
Archiv fur Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik
Archiv fur die Geschichte des Sozialismus und der Arbeiterbewegung
Berliner Volksblatt
Dokumente des Fortschritts
Dokumente des Sozialismus
Die Friedenswarte
Die Hilfe
Justice
Leipziger Volkszeitung
The Nation
Neue Deutsche Rundschau {Freie Volksbuhne)
Die Neue Gesellschaft
Die Neue Zeit
Preussische Jahrbucher
The Progressive Review
La Revue socialiste
Der Sozialdemokrat
Die Sozialistischen Monatshefte (Sozialistischer Akademiker, 1895-6; thereafter
Sozialistische Monatshefte)
Vorwdrts
261
262 Select bibliography
Von der Sekte zur Partei: Die deutsche Sozialdemokratie Einst undjetzt. Jena, 1911
Von 1850 bis 1872: Kindheit und Jugendjahre. Berlin, 1926
"Vorwort," in Noe Zhordaniya, Marxismus und Demokratie. Berlin, 1921
"Vorwort des Herausgebers," in David Koigen, Die Kultur der Demokratie. Jena,
1912
Die Wahrheit u'ber die Einkreisung Deutschlands: Dem deutschen Volke dargelegt.
Berlin, 1919
Was ist der Marxismus: Antwort auf eine Hetze. Berlin, 1924
Was die Sozialdemokratie will. Die Ziele, die Grundsdtze und die Politik der
Sozialdemokratie. n. d. [1920]
Wesen und Ansichten des burgerlichen Radikalismus. Munich, 1915
Wie eine Revolution zugrunde ging. Stuttgart, 1921
Wirtschaftswesen und Wirtschaftswerden: Drei gemeinverstdndliche Abhandlungen.
Berlin, 1920
Zur Frage: Socialliberalismus oder Collectivismus. Berlin, 1900
Zur Geschichte und Theorie des Sozialismus. 4th ed. Berlin, 1904
SECONDARY SOURCES
BOOKS AND DISSERTATIONS
Abendroth, Wolfgang, Aufstieg undKrise der deutschen Sozialdemokratie. Frankfurt,
1969
After the Fall: The Failure of Communism and the Future of Socialism. Robin
Blackburn, ed. London, 1991
Anderson, Charles W., Pragmatic Liberalism. Chicago, 1990
Angel, Pierre, Eduard Bernstein et L'Evolution du Socialisme Allemand. Paris, 1961
Arato, Andrew, and Joshua Cohen, Civil Society and Political Theory. Boston, 1992
Aronson, Ronald, After Marxism. New York, 1995
Aschheim, Steven E., The Nietzsche Legacy in Germany 1890-1990. Berkeley, CA,
1992
Avineri, Shlomo, The Social and Political Thought of Karl Marx. Cambridge, 1968
Ball, Terence, Reappraising Political Theory. Oxford, 1995
Barber, Benjamin, Strong Democracy. Berkeley, CA, 1984
Baron, Samuel, Plekhanov: The Father of Russian Marxism. Stanford, CA, 1963
Barone, Charles A., Marxist Thought on Imperialism: Survey and Critique. London,
1985
Basler, Gerhard P., "The Origins of German Communism. 1900-1917." PhD
dissertation, University of Kansas, 1966
Bassermann, Karola, Ernst Bassermann. Mannheim, 1919
Beilharz, Peter, Postmodern Socialism. Melbourne, 1994
Labour's Utopias: Bolshevism, Fabianism, Social Democracy. London, 1992
Bellamy, Richard, Liberalism and Modern Society. University Park, PA, 1992
266 Select bibliography
Berlau, Joseph A., The German Social Democratic Party 1914-1921. New York,
1949
Bernstein to Brandt: A Short History of German Social Democracy. Roger Fletcher,
ed. London, 1987
Bernstein und der demokratische Sozialismus. Horst Heimann and Thomas Meyer,
eds. Berlin, 1978
The Betrayal of Marx. Frederick Bender, ed. New York, 1976
Between Totalitarianism and Postmodernity. Peter Beilharz, Gillian Robinson, and
John Rundell, eds. Cambridge, MA, 1992
Blaazer, David, The Popular Front and the Progressive Tradition: Socialists, Liberals,
and the Quest for Unity, 1884-1939. Cambridge, 1992
Bobbio, Noberto, Which Socialism? Cambridge, 1986
Liberalism and Democracy. London, 1988
Boggs, Carl, The Socialist Tradition: From Crisis to Decline. New York, 1995
Bouvier, Beatrix W., Franzosische Revolution und deutsche Arbeiterbewegung.
Bonn-Bad Godesberg, 1982
Bowles Samuel, and Herbert Gintis,, Democracy and Capitalism: Property, Commu-
nity, and the Contradictions of Modern Social Thought. New York, 1987
Braun-Vogelstein, Julie, Heinrich Braun. Stuttgart, 1967
Braunthal, Julius, History of the International 1864-1914. Henry Collins and
Kenneth Mitchell, trans. London, 1966
Breitman, R., German Socialism and Weimar Democracy. Chapel Hill, NC, 1981
Breuilly, John, Labour and Liberalism in Nineteenth-Century Europe: Essays in
Comparative History. Manchester, 1992
Briggs, A., Victorian People. London, 1954
Bronner, Stephen Eric, Rosa Luxemburg: A Revolutionary for Our Time. New York,
1987
Socialism Unbound. New York, 1990
Moments of Decision. New York, 1992
Buse, Dieter K., "Friedrich Ebert and German Socialism, 1871-1919." PhD
disseration, University of Oregon, 1972
Callari, Antonio, Stephen Cullenberg, and Carole Biewener, Marxism in the
Postmodern Age. New York, 1994
Callinicos, Alex, The Revenge of History: Marxism and the East European Revol-
utions. University Park, PA, 1991
Marxism and Philosophy. New York, 1985
Carsten, Francis L., Eduard Bernstein 1850-1932: Eine politische Biographie.
Munich, 1993
August Bebel und die Organisation der Massen. Berlin, 1991
Carver, Terrell, Marx and Engels: The Intellectual Relationship. Bloomington, IN,
1983
Friedrich Engels. His Life and Thought. Manchester, 1989
Civil Society and the State. John Keane, ed. London, 1988
Clarke, Peter, Liberals and Social Democrats. Cambridge, 1978
Cohen, G. A., Karl Marx's Theory of History. Princeton, 1978
Cole, G. D. H., A History of Socialist Thought. 3 vols. London, 1953-6
Coletti, Lucio, From Rousseau to Lenin. London, 1974
Select bibliography 267
Grebing, Helga, Der Revisionismus: Von Bernstein bis zum 'Prager Fruhling'.
Munich, 1977
Greenfield, Liah, Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity. Cambridge, MA, 1992
Groh, Dieter, Negative Integration und revolutiondrer Attentismus: Die deutsche
Sozialdemokratie am Vorabend des Ersten Weltkrieges Frankfurt-Main, 1973
Grundsdtzliches zum Tageskampf: Festgabe fur Eduard Bernstein. Mitarbeiter des
Breslauer Volkswacht, eds. Breslau, 1925
Giinther, Ernst, "Die revisionistische Bewegung in der deutschen Sozialdemok-
ratie, Teil I: Die allgemeinen theoretischen Grundlagen." PhD dissertation,
Universitat Freiburg, 1905
Gustafsson, Bo, Marxismus und Revisionismus. Frankfurt-Main, 1972
Guttsman, W. L., The German Social Democratic Party 1875-1933. London, 1981
Habermas, Jurgen, Knowledge and Human Interest. Boston, 1971
Der philosophische Diskurs der Moderne. Frankfurt-Main, 1985
Die Nachholende Revolution. Frankfurt-Main, 1990
Texte und Kontexte. Frankfurt-Main, 1991
Hall, Alex, Scandal, Sensation and Social Democracy: The SPD Press and Wilhelmine
Germany 1890-1914. Cambridge, 1977
Hansen, F. R., The Breakdown of Capitalism: A History of the Idea in Western
Marxism, 1883-1983. London, 1985
Harrington, Michael, Socialism Past & Future. New York, 1989
Harris, James F., A Study in the Theory and Practice of German Liberalism: Eduard
Lasher, 1829-1884. Lanham, M D , 1984
Heckart, Beverly, From Bassermann to Bebel: The Grand Bloc's Quest for Reform in
the Kaiserreich, 1900-1914. New Haven, CT, 1974
Heimann, Horst, Die Voraussetzungen des Demokratischen Sozialismus und die
Aufgaben der Sozialdemokratie. Bonn, 1991
Hirsch, Helmut, August Bebel. Sein Leben in Dokumenten, Reden und Schriften.
Koln-Berlin, 1968
Der "Fabier" Eduard Bernstein. Berlin, 1977
Holthey, Helmut, Cohen and Natorp. 2 vols. Basle, 1986
Holzheuer, Walter, Karl Kautskys Werk als Weltanschauung. Beitrag zur Ideologic
der Sozialdemokratie vor dem Ersten Weltkrieg. Munich, 1972
Howard, Dick, From Marx to Kant. Albany, 1985
Howard, M. C. and J. E. King, A History ofMarxian Economics: vol. I, 1883-1929.
Princeton, 1989
Hulse, James W., Revolutionists in London. A Study of Five Unorthodox Socialists.
Oxford, 1970
Hunley, J. D., The Life and Thought of Friedrich Engels. New Haven, CT,
1991
Hiinlich, Reinhold, Karl Kautsky und der Marxismus der II Internationale. Marburg,
1981
Hunt, Richard N., German Social Democracy 1918-1933. New Haven, 1964
Hyrkkanen, Markku, Sozialistische Kolonialpolitik: Eduard Bernsteins Stellung zur
Kolonialpolitik und zum Imperialisms 1882-1914. Helsinki, 1986
Imperial Germany. James J. Sheehan, ed. New York, 1976
Jacobs, Jack, On Socialism and the Jewish Question after Marx. New York, 1993
Select bibliography 269
Socialism in History: Political Essays of Henry Pachter. Stephen Eric Bronner, ed.
New York, 1984
Stammer, Gerhard, Die Kunst des Unmoglichen oder die Politik der Befreiung: Uber
Eduard Bernsteins halbherzigen Versuch, Marx mit Kant zu korrigieren. Frank-
furt-Main, 1989
Stargardt, Nicholas, The German Idea of Militarism: Radical and Socialist Criticsy
1866-1914. Cambridge, MA, 1994
Steenson, Gary P., After Marx, Before Lenin: Marxism and Socialist Working-Class
Parties in Europe, 1884-1914. Pittsburgh, 1991
KarlKautsky, 1854-1938: Marxism in the Classical Years. Pittsburgh, 1978.
"Not One Man! Not One Penny!" German Social Democracy, 1863-1914.
Pittsburgh, 1981
Steigerwald, Robert, Burgerliche Philosophic und Revisionismus im imperialistischen
Deutschland. Berlin, 1980
Steinberg, Hans-Josef, Die deutsche sozialistische Arbeiterbewegung bis 1914. Frank-
furt-Main, 1979
Sozialismus und deutsche Sozialdemokratie. 4th ed. Berlin, 1976
Steinmetz, George, Regulating the Social: The Welfare State and Local Politics in
Imperial Germany. Princeton, 1993
Stern, Fritz, The Failure of Illiberalism. New York, 1992
Strutynski, Peter, Die Auseinandersetzungen zwischen Marxisten und Revisionisten in
der deutschen Arbeiterbewegung der Jahrhundertwende. Koln, 1976
Sweezy, Paul, The Theory of Capitalist Development. New York, 1946
Taylor, Charles, The Ethics of Authenticity. Cambridge, MA, 1992
Tetzel, Manfred, Philosophie und Okonomie oder das Exempel Bernstein. Berlin,
1984
Theiner, Peter, Sozialer Liberalismus und deutsche Weltpolitik: Friedrich Naumann
im Wilhelminischen Deutschland, 1860-1919. Baden-Baden, 1983
Tschubinski, Wadim, Wilhelm Liebknecht. EineBiographie. Bernhardjahnel, trans.
Berlin, 1973
Tsuzuki, Chushichi, H. M. Hyndman and British Socialism. London, 1961
Tucker, Robert C , Philosophy and Myth in Karl Marx. 2nd ed. Cambridge, 1972
The Value Controversy. Ian Steedman, ed. London, 1981
van der Berg, Axel, The Immanent Utopia. Princeton, 1988
van der Linden, Harry, Kantian Ethics and Socialism. Indianapolis, 1988
Victorian Liberalism: Nineteenth Century Political Thought and Practice. Richard
Bellamy, ed. London, 1990
Volkagonov, Dmitri, Lenin. New York, 1994
Vorlander, Karl, Kant und Marx: Ein Beitrag zur Philosophie des Sozialismus.
Tubingen, 1926
(
Walther, Rudolf, ". . .abernachderSundflutkommenwirundnurwir": Zusammen-
3
bruchstheorie , Marxismus und politisches Defizit in der SPD, 1890-1914.
Frankfurt-Main, 1981
Walzer, Michael, Spheres of Justice. New York, 1983
Wegner, Konstanze, Theodor Barth und die Freisinnige Vereinigung: Studien zur
Geschichte des Linksliberalismus im wilhelminischen Deutschland, 1893-1910.
Tubingen, 1968
Select bibliography 273
West, Cornel, The Ethical Dimensions of Marxist Thought. New York, 1991
Wette, Wolfram, Kriegstheorien Deutscher Sozialisten. Stuttgart, 1971
White, Stephen K., Political Theory and Postmodernism. Cambridge, 1991
Willey, Thomas. Back to Kant. Detroit, 1978
Winkler, Heinrich August, Liberalismus und Antiliberalismus. Gottingen, 1979
Der Schein der Normalitdt. Arbeiter und Arbeiterbewegung in der Weimarer
Republic 1924-1930. Berlin-Bonn, 1985
Von der Revolution zur Stabilisierung: Arbeiter und Arbeiterbewegung in der
Weimarer Republik, 1918 bis 1924. Berlin-Bonn, 1984
Wistrich, Robert S., Revolutionary Jews from Marx to Trotsky. New York, 1976
Wollstein, Giinther, Theobald von Bethmann Hollweg: LetzterErbe Bismarcks, erstes
Opfer der Dolchstosslegende. Gottingen, 1995
Working-Class Formation: Nineteenth-Century Patterns in Western Europe and the
United States. Ira Katznelson and Aristide Zolberg, eds. Princeton,
1986
Zarusky, Jurgen, Die deutschen Sozialdemokraten und das sowjetische Modell:
Ideologische Auseinandersetzungen und aussenpolitische Konzeptionen,
1917-1933. Munich, 1992
ARTICLES IN JOURNALS
Barber, Benjamin R., "An Epitaph for Marxism," Social Science and Modern
Society 33.1 (1995), pp. 22-26
Blackburn, Robin, "Fin de Siecle: Socialism after the Crash," New Left Review
185 (1991), pp. 5-66
Brown, Doug, "Thorstein Veblen Meets Eduard Bernstein: Toward an Institu-
tionalist Theory of Mobilization Politics," Journal of Economic Issues 25.3
(September 1991), pp. 689-708
Carsten, Francis, "Georg von Vollmar: A Bavarian Social Democrat," Journal of
Contemporary History 25 (1990), pp. 317-335
Colletti, Lucio, "The Theory of Crash," Telos 13 (Fall, 1972), pp. 34-36
Fetscher, Iring, "Das Verhaltnis des Marxismus zu Hegel," Marxismusstudien III
(1960), pp. 66-169
Fletcher, Roger, "Revisionism and Wilhelmine Imperialism," Journal of Contem-
porary History 23 (1988), pp. 347-366
"Revisionism and Nationalism: Eduard Bernstein's Views on the National
Question, 1900-1914," in Canadian Review of Studies in Nationalism 11.1
(1984), pp. 103-117
"Cobden as Educator: The Free-Trade Internationalism of Eduard Bern-
stein," The American Historical Review 83 (1983), pp. 561-578
"In the Interest of Peace and Progress: Eduard Bernstein's Socialist Foreign
Policy," Review of International Studies 9 (1983), pp. 79-93
"British Radicalism and German Revisionism: The Case of Eduard Bernstein,"
The International History Review 4.3 (1982), pp. 339-370
"A Revisionist Looks at Imperialism: Eduard Bernstein's Critique of Imperial-
ism and Kolonialpolitik, 1900-1914," Central European History 12 (1979), pp.
237-271
274 Select bibliography
"World Power Without War: Eduard Bernstein's Proposals for Alternative
Weltpolitik" Australian Journal for Politics and History 25 (1979), pp.
228-236
"Bernstein in Britain: Revisionism and Foreign Affairs," The International
History Review 1 (1979), pp. 349-375
"An English Advocate in Germany: Eduard Bernstein's Analysis of Anglo-
German Relations, 1900-1914," Canadian Journal of History 13 (1978), pp.
209-235
Fricke, Dieter, "Zum Bruch Eduard Bernsteins mit den 'Sozialistischen Monat-
sheften' im Herbst 1914," BzG (1975/3), pp. 454-468
"Die Ruckkehr Eduard Bernsteins in das Deutsche Reich 1901," Zeitschriftfur
Geschichtswissenschaft 22.12 (1974), pp. 1,341-1,347
Fukuyama, Francis, "The End of History," The National Interest 16 (Summer,
1989), pp. 3-18
Fulberth, Georg, "Zur Genese des Revisionismus in der deutschen Sozialdemok-
ratie vor 1914," Das Argument 13.1-2 (March 1971), pp. 1-21
Gorman, Robert A., "Empirical Marxism," History and Theory 20.4 (1981), pp.
403-423.
Heimann, Horst, "Die Bedeutungdes revisionistisch-reformistischenTheoriean-
satzes Bernsteins fur den demokratischen Sozialismus," Neue Gesellschaft 24
(December 1977), pp. 1,017-22
Hill, C. E., "Sidney Webb and the Common Good: 1887-1889," History of
Political Thought 14.4 (Winter, 1993), pp. 591-622
Keck, Timothy, "The Marburg School and Ethical Socialism," The Social Science
Journal 14.3 (1977), pp. 105-119
Kleger, Heinz, "Evolutionarer Sozialismus. Oder: warum noch einmal Bernstein
lesen?," Widerspruch 19/90 (1990), pp. 38-52
Koth, Harald, "Der subjektive Faktor in Theorie und Praxis bei Karl Kautsky und
Eduard Bernstein (1890-1896)," Beitrdge zur Marx-Engels-Forschung 16
(1984), pp. 265-270
Marks, Harry, "The Sources of Reformism in the Social Democratic Party of
Germany, 1890-1914," Journal of Modern History 11 (1939), pp.
334-356
Morgan, David W., The Father of Revisionism Revisited: Eduard Bernstein,"
Journal of Modern History 51 (September, 1979), pp. 525-532
MourTe, Chantal, "Toward a Liberal Socialism?," Dissent (Winter, 1993), pp.
81-87
Offe, Claus, "Thesis on the Theory of State," New German Critique 6 (Fall, 1975),
pp. 137-147
Pierson, Stanley, "Ernest Belfort Bax: 1854-1926. The Encounter of Marxism
and Late Victorian Culture," The Journal of British Studies 12 (1972), pp.
39-60
Radice, Giles, "The Case for Revisionism," The Political Quarterly 59 (1988), pp.
404-415
Rogers, H. Kendall, "Eduard Bernstein Speaks to the Fabians: A Turning-Point
in Social Democratic Thought?," International Review of Social History 28
(1983), pp. 320-338
Select bibliography 275
ARTICLES IN COLLECTIONS
Bohm-Bawerk, Eugen, "Karl Marx and the Close of his System," in Sweezy, Karl
Marx and the Close of his System
Duncan, Graeme, "The Marxist Theory of the State," in Parkinson, Marx and
Marxisms
Eley, Geoff, "Liberalism, Europe, and the Bourgeoisie, 1860-1914," in Black-
bourn and Evans, The German Bourgeoisie
Freudenthal, Gideon, "Otto Neurath: From Authoritarian Liberalism to Empiri-
cism," in Dascal and Griingard, Knowledge and Politics
Gneuss, Christian, "The Precursor: Eduard Bernstein," in Labedz, Revisionism
Heller, Agnes, "On Formal Democracy," in John Keane, ed. Civil Society and the
State
Himmelmann, Gerhard, "Die Rolle der Werttheorie in Bernsteins Konzept der
politischen Okonomie des Sozialismus," in Heimann and Meyer, Bernstein
und der demokratische Sozialismus
Kocka, Jiirgen, "Problems of Working-Class Formation in Germany," in Ira
Katznelson and Aristide Zolberg, Working-Class Formation: Nineteenth Cen-
tury Patterns in Western Europe and the United States
Meyer, Thomas, "Elemente einer Gesamttheorie des Demokratischen Sozialis-
mus und Hinderung ihrer Durchsetzung in der Weimarer Republik," in
Heimann and Meyer, Reformsozialismus und Sozialdemokratie
Miller, Susanne, "Bernstein's Political Position 1914-1920," in Fletcher, Bern-
stein to Brandt
Mommsen, Hans, "Nationalismus und die nationale Frage im Denken Eduard
Bernsteins," in Heimann and Meyer, Bernstein und der demokratische
Sozialismus
Neubach, Helmut, "Von Franz Ziegler bis Eduard Bernstein: Die Vertreter der
Stadt Breslau im Deutschen Reichstag, 1871-1918," in Johannes Barmann,
Alois Gerlach, and Ludwig Petry, Geschichtliche Landeskunde, vol. II, Wies-
baden, 1969
Neumann, Lothar F., "Die Werttheorie und der Sozialismus bei Marx, Bernstein
und in der heutigen Diskussion," in Heimann and Meyer, Bernstein und der
demokratische Sozialismus
Pachter, Henry, "The Ambiguous Legacy of Eduard Bernstein," in Bronner,
Socialism in History
276 Select bibliography
277
278 Index
Bernstein, Eduard (cont.) Bernstein, Max (Bernstein's brother), 25,
and Engels' Anti-Duhring, 40 33
in England, 47, 57-59, 66-70, 166-167 Bernstein, Regine (formerly
family origins and childhood, 21-25 Zadek-Schattner, Bernstein's wife),
images of, 19-21 56-56, 245
last years, 245-247 "Bernstein Renaissance" (1970s), 146
lectures— Bismarck, Prince Otto von, 28, 29, 31, 32
"How Is Scientific Socialism anti-socialist laws, 41-45, 53, 57, 60
Possible?," 167 dismissal of, 59
"What is Socialism," 223 and Lassalle, 36
"What Marx Really Taught," 74 social legislation, 44, 51
marriage, 56 Blanqui, Auguste, 236
nervous breakdown, 70 Bloch, Joseph, 166, 191-192, 199, 210
as Reichstag representative, 167-171 Bios, Wilhelm, 44, 50
and religion, 25-26 Blum, Leon, 251
return to Germany, 165-167 Bobbio, Norberto, 251
school years, 25-27 Bohm-Bawerk, Eugen von, 120, 124-125,
"sexual education," 27 126
as a socialist, 27-34 Bolshevism, Bernstein's critique of, 224,
"Stuttgart Letter," 84 236-241
in Switzerland, 45-57 bourgeois press, and the Revisionist
and the USPD, 224 Controversy, 162-165
works— Brandt, Willy, 253
"The Bolshevist Brand of Socialism," Braun, Adolf, 243
239-240 Braun, Heinrich, 160-162, 163
"Class and Class Struggle," 173 Braun, Lily, 176
Commentary on the Gorlitz Party Braunthal, Julius, 10
Program, 227-228 Breitscheid, Rudolf, 191
Cromwell and Communism, 58, 172, Brentano, Lujo, 5, 31, 33, 38, 220
248 Breslau Party Congress (1895), 72
The Essence of Economics and EconomicBreuel, Ernst, 50-51
Development, 225 Bright, John, 220
Ferdinand Lassalle As a Social Britain—
Reformer, 58, 248 Bernstein in England, 47, 57-59,
From Sect to Party, 111 66-70, 166-167
The German Revolution, 225 and the Kaiser's foreign policy,
History of the Berlin Labor Movement, 202-203
172 labor movement, 47, 66-70
The Labor Movement, 177 liberals, 67-69, 131,210
"The Nationalism of Fichte and Bronner, Stephen Eric, 174, 248
Lassale," 202 Brunhuber, Robert, 164
"Parliamentarianism and Social Biichner, Georg, 34
Democracy," 172 Biichner, Ludwig, 47, 111
The Preconditions of Socialism, 85, Buckle, Thomas Henry, 47
151, 155, 157, 159-160, 173, 236 Bukharin, M., 239
Socialism Past and Present, 225-226 Bulow, Chancellor Prince Bernhard von,
"The Task of the Hour," 246-247 166, 176, 189
"Three Star Article," 173 "Bulow Bloc," 190-191
"Twelve Principles of the Political Butler, Judith, 254
Mass Strike," 188
and Zionism, 221-223 Calwer, Richard, 193
Bernstein, Jakob (Berstein's father), 21, Campbell-Bannerman, Henry, 220
23, 24, 25, 26 Capital (Marx), 40, 58, 71, 76, 89, 93, 117
Bernstein, Johanna (Bernstein's mother), and Bolshevism, 238
21,23-24,25 and the labor theory of value, 121
Index 279
and Marxism socialism, 89, 90, 91 Darwin, Charles, 47
capitalism— Origin of the Species, 93
advanced, 9, 10, 11 David, Eduard, 59, 83, 116, 156, 209,
and Bernstein's revisionism, 80-81 212
and historical materialism, 112-113 and the First World War, 219, 220,
and liberal socialism, 139 221
post-industrial, 253-254 democracy—
and scientific socialism, 94-95, 102 and Bernstein's evolutionary socialism,
and theories of value, 120-128 7-8, 10, 143
theory of "collapse" of, 32, 54, 70, 77, as a cooperative ideal, 257
80, 94, 95, 102, 153 direct, 131, 143, 228
Caprivi, Leo von, 59 extending political and economic,
Carey, Henry, 38 140-147
Catholic Centre Party, 176, 190 representative, 143
Central Working Alliance, 231 Democratic Union Party, 194
civil liberty, 138 Dietz, J. H. W., 50
civil society, and liberal socialism, 135, Dilthey, Wilhelm, 116, 248
136, 137-138, 258 direct democracy, 131, 143, 228
class— Dolchstosslegende, 241-242
and Bernstein's revisionism, 82, Duhring, Eugen, 7, 31, 34, 38-39, 111
173-174, 176, 205 see also Anti-Duhring
in the Weimer Republic, 233
class conflict, and "liberal" socialism, Ebert, Friedrich, 12, 213, 217, 219, 225,
132-133 231,241,243
Cobden, Richard, 7, 67-68, 210 economic democracy, extending, 140-147
Cohen, G. A., 125 economic policies, and left-liberalism,
Cohen, Hermann, 116, 118 158
Coleridge, Samuel Taylor, 68 Einstein, Albert, 21, 220
Coletti, Lucio, 125 "Eisenacher" socialists, 30-31, 32, 36-37,
colonialism, and culture, 205-211 38, 53, 144, 213, 217, 244
commodity fetishism, 121-122 Eisner, Kurt, 116, 180, 215
Communist Manifesto (Marx and Engels), Elm, Adolf von, 182
9,32, 37,43, 153 Elster, Jon, 125
and Bolshevism, 236, 237-238 empiricism, and Bernstein's evolutionary
and historical materialism, 110 socialism, 117
and liberalism, 135 encirclement theory, 241
and scientific socialism, 91 end of socialism, 6, 14-15
and the SPD Youngsters' rebellion, 60, and evolutionary socialism, 253-260
61 Engels, Friedrich, 4, 8, 19, 26, 118
Comte, A., 99 Anti-Duhring, 39^0, 41, 45, 46, 48,
Constitutional Patriotism, 198 91,92,93-94, 171
cooperation, and evolutionsary socialism, and Bernstein in England, 69, 70-71
139-140 Bernstein as successor of, 249
cooperative ideal, democracy as a, 257 Bernstein's relations with, 47, 55, 58,
cosmopolitan patriotism, 202 59,71
"Covenant of Peace among the Nations," and Bernstein's revisionism, 78-79,
203 80-81,84, 103, 144, 164
critical idealism, 116, 157 and Bernstein's wife, 57
critical socialism, 107 and Bolshevism, 237, 238
Critical Theory, 251 and colonialism, 205, 206
cultural rights, 208 and criticism of Kautsky, 49-50
culture, and colonialism, 205-211 and critics of Bernstein, 153, 154
Cunow, Heinrich, 219, 227 death, 71
and Der Sozialdemokrat, 51
Dahrendorf, Ralf, 10 and the Franco-Prussian War, 219
280 Index
Engels, Friedrich (cont.) Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 34, 36, 79
and the German workers' movement, and Bernstein's "noble patriotism,"
34, 37, 45 201-202
and the Gotha Program, 38 First World War, 217-223
and historical materialism, 110-112 and German war guilt, 241-244
and Hochberg, 45-46 Flesch, Karl, 46
influence on Bernstein, 248 Fourier, Charles, 79, 95, 105
and the "Lassalle Legend," 63 Fox, Charles James, 220
and liberal democracy, 134 France—
Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of 1848 revolution, 236
Classical German Philosophy, 111 Millerand Affair, 155-156
and Marxist socialism, 89-90 and the Moroccan Crisis (1905), 190
and the mass-strike debate, 186 Franco-Prussian War (1870), 27, 31, 172,
The Origin of the Family, Private Property 219, 244
and the State, 134 Frankfurt National Assembly, 24, 34
and scientific socialism, 92-94, 95, Frankfurt School of Social Research, 251
100-101, 175 free trade, 210, 223
Socialism: Utopian and Scientific, 92 freedom, individual, 130, 137, 138
and the SPD— Freiheity Die (Liberty), 43
Erfurt Party Program, 64-65 French Labor Party, 110
policy of "intransigent opposition," French "Minimalist Program," 63
53-54, 55 French Revolution, 255
socialist revolution blueprint, 61-62 and liberal socialism, 136, 137, 139
Youngsters' rebellion, 60-61 Fritzsche, Friedrich, 29, 30
on the state, 130 Fukuyama, Francis, 253
see also Communist Manifesto
Erfurt Party Program (1891), 62-65, 66, Gay, Peter, 1
73, 80, 83, 91, 226 Geiser, Bruno, 44
and Bernstein's revisionism, 157, 175 General German Workers' Association
Kautsky's commentary on the, 91, (ADAV), 36
94-95 German Communist Party (KPD), 228,
and Kautsky's The Road to Power, 214 229, 232, 240
1921 revision of, 231 German Democratic Pary, 232
and scientific socialism, 100, 106, 107 German labor movement, 34-40
Erzberger, Matthias, 190 see also SPD (German Social
ethical socialism, 45, 74, 253 Democratic Party)
and Bernstein's revisionism, 97 German liberalism, 22
and instrumentalism, 259 decline of, 28, 33
ethics— "German Question," 196, 241
and historical materialism, 108-115 German Revolution (1918-19), 142,
and scientific socialism, 128 223-225, 236
and theories of value, 127-128 German social democracy, 2, 3, 34^40
ethnonationalism, 199-200, 201, 203, see also SPD (German Social
204,218 Democratic Party)
Eurocommunism, 253 German war guilt, and the socialist right,
European social democracy— 241-244
crisis of, 1,2 Gohre, Paul, 161
and pluralism, 256 Golitz Program (1921), 13, 226-229, 231
evolution and sexual behaviour, 207 Gotha Program (1875), 38, 63, 65
exchange value, 121 Gouldner, Alvin, 89
Great Depression (1873), 32, 49
Fabian socialism, and Bernstein, 66-68 Great War, 217-223
factory councils, 227-228 Grey, Sir Edward, 206, 209
Falkenhayn, Erich von, 201, 202 Grillenberger, Franz, 44, 51
Ferry, Luc, 251 Groener, Wilhelm, 231
Index 281
Groh, Dieter, 62 Hyndman, Henry, 69-70, 153
Griin, Karl, 34
Guesde, Jules, 43, 155 ILP (Independent Labour Party), 68
"immiseration thesis," 82
Haase, Hugo, 218, 219, 222, 225 Imperial Government steamship bill,
Habermas Jiirgen, 198, 255 51-53
Haeckel, Ernst, 47 Independent Labour Party (ILP), 68
Hallgarten, Charles, 161 individual freedom—
Hardy, James Keir, 68 and liberal socialism, 137, 138
Harrington, Michael, 258-259 and the state, 130
Harrison, Austin F., 164-165 industrialization in Germany, 76, 158
Hasenclever, Wilhelm, 44, 50, 51
Hasselmann, Wilhelm, 43 Jacobinism, 172
Hatzfeldt, Countess Sophia von, 35, 36 Jacoby, Johann, 7, 24, 35
Hegel, G. W. F., 9, 75-76, 79, 92, 249 Jaures, Jean, 153, 219, 248, 251
and historical materialism, 111 Jevons, Stanley, 120
and neo-Kantianism, 115, 116, 117 journals—
and scientific socialism, 92, 93, 96, 100 revisionist, 171
Heidegger, Martin, 254 socialist, 47
Heidelberg Program (1925), 229, 231 Sozialdemokrat, Der, 42, 46^7, 49,
Heidelberg School, 116 50-51, 53, 57,66, 197
Heimann, Eduard, 230 Sozialistische Monatshefte (journal), 166,
Heine, Wolfgang, 83, 161, 179, 186-187, 199, 210, 220
210 Vorwarts, 47, 58, 79, 84, 165, 180, 240
Heller, Hermann, 230 Judaism, 21, 23, 26
Helphand, Alexander ("Parvus"), 80, 83, and Zionism, 221-223
153,183
Heretier, Louis, 76 Kampffmeyer, Paul, 84, 212
Hes, Moses, 34 Kant, Immanuel, 7, 11, 79, 107, 114,
Hildebrand, Gerhard, 180-181 115,203
Hilferding, Rudold, 234, 246 and colonialism, 209
historical materialism, 11 and cosmopolitan patriotism, 202
and ethics, 108-115 and liberalism, 136, 137
and scientific socialism, 96, 106 Perpetual Peace, 249
History of the 1848 French Revolution and representative democracy, 143
(Heretier), 76 see also neo-Kantianism
History of British Trade Unions (Webb), 56 Kautsky, Karl, 4, 12, 39, 118
Hitler, Adolf, 235, 246, 247 on Bernstein, 20
Hobhouse, L. T., 7, 68, 131 and Bernstein in England, 70
Hobson, J. A., 7, 68, 131 and Bernstein's empiricism, 115
Hoch, Gustav, 243 and Bernstein's "noble patriotism,"
Hochberg, Dr Karl, 45-46, 48, 75, 76, 197, 201
76-77 Bernstein's relations with, 47-49, 51,
Hollweg, Chancellor Theobald von 58, 245
Bethmann, 219 and Bernstein's revisionism, 78, 83, 84,
Hook, Sidney, 1 96, 97, 119, 152-153, 157, 171,
Horkheimer, Max, 251 178, 250
Hue, Otto, 159 and the state, 132
Hugenberg, Alfred, 192 and Bolshevism, 237
human rights— and colonialism, 205
and Bernstein's evolutionary socialism, criticisms of Bernstein, 161
119 Das Erfurter Programm, 91, 94-95
and liberalism, 136, 137-138 and democracy, 176
Humboldt, Alexander von, 21 and Engels' Anti-Duhring, 40
Hunley, J. D., 249 Engels' criticism of, 49-50
282 Index
Kautsky, Karl (com.) left-liberals—
and the First World War, 220, 221 democratic alliance with socialists,
and German nationalism, 191, 193-194 194-197, 218
and German war guilt, 244 and German nationalism, 190-191
and the KPD, 229 and the mass-strike debate, 186,
and liberalism, 135 188-189
and Marxism internationalism, 203 overtures to Bernstein, 157-162
and the mass-strike debate, 183, 185, Legien, Carl, 184-185, 231
186, 188 "Leipzig High Treason Trials," 30-31
and the Millerand Affair, 155-156 Lenin, V. I., 4, 118, 140, 153, 237, 239,
and Neue Zeit (journal), 50, 55, 58 240
and reformism, 143, 210-211 What is to Be Done?, 251
The Road to Power, 214-215 Leuthner, Karl, 193, 199, 203, 252
and scientific socialism, 100, 106, 108 liberal critics of Bernstein, 12
and the SPD, 54-55, 72, 75, 78 "liberal imperialism," 206
bureaucrats, 211, 212, 214-215, 216, liberal socialism, contemporary forms of,
217 251,257-260
Dresden Party Conference, 179, 180 liberalism—
Erfurt Party Program, 63-64, 91, and Bernstein's evolutionary socialism,
94-95 6-10, 119, 177
Liibeck Party Conference (1^01), British liberals, 67-69, 210
168, 169 German, 22
Keim, General, 192 and Bernstein's "noble patriotism,"
Kingsley, Charles, 68, 71 200-201
Korsch, Karl, 251 New Liberals, 68-69, 131, 138
KPD (German Communist Party), 228, and socialism, 119, 133-140, 147, 232
229, 232, 240 and the state, 131-134
Kreisky, Bruno, 253 and the "workers" question, 29-30
see also left-liberals
labor movement— Liebknecht, Karl, murder of, 225
British, 47, 66-70 Liebknecht, Wilhelm, 30, 31, 37, 55, 118,
German, 34-40 144
see also SPD (German Social and Bernstein's revisionism, 7, 84
Democratic Party) and Duhring, 39
Labor Question, The (Lange), 75 and the Erfurt Party Program, 63
labor unions, see trade unions and evolutionary socialism, 62
Labriola, Antonio, 100, 107, 237 and the First World War, 218
Lafargue, Paul, 43 and German nationalism, 193, 194
Lange, Friedrich Albert, 4, 7, 35, 45, 74, and the Gotha Program, 38, 63
133 and the Leipzig High Treason Trials, 30
Bernstein's study of, 75-76 and the mass-strike debate, 183, 185,
and neo-Kantianism, 103, 116-118 187
"regulative ideals," 113 and the SPD bureaucrats, 217
The Labor Question, 75 and the steamship subsidy bill, 52
Lassalle, Ferdinand, 31, 34, 35-36, 37, Vorwdrts (journal), 58
38, 39, 63, 75 Lobe, Paul, 20, 247
Bernstein's study of, 58-59, 63, 248 Locke, John, 136, 208
and the Gorlitz Party Program, 227 logical positivism, 251
and the role of the state, 130 Lukacs, Georg, 115, 248, 251
and the universal suffrage, 143 Luther, Martin, 37
Lassalleans (state socialists), 53 Luxemburg, Rosa, 4, 7, 12, 118, 163
Law of Incomplete Realization, 257 and Bernstein's empiricism, 115
League of Nations, 223-224, 225 and Bernstein's revisionism, 83, 84, 89,
Ledebour, Georg, 219 96-97, 119, 152, 153-155, 165,
Lederer, Emil, 230 171
Index 283
and liberalism, 134-135 and Bernstein's revisionism, 71-85,
and the mass-strike debate, 183, 184, 151-157, 163-165,251
185, 187, 188 and Bismarck's anti-socialist laws, 45
murder of, 225 "Eisenacher" socialists, 30-31, 32,
Reform or Revolution?, 92, 95-97, 36-37, 38, 53
153-155 and factory councils, 227-228
and reformist gradualism, 143 and the German labor movement, 37,
and SPD bureaucrats, 217 41
Lyotard, Jean-Francois, 254 and German nationalism, 191-195
and historical materialism, 108-115
MacDonald, Ramsay, 68, 167, 220 and Liebknecht, 37
Malon, Benoit, 43 Marxism socialism in the 1890s, 89-97
Man, Hendrik de, 230 and the "New Left," 257
Marat, Jean Paul, 70 and political expediency, 181-182
Marburg School, 116, 117, 118 postive-inductive method of Marxist
marginal utility theories of value, 120, socialism, 99
124-126 and the SPD, 54-55, 59-60, 72,
Marx, Eleanor, 71 73-74
Marx, Karl, 4, 21,31 in the Weimar Republic, 232-234
and Bernstein, 12, 47, 248 and theories of value, 120-128, 133
Bernstein's criticisms of, 197 "theory of breakdown," 75
and Bernstein's evolutionary socialism, and the "Three-Star Article," 46
164 see also orthodox Marxism
and Bolshevism, 237-238, 239 Marxism-Leninism—
and colonialism, 205 Bernstein's critique of, 236-241
and critics of Bernstein, 154 collapse of, 1, 2, 253
Critique of the Gotha Program, 129 Massingham, H. W., 68
and Duhring, 39 Mayer, Gustav, 162
and the Franco-Prussian War, 219 Mehring, Franz, 153, 171, 195
and the French "Minimalist Program," Meinecke, Friedrich, 248
63 Menger, Carl, 120
and the German workers' movement, Michels, Robert, On the Sociology of
34, 35, 36, 37, 45 Parties in Modern Democracy,
and the Gotha Program, 38 215-216
and historical materialism, 109, 110, Michnik, Adam, 255
111, 114 Mill, John Stuart, 4, 7, 11, 68, 75
and Hochberg, 45-46 and liberalism, 136
"immiseration thesis," 82 and representative democracy, 143
and Kautsky, 50 Miller, Suzanne, 220
Lange on, 117 Millerand, Alexandra 155-156
and Lassalle, 63 Miquel, Johannes von, 30
and liberalism, 134, 135-136 Misere de la Philosophie, 57
and Marxism socialism, 89-90, 95-96 Mitterand, Francois, 253
On the Jewish Question, 129 modernity—
"Robinson Crusoe economists," 129 and Bernstein's evolutionary socialism,
and the role of the state, 128-130 9
and scientific socialism, 92, 93, and the state, 131
100-108 Molkenbuhr, Hermann, 191
see also Capital, Communist Manifesto Mommsen, Theodor, 5
Marx-Lafargue, Laura, 61 moral historicism, 109
Marxism— More, Sir Thomas, 28
and Bernstein's evolutionary socialism, Moroccan Crises, 189, 190, 193, 202
8-10 Morris, William, 44, 68
and Bernstein's "noble patriotism," Most, Johann, 43
203-204 Motteler, Julius, 49, 57
284 Index
MSPD (Majority Socialists), 231 Owen, Robert, 68, 79, 95, 105
Muller, Hermann, 213
pacificism, 220-221
Naphtali, Fritz, 146, 230 Palme, Olof, 253
Nathan, Paul, 166, 191 Pannekoek, Anton, 153
Nation, The (journal), 166 Paris Commune (1871), 27, 41, 130
nationalism— "Parvus" (Alexander Helphand), 80, 83,
and Bernstein's "noble patriotism," 153, 183
197-204 patriotism—
ethnonationalism, 199-200, 201, 203, Bernstein's theory of noble, 197-204
204,218 constitutional, 198
Prussian, 27 cosmopolitan, 202
threat of, 189-197 "Peace Manifesto," 220-221
Nationalist Controversy, 204 Pease, Edward, 67
nationalist revisionists, 192-194, 204, Peffer, R. G., 109, 122
211,252 Peus, Heinrich, 83, 156
and the First World War, 218-219 Philosophic Radicalism, and Bernstein,
Natorp, Paul, 116, 251 67-68
natural law, 136 Pierson, Stanley, 181
Naumann, Friedrich, 5, 12, 158-160, Plekhanov, George, 4, 80, 97, 118, 153
181,201 political democracy, extending, 140-147
and colonial policies, 209 political economy, and theories of value,
Demokratie und Kaisertum, 160 120-128
Nechaiev, Sergei, 238 Popper, Karl, 109, 112,251
Nelson, Leonard, 230 post-modernism, 254
neo-Kantianism, 95, 115-119 Praktiker, 1?>-1^
and Bernstein's revisionism, 74, 75-76, private property—
97, 157, 178,251 and capitalism, 123
and Bolshevism, 239 right to, 147
and ethics, 114, 115 and the "transition question," 228
Marburg School, 116, 117, 118 protectionism, 210
and scientific socialism, 103-104, Proudhon, Pierre-Joseph, 57, 123, 127
107-108 Prussia—
Neue Rheinische Zeitung, 50 anti-Semitism, 23, 26
NeueZeit (journal), 50, 55, 58, 166, 179, 1848 revolution, 24
215 nationalism, 27
and Bernstein's revisionism, 75, 79, 84, system of government, 24-25
97, 165
Neurath, Otto, 251 Quark, Max, 59
New Fatherland Association, 220
New Liberals, 68-69, 138 Radicalism, Philosophic, 67-68
and the state, 131 Reform or Revolution? (Luxemburg), 92,
newspapers, and the Revisionist 95-97, 153-155
Controversy, 162-165 reformist gradualism, 140, 142, 201,
Nietzsche, F., 192-193 228-229, 248
noble patriotism, Bernstein's theory of, Reichstag representative, Bernstein as,
197-204 167-171
Noske, Gustav, 192, 193, 219, 225 religion, Bernstein's views on, 25-26
Nove, Alec, 125 Renaut, Alain, 251
revisionism, 71-85, 89, 90-91, 96-97,
Oberwinder, Heinrich, 48 151, 176-204
On Social Peace (Schulze-Gavernitz), 75 and Bernstein's "noble patriotism,"
Oppenheimer, Franz, 5, 157, 158 197-204
Origin of the Species (Darwin), 93 and Bernstein's writings, 171-175
Oswald, Eugen, 71 and the bourgeois press, 162-165
Index 285
critics of, 152-155, 156-157 Schulze-Delitzsch, Hermann, 22, 30
and the Dresden Party Conference Schulze-Gavernitz, Gerhard von, 75
(1903), 179-182 Schumpeter, Joseph, Capitalism, Socialism
and left-liberalism, 157-162 and Democracy, 163
and the Liibeck Party Conference Schweitzer, Johann-Baptiste, 36
(1901), 168-169 science—
and Marxist socialism, 89-91, 96-97, natural and social, 98-99, 102
163-165 and teleology, 101-108
and the mass-strike debate, 182-189 scientific socialism, 91, 92-108
Revisionist Controversy, 12-13, 20, Bernstein's refutation of, 167-168
72-85, 228 and ethics, 118
and SPD bureaucrats, 211-217 and theories of value, 127
and the threat of nationalism, 189-197 SDAP (German Social Democratic
see also nationalist revisionists Workers' Party, later SPD), 38
revolution, and reformist gradualism, 142 sexual behaviour, and evolution, 207
revolution (1848), 24, 129, 236 Shaw, George Bernard, 7, 67
Ricardo, David, 121, 122 Sighele, Scipio, 76
Richter, Eugen, 5 Simmel, Georg, 116
Rickert, Heinrich, 116 Singer, Paul, 185, 195, 205
Rifkin, Jeremy, 257 Smith, Adam, 121, 122
rights— social democracy—
cultural, 208 German, 2, 3, 34^10
and economic democracy, 147 and left-liberalism, 157-158
industrial, 144 and liberal socialism, 133
and liberal socialism, 134, 135-136, see also SPD (German Social
258 Democratic Party)
political, 144, 186 Social Democratic Association, 222
to private property, 147 social justice, ideal of, 260
see also human rights social legislation, under Bismarck, 44, 51
Robinson, Joan, 125 "Social Question," 255
Rodbertus, Carl, 34 socialism—
Roemer, John, 125 and liberalism, 119, 133-140, 147
Rosebery, Archibald Philip Primrose, fifth meaning of, 89-119
Earl of, 206 and science, 98-101
Rosselli, Carlo, 251 see also scientific socialism
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 143 Socialism and the Capitalist Economic Order
Ruskin, John, 68 (Wolf), 75
Russian revolutionaries (1905), and the socialist colonialism, 206-211
mass-strike debate, 183-184 Socialist International, Stuttgart Congress
(1907), 209
Saint-Simon, Claude Henri, Comte de, 79 Sombart, Werner, 124, 125, 126, 163
Sand, George, 47^48 Sorel, Georges, 251
Schattner, Carl, 56 Soviet communism, collapse of, 253
Scheidemann, Philip, 213, 219, 225, 241, Sozialdemokraty Der (SPD journal), 42,
243 46^7, 49, 50-51, 53, 57, 66, 197
Scheu, Andreas, 48 Sozialistische Monatshefte (journal), 166,
Scheu, Josef, 48 199, 210, 220
Schiller, Friedrich, 26, 137 Spartakus Uprising (1919), 225
Schippel, Max, 193,210 SPD (German Social Democratic
Schmidt, Helmut, 256 Party)—
Schmidt, Konrad, 7, 83, 97, 116, 251 and Bernstein as Reichstag candidate,
Schmoller, Gustav, 31 170
Schonlank, Bruno, 59, 73-74, 169 "Bernstein Renaissance" (1970s), 146
Schorske, Carl, 13 and Bernstein's evolutionary socialism,
Schramm, C. A., 46 4, 5, 147, 151, 175
286 Index
SPD (German Social Democratic Party) Youngsters faction, 60-61, 110
(com.) see also Erfurt Party Program;
and Berstein's "noble patriotism/* revisionism; Sozialdemokrat, Der
197-204 Spencer, Herbert, 210
and Bernstein's writings, 173, 174, 175 Spengler, Oswald, 248
and Bismarck's anti-socialist laws, Stalin, Joseph, 246
41-45, 53, 57, 60 Stampfer, Friedrich, 246, 247
blueprint for "reformist" party state, role of the, 128-134
program, 175 Staudinger, Franz, 116, 251
and Braun, 162 Steenson, Gary, 52, 54, 185
Breslau Party Congress, 72 Stinnes, Hugo, 231
Chemnitz Party Conference (1912), Stresemann, Gustav, 12, 159
181,217 surplus value, theory of, 120, 122,
colonialism and culture, 210-211 126-127, 128
and cooperation with the liberals, Sweezy, Paul, 125
194-197 Switzerland—
Dresden Party Conference (1903), Bernstein's exile in, 45-57
176-182 SPD conferences in, 43
and the First World War, 218-221
general elections— taxation, and the SPD, 170-171
(1903), 177-178 teleology, and science, 101-108
(1924), 244 Thalheimer, August, 233
and German nationalism, 190, Third World communism, 253
191-197 "Three-Star Article," 46
and German war guilt, 241-244 Tillich, Paul, 230
Gorlitz Party Program (1921), 13, trade unions—
226-229,231 and democracy, 141-142, 144-145
Gotha Program (1875), 38, 63, 65, 66 and the Gorlitz Program (1921), 228
Hanover Party Conference (1899), 155, and left-liberals, 158
156 and liberal socialism, 133
Heidelberg Program (1925), 229, 231 and the mass-strike debate, 182-189
Jena Party Conference (1905), 185 and theories of value, 127
and the "Kautsky-Bebel axis," 55 trancendental ideal, in evolutionary
Liibeck Party Conference (1901), socialism, 101-102, 103-104
168-169 "transition problem," in socialist theory,
Mannheim Party Conference (1906), 80-81, 228
185,216 Trotsky, Leon, 183, 239
and Marxism, 54-55, 59-60 Tudor, Henry, 43, 53, 79
and the mass-strike debate, 182-189
moderates, 44, 51-53, 54, 60, 62 universal suffrage, 130, 143, 144
and the "New Course" in Germany, use-value, 121, 126
59-65 USPD ("Independent" Social Democratic
origins, 38 Party), 222-223, 224, 225, 226,
policy of "intransigent opposition," 228, 229, 241, 244
53-54, 55 "Utopia," 28, 29
and political democracy, 141-142 Utopian socialists, 95, 105
radicals, 44-45, 49, 52
and the steamship subsidy bill, 51-53 Vahlteich, Julius, 30
taxation policy, 170-171 value, theories of, 120-128
theory-practice gap, 55, 171, 230-236 VDAV (Congress of German Workers'
and the USPD, 224, 244 Associations), 36-37
victory of the "party bureaucrats," Verein, 31-32
211-217 Versailles Treaty (1919), 242
in the Weimar Republic, 230-236 Vollmar, Georg von, 46, 59, 72, 73,
Weltanschauung, 33-34, 54 178-179
Index 287
and the Dresden Party Conference, Weimar Constitution, 231
179,180 Weimar Republic, 13, 14, 176, 196,
Volrlander, Karl, 7, 20, 116, 118, 157, 224-229
251 dynamics of social change, 230-236
Vorwdns (journal), 47, 58, 79, 84, 165, Weitling, Wilhelm, 34, 95
180, 240 West, Cornel, 5-6
Wilhelm I, King of Prussia (later German
wages— Emperor), 27, 28
system of wage determination, 128 Wilhelm II, Kaiser, 41, 59, 189, 190, 202
and theories of value, 122-123, 127 Wilson, Woodrow, 223
Walzer, Michael, 255 Windelband, Wilhelm, 116
Webb, Beatrice, 7, 56, 67, 68 Winkler, Heinrich August, 242
Webb, Sidney, 4, 7, 56, 67, 144 Wolf, Julius, 75
Weber, Max, 5, 9, 29, 31 "workers" question, 29-30
Archives for Social Science, 249
on Bernstein, 20-21 Young Liberal Clubs, 159
and colonial policies, 209
and Naumann, 158, 159 Zadek, Ignaz, 56
and neo-Kantianism, 107-108 Zadek, Lily, 222
The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Zadek-Schattner, Regine (Bernstein's
Capitalism, 20-21 wife), 56-56, 245
and SPD bureaucracy, 216 Zetkin, Klara, 193, 233
Wehler, Hans-Ulrich, 42, 72, 231 Zionism, 221-223