Simon Conway Morris-Life's Solution-Cambridge University Press (2003) PDF
Simon Conway Morris-Life's Solution-Cambridge University Press (2003) PDF
Simon Conway Morris-Life's Solution-Cambridge University Press (2003) PDF
‘Having spent four centuries taking the world to bits and trying to find
out what makes it tick, in the twenty-first century scientists are now
trying to fit the pieces together and understand why the whole is greater
than the sum of its parts. Simon Conway Morris provides the best
overview, from a biological viewpoint, of how complexity on the large
scale arises from simple laws on the small scale, and why creatures like
us may not be the accidents that many suppose. This is the most
important book about evolution since The Selfish Gene; essential
reading for everyone who has wondered about why we are here in a
universe that seems tailor-made for life.’
John Gribbin, author of Science: A History
‘Is intelligent life in the Universe common or incredibly rare? Are even
planets like the Earth rare? We won’t really know until our searches are
further advanced, but until then these debates pivot on the tension
between contingency and convergence. Advocates of the first point to
the unlikelihood of particular historical paths, while those favoring the
second emphasize multiple paths to similar functional outcomes. In
Life’s Solution Conway Morris argues that the evidence from life on
Earth supports a variety of paths leading toward intelligence. Our
searches for life elsewhere are informed by such insights into life here.’
Christopher Chyba, Stanford University and the SETI Institute
Life’s Solution
Inevitable Humans in a
Lonely Universe
Notes 333
Index 446
Preface. The Cambridge
sandwich
organisms that have ever been’7 could settle this issue,8 Life’s
Solution sets out to demonstrate that what we already know gives
some strong indicators of what must be: even in this book pigs
don’t fly.
The central theme of this book depends on the realities of
evolutionary convergence: the recurrent tendency of biological
organization to arrive at the same ‘solution’ to a particular ‘need’.
Perhaps the best-known example is the similarity between the
camera-like eye of the octopus and the human eye (or that of any
other vertebrate). As we shall see in this particular instance, where
the camera-like eye has evolved independently at least six times,
Maynard Smith’s premise that ‘only a limited number of ways in
which eyes can possibly work’ is amply confirmed. If this book
happens to serve no other purpose than act as a compilation of
evolutionary convergences, be it head-banging in mole rats and
termites or matriarchal social structure in sperm whales and
elephants, then that will be sufficient. But, of course, the net is in
pursuit of a much bigger prey. Its main, but not ultimate, aim is to
argue that, contrary to received wisdom, the emergence of human
intelligence is a near-inevitability. My purpose is not to demonstrate
the inevitability of a five-fingered organism, although in this context
it is amusing to note that the famous panda’s ‘thumb’ is, in one
sense, convergent.9 Nor is it my aim to find repeated examples of
species with 32 teeth, even though we might note that there are a
number of fascinating examples of dental convergence. And it is this
that matters, not five of this or 32 of that, but the recurrent
emergence of various biological properties.
This book has its anecdotes, from baboons operating railway
signals to a harbour seal that spoke like an inebriated Bostonian, but
there is a serious argument that takes us from the apparently arcane,
such as the natural (and convergent) gyroscopes of insects, through
to the convergences of the sensory modalities (vision, of course, but
also olfaction, hearing and echolocation, electroreception, and so on)
to agriculture, brain size, and culture. And there are four
conclusions. First, what we regard as complex is usually inherent in
simpler systems: the real and in part unanswered question in
evolution is not novelty per se, but how it is that things are put
together. Second, the number of evolutionary end-points is limited:
by no means everything is possible. Third, what is possible has
preface. the cambridge sandwich xiii
this leads to the last two chapters (10 and 11), and a brief coda
(Chapter 12). Too often evolutionary convergence is regarded as
simply anecdotal, good for a bedtime story. Its importance is surely
underestimated, and for two reasons. The first is scientific. Ideas on
evolution about such features as adaptation and trends have been
under fierce attack, especially by those who believe that if
contingent happenstance dogs every step of evolution then assuredly
the emergence of humans is a cosmic accident, leaving us free to
make the world as we will, with such happy results as are plain to
see. Yet convergence tells us two things: that evolutionary trends are
real, and that adaptation is not some occasional cog in the organic
machine, but is central to the explanation of how we came to be
here. In principle, such ideas are in themselves so unremarkable as
to require no comment, were it not for the ferocious attacks by such
writers as S. J. Gould. What, one wonders, did he get so excited
about, and how, one may ask, has our understanding of evolution
really changed despite more than forty years of polemic?
Yet, convergence also opens another door. If the emergence of
our sentience was effectively inevitable, then perhaps we should
take rather more seriously the sentiences of other species? So too
perhaps we should stand back and consider what a very odd set-up it
is we inhabit, from the eerily efficient genetic code, to the deeply
peculiar molecule DNA, to a set of biological organizations that
repeatedly throw up complex structures, not least the brain. The late
Fred Hoyle, no friend of most biologists, carried some strange ideas
about the origins of biological complexity to his grave, yet his
remark that the Universe was a set-up job rings strangely true.
Having said that, if you happen to be a ‘creation scientist’ (or
something of that kind) and have read this far, may I politely suggest
that you put this book back on the shelf. It will do you no good.
Evolution is true, it happens, it is the way the world is, and we too
are one of its products. This does not mean that evolution does not
have metaphysical implications; I remain convinced that this is the
case. To deny, however, the reality of evolution and more seriously
to distort deliberately the scientific evidence in support of
fundamentalist tenets is inadmissible. Contrary to popular belief,
the science of evolution does not belittle us. As I argue, something
like ourselves is an evolutionary inevitability, and our existence also
xvi preface. the cambridge sandwich
The publisher has used its best endeavours to ensure that the URLs
for external websites referred to in this book are correct and active at
the time of going to press. However, the publisher has no
responsibility for the websites and can make no guarantee that a site
will remain live or that the content is or will remain appropriate.
Abbreviations
general
ATP adenosine 5 -triphosphate, the triphosphate of the
nucleotide adenosine, which plays a key role in the
energetics of the cell. See also p. 25.
BP before the present; by convention taken as before 1950.
CHZ the Circumstellar Habitable Zone, the zone surrounding a
star in which the evolution of life is both possible, and can
be maintained for protracted intervals of time. See also pp.
83, 99–100.
DNA deoxyribonucleic acid, the nucleic acid that forms the basis
of genetic inheritance in nearly all organisms. See also
pp. 4, 23–24.
EOD electric organ discharge; the discharge of electricity from
specialized tissues in fish. See p. 184.
IDO the enzyme indoleamine 2,3-dioxygenase.
JAR jamming avoidance response, exhibited by fish that use
electrogeneration. See p. 186.
K/T the boundary between the end of the Cretaceous (K) period
and the beginning of the Tertiary (T) era at about 65 Ma
ago. The K/T event that occurred at this time resulted in a
mass extinction. See pp. 94–95.
LPTM the late Paleocene thermal maximum, a warm interval that
occurred during the Paleocene period at c. 55 Ma.
OZMA (Project) the first radio-telescope project to search for
extraterrestrial signals, so named by Frank Drake in
reference to organisms as strange as the Wizard of Oz. See
p. 231.
PAHs polycyclic aromatic hydrocarbons; organic compounds with
a carbon “network” that are abundant in the Universe. See
p. 43.
xx list of abbreviations
Mass
g gram (0.03527 ounce)
kg kilogram, 1000 grams (2.2046 pounds)
Time
s second
Ga billion years (109 years)
Ma million years (109 years)
Frequency
Hz herz, frequency per second
kHz kiloherz, 1000 Hz
MHz megaherz, 106 herz.
list of abbreviations xxi
Temperature
◦
C degree Celsius (0 ◦ C is the freezing point of water, 100 ◦ C is
the boiling point of water).
K temperature on the Kelvin (thermodynamic) absolute scale
(with 0 K as absolute zero); 1 degree K = 1 degree C; 0 ◦ C is
about 273 K and 100 ◦ C is about 373 K.
Pressure
Pa Pascal, SI unit of pressure, equivalent to the pressure
produced by a force of one newton applied (uniformly) over
an area of one square metre; 105 Pa (100 kPa) is equivalent to
1 bar, or roughly 1 atmosphere.
1 Looking for Easter Island
living forms this ranges across many scales of complexity, from bac-
teria that build colonies like miniature trees1 to immense societies
of ants whose populations run into the millions and, independent of
us, have stumbled across the advantages of agriculture (Chapter 8).
And it is a history that is by no means confined to the complex-
ity of colonies or the limpidity of a geometric shell. It is as much
in the range, scope, and acuity of living organisms. They may be
mere machines, but consider those owls whose hearing can pinpoint
within a two-degree arc the rustling made by a mouse,2 the naviga-
tional abilities of albatrosses across the seemingly trackless South-
ern Ocean3 (Fig. 1.1), or even Nellie the cat that smelled Madagascar
across more than two hundred miles of ocean.4 But despite our admi-
ration, wonder, and – if we are candid – even awe, surely we can still
offer the following paraphrase: evolution happens, this bone evolved
from that one, this molecule from that one. To be sure, not every
transformation and transition will be elucidated, but we are confi-
dent this is because of a lack of information rather than a failure of the
method.
Yet despite the reality that, as it happens, we humans evolved
from apes rather than, say, lizards, let alone tulips, the interpretations
surrounding the brute fact of evolution remain contentious, contro-
versial, fractious, and acrimonious. Why should this be so? The heart
of the problem, I believe, is to explain how it might be that we, a prod-
uct of evolution, possess an overwhelming sense of purpose and moral
identity yet arose by processes that were seemingly without meaning.
If, however, we can begin to demonstrate that organic evolution con-
tains deeper structures and potentialities, if not inevitabilities, then
perhaps we can begin to move away from the dreary materialism of
much current thinking with its agenda of a world now open to lim-
itless manipulation. Nor need this counter-attack be anti-scientific:
far from it. First, evolution may simply be a fact, yet it is in need
of continuous interpretation. The study of evolution surely retains its
fascination, not because it offers a universal explanation, even though
this may appeal to fundamentalists (of all persuasions), but because
evolution is both riven with ambiguities and, paradoxically, is also
rich in implications. In my opinion the sure sign of the right road is
a limitless prospect of deeper knowledge: what was once baffling is
now clear, what seemed absurdly important is now simply childish,
yet still the journey is unfinished.
looking for easter island 3
designing a car, nor for that matter mixing the driest of Martinis, let
alone being haunted by existentialist doubts.
This problem of inherency, however, is far more prevalent and
pervasive than the local quirk that chimps and humans are genom-
ically almost identical, but otherwise separated by an immense gulf
of differences. Let us look, for example, at a much deeper stage in our
evolution, effectively at the time of the ancestors of the fish. Enter
the moderately undistinguished animal known as the lancelet worm
or amphioxus (Branchiostoma and its relatives, Fig. 1.2). By general
agreement this beast is the nearest living approximation to the stage
in evolution that preceded the fish, which in turn clambered on to
land, moved to using the egg, grew fur, and in one lineage developed
into socially alert arborealists. All these changes and shifts must have
been accompanied by genetic changes, but if we look back to am-
phioxus we see a genetic architecture in place that seemingly has no
obvious counterpart in its anatomy. To give just one example: the cen-
tral nervous system of amphioxus is really rather simple. It consists
of an elongate nerve cord stretching back along the body, above the
precursor of the vertebral column (our backbone, consisting of a row
of vertebrae) and a so-called brain. The brain can only be described
as a disappointment. It is little more than an anterior swelling (it is
called the cerebral vesicle) and has no obvious sign in terms of its
morphology of even the beginnings of the characteristic threefold di-
vision seen in the vertebrate brain of hind-, mid- and fore-sections. Yet
the molecular evidence,6 which is also backed up by some exquisitely
fine studies of microanatomy,7 suggests that, cryptically, the brain of
amphioxus has regions equivalent to the tripartite division seen in
the vertebrates.
The clear implication of this is that folded within the seem-
ingly simple brain of amphioxus is what can almost be described as
a template for the equivalent organ of the vertebrates: in some sense
amphioxus carries the inherent potential for intelligence. Quite how
the more complex brain emerges is yet to be established. The evi-
dence that a key development in the molecular architecture of the
vertebrates was episodes of gene duplication,8 that is, doubling up of
a gene, could well give one clue. This is because the ‘surplus’ gene
is then potentially available for some new function. It could alterna-
tively be claimed that amphioxus is secondarily simplified (the con-
dition sometimes referred to as regressive), but it retained genes for
inherency: where is the ground plan in evolution? 7
figure 1.2 The amphioxus animal. Upper, entire animal. The anterior
end is to the right, with the ‘brain’ located towards upper side.
Prominent white units are gonads. Lower, detail of anterior with
prominent feeding (buccal) tentacles and more posteriorly gill bars. The
notochord is the longitudinal structure slightly above the mid-line, with
closely spaced vertical lines. The nerve cord lies above the notochord,
with minimal enlargement at the anterior. (Courtesy of Dale Stokes,
Scripps Institution of Oceanography (upper) and Thurston Lacalli,
University of Victoria, British Columbia (lower).)
I agree. Not all is possible, options are limited, and different starting
points converge repeatedly on the same destinations. Any such evo-
lutionary journey, including navigation through protein ‘hyperspace’
must presuppose intermediary stages. And here there may be further
constraints because seemingly ‘sensible’ paths may turn out to be
non-functional.17 The ‘landscape’ of biological form, be it at the level
of proteins, organisms, or social systems, may in principle be almost
infinitely rich, but in reality the number of ‘roads’ through it may be
much, much more restricted.
This is not to say that there are no alternatives: patently there
are, and the world is a diverse place. Smith and Morowitz remind us
that despite these potential immensities the actual ‘Game of Life’,
as they call it, is still going to be played the same way everywhere.
Here are the four basic rules, which incidentally presuppose variation
(which is offered by the different alleles (determining characters) of a
gene) and subsequent process of selection.
it matters little what our starting point may have been: the different
routes will not prevent a convergence to similar ends.21
eerie perfection
The understanding of the genetic code was, after the elucidation of the
structure of DNA with its four bases and famous double helix, the next
triumph in the field of molecular biology. As already noted, proteins
are built from the twenty available amino acids,22 although it has long
been known that particular examples, such as the protein collagen
that goes to form such structures as tendons (Achilles’ heel) or the
silk proteins that form the spider’s web, are enriched in particular
amino acids which reflect, in ways that even now are not completely
understood, the functional and structural properties of these and other
proteins. Thus collagens are enriched in such amino acids as proline,
while spider-silks possess notable quantities of alanine and glycine.
Each of the amino acids is coded for by a set of three nucleotide
base pairs, accordingly known as a triplet. The original code is, of
course, stored in the DNA of the chromosomes, but the actual synthe-
sis of the amino acids occurs through the agency of the RNA in minute
structures within the cell known as the ribosomes. Thus, in RNA the
four bases are adenine (A), cytosine (C), guanine (G), and uracil (U),
the last of which substitutes for thymine (T), which is found in DNA
only. With a triplet code and four base pairs there are of course 64 pos-
sible combinations. This implies that with only 20 amino acids there
is a considerable degree of redundancy, even with the assignment of
certain codons to signal ‘Start’ and ‘Stop’. In fact we see that only two
amino acids (methionine (abbreviated M) and tryptophan (W)) rely on a
single codon each (respectively coded for by AUG and UGG), whereas
the remaining 18 amino acids are able to call upon from two to six
codons. (For example, histidine (H) uses either CAC or CAU; arginine
(R) employs CGU, CGC, CGA, CGG, AGA, and AGG.) It has long
been known that this redundancy means that mistakes in coding may
not be detrimental; if a substitution within the codon fails to result in
the identical amino acid, it stands a good chance of producing another
amino acid with similar properties. Amino acids with similar proper-
ties, of which their affinity to or repulsion from water (the property of
polarity) is particularly important, also tend to have similar pathways
of biosynthesis. Here, too, if errors occur then the mistake need not
be lethal. For these and other reasons, therefore, it is clear that the
14 looking for easter island
fascinating bird with highly adaptable feeding habits. The kea also
has a penchant for trashing cars, and its behavioural characteristics in-
clude delinquent gangs of young birds.27 In passing I should also men-
tion that notwithstanding the overwhelming evidence for adaptation
and functional demands faced by organisms there remain some ex-
amples of structures whose significance still baffles biologists. John
Currey gives a nice example in the form of the rostral bone in the
snout of Blainville’s beaked whale (Mesoplodon densirostris).28 As the
species name suggests, this bone is incredibly dense, but why? One
can speculate that it might be employed in fighting, but this rostral
bone is very brittle, a consequence of its very low organic content.
Alternatively, it might act as ballast,29 but Currey is candid when he
writes, ‘At the moment, its function, in this rarely found whale, is a
mystery’.30
By this stage you will be wondering what possible connection
could exist between the safety factors of a kangaroo, let alone the
rostral bone of a rare whale, and the efficiency of the genetic code.
The point, simply, is that given the realities of the physical world and
adaptation, organisms and their components should be designed to do
the job adequately, but no more. Humans shudder at the prospect of
hurtling to their doom down a lift shaft, and so incorporate a safety
margin that seems to be found very seldom in organisms. And at first
sight this is what we should see in the genetic code: it certainly isn’t
random; in fact it is really rather good. But in recent years a group
of molecular biologists, notably Steve Freeland and Laurence Hurst,
have been trying to arrive at a more precise answer.31
Their approach is computer-based, and the basic aim is to ran-
domize the genetic code and then compare the efficiency of a certain
fraction of the vast number of alternative codes the computer can
generate with the real one, here on Earth. There is, of course, the im-
plicit assumption that a genetic alphabet composed of two base pairs
(that is AT/CG),32 as well as the system of triplet codons and the
20 amino acids33 available for protein construction found in all ter-
restrial life represents some sort of norm. Alternatives to codon usage
and the number and type of amino acids can, of course, be envisaged,
but Arthur Weber and Stanley Miller have gone so far as to suggest
that ‘If life were to arise on another planet, we would expect that . . .
about 75% of the amino acids would be the same as on the earth.’34
Naturally we need to be cautious in assuming that even if proteins
16 looking for easter island
2500
2000
Number of codes
10 000
5000
0
2.00 5.00 8.00 11.00 13.40
Relative efficiency of code
the arguments for design and intelligent planning have such a peren-
nial appeal. Whether it be by navigation across the hyperdimensional
vastness of protein space, the journey to a genetic code of almost eerie
efficiency, or the more familiar examples of superb adaptation, life has
an extraordinary propensity for its metaphorical hand to fit the glove.
Life depends both on a suitable chemistry, whose origins are literally
cosmic, and on the realities of evolutionary adaptation. The chemistry
is acknowledged but largely ignored; the adaptation is often derided as
a wishful fantasy. As with the audacious and intelligent Polynesians,
so life shows a kind of homing instinct. Its central paradox revolves
around the fact that despite its fecundity and baroque richness life
is also strongly constrained. The net result is a genuine creation, al-
most unimaginably rich and beautiful, but one also with an underlying
structure in which, given enough time, the inevitable must happen.
finding easter island 21
on the one hand [there is] the endless complexity of the process,
on the other the simplicity of the principle. To make everything
that can be called alive, to monitor the development of every fern
and feather on earth, to direct their growth, to enable them to
function, to replace worn-out parts, to turn things on, to turn them
off – for all those activities to be orchestrated by just four kinds of
24 can we break the great code?
These comments are important in the context of what is, and is not,
likely in alien ‘biospheres’. It is important to stress that Fry does
not regard non-carbaquist life forms as impossible, but in some con-
texts, e.g. stellar interiors, their detection is problematic, and even
planetary-based systems that might involve liquid ammonia or silicon
‘backbones’ (note 10) run into difficulties. Thus, liquid ammonia
requires very low temperatures (less than −33 ◦ C) and its ice sinks,
unlike water ice, which is a remarkable solid in that it floats on its
own liquid. Fry concludes, together with most workers, that life else-
where, if there is any, is most probably carbon-based.
Somewhat similar arguments may also apply to a number
of elements vital for the operation of life, perhaps most notably
phosphorus.14 In the chemical form of phosphate it plays key, and
probably irreplaceable, roles. Of central importance is its employment
in the construction of the nucleic acids, the building blocks of DNA
and RNA. Phosphorus is also integral to the molecule ATP (adenosine
triphosphate), which is central to the storage and transfer of energy
within the cell. As with the case of the merits of silicon versus carbon,
it needs to be emphasized that it is not that alternatives simply can-
not be envisaged. Indeed, if humans had been detailed to get the whole
26 can we break the great code?
process going, the eager occupants of the First Laboratory might well
have passed by phosphates to consider such biochemical alternatives
as arsenic and silicic acid (note 14). As is repeatedly the case in looking
at the basis of life, however, these alternatives are substantially less
fit for the purpose. As we shall also see when discussing some current
problems in understanding the origin of life (Chapter 4), it is proba-
bly just as well that humans or their equivalents were not recruited
to the First Laboratory: my guess is that they would still be hard
at work.
There is another twist to the way life uses the elements of the
periodic table. Consider, for example, the rather unfamiliar element
known as molybdenum. Some years ago Francis Crick and Leslie Orgel
came up with a particularly intriguing idea that nicely reflected their
ingenuity and lateral thinking.15 In essence their argument was as
follows: molybdenum is an essential element for life. It plays, for
example, a key role in various enzymes. On Earth, however, the avail-
ability of this element seems to be drastically limited, occurring as
it does in only minute concentrations. Crick and Orgel’s imaginative
leap was to argue that this dependence on molybdenum was not an
unfortunate, if brute, fact, but actually it indicated that our ances-
try was far from Earth, derived from life forms where the precious
molybdenum was more freely available. The idea that we might rep-
resent marooned colonists – perhaps from a long-dead planet engulfed
in some stellar catastrophe – has a romantic appeal that taps a recur-
rent root in humans of displacement and longing. Not, of course, that
these hypothetical colonists would be anything more than bacteria
or some such equivalent. In any event, the history of life provides no
evidence (although perhaps it should) of any subsequent visitation, let
alone intervention, by extraterrestrials. Of course, getting even bacte-
ria across the interstellar wastes, those cubic parsecs of hard vacuum
drenched in radiation, is in itself so problematic that it may be rea-
sonable to suppose that if panspermia (that is, transport from one star
system to another16 ) occurs at all it can only be by a directed, that is,
an intelligent, activity. And this is what Crick and Orgel suggested:
from a simple observation, too little molybdenum, to a bold hypoth-
esis of a directed panspermia. The latter notion may still be credible,
but, alas, the original estimates of the amounts of molybdenum were
too pessimistic. It looks as though even on Earth there is actually
enough.17
dna: the strangest of all molecules? 27
Introducing peculiar base pairs is, of course, not the only way
of meddling with DNA (and RNA) to see what alternatives might ex-
ist, either in the laboratory or extraterrestrially. The question can, in
any event, be tackled from several directions. Here, too, the results
are neither comprehensive nor complete, but for the most part they
seem to suggest that finding viable alternatives to DNA in any sort
of natural context may be difficult, and perhaps even impossible. For
example, if a series of base pairs are linked to make a short strand, in
a process known as oligomerization, then if this is carried out in the
test tube, the results are interestingly different from those obtained
within the living cell. Although the molecules that are employed to
build DNA are relatively simple, the association of the various com-
ponents is precisely determined. For example, the phosphate unit and
the sugar (known as a ribose), both of which are essential compo-
nents of DNA, are each attached to the other principal unit, i.e. the
nucleotide (e.g. adenine) at two specific locations of sites. In ‘real’
DNA, which is made in organisms, the linkage is at sites 3 and 5
(the superscripts refer simply to positions on the molecule). In con-
trast, in the artificial situation in the laboratory, the linkage positions
are now at 2 and 5 .36 Perhaps the former arrangement (3 ,5 ) evolved
from the latter (2 ,5 ), abiotic leading to biotic. If it did, this may not
be surprising, because DNA showing the 2 ,5 linkage seems to be per-
ceptibly weaker and, at least under laboratory conditions viable only
when the salt content of the surrounding solution is elevated.37 In
the case of RNA matters are somewhat different. This is because here
an ‘abiotic’ 2 ,5 linkage does not seem to be prejudicial to its opera-
tion until, that is, DNA is involved in the system. Then everything
collapses.38
What else can we tinker with? Another key element is the sugar,
ribose in RNA and deoxyribose in DNA. As we shall see subsequently
(Chapter 4), one of the particular hurdles in understanding how life
itself might have originated is to find a believable pathway by which
ribose might be synthesized, at least in sufficient quantities to be of
any use. At this juncture all we need to ask, in the context of alter-
native worlds, is whether ribose (or deoxyribose) is the only molecule
in town? In fact, this topic has been explored in considerable detail
by Albert Eschenmoser and his team, in what is appropriately termed
an aetiology of nucleic acids,39 and what has been very appropriately
described as ‘a chemical tour de force.’40
dna: the strangest of all molecules? 31
For centuries, if not millennia, we have looked towards the night sky
and with the glory of the Milky Way, now enhanced beyond earlier
imagination by the extraordinary pictures captured by such great tele-
scopes as the Hubble and Keck, felt a deep resonance, a wider and
wilder reality, a glimpse of a cosmic architecture. Naturally enough
such an awestruck view has also enfolded the prospect of other habit-
able worlds. Yet it is only quite recently that a deeper, more pervasive
view has emerged that looks beyond the question of extraterrestrials
to invoke organic activity on a truly universal scale, life as a cosmic
imperative. In the previous chapter I mentioned Christian de Duve,1
and perhaps he best of all encapsulates this wider and more optimistic
view that the Universe is not a howling wilderness, but part of our
home. Thus he writes, the ‘Universe is a hotbed of organic synthe-
ses leading among others, to amino acids and other typical building
blocks of life. This ‘vital dust’ permeates the entire Universe and
most likely represents the chemical seeds from which life arose.’2
Nor is de Duve the only exponent of life as a cosmic principle. Cyril
Ponnamperuma, for example, has stated that ‘You look at the inter-
stellar molecules and you see cyanide and formaldehyde. These two
can provide the pathway for everything else. There is a simplicity
in the whole scheme – so much so that you practically feel that
the whole universe is trying to make life.’3 Such a cosmic dimen-
sion has a strong resonance with our sense of belonging somehow to
a wider order, but it still could be a serious misreading of the evi-
dence. Here I shall take a contrary view and shall argue on the basis
of several different approaches that ‘Life may be a universal princi-
ple, but we can still be alone.’4 In this regard, major stumbling blocks
might be the apparent difficulty in understanding how life actually
originated (Chapter 4) and the possible dearth of habitable planets
(Chapter 5), but first in pursuit of de Duve’s vision let us look into
outer space.
a martini the size of the pacific 33
has been claimed to yield evidence consistent with Martian life, and
one of the lines of evidence is the recovery of undoubted PAHs.9 The
other lines of evidence include (a) tiny crystals of magnetite,10 said to
be similar to those made by certain terrestrial bacteria that act as tiny
intracellular magnets; (b) putative fossils; and (c) the geochemistry,11
especially of the carbonate,12 and the related question of the tempera-
ture at which it was formed. Unfortunately the enthusiasm of the orig-
inal team investigating this meteorite has not been matched by most
other scientists. Whatever the significance of these Martian PAHs,
which are also well known in carbonaceous meteorites,13 the general
consensus is that, as for the other lines of evidence, non-biological
processes are much more likely to be responsible. So, too, on a much
grander scale, the interstellar equivalents may tell us little of a Uni-
verse pregnant with life, but may rather point to the existence of a
universal ‘goo’. These PAHs are incredibly stable, going nowhere, an
end-product with no future. Is this too pessimistic a view? Not accord-
ing to received opinion, which not only embraces life as a cosmic prin-
ciple but also seizes upon the only strictly tangible evidence we have
for extraterrestrial organic matter, which is in the form of meteorites.
reason to doubt that multiple deaths and injuries have been caused
by meteorites, although in many instances the casualties probably
resulted from the collapse of the building rather than from a direct hit.
Moreover, a more recent survey17 provides a list of buildings hit (one
through the observatory of an amateur astronomer), near misses, and
several deaths. There is little doubt that further mining of historical
records (see also note 15) will reveal more examples of meteoritic
casualties. So, too, one may expect, will archaeological evidence. Of
course, it is tempting to ascribe the collapse of great civilizations to
such cosmic interruptions, but to date there is little, if any, evidence
to support such ideas. There is, however, evidence for a major impact
(the Kaali event) on the Baltic island of Saaremaa (Estonia) during the
local Bronze age18 (c. 400–800 bc; a possible report by the famous
traveller Pytheas, who originated from the Greek colony of Marseille,
might narrow this event to c. 350 bc). The energy released was about
equivalent to the atomic bomb that destroyed Hiroshima, and as is
evident both from the crater and the pollen record the impact must
have led to widespread devastation.
Yet, from the prospect of the origins of life, certain meteorites,
and especially a rather peculiar class known as the carbonaceous chon-
drites, are now being taken as a key creative agency. As such, these
meteorites provide a terrestrial glimpse of the vital principle that, it is
suggested, permeates the entire Universe. Carbonaceous meteorites
are quite rare, but the most famous examples (such as the Allende,
Murchison, and Orgueil) have proved treasure troves of information
on extraterrestrial organic chemistry. There is, however, a potentially
major problem because not only do they quickly disintegrate, but there
is the ever-present danger of contamination from terrestrial sources.
Not surprisingly, new discoveries, for example, the Tagish Lake fall,19
excite considerable attention. The Tagish Lake find was especially
propitious because the meteorite came down at a low angle and its
fall was observed; and its rapid recovery from an ice-covered lake in
northern British Columbia ensured a remarkably pristine sample. It
has yielded many surprises. The fact that its chemistry is very dif-
ferent from that of other carbonaceous meteorites implies that our
overall understanding is far from complete.20 Most striking perhaps
is the low concentrations of amino acids, some of which are clearly
terrestrial contaminants.21 Even so, many of the organic molecules
discovered in this and other meteorites are indigenous and represent
36 universal goo: life as a cosmic principle?
the material necessary for life to emerge – in other words those build-
ing blocks that are basic to life on Earth and presumably anywhere
else. So, in contrast to the blocks of iron and stone wreaking destruc-
tion, here we have a potentially rich brew of chemicals that, at the
dawn of Earth history, might have helped to initiate the whole process
of organic evolution.
As we shall see, the importance of the carbonaceous meteorites,
as well as comets, in enabling the Earth to become habitable should
not be underestimated. A closer look, however, suggests that to regard
these meteorites as some sort of primitive crucible out of which life
could take its first steps may not merely be simplistic: it could be seri-
ously misleading. Consider, for example, the amino acids22 recovered
from various carbonaceous meteorites, such as the famous Murchison
fall that landed near the town of the same name, in Australia in 1969.
Certainly these compounds occur in some abundance, but it is very
significant that only the simplest types of amino acids are found and
that they represent two groups (the monoamino monocarboxylic and
monoamino dicarboxyl classes). There is, moreover, another equally
important observation that, of the various molecular configurations
that can exist in these two groups, effectively all are found in the
meteorites.23 The message is simple. These amino acids are by def-
inition organic, but the processes of formation are patently abiotic
and unrelated to the ways in which amino acids are made in a biol-
ogical cell. Exactly the same remarks apply to the more recent
discovery in carbonaceous meteorites of compounds related to the
sugars.24
The restriction to the simpler types of molecule and the explo-
ration of all possible variants is non-selective and in marked contrast
to the activities of life. These extraterrestrial amino acids are the prod-
uct of an unconstrained chemistry, with no hint of life’s strange speci-
ficities and subtle avenues of synthesis. Within the restricted range
of the simple amino acids, all available types have been produced in
these carbonaceous meteorites by the random combination of yet sim-
pler precursors, but then the chemical process comes to a full stop.
In such an environment it is scarcely surprising that we see an expo-
nential decline in the abundance of amino acids with a larger number
of carbon atoms in their framework. Again the message is abiologi-
cal: even slightly more complex molecules are much more difficult to
assemble.
goo from the sky 37
that were clearly terrestrial contaminants. But are there other ways in
which more complex structures might emerge: perhaps some of these
extraterrestrial organic compounds exhibit self-organizing properties
that could give us at least a glimpse as to how life emerged from a
distinctly discouraging mess? Nearly all are agreed that at some point
a key step in making life had to be the invention of some sort of en-
velope, a proto-cell, in which the nascent biochemical machinery of
replication and molecular synthesis could be shielded from the chem-
ical chaos of the surrounding milieu. And there are some intriguing
hints as to how this might have happened. Among the hydrocarbons
found in the carbonaceous meteorites are some compounds quite like
the lipids. These are the fatty compounds that typically make up part
of the wall of a living cell. Experimental manipulation of such ex-
traterrestrial compounds typically leads to the formation of simple
droplets, as you might see if you splash olive oil into water. Under cer-
tain conditions, however, genuine vesicles, apparently with a double-
walled membrane (as in living cells), can be formed.29 These artificial
vesicles are very small, typically in the micron range and so compa-
rable in size to bacteria. The main snag, however, is that although
hydrocarbons of a suitable size (that is with chains ranging in length
from 12 to 20+ carbon atoms) occur in the carbonaceous meteorites,
as yet no plausible prebiotic milieu has been devised in the labora-
tory to synthesize hydrocarbons of a comparable length. The obvious
implication is that life might not have emerged unless these extrater-
restrial hydrocarbons had been delivered to the surface of the early
Earth.
a life-saving rain?
It seems that however and wherever extraterrestrial organic material
was, and still is being, formed it may be of limited relevance to un-
derstanding how the building blocks of life came to be assembled and
coordinated on the early Earth. Even so, there are still strong argu-
ments that without chunks of extraterrestrial material, rich not only
in organic compounds but also in water (as ice) and other volatiles,
in the form of both carbonaceous meteorites and comets, then life
on Earth might never have arisen. This in turn would have precluded
some billions of years of evolution during which at least one sentient
species could evolve to a position where it could begin to think about
the whole business.
So why should carbonaceous meteorites and comets play such
a key role? By general agreement the Solar System originated from a
huge cloud of interstellar dust that, perhaps nudged by the blast from
a nearby supernova, subsequently condensed into a rapidly spinning
disc. Out of this emerged the central star and a series of planets. In
our system only one body, our Sun, achieved sufficient mass to initi-
ate the thermonuclear reactions that provide the sunlight. The rapid
processes of accretion, and especially the gravitational maw of the
newly forming Sun, means that even as the planets continued to col-
lide and grow, the central star itself achieved a large enough size to
begin to shine. The prospect for those planets nearer to the Sun was
not good, at least for the future of life. This is because the effect of the
Sun’s radiation was to drive volatile compounds (necessary to form
an atmosphere and ocean) out to the cooler regions of the spinning
disc, to or beyond the so-called ‘snowline’ which approximates to the
present-day position of Jupiter. Stripped of their volatiles, planets like
the Earth would be reduced to balls of bone-dry rock, with the ele-
ments that are essential to life either driven far beyond the orbit of
Mars or locked up in crystal lattices within the interior of the planet.
There would certainly be no oceans, and presumably no chance for
life to emerge.
So what are we doing here? One possibility is that such a planet
as Earth did not accrete in its present position, but formed in an orbit
much further out where the volatiles were ready to provide it with the
mantle of atmosphere and ocean. Subsequently, under the influence
of the chaotic system of planetary movements, the Earth was flung
inwards, to occupy an orbit much closer to the Sun and – by strange,
a life-saving rain? 43
Robert Shapiro (see note 16). Another individual for whom I have a
particular admiration in this context is Leslie Orgel, not only because
he is a key individual in the study of the origin of life, but as impor-
tantly because, in contrast with the sunny optimism displayed in so
much of the literature, his papers reveal a traveller who knows he
might be on the high road to success, but will not be totally surprised
if the path leads to a fetid bog. This stance is neatly encapsulated in
one his review articles,6 where he writes:
Yet, the study of life’s origins is set in a paradox because the un-
derlying principles could not be more straightforward. This is because
the first chemical steps that led to the processes of self-replication (ul-
timately held in the thrall of DNA) and controlled cycles of chemistry
(what we call metabolism) must have been simple. Knowing these
foundations it surely cannot be that difficult to add storey to storey,
ultimately to remove the scaffolding, and so reveal the functioning
cell, a near-miracle of encapsulated design but arising by unremark-
able processes?
To be sure we must acknowledge preconditions, including the
fact that if the precursors of life had not rained from the heavens on
to the surface of the early Earth, supplying it again and again with
volatiles, then quite possibly there would have been no oceans or at-
mosphere. Without this cosmic drizzle it is quite possible that life
would never have had either the building blocks or the milieu neces-
sary for its origination. On the other hand, such an influx of water and
organic compounds is hardly relevant to the actual question, how did
life begin? This is because the simplest of the molecules required for
the beginning of organic chemistry, compounds such as formaldehyde
and hydrogen cyanide, are themselves readily synthesized in at least
some circumstances that might have occurred on the early Earth.8
In other words, it doesn’t really matter where such compounds
form: what does matter is what happens next. So, too, with the next
46 the origin of life: straining the soup or our credulity?
stage, that is, the assembly of such basic building blocks of life as
the amino acids, sugars, and hydrocarbons, as well as the nucleotides
that are fundamental to DNA. Such syntheses are widely regarded
as inevitable, and images of warm ponds, seething volcanic springs,
and massive thunderstorms rumbling across a deserted yet pregnant
landscape are used to feed the imagination. At this stage, life has
yet to exercise its peculiarly specific grip, its spinning of the ge-
netic code, its weaving of biochemical complexities; but no matter:
despite the vast pot-pourri of resultant chemicals, the nascent pro-
cesses of Darwinian selection are already winnowing and reaping,
the inappropriate is steadily devoured in chemical competition with
the winners. Metaphorically the molecules slug it out by tooth and
claw. Cycles develop, life emerges, and four billion years later one
species invokes the marvels of autocatalysis and emergent proper-
ties to cap the argument. These ideas are the bread and butter, so
to speak, of a substantial part of the origin-of-life industry. They
are well encapsulated in the proposals of Manfred Eigen.9 An im-
portant part of his argument is the emergence of primitive cycles
that combine, as so-called hypercycles, to permit replication. A cri-
tique of Eigen’s ideas is offered by John Maynard-Smith,10 who sug-
gests that the mechanism of hypercycles becomes plausible only if
it is housed within a cell, and the origin of the cell . . . ? Even so,
the drums and trumpets that regularly sound in support of self-
organization and autocatalysis as appropriate mechanisms that could
lead to stable and self-replicating systems form a regular musical ac-
companiment to those who believe that these precepts are a highly
desirable, if not necessary, goal,11 even though there are painfully few
experiments.12
And yet, something is clearly missing: life cannot be created in
the laboratory, nor is there any clear prospect of it happening. When
we return to the simpler stages of organic synthesis, the apparently
crisp outlines begin to blur. Even the arrangement of the experimental
apparatus, the literal disposition of the test tubes, can spell the differ-
ence between success – of a sort – and yet another failure. And yes,
certain compounds can be generated, but as often as not in minute
quantities, mixed up with all sorts of other goo and under conditions
which, to be frank, bear precious little resemblance to anything con-
ceivably like the early Earth.
finding its path 47
quest for what they refer to as the ‘one-pot reaction’, in which chemi-
cals go in at one end and a replicating system emerges from the other.
A survey of this area, which occupies the remainder of this chapter,
reveals a picture that can only be described as distinctly discouraging.
Indeed, there is a quite general pattern of problems.
Formose reaction
14 16 18 20 22 24 26 min
might expect on the early Earth, and indeed ribose is produced. But
there is a snag: the yields are very low and the formose reactions
produce a disturbingly large array of other compounds (Fig. 4.1). To
compound the difficulties the ribose is rather unstable24 and degra-
dation is particularly rapid if the solution becomes more alkaline.
It is, of course, possible to tinker with the reaction to engender a
greater degree of selectivity, but unfortunately this does not in itself
boost ribose production. So we seem to have been led into an impasse.
Nothing daunted, chemists have devised reaction pathways that can
produce reasonable quantities of ribose,25 but the sheer complexity of
the process and the careful manipulation of the many steps during the
reaction make one wonder about its applicability to the origin of life.
52 the origin of life: straining the soup or our credulity?
on the flat
Mineral surfaces have played a key role in many speculations concern-
ing the origin of life, and for rather simple reasons. One is the potential
for the binding and selective entrapment of key molecules, possibly
with the added bonus of orientating them in some sort of regular ar-
ray. Of particular importance would be a prebiotic process of stringing
together simpler building blocks, a process known as oligomerization.
What might be a demanding and problematic process in a free aque-
ous environment, with its continuous molecular jostling and recur-
rent danger of chemical interference by such processes as hydrolysis,
might be neatly short-circuited on the surface of some mineral such
as a clay or the phosphorus-rich apatite. Mineral surfaces potentially
have other advantages. These include an enormous surface area, espe-
cially if the mineral grains are small. Thus a cubic centimetre of clay
will contain particles whose total surface area, so Christopher Jeans
tells me, could, in principle, reach an astonishing 1800 m2 , roughly
equivalent to nine tennis courts. Moreover, if the mineral grains are
not too tightly packed then an interconnecting system of pores exists
so that fresh solutions can be swept in to supply a growing molecule.
And there is an added bonus if the mineral happens to have some sort
of catalytic property, capable of accelerating chemical reactions. It all
sounds very promising.
The experimental work is certainly interesting. Although most
efforts have been expended in persuading amino acids to link
together,29 the necessary step to form first a polypeptide and ul-
timately a protein, there have also been investigations into the
oligomerization of nucleotides,30 which would be analogous to build-
ing a strand of DNA. In these experiments typically only a very limited
variety of the potential building blocks is used, and quite often it is
the oligomerization of only one type of molecule that is attempted.
54 the origin of life: straining the soup or our credulity?
in any way equivalent to the atmosphere of the early Earth. At the time
of these investigations it was widely assumed that this early atmo-
sphere was devoid of oxygen. This was a reasonable enough assump-
tion given that life, specifically photosynthesis by algae and plants, is
the main source of this toxic and corrosive gas.69 It was also assumed
that the early atmosphere was quite rich in two key gases: ammonia
(NH3 ) and methane (CH4 ). Only a small amount of ammonia is re-
quired (at 25 ◦ C about a millionth of an atmosphere), but as Miller
himself remarked, ‘The details of the ammonia balance on the prim-
itive earth remain to be worked out.’70 In the experiments the levels
of methane were much higher, typically up to 0.2 of an atmosphere.
Again Miller noted, ‘This pressure is used for convenience, and it is
likely, but never demonstrated, that organic synthesis would work
at much lower partial pressure of methane.’71 Nobody disputes that
establishing the nature of the early atmosphere is problematic, but
the general consensus now is that so far as the Earth was concerned
methane, and even more so ammonia, were present only in small,
perhaps negligible, quantities. Rather than being strongly reducing,
the air was probably only slightly so, being composed of a mixture of
carbon dioxide, carbon monoxide, water vapour and nitrogen. In these
conditions attempts to produce not only amino acids but also com-
pounds such as the key precursor hydrogen cyanide (see note 8) are
effectively failures. It is hardly surprising, therefore, that other ways of
generating amino acids abiotically have been sought. As we saw in the
previous chapter, one hypothetical route is simply by cometary impact
(‘extraterrestrial infall’) and suchlike. A popular alternative, already
mentioned, is to consider hydrothermal systems, such as mid-oceanic
ridges, where amino acids can be generated at surprisingly high tem-
peratures, at least in experimental analogues,72 although with some
important provisos.73
Miller himself shows considerable candour in discussing the re-
search programme he has inspired. Despite the iconographic status of
his early experiments in sparking a methane-rich gas mixture, he and
his colleagues have no illusions that they are in any stronger position
to arrive at that long-sought-after ‘one-pot reaction’: chemicals in at
one end, cells out the other. The origin of some of the hydrocarbons
is a case in point. Here the usual invocation is to draw attention to a
process known as the Fischer–Tropsch reaction, where at quite high
temperatures (c. 200–400 ◦ C) high yields of hydrocarbons are obtained
a sceptic’s charter 63
a sceptic’s charter
The description of this bringing together of the basic ingredients for
life has been reduced to near parody by Robert Shapiro,75 but, how-
ever amusing, he is making a serious scientific point. The nub of his
argument, which I paraphrase below, is that even ignoring the com-
plex chemical reactions with their plethora of irrelevant by-products,
the varying stabilities of the resultant chemical compounds, the fre-
quently pathetically low yields, not to mention the various laboratory
protocols that necessarily insist on convenience of chemical purity
and efficiency of human-directed reactions, the range of molecules
necessary for life to emerge can be synthesized only in widely, if not
wildly, different environments. To be sure, in certain cases impor-
tant molecules, such as the simpler amino acids, can be generated in
a series of quite different settings. In other examples, however, syn-
thesis depends on rather specific pathways, while the stability of a
particular molecule is often precarious and sometimes dependent on
a particular environment. The sugar ribose, as we have seen, is de-
composed in only a few weeks, but most notorious in this respect
are the nucleotides, such as adenine, which for long-term survival
ideally require conditions well below freezing.76 Inconveniently, the
reverse holds for other molecules, at least in some high-temperature
hydrothermal settings. So let me give the gist of Shapiro’s scenario
for what might be needed to bring the prebiotic ingredients together
64 the origin of life: straining the soup or our credulity?
only been human, they would have embraced at the joy of their first
meeting, and in anticipation of the glorious future that lay ahead of
them. They would then have taken turns, each describing the mar-
vellous and different series of events that led to its own creation.’77
Nor does the story end there. Before life itself can emerge in
Shapiro’s tale more fortunate accidents involving phosphate-rich min-
erals, convenient catalysts, and floods are required; but his point has
already been made well enough. It might have been made, but has it
been heard? To show that Shapiro’s thinking is by no means off limits,
consider these remarks by two of the most respected experts, Gerald
Joyce and Leslie Orgel,78 in a section headed ‘ The prebiotic chemist’s
nightmare:
I should emphasize that Joyce and Orgel are equally careful to point
to encouraging lines of research, but near the end of the chapter they
remark, ‘There remains a lingering doubt that we are on the right track
at all.’81
How then can we escape these dilemmas? The sheer unlikeli-
hood of a ‘one-pot reaction’ emerging in any natural and primitive en-
vironment helps to explain the paradox of both frustration at repeated
failure and hope springing eternal that some environment – pyrite?
66 the origin of life: straining the soup or our credulity?
(soup, clay, clouds . . .) they share the common hypothesis that the
steps from inert to vital must be those of an unbroken continuity.
It would be an uncomfortable corollary if the series of meetings,
interactions, and reactions of those few chemicals that led to the ori-
gin of life were little more than a series of fortuitous and happy flukes.
If so, a scientific campaign for understanding the origin of life is not,
to put it mildly, going to be straightforward. It is hardly surprising that
George Wald91 wrote, ‘One has only to contemplate the magnitude of
this task [of making life] to concede that the spontaneous generation of
a living organism is impossible. Yet here we are – as a result, I believe,
of spontaneous generation.’92 This quotation has become justifiably
famous, but it is sometimes forgotten that in its original context there
was a very strong underlying assumption that such a process of spon-
taneous generation could be possible only if there were enough aeons
of time. As we shall now see, there probably were not, and to make
matters worse what obviously did happen in our Solar System may
itself be either a very rare occurrence, or, dangerous thought, possibly
unique.
5 Uniquely lucky? The
strangeness of Earth
10−1
10−2
Densest cratering
Uplands
Cumulative crater density
10−3
Tranquillitatis
Procellarum
10−4 Copernicus Crisium
Imbrium
Tycho
10−5
10−6
0 1 2 3 4 5
Age (Ga)
to life on Earth. In fact, the opposite is the case. Consider that if the
Moon was subject to so heavy a bombardment, then the much greater
gravitational attraction of the Earth, with a mass almost one hun-
dred times greater than that of the Moon, would almost certainly
have made it subject to an even more severe bombardment. Unlike
the Moon, the Earth now shows no direct trace of this bombardment:
the ceaseless processes of erosion and crustal recycling have oblit-
erated all the evidence. Many of the impacts must have been large,
and a few were cataclysmic. What happens when something very big
hits the Earth?7 The amount of energy released is enormous, so great
in fact that the heat generated was probably sufficient to evaporate
the entire world ocean. The net result is that the surface of the Earth
would then have become an inferno. Initially there would be an at-
mosphere of rock vapour, but this would cool quite quickly. This rock
would rain down in a couple of months to form a layer carpeting the
Earth to a depth of several hundred metres. The Earth would still be
a searing desert, and the atmosphere would remain a boiling mass
of water vapour and other gases: a scene in some ways resembling
the present-day Venus, where the surface temperatures are an uncom-
fortable 480 ◦ C. Venus has become trapped in a permanent furnace,
too close to the Sun and with an atmosphere that acts as a power-
ful and irreversible greenhouse. On the early Earth, however, after
each giant impact the excess heat was radiated into space, the atmo-
sphere cooled, and it began to rain, for perhaps 3000 years as the oceans
refilled.8
It is estimated that during the later bombardments the Earth
may have been pounded by five or so of these monster impacts, each
capable of evaporating the ocean and presumably sterilizing the sur-
face. In the case of the lunar maria, which as noted above, were also
formed in the late bombardment episode, it appears that although
they formed during a fairly substantial interval, the largest impacts
are quite closely clustered in time and, more significantly, terminated
rather abruptly about 3800 Ma ago. Now this happens to be a rather
significant date in Earth history, because it is the age of the oldest rea-
sonably well-preserved sediments.9 These are the famous sediments
from the Isua Supergroup of central – west Greenland. Despite meta-
morphism, a wide variety of lithologies, including waterlain conglom-
erates, are known. Although fossils are lacking10 the presence in these
sediments of carbon, altered by metamorphic heat to the mineral
battering the earth 73
content with even 10 Ma.18 This, incidentally, is not to say that life
did not emerge earlier. Quite possibly it did; in principle it could
have evolved several times,19 but was repeatedly snuffed out when the
oceans boiled and billions of tons of rubble descended to a fiery surface.
What of the other two possibilities mentioned above? It is
scarcely surprising that an estimate of a mere 20 Ma (or even 10 Ma)
for life to originate is sometimes greeted with considerable unease, if
not disbelief. As we saw at the end of the previous chapter (see p. 68),
it is a common assumption that life will certainly emerge at least in an
Earth-like milieu, but it needs not only time, but aeon stacked upon
aeon as the chemicals blindly combine and re-associate, with the thin
red thread of vitality worming its way past uncounted blind alleys
and entropic pits. One response is that life is indeed an abrupt pro-
cess of self-assembly, by implication a cosmic inevitability, as natural
as water being wet. Quite possibly so, but the experimental morass
reviewed in the preceding chapter might give us pause for thought.
So can we find a loophole, to allow more time for the emergence of
life?
There are certainly two possibilities. The first is that despite
the violence of the giant impacts, life not only evolved much earlier,
rocked by wave after wave of planetary disaster, but still managed to
cling on. Nobody doubts the tenacity of life, but not until the discov-
ery of deep-sea hydrothermal ecosystems with bacteria that incredibly
are able to function at temperatures close to 100 ◦ C was there any hint
as to how early life might have survived repeated thermal catastro-
phe. It is certainly interesting that many of the bacteria that appear
to fall closest to the root of life are adapted to function at very high
temperatures, and hence are known as the extreme thermophiles.20
This could indicate either the ancestry of life on a hot Earth, or more
probably an ability to survive a series of thermal ‘bottlenecks’, each
imposed by the vast quantities of energy released by a giant impact.
Despite the widespread popularity of these ideas (a sort of bacterial
equivalent of Benvenuto Cellini’s story of the fire-salamander bask-
ing in the flaming coals), some scientists continue to argue that the
most primitive forms of life were adapted to much more moderate
temperatures.21
So perhaps life is even more ancient than we suppose, with its
origins in the great heat of hydrothermal vents and its early survival
set against a backdrop of mega-impacts and searing temperatures far
the mars express 75
beyond any human tolerance. But there is a third way: in the begin-
ning our world was still far too dangerous, and by the time conditions
were stable enough to allow life to begin to evolve, it was far too
late. Hence, the third of the possible explanations for life appearing
no sooner than the great bombardment had ceased: life had indeed
evolved, but elsewhere, on Mars. Terrestrial proto-life didn’t stand a
chance.
it seems likely that the basic building blocks of life anywhere will
be similar to our own, in the generality if not in the detail. Thus,
the 20 common amino acids are the simplest carbon structures
imaginable that can deliver the functional groups used in life . . .
Similarly, the five-carbon sugars used in nucleic acids are likely to
be repeated themes . . . Further, because of the unique abilities of
purines and pyrimidines to interact with one another with
particular specificity, these subunits too, or something very
similar to them, are likely to be common to life wherever it
occurs.32
HD187123
HD75289
TauBoo
51Peg
Ups And
HD76700
HD49674
HD217107
HD162020
HD38529 (3.5 AU)
55Cnc (5.9 AU)
GL86
HD195019
GL876
Rho CrB
HD168443
HD114762
70Vir
HD80606
HD37124
HD12661
HD210277 KEY
HD128311
>1 Jupiter mass
16CygB
47UMa (3.7 AU) >1-- 4 Jupiter masses
14Her >4--11 Jupiter masses
HD216437 >11 Jupiter masses
0 1 2 3
Astronomical units
figure 5.3 A sample of extra-solar planets, scaled to our Solar System and the size relative to Jupiter.
(An astronomical unit is the distance from the Earth to the Sun, and is equivalent to 1.49 × 1011 m.)
Data taken from websites given in note 33.
making the solar system 81
unimaginable. As we shall see later (Chapter 6), this has not prevented
speculation about possible forms of life, although such hypotheses are
unlikely to be compatible with the extreme turbulence of such giant
worlds.
The real surprise, however, is not so much the enormous size
of these newly discovered planets but how closely some of them orbit
their stars (hence their nickname of ‘hot Jupiters’). Some are substan-
tially nearer to their stars than Mercury is to the Sun, whirling around
their stars in a few days. The searing surface temperatures that are in-
evitable so close to the star almost certainly preclude the possibility
of life. To complicate matters, many of these planets have eccentric
orbits. Even on the Earth, with a rather mild eccentricity (0.0167) the
variation in distance from the Sun is clearly discernible in climatic
changes. For extra-solar planets with eccentricities up to 0.93 (as for
HD 80606), the thermal regime at the surface will be much more
variable.
Although with present-day techniques we can detect only giant
planets, the continuing torrent of discoveries strongly suggests a trend
towards the majority of planets being relatively small. For example,
the planet orbiting the star HD 76700 has a mass approximately one-
fifth that of Jupiter, while that of HD 49674 is even smaller. As more
observations are made, planets more distant from their stars, which
take longer to complete an orbit, will also be detected. As noted above,
the third planet of 55 Cancri is remote from its star, taking more than
14 years to complete its orbit. It is important to stress that much
smaller planets, similar in size to the Earth, are still beyond the lim-
its of detection. There is so far no reason to think that such planets
cannot exist, somewhere. Telescopes suitable for their detection are
already being designed. And there is some cause for optimism. Some
earlier computer models of solar system formation were able to pro-
duce terrestrial planets, but there were difficulties. For example, both
the eccentricity and the inclination of the orbits were substantially
greater than those of the Earth, and there were also problems in ‘mak-
ing’ smaller planets, comparable to Mars and Mercury.39 Still, refine-
ments continue to be made, both as a result of new knowledge of
extra-solar systems and faster methods of computation. The results
obtained by John Chambers are impressive,40 inasmuch as it is now
possible to produce a range of hypothetical solar systems (Fig. 5.5)
equipped with a variety of terrestrial planets which ‘are reasonable
82 uniquely lucky? the strangeness of earth
100
50
Velocity (m s−1)
−50
−100
Ups And
150
Ups And
100
Velocity residuals (ms−1)
50
−50
−100
4.6-day sinusoid
removed
−150
1992 1994 1996 1998 2000
Time (years)
removed
making the solar system 83
Start 3 Ma
0.8
0.6
0.4
0.2
0.0
10 Ma 30 Ma
0.8
Eccentricity
0.6
0.4
0.2
0.0
60 Ma 200 Ma
0.8
0.6
0.4
0.2
0.0
0.5 1.0 1.5 2.0 0.5 1.0 1.5 2.0
Semi-major axis (AU)
were to a large extent unpredicted. These new results are forcing rad-
ical reconsiderations of how the nebular discs collapse into planets.
What to us is a familiar arrangement in our Solar System of an inner
series of small rocky planets and an outer group of gas and ice giants
may be very much less common than was once thought, and may be
very rare indeed.
Perhaps the most dramatic implication is the strong likelihood,
indeed near certainty, that the giant planets detected so far in the
ninety-odd extra-solar systems actually formed much further away
from their stars, and only subsequently were moved into their present
position of proximity.43 The reason for thinking this is that it is
effectively impossible for a planet to accrete so close to the star, and
mechanisms exist to explain why the planet should spiral inwards. It
will be obvious that even if life evolves on such planetary giants it will
be doomed as its home migrates closer and closer to its sun. Indeed,
in many instances it is likely that the planet’s ultimate destination
is the star itself, to be swallowed in the thermonuclear maelstrom.
To observe such a catastrophe is beyond our present technology,
but evidence for such an engulfment already exists.44 If the planet
86 uniquely lucky? the strangeness of earth
rare moon
At present the search for extraterrestrial life would receive immense
encouragement if a solar system at least similar to ours were to be
detected. Building a broad facsimile, however, may only be a first step,
because on closer examination our Solar System possesses a series of
apparent oddities (note 1) that may play crucial roles in the emergence
of life. Here our Moon, distant Jupiter, and the rare spectacle of a
comet all indicate that once again the Solar System may represent a
very special arrangement, and Earth an equally special abode.
Let us return to our most familiar planetary companion, the
Moon. As we have seen, it is scarred with a record of the early and
cataclysmic history of the Solar System, mutely reminding us of the
cataclysmic beginnings to the Earth’s history and the precarious, and
perhaps repeatedly frustrated, hold that life then had. Although there
have been a number of theories as to how the Moon came to be asso-
ciated with the Earth, it is now widely agreed that our satellite was
itself a product of a violent impact between the newly formed Earth
and another body, approximately the size of Mars.50 The reasons for
thinking that the Moon is a genuine daughter rather than a chance
capture are various; they include certain geochemical coincidences
and the nature of the dynamical relationship between the two bod-
ies. The Moon itself, however, is very old; it records the early bom-
bardment episodes, and rocks collected by the Apollo missions date
back close to the dawn of the Solar System.51 Given that the Earth
had formed by about 4500 Ma ago, perhaps 100 Ma after the initi-
ation of the Solar System,52 then the mega-impact that led to the
Moon could have been only a little later.53 Some evidence suggests
that at this early stage the Earth may have been somewhat smaller
than at present, and that the impact added substantially to its mass.54
Alternatively, the collision could have occurred somewhat later as the
Earth approached its existing size.55
88 uniquely lucky? the strangeness of earth
The collision must have been truly cataclysmic, and has been
analysed by the application of some remarkable computer models.
These give a glimpse of just how catastrophic the event must have
been, but more importantly they reveal that making the Moon may
be far from a straightforward process. Not surprisingly, modelling this
impact is computationally intensive, and delineating the exact na-
ture of the collision depends on a number of variables that in turn
are difficult to constrain. These include the mass of the collider, its
composition (for example, how iron-rich it was), the amount of an-
gular momentum available, and whether the collision was glancing
or head-on. In one such simulation56 the impactor plunges through
the mantle of the proto-Earth, settling on the core. As it does so the
massive release of energy ejects the existing atmosphere and replaces
it with one made of vaporized rock. As these investigators dryly note
the hemisphere which received the impact was ‘devastated’, while the
opposite hemisphere fared little better when a wall of molten rock
flowed across it. Other simulations show the early Earth deforming
as the result of the impact, like a high-speed photograph of a bouncing
tennis ball.
A key result of this giant impact, however, was the detachment
of sufficient material to form the Moon. It is here that we may begin
to run into difficulties. The simulations tend to suggest that building
a single large Moon from the material blasted off by the giant impact
is difficult.57 The alternatives might be either a series of small moon-
lets or even a ring of material, the latter analogous to those encircling
Saturn (and also, as recently discovered, Jupiter, Neptune, and
Uranus), being more likely to end up orbiting the devastated Earth.
At first sight a ring of debris around the Earth would seem a promis-
ing start towards the aggregation of a larger moon. Some of the models
are not, however, very encouraging: either the single body is too small
or the disc inconveniently aggregates into several moons.58 This sim-
ulation of the possible methods of coalescence of impact debris into
larger bodies is necessarily simplistic and looks at the behaviour of
only 37 ‘particles’, each with a radius of approximately 500 km. Even
this was computationally extremely demanding, but, as the investi-
gators remark, they ‘identify only a few scenarios in which a single
Moon results’.59 Further analyses60 are somewhat more optimistic,
although a recurrent difficulty is that a single large body tends to
form near to the Earth, close to the Roche limit, the point at which
rare moon 89
the gravitational field of the Earth would tear the new Moon to pieces.
Other simulations tended to form several smaller moons, and the con-
ditions necessary to form our Moon seem to remain very sensitive to
starting conditions. The problem of propelling a large mass of ma-
terial clear of the Roche limit is also stressed by A. G. W. Cameron
(see note 57). One way to achieve this is a collision with high angular
momentum. The question then arises as to how this angular momen-
tum was subsequently lost. It is important to stress that increasingly
sophisticated simulations are serving to constrain some of the bound-
ary conditions from which the Moon could form. Various sensitivities
still remain, and the work done so far suggests that a wide variety of
possible end-points different from the actual configuration are equally
feasible. A comprehensive simulation may explain much of the his-
tory of the actual impact, but apparently minor variations could have
led to a profoundly different end-point.
As Jack Lissauer has remarked, ‘It’s not easy to make the
Moon’.61 This is brought into sharp focus by some earlier remarks
by A. G. W. Cameron and W. Benz.62 Thus, concerning the origin of
the Moon they wrote:
They continue, ‘This issue lies well beyond the present reach of
science.’63
Although not everyone would agree that the nature of the Earth’s
atmosphere was critically controlled by the Giant Impact, it still
remains the case that even given such an immense collision, forming
the Moon was difficult, possibly extraordinarily difficult. Yet, without
our daughter satellite this world would certainly be a very different
place, and arguably much less benign.64 One advantage of having a
Moon is that it confers considerable stability to the axis of rotation of
the Earth, making it difficult to shift it appreciably from the existing
90 uniquely lucky? the strangeness of earth
◦
inclination of about 23 .65 To be sure there are controversial hypothe-
ses proposing that in the geological past there have been major shifts
in obliquity, with the Earth falling in effect on its side, to explain
climatic anomalies such as glaciations in equatorial regions.66 The
notion of profound changes in obliquity has not been well received,
but there is little doubt that without the Moon the Earth would have
been just as subject to chaotic shifts in obliquity as have occurred in
the other planets.67 At the least such shifts in obliquity would have
had major, possibly catastrophic, climatic consequences (Fig. 5.6).
But having the Moon has other advantages. Neil Comins,68 for
example, reminds us that the coupling between the Earth and its large
Moon leads to the transfer of angular momentum from the larger to the
smaller body, because of such factors as tidal friction. This has the re-
sult during geological time of both increasing the separation between
the Earth and Moon and, more importantly, decreasing the Earth’s
rate of rotation. The most obvious result of this slowing in rotation
is an increasing day length and a corresponding smaller number of
days in the year, for which the fossil record shows some confirmatory
evidence.69 If, however, the rate of rotation had not decreased, then
Comins suggests, by analogy with other rapidly rotating planets, that
the wind speeds on the Earth would be persistently higher, with many
more violent and protracted storms. A planet with life, perhaps, but
with winds tearing across the world at an average speed of 200 km per
hour it would be an uncomfortable place to exist. Marine life would
face continuously stormy seas, while on the continents vegetation
would be tough and ground-hugging and most animals would perhaps
be burrowers.
Having the Moon therefore seems to confer significant advan-
tages. Without it life would presumably still be possible, but it might
be more stressed and probably very different; and the emergence of
intelligence (Chapter 9) might well be compromised. Early in the his-
tory of the Solar System other giant impacts on Mars and Venus might
have spalled off material to make moons. The disproportionately large
size of the metallic core of Mercury has been used as an argument for
another giant impact that smashed away most of that planet’s outer
layer.70 Some scientists71 have consequently tended to argue that the
Earth’s Moon is not so exceptional: perhaps, they say, Venus lost any
satellites it had by the action of solar tides, while Mars was too small
and gravitationally weak to retain any such moons.72 The evidence
23.5° obliquity
305 +5°
+85°
265
−85°
245
90° obliquity
−85°
340
Surface temperature (K)
+85°
300
+5°
260
0 90 180 270 360
Longitude, with respect to vernal equinox
from the modelling of the Giant Impact that is thought to have pro-
duced the Moon, however, suggests that the impactor may have been
as large as Mars, and possibly substantially bigger. Even in the early
history of the Solar System, such a collision would have been very
rare, and as we saw above even size alone may not guarantee a Moon.
Also, it may well be that had this Giant Impact not occurred then
the Earth would have been a substantially smaller body. Is that so
important? It turns out that it is.
impact, but still in a world far away. Yet this capture and destruc-
tion actually appear to have a direct relevance to our own existence.
As George Wetherill76 reminds us, the powerful gravitational ‘well’
provided by Jupiter serves to deflect and capture innumerable comets
that would otherwise continue to hurtle towards the inner Solar Sys-
tem. Not only that, but other estimates77 suggest that about half the
comets entering the planetary Solar System from the more remote
Oort Clouds are then flung into interstellar space by the slingshot
effect of Jupiter’s gravity. The importance of this observation will be
returned to below. This still leaves plenty of comets roaming around
the Solar System in a variety of orbits, but Wetherill estimates that
without the shielding influence of Jupiter the comet flux to the Earth
would be about a thousand times greater. That would be bad news for
life on Earth and, as Wetherill observes, ‘this could frustrate the evolu-
tion of organisms that observe and seek to understand their planetary
system.’78
The danger of impacts has been brought into sharp focus, of
course, by the famous end-Cretaceous extinctions, the so-called K/T
event.79 Given the protracted time that ecosystems require to recover
from such disasters, typically a couple of million years,80 it is difficult
to believe that a repeatedly traumatized biosphere, suffering recurrent
and frequent impacts, would be similar to that of our own Earth. More
than a hint of this grim conclusion comes not only from the mayhem
associated with the extinctions, but also from some rather startling
evidence concerning the aftermath of perhaps the two greatest catas-
trophes, specifically the end-Permian (c. 250 Ma) and end-Cretaceous
(c. 65 Ma) events. Here the ecological disruption seems to have been
so severe that it almost seems as if the evolutionary clock had been
wound back to a time when there were no animals; a ‘return’ to Pre-
cambrian ecosystems dominated by microbial activities, with bacteria
and various mostly single-celled eukaryotes. Such a world, before an-
imals literally imprinted themselves on the biosphere, was evidently
very different from the one familiar to us. Thus, following the Permian
debacle there is some intriguing evidence for the wide-scale return
both of stromatolites81 and other microbially bound sediments.82
Analogous evidence for profound ecological disruption after the
end-Cretaceous catastrophe comes from a study of the sedimentary
carbon. The aftermath of this catastrophe has been something of
a paradox because although the marine algae, and thereby primary
jupiter and the comets 95
as dolphins, ants, and mystics, were far removed, out at the ‘snow-
line’. This, as mentioned, is adjacent to the orbital position of Jupiter
and it was Jupiter that was in a position to displace the water-rich
asteroids89 back towards the inner Solar System. If, however, Jupiter
had formed somewhat inward of its present position, then the Earth
might have remained sterile and dry. This is because Jupiter would
have still efficiently scattered the volatile-rich asteroids, but in the
wrong direction, outwards and away from the inner rocky planets.90
But what of the comets? Given that they appear to be largely
composed of ice, would they not be an ideal source of the Earth’s
volatiles?91 So far as water is concerned, however, it seems that the
comets may have made only a minor contribution. The reason for
thinking this is that the ratio in water between the isotope of ‘heavy’
hydrogen, known as deuterium, and the ‘light’ hydrogen is, in the few
comets yet examined, very different from that of the Earth’s oceans.
Hence the preferred source from the asteroids (note 89). This does
not mean, however, that comets played no part in ensuring the hab-
itability of the Earth; far from it. The principal source of the organic
compounds, the raw material for the origin of life, was probably de-
livered to the Earth at a late stage of its accretion, by a cometary
bombardment.
So, if Jupiter had been in the wrong position, perhaps there
would have been no oceans, and perhaps if the comets had not ar-
rived, no life? In this context it is therefore intriguing to learn that
cometary systems around other stars may be less common than might
be expected, and perhaps even rare. There are several reasons for
thinking this.92 In the case of our Solar System the estimated pop-
ulation of comets runs into the trillions, perhaps about 1013 . Broadly
these fall into two categories: those located somewhat beyond the
orbit of Neptune (the Kuiper Belt); and much further out a vast num-
ber, occupying an immense volume of space, far beyond the plan-
ets, in what is known as the Oort Cloud (see note 77). It is thought
that the Kuiper Belt and Oort Cloud supply respectively the so-called
short- and long-term comets. So what does this have to do with comets
from other solar systems? The explanation is that on the edges of our
Solar System the gravitational pull of the Sun is so weak that any
nearby disturbance, perhaps a passing star (not in itself an unlikely
occurrence given that the outer Oort Cloud extends about half-way
to the nearest star), will exert its own gravitational field and so disrupt
98 uniquely lucky? the strangeness of earth
may be an inevitability, but on Earth at least this process has taken bil-
lions of years. For this to happen demands the persistence of a zone of
safety, that is a Circumstellar Habitable Zone (CHZ). To us humans, of
course, the concept of a habitable zone is exceedingly narrow: without
technology we can neither fly nor burrow, and swimming beyond very
modest depths requires elaborate paraphernalia. Even the biosphere,
from the deepest bacteria to the migrating storks drifting past turbo-
props at 20 000 feet (6000 metres), occupies an exceedingly thin skin,
wedged between the intense heat and pressure of the Earth’s interior
and the sterile vacuum of outer space. Yet despite these flanking hos-
tilities beneath our feet and above our heads, the Earth itself occupies
a zone of comfort, a planetary Habitable Zone, and it is to this topic
we now turn.
0 0.5 1 1.5 2
R (AU)
−1
giants. The converse is also true: stars of low metallicity will gener-
ally lack planets.110 It also seems likely, however, that stars with a
proportionally higher metallicity are more likely to be accompanied
by ‘hot Jupiters’. But, as we have already seen, as such a giant migrates
inwards from its original orbit to position very close to its star so it
will either destroy or eject any earth-like planets. There is therefore
a fine balance in a solar system between having a star with sufficient
metallicity to ensure the existence of earth-like planets and having
a star with too high a metallicity that will lead to the spawning of
destructive ‘hot Jupiters’. These observations can then be combined
with calculations of the rate of star formation (and thus, in suitable
just the right place 103
a cosmic fluke?
Earlier I remarked on the almost gleeful abasement of humans, not
least to inform us that we are insignificant worms in the cosmic
drama. One powerful ingredient of this dreary world picture is the
Copernican triumph, of Earth the Insignificant. Perhaps so, but it
could be that our planet and its Solar System are both very much
odder than is realized. Life may be a universal principle, but we can
still be alone. Suppose, at least for the sake of the argument, if not hu-
mility, we really are. Suppose also that the Earth is genuinely a cosmic
accident, a chance fluke arising from spinning clouds of dust and gas.
Such a view is now widely accepted, but so, too, are such principles
applied with equal conviction to the history of life. From its start-
ing point, however and wherever that strange event might have been,
orthodoxy states that evolution can potentially explore a million dif-
ferent trajectories. Even if somewhere there is a planet like the Earth,
so the argument continues, there may well be life but assuredly no
biped writing lines similar to these. In the next few chapters I shall
try to persuade you to take another view.
6 Converging on the extreme
universal chlorophyll?
At first sight the problem of addressing the question of evolutionary
alternatives seems almost intractable. How can we begin to compare
something of which we know nothing with that with which we are
universal chlorophyll? 107
the crew on a sinking ship are ordered into the hold to stem the flood,
and are all issued with sieves.
Nor is this the only problem the photosynthesizers face. An
essential prerequisite of the process, of course, is carbon dioxide. Sup-
pose, however, that the amount of this gas in the atmosphere were
to plummet drastically. This might be due to a number of natural
processes, such as episodes of massive mountain-building that expose
vast areas of rock and scree where the carbon dioxide can be ‘soaked’ up
by the enhanced rates of rock weathering. Plants would be faced with
an extremely serious problem, and it was one that actually started
about 15 million years ago. At this time the levels of atmospheric
carbon dioxide began to decline precipitously, in part probably be-
cause of the uplift of a series of huge mountain belts, most notably
the Himalayas. The plants’ solution was to modify the steps in the
photosynthetic process, leading to a transition from so-called C3 pho-
tosynthesis to a C4 mode (the numbers refer to the number of carbon
atoms in the first compound to be formed). The details of this C4 pho-
tosynthesis are considered in Chapter 10, but what is worth noting
here is that its evolution is rampantly convergent.
The processes of photosynthesis are, therefore, hedged in with
many constraints, but even so chlorophyll is a remarkable molecule
that effectively underpins the entire biosphere. It is thus rather sur-
prising to learn that not only does chlorophyll fall short in such mat-
ters as the effectiveness of its RuBisCO, but it also seems to suffer
from rather more general difficulties. George Wald, in particular, has
pointed out that if one compares the absorption spectra of the vari-
ous types of chlorophyll to the available visible light spectrum of our
Sun the match is, to put it mildly, disappointing (Fig. 6.1). Clearly
the chlorophyll has to absorb some sunlight or it simply would not
work. In addition, different types of chlorophyll vary somewhat in
their absorption spectra: chlorophyll d, for example, shows a rather
remarkable shift towards absorption of red light.12 Accordingly chloro-
phyll has some latitude in the wavelengths of light it is best adapted
to absorb, but it is all the more remarkable that the lion’s share of
the Sun’s radiant energy remains largely untapped. And from this ap-
parent anomaly Wald draws a very interesting inference. He argues
that, however desirable a ‘perfect’ chlorophyll might be, it is simply
not attainable: as the initial supplies of prebiotic ‘soup’ run out, so
life must move to the situation where it can synthesize its own food
110 converging on the extreme
figure 6.1 A comparison between the spectrum of the Sun and the
absorption spectra of three types of chlorophyll. Note how the spectra of
the chlorophylls differ, but none is able to intercept the maximum
output of the Sun. An ‘ideal’ chlorophyll would mirror the outline of the
Sun’s spectral profile, leading George Wald to suggest that not only is
terrestrial chlorophyll the best available, but anywhere else in the
Universe on a planet the same chlorophyll will occur. (Redrawn from
figure by Emai Kasai on p. 96 of G. Wald’s article ‘Life and light’,
Scientific American, vol. 201 (4), pp. 92–108. Copyright c 1959 by
Scientific American, Inc. All rights reserved.)
from the light of its sun. Accordingly the necessary machinery, in-
cluding chlorophyll, must evolve. On this basis Wald draws a bold
conclusion, remarking that ‘When that time comes, it seems to me
likely that the same factors that governed the exclusive choice of
the chlorophylls for photosynthesis on the Earth might prove equally
compelling elsewhere.’13
We have already seen that the chances of encountering habit-
able planets may be much lower than is generally supposed, but what
if we do locate an alien biosphere? Wald’s arguments suggest that
however many light years we may be from the Earth, if we discover a
planet and wander along its remote shores with their entanglements of
the wheels of life? 111
seaweeds or explore its immense forests, sure enough there will be the
same and all-too-familiar chlorophyll soaking up the light of an alien
star.14
The only other way in which at least some animals can loco-
mote in this fashion seems to be to turn the entire body into a wheel.
Perhaps the most remarkable of such examples are certain shrimps
(stomatopods) that can execute up to 40 consecutive rolls,20 and a
pangolin21 on the island of Siberut, west of Sumatra, which has been
observed to roll itself up and then go crashing through the under-
growth of a steep slope.22 Other examples, such as cartwheeling
spiders and sea anemones,23 not to mention the so-called circumro-
tatory corals,24 are interesting in their own right, but scarcely qualify
as wheeled organisms. Organic wheels, therefore, seem to be an ex-
cluded possibility, and it is not difficult to see why. In a thoughtful
study Mike LaBarbera points out that, among other factors, any ani-
mal wheels of reasonable size would presuppose effectively flat and
continuous surfaces.25 Hence our need for roads as well as, more lo-
cally, ramps for wheelchairs. In the natural world as often as not, and
especially on sea floors, this means acres of mud and other soft, sticky,
substrates, ideal for getting bogged down. On this planet, and perhaps
everywhere, any wheeled organisms are going to be bipeds cycling to
the pub.26
fortean bladders
Is there any other neglected possibility? R. A. Fortey, for example, has
pondered whether any major ecological niche remains untenanted,
and suggests that one such niche might exist.27 Thus he writes that
‘High in the atmosphere there is a stream of air which transports in-
sects and spiders, like some plankton of the ether. Could an aerial
‘whale’ have evolved to harvest this stratospheric protein: a light,
flying animal with a wide feeding gape, an animal that could cast
a shadow across the sky?’28 Fortey is careful to note that there might
be good explanations why such an animal could not exist, but for
whatever reason he does not choose to address them.
In principle, such a Fortean bladder,29 named in honour of that
master of intangible aerial phenomena, Charles Fort (see also note 49),
should be biologically unproblematic.30 Perhaps the best analogy is
the swim-bladder found in many fish, a gas-filled organ that confers
buoyancy.31 The ever-present problem of leakage of gas is controlled
by deposition in the swim-bladder wall of guanine crystals32 that
evidently confer impermeability. In looking at the swim-bladder of
the conger eel Eric Denton remarked that removal of the silvery layer,
fortean bladders 113
ground the concentration of organisms drops off very rapidly with in-
creasing height.51 This is, of course, why on land and in the air there is
no equivalent to the aquatic suspension feeders that strain the much
more viscous water for tiny particles; apart from birds such as swal-
lows, the nearest approach to terrestrial suspension feeders are the
web-spinning spiders.
a silken convergence
Spiders, of course, are celebrated for their ability to extrude liquid pro-
tein through the narrow nozzles of their spinnerets, and thereby draw
out a slender thread of silk.52 Although it is generally agreed that these
spinnerets are modified appendages the origins of the silk glands are
still rather mysterious.53 Even so, spider’s silk itself is probably most
familiar from the orb-webs, even though it is also employed in a num-
ber of other ways. The ogre-faced spiders, for example, capture their
prey with a gladiator-like net of sticky silk (see also Chapter 7, p. 156,
for a discussion of the huge eyes of these spiders). The mechanical
properties of spider silk, not least its strength, are quite remarkable.
It is also well known that the orb-weavers (the araneoids) can secrete
several types of silk,54 each with its own combination of physical prop-
erties, including mechanical properties (e.g. tensile strength, tough-
ness), and degree of stickiness, that make it suitable for different parts
of the web. These physical properties arise from the behaviour of the
silk proteins,55 known as fibroins, and the key role of a few amino
acids, notably alanine and glycine. The proteins are, of course, coded
for by specific genes,56 and some of the structural units in the fibroins
are remarkably conservative, apparently maintaining the same organi-
zation for more than 100 Ma. Clearly, therefore, functionality cannot
be jeopardized and this is a good example of what is called stabilizing
selection.57 It is a curious thought that an insect blundering into a spi-
der’s web is encountering a molecular predicament that is unchanged
since the time of the dinosaurs. Not only that, but, as Catherine Craig
and her colleagues remark, the evolution of these proteins has been
by ‘selection for functional properties specific to the ecological pur-
poses for which they are used.’58 These comments were made in the
context of discussing such properties as ultraviolet reflectance. This
determines how visible the silk is to a passing insect and thereby
appears to explain the dramatic evolutionary success of the spiders,
especially the familiar orb-web spinners. Craig et al. suggest that these
116 converging on the extreme
the worker, the larva keeping itself rigid, a tiny patch of silk is laid
down on the leaf surface before the larva is carried across to the other
side of the leaf where the silk thread, spun out during its transport, is
reattached. Not only do ants construct tents; so also do some tropical
bats,71 although the latter do not of course employ silk.72 And the
purpose of these tents? Protection of a sort, but apparently for males
guarding their harems.
figure 6.2 A plot of ‘skeleton space’, a matrix that divides the skeleton
into seven major categories (and 21 variables), starting with whether
they are internal (as in us and other vertebrates) or external (as in
arthropods). This gives a total of 186 pair-combinations, of which a
handful are effectively impossible. Of the remainder, the majority are
either abundant or common, having evolved many times; in rare
instances evolution of such an arrangement usually has occurred at least
twice. (Redrawn from fig. 12 of Thomas and Reif (1993; citation is in
note 74), with the permission of the Society for the Study of Evolution
and the authors.)
matrices and skeletons 119
play it again!
But what of counterfactuals, the replaying of history that exerts such
an eerie fascination? Just consider the ‘what ifs’ of European history: a
successful Spanish armada? A Catholic Europe, with science emerging
in a society that presupposed that the Universe was both rational and
had a moral architecture?82 A Charles the First who engaged and de-
feated the Scots in 1639? No English Civil War? No Lord Protector? An
eighteenth century without the brilliant chemist Antoine Lavoisier?
No reform of the French gunpowder industry, a vital component
of the armament shipments to the American colonies in rebellion
against the British Crown?83 Napoleon Bonaparte triumphant at
Waterloo and Europe’s first police state fully operational by 1820,
rather than three more attempts (1870, 1914, 1940) – and as for the
the fourth? German hegemony and the Euro by 1916 as the British
Cabinet avoids conflict by persuading the Germans not to invade
‘gallant, little Belgium’? England invaded by the Nazis in 1940? The
Bloomsbury group taking their cyanide, while in Cambridge a very se-
nior figure glances at King’s College chapel and then carefully adjusts
his swastika armband?84 Looking for trends in history is now deeply
unfashionable, yet so far as the biological equivalent is concerned
play it again! 121
we find that here at least trends have a reality, and are not only
self-evident in the history of life but are even testable in the
laboratory.
The organism of choice is, unsurprisingly, a bacterium, specif-
ically the microbiologist’s equivalent of the fruit-fly and the mouse,
that is, Escherichia coli, more usually referred to as E. coli. This has
some substantial advantages for the study of evolution.85 The genet-
ics of this bacterium are well understood, and population growth is
very fast: in favourable conditions the cells divide as frequently as
once every 20 minutes. Moreover, even as the descendant lineages are
allowed to mutate along a myriad of evolutionary trajectories the an-
cestral ‘race’ can be preserved by the simple expedient of freezing, to
be reawoken when a comparison needs to be made between the start-
ing point and a population that might have been evolving for literally
thousands of generations.
And it is on this basis that Richard Lenski, Michael Travisano,
and their colleagues have undertaken a series of elegant experiments
to see how evolution replays itself. In one experiment these inves-
tigators set up 12 separate populations of E. coli.86 Each was then
allowed to diversify – effectively to evolve – independently for
2000 generations. At this stage each of these populations was di-
vided into three, and the resultant 36 populations were then left to
evolve yet further, for another 1000 generations. At this stage, 36 dif-
ferent evolutionary trajectories have been followed. So far, so good,
but now these populations are introduced to a novel substrate, the
sugar maltose. E. coli much prefers glucose, and maltose is biochem-
ically challenging. For each population a new ‘history’, the struggle
with maltose, will now unfold. The investigators specifically wanted
to see what would happen with the bacteria living on the maltose
substrate after 1000 generations had elapsed. The real objective of the
experiment was to weigh up statistically the relative importance of
three factors: those of chance (life’s grand lottery), adaptation (with the
implications of trends and optimization), and history (play it again!).
Which is the most important? If chance played the main role then the
36 populations would be expected to evolve in all sorts of different
directions, each caught in a contingent net of circumstances. Con-
versely, if adaptation by selection was important then the populations
should converge on one (or more) stable end-points. And how on earth
can we rerun history multiple times? That is the point of arranging
122 converging on the extreme
A
1.4
Derived fitness in maltose
1.2
A
A
1.0
0.8
0.6
0.6 0.8 1.0 1.2
Ancestral fitness in maltose
B
0.30
Derived fitness in maltose
0.20 Before
0.10
0.00
Ad Ch Hi
ap an sto
tat ce ry
ion
figure 6.3 Rerunning the history of evolution, with the bacterium
Escherichia coli. The upper panel shows the relative increase of fitness
of 12 replicate populations (A→L) of E. coli, each subdivided three
times, when placed on a maltose substrate. The dotted line would be the
case of no increase in fitness, and clearly all 36 sub-populations have
increased their relative fitness, even those that ancestrally had a high
fitness to maltose. The lower panel disentangles the relative roles of
adaptation, chance and history during this process. Note chance has a
very limited role, that of history declines substantially, while that of
adaptation increases markedly. (Reprinted (excerpted) with permission
from M. Travisano, J. A. Mongold, A. F. Bennett and R. E. Lenski,
Science, vol. 267, pp. 87–90. Fig. 2A and 2B. Copyright 1995. American
Association for the Advancement of Science.)
124 converging on the extreme
attacking convergence
Such multiple evolutionary trials suggest that life is far from some sort
of contingent muddle, yet the criticism might be levelled that they
are either rather general, such as the example of the matrix of skeleton
space, or very specific, good for an anecdote over a pint of beer in the
Green Dragon but hardly of any real evolutionary significance. Some
examples do indeed seem to be little more than curiosities, such as the
Jurassic crustacean that is reminiscent of the trilobites,107 or a fossil
bryozoan that adopts a form of spiralling fans that as a bryozoan design
had disappeared more than 200 million years earlier.108 Occasionally
these reappearances seem more like zombies.109 Such is the case in
certain fossil snails found in sediments of Triassic age, that is, the
geological interval that followed the great end-Permian catastrophe.
They are remarkably similar to the pre-catastrophe snails, but it is not
clear whether this is because they are in fact survivors of the debacle
(Lazarus taxa) or actually represent new species, but evolving along
the same old tracks (Elvis taxa).110
What convergence is, and what it might imply, I hope will be-
come clearer as this book unfolds. A few preliminary remarks, how-
ever, may be apposite. First and most obviously, biological conver-
gence can mean many things and operate at many levels. As I shall
argue, however, there are some common implications, despite the
attacking convergence 127
designs, are also convergent within the flying insects.116 Insects are
a rich source of insights into many other convergences, some of
which (e.g. compound eyes (Chapter 7), eusociality (Chapter 8), hal-
teres (Chapter 7), silk (see above, p. 115), and trachea (Chapter 10) are
mentioned elsewhere. So, too, are the related crustaceans. In the im-
mediate context of attack and defence the repeated evolution of the
pectinate claw is a striking example.117 Yet more intriguing is the
repeated emergence of a crab-like form118 from among the decapod
crustaceans, otherwise familiar in the form of the lobster. This exam-
ple is of particular interest because, in contrast to many, if not most,
examples of convergence where the arrangement has a clear function-
ality in response to a particular adaptive challenge, in the recurrent
emergence (five times) of a crab-like form there is no apparent associ-
ation with a specific mode of life or environment.119
Let me give you another example, again from the world of at-
tack and mayhem. This is in the form of the independent evolution
of dagger-like canines in both placental cats (the sabre-tooth felids)120
and a group of South American marsupials known as the thylacos-
milids (Figure 6.5).121 In fact, the evidence suggests that even within
the placental felids the sabre-tooth habit evolved several times.122 The
dinosaur enthusiast Bob Bakker has also suggested that an analogy to
these sabre-toothed mammals can be found in the allosaurids of the
Jurassic.123 Although as a group the marsupials, best known in the
guise of the kangaroo and wombat, tend to be regarded in some gen-
eralized sense as inferior to the placentals, this is too simplistic.124
So, too, the rich, but now largely extinct, diversity of South American
marsupials is widely regarded as having been competitively inferior
to the onslaught of the placental mammals that surged south when
the linkage to North America was secured via the newly emergent
Panamanian isthmus several million years ago.125 In fact, in the mar-
supial thylacosmilids the sabre showed a number of what appear to
be design advantages when compared with the placental equivalents,
including the possession of a protective flange (the placental sabre-
tooth known as Barbourofelis shows the nearest equivalent), a self-
sharpening mechanism (presumed to act against some sort of horny
pad), and a deeper insertion into the skull that presumably afforded
a more secure housing for the canine. It need hardly be stressed that
despite this manifest convergence neither group escapes its imprint
of phylogenetic history, which is marked, for example, in the spe-
cific structure of the teeth.126 It is also worth remarking that the
figure 6.5 Convergence in the sabre-tooth, between the marsupial
thylacosmilid (upper) and placental cat (lower). (Copyright Marlene Hill
Donnelly (the Field Museum, Chicago), with permission, reproduced
from fig. 10 of L. G. Marshall’s The great American interchange – an
invasion induced crisis for South American mammals (pp. 133–229), in
Biotic crises in ecological and evolutionary time, edited by M. H.
Nitecki (Academic Press, Orlando, Florida).)
131
132 converging on the extreme
figure 6.8 Convergent evolution in the burrowing (fossorial) mammals, including the familiar mole
(Talpa), mole-rat (Spalax), and marsupial mole (Notoryctes). (Reproduced from fig. 1 of E. Nevo (1995)
Mammalian evolution underground. The ecological–genetic–phenetic interfaces, Acta Theriologica,
Supplement 3 (Ecological genetics in mammals II, eds. G. B. Hartl and J. Markowski), pp. 9–31, with
permission of author and Acta Theriologica.)
convergence: on, above, under the ground 141
have both these types of eye – camera and compound – evolved several
times, but even the very mechanisms of seeing in terms of the neural
architecture have also shown multiple convergences. Have I missed
the right road? I give a sceptical cough; both animals can hear me,
one through its triangular, furry ears and the other using the so-called
Johnston’s organs. What could be more different? Yet the auditory
mechanisms are convergent. The cat and the mosquito can smell me,
but again the differences between the nostrils of this feline mammal
and the ‘nose’ of that blood-sucking insect (actually located on its
antennae) are in reality superficial. This is because the mechanisms of
olfaction are also strongly convergent. Even the way in which the cat
and the mosquito walk is convergent in terms of their neural circuits,
reflexes, and motor control: four legs or six, it really does not make
very much difference.7
a balancing act
So, if convergence is going to be a guiding principle in understanding
evolution, then of all the areas worth investigating one of the most in-
teresting must surely be to look at what constraints, if any, accompany
the development of sensory organs. It is here, if anywhere, that we
can approach the wider problem of the evolution of nervous systems,
brains, and perhaps ultimately sentience. And this in turn might give
some clues as to whether indeed intelligence is some quirky end point
of the evolutionary process or whether in reality it is more-or-less
inevitable, an emergent property that is wired into the biosphere.
A similar question has been succinctly posed by David
Sandeman.8 He writes, ‘it may be of interest to ask whether there are
sensory organs that are unique and not convergent . . . One of the most
bizarre and ingenious equilibrium systems that have arisen is without
doubt the halteres of the dipteran flies’ (his emphasis).9 The halteres,
it may need to be explained, are the organs for balance in the flies.
They are located on the back of the fly and resemble tiny drumsticks.
In flight they swing continuously to act as gyroscopes that serve to
detect angular accelerations. It has long been realized that the hal-
teres are derived from the pair of hind-wings of the fly (most insects
have two pairs of wings), and are indeed, in Sandeman’s terminology,
‘bizarre and ingenious’. Surely these qualify as a unique biological
invention? Not a bit of it. Sandeman’s question was rhetorical. He
reminds us that very similar structures are found in another group
a balancing act 149
Optic nerve
Retina
Pigmented layer
Nuclear layer
figure 7.2 Convergence of the camera-eye, including the classic comparison between the octopus (cephalopod) and human
(vertebrate), as well as the alciopid polychaete (annelid). (Redrawn from various sources.)
returning the gaze 153
the eye-cup, the associated nerve cells extend into the body to make
their connection with the brain. In contrast, the vertebrate retina is
effectively an outgrowth from the central nervous system. The net
result of this process is that, in contrast to the molluscs, in the ver-
tebrates the nerve cells come to overlie the retina. The exit point of
these nerves to the optic tract, which then leads to the brain, results in
a ‘hole’ in the retina, better known as the ‘blind spot’. Accordingly the
arrangement of nerve cells and retina in molluscs and vertebrates is
reversed, the cephalopods having arguably the more ‘sensible’ design
of nervous layer beneath sensory retina.
The cephalopod lens is also formed in a rather different way.23 It
has a rather remarkable layered structure,24 and being inflexible can-
not change its shape to assist in the process of focusing.25 It is still
not clear exactly how the cephalopods manage to focus, but most
probably it is by moving the entire lens backwards or forwards.26
The style of construction of the lens may also explain why at least
some cephalopods are able to correct for spherical aberration. (This is
a phenomenon in which the light rays, on passing through the lens,
fail to focus at a single point, resulting of course in a blurred image.)
Even so, correction for such aberration seems to be less refined than
in the fish. In the fish eye the refractive index (which is a measure
of how much the light ray is bent as it passes from one medium to
another) varies through the thickness of the lens. In cephalopods, how-
ever, spherical aberration may be dealt with by using non-spherical
lenses, which in turn is possible because of their different mode of
formation.27 These differences perhaps represent relative disadvan-
tages of cephalopods as compared with fish.
Control of eye movements is, of course, critical. This is achieved
by the so-called extra-ocular muscles that are attached to the exterior
of the eyeball. Through what is known as the oculomotor control sys-
tem, routed via the brain, this arrangement is linked to the organs
of balance and so provides a coordinated arrangement, referred to as
the vestibulo-oculomotor reflex.28 As already noted there are inter-
esting convergences in the systems of balance, which in cephalopods
are represented by the statocysts and in vertebrates by part of the
inner ear. Given the nature of the oculomotor system it is not sur-
prising to find convergences in the brain pathways between some
cephalopods, such as the octopus, and the vertebrates.29 The degree of
similarity between these systems is, in one sense, hardly surprising,
154 seeing convergence
eyes of an alien?
It is beginning to look, therefore, as if active, fast-moving, and at least
in some cases intelligent animals opt for the camera-eye.64 So, too,
we need to remind ourselves that commonalities of eye structure may
lead to convergences in brain structure and the evolution of visual cen-
tres, which is at least the case within the mammals.65 Yet, so far as
visiting aliens go the story more often looks to the immense cylinder,
embedded in the cricket pitch, the hatch slowly opening, a hideous
scrabbling before the bug-eyed monster levers itself out and begins
its obligatory, laser-cannon-powered destruction of the pavilion. The
inspiration for this abrupt interruption of the smooth running of the
Home Counties is presumably the alien-like appearance of insects,
robotic limbs, and empathy-free compound eyes. Clearly, given the
immense success of the arthropods, the compound eye has its advan-
tages. For example, the eyes of some deep-sea crustaceans are remark-
ably adept at collecting the minute quantities of light available at
depth, and do so by employing a sort of fibre-optic system.66 This spe-
cialized arrangement has arisen independently in two pelagic groups,
specifically a galatheid crab and the euphausiids.67 Not only that,
but it now seems likely that the compound eye itself is convergent
in the arthropods, evolving independently in a group of crustaceans,
the ostracods.68 It is interesting also to note convergent evolution of
the compound eye in the sabellid annelids69 and bivalve molluscs70
(Fig. 7.3). In the sabellid annelids this type of eye evidently has evolved
independently several times.71 In both these groups the shared con-
vergence seems to reflect, however, a rather different adaptation from
eyes of an alien? 159
that found in the arthropods; here the compound eyes appear to act as
a sophisticated optical alarm.72
Yet it is in the arthropods that the compound eyes are most
familiar, ranging as they do from the familiar example of the insects
to the calcite lens of the extinct trilobites.73 Trilobite eyes are often
claimed to be unique, but in fact they show two interesting conver-
gences. The first is in terms of general organization, and entails a
comparison with the eyes of the strepsipteran insects,74 a group that
we encountered earlier in the context of their convergently derived
gyroscopic halteres. The overall resemblance to trilobite eyes, espe-
cially the more advanced type known as schizochroal (see below) is
quite striking, but strepsipteran eyes (Fig. 7.1) are not calcitic. An
equivalent arrangement, albeit on a smaller scale, is found, however,
in a group of echinoderms mentioned above, the brittle-stars. Here,
on the upper side of the five arms, there are the characteristic calcitic
ossicles that make up the flexible skeleton, but evidently modified
for the purposes of vision.75 As in the trilobite lens, the optic axis is
parallel to the line of sight, an important feature because the mineral
calcite shows strong double refraction. This means that light passing
through the crystal at an angle to the optic axis is split into two rays,
resulting in the formation of a double image. Along the optic axis
of the crystal, however, the rays remain together, so that the trans-
mitted image remains single.76 This convergence in calcitic eyes may
extend further because each brittle-star ossicle is composed of a series
of lenses, each forming a dome-like structure, which is strongly rem-
iniscent of a trilobite compound eye. Just what the brittle-star ‘sees’
160 seeing convergence
figure 7.4 The compound eye of a mysid shrimp. Above, entire eye
with simple eye located on posterior side. Below, transverse section of
eyes. Simple eye is on lower side. (Photographs courtesy of Professor
D-E. Nilsson, University of Lund.)
162 seeing convergence
each underlie a separate lens, have been diverted to supply the gi-
ant lens. In life the eyes of the shrimp can move freely, and used
together the two giant lenses evidently act as a binocular. Looking
at this animal changes our perception; as Dan Nilsson and Richard
Modlin remark, ‘Viewing the live animal from behind . . . gives an
almost uncanny feeling of being observed’.83
So here in one particular arthropod we have a design that ap-
proaches that of our own eyes; yet from the point of view of evolution
it appears to be a dead end. As the investigators remark,
The answer may lie in the difficulties in reorganizing the neural cir-
cuitry and, as it happens, with the notable and already noted exception
of some spiders (see p. 157), nearly all other arthropods remain stuck
with their compound eyes.
In the final analysis camera-eyes are not only different from
compound eyes; they are better. This is because in the compound
eye the visual array can be increased both by expanding the overall
area of the eye and also by the increasingly dense packing of the lens.
There are, however, limits to both, and in particular as the lenses
shrink in size so their ability to collect enough light to function is
compromised. Calculations suggest that if humans were to rely on
a compound eye to achieve equivalent vision it would have to be
at least a metre across, and more realistically up to 12 metres wide
(Fig. 7.5).85 On distant planets there might (or might not) be bug-eyed
aliens, but any astronomers are almost certainly going to be equipped
with camera-eyes. Perhaps, too, they will have binocular vision, a rea-
sonable enough assumption given its convergent acquisition in birds
and mammals.86 Yet, it is also worth remarking here that in a certain
eyes of an alien? 163
there’. Even let us suppose that our extraterrestrial has the inevitable
camera-eyes, but these are mounted in little turrets and able to swivel
independently. Again we can find a striking convergence here on
Earth. Such an arrangement is well known in the chameleon lizards. It
entails some remarkable changes to the basic camera-eye. Among the
most striking of these is the suppression of the lens and its replace-
ment for refractive purposes by the cornea, which is duly equipped
with muscles to effect the changes in shape necessary for focusing.
How odd, but this rearrangement is strongly convergent on the eyes
of the sand-lances, a group of fish.91 And despite the different media,
air as against water, there is a common adaptive explanation. Both
chameleons and sand-lances are capable of exceedingly accurate and
rapid strikes at their respective prey: in effect the lunging of the entire
fish is equivalent to the darting of the chameleon tongue.92
In discussing eyes a number of qualifications are important.
First, it is agreed that eyes have evolved independently very many
times. In their classic paper Luitfried v. Salvini-Plawen and Ernst
Mayr93 write, ‘Summing up the different and convergent sequences
towards eye perfection in general, there are about 20 or even more
independent lines of differentiation including at least 15 cases of
independent attainments of photoreceptors with a distinct lens.’94 Al-
though I have emphasized the importance of compound and camera-
eyes and their convergences, unique optical configurations do occur.
Perhaps the best example is the remarkable eye (or eyes, given that
an individual has a whole series distributed along the shell margin)
of the scallop, which although camera-like has a system of inter-
nal mirrors.95 As Michael Land aptly remarked,96 this represents ‘an
almost unique example of a type of eye that should exist, but which
had not been found until relatively recently’.97 Even so, the reflec-
tivity of the eye depends on the mirror-like properties of the material
guanine.98 This compound has already been encountered in the rather
different context of providing thin, flexible sheets that would help to
gas-proof a Fortean bladder (pp. 112–113). In an optical context, how-
ever, not only is guanine found in scallop eyes, but it also forms the
reflective structures, known as the tapetum, that are found in the
eyes of certain vertebrates, notably deep-sea fish, where they act to
concentrate light.99 Nor does its ‘optical’ use stop there, because the
silvery guanine is also widely used as a reflector to channel the light
generated by the luminescent organs known as photophores.100
eyes of an alien? 165
however strange the construction of the eye may be, such as is seen
in the remarkable mirror optics of the scallop eye (which actually has
a direct parallel to some telescopes95 ), the transparency is still con-
ferred by the agency of crystallins.116
The importance of the crystallin proteins in conferring trans-
parency to tissues is nicely shown in what might be called a ‘reverse
eye’. In some squid, for example, the body bears bioluminescent organs
(the photophores) that emit flashes of light. The tissue of this ‘reverse
eye’ is derived from the musculature, yet not only are there sometimes
lenses117 but once again the transparency is conferred by recruitment
of a crystallin.118 More generally, the wide range of co-opted proteins
that provide transparency, be it in eyes or ‘reverse eyes’, is another
striking example, not only of convergence, but also of biochemical
convergence.119 Just as I speculated that alien astronomers (if there
are any) would be searching the skies using camera-eyes, so it would
also seem more than likely that inside their eyes the lenses would be
packed full of the direct equivalents of the crystallin proteins.
The other essential component of any eye is a mechanism for
converting the incoming photons into electrical signals that, some-
how, the brain can interpret as an image. In detail this entails a very
complicated sequence, but the key element is a group of proteins
known as the opsins. Of these the protein rhodopsin is probably the
most familiar. Its basic structure is of some interest in that we shall
encounter the arrangement of seven α-helices, each of course made of
a string of amino acids, spanning two sides of a lipid membrane in an-
other sensory context (pp. 180–181). Embedded within the rhodopsin
molecule, and attached to two of the α-helices, is a molecular unit
known as a chromophore. This is usually a derivative of vitamin A,
known as retinal120 and hence explains why such a vitamin disorder,
sometimes genetic, can lead to difficulties with sight.121
Rhodopsin is, therefore, as integral to vision as are the crys-
tallins. This protein also offers further insights into the nature of
convergence in at least two ways. The first is rather specific, and
concerns the – to us – familiar property of colour vision. The second is
more general and also controversial: how many times has rhodopsin
evolved? To humans the glory of a rainbow is appreciated because
our colour vision is trichromatic (blue, green, red), a relatively un-
usual condition among the animals. In mammals, for example, it is
otherwise found only in the apes and their close relatives, the Old
168 seeing convergence
universal rhodopsin?
As it happens, a number of other proteins can act as light receptors,
and they too provide some illuminating cases of convergence. Yet
the rhodopsin molecule seems to offer various advantages: as Russell
Fernald156 has remarked, in the context of vision although an opsin
‘is not the only way to detect light . . . it has proven irresistible for use
in eyes’.157 Rhodopsin is remarkably widespread, and apart from its
near-universal adoption in the various visual systems this molecule
has long been known to occur in the bacteria. These organisms exist
as two kingdoms, the Archaea and the Eubacteria, of which a typical
representative is E. coli. The most notable examples of rhodopsin are
in those Archaea referred to as halophiles. As their name indicates,
they live in salt-ponds, where their immense numbers frequently
colour the lagoons red or purple, which is the colour of the pigment
associated with their rhodopsin. The molecular architecture of this
so-called bacteriorhodopsin,158 with seven α-helices spanning a lipid
membrane, is the same as the molecule in our retina. So, too, is its
basic dependence on light, but in the bacterial variety the energy of
the Sun’s photons is used to drive a proton pump159 to transfer hy-
drogen ions (i.e. protons, H+ ) as the basis of the cell’s energy system,
specifically by the synthesis of ATP.
universal rhodopsin? 171
smelling convergence
Given that key molecules required for vision, such as rhodopsin and
the crystallin proteins, evolved in single-celled organisms this sug-
gests that given time182 and the adaptive value of light discrimination
then the evolution of the eye seems to be a near inevitability. And so
fascinating is the story of the evolution of the eye, not to mention our
particular dependence on vision, that we tend to forget other types of
sensory world, even when walking the dog at night with the air full of
bats: to us other senses, such as those of olfaction and echolocation, are
almost closed books. Yet the principle of evolutionary convergences
should encourage us to think, not only of recurrent re-emergences
of given senses, but also about deeper similarities of sensory input,
such as those of hearing, generation of electrical fields, and perhaps
even the sense of smell. In this last case there have been some curi-
ous experiments, such as those by the remarkable Victorian polymath
Francis Galton. Today he is probably best remembered for his inter-
est in hereditary principles and the related application of eugenics,183
the monstrous nature of which was articulated with characteristic
prescience by G. K. Chesterton.184 Galton’s autobiography185 is still
174 seeing convergence
figure 7.7 The star-nose mole, a typical mole in terms of its powerful
fore-limbs, but remarkable for its tentacular nose, with its nostrils
clearly visible. (Photograph courtesy of Professor K. C. Catania
(Vanderbilt University, Tennessee).)
figure 7.8 Details of the nose of the star-nosed mole. Above, detail of a
tentacle, studded with the sensory Eimer organs. Opposite, electron
micrograph of the nose. The analogue of the fovea is represented by the
two central lobes beneath the nostrils. (Photographs courtesy of
Professor K. C. Catania (Vanderbilt University, Tennessee).)
smelling convergence 177
relay neurons’. These writers are fully aware of the implications when
they continue, ‘The primary olfactory centers in the brains of verte-
brates and insects thus appear to share canonical cell arrangements
and common physiological properties . . . Furthermore, vertebrates
and insects show remarkable parallels in events underlying the de-
velopment of glomeruli . . . Do such commonalities suggest that the
glomerulus, as an olfactory functional unit . . . originated in a common
bilaterian ancestor [i.e. to insects and vertebrates]? Or, is common de-
sign and physiology the consequence of convergent evolution? Is there
a uniquely logical response to common selective pressures such that
to construct a glomerulus requires the same set of rules?’213
A definitive answer is not yet possible, but given the differences
in the molecular genetics of olfactory receptor coding, the evidence
points strongly to convergence. This is because the predecessors of
the vertebrates, the amphioxus animal (see Chapter 1), and the in-
sects, that is the aquatic crustaceans,214 do not possess such glomeruli,
which indicates that the method of effectively identical olfaction
arose independently.
Once again it seems that the options are limited. There may
be only a few ways to smell, and, as we have seen in the star-nosed
mole, if a nose is not used for olfaction it can end up as the sen-
sory equivalent of an eye. And again there may be deeper similar-
ities pointing towards the inevitability of evolutionary end results.
The processing of the olfactory signals, and especially the recogni-
tion of particular odours, involves a synchronized neuronal activity
that leads to an oscillatory firing of the neurons. The associated net-
works are not only similar in both the insects and the vertebrates,
but they in turn may also find parallels to what occurs in the process-
ing of visual stimuli in the mammals, at least.215 Further evidence for
more profound similarities between the processes of olfaction and vi-
sion also comes from an investigation of proteins known as arrestins
which, as their name suggests, are involved with the termination of a
physiological process, such as the quenching of phototransduction in
rhodopsin.216 Given that the proteins involved with olfaction have a
basic similarity to such visual proteins as rhodopsin,217 it would not
in principle be surprising to find arrestins also involved with the olfac-
tory transduction pathway. What, therefore, is the more remarkable
is evidence for a specific family of arrestins that is involved in both
visual (eye) and olfactory (antenna) transduction in insects.218 This is
the echo of convergence 181
the great traveller and naturalist Alexander von Humboldt, and sub-
sequently were engagingly described by Donald Griffin.228 Oilbirds
are nocturnal. They are also noisy animals, but can they echolocate
when travelling to or from their perches in the caves? Griffin listened
to them as they poured out of their cave at twilight, remarking, ‘Per-
haps the clicks were call notes, perhaps they were something analo-
gous to profanity, or perhaps they were symptoms of some other avian
emotion whose nature we could not guess.’229 His subsequent exper-
iments, however, showed that the ability to echolocate was genuine,
with the series of sharp clicks clearly audible to humans. Continu-
ing work230 has shown that the resolution of oilbirds’ echolocation
is rather crude, at least when it comes to avoiding discs deliberately
suspended in their flight path.
Interestingly, despite having well-developed eyes the oilbirds
appear to lack binocular vision,231 which is otherwise a general char-
acteristic of birds and convergent on other vertebrates (p. 162). In some
ways this makes the behaviour of the Asian swiftlets all the more ex-
traordinary, since their echolocatory abilities enable them to avoid
much smaller objects.232 Although their echolocation does not rival
that of bats,233 nevertheless in their natural habitat the pitch-dark
caves are filled with flying swiftlets, seldom if ever colliding and read-
ily finding their respective nests. Bats, dolphins, and even some birds,
therefore, have all entered a sensory world that is apparently almost
completely unknown to us (note 227). It is fascinating to speculate
what sort of echolocatory image these animals ‘see’. Although it is
now time to turn to the even stranger world of electrical perception, it
is worth remembering that as the commonalities of convergence con-
tinue to emerge so we may find that apparently alien perceptions, and
even mentalities, may not be as remote as has sometimes been imag-
ined. Even to enter the mind of a bat may not be as difficult as is some-
times supposed. We return to this topic in Chapter 9 (pp. 265–266).
shocking convergence
Of the sensory systems it is perhaps those involving the generation of
electrical fields that are the most remote from human experience. Per-
haps it is not surprising that it has been suggested that the exquisitely
sensitive nose of the star-nosed mole possesses an electrical sensi-
tivity, but this proposal is viewed with considerable caution.234 Even
so, such sensitivity is certainly possessed by some other mammals,
shocking convergence 183
12.0
Elect. sim.
Visual sim.
7.0
Position along fish
2.0
−3.0
0.0 60.0 120.0 180.0
Position in brain
figure 7.10 Seeing in the mormyrid fish, in terms of visual stimulation
(dots) and electrical stimulation (asterisks) with respect to the response
of a moving image or electrical stimulation along the body length versus
the corresponding response position in the brain, specifically tailward of
the anterior margin of the optic tectum. The overlap and parallelism of
either stimulation suggests that the sensory modalities are in one way
equivalent. (Redrawn from fig. 7A of W. Heiligenberg and J. Bastian
(1984). The electric sense of weakly electric fish. Annual Review of
Physiology, vol. 46, pp. 561–83, 1984. With permission, from Annual
Review of Physiology, vol. 46, c 1984 by Annual Reviews, www.
annualreviews.org, and the authors)
hearing convergence
Hearing, of course, depends on the transmission of vibrations, and
their transduction into electrical signals that in ways analogous to
sight and smell are interpreted as sound. For most of us hearing is
almost as important as sight, and since the invasion of land by the
tetrapod vertebrates, effectively beginning with an amphibian-like
creature,288 this sensory modality to detect and track airborne sounds
has been extensively developed.289 Yet the evolutionary evidence sug-
gests that the evolution of the tetrapod ear, with its tympanic mem-
brane and associated features, such as pressure-relief mechanisms
and differential ossification to provide an otic capsule that helps to
refine the auditory mechanism, has evolved independently several
times among the vertebrates.290 More specific convergences are also
found. For example, in the vertebrates impinging sound waves are in-
geniously amplified via the hairs located within the spiral-shaped part
of the inner ear known as the cochlea.291 This structure contains spe-
cialized hair cells that are involved with auditory perception. While
the differences between the arrangement found in birds as against
mammals have long been appreciated, it is also evident that there are
important convergences.292 So, too, within the mammals themselves
there are some interesting examples of convergence, perhaps most
notably among the many subterranean species that, as already noted
(pp. 139–141), provide many other insights into convergence. In their
fossorial environment the sensitivities of hearing, not surprisingly, are
shifted towards the lower sound frequencies. Even so, vocalizations
and hearing carry only for about five metres.293 Across longer dis-
tances communication is by seismic pulses, e.g. head-banging or foot-
drumming, and does not appear to utilize the ears.294 The auditory
systems of the underground mammals nevertheless show some strik-
ing convergences linked to the shared mode of life. Unsurprisingly, the
hearing convergence 191
external ear lobes (or pinnae) are greatly reduced, if not absent. Within
the middle ear there are a number of parallel changes to meet the need
for detecting low-frequency sounds; far from this part of the ear being
vestigial it is actually highly adapted.295 So, too, within the inner ear
there are further convergences, such as those concerning the arrange-
ment of the semicircular canals that probably play a significant role
in navigation through the maze-like world of these mammals.296
Other animals hear, but in groups such as the insects this has
long been assumed to be a passive process, lacking the sophisti-
cated physiological features found in mammals, in which acuity of
hearing is sensitive to the animal’s metabolism and also shows a
feature known as autonomous vibration, which is important in the
process of sound amplification. This now appears to be incorrect. In
such dipteran insects as the mosquito the equivalent of the ear is a
complex antennal structure, including the so-called Johnston’s organ.
This structure is richly endowed with nerve cells, is correspondingly
very sensitive to sounds,297 and now it transpires that the hearing
of mosquitoes is much more similar to that of mammals than was
realized. As Martin Göpfert and Daniel Robert298 remark,
recurrent protein designs, but also the way in which meaning is con-
veyed and recognized. Human speech, and thus hearing, is well known
for what is referred to as ‘categorical perception’. That is, despite a con-
tinuum of sound we divide the signal into discrete categories. So, too,
with other vertebrates, such as birds,321 and also insects.322 As Robert
Wyttenbach and his colleagues remark, ‘categorical perception may
be a ubiquitous feature of perceptual systems in many animals, in-
vertebrate as well as vertebrate.’323 Star-nosed moles and stridulating
crickets, echolocating bats, and electric mormyrids are all reminders,
not only of a rich sensory universe, but also of one in which emerging
mentalities may find fertile ground for evolutionary innovations but
ultimately shared experience.
thinking convergence?
When we reconsider this range of animals, embedded in their respec-
tive environments of complex sensory perceptions, it seems safe to
conclude that, despite what to us are largely alien means of percep-
tion, the many analogies that exist with our sense of vision are a pow-
erful argument for the importance of convergence in evolution. But
is this so important? At one level the conclusion might seem rather
trivial. After all, it only reminds us that the world is subject to con-
straints; nervous systems interpret the sensory input, be they from
noses, eyes, ears, or electric organs, and they all have a fundamen-
tal similarity of operation. Hence the trajectories towards any style
of perception in any possible evolutionary history are indeed greatly
restricted. Convergences are inevitable, but again, so what?
There is, however, something else worth knowing. Let us re-
turn to the mormyrid fish, but this time to look at their brain.324 Not
only does it have a strange, almost crystalline, internal structure, but
also a well-developed series of lobes (Fig. 7.11). Most remarkable in
the latter context is the enormous enlargement of the cerebellum (no-
tably the region known as the valvula cerebelli), although a number of
the other regions (e.g. the acoustico-lateral area, mesencephalon, and
corpus cerebelli) also contribute to its extraordinary size. Consider for
example the remarks by R. Nieuwenhuys and C. Nicholson when they
write, ‘Opened the skull of a mormyrid fish reveals, however, a totally
different picture [from the standard teleost brain, say of a trout]. It is
immediately apparent that the brain is of a relatively enormous size
and that none of the structures mentioned above [in the basic brain]
thinking convergence? 195
C3
C4 Va
CL
ELL
C2 C1
Cr TL
can be readily seen.’325 In Fig. 7.11, note, in particular, how the cerebel-
lum ‘flows’ over much of the rest of the brain, in a manner reminiscent
of the massive neocortical expansion of the human cerebral lobes. Not
only are these lobes enormously enlarged, but in addition to this hy-
pertrophy the total area of the brain is further increased by both a series
of deep folds and a series of fine ridges. It is all the more intriguing to
note that in relation to its body size the mormyrid brain is compara-
ble to the disproportionately enormous brain within our skulls. Not
only that, but more than half the consumption of body oxygen in the
mormyrid is accounted for by the brain, a figure three times greater
than for humans.326 And this is hardly surprising; as already noted,
these fish live in a rich electrical environment, requiring sophisticated
neural processing involving recognition of other fish and navigation in
near-darkness through a cluttered and potentially lethal environment.
And the gymnotids, with their convergent electrical system; what of
196 seeing convergence
I have just woken from a hideous nightmare, the sort of dream that
haunts you for days afterwards. I have visited, or been sent to, a terri-
ble world, and to make things worse it had strange parallels to ours,
only it was alien and mechanical. I am standing on a wide highway,
with robot-like workers rushing in either direction. On either side of
this stream miniature versions scurry everywhere, patrolling the mar-
gins, ceaselessly on guard. Such is the flow of traffic that the earth
has long since been beaten flat; not a shred of vegetation obstructs
the road. In one direction the army of helots marches empty-handed,
but towards a truly immense forest which I can see only dimly as
there is something not quite right with my vision. My sense of smell
is, however, overwhelmingly acute, and wave after wave of olfactory
messages urge me to obey the twin commands of unceasing work and
obedience. Still looking towards the distant forest, I see that from
this direction the army returns, each worker scurrying forward with
a parcel of food. New olfactory orders are issued, and I am impelled
to follow the returning stream. After walking for hours I am driven
into a set of huge subterranean chambers. Here the activity is at a
frenzy, yet there is also an underlying order. My senses reel: from the
ceilings hang huge clumps of what look like some sort of fungus, but
it is being tended with the utmost care and attention. Now I can see
workers busy with weeding; others seem to be applying herbicides,
and yet more are either collecting pieces of the fungus or extending
the zones of cultivation. Yet for all its strangeness this world is a lit-
tle too familiar for comfort. The workers rushing past me are indeed
literally bug-eyed monsters, sinister antennae constantly in motion,
with hardened carapaces, and in some cases carrying miniature ver-
sions of themselves. But it is also clearly an organized society, a vast
underground city entirely dependent for its well-being on the cease-
lessly maintained fungus farms. As I awake from this dry and soulless
world, I realize suddenly that I have not been among the extraterres-
trials, but have been mingling with the leaf-cutting ants who quite
independently of humans have invented agriculture.
198 alien convergences?
figure 8.1 Attine ants at work. Left: with mandibles poised above a
leaf. Right: with a minima. (Photographs courtesy of Cameron Currie,
University of Kansas, Lawrence.)
processing the leaves within the nest.7 Travel is often via well-defined
and more-or-less permanent paths,8 which may stretch for consider-
able distances, sometimes 100 metres. On the main thoroughfares the
ground may be cleared to form a smooth highway that in turn maxi-
mizes walking speeds. In these social insects three distinct castes are
recognized, and in addition a miniaturized variety (the minims) may
also occur. Some of these minims spend time working in the gardens,
as well as riding on the larger ants, where they engage in grooming
and cleaning activities. Another important role, only recently appre-
ciated, is to patrol the edges of the trails along which the foragers
march, on the lookout for danger and when appropriate issuing an
alarm.9 Yet others ‘hitch-hike’ on the leaf fragments as they are being
carried back to the nest, in part probably to defend the leaf-carriers
from attack by parasitoid flies (known as phorids) and possibly also
to begin the preparation of the leaf prior to its arrival at the nest.10 In
the nest itself, the soldier caste is vigorous in defence.
The collected leaves are not eaten directly11 but are used to pro-
vide a mulch for fungus gardens that are located within the nest. The
leaves, of course, are fresh and the initial preparation, which as al-
ready noted may start during transport, includes a stripping away of
the outer waxy layer. This process, achieved by a sort of licking, also
appears to inhibit the activity of associated microorganisms, the con-
trol of which is a central necessity to the health of the fungus farm.
Thereafter the leaves are shredded and pulped, and at this stage are
ready for fungal innoculation.12 The saprophytic activities of the fungi
break down the plant material, especially the resistant cellulose, and
so provide an edible crop for the ants.13 The gardens are subject to
careful and ceaseless maintenance. Weeding,14 especially of infected
areas, is undertaken principally by tiny ants (the minims). In weed-
ing several minima typically loosen the offending item before it is
removed by larger ants. In addition to weeding, the minima also en-
gage in grooming, that is the removal of alien spores. If necessary the
ants will also transfer the fungi to parts of the nest with more suitable
humidity15 and temperature.16 In addition to weeding there is also the
activity of pruning, again to encourage the harvest.17 The application
of fertilizers is in the form of a manure, an excrement rich in nitrogen
as well as an enzyme supplement.18 The harvest is ready and, in the
more advanced types of cultivation, cropping involves the cutting off
200 alien convergences?
of the knob-like ends of the fungus, which are rich in protein, sugars,
and other compounds.19
As on our own farms there is, however, a recurrent danger of
invasion by pathogens. For the ants’ fungal gardens the principal risk
comes from a virulent parasite, also a fungus, Escovopsis. If it is not
controlled, the garden is soon converted into a mouldering and black-
ened ruin.20 How do the ants avert disaster? They apply the equiva-
lent of a herbicide, specifically in the form of an antibiotic.21 This is
derived from streptomycetean bacteria, the filaments of which grow
attached to the bodies of the ants.22 In addition to these fungicides
it is likely that other chemicals, including again antibiotics, secreted
by the ants themselves, also help to inhibit the growth of unwanted
bacteria and fungi.23 Both provide defences against infestation, but in-
terestingly the ants show a trade-off whereby newly imported leaves
are protected by the ants (mostly minims) using their own secretions.
This helps to provide an all-round microbial defence. However, in the
older parts of the fungus garden, where the fungal biomass is higher
and presumably more vulnerable to attack by the parasitic Escovopsis,
the larger ants responsible for this area of maintenance rely on the
bacterial defences.24 Nor are these the only risks faced by the ant-
gardeners: on occasion a specialized predator aggressively sweeps in,
expels the attine ants, and usurps the garden.25 These so-called ‘agro-
predators’ are a particular species of myrmicine ant, unrelated to the
leaf-cutters and related attine ants. In addition to usurping the gardens
these myrmicines have been observed to place their larvae adjacent to
those abandoned by the vanquished attines, where most probably the
latter larvae act as a convenient source of protein. Yet more terrible
fates await other attine nests when their citadel falls, after stiff resis-
tance and appalling casualties on both sides, to army ants. Here part of
the resistance entails plugging nest entrances and building barricades
with leaf fragments.26
military convergence
In parentheses, one should note that the army-ant syndrome has
evolved independently several times.27 This particular example of
convergence is important for two reasons. The first is simply
connected to the intrinsic fascination of a sophisticated biological
organization, replete with militaristic metaphors and an associated
military convergence 201
figure 8.2 The bivouac of the army ant Eciton. (Photograph courtesy of
David Kistner, California State University, Chico.)
Not only is this true for the army ants, but study of other social
insects may reveal other interesting evolutionary parallels. Consider,
for example, the advanced eusocial bees,36 with their familiar division
of labour, notably the queen and pollen-gathering workers. These an-
imals have fascinated humans for millennia. In England it is still the
custom, when the beekeeper has died, for a friend to go to the hive and
tell the news to his or her bees. In a different way, in past centuries the
industry and organization of the hive invited obvious political analo-
gies. Now this fascination extends to evolution with the realization
that bees have cognitive capabilities and a plasticity of behaviours
that otherwise are known only in the vertebrates,37 and, no less sur-
prisingly, other features such as exhibiting sleep-like states.38 Or is it
surprising? Sleep may have several functions, but one widely agreed
purpose is the need to consolidate memories.39
In any event, the complexity of bees not only has some intrigu-
ing parallels to vertebrate mental processes, but has been arrived at
military convergence 203
‘Big, fierce societies’46 may lead not only to the emergence of col-
lective intelligences but to ones that are, from our point of view, so
alien as to be useful in envisaging extraterrestrial societies. In this
context some remarks by Nigel Franks, a leading specialist on army
ants, are intriguing, if also in places self-confessedly speculative. In
reviewing the extraordinary social structure of these insects he ob-
serves how it is among the army ant colonies ‘we see the emergence
of flexible problem solving far exceeding the capacity of the indi-
vidual’, a capacity that finds no rival in other animals, apart from
humans. This, as Franks stresses, presupposes effective communica-
tion, so that ‘intelligence, natural or artificial, is an emergent property
of collective communication . . . This is exactly what happens when
army ants pass information from individual to individual through the
“writing” and “reading” of symbols, often in the form of chemical
messengers or trail pheromones, which act as stimuli for changing
behavior patterns.’ So it is that we can see a transformation of a sys-
tem from being hard-wired to flexible via ‘increasingly sophisticated
patterns of communication’.47 Such a pheromone-based society48 may
204 alien convergences?
World army ants, natural selection may have had to select for a
surprisingly small and simple set of rules to generate swarm-
raiding patterns. Thus self-organization theory may help to
explain why we observe such a high level of convergent evolution
in certain biological structures.50
convergent complexities
The behaviour of complex social insect societies, and specifically the
army ants, is more than a digression. This is because the emergence
of such biological complexity may be much more constrained than is
sometimes imagined.51 At the least it is a reminder that carnivorous
species can be more successful, at least in terms of colony size, than
the farming ants (and, as we shall see below, termites). Success, as
even the most jaded (if not jealous) scientist well knows, is relative.
Size, we are reassured from the most reliable sources, is not all. In
their relative adaptive contexts social wasps and bees have taken over
their respective worlds. So, too, the attine ants have evolved a remark-
able system of fungal cultivation. In each of these examples we have
evidence of extensive appropriation of resources, capable of maintain-
ing large and complex societies. Life beyond these ‘cities’ and ‘armies’
remains, of course, diverse and marvellous: the biological world is by
no means reduced to a monochrome. Nevertheless, the repeated rise
of such societies, and at least evidence of the displacement and ulti-
mate extinction of less successful equivalents, suggests that such an
arrangement is a biological inevitability.
So, too, in any specific case if a group ‘decides’ to adopt a partic-
ular strategy, say agriculture, then the routes to success will be very
limited. It is time, therefore, to return to the parallels between ant
and human farming, and thereby consider some implications of such
a commonality. As in our mushroom farms, the activities are carried
out underground, since, unlike plant crops, the fungi have no need
for sunlight. The farms are located in elaborate nests, equipped with
ventilation shafts52 and in certain species also dump-pits – some large
enough to house a man53 – which are used for waste disposal (Fig. 8.3).
Just as in human societies, control of the waste is very important for
the health of both the colony and the fungal colonies, and it now
appears that the risky business of waste management54 may be ‘allo-
cated’ to the older workers, nearing the ends of their lives and less valu-
able to the colony. It seems that once assigned to dump management55
206 alien convergences?
figure 8.3 The fungus farm of the attine ants, with large central
chamber containing pendant clumps of the fungus and one worker (!)
Note the tunnel system leading to the outside world, and the capacious
dump-chambers. (Reproduced from fig. 29 of Jonkman (1980; citation is
in note 53), with permission of Blackwell Wissenschafts Verlag GmbH
and the Jonkman family.)
colony size. In the process a few species have developed some of the
largest ant colonies known,’59 with populations estimated to reach
at least seven million,60 and typically exceeded only by the aggres-
sive army ants (p. 201). Gigantic populations dependent on highly
organized societies: does it sound familiar? And, as with the eusocial
bees, there may even be lessons for us. The fungal gardens are usually
monocultures. But as humans know (or should know), monocultures
have their risks, being notoriously liable to invasion by viruses, fungi,
and other pests. The use of the streptomycene antibiotics (note 22)
has, of course, a direct parallel in human medicine. What seems quite
remarkable is that the resistance conferred by the antibiotics seems
to have been maintained by these ants for literally millions of years,
in comparison to our experience where in only a few decades we have
seen the seemingly inexorable rise of ‘superbugs’, resistant to nearly
all treatments. In reality the system of ant farming and its crop protec-
tion is presumably much more dynamic. It appears that the more vir-
ulent strains of pathogenic fungi occur in the more advanced species
of attine ants, which in turn are more reliant on monocultures. It is
hardly surprising that there is evidence for exchange (and stealing) of
fungal cultures between colonies.61
The agricultural activities of the attine ants are surely one acme
of arthropod organization, and further parallels with human agricul-
ture may well emerge. As a leading worker, Ulrich Mueller, has re-
marked: ‘The more I study [the fungal gardens] the more analogies
I find between human agriculture and ant agriculture.’62 Given the
nutritional value of fungi and the ease of propagation, it is not so sur-
prising that other insects have also learnt the art of agriculture. Thus
the ambrosia beetles, a type of weevil, have evolved a mutualistic re-
lationship with a group of ascomycetes known as the ophiostomatoid
fungi.63 The general arrangement is certainly rather different from
that of the attine ants because these beetles bore into tree trunks,
so producing a complex series of galleries. The beetles are responsible
for introducing the fungi. These are carried in containers (mycangia)64
that consist of cuticular pockets with associated secretory glands that
evidently ‘control the growth and form’ of the fungi.65 The mycangia
share, therefore, a basic function, but their form is extremely varied,
and in different species they occur on many parts of the carapace.
As ever in evolution, ‘needs must’: who cares whether the container
(in this case the fungal-ferrying mycangia) comes from, so long as
it works? So far as beetle and fungus are concerned, both sides are
208 alien convergences?
Evidently this agriculture is different from that of the attine ants, just
as human agricultures vary.
Other convergences also emerge. Communication among ants
is famous for its pheromone-based system, but in the termites seis-
mic communication is achieved in the soldier caste by drumming
the head against the substrate,78 a method also used by subterranean
mammals (Chapter 6, p. 141). Seismic communication is also used by
the leaf-cutter ants.79 In these ants, although the sound is produced as
a stridulation, it is transmitted through the ground. Typically stridu-
lations are produced only when the individual attine ant is immo-
bilized, such as occurs by collapse of part of the earthworks. These
210 alien convergences?
cries of distress elicit rapid digging by other workers, who can detect
sounds through 5 cm of earth and will begin rescue work if the thick-
ness is no more than 3 cm. In the termites this alarm reaction can
evidently be triggered either by air currents or vibrations. The more
advanced fungus-growing termites are particularly sensitive in this
respect. Rather remarkably, the signal can be propagated by chains
of soldiers, each re-amplifying the signal in a way analogous to the
now-redundant methods of human communication using smoke and
drums,80 as well as the periodic re-amplifications observed in the
transmission of signals along the nervous system.
Although they are in certain respects less sophisticated, it is ap-
propriate to mention in passing the so-called ant-gardens, which are
arboreal earthen structures known as ‘cartons’. In this arrangement
certain species of epiphytic plant are encouraged to grow on the nests,
from seeds that are collected by the ants and planted in the nest wall. In
due course these plants germinate, grow (and thereby provide a source
of extra-floral nectar), extend roots that probably help to strengthen
the nest, eventually flower, and so produce seeds, the fruit of which
is eaten before they are planted . . . and so the cycle continues.81 In
a few instances fungi are employed in the ‘cartons’, probably to help
bind the structure and possibly also to release antibacterial chemicals.
Interestingly, in some cases the fungus is effectively a monoculture,
apparently maintained by weeding and feeding. So far as can be told,
however, the fungal products themselves are not directly cropped.82
Other activities of these garden ants include the pruning of surround-
ing vegetation, probably to create a ‘fire zone’ to reduce the risk of in-
vasion by other ants,83 the collection of vertebrate faeces, presumably
as fertilizer, and perhaps the choice of plants that, like those cartons
with fungi, release chemicals that help to keep pathogens at bay.84
This section on the ants (and termites) has included more than
its fair share of digressions, but I hope that the common thread of ex-
ploring convergences still runs through the narrative. Consider again
the army ants: living in the midst of their mobile and aggressive col-
umn has its self-evident risks, yet various species have managed to
insinuate themselves into the ants’ social system. Most striking in
this instance are probably the various staphylinid beetles. These have
effectively transformed their bodies into an ant shape that readily de-
ceives the actual ants.85 Hiding yourself in an aggressive raiding col-
umn may yield various benefits, not least an uncontested share of the
convergent complexities 211
booty and also some protection from predators. Typically the beetles
travel in the centre of the column, and are not found in the vanguard.
In times of excitement, such as during an episode of emigration, the
beetles may ride on the ants themselves and despite continuous an-
tennal interrogation never seem to be recognized as interlopers. The
way in which these beetles have transformed themselves into ant-
mimics is very striking (Fig. 8.4), and the selective pressure to sur-
vive in a jostling mass of aggressive workers can explain how such
a transformation in the staphylinids has occurred independently on
multiple occasions.86 In at least one instance the convergence extends
to a colour matching, whereby a geographical variation in the ant col-
oration is matched by the beetle.87 As David Kistner (Fig. 8.5) points
out, given that the ants are effectively blind, this mimicry supports
the idea that it serves to dupe ‘educable predators which sit by the
raiding columns to pick up insects which are stirred up by the raid’.88
Nor is this the only example of a convergence between a mimic and
an army ant. A common association is the attachment of mites to
the exterior of insects (and other animals such as birds and mammals,
clinging respectively to feathers and hair; pass me the nit comb), but
in the case of the mite Planodiscus ‘the sculpture of the mite and
212 alien convergences?
figure 8.5 David Kistner and his wife in the field in Ecuador, collecting
staphylinid beetles and army ants. (Photograph courtesy of David
Kistner, California State University, Chico.)
the ant’s leg is nearly identical. Also the arrangement and number of
setae on the mite approximates the arrangement and number of setae
on the leg. Thus when the ant grooms its leg, the tactile stimulation
[as it passes over the mite] will be similar to that of the leg itself.’89
In Chapter 6 (pp. 116–117) I briefly introduced the tent-building
capacities of the aptly named weaver ants. Here, too, there are some
striking cases of mimicry, which here involve weaver ants and a crab
spider, Amyciaea forticeps.90 As it happens, the weaver ant in ques-
tion, found in India and known as the Indian Red Ant (Oecophylla
smaragdina), is also associated with another spider (Myrmarachne
plataleoides) that in turn is ‘a perfect mimic of the red ant; so per-
fect is this mimicry that even experienced biologists may pass it by
as an ant, in the field.’91 Despite its close association with the Indian
Red Ants, which can be very aggressive, M. plataleoides takes good
care to avoid the ants. Possibly it employs its mimicry to fool other
convergent complexities 213
are these mimicries and their various manifestations,96 that for the
purposes of this book they can, I hope, largely be taken for granted.97
The complexity of both ant and termite colonies, not to mention their
various guests and symbionts, also provide a rich field within the topic
of convergence, and one that can be analysed at several levels. Pass-
ing comment has already been made on such built structures as trails
and tunnels, farms, and cartons, and it is clear that much remains
to be discovered about these various constructions in an adaptive
context.98
These insects, moreover, are by no means the only arthro-
pods to have evolved constructional abilities. Take, for example, the
beach-dwelling orypodid crabs. These crustaceans are highly territo-
rial and protect their domains from intrusion by a variety of complex
behaviours that include the building of mud fences and also the plug-
ging of neighbouring burrows. Sometimes the occupant is evicted, but
in other cases it is entombed. As might be expected, at least some of
these behavioural repertoires are convergently acquired within this
group.99 Nor is this the only example of such sophistication of be-
haviour. The fiddler crab is famous for its signalling, achieved by
movement of its hypertrophied claw. It now transpires that the sig-
nalling for mates, in a process known as ‘lekking’ in which numer-
ous associated males signal simultaneously to choosy females (a well-
known characteristic of some birds), also occurs in these crabs.100
first pumped to the lung/gill in order to collect the oxygen (and dis-
pose of carbon dioxide). The blood is then returned to a second set of
chambers in the heart where it is dispatched at full force into these
elastic arteries. Even so, despite the shared principle there are signif-
icant differences. The branchial heart in cephalopods, which as the
name indicates is responsible for feeding blood to the gills, is sepa-
rate from the main pump. Furthermore, it is not very muscular, and
probably has additional excretory functions.116 The main systematic
heart is powerful and muscular, but its structure only approximates
to the vertebrate arrangement.117
Despite their manifest differences, the convergences between
the cephalopods and vertebrates have attracted the attention of many
biologists. Of greatest significance surely are those that pertain to the
camera-like eye (Chapter 7) and brain (note 108). Others are probably
less significant, but still intriguing. Earlier, in discussing the hypo-
thetical Fortean bladders I remarked on the convergence between the
relatively familiar fish swim-bladder and that of an octopus (note 35,
Chapter 6). Another interesting convergence with the vertebrates is
the development of a cartilage-like tissue in the head.118 In fact, the
roster of convergences is still not complete. Consider, for example,
that part of the cephalopod sensory system associated with the skin.
This is strongly analogous to the lateral-line system found in the fish
and aquatic amphibians,119 and it too is sensitive to pressure waves
travelling through the water.120
Having reviewed earlier (Chapter 7) not only convergences in
particular sensory systems but also possible underlying commonali-
ties (which are equally important), it is not surprising that, at least
so far as the fish are concerned, there is evidence that the lateral line
can help the animal to form a ‘hydrodynamic image’.121 What sort
of ‘map’ or ‘image’ this might form in the brain is still a matter for
speculation. It is likely, however, that the input from the lateral line
produces a ‘pressure world’, analogous both to the ‘electrical world’
of the mormyrids and other electrosensitive fish and to one that is
integrated with other sensory inputs, such as vision.
Self-evidently, as an aquatic adaptation the lateral line of the
fish (and amphibians) was lost as the tetrapods clambered on to land.
In the case of the manatees (or dugongs), which are secondarily aquatic
mammals, the arrangement and anatomy of the post-cranial hairs are
something of an evolutionary novelty. Their sensitivity to changes
hearts and minds 217
honorary mammals
So building complex circulatory systems, peering at the world through
a camera-eye, and employing intelligence with a large brain have all
evolved convergently. We are, however, in pursuit of the humanoid,
and I shall assume that the galactic equivalent is in some sense
mammal-like. This may seem too bold a claim, but let us see. So far
as the Earth is concerned, there is a simple natural experiment. What
we need to do is find a landmass which the mammals have failed to
colonize. There is an excellent example, and it is called New Zealand.
Indeed, Jared Diamond124 went so far as to say ‘New Zealand is as close
as we will get to the opportunity to study life on another planet.’125
For at least 85 million years126 these islands have remained isolated in
the Pacific Ocean, too remote to be colonized by any of the terrestrial
mammals, other than by the bats and much later the boat-travelling
Polynesians who arrived about ad 1000. New Zealand, however, had
plenty of other inhabitants. Particularly extraordinary are the giant
wingless crickets, known as wetas, relatives of the grasshopper and lo-
custs. These are ecologically convergent on mice and rats, ‘resembling
rodents not only in their biomass, but also in nocturnal foraging and
diets, use of diurnal shelters, polygamy and even their droppings’,127
and when surprised leaping across the forest floor.128
Nor are these the only animals in New Zealand to approach
mousedom. Diamond remarks that the ‘Stephens Island wren . . .
was . . . the world’s only known flightless songbird and functioned
as an avian mouse.’129 So, too, one of the endemic bats (Mystacina)
is also convergent on a mouse-like habit, being partially terrestrial
and when walking on the ground folding its wings to protect the del-
icate membranes.130 Presumably like the bats the ancestors of these
birds had originally flown there, but perhaps because of the absence
of other ground-dwelling competitors many of them became flight-
less. These include an extraordinary nocturnal parrot, known as the
kakapo, which grows as big as a turkey.131 The most famous are the
kiwi and the much larger moa.132 These birds are not closely re-
lated and, arrived at flightlessness convergently.133 The moas have
vanished, and their extinction was almost certainly by way of the
stew-pots, roasts, and fricassees of the Maoris.134 The much smaller
kiwis, however, avoided the category of a walking larder. If, as for
the moa, we had only the bones, it is unlikely that we would ever
have realized that in a land without mammals, the kiwi (Fig. 8.7)
honorary mammals 219
figure 8.7 The kiwi, a flightless bird, emblem of New Zealand, but
also an ‘honorary mammal’. (Reproduced from the figure on p. 103 of
Calder (1978; citation is in note 135), with the permission of the artist,
Alan D. Iselin.)
When one adds to this list [that is reproduction] the kiwi’s burrow
habitat, its furlike body feathers and its nocturnal foraging, highly
dependent on its sense of smell, the evidence for convergence
[with mammals] seems overpowering. Only half jokingly I would
add to the list the kiwi’s aggressive behavior . . . When I intruded
on his domain at night, [the male kiwi] would run up to me
snarling like a fighting cat . . . and drive his claws repeatedly into
my ankles until I went away. For this behavior and the many other
reasons [given] . . . I award this remarkable bird the status of an
honorary mammal.140
the body, the movement of red muscles towards the interior of the
animal, combined with the body becoming larger and thicker, and a
style of locomotion known as thunniform, in which swimming is
achieved by oscillation of the tail rather than sinuous deformation
of the entire body. Yet this complex arrangement was convergently
arrived at in the lamnid159 and alopiid sharks, where again it prob-
ably evolved independently in each group.160 There are, moreover,
more specific convergences161 such as the ‘Striking parallels in both
structure and function [that] exist between the shark orbital rete [a
fine network of blood vessels] and the mammalian carotid rete which
serves as a brain cooling system in mammals’.162
The adoption of this type of endothermy is significant because it
evidently allowed an expansion of a habitable zone, and in these fish it
made possible the invasion of a vast new realm, specifically the cooler
(and deeper) parts of the ocean. As Barbara Block and her co-workers
note, the multiple origins of endothermy indicate ‘Strong selection
for this energetically costly metabolic strategy’.163 In other words, en-
dothermy is expensive, but well worth the cost by being highly adap-
tive and accompanied by success. Costs, as ever, have risks, and in
the context of endothermy there is another interesting physiological
convergence. This involves a pathological condition known as ma-
lignant hyperthermia, in which the muscles produce excessive heat
that if unchecked leads to severe tissue damage and death. In mam-
mals it has a genetic basis, and may manifest itself in anaesthetized
humans undergoing surgery, as well as in genetically disposed pigs
that panic in the slaughterhouse.164 A strikingly similar syndrome is
found in highly stressed tuna, especially those caught on a hook and
line. This leads to so-called ‘tuna burn’, badly damaged musculature
and subsequent rejection by the fastidious Sashimi enthusiast.165
What then is the significance of the convergent evolution of
endothermy in the birds and mammals? C. G. Farmer has argued that
among the welter of possibilities the key factor is parental care.166 Of
central importance is the need for sustained exertion, to enable the
parent(s) to collect sufficient food not only to maintain their ravenous
fledglings or litter, but also for them to grow as quickly as possible and
thereby decrease their vulnerability. Even in those birds and mammals
that characteristically save energy by entering a state of torpor and
letting their body temperature decline, incubating birds and pregnant
mammals typically retain a higher body temperature. Farmer suggests
warming to, singing of, chewing convergence 225
that the original trigger for bird and mammal warm-bloodedness was
connected to reproduction and the increased production of hormones,
e.g. from the thyroid, which in turn are also important determinants
of metabolic rates. She continues by noting that
Thus, as we saw earlier, not only are there good arguments that aliens
would see and smell using very similar proteins to those we use, but
their electrical conductivity would again converge towards the same
solution.
quite clearly has been co-opted in the animals for neural functions. We
know this also because molecules characteristic of the process of ner-
vous transmission and activity are found in single-celled protistans,
notably the ciliates.43 In these tiny organisms there are no nerves,
let alone brains; so what are these molecules employed for? Ciliates
show a sexual process known as conjugation in which individual cells
must first confirm their compatibility (recognition) before adhering in
order to allow exchange of genetic material. All this depends on the
molecule acetylcholine and a number of other key receptors.
The molecular architecture of the nervous system is complex
in other ways. For example, certain hormones, the neuropeptides, are
also important. At first sight it is quite surprising that hormones such
as corticotropin, which is important in the pituitary gland, as well as
β-endorphin-like molecules and dopamine, have also been found in
the ciliates.44 Given that these organisms lack any sort of nervous
system, the function of these neuropeptides is somewhat enigmatic.
Nevertheless in their own way the ciliates are sophisticated organ-
isms and use of messenger molecules is to be expected.45 George
Mackie46 has aptly referred to these molecules occurring in protis-
tans as ‘prophetic’, and they underline the likelihood of more complex
structures, say a brain, emerging from the unicellular substrate.
Other types of complexity in both bacteria and various eu-
karyotic microbes have been comparatively well known for many
years, not least the remarkable propensity for certain bacteria
(the myxobacteria) and eukaryotic slime moulds (Dictyostelium) to
aggregate into quasi-multicellular organisms, some of which display
a mobile slug-like behaviour. There is, however, newly emerging
information, across a wide front of enquiry, that is demonstrating
hitherto unappreciated levels of complexity that correspond in a num-
ber of interesting ways to the social behaviour of animals and higher
organisms.47 Thus, aspects of sociality such as foraging and coop-
erative hunting, specialized dispersal forms, genetic altruism, and
(perhaps most interestingly) communication, using various chemi-
cal signals,48 have now been identified. As Bernard Crespi remarks,
‘The social phenomena uncovered so far allow the first direct compar-
isons between microorganisms and macroorganisms [and in the text
he lists seven social attributes], which reveal convergences in behav-
ior that are clearly suggestive of adaptation.’49 Not only that but, as
pointed out by various authors,50 the social interactions, synchronized
genes and networks 237
the appendages, and accordingly when there was a need for improved
sensory perception so parts of the body protruded to extend the spa-
tial range of the sensory cells. Only later were such outgrowths on
occasion employed for such purposes as locomotion. The widespread
expression of the gene distal-less is, therefore, effectively a reflec-
tion of the recurrent and independent evolution of such limbs: in
a sense distal-less hitchhikes as a sensory protrusion and is subse-
quently transformed to allow an additional function such as a leg or
an antenna.79 So limbs, like eyes, may be underpinned by a similar
genetic architecture, but the end-product is still convergent. Nowhere
may this principle be more important than in the origin of advanced
nervous systems and the role of a gene known as otx (the vertebrate
homologue of the otd (orthodenticle) gene found in the fruit-fly).80 In
vertebrates otx plays an important role in the early stages of brain de-
velopment. So, too, does otx in insects, but the expression patterns are
not identical. Most probably the gene is conserved, but echoing Nagy
the researchers Nic Williams and Peter Holland81 also remark that
while conservation is the most plausible explanation, the alternative
of ‘convergent evolution cannot be ruled out by current molecular
evidence’.82
some rather surprising directions. To get to his post at the signal box
Mr Wide travelled on a special trolley, and Jack’s job was to put the
vehicle on the rails and push Mr Wide to work (Fig. 9.1). On the down-
hill sections of the track both human and baboon enjoyed the ride.
Nor was the trolley Jack’s only duty. Other responsibilities included
pumping and carrying water, gardening, and locking doors and, when
necessary, handing over a key to passing train drivers who needed
to unlock the points giving access to the coal yard. On one occasion,
when Mr Wide had injured his arm in a fall, Jack, who had already been
trained to work the levers for the signals, following commands from
his human friend, took over the actual signalling. As Euan Nisbet
continues, on the basis of reliable witnesses: ‘Jack knew every one
of the various signals and which lever to pull – not unnaturally the
railway passengers objected initially but the baboon never failed dur-
ing his many years of work.’ It is scarcely surprising to learn that
the emotional bond between ape and man was very close, and found
expression by mutual grooming. On one occasion offensive remarks
made to Mr Wide by another railwayman led to Jack jostling him off
the platform. One wonders what Jack would have made of the much-
delayed 08.06. After nine years of service, Jack died of tuberculosis.
Mr Wide was broken-hearted.
This story, which is certainly true, and strangely moving, is
meant to be more than a diversion, because in its own way it is another
example of evolutionary inherency. So we return to the question of the
prevalence, or otherwise, of humanoids. With so many of the building
blocks of life in place, even at the time of the Cambrian ‘explosion’
more than half-a-billion years ago, when does the merely likely be-
come the almost inevitable? Here, in our tracking of the humanoid,
let us grant, for the sake of the argument, that we have organisms that
are able to move freely, have well-developed sense-organs and a ner-
vous system capable of interpreting all manner of signals. On Earth
we call them animals. What then among all the millions of species is
special to us? One feature that might come to mind, so to speak, is
intelligence, but as we shall now see we are not the only players.
giant brains
The many convergences documented in the last chapter, from the
agriculture of ants to the vocalization of birds, are strong evidence
that the evolutionary emergence of many complex systems is highly
probable, if not inevitable. Yet the sceptic will still pause in thought.
figure 9.1 Jack standing against the trolley with Mr Wide; note the lever frame in the background.
(Photograph courtesy of Euan Nisbet, Royal Holloway, University of London.)
giant brains 245
Man
4 Brain size
Dolphin
EQ
2 Chimpanzee
Squirrel
monkey
Sheep
Pilot whale
1 Hedgehog
Rat Elephant
Hump whale Cat
Opossum
−10 0 10 20 30
Coefficient
Such similarities are indeed intriguing but do they really address the
central question as to whether or not humans as a biological prop-
erty are inevitable? This is because as well as having a complex social
system, agriculture, placentas and live birth, warm-bloodedness, and
vocalization, we have something else. Even if some reptiles give birth
to live young, and others chewed the equivalent of celery, their mental
powers neither were nor are conducive to rumination. Whatever may
be said in favour of reptiles, their brain size is distinctly disappointing.
Bigger brains are largely the prerogative of the birds and mammals, al-
though as we saw earlier the electrosensory mormyrid fish also weigh
in with a hefty brain. To a first approximation the size of the brain
scales to the body mass (Fig. 9.2).86 Most mammals, the group upon
which I shall now concentrate, have a brain whose size matches the
246 the non-prevalence of humanoids?
body, but some have a brain smaller than would otherwise be pre-
dicted. The tenrec, an insectivore, is one such example.87 Conversely,
other mammals have disproportionately large brains. Elephants are
big, but their brains are even more massive than would be predicted.
Humans, of course, are the exception of exceptions, with a brain ap-
proximately seven times bigger than it ‘should’ be. This strange con-
dition was arrived at by an astonishing neural trajectory that began
about four million years ago, with the later australopithecine apes. It
is often thought that this must have been a biologically unique event,
unrepeatable and dependent on a series of peculiar historical factors
without parallel elsewhere. William Calvin,88 for example, regards
attempts to conjure up particular explanations for the evolution of a
large brain as little more than caricatures. In particular, and referring
to an idea that has wide currency, he regards such a feature as intelli-
gence as being an unforeseen consequence of a neural machinery that
has been selected for some other reason. Intelligence, in this scenario,
is not primarily adaptational and as such might be reduced to an evo-
lutionary fluke, unique to humans and their nearest relatives and, to
echo G. G. Simpson (see note 2), unlikely to be found elsewhere in
the Galaxy.
In fact the evidence suggests otherwise, at least on this planet.
To start with, there is strong evidence that among the primates those
with bigger brains show more innovatory behaviours, social learning,
and tool use, while among the birds those with greater behavioural
flexibilities and adventurousness (or fewer neophobias) again have
larger brains.89 This accords with the fact, returned to at various points
below, that some monkeys, parrots, and crows are all markedly intel-
ligent. So, too, of course, are the great apes, but at least in this case
the fact that chimps, for example, have important parallels to human
mentality is hardly surprising. To find striking similarities to human
intelligence that might persuade the disinterested reader that such
represents a general biological property likely to emerge on any suit-
able planet, we need to turn to the toothed whales (the odontocetes)
and especially the dolphins.
It has long been recognized that for their size some of the toothed
whales, of which the dolphins are one group, have large brains.90 A
straightforward comparison with other groups of mammals, of which
the humans and related anthropoid primates are the most relevant,
nevertheless runs into some difficulties. Rather self-evidently the size
giant brains 247
6
Pacific white-sided dolphin
5 Tucuxi dolphin
Common dolphin
EQ.67 4 Bottlenose dolphin
Dall's porpoise
3
range of the bigger whales far outstrips the great apes: a typical killer-
whale weighs about seventeen times as much as a gorilla. Scaling of
body and brain masses across these size differences is not necessarily
easy. More importantly, the buoyancy of sea water means that a large
body size can be achieved without the imposition of a crushing gravi-
tational burden, and in addition a large part of the body tissue consists
of blubber. As its primary function is that of insulation, it is neurologi-
cally inert and accordingly requires no investment by the brain tissue.
The net result is that toothed whales have a rather different ratio of
body weight to brain mass when compared to the primates. Appro-
priate corrections therefore have to be made, but once this is done
it can be shown that not only do several types of dolphin (including
the Pacific white-sided, Tucuxi, common, and bottlenose) have large
brains, but in proportion to the brains of our three nearest relatives
(chimp, gorilla, and orang-utan) they are significantly larger.91 Indeed,
as Lori Marino has shown, until about 1.5 Ma ago, these dolphins were
the biggest-brained creatures on the planet. Only then, at about the
time of Homo erectus, did the brain size of hominids overtake that of
the dolphins (Fig. 9.3).92
248 the non-prevalence of humanoids?
The questions then arise as to how, when, and why did dolphin
brains get so large, and to what extent are the convergences with the
brains of the great apes actually informative?93 So far as the origins of
the story are concerned, it is not surprising to learn that well-preserved
fossil skulls of toothed whales are only moderately common. Nor has
it been easy to measure the so-called endocranial volume, which is a
fair guide to brain size, at least until the advent of non-invasive medi-
cal techniques, such as computer tomography (CT). In any event, the
fairly limited evidence suggests that the early whales had brains of
unremarkable size, some of which were, indeed below average.94 The
transition by whale ancestors from a terrestrial habitat to an aquatic
existence, the elucidation of which has been one of the triumphs of
palaeontological investigation,95 was evidently not in itself a spur
to bigger brains. A dramatic increase in brain size is apparent when
present-day dolphins are compared with these early ancestors, but the
exact history is still not resolved. The increase probably started in
the Oligocene, about 30 Ma ago, followed perhaps by a further jump in
the Miocene. Nor, too, is it yet clear whether these spurts of encephal-
ization were geologically sudden or more gradual.96 Nevertheless, it
appears that by the Miocene (if not before) brain size had increased
suddenly, especially in the ancestors of the porpoises and dolphins.
It is surely significant that this vast organ, which metabolically is
ruinously expensive,97 has been maintained for a protracted period,
probably far in excess of that for hominids, and possibly for as long as
20 Ma.98 Evidently big brains may be, in at least some circumstances,
adaptively useful, and are not just fickle blips of happenstance that
in due course sink back into the chaotic welter of the evolutionary
crucible.99
What, however, might have initiated one or more upsurges in
dolphin brain size? At present perhaps the best evidence is that the
trigger was environmental, specifically the dramatic cooling of the
Southern Ocean.100 Among the consequences of this event, which was
the harbinger of global refrigeration that culminated in the present
ice age, was increased oceanic productivity as marine upwelling
intensified.101 As Australia pulled away from Antarctica, marking
the final break-up of the once immense supercontinent known as
Gondwana, so the circum-Antarctic current became firmly estab-
lished, the ice caps began to spread down from the mountains of the
Antarctic continent, and in the adjacent oceans the baleen-sievers
giant brains 249
and predatory toothed whales both diversified, the deep waters filling
with their clicks, whistles, and other vocalizations. This environmen-
tal trigger has an interesting parallel, perhaps, with the hominid story
because it has been suggested that the major increases in brain size in
such forms as Homo erectus may have been encouraged by increas-
ing aridity in Africa, imposing new stringencies but also spurring new
possibilities.102
Large brains may therefore be favoured when the environment
offers a special challenge. Their persistence for many millions of years
requires, however, additional explanations. Of these it may be that the
emergence of sophisticated social organizations (with an emotional di-
mension) and the necessary corollary of advanced vocalizations may
be especially significant. The social structure of dolphin groups, espe-
cially in the well-studied bottlenoses, is directly relevant to the theme
of evolutionary convergence.103 At first sight it might seem rather re-
markable that the bottlenose dolphins show ‘striking parallels in so-
cial organization and complexity with that of the chimpanzee’,104 as
well as parallels to the ateline or spider-monkeys,105 a group to which I
return below on account of a series of other instructive convergences.
Such associations fall into a category known as fission–fusion soci-
eties, which as the name suggests are rather fluid in their composition,
with alliances and coalitions of varying durations.106 Societies of this
type are, as Marino notes, ‘extremely complex because they represent
a constantly dynamic social situation involving the movement of dif-
ferent individuals into and out of groups at various times’.107 Even
so, some individuals may stay together for protracted intervals, and
a common feature is a stable alliance of two to three male dolphins.
These males form temporary consortships with females. Mating is
probably promiscuous, but so far as the females are concerned it is
also highly coercive.108
The similarity with chimp societies is another fine example of
convergence within social systems. Nor is this resemblance likely to
be accidental. On the contrary, it is much more likely to be adaptive
and arises because despite the radical ecological differences there is
a deeper constraint imposed by the patchiness in space and time of
food resources in both ocean and jungle.109 The parallels are not exact;
why should they be? Moreover, as studies of the dolphins continue, so
further complexities in the structure of their societies are emerging.
They indicate that, in some ways, despite having a fission–fusion
250 the non-prevalence of humanoids?
society, the dolphins have advanced further than our closest relatives,
the chimps. It is now apparent that their societal structure is more
complex than hitherto realized, and that with dolphin groups form
so-called ‘super-alliances’. This clearly implies that their intelligence
is well suited to handling an extended social network comprising at
least a hundred individuals.110 Such intelligence is also well attested
in the examples of cooperation between dolphins and humans, no-
tably in the dolphins’ assistance with fishing by providing clues as to
where to cast the net or in herding the fish.111
This example of convergence in a sophisticated social context
finds another very interesting parallel, but this time between two
larger-than-average mammals, the sperm whales and the elephants.112
Linda Weilgart and her colleagues comment that despite their
self-evident differences in ‘a remarkable number of ways, including
life history and ranging behavior, sperm whales and elephants resem-
ble each other more than they do other animals – even ones that share
similar ancestries, diets, environments and predators. The closest re-
semblance is found in their complex and unusual, but comparable,
social organization.’113 In both these gigantic mammals the females
and young form highly social units, highly communicative with vari-
ous long-distance vocalizations.114 Socialization is intense, and in the
sperm whales, for example, there seems to be a form of ‘babysitting’ in
which the vulnerable young are cared for by other adults when their
mothers are engaged in deep dives in pursuit of food.115 The males,
in contrast, are solitary and wide-ranging, and return to the mating
game only when they are not merely sexually mature but big enough
to win contests. Social complexity, communal care of the young, in-
telligence, and memory, as well as longevity, seem to be the key in-
gredients in driving this remarkable convergence.
In the sophisticated and dynamic milieu of many cetacean so-
cieties, it is not surprising that vocalizations are complex and var-
ied, especially in the dolphins. As has been repeatedly pointed out,
the relative opacity of water means that facial expressions are of very
limited use, and so sound production and acoustics have largely taken
priority. In the specific case of the dolphins their fission–fusion soci-
eties are probably highly dependent on the production of recognizable
whistles and other noises.116 Indeed, there is evidence that the vocal-
izations are far from a cacophony. Dolphins are accomplished mimics,
and the speed and accuracy with which they can imitate given sounds
giant brains 251
they were not afraid to suggest that such learning might occur ‘as a
consequence of exposure to the sounds of tutors’. They concluded that
the ‘Vocal similarity [of the pod] seems to be correlated with the mul-
tilayered structure of killer whale society, and ultimately to the social
interactions that contribute to the stability of the social structure.’170
Shifts in sound production might certainly, as the various investi-
gators are careful to point out, be underpinned by a genetic change,
but it seems just as likely that it is by imitation, improvisation, and
experimentation. So, too, in humpback whales the arrival of some
‘foreigners’ led to a rapid adoption of the new song, literally a ‘cultural
revolution’.171 And should we be so surprised? Like humans, these ma-
rine mammals are long-lived, show a high degree of cognition, demon-
strate prolonged parental care, and form cohesive societies.
In their various ways a number of marine mammals, and es-
pecially the dolphins and some of the other toothed whales, are in-
triguing in their social complexity and cognitive abilities. Much is
convergent with other intelligent mammals, including humans, and
it is a clear enough indication that at least in this biosphere if we had
not emerged as the cerebral species then at some point, and probably
sooner rather than later, someone else would. In this sense, humans,
as a biological property, were inherent from at least the Cambrian
period, if not before. The life of a dolphin appears to be rich and com-
plex, but in evolutionary terms these large-brained cetaceans seem to
have reached an impasse. Because they are highly adapted for swim-
ming and living in the sea, they would seem to be unlikely candi-
dates for the emergence of an advanced technology. Even so, despite
their aquatic milieu, when it comes to tool use then, once again, the
flippered dolphins surprise us. At least one group, principally more
solitary females, has learnt to root up conical sponges and stick them
on to their anterior beak, a structure known as the rostrum.172 Sev-
eral alternative explanations can be entertained. Perhaps it is just that
dolphins enjoy fooling around. Another possibility is that the sponges
have medicinal properties. The most likely explanation, however, is
that the sponge acts as a natural glove and as the dolphin rootles
around in the sea bed, so it receives some protection from an alarm-
ing array of venomous animals, such as the stone-fish, scorpion-fish,
sting-rays, sea-snakes, and the occasional blue-ringed octopus. Nor is
this the only example of tool use by cetaceans. We saw earlier evidence
of cognitive capacities in the formation of bubble rings by dolphins,
grasping convergence 261
grasping convergence
If the path to the humanoid is characterized by any feature other than
the carrying of a large brain rich in mentalities, it is the tools dropped
on the way. Chosen and then discarded, tools epitomize intelligence
and the purposeful. To be sure, those constructed by animals may
seem primitive in the extreme, but it is clear enough that human
technologies ultimately are based on the same antecedents. More im-
portantly it is also now obvious that such an evolutionary ability may
be rare, but it has emerged independently a number of times: inherent
in evolution is not only intelligence and cognitive sophistication, but
also technology. Tool use, per se, is of course well documented in a
wide variety of birds,175 but a particularly famous example is provided
by the New Caledonian crows.176 This example has excited interest
because of evidence for the manufacture of both particular tool types,
including hooks,177 and their standardization, features that had been
thought to be effectively restricted to the advanced primates. In ad-
dition, Gavin Hunt documents lateralization in tool use and a rule-
based method of construction.178 He also stresses that in a number
of respects the more famous chimpanzee tool cultures do not match
that of these crows, and concludes:
At the least, crows provide an extant species for learning about the
neuropsychology associated with . . . tool-making, such as
handedness, hook use and the shaping of tools to rule systems,
including an opportunity to see whether left-hemisphere
specialization of the brain for the organization of sequential,
manipulatory behaviours in tool-making might indeed be
phylogenetically very ancient. If crows’ tool behaviour involves
cultural transmission, they also offer the opportunity for studying
tool-making by pre-modern humans where cognitive, behavioural
and social processes may have resulted in largely repetitive rather
than innovative tool manufacture, and symbolism and language
were rudimentary or absent.179
262 the non-prevalence of humanoids?
Apart from the parrots, already mentioned, and for which considerable
evidence for cognitive sophistication exists,180 many ornithologists
have remarked on the general intelligence of crows. Recent observa-
tions on tool modification and goal-directed activities in the American
crow bear this out.181
Tool use in chimps has, not surprisingly, received extensive at-
tention. Most of the work focuses, reasonably enough, on the use of
sticks and stones.182 The closely related bonobo is also known to en-
gage in tool-making. Remarking on one particular case, Nicholas Toth
and his colleagues183 noted that the bonobo in question, one Kanzi,
showed ‘exceptional progress to date [but] his skill in flaking stone still
contrasts sharply to that of Oldowan hominids’.184 They were unsure
as to whether this was more a reflection of manipulative abilities as
against cognitive constraints. Interestingly, however, chimps also use
twigs for dental care in activities that include cleaning the teeth and
helping to yank out deciduous ones.185 Much of this activity is self-
directed, but examples are also known of one individual performing
elementary dentistry on another chimp.
Nor is tool use among non-human primates confined to chimps.
Significantly in some of the New World monkeys, whose evolution-
ary history has been separated from that of the Old World monkeys
(and their descendants, the great Apes) for about 30 Ma, have conver-
gently acquired tools. In particular, capuchin monkeys (Cebus), and
also some of the callitrichids (specifically the golden lion tamarins186 )
show extensive tool use for a variety of purposes, including a prim-
itive lithic technology when provided with suitable materials in
captivity.187 Suzanne Chevalier-Skolnikoff188 also emphasizes that
tool use is unlikely to have arisen by trial and error (fiddling around
if you will) but is a direct product of advanced sensorimotor abili-
ties: that is, capability combined with motivation. It is difficult to
escape the conclusion that once such abilities are in place, tool use
becomes an inevitability. In reviewing the earlier literature on tool use
by capuchins, Gregory Westergaard and Stephen Suomi provide an ef-
fective counterpoint to Chevalier-Skolnikoff’s comments.189 They re-
mark, ‘We suggest that the ability to make and use simple stone tools
is a primitive behavioral capacity that may have been “discovered”
numerous times and utilized by more than one hominid genus and
species’.190 This idea echoes an earlier suggestion by Sue Parker and
grasping convergence 263
a long quotation, but if at the end you don’t rub your eyes, obviously
you are more immune to surprise than I am. Thus Williston writes:
that ‘sees’ with its nose, suggest that there are deep commonalities in
both neural systems and the associated transduction proteins. These
may enable wildly different sensory systems, in effectively unrelated
animals, to build similar cognitive maps.208 If that is so, then arguably
the root problem of consciousness, the qualia (e.g. the redness of the
sunset on Threga IX), have deep-seated similarities that require an in-
terpreter rather than blank incomprehension. Incidentally, this is not
necessarily to deny another point made by Nagel, to the effect that
our neural architecture may for ever preclude the comprehension of
certain realities. Thus he writes ‘one might also believe that there are
facts which could not ever be represented or comprehended by human
beings, even if the species lasted forever, simply because our structure
does not permit us to operate with concepts of the requisite type.’209
An interesting thought, especially if all intelligences have a universal
neuronal basis.
Whatever truth there may be in these suppositions, the study
by de Winter and Oxnard (note 204) of how these three groups of
mammals occupied the various zones of ‘brain space’ leads to some
very interesting, if perhaps by now unsurprising, conclusions. As has
been long known, within each of the three groups there are recur-
rent convergences in terms of life, habit, and behaviour. For example,
among the bats carnivory, by which is meant the ability to capture
live vertebrate prey, has evolved several times.210 So, too, among the
insectivores there have been multiple convergences associated with
the transition from the terrestrial environment either to the aquatic
realm or to a burrowing mode of life; and in the primates leaf-eating
has evolved several times.211 Such convergences are, of course, a prin-
cipal theme of this book, but the work of de Winter and Oxnard is of
particular importance because they find that the convergences that
lead to the adoption of similar life-styles are mirrored in the brain
structure. Neurology, and by implication mentality, overrides phy-
logeny. One significant implication of this analysis is that it points
to the pervasive influence of evolutionary selection: how else can we
explain such similarities? The net result, as Winter and Oxnard note,
is that one can ‘infer important ecological and behavioural attributes
of a mammal from . . . knowledge of its brain proportions alone.’212
So confident are these researchers that in one case, those bats that
visit plants, for example, to feed on nectar, they predicted that cer-
tain of the Old World bats would show this ecology even though at
converging on the humanoid 267
the time the habit of plant visiting was believed to be restricted to the
New World bats. Subsequent observations on the Old World murinine
bats confirmed this prediction.213 Indeed, these and other analyses214
indicate that the general rules of brain organization confer a wider pre-
dictability to a number of evolutionary processes. As Leah Krubitzer
has remarked on the evolution of cortical structure,
Who are those figures in shadows, tracking our own history? Step
forth the Neanderthals, a much-researched and on occasion much-
abused group.279 Either way their study is accompanied by continuous
controversy. Nevertheless, the majority opinion is that they repre-
sent a separate species, Homo neanderthalensis, a view established
on differences in skeletal structure280 and development281 and more
recently on the basis of the recovery of ancient DNA.282 Their mas-
sive and powerful construction, and details such as huge noses, are
evidently adaptations to living in hostile, near-tundra conditions, of
dealing with bouts of intense cold, and an erratic food supply that
led to the adoption of hunting patterns rather different from those
of Homo sapiens.283 Our and Neanderthal brain sizes are equivalent,
and it is beyond all reasonable doubt that they controlled fire and
employed the red pigment ochre, possibly for body decoration. Un-
equivocal evidence for cannibalism also exists,284 but the discovery
of skeletons with severe impairments indicates that the infirm and
crippled were at least sometimes tended to. Famous examples come
from the Shanidar caves in Iraq.285 Of the series of Neanderthal skele-
tons, a majority shows evidence of various traumatic injuries. One of
the individuals (Shanidar I) had particularly dramatic injuries, perhaps
caused by a rock fall, that included cranial damage, a fractured foot,
and an arm that had withered. This individual lived, for a Neanderthal,
to a relatively advanced age, and the extent of his disabilities indicates
a society capable, for whatever reason, of care and compassion.286 Even
so, Neanderthal life was evidently robust and demanding. A general
survey of Neanderthal trauma287 confirms the prevalence of injuries,
as well as the very high incidence of neck and head damage. Thomas
Berger and Erik Trinkhaus remind us that although the old and in-
firm might receive care, the general ‘dearth of older Neanderthals’
suggests that ‘these hominids did not sacrifice the survival of the so-
cial group as a whole when it was threatened by an immobile indi-
vidual’. Despite the likely employment of spears in hunting, these
may have been used principally for thrusting rather than throwing.
As Berger and Trinkhaus dryly note, ‘Given the tendency of ungulates
to react strongly to being impaled, the frequency of head and neck, as
well as upper limb, injuries seen in the Neanderthals should not be
surprising.’288 And if the Neanderthal escaped the charging ungulate,
then there was also the risk of attempted murder.289 What is espe-
cially intriguing is the evidence for deliberate burial (Fig. 9.6). This too
converging on the ultimate 277
the Neanderthals not only making more advanced tools but, even
more remarkably, by shaping bones and teeth to form artefacts. No-
table finds from the excavations at Arcy-sur-Cure302 include necklace
pieces (Fig. 9.7) composed of canine teeth and fossils. This break-
through, which for obscure reasons did not spread to Iberia,303 took
place after tens of thousands of years of seeming cultural stagnation,
and has been interpreted as largely imitative on the Aurignacian cul-
tures of the incoming H. sapiens, if not acquired by trading or even
scavenging abandoned sites.304 A useful analogy, suggested by Paul
Mellars, is with the cargo cults of such islands as New Guinea and the
New Hebrides.305 On some of the islands, such as Tanna in the New
Hebrides where the John Frum cult still exists, the indigenes con-
struct elaborate cult centres which include model aeroplanes, upon
which it is hoped the desired objects will arrive.306 If these artefacts
had been found in an archaeological context, it would not be sensible,
as Mellars reminds us, to conclude that the islanders had any practical
280 the non-prevalence of humanoids?
It was a cold spring day, and the little boy had been out for too long,
playing in the pond. The other members of the family were not pay-
ing much attention, and it was only with a start that the father first
realized that the boy was no longer to be seen; then with a surge of
anguished alarm he saw that not far from where the boy had been wad-
ing something was now floating. All attempts at resuscitation were
futile. With great sadness they left the ambulance as the metal doors
closed. Swiftly they made their way home, already late to prepare for
the Sabbath. Young Adolf was dead.
To judge from the recurrent, if not increasing interest in counter-
factual histories, be it the untimely demise of either tyrant or genius,
the what-ifs of history seem to loom ever larger as the tapestry of
events weaves folly compounded with stupidity, the witless leading
the insane, to the soft applause of the flaccid and the time-server: ‘All
loyal, my lord’. So many missed opportunities, such corruption and
malice, laced with vaunting pride. All seems to be dependent on the
twists and turns of fate, epitomized by the loose nail of the horse’s
shoe by which a kingdom is lost.
So, too, it is now widely thought that the history of life is little
more than a contingent muddle punctuated by disastrous mass ex-
tinctions that in spelling the doom of one group so open the doors of
opportunity to some other mob of lucky-chancers. The innumerable
accidents of history and the endless concatenation of whirling cir-
cumstances make any attempt to find a pattern to the evolutionary
process a ludicrous exercise. Rerun the tape of the history of life, as
S. J. Gould would have us believe, and the end result will be an ut-
terly different biosphere. Most notably there will be nothing remotely
like a human, so reinforcing the notion that any other biosphere,
across the galaxy and beyond, must be as different as any other: per-
haps things slithering across crepuscular mudflats, but certainly never
the prospect of music, nor sounds of laughter. Yet, what we know of
evolution suggests the exact reverse: convergence1 is ubiquitous and
the constraints of life make the emergence of the various biological
284 evolution bound: the ubiquity of convergence
ubiquitous convergence
Before moving to some examples specifically in the areas of behaviour
and molecular biology, where convergence a priori would be surpris-
ing, let me try to show you how ubiquitous is the phenomenon of con-
vergence. Science fiction is replete with examples of the ‘insectoid’,
vaguely modelled on the apparently robotic scrabblings of a terres-
trial counterpart. Evolutionary orthodoxy, of course, is that such a
creature is a contingent accident, assembled by chance histories and
circumstances. Insects are interesting; insects are monophyletic; but
in the final analysis that is all there is to say. If, however, we consider
‘insectoids’ as a biological property then perhaps something more gen-
eral emerges. So what is the design specification? Among the defining
features of the insects are the following: an articulated exoskeleton
arising from the process of arthropodization; compound eyes; a hexa-
pod gait whereby three of the six walking legs are always on the ground
and thereby define a triangle (two legs on one side, one leg on the other)
that keeps the animal stable; respiratory tubes known as tracheae that
serve to bring oxygen into the interior animal via special openings
(spiracles) on the side of the body; and, to complete this list of evolu-
tionary peculiarities, the development of complex eusocial colonies,
as in the honey bees. All pretty strange, all one-offs in the great lot-
tery of life? On the contrary, all are convergent. Arthropodization may
have evolved as many as four times independently;3 the convergent
evolution of compound eyes was addressed in Chapter 7; a hexapod
gait is inferred in eurypterids (an extinct group related to the scor-
pions) such as Hibbertopterus that moved out of water on to land;4
tracheae evolved independently at least four times5 (as has the method
of gas exchange6 ); and a eusocial organization has not only evolved in-
dependently in many groups of insects (ants, bees, termites, wasps),
ubiquitous convergence 285
but is also found in the shrimps and various mammals, most famously
the naked mole-rats (Chapter 8).
Yet despite the textbook examples of convergence, such as the
camera-eye of vertebrates and cephalopod molluscs, along with the
seemingly arcane, for example, birds that can echolocate (p. 181) or
reptiles with a dentition similar to that of mammals (p. 227), my the-
sis is that both the extent and the importance of convergence have
been consistently underestimated. By this I do not mean so much
the innumerable examples. These are mostly known only to the spe-
cialists, and even among them the convergences tend to be treated
as simple curiosities, with the customary adjectives of ‘remarkable’
and ‘surprising’ (see p. 128). Rather it is my suggestion that by un-
derstanding convergence we can constrain what sort of biosphere we
might expect, especially in an extraterrestrial context. To be sure, for
the most part any discussion concerning convergence tends to revolve
around the immediate realities of the physical world. In this sense the
repeated evolution of features as distinct as stabbing canines (p. 130)
or electroreception in fish (p. 182) are, on a closer analysis, hardly sur-
prising. There are, however, other more complex convergences, such
as the cognitive functions of dolphins (p. 258). Nor in this context
should we be surprised to see the repeated re-emergence of advanced
and sophisticated social organizations. The comparison between the
elephant and the sperm-whale (p. 250) is a fine example, as are the
similarities between the fission–fusion societies of chimp and dol-
phin (p. 249). Because of the general emphasis on physical constraints
in evolution, these examples of societal convergence surely deserve
to be more widely known.
Indeed, I rather suspect that the role of convergence in the be-
havioural realm will produce quite a few more surprises. Earlier I
referred to the way in which electric fish and moths, generating re-
spectively electrical and sound signals, show a convergence in the way
they confuse potential predators. At present, however, the number of
examples of convergences in the behavioural repertoire is rather lim-
ited. Indeed, at first sight such convergences would seem to be rather
unexpected given the complexity and range of responses. Neverthe-
less the examples now available, including the courtship behaviour
of houseflies,7 lacewings,8 crickets,9 and bowerbirds,10 give some in-
dication of the many other examples of behavioural convergence that
probably await recognition. The case of the bowerbirds is, of course, of
286 evolution bound: the ubiquity of convergence
distantly related groups whose common ancestor lived long ago in the
geological past, and which very probably did not possess the relevant
character we identify as convergent.
respiratory convergence
Despite the apparent ubiquity of convergence, there are some areas
of evolution where the role of convergence would be expected to be
minimal. Of these molecular biology is surely the prime candidate. It
is not difficult to see why. As was discussed earlier, the combinatorial
‘universe’ of protein space is unimaginably vast, which suggests that
the likelihood of navigating to the same ‘destination’ is exceedingly
remote. In itself this may not be terribly important. The success of
proteins depends on their overall structure and, to a first approxima-
tion, the precise sequence of amino acids may not make that much
difference. To be sure, the structure at particular sites may be exceed-
ingly sensitive to the substitution of one amino acid by another, and as
we have already seen in such examples as trichromatic colour vision
(p. 167), these substitutions also give insights into a particular sort of
molecular convergence. Such substitutions, however, presuppose an
existing protein that is already functional. However, we also discover
that, despite the combinatorial immensity of protein ‘hyperspace’, in
other ways the landscape of possibilities is again somewhat limited.16
This is simply because proteins are constructed from a limited num-
ber of ‘building blocks’. Furthermore, in at least the case of certain
structures such as the so-called α/β barrels17 , there is evidence that
the arrangement may have been arrived at convergently. It is useful,
therefore it evolves. Even so, it must be acknowledged that there is
considerable tension, metaphorically speaking, in the study of pro-
tein evolution in deciding whether a structure has evolved because
of a common ancestry, even when no sequence similarity remains, or
because of general constraints on protein structure and function.18
As such, this suggests that molecular convergence at the level
of proteins need not be unexpected. For example, the general view
is that the haemoglobins found in organisms as different as humans
and cyanobacteria are similar because they all derive from a common
ancestral protein. Yet it is also possible that the haemoglobins found
in the protistan ciliates and cyanobacteria actually have a separate
origin,19 albeit with the complication that the cyanobacteria may have
acquired them from the ciliates by a lateral transfer.20 In the context
288 evolution bound: the ubiquity of convergence
case, this protein has been co-opted from an earlier role; in this partic-
ular instance from functions that include control of the stomata and
assimilation of nitrogen. Until recently it was also thought that an
essential aspect of C4 photosynthesis was the possession of a Kranz
anatomy, but so far as a C4 chenopodiacean plant (Borszczowia) is con-
cerned its distinctive leaf anatomy does not depend on the dual-cell
arrangement seen in classical Kranz anatomy.52
There are some interesting nuances in this story. First, although
described as C4 photosynthesis, the pathways in the respective plants
show various differences and degrees of completion in the transition
from the C3 to C4 photosynthesis.53 As is effectively inevitable in
evolutionary convergence, there are multiple pathways to the same
destination. Even so, there are a number of peculiarities in this evo-
lutionary process. One of the most obvious is that C4 photosynthesis
is not generally known among the trees, although some shrubs with
secondary woody growth are C4 photosynthesizers, and in Hawaii a
rare tree (Chamaesyce forbesii) also has this type of photosynthesis.54
Despite this restriction in land plants, what appears to be an indepen-
dent acquisition of the C4 pathway is known in some algae, specifi-
cally the diatoms.55 Second, although the story of the rise of C4 plants
focuses on events beginning about ten million years ago (see note 49),
there may be a deeper history. There are at least hints of a precipitous
drop in carbon dioxide about 90 Ma ago and a corresponding appear-
ance of C4 photosynthesis.56 More tenuous is the possibility that a
much earlier drop in atmospheric CO2 , linked to the late Palaeozoic
ice ages (late Carboniferous – early Permian, c. 280 Ma ago) also saw
an independent development of the C4 pathways.57
Once again evolutionary inevitabilities emerge. If George
Wald is correct and chlorophyll is universal (Chapter 6), so, too, is
photosynthesis. On planets where the levels of atmospheric carbon
dioxide happen to decline, and given that only on tectonically active
planets where water, plate tectonics, and mountain-building interact
will atmospheric carbon dioxide fluctuate, the C4 photosynthetic
pathway will inevitably follow. Without C4 plants, humans would
face a rather different world. Some of the most important groups of
C4 photosynthesizers are the grasses, including wheat and rice and
(originating in the New World) maize. Even within the grasses it
appears that the C4 process was arrived at independently at least four
times.58
the molecules converge 295
the nose, where it serves to protect these exposed surfaces from in-
fection. Lysozyme, however, has another role. This is to assist with
the digestion of the tough plant material scooped up by cows and
other ruminants. The basic principle is to employ bacteria in a re-
action chamber, the rumen. The role of the bacteria is to attack the
plant cellulose, and so allow fermentation of the swallowed vegeta-
tion. The resultant slurry is then processed in the stomach, using
the enzyme lysozyme. This arrangement of rumen and stomach with
lysozyme activity, familiar from the cow, has evolved convergently
in one group of primates, the colobine Old World monkeys, e.g. the
langur,84 and also a rather odd bird known as the hoatzin.85 This ani-
mal, which lives in the Amazon forests and eats a diet made up largely
of leaves,86 is probably best known because of its supposed parallels
with the bird–dinosaur Archaeopteryx.87 The hoatzin has shifted its
diet from the softer fruits to tougher leaves, and here too lysozyme
is employed. Molecular convergence between the lysozymes of these
monkeys and the ruminants has significantly also been identified,88
and so, too, with the hoatzin birds.89 But is it really a convergence?
When the overall sequences of the lysozymes in primates and rumi-
nants are compared, the phylogeny is as expected, whereas if the con-
vergence were unrecognized it could be used mistakenly as a sign
of common ancestry and so would ‘artificially’ bring the two groups
together.90 This, however, is not quite the point because it is the spe-
cific similarities within the lysozyme molecule, at five or so amino
acid sites, which excite our interest,91 because of both the molecular
convergence and the implication that observations of this kind have
for molecular adaptation.92 It would be misleading, of course, to sug-
gest that these examples of molecular convergences are particularly
frequent, but examples in some key enzymes suggest that as with
DNA (p. 31) and chlorophyll (p. 110) there may be some effectively
universal constraints.
were ever any doubt, the reality of evolutionary adaptation.97 For ex-
ample, writing on the topic of ecomorphological diversification in
freshwater fish, Kirk Winemiller98 remarked, ‘The concept of ecologi-
cal convergence and independent evolution of equivalent ecomorpho-
types deserves special attention because of its implications for general
ecological and evolutionary theory,’ and he continued, ‘the remark-
able qualities exhibited by several convergent pairings makes the phe-
nomenon difficult to dismiss as arising from stochastic processes.’99
Rob Foley100 is more trenchant: ‘Convergence is perhaps the strongest
evidence for adaptation, and indicates that despite the contingent fac-
tors that lie at the base of evolutionary episodes, the rules of survivor-
ship and reproductive success govern the final outcome.’101 Earlier I
introduced the many convergences in the subterranean mammals, and
it is no accident that Eviator Nevo’s masterly overview102 of this topic
is equally a renewed prolegomenon on behalf of the importance of the
adaptational explanation. Using multiple examples, he proclaims that
‘the adaptationist programme is as vital as ever.’103
Much as I disagree with the world picture of Richard Dawkins,
with its questionable genetic reductionism and etiolated secular
pieties, his explanations and enthusiasm for the reality of adaptation
are of great value.104 This is the way the world is, and in one way the
only interesting question is how different could it be, in terms of both
mechanism and end results? So far as the former is concerned, the
much-vaunted plurality of alternative evolutionary mechanisms ap-
pears, at best, to be of marginal relevance. Consider, for example, the
notion of ‘historical burden’, the constraints of past ‘decisions’ that
guide, restrict, and perhaps even stymie a phylogenetic ‘career’. That
such constraints exist is undeniable, but what is far more interesting
is the way in which organisms repeatedly ‘get round’ these problems,
which is why convergences are ubiquitous. This is neither to suppose
that everything is possible, nor to deny the reality of contingent hap-
penstance in biological history.105 Even to acknowledge the realities of
convergence is not to imagine that every organism is ‘trying’ to evolve
into a human. The Earth’s biosphere is patently a product of diver-
gences, but as this book emphasizes there is an underlying structure
that imposes limits and delineates probabilities of outcomes. Some
evolutionary trajectories point to increasing complexity, but simpli-
fication can be just as prevalent. Thus, there are a number of excel-
lent examples from among the animals of what appears to our eyes
convergence and evolution 303
converging trends
This ubiquity of convergence and the likelihood that the great ma-
jority of the examples are almost certainly the result of selective pro-
cesses operating in the context of adaptation has the obvious corollary
that common evolutionary destinations presuppose specific, and re-
stricted, trajectories. To mainstream evolutionary biology the exis-
tence of trends is entirely unremarkable.112 For example, Christine
Janis and John Damuth in a wide-ranging review of mammalian evo-
lution and convergence remark, ‘We regard the widespread occurrence
of detailed ecomorphic convergences to be prima facie evidence for
sustained, adaptive, phyletic trends at lower hierarchical levels,’113
and in their conclusions go on to say, ‘It should be clear at this point
that we feel that the adaptive component has been dominant in his-
torical trends observed in the Mammalia.’114 To be sure, like adap-
tation, an apparent failure to demonstrate a trend may tell us more
about the method employed than about the non-existence of the trend.
Yet trends imply directionality, and perhaps progress (note 112). It is
hardly surprising then that in his decades-long campaign against adap-
tation, S. J. Gould sought to demolish such ideas, arguing in particular
that we would do better to look at the changes in variance as lineages
evolve,115 with the corollary that the trend is no more than a diffusion
away from a restraining boundary.
So are trends with a directional component that might arise
from a persistent pressure, such as natural selection, not only real but
sufficiently common to be important? The ubiquity of convergence
would argue so, but in this context I am more interested in direc-
tionality in evolution per se. Take, for example, what is probably the
best-known evolutionary trend, that of size increase. This is known
as Cope’s rule. Yet, for the most part the reality of this rule has been
converging trends 305
has run out of things to ‘do’), but it might equally reflect ‘persistent
selection favoring similar general forms.’125 Wagner’s study, which
encompasses a wide variety of fossil clades, was concerned with their
specific histories, which led consistently to the exhaustion of poten-
tial: in each case the tape of life was not only rerun, but rerun re-
peatedly. In a wider context, and as has already been emphasized, this
does not negate the self-evident reality of continuing diversification. It
might be objected that this undermines the principle of predictability
as inferred from the ubiquity of convergence. What evolution cannot
do is see into future diversification so far as the envelope of possibil-
ities is concerned, although it can be equally sure that a great deal of
what does one day evolve will have emerged in parallel circumstances,
in other times and places. What we can also say is that whenever the
known edge of the evolutionary envelope is reached, be it in terms
of intelligence or agriculture, then it will be explored independently
several times.
In their own ways the realities of adaptation and evolutionary
trends (and the exhaustion of possibilities) excite little comment in
the mainstream of biology; why should they? Not everything need be
adaptive, nor are random walks by any means impossible, but are they
effectively peripheral to the argument? And what about evolutionary
progress, that term that S. J. Gould126 gently refers to as ‘noxious’.127
Simply because evolution has delivered us to a point where only now
can the word ‘progress’ make any sense, need not mean that it either
has no relevance to the human condition or that it lacks an evolu-
tionary reality. That the bacteria are still with us, and that without
them the planet would soon grind to a halt in the absence of their
recycling abilities, misses the point. Neither is progress a question
of the sheer number of species, nor the supposed number of body
plans. What we do see through geological time is the emergence of
more complex worlds. Nor is this a limiting view. It might be pre-
mature to suppose that even the bacteria of today are some sort of
‘honorary fossils’, unchanged relicts from the Archaean pond-scum.
Nor need we imagine that the appearance of humans is the culmina-
tion of all evolutionary history. Yet, when within the animals we see
the emergence of larger and more complex brains, sophisticated
vocalizations, echolocation, electrical perception, advanced social
systems including eusociality, viviparity, warm-bloodedness, and
agriculture – all of which are convergent – then to me that sounds like
progress.
308 evolution bound: the ubiquity of convergence
central as the agency, but the nodes of occupation are effectively pre-
determined from the Big Bang.
One such node is, of course, that of the humanoid, and from
the present evolutionary perspective we are undeniably unique. Yet,
as I have already argued, if we had not arrived at sentience and called
ourselves human, then probably sooner rather than later some other
group would have done so, perhaps from within the primates, perhaps
from further afield, even much further afield. Yet it is our prerogative
to explore the natural world, and thereby document evolution, and
in the footsteps of Darwin marvel at its diversity. These discoveries
have not been without their cost. Not only are our animal origins plain
to see, but so, too, it is now supposed that with our origins revealed
this must banish any religious instinct: what was almost universally
believed is now to be seen as an immense delusion. Now is the time,
it is proclaimed, to adopt wholeheartedly the naturalistic view of life,
not only to expel the mysteries, but to deride the ignorant and mould
the world as we will. In the next, penultimate, chapter we shall see
that things are not necessarily so simple.
11 Towards a theology
of evolution?
an evolutionary embedment
It is self-evident that whatever our peculiarities as humans, we are
embedded in the natural world, and just as clearly we are one product
of an evolutionary process that began about four billion years ago. In
itself, the mechanism of evolutionary change is so unexceptional as to
be almost trivial. As Martin Carrier4 has written, ‘Darwinian theory
plays a role in evolutionary biology that is analogous to the one New-
tonian theory plays in celestial mechanics. It provides the mechanism
of change; it specifies the law-governed processes that determine how
species develop and adapt in a possibly changing environment.’5 Des-
pite this simple process most biologists will freely acknowledge that
both the routes and the products of evolution are profoundly fascinat-
ing. I have already alluded to a few of these, such as the problem of the
origin of life itself. Probably of equal moment is to discover how it is
that proteins fold so effectively and quickly. Evolution also presents
what Denis Duboule and Adam Wilkins6 have termed ‘bricolage’, that
is the surprising co-option and redeployment of biological material for
unexpected uses. An excellent example is the crystallin proteins of
the eye lens, which as discussed in Chapter 7 (p. 166) are routinely
and independently co-opted from heat-shock and other stress-related
proteins that evolved thousands of millions of years before any eye
could see.
Biologists also have, in the true Darwinian spirit, immense ad-
miration for the jury-rigging of biological design, whereby co-option
and modification lead to the functioning whole. And, if they are
an evolutionary embedment 313
honest, they may feel a sense of unease about the fluidity and grace of
adaptation. It has an almost uncanny sense of precision and balance,
which humans achieve only rarely in technology or art. Not only does
one admire the pervasiveness and ubiquity of integrated organic com-
plexity, but one cannot help but be impressed by its sensitivity, in
some circumstances, to minute changes so that sometimes even a
single amino acid substitution in a protein can lead to a major change
of functionality, if not catastrophe. And for some – probably many –
when we review the broad sweep of evolution and greet first the flick-
ering and then the full emergence of consciousness, that is all there is
to say. Science must work in a naturalistic framework, and again many
appear content to live with this arrangement. Roll on that cellulose-
digesting gene, and let us treat the world as open to unlimited
manipulation.
Yet, there are nagging doubts. Yes, it may all be due to a few
misfiring neurons, perhaps an extra dollop of neuropeptide or what-
ever, but the fact remains that humans have an overwhelming sense
of purpose. As a species we are strangely comfortable to find ourselves
embedded in a teleological matrix. So the intention of this chapter is
to begin to see whether the idea of a telos7 is redundant, to ask if some
of our predecessors who saw their religious faith either ebb or haem-
orrhage were both misinformed and over-pessimistic, and to enquire
whether some common ground can be regained.
One clue is surely our admiration for moral greatness. Rather,
however, than argue or defend any particular individual, although
there are many such men and women, let us recall the cosmic view
of G. K. Chesterton.
Reason and justice grip the remotest and the loneliest star. Look at
those stars. Don’t they look as if they were single diamonds and
sapphires? Well, you can imagine any mad botany or geology you
please. Think of forests of adamant with leaves of brilliants.
Think the moon is a blue moon, a single elephantine sapphire. But
don’t fancy that all that frantic astronomy would make the
smallest difference to the reason and justice of conduct. On plains
of opal, under cliffs cut out of pearl, you would still find a
notice-board, ‘Thou shalt not steal.’8
darwin’s priesthood
As I have already indicated, such views as those expressed by Peacocke
and others may strike a chord in places, but I suspect that they
will also be widely regarded as quaint and antiquated. Indeed
these views are under full-scale assault by a group that allows
a unique priority to Darwinian mechanisms and, in most cases,
the primacy of the gene. These ultra-Darwinists are highly promi-
nent, not least because the shoulders on which they stand in-
clude Huxley, Simpson, and Mayr, all giants in their various ways
within the Darwinian synthesis. Let me make some initial obser-
vations, which in today’s climate of accommodating pluralism and
relativism will, I suppose, seem deeply unfair. I am driven to ob-
serve of the ultra-Darwinists the following features as symptomatic.
First, to my eyes, is their almost unbelievable self-assurance, their
breezy self-confidence.11 Second, and far more serious, are partic-
ular examples of a sophistry and sleight of hand in the misuse of
metaphor, and more importantly a distortion of metaphysics in sup-
port of an evolutionary programme. Consider how ultra-Darwinists,
having erected a naturalistic system that cannot by itself possess
any ultimate purpose, still allow a sense of meaning mysteriously
darwin’s priesthood 315
heresy! heresy!!
Let me continue this brief review with two other episodes that in
their different ways are almost comic, but in at least the first case
have a much darker side. Otherwise each is very different. The first
concerns Ernst Haeckel, the keeper of the Darwinian evangeliarium
in Germany, and the second the farce of the Dayton ‘Monkey Trial’ in
1925. In the mind of Haeckel, Darwin was the greatest of heroes, and
Darwinism the new beacon to lead the world from its benighted obscu-
rantism. There is an amusing, at least to the English, story of Haeckel
crossing the Channel and visiting Down House: a metaphorical, if not
literal, genuflection between Teutonic adorer and English gentleman
scientist. There was, however, no meeting of the minds. The
German was effusive, gushing, bombastic, enthusiastic, and Darwin?
well . . .
Haeckel had seized upon the Darwinian explanation and vigor-
ously and tirelessly promoted it in Germany. Not only was this done
with books, but also with lavishly illustrated lectures. Concerning
heresy! heresy!! 319
the latter, Daniel Gasman23 refers to a poster for one such lecture
in Berlin, and remarks how this example of Darwinismus-Kunst pro-
vided ‘a sinister environment for a Darwinian Passion Play.’24 It is,
moreover, Gasman who has done much to reveal the rottenness at the
heart of Haeckel’s project.25 As I remarked elsewhere26 when drawing
upon his work:
lawyer in America, already notorious for his risky and ingenious de-
fence of Nathan Leopold and Richard Loeb, two Chicago teenagers
who abducted, bludgeoned to death, and then mutilated with acid
a schoolboy and neighbour, a luckless fourteen-year-old known as
Robert Franks. This murderous pair were bunglers of a high order,
but had it seems undertaken the atrocity in the belief that they would
escape detection. There was, ostensibly, no other motive. At the trial,
Darrow undercut the prosecution by an unexpected change to a plea of
‘Guilty’, followed by a rhetorical harangue to the effect that Leopold
and Loeb retained their innocence because of the environment in
which they were nurtured, one of intellectual stimulation, but emo-
tional starvation, and in the case of Leopold, the corruption of a young
mind that inevitably results from being made to read Nietzsche. This
libertarian argument, delivered as a thrilling speech that concluded
with a quotation from Omar Khayyam, has plenty of resonances to-
day. As one writer on the Scopes Trial, Kevin Tierney, notes, at the
end of the speech, ‘many in the audience were crying. Darrow had
taken the case far beyond the bounds of reason and logic . . . It was
his most masterly oration, rousing his audience to display emotion
openly beyond what the conventions allowed . . . The spellbinder has
cast his spell once again.’30
Thus Darrow embraced a moral perspective, as exemplified by
the Leopold and Loeb trial, which led to Dayton and his battle against
Bryan. Here was a very different man. No fool: as a Democrat, he
had been quite close to winning the American presidency, and at the
time of Dayton was America’s greatest defender of fundamentalist
Christianity. Like Darrow he, too, was a brilliant orator. And it was
this engagement, between Bryan and Darrow, rather than either the
teaching of evolution or its scientific truths, which lay at the heart of
this trial. To be sure, the action began as a defence of the protection of
civil liberties and the necessary separation of Church and State, and
this was initiated as a test case by the American Civil Liberties Union
(ACLU). To their dismay, Darrow effectively imposed himself, offer-
ing to waive fees in his determination to ridicule and thereby crush
the forces of religious obscurantism and, quite incidentally, maintain
his public profile. Before long, the ACLU effectively lost control of
events as Darrow hijacked the circus for his own good purposes. Op-
posed to him, with Bryan as its senior spokesman, was a largely rural
constituency that possessed a heartfelt, if largely inarticulate, belief
heresy! heresy!! 321
agenda that has curious echoes of the very systems they purport to
despise.
genetic fundamentalism
That biology can be co-opted for agendas, if not ideologies, that
promise an ever-more-perfect future, albeit across piles of corpses,
is evident from the lunacies adopted by totalitarian states. Such mad-
ness is, of course, a thing of the past – or is it? Now new distortions
beckon, not least those to be allowed by assigning a protean mal-
leability to life as engendered by genuflection to the primacy of the
gene. Now the gene is all-powerful. Susan Oyama37 describes genes as
‘molecular agencies that are immortal, omnipotent, omniscient, and
even immaterial’.38 In a related vein, Peter Koslowski’s39 critique of
this view, as it has been offered by Dawkins, defines an approach that
‘concedes a faculty for aspiration, intentionality and consciousness
to the genes. In doing so, he [Dawkins] falls into a genetic animism,
which apportions perception and decision to the genes and oversub-
scribes by far to the efficiency and the speed of Darwinian selection
mechanisms.’40
Such critiques differ greatly from the popular notion of the gene,
which does indeed seem to be able to act as a universal agency. The
spectacular examples of genetically controlled defects, not to mention
the generation of ectopic monsters with hideously sprouting organs,
reveal the potency of the gene. So, too, in examples of caste structure,
especially in eusocial animals (p. 142), the paradox of sterile workers
ceaselessly toiling for the benefit of the hive or nest is explicable by
a proportion of their genes surviving41 even though they themselves
either cannot or will not reproduce.
A closer examination, however, reveals that these particular ex-
amples fall far short of allowing the gene per se a universal application.
In her essay ‘The gene is dead – long live the gene!’ Eva Neumann-
Held42 argues that regarding the genes generally as particulate objects
of heredity is hopelessly simplistic. The genes make sense only in a
known context, but in reality to know in sufficient detail a context
that will provide the sought-after predictability may be very difficult,
perhaps impossible. That is why it is so misleading, if not dangerous,
to speak of genes for, say, schizophrenia or aggression. Given the right
set of prompts (who knows, perhaps plenty of junk food?) then the risk
could increase – or decrease. And what else are we meant to expect?
324 towards a theology of evolution
Outside its cellular milieu the DNA is biologically inert, if not use-
less. Genes may provide a switchboard for life, but the complexity of
life will depend on something else: how the same genes may be re-
cruited to make different products, how the developmental networks
change and evolve, and how apparently trivial events such as gene
duplication and protein isoforms open immense new territories for
biological exploration. Life may be impossible without genes, but to
ascribe to them powers of intentionality misses the mark.
Despite these qualifications, however, the hard-core view that
claims primacy of the gene holds sway. In some hands, perhaps most
notably those of the sociobiologist E. O. Wilson, it is a vehicle of
unbounded faith both in its power and in terms of its implications,
not least for the human prospect. This is spelt out, for example, in
Consilience,43 which is an extended belief-statement in an overarch-
ing system where all will be explained – society, art, religion – by
the gene. Wilson expresses himself with fervour and conviction, but a
more dispassionate reading of Consilience leaves me more impressed
by Wilson’s faith in the argument, accompanied by leaps in logic, un-
warranted assumptions, and over-simplification.44 And the world pic-
ture of genetic primacy has a well-known parallel, that is, the mental
equivalents of genes. They too are all-purpose, if elusive, little things
that are known as memes. Perhaps that irritating little tune that con-
tinues to bounce around your head is a meme? One cannot but no-
tice how trivial many of the examples presented are, unless it is to
portray the sheer wickedness of religious beliefs inculcated into the
brains of morally helpless humans. Happily, the alternative religions
of consumerism and shopping are arrived at by the exercise of human
dignity, unpersuaded by anything remotely like a meme. So, too, in
a way reminiscent of the notion of ‘junk’ DNA, one cannot help but
notice that the discussion of memes is often pejoratively associated
with some notion of ‘mind-parasites’. But memes are trivial, to be ban-
ished by simple mental exercises. In any wider context they are hope-
lessly, if not hilariously, simplistic. To conjure up memes not only
reveals a strange imprecision of thought, but, as Anthony O’Hear45
has remarked, if memes really existed they would ultimately deny
the reality of reflective thought.
These views on genes and memes matter very much, because
granting such molecular (or memal) hegemony puts us back firmly
on the path towards the Abolition of Man.46 And yet the rot started
genetic fundamentalism 325
a path to recovery?
The corrosive view that all in this world is to be bent to our pleasure
or whim is hedged in reality with expediencies and half-truths, and
in the view of many represents the royal road to catastrophe. So how
might we begin to think about, let alone achieve, a Recovery? First,
we need to recall the limits to science. It is no bad thing to remind
ourselves of our finitude, and of those things we might never know.
Practically, we should not be afraid to acknowledge that there are ar-
eas that Roger Shattuck calls Forbidden knowledge,54 too dangerous
in our present state of understanding to explore. At its simplest it is
a precautionary principle, and more significantly a belated acknowl-
edgement that the architecture of the Universe need not be simply
physical. We should also recall, as if we needed reminding, that we
are mortal and limited, and thus should remember that the old myths
of unrestricted curiosity and the corruption of power are not neces-
sarily fables.55
Second, for all its objectivity science, by definition, is a human
construct, and offers no promise of final answers. We should, however,
a path to recovery? 327
who took religion seriously, noted, other descriptions have their own
power. In Personal knowledge58 he writes:
The book of Genesis and its great pictorial illustrations, like the
frescoes of Michelangelo, remain a far more intelligent account of
the nature and origin of the universe than the representation of
the world as a chance collocation of atoms. For the biblical
cosmology continues to express – however inadequately – the
significance of the fact that the world exists and that man has
emerged from it, while the scientific picture denies any meaning
to the world, and indeed ignores all our most vital experience of
this world. The assumption that the world has some meaning
which is linked to our own calling as the only morally responsible
beings in the world, is an important example of the supernatural
aspect of experience which Christian interpretations of the
universe explore and develop.59
So, at some point and somehow, given that evolution has pro-
duced sentient species with a sense of purpose, it is reasonable to
take the claims of theology seriously. In recent years there has been a
resurgence of interest in the connections that might serve to reunify
the scientific world-view with the religious instinct. Much of the dis-
cussion is tentative, and the difficulties in finding an accommodation
remain daunting, but it is more than worth the effort. In my opinion
it will be our lifeline.
converging on convergence
The principal aim of this book has been to show that the constraints
of evolution and the ubiquity of convergence make the emergence
of something like ourselves a near-inevitability. Contrary to received
wisdom and the prevailing ethos of despair, the contingencies of bio-
logical history will make no long-term difference to the outcome. Yet
the existence of life itself on the Earth appears to be surrounded with
improbabilities. To reiterate: life may be a universal principle, but we
can still be alone. Whether or not this is literally true may never be
established, and, as many of us have argued, it is far more prudent to
assume that we are unique, and to act accordingly.60
Yet now we are faced with a special dilemma. The very scientific
method that allows us to study the natural world, be it interstellar or-
ganic molecules or memory in dolphins, also gives us tools that treat
converging on convergence 329
the world as endlessly malleable, ostensibly for the common good but
as often as not for the enrichment of the few and the impoverishment
of the many. Such attitudes fly in the face of traditional wisdoms,
and in part explain the existing antagonisms between scientific prac-
tices and religious sensibilities. Mutual misunderstandings, fuelled by
naivety and ignorance, can only lead to warfare. Although science may
emerge triumphant, it will be a pyrrhic victory; the conquered king-
dom will lie in ruins, strewn across a plain of infinite melancholy.
Constructive approaches are more difficult, and are usually viewed
with contempt, but I believe promise far more. In essence, we can
ask ourselves what salient facts of evolution are congruent with a
Creation. In my judgement, they are as follows:
the fact that he is not a beetle. The most brilliant exponent of the
egoistic school, Nietzsche, with deadly and honourable logic,
admitted that the philosophy of self-satisfaction led to looking
down upon the weak, the cowardly, and the ignorant.63
The vehicle landed at 15.47 GMT, just over a mile from Kimmeridge,
on the south coast of England. ‘Just in time for tea?’ murmured my
companion, as we climbed through the long grass, insects rising in
the summer air. There, already sitting on the ground, were the three
extraterrestrials. As we joined them, I asked, ‘Would you like some
water?’ ‘Or perhaps something stronger?’ suggested my companion.
‘Thank you’, came the grave reply. ‘We ourselves are thirsty, on such
a warm day. And maybe something for our plants?’ The chlorophyll
of the alien species blended well with the surrounding vegetation, its
flowers a deep purple. When our visitor picked up one of the pots,
it slipped and in catching it he grazed his finger. Red blood oozed
to the surface. ‘Haemoglobin, I suppose?’ They nodded. Our hands
clasped, both warm to the touch. It seemed superfluous to ask, but
the beating of a vein hinted at the inevitable dual circulation sys-
tem and arteries with their elastic proteins. One of them sniffed the
air appreciatively; the world smelt beautiful as their and our nasal
glomeruli registered the olfactory signals. As the swallows screamed
overhead, the minute hairs in our ears and the auditory equivalents
of the extraterrestrials acted in the same way, transducing the sound
into a register of inner music. ‘Observe the pointed wings of those
flying animals – swallows, did you say? – clearly migrants, just as at
home.’ We strolled slowly back down the hill, towards the sea. Des-
pite the steepness of the slope, the aliens were confident, their bal-
ancing mechanisms the same, their walking movements controlled
by the same neural network. We stopped on the cliff edge; in the
bay three dolphins moved westwards. ‘Fast and effective swimmers,
I see; what other shape could they possibly have?’ All of us looked
at them with common delight, through camera-eyes, lenses full of
crystallins and retinas with opsin molecules making photons into
sight. By now dusk was falling, Venus already bright in the sky. It
was time to go home. ‘Before you leave, may I ask where you are
332 last word
from? Was it a very long journey?’ But we already had guessed. ‘A long
journey? Well, only in some ways. Where is our home? Why, the
planet we call Earth, of course. Surely you already knew in your
hearts that there is only one Earth?’ We were, of course, looking at
ourselves.
Notes
A note about the notes. The principal aim is to give citations, chapter and verse, to the many
facts, interpretations, and sources I give. Many more could have been given, but I hope they
form a useful introduction. Where a reference is repeated the original note is also cited. There
are also a few cross-chapter citations.
paper by P. Müller and D. Robert in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 204, pp. 1039–1052,
2001; see also note 305 in Chapter 7.
3. For this and other remarkable examples of long-distance navigation see F. Papi and P. Luschi
in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 199, pp. 65–71, 1996.
4. See Simon Winchester’s book The river at the centre of the world: A journey up the Yangtze,
and back in Chinese time (Viking [Penguin], London, 1997), pp. 96–97.
5. But not necessarily; A. Eyre-Walker in Genetics (vol. 152, pp. 675–683, 1999) provides
evidence of selection in the evolution of junk DNA of junk DNA, while W. Makalowski (in
Gene, vol. 354, pp. 61–67, 2000) argues that it is more like a genomic scrapyard, to be pillaged
as and when necessary. Others, such as R. N. Mantegna et al. in Physical Review Letters, vol.
73, pp. 3169–3172, 1994 suggest that junk DNA encodes information analogous to the
structure of language (specifically an equivalent to Zipf’s law, where the total numbers of
occurrences of words in a text fall on a linear distribution when plotted on a log–log scale, and
also find evidence for redundancy whereby meaning is preserved even with deletions). These
views are questioned and replied to in a subsequent issue (vol. 76, pp. 1976–1981).
6. See L. Z. Holland and N. D. Holland in American Zoologist, vol. 38, pp. 647–658, 1998;
W. R. Jackman et al. in Developmental Biology, vol. 220, pp. 16–26, 2000; H. Toresson et al.
in Development, Genes, and Evolution, vol. 208, pp. 431–439, 1998; T. V. Venkatesh et al. in
Development, Genes, and Evolution, vol. 209, 254–259, 1999; H. Wada et al. in
Developmental Biology, vol. 213, pp. 131–141, 1999; and N. C. Williams and P. W. H. Holland
in Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 15, pp. 600–607, 1998.
7. See T. C. Lacalli et al. in Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B,
vol. 344, pp. 165–185, 1994, and vol. 351, pp. 243–263, 1996, as well as Acta Zoologica
(Stockholm), vol. 80, pp. 113–124, 1999 and Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B,
vol. 266, pp. 1461–1470, 1999.
8. See P. W. H. Holland in Development (Supplement 1994), pp. 125–133, 1994; American
Zoologist, vol. 38, pp. 829–842, 1998; and Seminars in Cell & Developmental Biology,
vol. 10, pp. 541–547, 1999.
9. Such examples are known from the Lower Cambrian (Chengjiang fossil assemblages): see
D. Shu et al. in Nature, vol. 384, pp. 157–158, 1996; and from the Middle Cambrian (Burgess
Shale): see papers by A. M. Simonetta et al. in Bollettino di Zoologia, vol. 62, pp. 243–252,
1995 and Italian Journal of Zoology, vol. 66, pp. 99–119, 1999.
10. This remarkable article, by Temple Smith and Harold Morowitz, entitled ‘Between physics
and history’, was published in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 18, pp. 265–282, 1982.
11. See especially W. M. Elsasser’s insights into what he calls very large and immense numbers,
in Reflections on a theory of organisms: holism in biology (Johns Hopkins University Press,
Baltimore, 1998). This equally strange and stimulating book is, as its subtitle indicates,
definitely anti-reductionist. Also very relevant to this question is Information and the origin
of life by B-O Küppers (MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 1990); see especially Chapters 6
and 7.
12. They are probably most familiar in the form of the digestive enzymes such as trypsin and
amylases, but they are essential in all parts of the cellular economy. Other enzymes are
essential for dealing with a stiff gin and tonic; here you need alcohol dehydrogenase.
13. T. Smith and H. Morowitz (1982; citation is in note 10), p. 268.
14. T. Smith and H. Morowitz (1982; citation is in note 10); both quotations are on p. 268.
15. See the short article on ‘Laws of forms revisited’, by M. Denton and C. Marshall in Nature,
vol. 410, p. 417, 2001. See also M. J. Denton et al. in Journal of Theoretical Biology, vol. 219,
pp. 325–342, 2002.
16. M. Denton and C. Marshall (2001; citation is in note 15), p. 417.
17. See, for example, the paper by Y-H. Lee et al. in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 45,
pp. 278–284, 1997, where they show how pathways through RNA sequence space may be
equally parsimonious, but not equally likely.
notes to pp. 12–15 335
18. Stephen Freeland reminds me, however, that while this axiom seems sensible, ‘the only
explicit rationale for this view is Fisher’s geometric theorem (in his The genetical theory of
natural selection [Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1930; see pp. 38–41]); a simple abstract model of
evolution that predicts an inversely proportional relationship between the magnitude of
effect of a random mutation and the probability that it will represent an adaptive
improvement’; see Freeland’s article in Journal of Genetic Programming and Evolvable
Machines, vol. 3, pp. 113–127, 2002.
19. Symbiosis means ‘living together’, and, although the term is often thought to be synonymous
with mutual benefit, biologists take a symbiosis to be a neutral term that can, if sufficient
information is available, be resolved as benefit (+), loss (−), or neither (0). Parasitism usually
has a winner (the parasite) and a loser (the host), thus (+)(−), unless each parasitizes the other,
i.e. (−)(−).
20. T. Smith and H. Morowitz (1982; citation is in note 10), p. 280.
21. This conceit of ‘Different routes to similar ends’ is specifically addressed by P. H. Harvey and
L. Partridge in Nature, vol. 392, pp. 552–553, 1998, as well as by the first author writing in
Current Biology, vol. 10, p. R271, 2000.
22. That may be the natural order, but biotechnological manipulation makes it possible to
introduce novel amino acids, thus artificially expanding the genetic code. See, for example,
L. Wang et al. in Science, vol. 292, pp. 498–500, 2001, and the following paper (pp. 501–504)
by V. Döring et al., as well as the commentary by A. Böch on pp. 453–454; see also M. Ibba
et al. in Current Biology, vol. 11, pp. R563–R565, 2001.
23. See the chapter (pp. 21–27) by J. M. Diamond in Principles of animal design: the optimization
and symmorphosis debate, edited by E. R. Weibel et al. (Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 1998). The graphic predicament of the lift plunging to its doom is based on
remarks made by Diamond in a lecture he gave in Cambridge.
24. See Henry Petroski’s Design paradigms: case histories of error and judgement in engineering
(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1994). The book is an absorbing discussion of the
trials, tribulations, and daring of bridge builders; Petroski’s remarks on the sociology of
engineering knowledge and tradition are also of great, and sometimes alarming, interest.
25. See, for example, G. M. Taylor et al. in Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, vol. 70,
pp. 37–62, 2000. They address safety factors in the claws of crabs, and also give a useful
introduction to the literature of this area.
26. Carl Gans ‘Momentarily excessive construction as the basis for protoadaptation’ is the title of
his paper in Evolution, vol. 33, pp. 227–233, 1979.
27. See Kea, bird of paradox: the evolution and behavior of a New Zealand parrot, by J. Diamond
and A. B. Bond (University of California Press, Berkeley, 1999).
28. See John Currey’s paper in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 202, pp. 3285–3294,
1999.
29. See J. D. Currey et al. in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 268, pp. 107–111,
2001, and also V. de Buffrénil and A. Casinos in Annales des Sciences naturelles, Zoologie,
Paris, vol. 16, pp. 21–32, 1995.
30. J. D. Currey (1999, citation is in note 28), p. 3289. In his paper Currey also draws attention to
the convergence between the teeth of the sea urchins (on which see R. Z. Wang et al. in
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 352, pp. 469–480, 1997),
which rasp the sea floor for edibles, and the gnawing incisors of the rodents.
31. The key papers are by Steve Freeland and Laurence Hurst in Journal of Molecular Evolution,
vol. 47, pp. 238–248, 1998 and Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 17, pp. 511–518, 2000a;
see also Trends in Biochemical Sciences, vol. 25, pp. 44–45, 2000b.
32. Concerning the optimitality of two base pairs see E. Szathmary in Proceedings of the Royal
Society of London B, vol. 245, pp. 91–99, 1991, and Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, USA, vol. 89, pp. 2614–2618, 1992. See also D. A. Mac Donaill in Chemical
Communications, vol. 18, pp. 2062–2063, 2002.
336 notes to pp. 15–23
33. A. L. Weber and S. L. Miller, in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 17, pp. 273–284, 1981,
draw on various lines of evidence (including prebiotic synthesis, stability, and function in
proteins) to argue that the 20 terrestrial amino acids are the norm.
34. A. L. Weber and S. L. Miller (1981, citation is in note 33), p. 273.
35. A. Jiménez-Sánchez, however, suggests (in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 41,
pp. 712–716, 1995) that the original arrangement in an ‘RNA world’ (see note 1, Chapter 4)
was still triplets (and one base pair (AU)), coding for seven amino acids (and a stop codon).
36. See J. T. Wong in Microbiological Science, vol. 5, pp. 174–181, 1988. R. Amirnovin in Journal
of Molecular Evolution, vol. 44, pp. 473–476, 1997, concludes that much depends on which
amino acids are assumed to have a biosynthetic linkage. M. Di Giulio and M. Medugno,
however, present a statistically based critique of Amirnovin’s idea in a subsequent issue
(vol. 50, pp. 258–263, 2000), reasserting their belief in ‘the intimate relationship between the
biosynthetic pathways of amino acids and the organization of the genetic code’ (p. 263). On
the other hand, T. A. Ronneberg et al. (in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
USA, vol. 97, pp. 13690–13695, 2000) speak strongly against the importance of biosynthetic
pathways, although they also emphasize that code expansion almost certainly occurred.
37. S. Freeland and L. Hurst (1998; citation is in note 31), p. 244.
38. S. Freeland et al. (2000b; citation is in note 31), p. 45.
39. It should be pointed out that the conclusions reached by Freeland and Hurst are not
universally accepted. See M. Di Giulio and M. Medugno in Journal of Molecular Evolution,
vol. 52, pp. 378–382, 2001, who argue that the effectiveness of the genetic code lies in a
co-evolution between the code and the biosynthetic pathways leading to the various amino
acids.
40. For example, the codons UAA and UAG, which nearly always mean stop, have been
reassigned in several unrelated groups to code for glycine. The evolvability of the genetic code
is reviewed by R. D. Knight et al. in Nature Reviews, Genetics, vol. 2, pp. 49–58, 2001, who
remark (p. 49) ‘Curiously, many of the same codons are reassigned in independent lineages,
frequently between the same two meanings . . . indicating that there may be an underlying
predisposition towards certain reassignments. At least one of these changes seems to confer a
direct selective advantage.’
41. See, for example, M. Guilio and M. Medugno in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 49,
pp. 1–10, 1999.
42. See Geoffrey Irwin’s book The prehistoric exploration and colonisation of the Pacific
(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1992).
37. See J. P. Dougherty in Journal of the American Chemical Society, vol. 114, pp. 6254–6255,
1992.
38. See T. L. Sheppard and R. Breslow in Journal of the American Chemical Society, vol. 118,
pp. 9810–9811, 1996.
39. The key review papers may be found by Albert Eschenmoser and colleagues in Science
(vol. 284, pp. 2118–2124, 1999) and Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere (vol. 24,
pp. 389–423, 1994 and vol. 27, pp. 535–553, 1997).
40. See K. D. James and A. D. Ellington in Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, vol. 25,
pp. 515–530, 1995; quotation is on p. 520.
41. Thus K. D. James and A. D. Ellington (1995; citation is in note 40) remark on work by the
Eschenmoser team that they ‘have concluded that very few [alternatives] can potentially form
complementary duplexes that would in theory be capable of self-replication . . . These
conclusions can be extended to nucleic acid bases as well as sugars: experiments with
alternate base pairing schemes have suggested that the current set of purines and pyrimidines
is in many ways optimal . . . the unnatural nucleic acid analogues that have been examined
experimentally have proven to be largely incapable of self-replication,’ p. 520.
42. ‘Why pentose – and not hexose – nucleic acids?’ is the main title of the paper by S. Pitsch
et al. in Helvetica Chimica Acta, vol. 76, pp. 2161–2183, 1993, and is answered with respect
to ‘a whole series of intrinsic steric handicaps’ (p. 2163). In his overview Eschenmoser (1999;
citation is in note 39) concluded that ‘The outcome of these studies has led to the conclusion
that for functional reasons, the three hexopyranosyl-(4 -6 ) oligonucleotide systems
investigated . . . could not have acted as viable competitors of RNA in the emergence of
nature’s genetic system’ (p. 2121).
43. Concerning alternatives to ribose, as five-carbon (pentose) sugars, see M. Beier et al. in
Science, vol. 283, pp. 699–703, 1999.
44. See the paper by K.-U. Schöning et al. in Science, vol. 290, pp. 1347–1351, 2000, as well as a
commentary by L. Orgel on pp. 1306–1307.
45. A. Eschemoser (1999; citation is in note 39), p. 2122.
27. Reviews can be found in a chapter (pp. 819–857) by J. R. Cronin et al. in Meteorites and the
early Solar System, edited by J. F. Kerridge and M. S. Matthews (University of Arizona Press,
Tucson, 1988), and The molecular origins of life: assembling pieces of the puzzle, edited by
A. Brack (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1998); see in particular pp. 119–146.
28. See, for example, P. G. Stoks and A. W. Schwartz in Geochimica et Cosmochimica Acta,
vol. 45, pp. 563–569, 1981.
29. See D. W. Deamer and R. M. Pashley in Origins of life and evolution of the biosphere, vol. 19,
pp. 21–38, 1989; see also J. P. Dworkin et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, USA, vol. 98, pp. 815–819, 2001.
30. Right-handed, or dextral (d-), amino acids do arise in various metabolic processes; see
D-amino acids in sequences of secreted peptides of multicellular organisms, edited by
D. Jollès (Birkhauser, Basel, 1998).
31. J. L. Bada et al. (Nature, vol. 301, pp. 494–496, 1983) gave a careful critique of M. H. Engel and
B. Nagy in Nature (vol. 296, pp. 837–840, 1982) and received in return a robust response.
32. See J. R. Cronin and S. Pizzarello in Science (vol. 275, pp. 951–955, 1997) and commentary on
pp. 942–943 by J. L. Bada; see also S. Pizzarello and J. R. Cronin in Geochimica et Cosmochimica
Acta, vol. 64, pp. 329–338, 2000 and M. H. Engel & S. A. Macko in Precambrian Research,
vol. 106, pp. 35–45, 2001. Subsequently, S. Pizzarello and G. W. Cooper (in Meteoritics &
Planetary Science, vol. 36, pp. 897–909, 2001) reported that alanine was originally racemic,
but an l-enantiomeric excess in glutamic acid was probably terrestrial contamination.
33. See, for example, J. Bailey et al. in Science, vol. 281, pp. 672–674, 1998, and accompanying
commentary by R. Irion on pp. 626–627. Their observation is based on infrared radiation, but
it is assumed that the UV part of the spectrum, which is energetic enough to break chemical
bonds, is also polarized. This is not to say that all such amino acids will be non-racemic.
Laboratory studies of the analogue of ultraviolet radiation on interstellar ices produced a
variety of amino acids, but these are racemic. See M. P. Bernstein et al. and G. M. Muñoz
Caro et al. in Nature, vol. 416, pp. 401–403 and 403–406 respectively, 2002, and commentary
by E. L. Shock on pp. 380–381.
34. See the paper in Nature (vol. 405, pp. 932–935, 2000) by G. L. J. A. Rikken and E. Raupach, as
well as the commentary by L. D. Barron on pp. 895–896.
35. See K. Soai et al. in Nature, vol. 378, pp. 767–768, 1995. Again the excess is small (about 2%),
and the chemistry seems to have rather little relevance to the origin of life.
36. See R. M. Hazen et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 98,
pp. 5487–5490, 2001. See also the paper by C. A. Orme et al. (Nature, vol. 411, pp. 775–779,
2001, with commentary by L. Addadi and S. Weiner on pp. 753, 755).
37. For an overview see Comets and the origin and evolution of life, edited by P. J. Thomas et al.
(Springer, New York, 1997), especially chapter 6 (pp. 147–173) by C. F. Chyba and C. Sagan.
38. Produced by ultraviolet irradiation in simulated interstellar conditions of PAH napthalene;
see M. P. Bernstein et al. in Meteoritics & Planetary Science, vol. 36, pp. 351–358, 2001.
Quinones are an important building block of chlorophyll, which in Chapter 6 is argued to be
the molecule of choice wherever in the Universe photosynthesis occurs.
39. See E. Pierazzo and C. F. Chyba in Meteoritics & Planetary Science, vol. 34, pp. 909–918, 1999.
5. Bartel and Unrau (1999; citation is in note 4), p. M9. See also notes 44 and 45.
6. See L. E. Orgel in Trends in Biochemical Sciences, vol. 23, pp. 491–495, 1998.
7. See L. E. Orgel in Trends in Biochemical Sciences, vol. 23, p. 491, 1998.
8. See, for example, A. Bar-Nun and A. Shaviv in Icarus, vol. 24, pp. 197–210, 1975; W. L.
Chameides and J. C. G. Walker in Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, vol. 11,
pp. 291–302, 1981; and J. P. Ferris and W. J. Hagan in Tetrahedron, vol. 40, pp. 1093–1120,
1984.
9. See Manfred Eigen’s influential article, entitled ‘Selforganization of matter and the evolution
of biological macromolecules’, in Die Naturwissenschaften, vol. 58, pp. 465–523, 1971; and
Steps towards life: A perspective on evolution (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1992).
10. See John Maynard-Smith in Nature, vol. 280, pp. 445–446, 1979.
11. See D. H. Lee et al. in Current Opinion in Chemical Biology, vol. 1, pp. 491–496, 1997.
12. See D. H. Lee et al. in Nature, vol. 390, pp. 591–594, 1997.
13. See Klaus Dose’s essay ‘The origin of life: More questions than answers’ in Interdisciplinary
Science Reviews, vol. 13, pp. 348–356, 1988. Although this article is more than ten years old,
little has changed to suggest we should take a more optimistic view.
14. Dose (1988; citation is in note 13), quotations are on pp. 348 and 349.
15. See John Horgan’s stimulating article in Scientific American, vol. 264(2), pp. 100–109, 1991.
16. In terms of general scepticism, the key text is Robert Shapiro’s book Origins, with the telling
subtitle A skeptic’s guide to the creation of life on Earth (Bantam, New York, 1987); I have
frequent recourse to Shapiro’s ideas later in this chapter. A generally sceptical view can also
be found in Chapter 16 of the book Blueprints: Solving the mystery of evolution (Oxford
University Press, Oxford, 1990) by M. A. Edey and D. C. Johanson.
17. J. Horgan (1991, citation is in note 15), p. 101.
18. See Anthony Keefe and Stanley Miller’s paper on ‘Potentially prebiotic syntheses of condensed
phosphates’ in Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, vol. 26, pp. 15–25, 1996.
19. A. Keefe and S. Miller (1996; citation is in note 18), p. 15.
20. Concerning its photochemical production in a prebiotic atmosphere, see J. P. Pinto et al. in
Science, vol. 210, pp. 183–185, 1980.
21. See R. Shapiro’s ‘Prebiotic ribose synthesis: a critical analysis’ in Origins of Life and
Evolution of the Biosphere, vol. 18, pp. 71–85, 1988; see also note 16.
22. L. E. Shapiro (1988; citation is in note 21), p. 83.
23. See T. Mizuno and A. H. Weiss in Advances in Carbohydrate Chemistry and Biochemistry,
vol. 29, pp. 173–227, 1974.
24. See R. Larralde et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 92,
pp. 8158–8160, 1995.
25. See D. Müller et al. in Helvetica Chimica Acta, vol. 73, pp. 1410–1468, 1990.
26. See G. Zubay’s paper in Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, vol. 28, pp. 13–26,
1998.
27. G. Zubay (1998; citation is in note 26), p. 19. This work is returned to by G. Zubay and T. Mui
in a subsequent issue of Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere (vol. 31, pp. 87–102,
2001), as part of a discussion of nucleotide synthesis. As usual, the general tone is upbeat, but
problems remain: ‘Limited success has been achieved in the synthesis of inosine . . . The
situation for adenosine is much worse . . . For several years we have tried in vain to improve
this system’, p. 100.
28. See K-U. Schöning et al. in Science, vol. 290, pp. 1347–1351, 2000; see also note 43, Chapter 2.
29. See, for example, the papers by J. P. Ferris et al. in Nature, vol. 381, pp. 59–61, 1996 (with
commentary on pp. 20–21 by G. von Kiedrowski) and A. R. Hill et al. and R. Liu and L. Orgel
in Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, vol. 28, pp. 235–243 and 245–257, 1998
respectively.
30. See Ferris et al. (1996), and S. J. Sowerby et al. (in Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, USA, vol. 98, pp. 820–822, 2001), which explored the differential adsorption of the
various nucleic acid bases on tiny particles of natural graphite, which the authors duly note
342 notes to pp. 53–56
‘is not considered a dominant prebiotic material’, followed by a prompt appeal to ‘zeolites,
feldspars and silicas’, p. 821.
31. See, for example, A. W. Schwartz and L. E. Orgel on ‘Template-directed synthesis of novel,
nucleic acid-like structures’ in Science, vol. 228, pp. 585–587, 1985.
32. R. Liu and L. Orgel (1998; citation is in note 29), pp. 256–257.
33. See Graham Cairns-Smith’s Genetic takeover and the mineral origins of life (Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge, 1982). Nevertheless, so far as I am aware no experimental work
has provided a reality check on this hypothesis, and in more recent discussions of the origin
of life these ideas typically receive routine genuflection rather than any serious engagement.
34. See F. G. Mosqueira et al. in Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, vol. 26, pp. 75–94,
1996.
35. F. G. Mosqueira et al. (1996; citation is in note 34), p. 92.
36. See J. D. Bernal in The physical basis of life (Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1951); Bernal’s
emphasis was very much on clay minerals, as well as quartz (pp. 33–37).
37. See, for example, M. Levy and S. L. Miller in Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, USA, vol. 95, 7933–7938, 1998, with specific reference to the thermal stability of
the nucleotides.
38. See Robert Shapiro in Planetary dreams: The quest to discover life beyond Earth (Wiley, New
York, 1999). This book echoes his interests and scepticisms about present attempts to
discover how life originated, but it is also both a passionate plea for the exploration of outer
space combined with a deep, almost religious, conviction that life is a universal principle.
Shapiro writes with a flair and accessibility that is difficult to match.
39. R. Shapiro (1999; citation is in note 38), p. 137.
40. G. Wächtershäuser has promoted his ideas widely and at some length; see, for example, his
papers in Progress in Biophysics and Molecular Biology, vol. 58, pp. 85–201, 1988;
Microbiological Reviews, vol. 52, pp. 452–484, 1988; and his chapter (on pp. 206–218) in The
molecular origins of life: assembling pieces of the puzzle, edited by A. Brack (Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge, 1998). An excellent overview of Wächtershäuser’s programme is
given by Fry (1999; citation is in note 1), pp. 162–172.
41. See, for example, E. Blöchl et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA,
vol. 89, pp. 8117–8120, 1992; D. Hafenbradl et al. in Tetrahedron Letters, vol. 36,
pp. 5179–5184, 1995; the two papers by C. Huber and G. Wächtershäuser in Science,
respectively vol. 276, pp. 245–247, 1997 and vol. 281, pp. 670–672, 1998 (with accompanying
commentary by G. Vogel on p. 627 and 629); W. Heinen and A. M. Lauwers in Origins of Life
and Evolution of the Biosphere, vol. 26, pp. 131–150, 1996; and G. D. Cody et al. in Science,
vol. 289, pp. 1337–1340, 2000 (with commentary by G. Wächtershäuser on pp. 1307–1308,
who remarks of these experiments ‘It remains to be established whether such conditions [200
MPa, 250 ◦ C] are geophysically possible’).
42. Experiments, promoted by those sceptical of the Wächtershäuser school, have looked at
prebiotic amino acid and nucleotide synthesis in a FeS/H2 S system and produced negative
results; see A. D. Keefe et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA,
vol. 92, pp. 11904–11906, 1995; see also the somewhat sceptical tenor of M. A. A. Schoonen
et al. in Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, vol. 29, pp. 5–32, 1999.
43. The paper by M. J. Russell and A. J. Hall in Journal of the Geological Society, London,
vol. 154, pp. 377–402, 1997 is a case in point. Despite its encouraging title ‘The emergence of
life from iron monosulphide bubbles at a submarine hydrothermal redox and pH front’, this
particular paper is strong on theory and expectations, but which pathways will ultimately
prove experimentally tractable is less obvious.
44. See Andrew Ellington’s brief overview in Biological Bulletin, vol. 196, pp. 315–319, 1999.
45. A. Ellington (1999; citation is in note 44), p. 317.
46. Literature on hydrothermal locales as the site for the shift from abiogenetic chemical
processes to life is fast expanding. Relevant material includes J. P. Amend and E. L. Shock in
notes to pp. 56–62 343
Science, vol. 281, pp. 1659–1662, 1998; J. P. Ferris in Origins of life and evolution of the
biosphere, vol. 22, pp. 109–134, 1992; N. G. Holm and E. M. Andersson in Planetary and
Space Science, vol. 43, pp. 153–159, 1995; E.-i. Imai et al. in Science, vol. 283, pp. 831–833,
1999; E. L. Shock and M. D. Schulte in Journal of Geophysical Research, vol. 103E, pp. 28,
513–28, 527, 1998; and N. G. Holm and J. L. Charlou in Earth and Planetary Science Letters,
vol. 191, pp. 1–8, 2001. See also note 72.
47. See, for example, N. R. Pace in Cell, vol. 65, pp. 531–533, 1991.
48. See, for example, V. Moulton et al. in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 51, pp. 416–421,
2000, who argue that the necessary folding of RNA is prejudiced at elevated temperatures,
although they are careful to note that this does not rule out other stages in the trek from
abiogenesis occuring in hot environments.
49. See M. Gogarten-Boekels et al. in Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, vol. 25,
pp. 251–264, 1995.
50. See, for example, P. Forterre et al. in Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, vol. 25,
pp. 235–249, 1995. Interestingly, in the context of Chapter 10, they argue that the key enzyme
used to stabilize DNA in hyperthermophiles, known as reverse gyrase, is actually a composite
and ‘originated from the “late” fusion of a bona fide DNA helicase and DNA topoisomerases
genes. Indeed many helicases and topoisomerases probably evolved independently from
different RNA-metabolizing enzymes of the RNA world . . . This is suggested by the existence
of several independent superfamilies of these enzymes’ (p. 241). See also note 21, Chapter 5.
51. See S. L. Miller and A. Lazcano in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 41, pp. 689–692, 1995.
52. From the experimental procedures given by Huber and Wächtershäuser (1998, citation is in
note 41), note 2 on p. 672 and Heinen and Lauwers (1996, citation is in note 41), p. 132.
53. See Leslie Orgel’s critique in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 97,
pp. 12503–12507, 2000.
54. L. E. Orgel (2000; citation is in note 53), p. 12506.
55. A. W. Schwartz and L. E. Orgel (1985, citation is in note 31), p. 586.
56. See S. J. Sowerby and W. M. Heckl in Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, vol. 28,
pp. 283–310, 1998.
57. S. J. Sowerby and W. M. Heckl (1998; citation is in note 56), p. 291.
58. S. J. Sowerby and W. M. Heckl (1998; citation is in note 56), p. 292.
59. S. J. Sowerby and W. M. Heckl (1998; citation is in note 56), p. 297.
60. See the paper by P. A. Bachmann et al. in Nature, vol. 357, pp. 57–59, 1992.
61. See C. Böhler et al. in Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere, vol. 26, pp. 1–5, 1996,
who report on the oligomerization of amino acids by micelles of CTAB, and also remark that
this process is achieved at ‘relatively concentrated aqueous solutions’ (i.e. 0.05 molar), but
with only a tenfold dilution ‘few long oligomers can be detected’, p. 1.
62. See L. E. Orgel in Nature, vol. 358, pp. 203–209, 1992.
63. L. E. Orgel (1992; citation is in note 62), p. 204.
64. L. E. Orgel (1992; citation is in note 62), p. 207
65. The original set of experiments by Stanley Miller and Harold Urey was published in Science,
vol. 117, pp. 528–529, 1953, and Journal of the American Chemical Society, vol. 77,
pp. 2351–2361, 1955.
66. Overviews by S. L. Miller et al. may be found in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 9,
pp. 59–72, 1976; Cold Spring Harbor Symposia on Quantitative Biology, vol. 52, pp. 17–27,
1987; and on pp. 59–85 of The molecular origins of life: assembling pieces of the puzzle,
edited by A. Brack (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1998).
67. See, for example, R. Stribling and S. L. Miller in Origins of Life and Evolution of the
Biosphere, vol. 17, pp. 261–273, 1987.
68. S. L. Miller et al. (1976; citation is in note 66), p. 64.
69. Toxic and corrosive? Within our biochemical citadels we take oxygen for granted, but rust
and raging forest fires are a more immediate reminder of the potency of oxygen.
344 notes to pp. 62–70
Reading, MA, 1996). See also J. Hartung in Meteoritics, vol. 11, pp. 187–194, 1975, and Lunar
Science, vol. VII, pp. 348–350, 1976. This interpretation was, however, queried by H. H.
Nininger and G. I. Huss in Meteoritics, vol. 12, pp. 21–25, 1977. They suggested that it might
more plausibly be interpreted as a meteorite that had entered the Earth’s atmosphere, but
happened to pass in front of the Moon’s disc, so being mistaken for an impact. There is a
further problem because such a major collision would lead to the ejection of huge quantities
of rubble, which would easily escape from the weak gravitational field of Moon and
subsequently be captured by the Earth. As P. Withers pointed out (in Meteoritics & Planetary
Sciences, vol. 36, pp. 525–529, 2001), this would have produced a spectacular week-long
meteor ‘storm’, for which there appears to be no historical evidence. Unless conditions were
very overcast in England during June 1178, the date of the inferred impact, it is unlikely that
Gervase would not have made some comment. This is because although Gervase’s chronicles
are mostly to do with matters of Church and State, he evidently had an eye for natural
phenomena. These included eclipses and, more remarkably, an earthquake in 1158 that was
felt across England. This is immediately followed by a report that in London the Thames
dried out so that people could cross it dry-shod, but this apparently is an unrelated
observation.
4 See W. K. Hartman et al. on pp. 493–512 of the book Origin of the Earth and the Moon, edited
by R. M. Canup and K. Righter (University of Arizona Press, Tucson, 2000). In their judicious
review they stress that the standard account of lunar bombardment, especially the intense
major episode at c. 3.8–4.2 Ga cannot be accepted uncritically, and various alternatives need
to be kept in mind. Evidence consistent with the late heavy bombardment episode, based on
the ages of meteorites that have come from the Moon, is given by B. A. Cohen et al. in
Science, vol. 290, pp. 1754–1756, 2000, while D. A. Kring and B. A. Cohen, in Journal of
Geophysical Research, vol. 107 (E2), pp. 4-1–4-6, 2002, review the evidence for this
cataclysmic episode throughout the inner Solar System.
5. See K. J. Zahnle and N. H. Sleep in their chapter (pp. 175–208) of Comets and the origin of
evolution of life, edited by P. J. Thomas et al. (Springer, New York, 1997).
6. A. Morbidelli et al. in Meteoritics & Planetary Science, vol. 36, pp. 371–380, 2001, suggest
that important components of the impactors were actually relatively small bolides, rather
than the monsters usually envisaged, whose high-inclination orbits relative to the planets of
the inner Solar System imparted high impact velocities.
7. See S. Chang on pp. 10–23 of Early Life on Earth, Nobel Symposium No. 84, edited by
S. Bengtson (Columbia University Press, New York, 1994).
8. These details are taken from the paper by N. H. Sleep and K. Zahnle in Journal of
Geophysical Research, vol. 103, pp. 28529–28544, 1998.
9. See, for example, A. P. Nutman et al. in Geochimica et Cosmochimica Acta, vol. 61,
pp. 2475–2484, 1997; Chemical Geology, vol. 141, pp. 271–287, 1997; and Precambrian
Research, vol. 78, pp. 1–39, 1996, as well as C. M. Fedo and M. J. Whitehouse in Science,
vol. 296, pp. 1448–1452, 2002.
10. Claims for actual fossils, such as yeast-like organisms described by H. D. Pflug in
Naturwissenschaften, vol. 65, pp. 611–615, 1978, have won almost no support.
11. Claims for an organic origin of the carbon, such as by S. J. Mojzsis et al. in Nature, vol. 384,
pp. 56–59, 1996 (with a cautious commentary by J. M. Hayes on pp. 21–22), have been
criticized; see J. M. Eiler et al. in vol. 386, p. 665, 1997. See also Fedo and Whitehouse (2002,
citation is in note 9) and M. A. van Zuilen et al. in Nature, vol. 418, pp. 627–630, 2002.
R. Schoenberg et al., in Science, vol. 418, pp. 403–405, 2002, suggest some of the carbon may
have a meteoric origin; see also A. D. Anbar et al. in Journal of Geophysical Research,
vol. 106E, pp. 3219–3236, 2001.
12. The isotopic studies of δ 13 C (i.e. the ratio of 12 C to 13 C) in the Isua Supergroup were pioneered
by M. Schidlowski (see Nature, vol. 333, pp. 313–318, 1988), and are consistent with more
recent work by M. T. Rosing in Science, vol. 283, pp. 674–676, 1999.
346 notes to pp. 73–77
13. Metamorphic gneisses from north-west Canada are dated at 3960 Ma by S. A. Bowring et al.
in Geology, vol. 17, pp. 971–975, 1989; mineral grains of zircons date back to c. 4400 Ma; see
S. A. Wilde et al. in Nature, vol. 409, pp. 175–178, 2001. Although these grains have been
reworked into younger rocks they still provide some indication of what the very early Earth
was like, and notably indicate the existence of some sort of ocean; see also S. J. Mojzsis et al.
in Nature, vol. 409, pp. 178–181, 2001.
14. See K. A. Maher and D. J. Stevenson in Nature, vol. 331, pp. 612–614, 1988; see also V. R.
Overbeck and G. Fogleman in vol. 339, p. 434, 1989, and N. H. Sleep et al. in vol. 342,
pp. 139–142, 1989. A more recent overview is given by K. J. Zahnle and N. H. Sleep (1997;
citation is in note 5).
15. Respective estimates are given by B. A. Cohen et al. (2000) and D. A. Kring and B. A. Cohen
(2002; citations in note 4).
16. See, for example, M. Gogarten-Boekels et al. in Origins of Life and Evolution of the
Biosphere, vol. 25, pp. 251–264, 1995; see also N. H. Sleep et al., in Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 98, pp. 3666–3672, 2001.
17. See V. R. Oberbeck and G. Fogleman in Origins of Life and Evolution of the Biosphere,
vol. 19, pp. 549–560, 1989; L. E. Orgel in a later issue (vol. 28, pp. 91–96, 1998) provides a
characteristically level-headed assessment of this topic.
18. See A. Lazcano and S. L. Miller in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 39, pp. 546–554, 1994.
19. See D. M. Raup and J. W. Valentine in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
USA, vol. 80, pp. 2981–2984, 1983.
20. See K. O. Stetter on pp. 1–18 (including the discussion) of a Ciba Foundation Symposium
(no. 202) Evolution of hydrothermal ecosystems on Earth (and Mars?), edited by G. R. Bock
and J. A. Goode (Wiley, Chichester, 1996).
21. See, for example, N. Galtier et al. in Science (vol. 283, pp. 220–221, 1999), as well as earlier
remarks by P. Forterre, for example, in Cell (vol. 85, pp. 789–792, 1996) and Current Opinion
in Genetics & Development (vol. 7, pp. 764–770, 1997); see also note 49, Chapter 4.
22. See N. H. Sleep and K. Zahnle (1998; citation is in note 8).
23. See J. W. Head et al. in Science (vol. 286, pp. 2134–2137, 1999). Other evidence for a much
more equable early climate on Mars is given by J. B. Pollack et al. in Icarus, vol. 71,
pp. 203–224, 1987; F. Forget and R. T. Pierrehumbert in Science, vol. 278, pp. 1273–1276,
1997; R. M. Huberle in Journal of Geophysical Research, vol. 103E, pp. 28467–28479, 1998;
and M. A. Mischna in Icarus, vol. 145, pp. 546–554, 2000.
24. One such recent announcement is of a discovery from the Oman desert, announced by E.
Gnos et al. in Meteoritics & Planetary Sciences, vol. 37, pp. 835–854, 2002.
25. Citations are in notes 9–12, Chapter 3.
26. These data and the following information are derived from B. Gladman’s paper in Icarus,
vol. 130, pp. 228–246, 1997.
27. See P. Davies on pp. 304–317 (including discussion) of G. R. Bock and J. A. Goode (1996;
citation is in note 20).
28. See R. M. E. Mastrapa et al. in Earth and Planetary Science Letters, vol. 189, pp. 1–8,
2001.
29. B. Gladman (1997; citation is in note 26) comments that the thickness of the Earth’s
atmosphere and the relatively small target size of Mars make both dispatch and destination
respectively more problematic. See also C. Mileikowsky et al. in Icarus, vol. 145,
pp. 391–427, 2000.
30. The exact quotation is ‘So I tell my students: learn your biochemistry here and you will be
able to pass examinations on Arcturus’, p. 16 of Life beyond Earth and the mind of Man,
edited by R. Berendzen, NASA Scientific & Technical Information Office, 1973.
31. The title of Norman Pace’s paper in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA,
vol. 98, pp. 805–808, 2001.
32. N. Pace (2001; citation is in note 31), p. 806.
notes to pp. 77–85 347
33. This is a very fast-moving field, with new results constantly being posted on websites:
www.exoplanets.org and www.obspm.fr/planets for example. Much of the information on
these extra-solar planets given below is derived from these sources. Published reviews include
those by J. T. Lunine in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 96,
pp. 5353–5356, 1999 and G. W. Marcy in his chapter (pp. 1285–1311) in Protostars and
planets, edited by V. Mannings et al. (University of Arizona Press, Tucson, 2000). Relevant
books include the fairly technical (S. Clark’s Extrasolar planets: The search for new worlds
(John Wiley [Praxis], Chichester, 1998); and, more accessible, D. Goldsmith’s Worlds
unnumbered: the search for extrasolar planets (University Science Books, Sausalito, CA,
1997).
34. See A. Vidal-Madjar et al. in Planetary and Space Science, vol. 46, pp. 629–648, 1998, who
suggests that gravitational perturbations and an occultation of the star hint at the presence of
giant planets within the disc.
35. Direct detection of a planet orbiting the star HD 209458 using photometry is reported by
D. Charbonneau et al. in Astrophysical Journal, vol. 529, pp. L45–L48, 2000. This planet had
already been detected by the radial velocity technique, but transit observations of the light
flux from the star provide other data. For example, it is significantly less dense than Saturn,
the least dense of the Solar System planets.
36. See R. P. Butler et al. in Astrophysical Journal, vol. 526, pp. 916–927, 1997, and D.
Goldsmith’s report in Science, vol. 296, p. 1951, 2002.
37. So far as I am aware a coherent consideration of life in a supergravity environment is not
available. The well-known essay On being the right size by J. B. S. Haldane (published in his
Possible worlds and other essays (Chatto and Windus, London, 1927)), as are various sections
in C. J. Pennycuick’s Newton rules biology: A physical approach to biological problems
(Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1992), see especially p. 53. The role of hypergravity (and its
reverse, weightlessness) has received extensive study with respect to rocket-borne ascent and
exploration of the Solar System; see, for example, Proceedings of the Annual Meetings of the
IUPS Commission on Gravitational Physiology, published as supplements to The
Physiologist (including vol. 23 (Suppl. 6), 1980; vol. 24 (Suppl. 6), 1981; vol. 26 (Suppl. 6), 1983;
vol. 28 (Suppl. 6), 1985; vol. 35 (Suppl. 1), 1992; vol. 36 (Suppl. 1), 1993). G. A. Cavagna et al. in
Journal of Physiology, vol. 528, pp. 657–668, 2000 (see also the commentary by A. E. Minetti
in Nature, vol. 409, pp. 467–468, 2001) assess the role of gravity on human walking, both at
lower values (equivalent to Mars) and at one-and-a-half times the Earth’s gravitational field.
38. See A. C. Cameron in Astronomy & Geophysics, vol. 43, pp. 4.21–4.25, 2002.
39. See, for example, J. E. Chambers and G. W. Wetherill in Icarus, vol. 136, pp. 304–327,
1998.
40. ‘Making more terrestrial planets’ is the title of J. E. Chambers’s paper in Icarus, vol. 152,
pp. 205–224, 2001.
41. J. E. Chambers (2001; citation is in note 40), p. 212.
42. J. E. Chambers (2001; citation is in note 40), p. 223.
43. See D. N. Lin et al. in Nature, vol. 380, pp. 606–607, 1996; see also J. C. B. Paploizou and
J. D. Larwood in Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society, vol. 315, pp. 823–833,
2000. In at least one case there is also compelling evidence that this process was both early
and relatively rapid; see J. I. Lunine in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
USA, vol. 98, pp. 809–814, 2001.
44. See G. Israelian et al. in Nature, vol. 411, pp. 163–166, 2001. The evidence is based on the
presence of a lithium isotope (6 Li), which is expected to occur in the early atmospheres of
giant planets, but is later destroyed as the star evolves.
45. See F. A. Rasio and E. B. Ford in Science, vol. 274, 954–956, 1996; S. J. Weidenschilling and
F. Marzari in Nature, vol. 384, pp. 619–621, 1996; N. Murray et al. in Science, vol. 279,
pp. 69–72, 1998; and F. Marzari and S. J. Weidenschilling in Icarus, vol. 156, pp. 570–579,
2002. In this last paper a ‘jumping Jupiter’ model is proposed to explain the ‘hot Jupiter’ close
348 notes to pp. 85–90
to its sun and to infer the existence of a more distant planet forming a stable system arising
from a chaotic beginning.
46. S. J. Weidenschilling and F. Marzari (1996; citation is in note 45), p. 620.
47. For an interesting discussion of the possibility of habitable moons orbiting extra-solar giant
planets see D. M. Williams et al. in Nature, vol. 385, pp. 234–236, 1997 (and the
accompanying commentary by C. F. Chyba on p. 201, which in part is also a paean for Carl
Sagan).
48. G. Gonzalez et al. in Icarus, vol. 152, pp. 185–200, 2001.
49. See, for example, papers by K. K. Khurana et al. in Nature, vol. 395, pp. 777–780, 1998 (and
accompanying commentary on pp. 749, 751 by F. Neubauer); R. T. Pappalardo et al. in Journal
of Geophysical Research, vol. 104E, pp. 24015–24055, 1999; J. S. Kargel et al. in Icarus,
vol. 148, pp. 226–265, 2000; and M. G. Kivelson et al. in Science, vol. 289, pp. 1340–1343,
2000; and X-P. Wu et al. in Geophysical Research Letters, vol. 28, pp. 2245–2248, 2001. There
is also a possibility that some sort of sub-surface ocean exists on another Galilean satellite,
Callisto; see J. Ruiz in Nature, vol. 412, pp. 409–411, 2001, and the commentary by K. A.
Bennett on pp. 395–396.
50. See C. K. Gessmann and D. C. Rubie in Earth and Planetary Science Letters, vol. 184,
pp. 95–107, 2000, and A. G. W. Cameron in Meteoritics & Planetary Science, vol. 36,
pp. 9–22, 2001; the latter account provides a helpful introduction to the earlier literature.
51. See C. Alibert et al. in Geochimica et Cosmochimica Acta, vol. 58, pp. 2921–2926, 1994.
52. See the papers by M. T. McCulloch in Earth and Planetary Science Letters, vol. 126, pp. 1–13,
1994; C. J. Allègre and et al. in Geochimica et Cosmochimica Acta, vol. 59, pp. 1445–1456,
1995; M. Ozima and F. A. Podosek in Meteoritics & Planetary Sciences, vol. 33 (4, Suppl),
p. A120, 1998; and F. A. Podosek in Science, vol. 283, pp. 1863–1864, 1999.
53. See, for example, D-C. Lee et al. in Earth and Planetary Science Letters, vol. 198,
pp. 267–274, 2002.
54. An argument based on tungsten isotopes; see A. N. Halliday and D-C. Lee in Geochimica et
Cosmochimica Acta, vol. 63, pp. 4157–4179, 1997.
55. See R. M. Canup and E. Asphaug in Nature, vol. 412, pp. 708–712, 2001, as well as the
accompanying commentary by J. Melosh on pp. 694–695.
56. See A. G. W. Cameron and W. Benz in Icarus, vol. 92, pp. 204–216, 1991.
57. This paper, by A. G. W. Cameron, the fifth in a series exploring the so-called Giant Impact
Hypothesis, is in Icarus, vol. 126, pp. 126–137, 1997. For an update and overview see A. G. W.
Cameron’s paper in Meteoritics & Planetary Science, vol. 36, pp. 9–22, 2001.
58. See R. M. Canup and L. W. Esposito in Icarus, vol. 119, pp. 427–426, 1996.
59. R. M. Canup and L. W. Esposito (1996; citation is in note 58), p. 429.
60. See S. Ida et al. in Nature, vol. 389, pp. 353–357, 1997.
61. This is the title of a commentary on the paper by S. Ida et al. (1997; citation is in note 60),
published in the same issue of Nature, on pp. 327–328.
62. A. G. W. Cameron and W. Benz (1991; citation is in note 56).
63. A. G. W. Cameron and W. Benz (1991; citation is in note 56), p. 215.
64. See P. D. Ward and D. Brownlee (2000; citation is in note 1), pp. 222–234.
65. See J. Laskar and R. Robutel in Nature, vol. 361, pp. 615–617, 1993.
66. The principal exponent of these ideas is G. Williams, who has published extensively on this
topic, including a recent paper in Sedimentary Geology, vol. 120, pp. 55–74, 1998; see also
Nature, vol. 396, pp. 453–455, 1998.
67. See J. Laskar and P. Robutel, in Nature, vol. 361, pp. 608–612, 1993.
68. See Neil Comins’s intriguing book What if the Moon didn’t exist: voyages to Earths that
might have been (HarperCollins, New York, 1993), which in addition to the title’s
consideration looks at a series of other questions, such as what the Earth would be like if its
obliquity were much greater (as for Uranus), what might happen if a black hole met the Earth,
and if the Earth were smaller; this last topic is returned to briefly below.
notes to pp. 90–95 349
69. See J. P. Vanyo and S. M. Awramik in Precambrian Research, vol. 29, pp. 121–142, 1985.
70. See W. Benz et al. in Icarus, vol. 74, pp. 516–528, 1988.
71. See, in particular, D. J. Stevenson in Annual Review of Earth and Planetary Sciences, vol. 15,
pp. 271–315, 1987.
72. Mars has two moons (Deimos and Phobos), but these are very small, respectively with
maximum lengths of 16 and 26 km. See P. C. Thomas on pp. 309–314 of Encyclopedia of the
Solar System, edited by P. R. Weissman (Academic Press, San Diego, 1999). These moons are
usually interpreted as captured asteroids, but, as Thomas notes, this is very difficult to
explain given their equatorial orbits. In addition, the long-term future of Phobos is uncertain,
and calculations suggest that its orbit will decay by tidal friction, with the moon crashing
onto the Martian surface within 100 Ma.
73. His stimulating article How common are habitable planets? may be found on pp. C11–C14 in
a special issue of Nature (vol. 402, 1999). N. F. Comins (see note 68) also explores in some
detail the consequences of living on a planet smaller than the Earth.
74. G. Gonzalez in Astronomy and Geophysics, vol. 40, pp. 318–320, 1999 explores some of these
points, remarking on both the roundness of the Moon (and the Sun) and the exactness of the
apparent sizes of each body (a tiny 3.7 arc minutes) allowing the Moon to block the bright
photosphere but not the dramatic chromosphere. Gonzalez also reminds us of the various
happy coincidences – the nature of the Sun, the Earth’s axial stability, the origin of the Moon
by impact, and the size of the Earth – that are probably prerequisites for astronomers to
evolve.
75. See pp. 210–213 of M. E. Bakich’s gazetteer to the Solar System, The Cambridge Planetary
Handbook (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2000). See also D. H. Levy’s Impact
Jupiter: The crash of comet Shoemaker–Levy 9 (Plenum, New York, 1995).
76. George Wetherill’s paper ‘Possible consequences of absence of “Jupiters” in planetary
systems’ was published in Astrophysics and Space Science, vol. 212, pp. 23–32, 1994; see also
his commentary in Nature, vol. 373, p. 470, 1995. The role of Jupiter as ‘goal-keeper’ is also
stressed by Ward and Brownlee (2000; citation in note 1), see pp. 235–242.
77. See P. R. Weissman in Nature, vol. 344, pp. 825–830, 1990, as well as his earlier paper
(pp. 272–282) in Dynamics of the Solar System, edited by R. L. Duncombe (Reidel, Dordrecht,
1979).
78. G. Wetherill (1994; citation is in note 76), p. 23.
79. Two accessible introductions are W. Alvarez’s T. rex and the crater of doom (Princeton
University Press, Princeton, 1997) and C. Frankel’s The end of the dinosaurs: Chicxulub
crater and mass extinctions (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999).
80. See J. W. Kirchner and A. Weil in Nature, vol. 404, pp. 177–180, 2000, and commentary by D.
Erwin on pp. 129–130.
81. See the paper by J. K. Schubert and D. J. Bottjer in Geology, vol. 20, pp. 883–886, 1992, and the
summary by D. J. Bottjer et al. in Geological Society of London Special Publication, vol. 83,
pp. 7–26, 1995.
82. See P. B. Wignall and R. J. Twitchett in Sedimentology, vol. 46, pp. 303–316, 1999. Other
parallels to sedimentary features typical of the earlier Precambrian environment might
include large-scale precipitation of sea-floor carbonate cements; see A. D. Woods et al. in
Geology, vol. 27, pp. 645–648, 1999.
83. See S. D’Hondt et al. in Science, vol. 282, pp. 276–279, 1998.
84. See the reports by G. A. Logan et al. in Nature, vol. 376, pp. 53–56, 1995, with an
accompanying commentary on pp. 16–17 by M. Walter; and in Geochimica et Cosmochimica
Acta, vol. 61, pp. 5391–5409, 1997.
85. See J. S. Lewis (1996; citation is in note 3), Chapter 14.
86. Concerning displacement of bodies from the asteroid belt see, for example, the papers by
P. Farinella et al. in Nature, vol. 371, pp. 314–317, 1994 and B. J. Gladman et al. in Science,
vol. 277, pp. 197–201, 1997.
350 notes to pp. 96–100
87. See, for example, the interesting studies by J. J. Sepkoski on pp. 211–255 of Evolutionary
paleobiology: in honor of James W. Valentine, edited by D. Jablonski et al. (University of
Chicago Press, Chicago; 1996), and with others in Paleobiology, vol. 26, pp. 7–18, 2000.
88. Concerning the final destiny of the Earth and the Solar System see the discussion by K. P.
Rybicki and C. Denis in Icarus, vol. 151, pp. 130–137, 2001. See also notes 105–107.
89. Evidence that the bulk of the Earth’s water derives from the outer asteroid belt is addressed by
A. Morbidelli et al. in Meteoritics & Planetary Science, vol. 35, pp. 1309–1320, 2000.
90. See J. I. Lunine (2001; citation is in note 43).
91. See C. F. Chyba and C. Sagan on pp. 147–173 of Comets and the origin and evolution of life,
edited by P. J. Thomas et al. (Springer, New York; 1997), and A. H. Delsemme in Advances in
Space Research, vol. 15(3), pp. 49–57, 1995.
92. C. F. Chyba in Advances in Space Research, 15 (3), pp. 45–48, 1995.
93. See papers by Z. Sekanina in Icarus, vol. 27, pp. 123–133, 1976, and more especially T. A.
McGlynn and R. D. Chapman in The Astrophysical Journal, vol. 346, pp. L105–L108,
1989.
94. Evidence for this is discussed by A. Vidal-Madjar et al. in one of their series of papers on β
Pictoris, specifically in Astronomy and Astrophysics (vol. 290, pp. 245–258, 1994) (see also in
the same journal A. M. Lagrange-Henri et al., vol. 190, pp. 275–282, 1988, and H. Beust et al.,
vol. 236, pp. 202–216, 1989).
95. See S. A. Stern et al. in Nature, vol. 345, pp. 305–308, 1990.
96. See S. A. Stern et al. in Icarus, vol. 91, pp. 65–75, 1991; this search entailed 17 nearby stars
and the authors emphasize the problems of detectability with present technology.
97. See G. J. Melnick et al. in Nature, vol. 412, pp. 160–163, 2001.
98. Although Chyba (1995; citation is in note 92) reminds us that it is possible to envisage a solar
system whose inner planets have received volatile delivery, but lacks an equivalent of the
Oort Cloud.
99. Three such episodes have been identified in the Precambrian, one about 2200 Ma ago (see, for
example, D. A. Evans et al. in Nature, vol. 386, pp. 262–266, 1997; D. McB. Martin in
Geological Society of America Bulletin, vol. 111, pp. 189–203, 1999; and J. L. Kirschvink
et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 97, pp. 1400–1405,
2000), and two at c. 700 Myr and 600 Myr ago (see P. Hoffman et al. in Science, vol. 281,
pp. 1342–1346, 1998, and supporting blasts in Nature, vol. 397, p. 384, 1999 and vol. 400,
p. 708, 1999; but see also G. S. Jenkins and C. R. Scotese in Science, vol. 282, pp. 1644–1645,
1998 (response by Hoffman et al. follows in pp. 1645–1646), G. S. Jenkins and L. A. Frakes in
Geophysical Research Letters, vol. 25, pp. 3525–3528, 1998; W. T. Hyde et al. in Nature,
vol. 405, pp. 425–429, 2000; and R. A. Kerr in Science, vol. 287, pp. 1734–1736, 2000; and M. J.
Kennedy et al. in Geology, vol. 29, pp. 443–446, 2001).
100. See H. C. Jenkyns and P. A. Wilson in American Journal of Science, vol. 299, pp. 341–392,
1999.
101. See, for example, James Lovelock’s Gaia: A new look at life on Earth (Oxford University
Press, Oxford, 1979) and The ages of Gaia: A biography of our living Earth (Oxford University
Press, Oxford, 1988).
102. See, for example, Michael Hart’s paper in Icarus, vol. 37, pp. 351–357, 1979.
103. A topic explored by J. Laskar in Nature, vol. 338, pp. 237–238, 1989.
104. See J. F. Kasting et al. in Icarus, vol. 101, pp. 108–138, 1993 and J. F. Kasting in Origins of Life
and Evolution of the Biosphere, vol. 27, pp. 291–307, 1997.
105. See S. Franck et al. in Naturwissenschaften, vol. 88, pp. 416–426, 2001; see also the papers by
S. Franck et al. in Journal of Geophysical Research, vol. 105E, pp. 1651–1658, 2000 and
Planetary and Space Science, vol. 48, pp. 1099–1105, 2000 (see also note 88).
106. See the papers by S. Franck et al. in Chemical Geology, vol. 159, pp. 305–317, 1999, and
Tellus, vol. 52B, pp. 94–107, 2000.
107. Franck et al. (2001; citation is in note 105), p. 420. One should note that they qualify this by
remarking that chemolithotrophic hyperthermophiles might persist for longer but ‘all higher
notes to p. 100–107 351
forms of life would certainly be eliminated’. Not all authors are quite so pessimistic;
T. M. Lenton and W. von Bloh (in Geophysical Research Letters, vol. 28, pp. 1715–1718, 2001)
give an extra 300 Ma (and perhaps a little more).
108. See C. H. Lineweaver in Icarus, vol. 151, pp. 307–313, 2001.
109. See for example, G. Gonzalez et al. in the Astrophysical Journal, vol. 511, pp. L111–L114,
1999. Although this correlation of metallicity and the presence of planets is strong, it is not
inevitable. In Astronomy & Geophysics (vol. 40, pp. 5.25–5.29, 1999) G. Gonzalez has also
suggested that in a number of respects, including its metallicity, our Sun may be anomalous.
However, I. N. Reid (in Publications of the Astronomical Society of the Pacific, vol. 114,
pp. 306–329, 2002) suggests that while there is a strong correlation between stellar metallicity
and the presence of planets, our Sun falls in the mid-range of such metallicities.
110. However, S. J. Vogt et al. report (in Astrophysical Journal, vol. 536, pp. 902–914, 2000) six
new planetary systems, of which two are metal poor.
111. See, for example, R. Jimenez et al. in Astrophysical Journal, vol. 561, pp. 171–177, 2001.
112. See the article ‘How old is ET?’ by R. P. Norris on pp. 103–105 of When SETI succeeds: The
impact of high-information contact, edited by A. Tough (Foundation for the Future, Bellevue
WA, 2000).
113. R. P. Norris (2000; citation is in note 112), p. 105.
114. See James Annis’s article in Journal of the British Interplanetary Society, vol. 52, pp. 19–22,
1999.
115. J. Annis (1999; citation is in note 114), p. 22.
116. See the paper by G. Gonzalez et al. in Icarus, vol. 152, pp. 185–200; 2001a, as well as a more
popular overview in Scientific American, vol. 285 (4), pp. 52–59, 2001b. In the context of a
special position of the Solar System with respect to our galaxy, see also the earlier paper by
L. S. Marochnik in Astrophysics and Space Science, vol. 89, pp. 61–75, 1983.
117. G. Gonzalez et al. (2001b; citation is in note 116), p. 59, left-hand column.
118. G. Gonzalez et al. (2001b; citation is in note 116), p. 59, right-hand column.
ultraviolet radiation. Given that this UV flux will be the norm on primitive planets, and the
fact that such building blocks of chlorophyll as quinones are synthesized in interstellar space
(see Chapter 3), so chlorophyll may be a universal molecule (note 13).
6. The general consensus seems to be that this endosymbiotic capture of the
cyanobacteria/chloroplast (and the comparable case of α-proteobacteria captured to yield in
due course the mitochondria) were unique events (see, for example, A. J. Roger and C. F.
Delwiche respectively in American Naturalist, vol. 154, pp. S146–S163 and S164–S177, 1999;
but see J. W. Stiller et al. in Journal of Phycology, vol. 39, pp. 95–105, 2003). Even so, although
rare, there are a number of other cases of what is called secondary endosymbiosis. This occurs
when two separate eukaryotes (or at least the plastid component) combine to form a single
organism. See, for example, papers by S. P. Gibbs in Annals of the New York Academy of
Sciences, vol. 361, pp. 193–207, 1981, S. E. Douglas et al. in Nature, vol. 350, pp. 148–151,
1991; S. Köhler et al. in Science, vol. 275, pp. 1485–1489, 1997, Z-d. Zhang et al. in Nature,
vol. 400, pp. 155–159, 1999; K. Takishita and A. Uchida in Phycological Research, vol. 47,
pp. 207–216, 1999, and Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 51, pp. 26–40, 2000 respectively;
and J. F. Saldarriaga et al. in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 53, pp. 204–213, 2001 (who
also present evidence for multiple loss of plastids). Helpful overviews of this area are provided
by G. McFadden and P. Gilson in Trends in Ecology & Evolution, vol. 10, pp. 12–17, 1995 and
T. Cavalier-Smith in Trends in Plant Sciences, vol. 5, pp. 174–182, 2000. Finally, and to
reinforce the likelihood that symbiotic unions between species are, in the grand order of
things, overwhelmingly probable, see the case in the insects where the symbiotic bacteria
have themselves symbiotic bacteria; see C. D. von Dohlen et al. in Nature, vol. 412,
pp. 433–436, 2001 (see also note 48).
7. Interestingly, the first major glaciations appear to date from the same interval (see, for
example, J. L. Kirschvink et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA,
vol. 97, pp. 1400–1405, 2000). One possibility is that as levels of oxygen increased so the
amount of reactive methane, a powerful greenhouse gas, declined. This in turn led to
planetary cooling and ultimately severe, perhaps catastrophic, glaciation (see A. A. Pavlov
et al. in Journal of Geophysical Research, vol. 105E, pp. 11981–11990, 2000).
8. See, however, Chapter 5 (pp. 72–73) for a more extended discussion of the significance of the
oldest sedimentary carbon.
9. The third carbon isotope, carbon 14 (14 C), is radioactive and is produced principally by cosmic
rays striking atoms of nitrogen. The relatively short half-life of 14 C means that it plays no
effective part in the biochemistry of photosynthesis and the geological burial of carbon.
10. As ever, this statement requires scientific qualification. Fractionation of carbon isotopes,
denoted by δ 13 C (the ratio of 12 C to 13 C against an agreed standard that by definition has a
δ 13 C of zero), occurs in other biochemical systems, such as methane generation by some
bacteria (methanogens). To the first approximation different metabolic processes imprint
separable isotopic signatures, with photosynthetic fractionation averaging c. 27‰ δ 13 C.
11. For helpful reviews of RuBisCO see the articles by F. C. Hartman and M. R. Harpel in Annual
Review of Biochemistry, vol. 63, pp.197–234, 1994 and G. Schneider et al. in Annual Review
of Biophysics and Biomolecular Structure, vol. 21, pp. 119–143, 1992. Some interesting
aspects of its molecular structure and possibly severe constraints on its function are addressed
by E. A. Kellogg and N. D. Juliano in American Journal of Botany, vol. 84, pp. 413–428,
1997.
12. The prokaryotic alga Acaryochloris lives within the tissues of tunicates and contains
significant proportions of chlorophyll d; see H. Miyashita et al. in Nature, vol. 383, p. 402,
1996, H. Schiller et al. in FEBS Letters, vol. 410, pp. 433–436, 1997. Concerning a similar
feature in the green alga Ostreobium, see P. Halldal in Biological Bulletin, vol. 134,
pp. 411–424, 1968, and B. Koehne et al. in Biochimica et Biophysica Acta, vol. 1412,
pp. 94–107, 1999. In part, at least, the red-shift is due to the shaded habitats of these
photosynthesizers.
notes to pp. 110–112 353
13. This quotation (pp. 13–14) is taken from George Wald’s stimulating and thoughtful paper
‘Fitness in the Universe: Choices and necessities’ in Origins of Life and Evolution of the
Biosphere, vol. 5, pp. 7–27, 1974.
14. R. D. Wolstencroft and J. A. Raven, in Icarus, vol. 157, pp. 535–548, 2002, have an interesting
discussion of how likely it is that photosynthesis has evolved on remote planets, and the
degree of similarity there might be to Earth. They conclude that the development of an
oxygenated atmosphere is very likely, although the energetics of photon capture and
specifically the number required to reduce a molecule of CO2 might differ.
15. D. J. DeRosier gives a helpful introduction to the flagellar motors of bacteria in Cell, vol. 93,
pp. 17–20, 1998, as do R. M. Berry and J. P. Armitage in Advances in Microbial Physiology,
vol. 41, pp. 291–337, 1999. See also in a thematic series ‘The molecular physics of biological
movement’, in Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 355, 2000
the papers by H. C. Berg (pp. 491–501) and R. M. Berry (pp. 503–509). Rotary activity is also
reported in eukaryotic cells, albeit involving the microtubules within the flagellum; see
C. K. Omoto and G. B. Witman in Nature, vol. 290, pp. 708–710, 1981.
16. More typical speeds are of the order of 200 rev/second, but Y. Magariyama et al. report speeds
of up to 1700 rev/second in the bacterium Vibrio alginolyticus; see Nature, vol. 371, p. 752,
1994.
17. See, for example, the account of how the filament is constructed given by K. Yonekura et al. in
Science, vol. 290, pp. 2148–2152, 2000, with an accompanying commentary by R. M. Macnab
on pp. 2086–2087, where he remarks that the assembly of this structure by the bacterium ‘is a
much more sophisticated process than any of us could have envisaged’, p. 2087.
18. See, in particular, M. J. Behe’s Darwin’s black box: The biochemical challenge to evolution
(The Free Press, New York, 1996). Unsurprisingly, the views of Behe have come under fierce
and justified criticism. As might be expected, orthodox Darwinists are willing to wade in, but
so are those who are keen to reconcile science and religion: see, in particular, K. R. Miller’s
thoughtful Finding Darwin’s God: A scientist’s search for common ground between God and
evolution (HarperCollins [Cliff Street Books], New York, 1999), especially Chapter 5.
19. This is F1 -ATPase, a component of the enzyme ATP synthase, which is located in the
mitochondria. See K. Kinosita et al. in Cell, vol. 93, pp. 21–24, 1998, two papers in
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 355, 2000, by A. G. W.
Leslie and J. E. Walker (pp. 465–472) and K. Kinosita et al. (pp. 473–489) respectively; and
M. L. Hutcheon et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 98,
pp. 8519–8524, 2001.
20. See the paper Locomotion like a wheel? by R. Full et al. in Nature, vol. 365, p. 495, 1993. An
analogy of a kind can also be found in the aquatic larvae of mosquitoes, which execute a
series of somersaults and still travel in a straight line through the water; see J. Brackenbury in
Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 202, pp. 2521–2529, 1999 for a revealing description of
this machine-like behaviour.
21. One should also note the convergences between the pangolin (an Old World group) and the
New World xenarthrans, which include the anteaters and armadillos; see F. Delsuc et al. in
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 268, pp. 1605–1615, 2001, where their
phylogenetic analysis ‘confirms that morphological similarities between xenarthrans and
pangolins are a spectacular example of convergence in relation to myrmecophagy [ant-eating]’
(p. 1612). The extent of the similarities between pangolins and xenarthrans is emphasized by
K. Z. Reiss in American Zoologist, vol. 41, pp. 507–525, 2001, where she has an interesting
discussion of the nature of convergences in both a phylogenetic and adaptational framework.
Importantly she comments that ‘there is no evidence that phylogenetic constraints have
facilitated or prevented the evolution of cranial muscle specializations for myrmecophagy’
(p. 520). These conclusions on convergence echo earlier work by K. D. Rose and R. J. Emry on
pp. 81–102 of Mammal phylogeny: Placentals, edited by F. S. Szalay et al. (Springer,
New York, 1993). Such critical assessments are of considerable importance in phylogenetics,
354 notes to p. 112
because prior analysis executed by hard-line cladists had strongly supported a link between
the pangolins and xenarthrans. As Rose and Emry comment, a credulous oversimplification
of ‘character states to facilitate algorithm-driven analyses often leads to unwarranted
confidence in some phylogenetic conclusions – for instance, the conclusion of synapomorphy
where homoplasy is more probable’ (p. 82). In the context of convergence among the anteaters
it is also worth remarking that a number of fossil forms, variously assigned to ant-eating
groups, may well be mistakenly allied because of unappreciated convergences in form and
function. Thus, Ernanodon from the Paleocene of China is probably convergent on the
xenarthrans (Rose and Emry 1993, p. 96; see also T. J. Gaudin in Fieldiana: Geology, vol. 41
(new series), pp. 1–38, 1999), while the much-discussed Eurotamandua from the famous
Messel oil shale (and also the Geiseltal lignite) of Eocene age in Germany poses serious
problems concerning the biogeographic dispersal of the xenarthran anteaters, problems that
as Delsuc et al. (2001) remark can be resolved if ‘the striking morphological resemblances
between this taxon [Eurotamandua] and Myrmecophagidae [anteaters] might be the result of
adaptive convergence towards fossoriality and ant feeding. This example once again
underlines how morphological adaptation to similar ecological niches could be positive
misleading in terms of phylogenetic signal’ (p. 1613).
22. A useful escape reaction, not least because the aboriginal tribe regards the pangolin as a great
delicacy. Details (of the escape tactics, not the recipe) are given by R. R. Tenaza in Journal of
Mammalogy, vol. 56, p. 257, 1975.
23. These examples are mentioned by R. L. Caldwell in Nature, vol. 282, pp. 71–73, 1979, a paper
whose principal purpose is to draw attention to the backward somersaulting abilities of the
stomatopods (see also note 20).
24. G. A. Gill and A. G. Coates, in Lethaia, vol. 10, pp. 119–134, 1977 remark, it is less clear
whether rolling of these more or less spherical coral colonies is achieved only when nudged
by another animal, say a fish, or even whether the colony remains in situ and grows by
periodic ‘press-ups’; see also J. B. Lewis’s discussion of spherical Siderastrea (S. radians) in
Coral Reefs 7, pp. 161–167, 1989.
25. LaBarbera’s paper is entitled ‘Why the wheels won’t go’, published in American Naturalist,
vol. 121, pp. 395–408, 1983. Also of interest are the remarks in ‘Why legs and not wheels’ by I.
Walker in Acta Biotheoretica, vol. 39, pp. 151–155, 1991, although her emphasis is more on
the contrast between biological and man-made systems.
26. Philip Pullman, in the last book of his neo-secular fantasy, The amber spyglass (Scholastic,
London, 2000), provides an ingenious portrayal of the wheeled malefa. Their wheels, however,
are derived from seed-pods, and the axle is effectively formed by a powerful claw with an
extending spur that locks into the pod. The reliance on the trees and their pods leads to an
ecological interdependence that provides Pullman with some graphic and imaginative writing.
27. See R. A. Fortey’s book Life: An unauthorized biography (HarperCollins, London, 1997).
28. R. A. Fortey (1997; citation is in note 27), p. 325.
29. R. A. Fortey was not the first to speculate on the existence of giant floating organic bladders.
Carl Sagan, for example, in Cosmos (Macdonald, London, 1981, see pp. 40–43) conjures up
what he dubs ‘floaters’ living high in the turbulent atmosphere of Jupiter-like planets. They
would, he proposed, either consume organic material synthesized abiotically in the reducing
atmosphere (in a Miller–Urey like fashion, see Chapter 4, pp. 60–62) or make their own food
in a way analogous to photosynthetic plants. These organisms, unlike the terrestrial Fortean
bladders, had, of course, a ready supply of hydrogen. Jupiter, too, is conceivably an abode of
life, but as R. D. MacElroy stresses in his chapter (pp. 69–93) in Chemical evolution of the
giant planets, edited by C. Ponnamperuma (Academic Press, New York, 1976) there are very
considerable difficulties. So far as Fortean bladders are concerned, the extreme atmospheric
turbulence would seem to make their survival problematic. As MacElroy writes, ‘We surmise
that the origin of life on Earth required surfaces and some degree of stability. Stability appears
not to be a general characteristic of Jupiter, except for the Great Red Spot. Postulating
notes to pp. 112–113 355
surfaces with stability in a turbulent atmosphere requires imagination and faith, but there is
historical precedence for the use and overuse of these qualities. Fanciful description of life in
places not visited has been one of the most wonderful and revealing aspects of man’s history.
Wonderful, because the descriptions show a basic belief that anything imaginable is possible;
revealing, because of the fundamental acceptance that the natural order of the Universe is to
be populated with live creatures. Inevitably, it is harshly revealed that the historical
descriptions of such magnificent beasts as unicorns and mermaids have been the result of
naı̈veté and the absence of facts. A biologist considering the possibilities of life on other
planets and their satellites is the most naı̈ve of scientists’ (p. 83).
30. See also my article ‘Palaeodiversifications: mass extinctions, ‘clocks’, and other worlds’ in
GeoBios, vol. 32, pp. 165–174, 1999.
31. Useful accounts of this organ are given by R. McN. Alexander in Biological Reviews, vol. 41,
pp. 141–176, 1966, and J. B. Steen on pp. 413–443 in vol. 4 of Fish Physiology, edited by W. S.
Hoar and D. J. Randall (Academic Press, New York, 1970).
32. G. N. Lapennas and K. Schmidt-Nielsen provide a helpful review in Journal of Experimental
Biology, vol. 67, pp. 175–196, 1977. The crystals of guanine are very thin, and when the
swim-bladder contracts they can strongly fold.
33. See his review on pp. 70–72 of Marine biology: its accomplishment and future prospect,
edited by J. Mauchline and T. Nemoto (Hokusen-Sha, Tokyo, 1991). Guanine, which is one of
the four bases of DNA, also acts as a reflective agent on the surface of fish, as well as in the
eyes of both sharks and scallops; see E. J. Denton in Philosophical Transactions of the Royal
Society of London B, vol. 258, pp. 286–313, 1970.
34. Counter-current systems are widespread and convergent in animals, especially those
involving heat exchange and thermoregulation. A well-known example is in long-legged
birds, whereby the feet, perhaps perched on the ice of a frozen lake, are markedly colder than
the rest of the body because the heat carried in the blood descending the legs is transferred by
the counter-current system to the ascending stream.
35. This interesting octopus is described by A. Packard and M. Wurtz in Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 344, pp. 261–275; 1994. More
speculatively A. Seilacher and M. LaBarbera have proposed (in Palaios, vol. 10, pp. 493–506,
1995) that the buoyancy of the ammonites, whose closest living relatives are squids,
depended upon a bladder-like arrangement with an associated gas gland. Seilacher and
LaBarbera suggest that the last-formed chamber retained a flexible wall, only later to calcify
as a subsequent chamber was delimited. In association with a putative gas gland this would
have allowed it to act as an analogue of the swim-bladder.
36. Concerning the siphonophores see the review by G. O. Mackie et al. in Advances in Marine
Biology, vol. 24, pp. 97–262, 1987.
37. Details of the gas gland are provided by D. E. Copeland in Biological Bulletin, vol. 135,
pp. 486–500, 1968. He suggests that carbon monoxide is produced because it is less markedly
soluble than carbon dioxide and so ‘more readily retained by the highly hydrated float tissue’
(p. 497). Other siphonophores also secrete carbon monoxide (see, for example, G. V. Pickwell
et al. in Science, vol. 144, pp. 860-862, 1964), as does the bladder kelp, an enormous brown
alga; see G. B. Rigg and B. S. Henry in American Journal of Botany, vol. 22, pp. 362–365, 1935.
In this seaweed, Nereocystis, the distal end bears a float with a capacity of four litres; see N.
L. Nicholson in Journal of Phycology, vol. 6, pp. 177–182, 1970. There is another interesting
convergence because as Rigg and Henry (1935) also remark ‘The inner surface of this float is
covered with a cobweb-like layer of tubular cells which bear such a striking resemblance to
the sieve tubes of higher plants in both structure and function that they [too] are commonly
referred to as sieve tubes’ (p. 363). Various other convergences between these giant brown
algae and other plants are addressed on pp. 19–20 of K. J. Niklas’s Plant biomechanics: An
engineering approach to plant form and function (University of Chicago Press, Chicago,
1992).
356 notes to pp. 113–114
balcony of a dwelling in the Huntington Beach area, California. The report continues, ‘a vet
analysed a sample and concluded it was the work of a huge pig’, which presumably had
detached itself from the passing flotilla in order to relieve itself.
50. The problem of envisaging a biological equivalent to an airship is addressed in his Cat’s paws
and catapults: Mechanical worlds of nature and people (Norton, New York, 1998); see
especially pp. 151–152. S. Vogel’s entertaining and informative books on biomechanics are
very well worth reading. So, too, is his succinct chapter ‘Convergence as an analytical tool in
evolutionary design’ (pp. 13–20) in Principles of animal design: The optimization and
symmorphosis debate, edited by E. R. Weibel et al. (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge,
1998).
51. See, for example, the paper by R. A. J. Taylor and D. Reling in Environmental Entomology,
vol. 15, pp. 431–435, 1986. To be sure, there are local concentrations of an ‘aerial plankton’,
especially in connection with atmospheric convergences, but as V. A. Drake and R. A. Farrow
(in Trends in Ecology & Evolution, vol, 4, pp. 381–385, 1989) emphasize, these are temporary,
and are usually associated with migration. Locusts are perhaps the most familiar example.
52. An excellent introduction to the spiders, with a helpful description of the complexity of the
silk glands and associated apparatus, is given in R. F. Foelix’s Biology of spiders (Oxford
University Press, Oxford, 1996 [Second edition]).
53. See the article by J. W. Schultz in Biological Reviews, vol. 62, pp. 89–113, 1987.
54. For a helpful overview of the mechanical design of spider silks, see J. M. Gosline et al. in
Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 202, pp. 3295–3303, 1999.
55. To a first approximation silk proteins are arranged either as α-helices or parallel β-pleated
sheets, the latter more familiar in the form of spider silk and commercial silk. A third variety
is the cross β-pleated sheet; see Craig (1997, note 61) for a helpful overview.
56. The gene family that encodes the fibroins is reported by P. A. Guerette et al. in Science,
vol. 272, pp. 112–115, 1996.
57. Conservation and convergence of spider silk fibroin sequences is reported by J. Gatesy et al.
in Science, vol. 291, pp. 2603–2605, 2001.
58. See C. L. Craig et al. in Evolution, vol. 48, pp. 287–296, 1994; quotation is from p. 293.
59. So far as I am aware the extrusion of liquid proteins to form silks is found only in the
arthropods. But there are other parallels, notably in the formation of the dogfish egg case.
This is composed of the protein collagen, which is extruded in a liquid crystalline state, and
like silk hardens with the loss of water. Helpful accounts of the egg-case production are given
by D. Feng et al. and D. P. Knight et al. in Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of
London B, vol. 343, pp. 285–302, 1994 and vol. 351, pp. 1205–1222, 1996 respectively, as well
as by D. P. Knight et al. in Biological Reviews, vol. 71, pp. 81–111, 1996. In addition, it is
worth noting that while silk proteins in arthropods are typically thought of in the context of
fibroins, ‘a collagen-like silk is produced by sawflies in the family Perigidae (Hymenoptera)’
(Craig, 1997; citation is in note 61, p. 244), while this family and the related Argidae also
employ polyglycine, an apparent precursor of collagen (see also the earlier review of arthropod
silks by K. M. Rudall and W. Kenchington in Annual Review of Entomology, vol. 16, p. 73–96,
1971, especially pp. 81–84).
60. This is Bombyx mori, which as E. B. Ford explains in Moths (Collins, London, 1955) produces
a silken cocoon of three layers of which the middle can be unwound to form ‘a single
unbroken thread about 1500 feet in length’ (p. 101).
61. The evolution of silks in arthropods is reviewed by C. L. Craig in Annual Review of
Entomology, vol. 42, pp. 231–267, 1997.
62. See J. Brackenbury in Physiological Entomology, vol. 21, pp. 7–14, 1996, where he describes
how certain caterpillars can descend from danger on a silk lifeline.
63. For an account of the New Zealand glow-worm, see J. E. Lloyd’s chapter on insect
bioluminesence (pp. 241–272) in Bioluminescence in action, edited by P. J. Herring (Academic
Press, London, 1978).
358 notes to pp. 116–119
64. See J. F. Jackson’s interesting account of web-building in other dipterans, and their connection
to Arachnocampa, published in American Midland Naturalist, vol. 92, pp. 240–245, 1974.
This paper is of additional interest because it addresses a macro-evolutionary fantasy put
forward earlier by Richard Goldschmidt, which he subsequently abandoned, to explain how
web-building, bioluminescence, and carnivory could have all evolved simultaneously.
65. See B. M. Walshe’s account of chironomid larval feeding in Proceedings of the Zoological
Society of London, vol. 121, pp. 63–79, 1951. The web is spun at frequent intervals, and then
consumed with its trapped contents.
66. A review of filter-feeding in aquatic insects is given by J. B. Wallace and R. W. Merritt in
Annual Review of Entomology, vol. 25, pp. 103–132, 1980.
67. J. M. Edington, in Journal of Animal Ecology, vol. 37, pp. 675–692, 1968, reports nets of
Plectrocnemia conspersa as being built of a series of irregular strands, up to c. 7.5 cm across.
68. See A. G. Hildrew and C. R. Townsend in Journal of Animal Ecology, vol. 45, pp. 41–57, 1976.
69. This information on weaver ants is from The ants by B. Hölldobler and E. O. Wilson
(Springer, Berlin, 1990), see pp. 620–622. Silk production in ants is typically associated with
the larvae, but as B. L. Fisher and H. G. Robertson demonstrate (in Insectes Sociaux, vol. 46,
pp. 78–83, 1999), adults of Melissotarsus also secrete silk threads.
70. Ants, incidentally, are by no means the only arthropods to make tents by the expedient of
folding together leaves. Various caterpillars of butterflies construct tents and other shelters by
bringing leaves, including those of grass, together with silk threads (see E. B. Ford’s Butterflies
(Collins, London, 1945, pp. 89–90); so, too, does the orthopteran Camptonotus (see Craig
1997, note 61, p. 251).
71. Concerning this behaviour see, for example, the papers by A. P. Brooke in Journal of Zoology,
London, vol. 221, pp. 11–19, 1990 and T. H. Kunz and G. F. McCracken in Journal of Tropical
Ecology, vol. 12, pp. 121–137, 1996. E. Cholewa et al. explain, in Biological Journal of the
Linnean Society, vol. 72, pp. 179–191, 2001, how damage to the leaves by the bats, necessary
for folding and achieved by chewing, is contrived so that water supply is maintained and the
leaf remains fresh.
72. Not that this prevents other animals using silk for their own purposes, such as birds
employing spider silk in their nest construction; a trait evidently arrived at independently
several times. See Bird nests and construction behaviour by M. Hansell (Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge, 2000).
73. See George Ledyard Stebbins’s paper Natural selection and the differentiation of angiosperm
families in Evolution, vol. 5, pp. 299–324, 1951.
74. Their work is published on pp. 283–294 in Constructional morphology and evolution, edited
by N. Schmidt-Kittler and K. Vogel (Springer, Berlin, 1991), and as a parallel paper in
Evolution, vol. 47, pp. 341–360, 1993. Thomas et al. (in Science, vol. 288, pp. 1239–1242, 2000)
extended this work to an analysis of how quickly the ‘skeleton space’ was occupied in the
Cambrian ‘explosion’. By reference to the Burgess Shale fauna, which shows an exceptionally
complete cross-section of Cambrian life, they conclude that occupation was very rapid.
75. Such explorations can be demonstrated, for example, in the case of the aperture of the
protistan foraminiferans (see V. Mikhalevich and J-P. Debenay in Journal of
Micropalaeontology, vol. 20, pp. 13–28, 2001). This seemingly minor example is important
because there have been relatively few investigations of such evolutionary ‘explorations’; it
also illustrates the general principle.
76. See the paper ‘Stingray jaws strut their stuff’ by A.P. Summers et al. in Nature, vol. 395,
pp. 450–451, 1998.
77. The bone-like structure in Ibla is described by H. A. Lowenstam and S. Weiner in Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 89, pp. 10573–10577, 1992. These authors
emphasize the convergence with lamellar bone, but are also careful to note various
differences. Barnacles themselves also show interesting convergences, one of which is a
striking trend in the reduction in the number of parietal plates in the acorn (or balanomorph)
notes to pp. 119–122 359
barnacles, a point noted by Darwin in his famous monograph on the cirripedes. A. R. Palmer,
in Paleobiology, vol. 8, pp. 31–44, 1982, argues that this reduction is a direct result of
predation pressure exerted by drilling gastropods, whose preferred mode of attack is at plate
margins: fewer plates, fewer margins and greater safety.
78. See D. A. Kelly in Integrative and Comparative Biology, vol. 42, pp. 216–221, 2002. Kelly has
some interesting comments on the nature of convergence, and also remarks ‘If, as
hypothesized, mammals and turtles independently evolved inflatable penises from ancestors
who lacked intromittent organs, the similarity of the anatomical designs . . . to produce penile
stiffness is astonishing’, p. 219. Interestingly, many mammals also possess a penis bone,
known as the baculum. They have their uses: a zoological club, to which I was invited to give
a lecture, keeps order by having to hand the baculum of a large sea-mammal, a walrus as I
recall.
79. The basic cycle of burrowing shown by many groups of invertebrates, entailing alternate
formation of the penetration and terminal anchors in the sediment, is strongly convergent;
see E. R. Trueman’s The locomotion of soft-bodied animals (Edward Arnold, London, 1975).
80. This group is relatively diverse today, but has a very poor fossil record; see S. E. Evans and D.
Sigogneau-Russell in Palaeontology, vol. 44, pp. 259–273, 2001.
81. The paper by J. C. O’Reilly et al. on hydrostatic locomotion in the caecilians is in Nature,
vol. 386, pp. 269–272, 1997.
82. That, in essence, is the thesis of Pavane by Keith Roberts (reprinted by VGSF, London, 1995) a
counterfactual science fiction novel: twentieth-century England is still firmly Catholic, and
the much-delayed scientific revolution is emerging in a Europe where there is still a chance of
avoiding the disasters that have arisen in the real world, where it is assumed that rather than
our being the custodians of God’s great creation, nature is infinitely malleable to our whims.
83. See A. Donovan’s Antoine Lavoisier: Science, administration and revolution (Cambridge
University Press, Cambridge, 1993). Lavoisier’s laboratory in Paris was one of the most
advanced of its type, equipped with superbly constructed instruments and a team of
enthusiastic and dedicated acolytes. Asked to advise on the atrocious state of French
gunpowder, he transformed both its quality and methods of production. A footnote to
history? Possibly not. It can be argued that the American War of Independence, which
depended critically on French supplies to the rebels, would have failed. An interesting
thought, and not for the usual reasons of injured British pride. It has been argued that an
important aim of the British government was to restrict the westward expansion of the
colonists (see R. Harvey’s A few bloody noses: The American War of Independence (John
Murray, London, 2001)), one result of which was the genocide of indigenous tribes and
nations, with the destruction of a cultural richness that is our common loss.
84. See Ferguson (1998; citation is in note 3) for interesting discussions of how the British might
have avoided the disaster of the trenches. John Adamson addresses Charles the First’s crucial
mistake in not attacking the Scots’ army on the Tweed in 1639. Andrew Roberts and Niall
Ferguson explore the consequences of England falling in 1940 by Nazi invasion.
85. Key papers are those by the groups led by R. E. Lenski and M. Travisano. The initial paper in
this series, by R. E. Lenski et al., was published in American Naturalist, vol. 138,
pp. 1315–1341, 1991. An overview by R. E. Lenski and M. Travisano is provided in
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 91, pp. 6808–6814, 1994, and
more recently by M. Travisano in Current Biology, vol. 11, pp. R440–R442, 2001.
86. The paper, entitled Experimental tests of the roles of adaptation, chance, and history in
evolution, is published in Science, vol. 267, pp. 87–90, 1995.
87. See the paper by F. Vasi et al. in American Naturalist, vol. 144, pp. 432–456, 1994, where they
looked at the effects of fluctuating resources: feast and famine. Taking twelve independently
evolving lines they asked whether the ‘derived genotypes exhibit the same suite of adaptive
changes in their life histories, or did they find alternate solutions to the challenges imposed
by the seasonal environment?’ They remark that superficially the evidence points to
360 notes to pp. 122–124
‘substantial divergence of the derived genotypes in the life-history bases of their improved
fitness’, but they continue, ‘it is equally important to emphasize that direction of
evolutionary change was highly parallel for most of the fitness components and life-history
traits’ (their emphasis). They concluded ‘there was near-perfect uniformity in the directional
responses exhibited by the replicate populations’ (quotations on p. 449).
88. A. Joshi (in Current Science, vol. 72, pp. 944–949, 1997) looked at how E. coli responded to
changes in temperature, again weighing up the relative roles of chance, history, and adaptive
convergence. He concluded, ‘In the case of adaptation to novel temperature, too, the
contribution of adaptation to fitness at 20 ◦ C [the bacteria having been ‘trained’ to ‘enjoy’
substantially higher temperatures of between 32 ◦ C and 42 ◦ C, either constant or fluctuating]
was significantly greater than the combined contribution of history and chance, despite a
significant increase over 1000 generations in the latter’, p. 946.
89. See, for example, the discussion by M. Travisano et al. in Evolution, vol. 49, pp. 189–200,
1996. This concerns the response of the bacteria to sugar substrates, where there are a
number of important qualifications when the bacteria encounter novel, i.e. non-glucose,
environments. Here the variation in evolved fitness was much greater, possibly owing to
heterogeneous pleiotropy.
90. The general topic of evolutionary ‘dead ends’ and how they are avoided is perhaps somewhat
neglected. Especially interesting is the problem of specialization, seemingly reducing the
range of evolutionary possibilities, and thereby increasing the risk of extinction. A good
example concerns the chrysomeline leaf beetles, as described by A. Termonia et al. in
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 98, pp. 3909–3914, 2001. As
larvae these animals synthesize chemical compounds to assist in defence. Convergently,
however, at least two groups of these beetles have learnt how to derive chemicals from a
specific group of host plants, known as the salicaceans, that confer defence. The advantage is
that metabolic energy does not need to be wasted by the insect in making defensive
chemicals, and as a bonus these larvae also derive a source of sugar. The problem, however, is
that they seemingly irretrievably commit themselves to the salicacean plants, so entering an
evolutionary cul-de-sac. This, however, did not happen because one group was able to shift its
metabolic pathways in a novel direction and so open up a whole new set of host–plant
associations. Another example of how specialization does not necessarily lead to an
evolutionary dead end is given by C. D’Haese in Cladistics, vol. 16, pp. 255–273, 2000. It
concerns another group of insects, the primitive and wingless collembolans. Here, too,
convergence is rife, and involves multiple occupation of habitats by generalized descendants
of specialized ancestors.
91. Just how dynamic the genome is during evolution is addressed by D. Papadopoulos et al. in
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 96, pp. 3807–3812, 1999. They
studied genome evolution in E. coli for 10 000 generations, which occurs over 1500 days. A
number of interesting results emerged, including the decoupling of genomic and phenotypic
(e.g. cell size, fitness) evolution. Thus adaptive changes slowed down markedly after the
2000th generation, but genomic evolution continued unabated.
92. Moreover, in experiments concerned with adaptation to temperature and a wider variety of
metabolic substrates (see M. Travisano and R. E. Lenski in Genetics, vol. 143, pp. 15–26,
1996) the results are more complex and reflect various sorts of divergence.
93. See number 6 in the series, published by M. Travisano in Genetics, vol. 146, pp. 471–479,
1997.
94. Specifically those selected for glucose and now transferred to maltose showed substantial
genetic variation but no improvement in fitness, whereas those adapted to maltose and
transferred to glucose showed effectively the opposite, i.e. equal fitness improvement
irrespective of whether it was glucose or maltose, but little genetic variation.
95. M. Travisano (1997; citation is in note 93), p. 476.
96. A. Joshi (1997; citation is in note 88), p. 947.
notes to pp. 124–126 361
97. The experiments are described on pp. 947–948 of Joshi (1997). He notes ‘the fact that for
fitness (or a trait strongly correlated with fitness), the effect of current ongoing selection
tends to obliterate the effects of historical and random divergence among lineages’, p. 948.
98. Joshi (1997), p. 949. The quote continues, ‘With a change in selection pressure, the genetic
structure of a population is rapidly shuffled and reorganized, much as what happens to a
particular sequence of sand dunes upon a sudden change in the direction of the wind’. The
wind bloweth where it will, but sand dunes still have a structure and so does the evolution of
life.
99. See H. Teotónio and M. R. Rose in Nature, vol. 408, pp. 463–466, 2000 (with commentary by
J. J. Bull on pp. 416–417).
100. H. Teotónio and M. R. Rose (2000; citation is in note 99), p. 465.
101. D. Schluter’s paper on ‘Tests for similarity and convergence of finch communities’ is
published in Ecology, vol. 67, pp. 1073–1085, 1986.
102. The question as to whether entire communities of organisms can converge in any exact sense
is generally greeted with negatives (see, for example, J. Blondel et al. in Evolutionary Biology,
vol. 18, pp. 141–213, 1984). Even so, the United States/International Biological Program
(US/IBP) Synthesis Series 3 and 5, respectively Convergent evolution in warm deserts: An
examination of strategies and patterns in deserts of Argentina and the United States, edited
by G. H. Orians and O. T. Solbrig, and Convergent evolution in Chile and California:
Mediterranan climate ecosystems, edited by H. A. Mooney (Dowden, Hutchinson & Ross,
Stroudsburg, PA, 1977) have not only many examples of pair-wise comparisons within
particular groups, but also some interesting remarks on the overall degree of convergence
between the North and South American communities. An overview of community
convergence is given by G. H. Orians and R. T. Paine in their chapter (pp. 431–458) in
Coevolution, edited by D. J. Futuyma and M. Slatkin (Sinauer, Sunderland, MA; 1983). For an
interesting example of community parallelisms in the fossil record, specifically between
Devonian brachiopod communities, see P. Wallace in Lethaia, vol. 11, pp. 259–272, 1978.
103. See his interesting discussion in Systematic Biology, vol. 41, pp. 403–420, 1992. Losos also
notes, perhaps surprisingly, that in two of the islands (Puerto Rico and Jamaica) ‘the assembly
of anole faunas . . . followed a highly similar evolutionary sequence’ (p. 415), suggesting in
turn that the evolutionary trajectories are channelled and thereby directive. Losos is careful
to point out the origins of such a ‘decision’ might lie in the existence of a particular
ecomorph, such as an arboreal generalist, and that another starting point, e.g. a grass-bush
ecomorph, might ‘exhibit a quite different trajectory of community assembly’ (p. 416). He
also has an interesting discussion of certain ecomorphs that ‘ought’ to exist on some islands
but do not, such as the absence of a grass-bush ecomorph in Jamaica. Subsequently Losos
et al. (in Science, vol. 279, pp. 2115–2118, 1998, with a commentary by G. Vogel on p. 2043)
extended this analysis of anolid lizards and concluded that: ‘adaptive radiation in similar
environments can overcome historical contingencies to produce strikingly similar
evolutionary outcomes’ (p. 2115). On the other hand, among the aquatic anolid lizards, a
habit that has evolved several times, there is no evidence for convergence; see M. Leal et al.
in Evolution, vol. 56, pp. 785–791, 2002. These workers suggest that the lack of convergence
may be because there are several distinct habitats, or alternatively ‘more than one way may
exist to adapt to a single habitat’ (p. 787).
104. A. Ben-Moshe et al., in American Naturalist, vol. 158, pp. 484–495, 2001, have compared the
community organization (and morphology in terms of teeth and skull patterns) in Old and
New World rodents, and identified patterns of ecomorphological convergence, that ‘strongly
indicates general rules governing ecological communities or guilds’, p. 484.
105. See, for example, the paper by R. Korona in Genetics, vol. 143, pp. 637–644, 1996, looking at
fitness convergence in a soil bacterium. Here, too, genetic variability was maintained even
though the replicates converged towards similar adaptive end points. See also R. C. McLean
and G. Bell in American Naturalist, vol. 160, pp. 569–581, 2002.
362 notes to pp. 126–130
106. Amelie Karlstrom and colleagues’ paper is published in Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences, USA, vol. 97, pp. 3878–3883, 2000.
107. Both crustaceans and trilobites are arthropods, but trilobites disappeared 250 Ma ago, rather
insignificant victims of the Permian mass extinctions. The Jurassic trilobite-mimic is
described by A. Radwanski in Acta Geologica Polonica, vol. 45, pp. 9–25, 1995. Trilobites
show their own convergences. N. C. Hughes et al. (in Evolution & Development, vol. 1,
pp. 24–35, 1999) give a particularly interesting example where a proetid trilobite
(Aulacopleura konincki) converges in form on the older olenimorph trilobites. It appears that
the proetid is reoccupying a specific habitat, low in oxygen. This paper is also important
because Hughes et al. provide cogent arguments in support of adaptational explanations in
the context of a trend to a more efficient mechanism, specifically protective enrolment.
108. The appropriately named Archimedes has a characteristic spiral column from which lace-like
fans arise. It is a widespread form, best known in Carboniferous strata. P. D. Taylor and F. K.
McKinney describe a mimic (in Journal of Paleontology, vol. 70, pp. 218–229, 1996), from the
Eocene of North Carolina. The second author also describes in the same journal (vol. 72,
pp. 819–826, 1998) another interesting case of convergence in the bryozoans, specifically in
the independent invention of structures that functionally mimic the specialized, non-feeding
zooids known as the avicularia.
109. Palaeontologists usually refer to taxa that bow out of the fossil record and then at some later
point in the stratigraphic column reappear as either Lazarus or Elvis taxa, terms coined
respectively by D. Jablonski in his chapter (pp. 183–229) in Dynamics of extinction, edited by
D. K. Elliott (Wiley [Wiley-Interscience], New York, 1986) and D. H. Erwin and M. L. Droser
in Palaios, vol. 8, pp. 623–624, 1993. The former are taxa that survive an extinction event, but
remain undetected, that is ‘dead’ to the fossil record (see the article by E. Fara in Geological
Journal, vol. 36, pp. 291–303, 2001 for an overview), only to re-emerge at some later date.
Elvis taxa, on the other hand, are those that which look like the pre-catastrophe forms, but
are mere imitations.
110. See the paper by D. H. Erwin and H-Z. Pan on pp. 223–229 of Biotic recovery from mass
extinction events (edited by M. B. Hart), Geological Society of London Special Publication
102, 1996.
111. Despite the similarities that define any evolutionary convergence, there are also subtle and
interesting differences, a point of very considerable importance for those interested in
explaining the realities of evolution: destinations are similar, seldom identical. Even so, on
occasion the degree of similarity is quite astonishing. K. C. Emberton (see Evolution, vol. 49,
pp. 469–475, 1995), for example, notes a convergence between two land snails so precise that
only a dissection allows them to be distinguished
112. This comparison is discussed by H. Ulrich in Natur und Museum, vol. 95, pp. 499–508, 1965.
113. A helpful review of mantispid biology is given by K. E. Redborg in Annual Review of
Entomology, vol. 43, pp. 175–194, 1998.
114. See the paper by U. Aspöck and M. W. Mansell in Systematic Entomology, vol. 19,
pp. 181–206, 1994. Writing of the Rhachiberothidae they comment, ‘We assume that the
raptorial forelegs have evolved independently of those of the Mantispidae. Parallel evolution
in related taxa is certainly more frequent than generally assumed, and quite natural due to a
similar gene pool’ (p. 204).
115. The mechanics of the predatory strike are described by P. T. A. Gray and P. J. Mill in Journal
of Experimental Biology, vol. 107, pp. 245–275, 1983.
116. See S. N. Gorb and R. G. Beutel in Naturwissenschaften, vol. 88, pp. 530–534, 2001, as well as
a more extended treatment by R. G. Beutel and S. N. Gorb in Journal of Zoological
Systematics and Evolutionary Research, vol. 39, pp. 177–207, 2001. In addition, similar
attachment structures have evolved independently in other arthropods; and these authors
comment on the interesting analogies with attachment devices in the vertebrates. It is also
worth mentioning the evidence for ‘remarkable convergence’ (p. 1509) in digital adhesive pad
notes to p. 130 363
design in some lizards; see E. E. Williams and J. A. Peterson in Science, vol. 215,
pp. 1509–1511, 1982, who draw attention to similarities with the beetles: as ever, different
starting point, same destination.
117. See the paper by D. Tshudy and U. Sorhannus in Journal of Paleontology, vol. 74, pp. 474–486,
2000, who note the independent evolution of pectinate claws in at least four lineages of
crustaceans. This example is quite telling because the claws are often found isolated as fossil
specimens and ‘Convergence in this claw form developed to the extent that isolated fossil
claws . . . commonly have been misidentified at high taxonomic levels’, p. 474.
118. See C. L. Morrison et al. in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 269,
pp. 345–350, 2002. These authors suggest that the trend towards ‘crab-ness’ is irreversible,
and they have an interesting discussion as to whether this form represents some sort of key
innovation or whether it is facilitated by developmental pathways.
119. Even so, C. L. Morrison et al. (2002; citation is in note 118) remark that in at least some cases
the key step in the transition to a crab morphology appears to have occurred in shallow
water.
120. There is an extensive literature on the sabre-tooth cats. Papers by W. A. Akersten in Los
Angeles County Museum Contributions to Science, vol. 356, pp. 1–22, 1985; M. Antón et al.
in Zoological Journal of the Linnean Society, vol. 124, pp. 369–386, 1998; and M. Antón and
A. Galobart in Journal of Vertebrate Paleontology, vol. 19, pp. 771–784, 1999, provide helpful
introductions.
121. Concerning the thylacosmilids, see the papers by W. D. Turnbull on pp. 399–414 in
Development, function and evolution of teeth, edited by P. M. Butler and K. A. Joysey
(Academic Press, London, 1978), and C. S. Churcher in Australian Mammalogy, vol. 8,
pp. 201–220, 1985.
122. A very useful overview of the sabre-tooth cats is given by A. Turner and M. Antón in their
book The big cats and their fossil relatives: An illustrated guide to their evolution and
natural history (Columbia University Press, New York, 1997). They point out that sabres
have evolved at least three times in the placentals, twice in the more advanced nimravids
(e.g. Barbourofelis) and felids (e.g. Homotherium and Smilodon), as well as in the more
primitive creodont oxyaenids (e.g. Apataelurus).
123. See Bob Bakker’s paper published in Gaia (Lisbon), vol. 15, pp. 145–158, 1998. One obvious
difference between the mammalian sabre-tooth cats and the allosaurids is that the latter do
not develop the giant canines, but Bakker suggests ‘that the entire upper jaw of allosaurs
functioned as one huge, saw-edged Samoan war-club, with each small, individual tooth acting
as a mega-serration. Polynesian warriors glued shark teeth to clubs, and the individual shark
tooth functioned as a mega-serration that was, on a much smaller scale, also serrated. Such a
club inflicts a long-jagged wound with concomitant trauma and blood loss, especially if the
mega-serrated blade is pulled backwards as it strikes its target’, pp. 152–153.
124. See, for example, J. A. W. Kirsch’s thoughtful paper on the adaptedness of marsupials in
American Scientist, vol. 65, pp. 276–288, 1977. Interestingly he suggests that the diagnostic
marsupium, that is, the pouch in which the young develop, actually arose several times
independently within the marsupials, an argument that presupposes that primitively this
group of mammals lacked the pouch.
125. This judgement is based in part on the near extirpation of the South American marsupial
faunas, including the thylacosmilids, following the so-called Great American Interchange
when island bridges (at c. 6 Myr) and then land bridges (at c. 2 Ma) were established that
linked this continent to North America. It now seems, however, that this is too simplistic,
and human activities may have also played a significant part in these extinctions. See, for
example, the paper assessing extinction patterns in the late Pleistocene mammals of South
America by E. P. Lessa and R. A. Farina in Palaeontology, vol. 39, pp. 651–662, 1996.
126. See, for example, W. V. Koenigswald and F. Goin’s remarks on enamel structure in
Palaeontographica, Abteilung A, vol. 255, pp. 129–168, 2000. In passing it is also worth
364 notes to pp. 130–135
drawing attention to a striking convergence between the tooth enameloid of two groups of
actinopterygian fish (characidids and sphyraenidids) and modern sharks, involving the
independent development of highly ordered, bending resistant structure; see the paper by
W-E. Reif in Scanning Electron Microscopy, 1979, pp. 547–554, 1979.
127. Specifically H. N. Bryant and C. S. Churcher write ‘Diverse dental anatomies among
sabre-tooths suggest that, despite necessary functional similarities, precise adaptations
varied. The hunting adaptations of these animals were surely diverse’; see Nature, vol. 325,
p. 488, 1987.
128. See his chapter (pp. 157–278) in The biology of marsupials, edited by D. Hunsaker (Academic
Press, New York, 1977). The examples given concern (a) the pronounced lamination of cells
and fibres found in the lateral geniculate nucleus of various marsupials and also primates and
carnivores, which as Johnson remarks, ‘raise many hypotheses about arboreality and visual
evolution’ (p. 262); (b) the occurrence of small cells in distinct subgroups in the phalanger
Trichosaurus that ‘resemble in many ways the “barrels” first described in sensory cortex of
mice and related to projections of vibrissae [whiskers] and other regions of high receptor
density in rats’ (pp. 221–222); and (c) ‘The formation of gyri and sulci at predictable loci in the
sensory representation in neocortex’ (p. 262) of both marsupials and placentals. Johnson
concludes by remarking, ‘Marsupials represent the great alternative case of mammalian
adaptive radiation, and when the same result happens in two such separate phylogenetic
lines, we can begin to identify the determining factors in brain evolution’ (p. 262).
L. Krubitzer, in Trends in Neurosciences, vol. 18, pp. 408–417, 1995, also has an interesting
discussion of some convergences in brain structure between placental and marsupial
mammals. It is also worth mentioning convergences of brain structure within the placentals,
of which one of the best known is the independent evolution of cytochrome oxidase-rich
‘blobs’ in the primary visual cortex of primates and cats; see T. M. Preuss in Brain, Behavior
and Evolution, vol. 55, pp. 287–299, 2000.
129. See, for example, W. R. Scott in Journal of Morphology, vol. 5, pp. 301–406, 1891.
130. See the series of comparisons drawn by G. Dubost in Revue écologie (Terre Vie), vol. 22,
pp. 3–28, 1968.
131. These parallels among placental mammals are addressed by O. Madsen et al. in Nature,
vol. 409, pp. 610–614, 2001. The following paper (pp. 614–618) by W. J. Murphy et al. is also
directly relevant.
132. See R. T. Bakker’s chapter (pp. 350–382) in Coevolution, edited by D. J. Futuyma and M.
Slatkin (Sinauer, Sunderland, MA, 1983).
133. R. T. Bakker (1983; citation is in note 132) p. 354.
134. See Kirk Winemiller’s paper in Ecological Monographs, vol. 61, pp. 343–365, 1991; see also
N. Lamouroux et al. in Ecology, vol. 83, pp. 1792–1807, 2002, who document community
convergence amongst freshwater fish on the basis of stream hydraulics, especially in terms of
the dimensionless Froude number.
135. The paper by R. Hanel and C. Sturmbauer is in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 50,
pp. 276–283, 2000; see also J. J. Day in Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, vol. 76,
pp. 269–301, 2002.
136. The description of replicate evolution in Lake Tanganyika cichlids is given by L. Rüber et al.
in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 96, pp. 10230–10235, 1999;
see also L. R. Rüber and D. C. Adams in Journal of Evolutionary Biology, vol. 14, pp. 325–332,
2001. This paper makes a specific attempt to remove the ‘burden of history’, whereby a
particular group has a limited evolutionary choice because of phylogenetic ‘decisions’ by its
ancestors. See also the general overview of the Rift Lake cichlids by M. L. J. Stiassny and A.
Meyer in Scientific American, vol. 280 (2), pp. 44–49, 1999, and the figure on p. 48 with the
remark that ‘distantly related cichlids. . .evolved to become uncannily alike.’
137. See R. Felger and J. Henrickson in Haseltonia, 1997 (part 5), pp. 77–85, 1997.
138. For a helpful review of the topic of plant adaptation to desert environments, see the chapter
(pp. 67–106) in Orians and Solbrig (1977; citation is in note 102). R. K. Peet, in American
notes to pp. 135–136 365
Naturalist, vol. 112, pp. 441–444, 1978, offers a short but incisive discussion on various
aspects of convergence, including the adaptations shown by various desert plants. His point
that there may be more than one adaptive solution to a problem (such as extreme aridity) is
important, and a useful counterbalance to over-simplistic thinking. Thus he points out that
in Australia native succulents are rare, but have flourished when introduced, e.g. the prickly
pear. In the end, what matters is how many adaptive solutions exist, and the extent to which
prior conditions govern final outcomes.
139. See the papers by R. M. Cowling et al., for example in Vegetatio, vol. 43, pp. 191–197, 1980,
Journal of Biogeography, vol. 21, pp. 651–664, 1994, and Australian Journal of Ecology,
vol. 19, pp. 220–232, 1994, as well as H. A. Mooney and E. L. Dunn in Evolution, vol. 24,
pp. 292–303, 1970.
140. This is known as myrmecochory. An interesting example of convergence between Australia
and South Africa species is discussed by A. V. Milewski and W. J. Bond on pp. 89–98 of
Ant-plant interactions in Australia, edited by R. C. Buckley (Junk, The Hague, 1982).
141. This overview of convergence across the globe is provided by P. B. Reich et al. in Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 94, pp. 13730–13734, 1997. As they remark,
‘What selection pressures would lead to such common “solutions” among phylogenetically
different groups? We hypothesize that there are interrelated constraints set by biophysics and
natural selection’ (p. 13733). Thus, in this case certain types of leaf simply cannot exist, while
others are effectively inevitable.
142. Many other examples of convergence in plants are given in K. J. Niklas’s authoritative The
evolutionary biology of plants (University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1997); see in particular
his Chapter 7. See also Vogel (1998, citation is in note 50) for a series of examples including
twist-to-bend ratios, vascular fluid flow, and leaf shape. More specifically, T. J. Givnish et al.
(in Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution, vol. 12, pp. 360–385, 1999) give an extensive list
of convergences in the commelinoid flowering plants, ranging from type of pollination, flower
structure, fruits, silica bodies, and xeric adaptations.
143. See the paper by K. J. Niklas in Evolution, vol. 45, pp. 734–750, 1991, which looks at the
biomechanical convergence in the petioles of flowering plants (angiosperms) and ferns.
144. The tree habit has evolved multiple times; for a specific example involving tree-ferns see
J. Galtier and F. M. Hueber in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 268,
pp. 1955–1957, 2001. Such comparisons also span geological time; H. W. Pfefferkorn et al. (in
Historical Biology, vol. 15, pp. 235–250, 2001), for example, draw attention to convergences
between trees growing in areas subject to flooding and high sedimentation rates in South
America today and the Carboniferous deltas of Laurasia. Many other types of plant habit have
also converged. Consider the Mediterranean-like evergreen sclerophyll shrubs, where
Mooney and Dunn (1970; citation is in note 139) explore the convergences imposed by
drought, fire, and mineral shortages.
145. Pollen and ovule each have half the complement of chromosomes, and hence are haploid, in
the same manner as egg and sperm. Successful fertilization combines the chromosomes, to
give the diploid seed that germinates and grows into the plant in the garden (known as the
sporophyte) where ultimately the sex cells are produced, female ovule to await male pollen,
and so the cycle continues . . .
146. Together with his famous metaphor of life’s diversity as a ‘tangled bank’, this phrase must be
one of the most quoted of Darwin’s remarks; first published in More letters of Charles
Darwin. A record of his work in a series of hitherto unpublished letters, edited by F. Darwin
and A. C. Seward (John Murray, London, 1903), see vol. II, pp. 20–21 for an extract from a
letter to J. D. Hooker written on 22 July 1879.
147. Represented by three genera: Ephedra, Gnetum, and Welwitschia.
148. Helpful overviews of the male and female reproductive structures in Gnetales are given
respectively by L. Hufford and P. K. Endress in International Journal of Plant Sciences,
vol. 157 (Supplement 6), pp. S95–S112 and S113–S125, 1996. To a first approximation the
gnetalacean flowers bear separate sexes, but various degrees of bisexuality are known.
366 notes to pp. 136–138
149. The identification and significance of the gnetalacean double fertilization is addressed by J. S.
Carmichael and W. E. Friedman in American Journal of Botany, vol. 83, pp. 767–780, 1996.
150. See, for example, the review paper by P. R. Crane et al. in Nature, vol. 374, pp. 27–33, 1995.
151. In the context of the water vascular system it is also worth noting that it, too, appears to be
convergent, having evolved independently in the bryophytes; see R. Ligrane et al. in New
Phytologist, vol. 156, pp. 491–508, 2002. Significantly, this convergence is not simple, but
entails considerable biochemical complexity.
152. See, for example, A. Hansen et al. in Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 16, pp. 1006–1009,
1999; T. Kh. Samigullin in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 49, pp. 310–315, 1999; and the
three papers in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA by K.-U. Winter et al.
(vol. 96, pp. 7342–7347, 1999); S-M. Chaw et al. (vol. 97, pp. 4086–4091, 2000); L. M. Bowe
et al. (vol. 97, pp. 4092–4097, 2000); Y-L. Qiu et al. in Nature, vol. 402, pp. 404–407, 1999 (as
well as the preceding paper by P. S. Soltis on pp. 402–404; Y.-L. Qiu et al. in Molecular Biology
and Evolution, vol. 18, pp. 1745–1753, 2001; S. Shindo et al. in Evolution & Development,
vol. 1, pp. 180–190, 1999, and International Journal of Plant Sciences, vol. 162, pp. 1199–1209,
2001; E. Gugerli et al. in Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution, vol. 21, pp. 167–175, 2001;
S. Magallon and M. J. Sanderson in American Journal of Botany, vol. 89, pp. 1991–2006, 2002;
and D. E. Soltis et al. in American Journal of Botany, vol. 89, pp. 1670–1681, 2002.
153. Interestingly, it is now known that at least some basal angiosperms have a diploid, rather
than triploid, endosperm; see J. H. Williams and W. E. Friedman in Nature, vol. 415,
pp. 522–526, 2002. It is also possible that the triploid condition evolved twice.
154. In support of the angiosperm–Gnetales connection the following characters in common are
often listed: lignin biochemistry (marked by the distinctive Mäule reaction (see R. D. Gibbs’
chapter (pp. 269–312) in The physiology of forest trees, edited by K. V. Thimann (Ronald, New
York, 1958), although he emphasizes that the corresponding lignin biochemistry has probably
evolved several times (p. 307)); a double integument; tunica formation in the apical meristem;
pollen wall (exine) structure; and lack of archegonia; see, for example, J. A. Doyle and M. J.
Donoghue in Botanical Review, vol. 52, pp. 321–431, 1986, p. 356, and P. Crane et al. (1995;
citation is in note 150), Box 1 on p. 29.
155. Thus S. Carlquist in International Journal of Plant Sciences, vol. 157 (Supplement 6),
pp. S58–S76, 1996 provides evidence to support the idea that xylem vessels in the Gnetales
are evolutionarily independent of those developed in the angiosperms.
156. The idea of a common ancestry to double fertilization is effectively the argument presented
by W. E. Friedman and S. K. Floyd in Evolution, vol. 55, pp. 217–231, 2001, who reasonably
remind us that key information in a number of plant groups is still wanting, especially with
respect to the origin of the endosperm.
157. There are, however, some dissenting voices. For example, M. Schmidt et al. (in Journal of
Molecular Evolution, vol. 54, pp. 715–724, 2002) argue on the bases of phytochrome genes
that Gnetales are basal to gymnosperms. This does not make Gnetales and angiosperms a
sister-group, but in principle it could mean that their common ancestor shared reproductive
organs preadapted for evolution towards flowers. A close relationship between Gnetales and
conifers was also questioned by C. Rydin et al. (in International Journal of Plant Sciences,
vol. 163, pp. 197–214, 2002).
158. See P. K. Endress (1996; citation is in note 148).
159. The question, of course, arises that if the triploid endosperm of angiosperms has a clear
nutritive value for the adjacent developing embryo, what then is the function of the diploid
supernumerary zygote in the gnetalaceans? The standard explanation (see, for example,
W. E. Friedman in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 92,
pp. 3913–3917, 1995) looks to the evolutionary phenomenon known as inclusive fitness,
whereby the embryo (and thereby its genes) receive the benefit of a nutritional supplement by
the ‘sacrifice’ of a genetically similar (or identical) partner.
160. Thus W. E. Friedman and S. K. Floyd (2001; citation is in note 156) remark, ‘Thus, it would
not be surprising if double fertilization, per se, represents an “apomorphic tendency”
notes to p. 138 367
[effectively the repeated likelihood that a particular character will appear; for further
discussion see P. D. Cantino in Systematic Botany, vol. 10, pp. 119–122; 1985] . . . of seed
plants that evolved several times, predicated upon the fact that all seed plants form pairs of
both male and female nuclei that may participate in separate fertilization events . . . If the
evolution of double fertilization is homoplasious among seed plant lineages, this
phenomenon would stand out as a premier example of an apomorphic tendency predicated
upon what has been referred to as an “underlying synapomorphy”. . . in essence, a case of
parallelism that results from an underlying developmental constraint or bias’ (pp. 225–226).
This, of course, opens an indefinite regression: are seeds, land plants, and sex all evolutionary
inevitable? If so, then sooner or later flowers.
161. S. C. Tucker, in International Journal of Plant Sciences, vol. 158 (Supplement 6),
pp. S143–S161, 1997, has an interesting discussion of convergences in flower structure. See
also L. Hufford’s analysis of floral homoplasies in the same issue, pp. S65–S80. More specific
examples of convergence in flowering plants are discussed by various authors, including P. K.
Endress et al. in Nordic Journal of Botany, vol. 3, pp. 293–300, 1983 (addressing the
appearances of apocarpy) and R. Dahlgren in Botaniska Notiser, vol. 123, pp. 551–568, 1970
(concerning South African leguminoseans).
162. See, for example, M. Proctor et al.: The natural history of pollination (HarperCollins, London,
1996), as well as more recent literature such as P. Bernhardt’s discussion of convergence in
beetle-pollinated flowers in Plant Systematics and Evolution, vol. 222, pp. 239–320, 2000,
and E. L. Borba and J. Semir’s discussion of convergence in fly pollination of orchids in Annals
of Botany, vol. 88, pp. 75–88, 2001.
163. See, for example, papers by V. Bretagnolle in The American Naturalist in vol. 142,
pp. 141–173, 1993, and P.-A. Crochet et al. in Journal of Evolutionary Biology (vol. 13,
pp. 47–57, 2000).
164. This topic is discussed by M. Mönkkönnen in Evolutionary Ecology (vol. 9, pp. 520–528,
1995), who points out that not only has long-distance bird migration evolved repeatedly, but
there is a strong tendency in the main feathers (the primaries) for the distal set to elongate
and the proximal ones to shorten, thereby bringing the wing-tips closer to the leading edge.
This topic was returned to in considerable detail by R. Lockwood et al. in Journal of Avian
Biology, vol. 29, pp. 273–292, 1998.
165. The osteology of migrant birds is addressed by R. G. Calmaestra and E. Moreno in Journal of
Zoology, London, vol. 252, pp. 495–501, 2000. The convergences are not in themselves
particularly surprising because all are related to the muscle insertions of the major flight
muscles.
166. The paper, specifically exploring convergences between carduelid finches and turdid chats, is
by A. Landmann and N. Winding in Oikos, vol. 73, pp. 237–250, 1995.
167. See the thoughtful paper by A. Barbosa and E. Moreno in Netherlands Journal of Zoology,
vol. 45, pp. 291–304, 1995, who analyse the bills, wings, and legs of four families of aerially
foraging birds. Their analysis is important because they weigh the relative influences of
adaptation for this demanding way of life against the constraints to change imposed by the
phylogenetic ‘burden’ inherited from the ancestral form that did not pursue this way of life.
Also relevant in the context of aerial insectivory is the paper by A. Keast et al. in The Auk,
vol. 112, pp. 310–325, 1995 on convergence, of a sort, between the flycatchers (tyrannids) and
the American Redstart.
168. This concerns the proposed convergence between the neotropical Honey Creepers,
specifically the nectar-adapted warblers (Parulidae) and tanagers (Thraupidae), a topic
addressed by W. J. Beecher in The Wilson Bulletin, vol. 63, pp. 247–287, 1951.
169. This unexpected convergence emerged as part of a wider study of bird phylogeny by M. Van
Tuinen et al. in Proceedings of the Royal Society B, vol. 268, pp. 1345–1350, 2001. The
considerable morphological similarities of grebes and loons had led them, by the irrefutable
certainties of cladistic analysis, to be regarded as closely allied. The molecular data, on the
other hand, strongly indicates that the similarities are the result of convergence. As these
368 notes to pp. 138–139
authors trenchantly remark, ‘We propose that this unusual alliance of birds has been
overlooked because of the exceptional adaptations to their respective aquatic niches have
obscured evolutionary history,’ p. 1349.
170. See the chapter (pp. 149–188) on adaptive radiations in birds by R. W. Storer in Avian biology,
vol 1, edited by D. S. Farner et al. (Academic Press, New York, 1971). Among the many
examples he gives are those of graviportal locomotion, climbing, webbing, diving (see also
citation in note 169), carnivory including multiple evolution of shrike-like forms, the carrion
eaters (e.g. vultures), and nectar feeders. Evidence for repeated convergence of feeding types is
also stressed by A. H. Bledsoe in The Auk, vol. 105, pp. 504–515, 1988 on the basis of
molecular data that cut radically across various morphological assumptions.
171. See, for example, the remarks by G. A. Bartholomew in his chapter (pp. 11–37) in New
directions in ecological physiology, edited by M. E. Feder et al. (Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 1987). In addition to noting that ‘Sphinx moths and hummingbirds are
aerodynamically similar and resemble each other when in flight despite totally different
morphological organization,’ he also shows that ‘The energy costs of hovering flight in these
two structurally and physiologically different types of organisms are remarkably similar’ (p.
21). He continues, ‘One can also translate this similarity into a general statement of
evolutionary interest. The aerodynamic constraints imposed by the combination of forward
flight, while searching for flowers, and sustained hovering, while feeding on nectar, are
associated with the evolution of similar body size, body shape, and wing shape in sphingids
and hummingbirds despite fundamentally different patterns of morphological organization.
The energy expenditures during hovering flight in these convergent insects and birds are
virtually identical and extremely high . . . sphingids and hummingbirds are approaching the
biological limit of aerodynamic performance for animals of their size’ (p. 22). In another
context R. K. Colwell, in American Naturalist, vol. 156, pp. 495–510, 2001, illustrates an
example of convergence (specifically Rensch’s rule > in larger species, > in smaller
species) between hummingbirds and flower mites, both of which compete for the same
resource and are subject to similar constraints in terms of sexual selection and
courtship.
172. The discovery of the toxin homobatrachotoxin in the skin and feathers of the bird Pitohui is
reported by J. P. Dumbacher et al. in Science, vol. 258, pp. 799–801, 1992; see also the
informative commentary by J. M. Diamond in Nature, vol. 360, pp. 19–20, 1992, where he
remarks that this ‘discovery provides an astonishing example of convergent evolution’, p. 19.
173. The bird in question, Ifrita, is probably not closely related to Pitohui, but its systematic
position is still enigmatic. It is unknown, therefore, whether its ability to make this alkaloid
toxin is an example of convergence; see J. P. Dumbacher et al. in Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 97, pp. 12970–12975, 2000.
174. The convergence in chemical ecology between heteropterans and the bird Aethia cristatellais
is reported by H. D. Douglas et al. in Naturwissenschaften, vol. 88, pp. 330–332, 2001. They
point out that the ultimate source of the toxin is not known, but it may act to repel
ectoparasites. Nor is this the only example of such a chemical convergence. An ability to
sequester pyrrolizidine alkaloids (PA) and cardiac glycosides (CG) from plants, to be employed
for defence or sometimes as pheromones, is well developed in arctiidid and ctenuchid moths
but has also evolved independently in nymphalid butterflies; see M. Wink and E. von
Nickirsch-Rosenegk in Journal of Chemical Ecology, vol. 23, pp. 1549–1568, 1997. In
addition, these authors remark on an extension of this example of convergence with the
independent evolution of PA sequestration in such beetles as Oreina. This example is
important because ‘The biochemical mechanisms that enable insects to sequester PAs or CGs
are certainly intricate’ (p. 1552), thus emphasizing that convergences are far from simplistic.
175. See the summary (pp. 213–214) of D. J. Futuyama’s contribution (pp. 207–231) in Coevolution,
edited by D. J. Futuyama and M. Slatkin (Sinauer, Sunderland, MA, 1983).
176. See W. Cooper in Journal of Zoology, London, vol. 257, pp. 53–66, 2002.
notes to pp. 139–143 369
177. See the remarks on p. 60 of G. G. Simpson’s paper in Bulletin of the Museum of Comparative
Zoology, vol. 139 (1), pp. 1–86, 1970, as well as an earlier paper, specifically on Necrolestos by
B. Patterson, in Breviora, vol. 94, pp. 1–14, 1958.
178. A key worker in this area is Eviatar Nevo. Particularly helpful is his Mosaic evolution of
subterranean mammals: Regression, progression and global convergence (Oxford University
Press, Oxford, 1999). This is an outstanding source book, not only for a detailed discussion of
convergences in the burrowing mammals, but also because of Nevo’s emphatic and repeated
emphases on the reality of adaptation and its central role in evolutionary biology.
179. Concerning powerful claws see also the paper by M. A. Coombs in Transactions of the
American Philosophical Society, vol. 73 (7), pp. 1–96, 1983, where she reviews the
occurrences of large mammalian herbivores with prominent claws. Three principal categories
of activity are identified (digger/tearer, bipedal browser, and climber), and each is identified by
a complex of associated characters.
180. ‘How to eat a carrot?’ is the intriguing main title of the paper by H. Burda et al. in
Naturwissenschaften, vol. 86, pp. 325–327, 1999. Concerning the use of smell by subterranean
rodents to detect and discriminate against plant food, see G. Heth et al. in Behavioral Ecology
and Sociobiology, vol. 52, pp. 53–58, 2002, who emphasize its convergent nature.
181. For overviews, see M. J. Mason and P. M. Narins in American Zoologist, vol. 41,
pp. 1171–1184, 2001, and Journal of Comparative Psychology, vol. 116, pp. 158–163, 2002. In
Chapter 8, we shall see how the burrowing termites and ants also employ seismic
communication (Chapter 8, notes 78 and 79).
182. There are, however, gradients of fierceness, and in desert environments behaviour in the mole
rat Spalax is unusually pacific, probably as an adaptation ‘to minimize overheating, water and
energy expenditure’; see E. Nevo et al. in Behaviour, vol. 123, pp. 70–76, 1992. The
physiological basis underlying this tendency towards pacifism is rather interesting, and may
involve the steroid corticosterone. In threatening situations, which may lead to overt
aggression, this chemical is generated to release metabolic energy. In doing so, however, it
also leads to elevated rates of filtration by the kidneys and thereby increases water
consumption, a problem for mole-rats living in arid environments who also need to avoid
overheating; see G. Ganem and E. Nevo in Behavioural Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 38,
pp. 245–252, 1996. Ganem also suggests, in a subsequent issue (vol. 42, pp. 365–367, 1998),
that another group of mole rats (the bathyergids) may have followed a similar pathway to
pacifism (see also ensuing discussion by H. Burda on pp. 369–370). This is very much the
exception, and as the writers also note the ‘animals were easily handled by us and caressed
freely like pets, an inconceivable act with other known Spalax species’ (p. 72).
183. See the paper by K. D. Rose and R. J. Emry in Journal of Morphology, vol. 175, pp. 33–56, 1983,
who note the phylogenetic confusion that these animals have sown whereby convergence is
mistaken for phyletic affinities to such groups as the xenarthrans (citation is in note 21).
184. See The biology of the naked mole-rat, edited by P. W. Sherman et al. (Princeton University
Press, Princeton, 1991), p. viii.
185. The independent evolution of eusociality in bathyergid mole-rats is described by J. U. M.
Jarvis and N. C. Bennett in Behavioural Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 33, pp. 253–260, 1993,
with specific reference to the Damaraland mole-rat (see also J. U. M. Jarvis et al. in Trends in
Ecology & Evolution, vol. 9, pp. 47–51, 1994, and C. G. Faulkes et al. in Proceedings of the
Royal Society of London B, vol. 264, pp. 1619–1627, 1997). The review by H. Burda et al., in
Behavioural Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 47, pp. 293–303, 2000, has an interesting
discussion as to why eusociality evolves in these mammals.
186. See the brief report by N. G. Solomon in Trends in Ecology & Evolution, vol. 9, p. 264, 1994.
187. See B. J. Crespi (in Nature, vol. 359, pp. 724–726, 1992); B. D. Kranz et al. (in Insectes Sociaux,
vol. 48, pp. 315–323, 2001); and T. W. Wills et al. (in Naturwissenschaften, vol. 88, pp. 526–
529, 2001), as well as a general review by Crespi et al. in Annual Review of Entomology,
vol. 42, pp. 51–71, 1997.
370 notes to pp. 143–145
have substantial similarity’ (p. 170). While ear reduction in these lizards is understandable as
an adaptation to a burrowing mode of life (protection, and perhaps also better transmission of
sound), Arnold is also careful to point out that such reduction occurs in some tree-dwelling
forms.
200. This is the famous lizard, Basiliscus, which lives in areas of central and South America, and
in many regions is referred to by the local inhabitants as Largarto Jesus Cristo, the Jesus
Christ lizard. For an account of its aquatic bipedalism see J. Laerm in American Midland
Naturalist, vol. 89, pp. 314–333, 1973, and Ecology, vol. 55, pp. 404–411, 1974.
201. C. Luke, in Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, vol. 27, pp. 1–16, 1986, provides
evidence that lizard toe fringes have evolved independently at least 26 times. While
emphasizing convergence in an adaptive context, such as the 12 (or 13) independent
originations of triangular toe-fringes among lizard inhabiting wind-blown sand, Luke is
careful to explore what may be non-adaptive aspects. Thus, two other fringe types are also
found in the habitat of wind-blown sand.
202. See J. J. Wiens and J. L. Slingluff in Evolution, vol. 55, pp. 2303–2318, 2001, with specific
respect to anguid lizards. Interestingly, they suggest that this trend to a snake-like form is
gradual and there is no need to invoke any macroevolutionary jumps.
203. A helpful overview of convergences among desert mammals is given by M. A. Mares et al. on
pp. 107–163 in Orians and Solbrig (1977; citation is in note 102), in a chapter that also has
interesting comparisons of various desert dwelling groups, including the amphibians, lizards
and ants. A parallel investigation with emphasis on macroecological similarities (or
otherwise) is given by M. L. Cody et al. on pp. 144–192 in Mooney et al. (1977; citation is in
note 102).
204. Key papers by M. A. Mares on convergence in the desert rodents may be found in Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 72, pp. 1702–1706, 1975; Paleobiology,
vol. 2, pp. 39–63, 1976; Bulletin of the Carnegie Museum of Natural History, vol. 16,
pp. 1–51, 1980; and BioScience, vol. 43, pp. 372–379, 1993.
205. Specifically, Mares (1980) writes, ‘it is likely that future evolution within these deserts will
be that of refinement within a guild, rather than the development of a new, exploited adaptive
zone. Only in the Monte and in Australia do there seem to be vacant zones awaiting
exploitation by rodents. Given the evenness with which such zones have been filled in other
desert areas, I feel that the evolution of such species in these deserts is highly probable,’ p. 42.
206. The relationships of these somewhat enigmatic marsupials are discussed by M. R.
Sanchez-Villagra in Zoological Journal of the Linnean Society, vol. 131, pp. 481–496, 2000,
and Palaeontology, vol. 43, pp. 287–301, 2001.
207. G. G. Simpson (1970; citation is in note 177), p. 49. Other aspects of this convergence include
the common possession in the argyrolagids and kangaroo rats of spaces within the palate, for
which no functional explanation appears to exist (it may be adaptive or possibly coincidental);
Simpson remarks that it is ‘baffling’ (see p. 50). Another shared feature is a very globular
bulla, which may be linked to hearing in arid environments.
208. See M. A. Mares (1975; citation is in note 204).
7. seeing convergence
1. So far as humans are concerned probably not, and in Chapter 9 I review how each step leading
towards humans has its parallels elsewhere. Concerning the woodpecker, J. M. Diamond has
stressed (e.g. in Chapter 12 of The rise and fall of the third chimpanzee (Radius, London,
1991)) how only this one group of birds has developed the complex of adaptations, such as
specialized beak, sawdust filters, skull structure, and musculature that together make
percussive attack on trees possible. He uses this example to argue that, in an analogous way,
humans (at least in a radio-building capacity) are also unique.
2. Vangids are a group of birds endemic to the island of Madagascar. They show a spectacular
adaptive radiation, one that rivals the Galapagos finches or Hawaiian honeycreepers.
372 notes to p. 147
S. Yamagishi and K. Eguchi note in Ibis, vol. 138, pp. 283–290, 1996 (see also S. Yamagishi
et al. in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 53, pp. 39–56, 2001) that ‘The bill shapes in this
family vary so widely that it is difficult to believe these vangids belong to a single family’
(p. 284). Their paper is an exploration of the wide range of foraging ecologies. In particular,
analysis of the Sickle-billed Vanga (Falculea palliata) ‘suggests that this species is a true
substitute for woodpeckers’. Yamagishi and Eguchi are careful to add that ‘Even with this
species, however, the niche of woodpeckers, with special adaptations for boring through the
concealing wood and for probing the exposed tunnel to catch the retreating insect, is not
completely occupied. Thus we may conclude that several vangid species each partially fill the
role of woodpeckers on this island’ (p. 288). M. Cartmill, in his chapter (pp. 655–670) in
Prosimian biology, edited by R. D. Martin et al. (Duckworth, London, 1974), also presents a
list of other islands, uncolonized by true woodpeckers, that in one way or another possess an
avifauna that has ‘developed adaptations analogous to the picid [woodpecker] specialisations
for tunnelling and probing in wood’ (p. 657).
3. Specifically these are the strongly convergent aye-aye (Daubentonia), certain marsupial
possums (Dactylopsila) (see Cartmill 1974), and an extinct group known as the apatemyids
(see W. v. Koenigswald and H.-P. Schierning in Nature, vol. 326, pp. 595–597, 1987). Of
Daubentonia Cartmill wrote that it ‘forages for wood-boring grubs in the rain forest . . . of
Madagascar. In feeding, it begins by tapping the surface of a branch . . . turning its large ears
towards the spot being investigated. Detecting an insect, it probes the crevices of the infested
plant with a grotesquely attentuated third finger, exposing deep-burrowing larvae by biting
and tearing at the wood with its rodent-like incisor teeth’ (p. 657). Cartmill continues by
addressing the similarities to Dactylopsila, remarking, ‘it must be assumed that all the
peculiar cranial traits [of Daubentonia and Dactylopsila] are . . . functionally related to their
other adaptations for preying on wood-boring insects. This assumption is further supported
by the fact that comparable peculiarities . . . are characteristic of woodpeckers’ (p. 662). In the
opinion of T. Iwano and C. Iwakawa (Folia Primatologica, vol. 50, pp. 136–142, 1988) the
aye-aye is better regarded as being convergent on squirrels, a group that is also absent from
Madagascar. So woodpecker or squirrel mimic? In one sense both, because N. Garbutt points
out in Mammals of Madagascar (Pica Press, Sussex, 1999) that the aye-aye is adept at opening
nuts and scooping out the contents with its extraordinary middle finger, and is also known to
raid coconut plantations. This animal also spends considerable time searching for insect
grubs, as described above. In any event, J. M. Diamond is less than impressed with these
convergences on woodpeckers (see his chapter (pp. 157–164) in Extraterrestrials: Where are
they?, edited by B. Zuckerman and M. H. Hart (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995
[Second edition]) He has a point, but to infer an absence of extraterrestrial intelligences on the
basis of woodpecker monophyly, and against the mass of other evidence for convergences at
all levels, suggests that it is perhaps a belief system that is being called into question.
4. This is the celebrated Bombardier Beetle. A helpful introduction is given by W. Agosta in his
book Bombardier beetles and fever trees: A close-up look at chemical warfare and signals in
animals and plants (Addison- Wesley, Reading, MA, 1996), see pp. 38–41. The mechanism of
bombardment depends on combining a mixture of hydroquinones plus hydrogen peroxide,
and driving the chemical reaction with enzymes. It produces a scaldingly hot (100 ◦ C) and
toxic defensive spray; see D. J. Aneshansley et al. in Science (vol. 165, pp. 61–63, 1969). In one
group of Bombardiers, the paussine beetles, the accuracy of the discharge is dependent on the
so-called Coanda Effect. This is familiar from the irritating habit of certain brands of teapot to
dribble the tea down the spout rather than into the cup. In the case of the Bombardier,
however, small flanges, that hitherto seemed to be without an adaptive function, ‘serve as
launching guides’ for the corrosive fluid when the animal chooses to shoot forwards; see
T. Eisner and D. J. Aneshansley in Science, vol. 215, pp. 83–85, 1982, as well as a subsequent
article by T. Eisner et al. in Psyche, vol. 96, pp. 153–160, 1989. Whether or not the bombardier
habit evolved independently in a variety of beetles is still debated; see for example T. Eisner
notes to pp. 147–149 373
et al. in Chemoecology, vol. 2, pp. 29–34, 1991. Squirting hot and toxic irritants in the faces of
your foes is not the only way to deal with trouble. Chapter 15 of The biology of the Coleoptera
(Academic Press, London, 1981) by R. A. Crowson gives many other fascinating examples of
how beetles defend themselves. Explosive discharges of protective chemicals are not confined
to the insects; some millipedes spray quinone-containing secretions, while the polydesmid
millipedes produce a protective cloud of hydrogen cyanide; see the description by T. Eisner
et al. of the defensive secretions of millipedes on pp. 41–72 of Arthropod venoms, edited by S.
Bettini (Springer, Berlin, 1978). Another fascinating example of defence is the release of fine
hairs that entangle a would-be predator, such as occurs in the larvae of the dermestid beetles
(more familiar as the ‘woolly bear’ and carpet beetle; my brother, unfamiliar with these
beasts, recently sent me a specimen for identification drowned in gin) (see M. Ma et al. in
Annals of the Entomological Society of America, vol. 71, pp. 718–723, 1978). An interesting
convergent arrangement has been arrived at by the polyxenid millipedes; see T. Eisner et al.
in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 93, pp. 10848–10051,
1996.
5. A group known as the tunicates (or sea-squirts), which are quite closely related to the
vertebrates, have a thick outer tunic which contains a proportion of the biopolymer cellulose;
see D. D. P. Delmer in Annual Review of Plant Physiology and Plant Molecular Biology,
vol. 50, pp. 245–276, 1999. Cellulose is otherwise unknown in animals but is typical of plants
(as well as algae and some bacteria; see Y. van Daele et al. in Bulletin de Société Royale
Sciences de Liège, vol. 59, pp. 329–417, 1990, and Biology of the Cell, vol. 76, pp. 87–96, 1992;
and S. Kimura et al. in Protoplasma, vol. 194, pp. 151–163, 1996, vol. 204, pp. 94–102, 1998,
and vol. 216, pp. 71–74, 2001). It is not clear whether cellulose has evolved more than once.
Given, however, that cellulose is just one example of a carbohydrate polymer (others being
chitin, which is typical of insect exoskeletons, and hyaluronan, which is important in skin
and cartilage), and that there is some evidence that hyaluronan synthase has probably evolved
twice (see A. P. Spicer and J. A. McDonald in Journal of Biological Chemistry, vol. 273,
pp. 1923–1932, 1998), then it would not be particularly surprising if the same held true for
cellulose (see p. 1930).
6. As discussed below the acuity of the compound eye is substantially less than that of the
camera-eye, and it is perhaps unlikely that the eyes of a mosquito could specifically resolve
my image. However, wasps have a visual acuity that permits identification of other
individuals; see E. A. Tibbetts in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 269,
pp. 1423–1428, 2002.
7. The details of convergence of vision, hearing, and olfaction are returned to below. The
similarities of motor control of locomotion in vertebrates and insects are reviewed by K. G.
Pearson in Annual Review of Neuroscience, vol. 16, pp. 265–297, 1993, and Current Opinion
in Neurobiology, vol. 5, pp. 786–791, 1995. In the former article, for example, he notes that
‘Many of the observations on the afferent control of the stance to swing transition in the cat
are closely paralleled by findings in the walking systems of crustacea and insects’ (p. 279).
(Citation is in note 28.)
8. See D. Sandeman’s absorbing paper ‘Homology and convergence in vertebrate and
invertebrate nervous systems’, published in Naturwissenschaften, vol. 86, pp. 378–387, 1999.
This article is a rich
source of insights on convergences, some of which are returned to below. As Sandeman
remarks, the topic remains of perennial interest because ‘Convergences provide us with a
glimpse of what may be a “best way” to achieve an end’, p. 386.
9. D. Sandeman (1999; citation is in note 8), p. 383.
10. The phylogenetic position of the strepsipterans has long been problematic, but molecular data
published by A. Rokas et al. in Insect Molecular Biology, vol. 8, pp. 527–530, 1999, suggests
this group is not close to dipterans, leaving little doubt that the evolution of halteres, as they
remark, is ‘a remarkable case of convergent evolution’ (p. 529). (See also note 11.)
374 notes to pp. 149–151
11. More details of these rather remarkable insects may be found in the review by J.
Kathirithamby in Systematic Entomology, vol. 14, pp. 41–92, 1989. Additional papers by
Kathirithamby on the strepsipterans include those on the elusive females (in Zoological
Journal of the Linnean Society, vol. 128, pp. 269–287, 2000), and a special issue (number 1) of
vol. 27 of International Journal of Insect Morphology and Embryology, 1998. The last paper
(pp. 53–60) in this issue, by M. F. Whiting, considers the phylogenetic position of the
strepsipterans, and contrary to Rokas et al. (1999) concludes that they are close to the
dipterans (but see the discussion by M. F. Whiting and J. P. Huelsenbeck in Systematic
Biology, vol. 47, pp. 134–138 and 519–537 respectively, 1998; see also W. C. Wheeler et al. in
Cladistics, vol. 17, pp. 113–169, 2001).
12. J. Kathirithamby (1989; citation is in note 11) notes, ‘Structurally and functionally the
mesothoracic wings of Strepsiptera are analogous to the dipteran halteres’ (p. 52), and this
comparison is pursued in greater detail by W. Pix et al. in Naturwissenschaften, vol. 80,
pp. 371–374, 1993.
13. Elytra are modified hind-wings characteristic of beetles, and although sometimes involved in
flight their principal function seems to be to provide a protective wing-case. However, in the
Uganda lymexylid beetle (Atractocercus brevicornis), which unusually for this group is a fast
flyer, the elytra have been modified into haltere-like organs. If they are removed, stable flight
is no longer possible. Interestingly, despite the use of these natural gyroscopes, the sensory
equipment of this African beetle is simpler than that seen in the dipterans. Details of this
remarkable beetle may be found in P. L. Miller’s paper in The Entomologist, vol. 104,
pp. 105–110, 1971.
14. See A. D. Imms’s A general textbook of entomology including the anatomy, physiology,
development and classification of insects (9th edition, revised by O. W. Richards and R. G.
Davies) (Methuen, London, 1957).
15. A. D. Imms (1957; citation is in note 14), p. 452.
16. An overview of this type of gravity perception, and especially the minerals employed, may be
found on pp. 190–196 in H. A. Lowenstam and S. Weiner’s On biomineralization (Oxford
University Press, New York, 1989); see also M. D. Ross in Advances in Space Research, vol. 4
(12), pp. 305–314, 1984.
17. These statocysts occur in the so-called Müller vesicles, found in a group of ciliates known as
the loxodids; see T. Fenchel and B. J. Finlay in Journal of Protozoology, vol. 33, pp. 69–76,
1986.
18. For a brief resumé see D. Sandeman (1999; citation is in note 8). More detailed accounts are
available in two consecutive papers by D. Sandeman and C. Janse, published in Journal of
Comparative Physiology, vol. 130, pp. 95–111, 1979, and D. Sandeman in Fortschritte der
Zoologie, vol. 28, pp. 213–229, 1983.
19. D. Sandeman (1983; citation is in note 8), p. 228.
20. Reference to the literature on eyes is given below, including a number of general reviews. In
this latter category should also be added vol. 2 (Evolution of the eye and visual system),
edited by J. R. Cronly-Dillon and R. L. Gregory, of Vision and visual dysfunction (Macmillan,
London, 1991), Animal eyes by M. F. Land and D-E. Nilsson (Oxford University Press, Oxford,
2002), the paper in Annual Review of Neuroscience, vol. 15, pp. 1–29, 1992 by M. F. Land and
R. D. Fernald simply entitled The evolution of eyes, and the review with the same title by M.
F. Land in Berlin-Brandenburgische Akademie der Wissenschaften Berichte und
Abhandlungen, vol. 8, pp. 311–334, 2000.
21. I should emphasize that there are many other types of eye (see references and citations note
20). These demonstrate a whole series of remarkable adaptations, not least the amazing
triple-lens system of the copepod Pontella. Although I touch on a few such examples my
emphasis here is on convergences and the limits of possibility.
22. A helpful overview of cephalopod eyes (and the other sense-organs) is given by B. U.
Budelmann in Marine and Freshwater Behaviour and Physiology, vol. 25, pp. 13–33,
1994.
notes to pp. 153–154 375
23. Not all cephalopods have lenses; for an interesting discussion of the primitive pinhole eye of
the cephalopod Nautilus see J. B. Messenger on p. 374 of Cronly-Dillon and Gregory (1991;
citation is in note 20). Land (2000; citation is in note 20) expresses surprise that Nautilus has
failed to evolve a lens: ‘The problem, from an evolutionary point of view is that almost any
blob of jelly, placed in the region behind the pupil, would improve both image quality and
light gathering power . . . Why did this not happen in Nautilus? I still find this a bigger
mystery than the origin of really good eyes, which so concerned Darwin’ (p. 321). This is a fair
point, but may in part be answered by reference to the olfactory capabilities of Nautilus; see J.
A. Basil et al. in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 203, pp. 1409–1414, 2000, as well as its
crepuscular habit and low metabolic rate (concerning the latter see R. G. Boutilier et al. in
Nature, vol. 382, pp. 534–536, 1996). When Nautilus ‘needs’ a lens, so it will be ‘provided’.
24. See the paper by B. Willekens et al. in Tissue & Cell, vol. 16, pp. 941–950, 1984, where they
document the lens structure of Sepiola.
25. For more information on the cephalopod lens see the review by J. M. Arnold on pp. 265–311
of Experimental embryology of marine and fresh-water invertebrates, edited by G. Reverberi
(North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1971). Other relevant papers by J. M. Arnold are in Journal of
Ultrastructure Research, vol. 14, pp. 534–539, 1966 and vol. 17, pp. 527–543, 1967
respectively, as well as T. J. C. Jacob and G. Duncan in Nature, vol. 290, pp. 704–706, 1981.
Other helpful reviews are in chapters 17 (by H. R. Saibil, pp. 371–397) and 18 (by I. A.
Meinertshagen, pp. 399–419) in Squid as experimental animals, edited by D. L. Gilbert et al.
(Plenum, New York, 1990).
26. The idea that focusing depends on the movement of the cephalopod lens is raised by J. G.
Sivak in Journal of Comparative Physiology, vol. 147A, pp. 323–327, 1982, although this idea
goes back many years; see J. S. Alexandrowicz in Archives de zoologie expérimentale et
générale, vol. 66, pp. 71–134, 1927.
27. The focal properties of the cephalopod lens are addressed by J. G. Sivak in Canadian Journal
of Zoology, vol. 69, pp. 2501–2506, 1991.
28. So, too, flying insects have a sophisticated and integrated control system that not only links
specific sensory inputs to motor control, but has fail-safe mechanisms whereby input of
faulty data does not lead to catastrophic error. See, for example, H. Reichert and C. H. F.
Rowell in Trends in Neurosciences, vol. 9, pp. 281–283, 1986, who note, ‘It would not be
surprising if similar principles of neuronal organization were found in all animals that need to
integrate a rhythmic motor output with non-phase-locked sensory input’, p. 283.
29. See the papers by B. U. Budelmann and J. Z. Young in Philosophical Transactions of the Royal
Society of London, B, vol. 306, pp. 159–189, 1984, the overview by B. U. Budelmann 1994
(citation is in note 22) as well as the detailed tabular comparison between cephalopod and
vertebrate vestibulo-oculomotor reflexes by B. U. Budelmann and Y. Tu in Vie et Milieu,
vol. 47, pp. 95–99, 1997. Details of the statocyst organization in octopus are addressed by B. U.
Budelmann et al. in Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 315,
pp. 305–343, 1987. These authors emphasize the complexity of the system, and while noting
the differences from the vertebrate system they also stress ‘striking analogies’, p. 340.
30. See H. Collewijn’s paper comparing eye movement of cuttlefish and rabbit, in Journal of
Experimental Biology, vol. 52, pp. 369–384, 1970. In addition A. McVean in Comparative
Biochemistry and Physiology, vol. 78A, pp. 711–718, 1984, emphasizes that in comparison
with the mammals, the extra-ocular muscles in the octopus are inferior in such matters as
speed of contraction and muscle viscosity. Interestingly, the arrangement of the musculature
that moves the head of the fly is analogous to the optic muscles so that the entire head
capsule, with its paired compound eyes, is equivalent to the vertebrate eye; see
N. J. Strausfeld et al. and J. J. Milde et al. in Journal of Comparative Physiology, vol. 160A,
pp. 205–224 and 225–238 respectively, 1987.
31. Earthworms are oligochaetes, and although once thought to be the most primitive annelids,
the almost entirely marine polychaetes are usually cast in this role. The leeches, famous for
their blood-sucking abilities, are thought to have arisen from the oligochaetes.
376 notes to p. 154
32. Key papers are those by C. O. Hermans and R. M. Eakin in Zeitschrift für Morphologie der
Tiere, vol. 79, pp. 245–267, 1974, and G. Wald and S. Raypart in Science, vol. 196,
pp. 1434–1439, 1977. Wald and Raypart are enthusiastic in their identification of the
convergences (with words such as ‘remarkable’ and ‘extraordinary’), whereas although
Hermans and Eakin (1974) accept convergence, at the same time they struggle to find an
underlying homology between the alciopid camera-eye and that of the
cephalopods.
33. Annelids and molluscs, as well as various other groups such as the brachiopods, nemerteans,
and platyhelminthes, are placed in a group known as the lophotrochozoans. Such similarities
as there are in terms of the camera-eyes are due to similar modes of embryological
development, and not because those of cephalopod and alciopid polychaete evolved from a
common ancestor that possessed such an eye.
34. G. Wald and S. Raypart (1977; citation is in note 32) remark, ‘The presence of accessory
retinas in alciopid eyes offers a prime instance of the phenomenon of evolutionary
convergence’, p. 1437. They suggest that they may function to detect light of long wavelength,
which penetrates more deeply into the sea, and could thus be used to judge depth.
35. A general overview of the camera-like eyes in both the heteropods (such as Pterotrachea) and
also Littorina and Strombus (see notes 37 and 38 respectively), is given by G. H. Charles on
pp. 455–521 of vol. II of Physiology of Mollusca, edited by K. M. Wilbur and C. M. Yonge
(Academic Press, London, 1966); see also the superb review by M. F. Land on pp. 471–592 of
Handbook of sensory physiology, vol. VII/6B: Invertebrate visual centers and behavior I,
edited by H. Autrum (Springer, Berlin, 1981), and also the chapter (pp. 364–397) by Messenger
in Cronly-Dillon and Gregory (1991; citation is in note 20).
36. Although reviewed in more recent literature, the key reference on heteropods was published
more than a century ago by R. Hesse in Zeitschrift für Wissenschaftliche Zoologie, vol. 68,
pp. 379–477, 1900. The complex structure of the photoreceptors in Pterotrachea, which have
some resemblances to those of vertebrates, is addressed by P. N. Dilly in Zeitschrift für
Zellforschung und mikroskopische Anatomie, vol. 99, pp. 420–429, 1969. A curiosity of the
heteropods is that although the eye is camera-like, the retina consists of a narrow ribbon. In
life there are rapid scanning movements in which the eye is rapidly flicked downwards and
then slowly returns to the horizontal position. M. F. Land, in Journal of Experimental
Biology, vol. 96, pp. 427–430, 1982, suggests that this scanning makes possible the detection
of stationary objects. Interestingly, in the heteropod Atlanta the movement of the eyes is
synchronous and their overlap suggests the possession of binocular vision (see notes 86 and
89).
37. Concerning the well-known winkle Littorina littorea, see the paper by G. F. Newell in
Proceedings of the Zoological Society of London, vol. 144, pp. 75–86, 1965. The eye structure
of L. irrorata is discussed by P. V. Hamilton et al. in Journal of Comparative Physiology,
vol. 152A, pp. 435–445, 1983.
38. Aspects of the sophistication of the eye of Strombus are addressed by H. L. Gillary in Journal
of Experimental Biology, vol. 60, pp. 383–396, 1974; vol. 66, pp. 159–171, 1977; and vol. 107,
pp. 243–310, 1983. Further details of the ultrastructure of these eyes are given by H. L. Gillary
and E. W. Gillary in Journal of Morphology, vol. 159, pp. 89–116, 1979; the light-sensitive
pigments (rhodopsin and retinochrome) are discussed by K. Ozaki et al. in Vision Research,
vol. 26, pp. 691–705, 1986.
39. For accounts of the structure of the cubozoan eye, see V. J. Martin in Canadian Journal of
Zoology, vol. 80, pp. 1703–1722, 2002, G. Laska and M. Hündgen in Zoologische Jahrbücher
Abteilung für Anatomie und Ontogenie der Tiere, vol. 108, pp. 107–123, 1982, and J. S. Pearse
and V. B. Pearse in Science, vol. 199, p. 458, 1978. See also J. Piatigorsky et al. in Journal of
Comparative Physiology, vol. 164A, pp. 577–587, 1989.
40. The suggestion that the lens might be adjustable was made by F. W. Berger in Memoirs from
the Biological Laboratory of the Johns Hopkins University, vol. 4(4), pp. vi + 84, 1900; see
pp. 44 and 58–60, see also Piatigorsky et al. (1989).
notes to pp. 154–156 377
41. See, for example, the work by M. J. F. Blumer et al. in Zoomorphology, vol. 115, pp. 221–227,
1995. Most probably the light-sensitive protein employed will be rhodopsin, the importance
of which is returned to below. C. Musio et al. report (in Journal of Comparative Physiology,
vol. 187A, pp. 79–81, 2001) a rhodopsin-like molecule in Hydra, but this animal lacks
eye-spots, and, curiously, expression of the protein is widely distributed across the
animal.
42. Evidence for the visual abilities of cubozoans is given by W. M. Hamner et al. in Marine
Freshwater Research, vol. 46, pp. 985–990, 1995, and they cite some intriguing observations
by an earlier investigator, J. H. Barnes. R. F. Hartwick (in Hydrobiologia, vol. 216/217,
pp. 171–179, 1991) also has some interesting comments on the possible role of vision in the
cubozoans, especially with respect to search for mates. G. I. Matsumoto (in Marine and
Freshwater Behavior and Physiology, vol. 26, pp. 139–148, 1995) also reviews the optical
acuity of the cubozoans, and leaves little room for doubt that these animals genuinely see
objects. See also S. E. Stewart in Marine and Freshwater Behavior and Physiology, vol. 27,
pp. 175–188, 1996.
43. This rather remarkable behaviour, for a cnidarian, is discussed by B. Werner in Marine
Biology, vol. 18, pp. 212–217, 1973, and entails transfer of the spermatophores to the female
in a series of specific steps. See also Hartwick (1991).
44. Comparable remarks apply also to the other cnidarians, such as Hydra, with their nerve nets.
For example, G. O. Mackie (in American Zoologist, vol. 30, pp. 907–920, 1990) points to
various under-appreciated complexities, including pacemakers and giant axons, as well as
quite sophisticated behaviours, remarking, ‘most modern workers would have to agree with
Parker [a distinguished biologist] in dismissing as inadequate both von Uexkull’s description
of sea anemones as “a bundle of reflexes” and, at the other extreme, Gosse’s [“hero” of
Edmund Gosse’s Father and son] picture of them as creatures endowed by consciousness and
will’, p. 917.
45. Unless one labels a pacemaker as a brain, and this is still remote from the bilaterian brain.
Nick Strausfeld has suggested to me that the earliest function of the brain was ‘to assess
asymmetries in the sensory surround and to compensate for these by appropriate motor
efferent reply. From this basal condition brains might have evolved specialized connections to
exploit asymmetries of the sensory world by mediating appropriate downstream asymmetries
of motion, which would provide for goal-directed behavior’ (personal communication;
10/02/2002).
46. See Matsumoto (1995, citation is in note 42), p. 146. He also hints that the unique lens
proteins (the crystallins; see Piatigorsky et al. (1989, citation is in note 39; see also note 114)
developed by the cubozoans might also be a significant factor. While the origin of these
cubozoan crystallins is, unsurprisingly, separate from other animals (see J. Piatigorsky et al.
in Journal of Biological Chemistry, vol. 268, pp. 11894–11901, 1993; see also J. Piatigorsky (in
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 98, pp. 12362–12367, 2001),
these novel lens proteins actually provide an excellent example of molecular convergence
(citation is in note 114 and Chapter 10).
47. The ‘unexpected complexity’ refers specifically to the enteric nervous system of echinoderms
as documented by J. E. Garcı́a-Arrarás et al. in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 204,
pp. 865–873, 2001.
48. Richard Satterlie and Thomas Nolan’s paper is in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 204,
pp. 1413–1419, 2001.
49. R. Satterlie and T. Nolen (2001), p. 1418.
50. However speculative intelligence based on a nerve net might be, so far as brains are
concerned we shall see in the following chapters that there are indeed several but convergent
routes to ‘orthodox’ intelligence.
51. An account of the predatory behaviour of a Panamanian species of Dinopis is given by M. H.
Robinson and B. Robinson in The American Midland Naturalist, vol. 85, pp. 85–96, 1971; the
behaviour of an Australian species is addressed by A. D. Austin and A. D. Blest in Journal of
378 notes to pp. 156–158
Zoology, London, vol. 189, pp.145–156, 1979. The sensitivity of the eyes of Dinopis to its
night-time prey is discussed below, but this spider may have a further trick up its ‘sleeve’. As
Austin and Blest note, ‘There is a suggestion that Dinopis may enhance prey/background
contrast by an ingenious device . . . Dinopis always defecates on completing
snare-construction . . . the white splash of faeces makes a conspicuous spot on the ground
roughly in the middle of the field which the spider surveys, and over which the prey must
run’, p. 156.
52. This account of the Dinopis eye is taken from the paper by A. D. Blest and M. F. Land in the
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 196, pp. 197–222, 1977. Further insights
into the rather remarkable sensitivity of this eye are given by S. Laughlin et al. in Journal of
Comparative Physiology, vol. 141A, pp. 53–65, 1980.
53. See the two consecutive papers by M. F. Land in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 51,
pp. 443–470 and 471–493, 1969, as well as the review on pp. 53–78 of Neurology of arachnids,
edited by F. G. Barth (Springer, Berlin, 1985).
54. See D. L. Clark and G. W. Uetz in Animal Behaviour, vol. 40, pp. 884–890, 1990.
55. See D. S. Williams and P. McIntyre in Nature, vol. 288, pp. 578–580, 1980. In addition to
describing the retinal structure that makes a telephoto component possible, they also
note a similarity to certain birds, remarking, ‘Both a group of vertebrates and invertebrates
have therefore adopted the same strategy to improve the visual acuity despite a restricted
cephalic space’, p. 580. Further, these workers demonstrate that the lenses of the jumping
spiders are able to correct for spherical aberration in the same way as the net-casting
spiders.
56. Concerning the spectral sensitivities of these jumping spiders, see A. D. Blest et al. in Journal
of Comparative Physiology, vol. 145A, pp. 227–239, 1981; S. Yamashita on pp. 103–117 of
Barth (1985; citation is in note 53); and A. G. Peaslee and G. Wilson in Journal of
Comparative Physiology, vol. 164A, pp. 359–363, 1989.
57. M. F. Land (1981; citation is in note 35), p. 515. Ten years later, Messenger, in Cronly-Dillon
and Gregory (1991; citation is in note 20), could write regarding Strombus, ‘Indeed we have no
clues to the function of these remarkable eyes’, p. 376.
58. Evidence of biotic interaction and displacement of the strombids against the aporrhaids is
reviewed by K. Roy in Paleobiology, vol. 22, pp. 436–452, 1996.
59. K. Roy (1996; citation is in note 58), p. 441. Further information on strombid behaviour and
ecology, especially its remarkable activity, is given by C. J. Berg in Behaviour, vol. 51,
pp. 274–322, 1974, and Bulletin of Marine Science, vol. 25, pp. 307–317, 1975.
60. See F. Evans, in Proceedings of the Zoological Society of London, vol. 137, pp. 393–402, 1961,
who describes the various behaviours of some Ghanaian winkles.
61. See P. V. Hamilton in Marine Behaviour and Physiology, vol. 5, pp. 255–271, 1978.
62. One should note there are other ways of dealing with the problem of seeing on featureless
tidal flats. In some shore-dwelling crabs, such as the fiddler crabs, the compound eyes are
mounted on long stalks like periscopes and have a high resolving power conferred by a
specific arrangement of the components (ommatidia) that provides a so-called acute zone; see
J. Zeil et al. in Journal of Comparative Physiology, vol. 159A, pp. 801–811, 1986. These
workers also remark that ‘visual systems adapted to the geometry of vision in a flat world’
(p. 810) have evolved independently in the insects, among the hemipterans and dipterans, and
an analogy can also be found between the acute zone of arthropods and the visual streak
found in the eyes of various vertebrates that live in open habitats.
63. Further discussion in the optical acuity of winkles can be found in the paper by P. V.
Hamilton and M. A. Winter in Animal Behaviour, vol. 30, pp. 752–760, 1982. Subsequently
these authors extended their study in vol. 32, pp. 51–57, 1984 to a variety of other snails,
emphasizing a range of visual abilities. Littorina irrorata was significantly better at shape
recognition than even a related snail, living in similar habitats, known as Tectarius
muricatus.
notes to pp. 158–159 379
75. See the paper by J. Aizenberg et al. in Nature, vol. 412, pp. 819–822, 2001 (and commentary
by R. Sambles on p. 783). Nor is this the first report of the possible role of the calcitic
skeleton in brittle-stars for optical sensitivity. For example, S. Johnsen in Journal of
Experimental Biology, vol. 195, pp. 281–291, 1994 suggests that parts of the skeleton are
sensitive to polarized light, and he subsequently reported the presence of probable rhodopsin
at the arm-tips (see Biological Bulletin, vol. 193, pp. 97–105, 1997).
76. A standard laboratory demonstration is to place a large crystal of clear calcite, known as
iceland spar, above a dot. Viewed through the crystal the dot becomes double, and as the
crystal rotates so one dot remains stationary, while the other dot rotates around it. If the
crystal is viewed along the optic axis, then the two dots coalesce into one.
77. For further information on the sensitivity of some brittle-stars, especially spectacular colour
changes, see G. Hendler in Marine Ecology, vol. 5, pp. 379–401, 1984.
78. Schizochroal eyes are particularly characteristic of the phacopid trilobites, and consist of
large biconvex lenses set in cup-like sclera and surrounded by calcitic skeleton.
79. Concerning the investigation of the doublet structure of schizochroal eyes in trilobites the
key figure is E. N. K. Clarkson, whose papers in Palaeontology, vol. 22, pp. 1–22, 1979, and
with J. Miller in Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 288,
pp. 461–480, 1980, provide the necessary details. A further development in this area is the
suggestion, by J. Gál et al. in Vision Research, vol. 40, pp. 843–853, 2000, that this type of
trilobite lens could also act as a bifocal.
80. K. M. Towe, in Geological Society of America Abstracts with Program, vol. 11, p. 529, 1979,
questions whether the supposed doublet structure is not an artefact of diagenesis, specifically
recrystallization and migration of ions.
81. This famous experiment was undertaken by K. M. Towe and reported in Science, vol. 179,
pp. 1007–1009, 1973, and involved capturing images of ‘happy faces’; see his Fig. 1j.
82. See the paper by D-E. Nilsson and R. F. Modlin in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 189,
pp. 213–236, 1994.
83. D-E. Nilsson and R. F. Modlin (1994; citation is in note 82), p. 216.
84. D-E. Nilsson and R. F. Modlin (1994; citation is in note 82), p. 227.
85. See K. Kirschfeld’s chapter on pp. 354–370 of Neural principles in vision, edited by F. Zettler
and R. Weiler (Springer, Berlin, 1976), as well as the additional remarks in Land (1981; see
note 35 for citation) on pp. 551–553. More details on what arthropod eyes are, and are not,
capable of is given by E. J. Warrant and P. D. McIntyre in Progress in Neurobiology, vol. 40,
pp. 413–461, 1993. The relative ineffectiveness of the compound eye has, moreover, been long
appreciated; see the paper by A. Mallock in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London,
vol. 55, pp. 85–90, 1894.
86. See, for example, the remarks by J. D. Pettigrew on the evolution of binocular vision
(pp. 271–283) in Cronly-Dillon and Gregory (1991; citation is in note 20). He also remarks
that such vision may extend at least to fish and amphibians. For an interesting exception to
avian binocular vision see note 231.
87. See M. F. Land’s paper in Journal of Insect Physiology, vol. 38, pp. 939–951, 1992.
88. M. F. Land (1992; citation is in note 87), p. 947.
89. See S. Rossel in Nature, vol. 302, pp. 821–822, 1983, and Y. Toh and J.-Y. Okamura in Journal
of Experimental Biology, vol. 204, pp. 615–625, 2001.
90. See, for example, the remarks by N. J. Strausfeld and J.-K. Lee in Visual Neuroscience, vol. 7,
pp. 13–33, 1991, which not only document some of the extraordinary complexity of the visual
centres in the insect brain, but also touch on the canonical properties of such nervous
systems as are shared by insect and primate.
91. See the fascinating paper by J. D. Pettigrew et al. in Current Biology, vol. 9, pp. 421–424,
1999, as well as the commentary by M. V. Srinavasan in Nature, vol. 399, pp. 305–306, 1999.
Concerning ‘This remarkable convergence’ (p. 424) Pettigrew et al. present a list (their Table
1) of the convergent features between the optics and behaviours of the chameleons and
notes to pp. 164–165 381
sand-lances. Thirteen are listed, of which five are not otherwise known in any other lizard or
fish. Srinivasan remarks ‘in these two animals, eye design cannot be predicted by evolutionary
origin – rather, it has been crafted almost exclusively by environmental constraints’, p. 305.
92. Rapid strikes at prey by using a tongue are also familiar in the frogs, where as K. C.
Nishikawa (in BioScience, vol. 47, pp. 341–354, 1997) notes that the more derived and
sophisticated method known as ‘inertial elongation of the tongue [has] evolved as many as
eight times independently’, and that ‘Surprisingly, novel sensory fibers (i.e. afferents) in the
tongue have evolved independently four to five times in frogs that use inertial elongation to
protract their tongues’, p. 344.
93. Luitfried v. Salvini-Plawen and Ernst Mayr’s much-cited paper ‘On the evolution of
photoreceptors and eyes’ was published in Evolutionary Biology, vol. 10, pp. 207–263, 1977.
94. L. v. Salvini-Plawen and E. Mayr (1977; citation is in note 93), p. 249.
95. See the helpful overview by M. F. Land in Scientific American, vol. 239 (part 6), pp. 88–99,
1978, as well as M. F. Land (1981), pp. 536–538, and Messenger (1991; both citations are in
note 35).
96. See his review on pp. 118–135 of J. R. Cronly-Dillon and R. L. Gregory (1991; citation is in
note 20).
97. M. F. Land (1991; citation is in note 20), p. 124 (his emphasis).
98. Guanine, however, is not a universal reflector, and in at least some cephalopods the material
employed appears to be chitin; see the paper by E. J. Denton and M. F. Land in Proceedings of
the Royal Society of London B, vol. 178, pp. 43–61, 1971.
99. In his 1981 paper M. F. Land (citation is in note 35) remarks on the surprising fact that the
deep-sea squids lack an equivalent tapetum, despite the manifest advantages of some such
light-gathering mechanism in the inky depths of this environment. Land, however, goes on to
note that one group of invertebrates, the lycosid spiders, has managed this feat.
100. This is particularly pronounced in the hatchet fish; see the paper by E. J. Denton on pp. 59–86
of Marine biology: its accomplishment and future prospect, edited by J. Mauchline and T.
Nemoto (Hokusen-Sha, Tokyo, 1991), as well as the paper by E. J. Denton et al. in
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 225, pp. 63–97, 1985.
101. There is a wide literature on protistan eye-spots. Useful overviews are given by K. W. Foster
and R. D. Smyth in Microbiological Reviews, vol. 44, pp. 572–630, 1980 and J. D. Dodge on
pp. 323–340 of Cronly-Dillon and Gregory (1991; citation is in note 20). More specific papers
include those by K. W. Foster et al. in Nature, vol. 311, pp. 756–759, 1984; G. Kreimer et al. in
FEBS Letters, vol. 293, pp. 49–52, 1991; W. Deininger et al. in EMBO Journal, vol. 14,
pp. 5849–5858, 1995; and E. Ebnet et al. in The Plant Cell, vol. 11, pp. 1473–1484, 1999.
Information on the genes connected to eye-spot formation, which has to occur every time the
cell divides, is given by M. R. Lamb et al. and D. G. W. Roberts et al. in Genetics, respectively
in vol. 153, pp. 721–729, 1999, and vol. 158, pp. 1037–1049, 2001.
102. What P. A. Kivic and P. L. Walne describe in the title of their paper as ‘multiple parallel
evolutions’ of protistan eye-spots is discussed in BioSystems, vol. 16, pp. 31–38, 1983. They
also emphasize that nearly always the photosensory apparatus arises as a modification of a
pre-existing system. Even bacteria have eye-spots; see P. Albertano et al. in Micron, vol. 31,
pp. 27–34, 2000.
103. See K. Schaller and R. Uhl in Biophysical Journal, vol. 73, pp. 1573–1578, 1997, where they
note that the reflectance is concentrated in the yellow part of the spectrum. The preceding
and companion paper by Schaller et al. (pp. 1562–1572) shows the remarkable phototactic
response of Chlamydomonas.
104. These are more familiar, and more unwelcome than is sometimes realized because
dinoflagellate ‘blooms’ are responsible for so-called red tides and in some instances for the
release of toxins whose transfer to shellfish can lead to dire consequences for the gourmet.
Information on these toxins is given by Y. Shimizu on pp. 282–315 of The biology of
dinoflagellates, edited by F. J. R. Taylor (Blackwell, Oxford, 1987).
382 notes to pp. 165–166
105. For a succinct review of dinoflagellate eye-spots see Dodge (1991; citation is in note 20).
106. Dinoflagellate ‘eyes’ are typical of the warnowiids, and interesting descriptions are given by
C. Greuet in Protistologica, vol. 4, pp. 209–230, 1968, and vol. 13, pp. 127–143, 1977; and
Cytobiologie, vol. 17, pp. 114–136, 1978. An overview is provided by the same author on
pp. 119–142 of Taylor (1987; citation is in note 104).
107. The dioptric properties of the crystalline lens are discussed by D. Francis in Journal of
Experimental Biology, vol. 47, pp. 495–501, 1967.
108. In his review of dinoflagellate evolution F. J. R. Taylor in BioSystems, vol. 13, pp. 65–108,
1980, remarks, ‘The ocelli exhibit an uncanny parallelism to the structure of metazoan eyes,
with all the major functional components except for conduction of signals, constructed
entirely at the subcellular level’, p. 76 (his emphasis).
109. See the chapter (pp. 207–227) by J. D. Dodge in The chromophyte algae: Problems and
perspectives, edited by J. C. Greene et al. (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1989). It also
appears that in the dinoflagellates the chloroplasts were acquired by secondary
endosymbiosis, which is again a convergent feature (see Chapter 6, note 6).
110. Ester Piccinni and Pietro Omodeo’s paper is in Bollettino di Zoologia, vol. 42, pp. 57–79, 1975.
111. E. Piccinni and P. Omodeo (1975; citation is in note 110), p. 72. This remark is echoed by
Taylor (1980; citation is in note 108) when he writes of the dinoflagellate eye-spot ‘What can
they do with a focussed image without a nervous system?’, p. 76.
112. Entanglement of prey is achieved by thread-like cnidocysts that are stored in specialized
organelles; see the papers by L. Mornin and D. Francis in Journal de Microscopie (Paris),
vol. 6, pp. 759–772, 1967 and C. Greuet in Protistologica, vol. 7, pp. 345–355, 1971; see also
the paper by C. Greuet and R. Hovasse in Protistologica, vol. 13, pp. 145–149, 1977, and
Greuet (1987; citation is in note 106).
113. The cnidocysts are convergent on the nematocysts of the cnidarians, which are painfully
familiar from jellyfish stings. What is probably another independent invention of the
cnidocyst is found in the myxozoans. Long thought to be protistans, it is now recognized they
represent parasitic metazoans. The cnidocyst-like structures, known as polar capsules,
seemed consistent with their being degenerate cnidarians (see, for example, M. E. Siddall
et al. in Journal of Parasitology, vol. 81, pp. 961–967, 1995 and M. Schlegel et al. in Archiv für
Protistenkunde, vol. 147, pp. 1–9, 1996), but it is now clear they are some sort of bilaterian, as
argued by J. F. Smothers et al. in Science, vol. 265, pp. 1719–1721, 1994, and by B. Okamura
et al. in Parasitology, vol. 124, pp. 215–223, 2002 (see also A. S. Monteiro et al. in Molecular
Biology and Evolution, vol. 19, pp. 968–971, 2002). Okamura et al. remark, ‘The resemblance
in morphogenesis and final structure of cnidarian nematocysts and myxozoan polar capsules
remains to be explained. We suggest the possibility that this may have arisen by independent
incorporation of eukaryotic symbionts into Cnidaria and Myxozoa which then evolved as
nematoblasts and capsulogenic cells respectively’, p. 222. These cnidocysts are only one of a
variety of so-called extrasomes, dischargeable thread-like structures (e.g. trichocysts,
toxicysts, etc.), found in various protistans; see K. Hausmann in International Review of
Cytology, vol. 52, pp. 197–276, 1978. His comments on the parallels are interesting:
‘Surprisingly, some enigmatic similarity exists between extrasomes and organelles of
systematically widely differing organisms such as . . . toxicysts of ciliates and the nematocysts
of cnidarians’, pp 267–268.
114. There is a rich and absorbing literature on the crystallins. Useful introductions can be found
in N. J. Clout et al. (Nature Structural Biology, vol. 4, p. 685, 1997); H. Janssens and W. J.
Gehring (Developmental Biology, vol. 207, pp. 204–214, 1999); J. Piatigorsky et al. (Journal of
Comparative Physiology, vol. 164A, pp. 577–587, 1989; Journal of Biological Chemistry,
vol. 267, pp. 4277–4280, 1992; Science, vol. 252, pp. 1078–1079, 1991; and especially their
wide-ranging review in European Journal of Biochemistry, vol. 235, pp. 449–465, 1996); P. J. L.
Werten et al. (Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 97,
pp. 3282–3287, 2000); G. Wistow et al. (Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
notes to pp. 166–168 383
USA, vol. 87, pp. 6277–6280, 1990; and Trends in Biochemical Sciences, vol. 18, pp. 301–306,
1993); and H. Chang et al. (Biophysical Journal, vol. 78, pp. 2070–2080, 2000).
115. The explanation for lens transparency was arrived at only relatively recently: see the paper in
Nature (vol. 302, pp. 415–417, 1983) by M. Delaye and A. Tardieu, as well as the
accompanying commentary by G. Benedek on pp. 383–384.
116. See the paper by J. Piatigorsky et al. in Journal of Biological Chemistry, vol. 275,
pp. 41064–41073, 2000. There appears to be only one crystallin in this bivalve mollusc, and it
is homologous to one of those found in the cephalopod eye.
117. A helpful review of these photophores is given by P. J. Herring in his chapter (pp. 199–240) in
Bioluminescence in action, edited by P. J. Herring (Academic Press, London, 1978).
A remarkable range of animals, not only in the sea but on land (e.g. fireflies) can produce
light, and Herring emphasizes how ‘luminescence has been developed on numerous separate
occasions’ (p. 239). Light production is also well known from dinoflagellates, sometimes
giving a beautiful oceanic phosphorescence, while glowing woods are illuminated by
bioluminescent fungi.
118. See M. K. Montgomery and M. J. McFall-Ngai in Journal of Biological Chemistry, vol. 267,
pp. 20999–21003, 1992. Nor is this the only such example of transformation of musculature
into a bioluminescent organ because I. A. Johnston and P. J. Herring describe such an example
(in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 225, pp. 213–218, 1985) in the
scopelarchid fish Benthalbella. It does not appear to be known whether this latter
transformation involves production of crystallins. The evolutionary versatility of the
modification of musculature extends yet further. This includes the development of electrical
organs, which will be considered below. In addition, rather remarkably an eye muscle of some
fish is modified as a heater organ to keep the eye and adjacent parts of the brain warm. See B.
A. Block and G. de Metrio et al. in Journal of Morphology, vol. 190, pp. 169–189, 1986 and
vol. 234, pp. 89–96, 1997 respectively.
119. For example, Piatigorsky et al. (1989; see note 114) remarks ‘The heterogeneity of proteins
that have been used as lens crystallins in different vertebrate and invertebrate species is
astounding. It is not known whether this is a consequence of evolutionary pragmatism with
many proteins being able to fulfil the requirements of lens transparency or whether each
species has differences which need lens proteins with special properties. In any case, the
diversity of lens crystallins throughout the animal kingdom is consistent with the occurrence
of convergent evolution’ (p. 584). A more specific example of convergence comes from the
crystallins found in the eye-lenses of frogs and lizards (geckos). These have been
independently recruited from the same protein superfamily, specifically a group of
stress-related enzymes known as the aldo-keto reductases; see M. A. M. van Boekel et al. in
Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 52, pp. 239–248, 2001. The geckos also show their own
example of ocular convergence. This concerns the shift from nocturnal vision to a diurnal
existence. This happened independently at least three times, and is established on the basis of
a study of the crystallins; see B. Röll in Naturwissenschaften, vol. 88, pp. 293–296, 2001.
120. See, for example, J. Nathans in Biochemistry, vol. 31, pp. 4923–4931, 1992.
121. Not to mention the story (or is it a myth?) of the pilots of the Luftwaffe being encouraged to
eat carrots (rich in vitamin A) before embarking on another night of flying in an attempt to
destroy the Royal Air Force.
122. See the papers by G. H. Jacobs et al. in Nature, vol. 382, pp. 156–158, 1996, and P. M. Kainz
et al. in Vision Research, vol. 38, pp. 3315–3320, 1998.
123. Evidence for trichromatic vision in Coquerel’s sifaka and the red ruffed lemur is presented by
Y. Tan and W.-H. Li in Nature, vol. 402, p. 36, 1999. These authors suggest trichromacy is
more primitive than has been thought, but the likelihood is that at least some features of
trichromatic vision in the primates are convergent; see G. K. Jacobs in Vision Research,
vol. 38, pp. 3307–3313, 1998, who emphasizes the case of the howler monkey (See also note
122).
384 notes to p. 168
124. Thus C. A. Arrese et al. (in Current Biology, vol. 12, pp. 657–660, 2002) suggest ‘the potential
for trichomacy in marsupials may have a different evolutionary origin from that in primates’,
p. 659.
125. A popular suggestion for the origin of trichromatic vision in these primates was to facilitate
the recognition of coloured fruits against the green background of the ancestral jungle habitat;
see the papers by B. C. Regan et al. in Vision Research, vol. 38, pp. 3321–3327, 1998, and
N. G. Caine and N. I. Mundy in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 267,
pp. 439–444, 2000.
126. See N. J. Dominy and P. W. Lucas in Nature, vol. 410, pp. 363–366, 2001, who emphasize the
maintenance of trichromatic vision (and its independent evolution in the New World howler
monkeys) as being linked to selection for young leaves, which in the tropics are coloured red,
rich in protein, and tender, and can provide an alternative in times of scarcity of fruit.
127. Vision in many of the New World monkeys, including the squirrel monkey and marmoset, is
therefore polymorphic (see J. D. Mollon et al. in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London
B, vol. 222, pp. 373–399, 1984) making them suitable for colour discrimination experiments,
such as those conducted by Caine and Mundy (2000; citation is in note 125). Despite their
classic status as dichromatic/trichromatic a number of details concerning the genetic
regulation are only now being worked out; see S. Kawamura et al. in Gene, vol. 269,
pp. 45–51, 2001. For an overview of the evolutionary genetics of primate colour vision, see
W-H. Li et al. in Evolutionary Biology, vol. 32, pp. 151–178, 2000. A similar polymorphism
leading to both dichromatic and trichromatic vision is also inferred in some prosimians; see
G. H. Jacobs et al. in Vision Research, vol. 42, pp. 11–18, 2002. It is uncertain whether this
condition is convergent with that found in the platyrrhine monkeys; see also note 123.
128. See the paper by S.-K. Shyue et al. in Science, vol. 269, pp. 1265–1267, 1995, where they
discuss the evidence for polymorphic trichromacy evolving independently in the marmosets
and squirrel monkeys.
129. See the discussion by M. J. Tovée et al. in Vision Research, vol. 32, pp. 867–878, 1992, see
especially p. 877.
130. See the anonymous remarks in a wartime issue of Nature, vol. 146, p. 266, 1940. The short
article is more to do with the implications of camouflage for the colour-blind, but this issue
of Nature also has a lively correspondence on the competence (or otherwise) of the military in
this area.
131. See E. B. Ford’s Moths (Collins, London, 1955) where he remarks that on visiting moorland in
search of the larvae of the Emperor moth their cryptic coloration makes their discovery quite
difficult even when fully exposed, yet the colour-blind can spot them ‘when 20 or 30 yards
distant’ (p. 95). Ford goes on to point out the potentially adaptive advantage of this sort of
colour blindness.
132. A useful overview of colour vision in mammals is given by G. H. Jacobs in Biological
Reviews, vol. 68, pp. 413–471, 1993.
133. Among the vertebrates ultraviolet (UV) vision is widespread, and has been documented in
fish, amphibians, reptiles, birds, and mammals; see G. H. Jacobs in American Zoologist,
vol. 32, pp. 544–554, 1992. See also note 144.
134. Male red–green colour blindness is because of a linkage to the X sex chromosome; see the
classic paper by J. Nathans et al. in Science, vol. 232, pp. 193–202, 1986, as well as a recent
update by S. Yokoyama and F. B. Radlwimmer in Genetics, vol. 153, pp. 919–932, 1999.
135. The spectral tuning of the protein necessary for red–green colour vision is discussed by
various authors, including J. Neitz et al. in Science, vol. 252, pp. 971–974, 1991.
136. Evidence for spectral tuning at the key sites being sometimes dependent on significant
changes in the molecular size of the amino acid is given by S-K. Shyue et al. in Journal of
Molecular Evolution, vol. 46, pp. 697–702, 1998.
137. See G. G. Kochendoerfer et al. in Trends in Biochemical Sciences, vol. 24, pp. 300–305, 1999.
In effect the absorption depends on very localized reconfigurations within the protein
molecule that alter either the electrostatic or dipolar electric charges.
notes to p. 169 385
138. See R. Yokoyama and S. Yokoyama in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
USA, vol. 87, pp. 9315–9318, 1990. Curiously the fish in question is a blind cave-dweller, but
it has evidently migrated to this habitat recently and the rhodopsin is still functional. It is
also worth noting that red–green vision is retained in the blind mole-rat (see p. 142, Chapter
6). Here it is suggested that it has been co-opted for the maintenance of circadian rhythms.
Details of this changed functionality are given by Z. K. David-Gray et al. in Nature
Neuroscience, vol. 1, pp. 655–656, 1998, who also show that the sensitivity is strongly
red-shifted, perhaps because the reduced eye is covered with skin and red blood vessels.
139. See Yokoyama and Radlwimmer (1999; citation is in note 134), where they review the
‘five-site rule’ for the mammals, reptiles (chameleon), birds (pigeon), and goldfish, and a
further update by these authors in Genetics, vol. 158, pp. 1697–1710, 2001.
140. For the various subtleties of substitution leading to red–green vision of mammals see the
paper by S. Yokoyama and F. B. Radlwimmer in Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 15,
p. 560–567, 1998.
141. Sensitivity to blue light in the Conger eel is discussed by S. Archer and J. Hirano in
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 263, pp. 761–767, 1996, who also review
parallel site substitutions in humans, birds, and other fish. See also B. S. W. Chang et al. in
Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution, vol. 4, pp. 31–43, 1995, who emphasize convergences
at sites in the rhodopsin associated with a blue shift.
142. ‘For whales and seals the ocean is not blue’ is the main title of the article by L. Peichl et al. in
European Journal of Neurosciences, vol. 13, pp. 1520–1528, 2001. Not only is the loss of blue
sensitive s-cones convergent (and may have also occurred twice within the whales), but it
probably confers an adaptive advantage.
143. Six sites are identified by A. J. Hope et al. (in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B,
vol. 264, pp. 155–163, 1997), of which two are of key importance.
144. In the case of birds the sensitivity to UV radiation can be achieved by a single amino acid
substitution, but the mechanisms adopted by other groups evidently differ, although they
depend on a limited number of site changes; see Y. Shi in FEBS Letters, vol. 486, pp. 167–172,
2000; and S. Yokoyama et al. and Y. Shi et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, USA, vol. 97, pp. 7366–7371, 2000, and vol. 98, pp. 11731–11736, 2001 respectively.
145. An overview of visual pigments in the invertebrates is, however, given by W. Gärtner and P.
Towner in Photochemistry and Photobiology, vol. 62, pp. 1–16, 1995.
146. Details of squid rhodopsin are addressed by A. Davies et al. in Journal of Molecular Biology,
vol. 314, pp. 455–463, 2001. There are some interesting differences from the mammals, not
least the high degree of ordering of the rhodopsin in the photoreceptor membranes. This
arrangement is linked to the ability both to detect polarized light and to optimize light
capture.
147. This example of convergence between squid and mammal rhodopsin is documented by A.
Morris et al. in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 254, pp. 233–240, 1993.
148. Concerning spectral sensitivities in the hymenopterans see D. Peitsch et al. in Journal of
Comparative Physiology 170A, pp. 23–40, 1992. See also B. S. W. Chang et al. in Gene,
vol. 173, pp. 215–219, 1996, where they report the detailed structure of honeybee
rhodopsin.
149. See the paper by A. D. Briscoe in Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 18, pp. 2270–2279,
2001. Briscoe suggests that in both these cases the molecular substitution may well be under
positive Darwinian selection, a topic returned to in its molecular context in Chapter 10. In
addition, Briscoe draws attention to parallels with crayfish (see also note 150), and
subsequently (Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 19, pp. 983–986, 2002) addressed the
parallel substitutions for red–green sensitivity in butterflies and bees.
150. The ability to absorb specific wavelengths of light in various species of freshwater crayfish is
discussed by K. A. Crandall and T. W. Cronin in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 45,
pp. 524–534, 1997. One should also note the adaptations for vision in deep-water shrimps,
where an otherwise unexpected near-ultraviolet sensitivity is linked to bioluminesence; see
386 notes to pp. 169–172
T. W. Cronin and T. M. Frank in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 263,
pp. 861–865, 1996.
151. See the paper by J. P. Carulli et al. in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 38, pp. 250–262,
1994.
152. See, for example, the use of oil droplets to confer ultraviolet vision in hummingbirds,
described by T. H. Goldsmith in Science, vol. 207, pp. 786–788, 1980.
153. See J. Marshall et al. in Current Biology, vol. 9, pp. 755–758, 1999.
154. For example, T. W. Cronin and N. J. Marshall, in Nature, vol. 339, pp. 137–140, 1989, report
ten or more types of photoreceptor sensitive to different wavelengths of light.
155. See the paper by D.-E. Nilsson and E. J. Warrant, in Current Biology, vol. 9, pp. R535–R537,
1999, which is a commentary on Marshall et al. (1999, note 153).
156. See R. D. Fernald in Current Opinion in Neurobiology, vol. 10, pp. 444–450, 2000.
157. R. D. Fernald (2000; citation is in note 156), p. 446.
158. There is a large literature on bacteriorhodopsin; for a helpful introduction see the article by
U. Haupts et al. in Annual Review of Biophysics and Biomolecular Structure, vol. 28,
pp. 367–399, 1999.
159. This is a slight simplification, inasmuch as there are also varieties that pump chloride (Cl)
ions (halorhodopsin) and are phototactic (sensory rhodopsin); the latter is returned to below
(citation is in note 171) in the context of colour discrimination.
160. See, for example, the paper by H. Luecke et al. in Journal of Molecular Biology, vol. 291,
pp. 899–911, 1999; and K. Palczewski et al. in Science, vol. 289, pp. 739–745, 2000 (and
commentary by H. R. Bourne and E. C. Meng on pp. 733–734).
161. See the papers by O. Béjà et al. in Science, vol. 289, pp. 1902–1906, 2000 (and accompanying
commentary by E. Pennisi on p. 1869), and Nature, vol. 411, pp. 786–789, 2001.
162. Recent papers on rhodopsin in the green algae include a review by J. L. Spudich et al. (Israel
Journal of Chemistry, vol. 35, pp. 495–513, 1995), as well as by M. Beckmann and P.
Hegemann (Biochemistry, vol. 30, pp. 3692–3697, 1991), W. Deininger et al. (1995), E. Ebnet
et al. (1999; both citations are in note 101), and L. Barsanti et al. in FEBS Letters, vol. 482,
pp. 247–251, 2000.
163. See W. Deininger et al. 1995 (citation is in note 101). The non-involvement of
chlamyrhodopsin in photoreception is addressed by M. Fuhrmann et al. in Journal of Cell
Science, vol. 114, pp. 3857–3863, 2001.
164. See G. Nagel et al. in Science, vol. 296, pp. 2395–2398, 2002 and O. A. Sineshchekov et al. in
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 99, pp. 8689–8694, 2002, as well
as the overview by K. D. Ridge in Current Biology, vol. 12, pp. R588–R590, 2002.
165. The paper describing fungal phototaxis is by J. Saranak and K. W. Foster in Nature, vol. 387,
pp. 465–466, 1997. Rhodopsin has also been identified in other fungi, notably Neurospora, but
here its function in terms of light regulation is less obvious, see J. Bieszke et al. in Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 96, pp. 8034–8039, 1999a. See also the same
group’s report of rhodopsin from a yeast in Biochemistry, vol. 38, pp. 14138–14145, 1999b.
166. See the papers by R. Henderson and G. F. X. Schertler in Philosophical Transactions of the
Royal Society of London B, vol. 326, pp. 379–389, 1990, and J. Soppa in FEBS Letters, vol. 342,
pp. 7–11, 1994. Soppa does not rule out descent from a common ancestor, but emphasizes the
lack of sequence similarities.
167. Most notably the pocket within the bacteriorhodopsin that binds the retinal has no
convincing counterpart in animal rhodopsin; see, for example, R. Henderson et al. in Journal
of Molecular Biology, vol. 213, 899–929, 1990.
168. See J. L. Spudich et al. (in Annual Review of Cell and Developmental Biology, vol. 16,
pp. 365–392, 2000, see pp. 379–380).
169. J. L. Spudich et al. (2000; citation is in note 168), p. 385. Despite the likelihood of
convergence between the rhodopsins it is only fair to point out that others regard them as
derived from a common protein; see, for example, Bieszke et al. (1999a), who tentatively
notes to pp. 172–174 387
suggest that their discovery of rhodopsin in Neurospora might provide a link, although
in their 1999b paper (both citations in note 165) they prefer to emphasize the differences.
170. Reviewed by H. G. Kohorana in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA,
vol. 90, pp. 1166–1171, 1993; see also W. Zhang et al. in a subsequent issue, vol. 93,
pp. 8230–8235, 1996.
171. Evidence for this colour discrimination is given by J. L. Spudich and R. A. Bogomolni in
Nature, vol. 312, pp. 509–513, 1984, with a commentary by L. Stryer on pp. 498–499. A
mutation analysis of this sensory rhodopsin is given by K-H. Jung and J. L. Spudich in Journal
of Bacteriology, vol. 180, pp. 2033–2042, 1998. Spectral sensitivity is also reported in the
proteorhodopsin; see Béjà et al. (2001; citation is in note 161).
172. The molecular basis of circadian rhythms is addressed by J. C. Dunlap in Cell, vol. 96,
pp. 271–290, 1999.
173. For an overview, albeit emphasizing their occurrence in mice, see A. Sancar in Annual
Review of Biochemistry, vol. 69, pp. 31–67, 2000.
174. See, for example, papers by Y. Miyamoto and A. Sancar in Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 95, pp. 6097–6102, 1998, and G. T. J. van der Horst et al. in
Nature, vol. 398, pp. 627–630, 1999. Similar functions in Drosophila are addressed by P.
Emery et al. in Cell, vol. 95, pp. 669–679, 1998.
175. See, for example, S. Folkard in Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B,
vol. 327, pp. 543–553, 1990. As Folkard notes (using the 24-hour clock), night is the realm of
accidents. Three Mile Island? 04.00; Chernobyl? 01:23; Bhopal? ‘just after midnight’.
Single-vehicle accidents are three times more likely to occur between 21.00 and 09.00 than
they are during the rest of the day, notwithstanding lower traffic density. If this is taken into
account, then the increase in vehicle accidents rises to twelve times. So far as the avoidance
of major catastrophes is concerned, Folkard suggests that ‘more extreme measures may be
required. The best solution here would appear to be create a nocturnal sub-society that not
only works at night, but also remains on a nocturnal routine on rest days’, p. 103. I assume
this suggestion is tongue-in-cheek, although I must say I am so glad I am an alpha . . .
176. The possibility is reviewed by A. Sancar (2000; citation is in note 173), see p. 62.
177. D. B. Small et al. in Plant Molecular Biology, vol. 28, pp. 443–454, 1995 discuss
cryptochromes in the alga Chlamydomonas.
178. See, for example, H-Q. Yang et al. in Cell, vol. 103, pp. 815–827, 2000.
179. This evidence for molecular convergence is addressed by A. R. Cashmore et al. in Science,
vol. 284, pp. 760–765, 1999.
180. See A. Sancar in Biochemistry, vol. 33, pp. 2–9, 1994.
181. The evidence against photolyases in humans is addressed by Y. F. Li et al. in Proceedings of
the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 90, pp. 4389–4393, 1993.
182. So how much time do we need? The famous article by D-E. Nilsson and S. Pelger, entitled ‘A
pessimistic estimate of the time required for an eye to evolve’ (in Proceedings of the Royal
Society of London B, vol. 256, pp. 53–58, 1994) suggests that the transformation from simple
eye-spot to fully functioning camera-eye can be achieved in substantially less than a million
years.
183. See his Hereditary Genius: An enquiry into its laws and consequences: first published in
1869, and its second edition in 1892. The latter is available as a reprint, with an introduction
by C. D. Darlington, and published by Fontana in 1962.
184. Chesterton’s book is entitled Eugenics and other evils (Cassell, London, 1922).
185. Francis Galton’s book entitled Memories of my life (Methuen, London, 1908); unfortunately it
has been long out of print.
186. Evident also from his panache and chutzpah when travelling through remote regions,
including his journey in Southern Africa, described in Narrative of an explorer in tropical
South Africa, being an account of a visit to Damaraland in 1851 (Ward Lock, London, 1889).
388 notes to pp. 174–178
Even better is his The art of travel; or shifts and contrivances available in wild countries
(John Murray, London, 1860 [3rd edition]).
187. Colin Beavan’s book is Fingerprints: Murder and the race to uncover the science of identity
(Fourth Estate, London, 2002).
188. C. Beaven (2002; citation is in note 187), p. 98.
189. This article was published in The Psychological Review, vol. 1, pp. 61–62, 1894.
190. F. Galton (1908; citation is in note 185), p. 284.
191. For an interesting discussion of some similarities between the ways olfactory information is
processed and language perceived, see T. S. Lorig in Neuroscience and Biobehavioral
Reviews, vol. 23, pp. 391–398, 1999, who suggests that there is at least some cortical overlap
in the brain.
192. Details of how the burrows are modified to allow habitation of such unpromising substrates
is given by G. C. Hickman in Canadian Journal of Zoology, vol. 61, pp. 1688–1692, 1983,
adaptations that he regarded as admirable. The exceptional diving abilities of the star-nosed
mole, and its respiratory implications, are addressed by I. W. McIntyre et al. in Journal of
Experimental Biology, vol. 205, vol. 45–54, 2002.
193. For an engaging account, with excellent illustrations, see the article by T. L. Yates in Natural
History, vol. 92 (11), pp. 54–61, 1983. Yates suggests that the divergence of the star-nosed
moles from other talpids is quite ancient, perhaps 30 million years ago, but that migration to
America may have occurred no earlier than the later Pliocene. Elsewhere, however, the
star-nosed mole is extinct.
194. The principal publications by K. C. Catania can be found in Nature, vol. 375, pp. 453–454,
1995 and Journal of Comparative Physiology, vol. 185A, pp. 367–372, 1999; see also the paper
by K. C. Catania and J. H. Kaas in BioScience, vol. 46, pp. 578–586, 1996.
195. For a review of Eimer’s organ in the mole group see K. C. Catania in Brain, Behavior and
Evolution, vol. 56, pp. 146–174, 2000. He emphasizes that although these remarkable
structures are effectively unique to the talpids, not only can their epidermal origin be inferred
with some confidence, but convergently derived structures do occur in other mammals,
notably the push-rod mechanoreceptors of the duck-billed platypus and echidna. Concerning
these latter structures see, for example, P. R. Manger and J. D. Pettigrew in Brain, Behavior
and Evolution, vol. 48, pp. 27–54, 1996, who also remark on the similarity with the Eimer’s
organ.
196. The way in which this fovea-like region gets a head-start in capturing a significant portion of
the nervous supply is described by K. C. Catania in Nature Neuroscience, vol. 4, pp. 353–354,
2001. He also notes that similar circumstances are found in the development of the fovea of
primate eyes; see P. Azzopardi and A. Cowey in Nature, vol. 361, pp. 719–721, 1993. See also
R. N. S. Sachdev and K. C. Catania in Journal of Neurophysiology, vol. 87, pp. 2602–2611,
2002.
197. K. C. Catania (1999; citation is in note 194), p. 367. The sensory representations of the
star-nosed mole in the overall context of mammalian cortical maps is addressed by J. H. Kaas
and K. C. Catania in BioEssays, vol. 24, pp. 334–343, 2002.
198. See the paper by K. C. Catania and M. S. Remple in Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, USA, vol. 99, pp. 5692–5697, 2002.
199. P. W. Lucas and P. F. Roche, in Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society, vol. 314,
pp. 858–864, 2000, present such evidence for free-floating planets (and also brown dwarfs) in
Orion; see also M. R. Z. Osorio et al. in Science, vol. 290, pp. 103–107, 2000, with
commentary by R. Irion on p. 26.
200. Concerning the navigational abilities of the blind mole-rats and the possible role of a
magnetic compass, see the papers by T. Kimchi and J. Terkel in Animal Behaviour, vol. 61,
pp. 171–180, 2001 and The Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 204, pp. 751–758, 2001.
201. Just how widespread the construction of such cognitive maps might be in the animal
kingdom may yet yield some surprises. Desert ants (Cataglyphis), for example, are famous for
notes to pp. 178–180 389
returning to their nests across hundreds of metres in a straight line. Evidently the ants know
how to sum up their outward journey and perform a path integration that allows them, in
ways not fully understood, to expedite their return; see S. Wohlgemuth et al. in Nature,
vol. 411, pp. 795–798, 2001 (and commentary by M. V. Srinivasan on pp. 752–755); see also
S. Åkesson and R. Wehner in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 205, pp. 1971–1978, 2002.
202. ‘Why do snakes have eyes?’ ask X. Bonnet et al. in Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology,
vol. 46, pp. 267–272, 1999, where they document the ecological flexibility of these blinded
snakes. And how did the tiger snakes get to Carnac Island? Evidently they were released there
by a travelling showman, after his wife was bitten by one and subsequently died.
203. Among the most famous of these is the infrared sensitivity, such as in the pit vipers. Rather
remarkably some insects have independently evolved a heat-sensitive organ, which has some
striking similarities to that of the snakes; see H. Schmitz et al. in Naturwissenschaften,
vol. 89, pp. 226–229, 2002.
204. See J. S. Edwards et al. in Journal of Neurobiology, vol. 20, pp. 101–114, 1989.
205. See K. C. Catania (2000, citation is in note 195).
206. See the paper by K. C. Catania et al. in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 202,
pp. 2719–2726, 1999 (and also Catania, 2000; citation is in note 195).
207. Changes in the masticatory apparatus of the star-nosed mole are discussed by T. E. Grand
et al. in Journal of Mammalogy, vol. 79, pp. 492–501, 1998. Concerning convergence amongst
the xenarthran and pangolin anteaters, see note 21, Chapter 6.
208. The glomeruli are dense, more-or-less spherical, aggregations of nervous tissue that consist of
first-order synaptic neuropil. It is clear that specific parts of the glomerulus are dedicated to
specific types of olfaction, such as the legendary sensitivity of some insects to sex
pheromones. There is an extensive literature on this topic. An introduction can be found in
such papers as those by B. S. Hansson et al. in Science, vol. 256, pp. 1313–1315, 1992; L. A.
Oland and L. P. Tolbert in Journal of Neurobiology, vol. 30, pp. 92–109, 1996; N. J. Vickers
et al. and P. P. Laissue et al. in Journal of Comparative Neurology, vol. 400, pp. 35–56, 1998,
and vol. 405, pp. 543–552, 1999 respectively; and R. Ignell et al. in Brain, Behavior and
Evolution, vol. 57, pp. 1–17, 2001.
209. For an overview see L. Dryer in Bioessays, vol. 22, pp. 803–810, 2000. In the fruit-fly some 59
genes have been identified as coding for the seven trans-membrane domain proteins used in
olfaction. See, for example, the paper by A. Gao and A. Chess in Genomics, vol. 60, pp. 31–39,
1999, where they note that the total number of olfactory genes involved could climb
substantially. While emphasizing the differences with vertebrates, Gao and Chess also note
some similarities, including ‘zoning’ of receptors. Vertebrates have about ten times as many
known olfactory genes, but they also code for transmembrane domain proteins, albeit with
little structural similarity to those of the insects; for an overview see P. Mombaerts in Annual
Review of Neuroscience, vol. 22, pp. 487–509, 1999 and Science, vol. 286, pp. 707–711, 1999.
210. See, for example, the paper entitled ‘Mechanisms of olfactory discrimination: converging
evidence for common principles across phyla’ in Annual Review of Neuroscience, vol. 20,
pp. 595–631, 1997 by J. G. Hildebrand and G. M. Shepherd, as well as the paper entitled
‘Olfactory systems: common design, uncommon origins?’ by N. J. Strausfeld and J. G.
Hildebrand in Current Opinion in Neurobiology, vol. 9, pp. 634–639, 1999.
211. In contrast to the insects, and most famously the moths, the action of sex pheromones in
vertebrates is less explored, but P. W. Sorenson et al. (in Current Opinion in Neurobiology,
vol. 8, pp. 458–467, 1998) emphasize the likely analogies in the use of these chemical
languages.
212. N. Strausfeld and J. G. Hildebrand (1999; citation is in note 210), p. 634.
213. N. Strausfeld and J. G. Hildebrand (1999; citation is in note 210), p. 635 (all
quotations).
214. The realization that insects probably emerged from the aquatic crustaceans has only become
apparent in recent years, largely thanks to molecular biology; see, for example, the papers by
390 notes to pp. 180–181
J. L. Boore et al. in Nature, vol. 392, pp. 667–668, 1998; E. Garcı́a-Machado et al. in Journal of
Molecular Evolution, vol. 49, pp. 142–149, 1999; and K. Wilson et al. in Molecular Biology
and Evolution, vol. 17, pp. 863–874, 2000. The ramifications of this proposal, not least in
terms of the origin of the insect wings from some sort of aquatic appendage (see M. Averof
and S. M. Cohen in Nature, vol. 285, pp. 627–630, 1997), and the hitherto unappreciated
similarities between the brains of crustaceans and insects (see, for example, M. Utting et al.
in Journal of Comparative Neurology, vol. 416, pp. 245–261, 2000) has led to some fertile
research.
215. This possibility is raised by G. Laurent and H. Davidowitz in their paper on insect olfaction
and oscillatory neural assemblies in Science, vol. 265, pp. 1872–1875, 1994 (see also the
accompanying commentary by D. W. Tank et al. on pp. 1819–1820). An update and overview,
with continued emphasis on the similarities between not only the vertebrates and insects,
but also the molluscs (in the form of the slug), are given by A. Gelperin in Journal of
Experimental Biology, vol. 202, pp. 1855–1864, 1999.
216. See, for example, the paper by V. V. Gurevich in Journal of Biological Chemistry, vol. 273,
pp. 15501–15506, 1998.
217. The shared presence of seven trans-membrane domain proteins is important because these
olfactory proteins belong to the same class (G protein-coupled receptors; for an overview see
H. G. Dohlman et al. in Annual Review of Biochemistry, vol. 60, pp. 653–688, 1991) as
rhodopsin (used in vision), and also function in taste (see M. A. Hoon et al. in Cell, vol. 96,
pp. 541–551, 1999). If proteins themselves are universal, so perhaps there is a strong
preference to use specific protein architectures to see, smell, and taste in much the same way.
218. See C. E. Merrill et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 99,
pp. 1633–1638, 2002, and the commentary by A. Nighorn and J. G. Hildebrand on
pp. 1113–1114.
219. See J. Riesgo-Escovar et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA,
vol. 92, pp. 2864–2868, 1995, who document a shared function in Drosophila vision and
olfaction for a phospholipase C.
220. Helpful introductions to this fascinating topic can be found in papers by M. B. Fenton in
Quarterly Review of Biology, vol. 59, pp. 33–53, 1984; U. M. Norberg and J. M. V. Rayner in
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 316, pp. 335–427, 1987; and
E. C. Teeling et al. in Nature, vol. 403, pp. 188–192, 2000. Concerning the phylogenetic
context of bat echolocation, see M. S. Springer et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences, USA, vol. 98, pp. 6241–6246, 2001. Bat echolocation has its examples of
convergence, notably the independent evolution of nasal-emitting sounds in rhinolophids and
phyllostomids; see S. C. Pedersen’s chapter (pp. 174–213) in Ontogeny, functional ecology
and evolution of bats, edited by R. A. Adams and S. C. Pedersen (Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 2000); see also E. C. Teeling et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, USA, vol. 99, pp. 1431–1436, 2002. So, too, two genera in these groups (Rhinolophus
and Pteronotus parnelli) have convergently arrived at Doppler-sensitive sonar; see M. Vater
on p. 145 of the same volume.
221. M. Ruedi and F. Mayer, in Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution, vol. 21, pp. 436–448, 2001,
discuss evidence for such convergence, and emphasize that ‘Independent adaptive radiations
among species of the genus Myotis therefore produced strikingly similar evolutionary
solutions in different parts of the world’ (p. 436). Various other examples of convergence are
presented, with the important corollary that ‘morphological similarity amongst these bats is
a poor predictor of their genetic similarities’ (p. 444). Ruedi and Mayer are unlikely to please
those biologists who appeal to contingent factors in evolution, given that the title of their
paper includes reference to ‘deterministic ecomorphological convergences’.
222. This ability of the blind to navigate by reflected sound is very variable, but the exceptional
few who surge through city streets, past crowds, obstacles, and traffic, are – at least to the
sighted – a matter of some astonishment. In Chapter 12 his book Listening in the dark: the
notes to pp. 181–182 391
acoustic orientation of bats and men (Yale University Press, New Haven, 1958) D. R. Griffin
has a very interesting discussion of this topic. In the 1974 reprint (Dover, New York) Griffin
draws attention to more recent work, including two papers in Science on the use of sonar by
blind humans, respectively by W. N. Kellogg, vol. 137, pp. 399–404, 1962 and C. E. Rice in
vol. 155, pp. 656–664, 1967.
223. J. P. Rauschecker and U. Kniepert (in European Journal of Neuroscience, vol. 6, pp. 149–160;
1994) discuss how in ‘visually deprived cats’ the auditory skills are markedly
enhanced.
224. For further details see the paper by J. Simmons et al. in Biological Bulletin, vol. 191,
pp. 109–121, 1996.
225. Concerning the perception in moths of the ultrasonic sound frequencies that the bats
generate see the papers by K. D. Roeder in Journal of Experimental Zoology, vol. 134,
pp. 127–157, 1957 (with A. E. Treat) and Animal Behaviour, vol. 10, pp. 300–304, 1962. On
the topic of evasion by the hunted moths see M. B. Fenton and J. H. Fullard in American
Scientist, vol. 69, pp. 266–275, 1981 and T. K. Werner in Canadian Journal of Zoology,
vol. 59, pp. 525–529, 1981. What may well be a convergent example of such sensitivity is the
evidence for ultrasound detection by a clupeid fish (the American shad), which would allow
evasive action on hearing the ultrasonic noises projected by the echolocatory and predatory
cetaceans; see D. A. Mann et al. in Nature, vol. 389, p. 341, 1997 and Journal of the
Acoustical Society of America, vol. 104, pp. 562–568, 1998.
226. This topic is reviewed by W. E. Connor in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 202,
pp. 1711–1723, 1999. He points out that while jamming of the bat’s echolocation system is a
widely accepted explanation, alternatives include startling the bat or advertising the moth’s
distastefulness (see, for example, D. C. Dunning and M. Krüger in Biotropica, vol. 27,
pp. 227–231, 1995). A helpful overview of the tactics and counter-tactics of insects and bats,
prey and predator, associated with sound and hearing is given by L. A. Miller and
A-M. Surlykke in BioScience, vol. 51, pp. 570–581, 2001. (See also note 256).
227. For a succinct account of this topic see chapters 5–7 of H. C. Hughes’ enjoyable book Sensory
exotica: A world beyond human experience (MIT Press, Cambridge; 1999).
228. D. R. Griffin (1958; citation is in note 222).
229. D. R. Griffin (1958; citation is in note 222), p. 287.
230. M. Konishi and E. I. Knudsen discuss how oilbirds hear and echolocate in Science, vol. 204,
pp. 425–427, 1979.
231. Concerning the visual system of oilbirds see the article by J. D. Pettigrew and M. Konishi in
National Geographic Society Research Report, vol. 16, pp. 439–450, 1984, as well as
comments by Pettigrew (1991; citation is in note 86). In the former paper they remark that
vision is more important than echolocation, and also draw parallels to the optics of other
nocturnal birds.
232. Details of these experiments are given by D. R. Griffin and R. A. Suthers in Biological
Bulletin, vol. 139, pp. 495–501, 1970. Somewhat similar conclusions were arrived at by M. B.
Fenton in Biotropica, vol. 7, pp. 1–7, 1975, where he noted that even obstacles only 1.5 mm
thick could be avoided. More recent work on echolocation in the swiftlets includes papers by
D. R. Griffin and D. Thompson in Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 10, pp. 119–123,
1982, and D. M. Smyth and J. R. Roberts in Ibis, vol. 125, pp. 339–345, 1983. The actual
mechanism of production of the echolocating clicks is discussed by R. A. Suthers and D. H.
Hector in Journal of Comparative Physiology, vol. 148A, pp. 457–470, 1982.
233. Thus Smyth and Roberts (1983) remark, ‘It is obvious that sensitivity of echolocation [in the
swiftlets] does not match the spectacular feats demonstrated by insectivorous bats in
detecting, ranging and tracking minute objects and in distinguishing between a variety of
shapes and textures’ (p. 345), although more precise comparisons can be made with some of
the fruit-bats, such as Rousettus. This animal belongs to the so-called mega-bats that as a
group evidently lost their ability to echolocate, so suggesting that its presence in the fruit-bat
392 notes to pp. 182–183
Rousettus is a secondary acquisition; see Springer et al. (2001; citation in note 220). One
might also note that among the fruit-bats nectarivory has evolved at least twice, and probably
several times; see J. A. W. Kirsch et al. in Australian Journal of Zoology, vol. 43, pp. 395–428,
1995 and L. J. Hollar and M. S. Springer in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
USA, vol. 94, pp. 5716–5721, 1997.
234. Electrosensitivity in the star-nosed mole has been posited by Grand et al. (1998; see note 207
for citation; see also Journal of Mammalogy vol. 74, pp. 108–116, 1993), but this proposal
receives short shrift from Catania (2000; see note 195 for citation).
235. Thus the duck-billed platypus is electroreceptive, using glands in its bill; see the two papers
in Nature by respectively H. Scheich et al. (vol. 319, pp. 401–402, 1986) and J. E. Gregory
et al. (vol. 326, pp. 386–387, 1987), as well as the article by U. Proske et al. in Journal of
Comparative Physiology, vol. 173A, pp. 708–710, 1993. So also is the related echidna; see, for
example, J. E. Gregory et al. in Journal of Physiology, vol. 414, pp. 521–538, 1989; K. H.
Andres et al. in Anatomy and Embryology, vol. 184, pp. 371–393, 1991; and P. R. Manger
et al. in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 264, pp. 165–172, 1997. This
electrical sensitivity arose independently of other vertebrates, notably the mormyrid and
gymnotid fish that are discussed below. Details of the electroreceptor structure are given by
Manger and Pettigrew (1996; citation is in note 195), and they also have a helpful discussion
of the similarities and differences in electroreception in the fish and monotremes. They list
three significant differences, but emphasize the more numerous similarities and stress ‘that
particular constraints are acting upon the evolution of electroreception’ (p. 49), where the
convergence emerges by the combination of physical constraints and adaptation to the
environment.
236. Concerning the basic similarities of the strongly convergent electric organs of the fish see the
review by H. H. Zakon and G. A. Unquez in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 202,
pp. 1427–1434, 1999, as well as Electric fishes: history and behavior (Chapman and Hall,
London, 1995), a book written largely by P. Moller but with various contributions by a
number of his colleagues.
237. In the context of the early recognition of electric fish, especially with respect to medicine, see
P. Kellaway’s essay in Bulletin of the History of Medicine, vol. 20, pp. 112–137, 1946, and also
D’Arcy Thompson’s discussion of the torpedo ray in A glossary of Greek fishes (Oxford
University Press, London, 1947), pp. 169–171. A more recent overview of the historical
importance of electric fish, including the debate between Galvani and Volta (hence galvanic
and volts), is given in the first chapter of Moller (1995).
238. The only surviving work by Scribonius Largus is his Compositiones medicae; see the edition
prepared by S. Sconocchia (BSB B. G. Teubner, Leipzig, 1983). Reference to the electrical uses
of the torpedo fish may be found in sections 11 and 162, translations of which are given by
Kellaway (1946, p. 130).
239. See, for example, J. M. Riddle’s Dioscorides on pharmacy and medicine (University of Texas
Press, Austin, 1985). Rather little is known of Dioscorides, other than that he was born in
Asia Minor, in Anazarbus, and he studied botany and pharmacology in Tarsus, ‘no mean city’,
as St Paul observed (Acts 22.39). Riddle casts doubt on the popular legend that Dioscorides
marched with the Roman legions.
240. See the edition of The Greek herbal of Dioscorides. Illustrated by a Byzantine A.D. 512.
Englished by J. Goodyer (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1933), p. 97; ‘The sea torpedo being
applyed in griefs in long continuance about ye head, doth assuage the fiercenesse of the grief:
the same too applyed doth stay up the seate, being either overturned, or else fallen downe’,
p. 97.
241. Not that the treatment fell out of fashion for many centuries. Thus, in his
Panzoologicomineralogia. Or a compleat history of animals and minerals (Godwin, Oxford,
1661) Robert Lovell writes of the aptly named Cramp-fish, i.e. torpedo, with reference to
Dioscorides that ‘Applied to the head, they help old paines thereof, and restraine the falling
out of the fundament’, p. 191.
notes to pp. 183–185 393
242. See Alison Winter’s Mesmerized: Powers of mind in Victorian Britain (University of Chicago
Press, Chicago, 1998).
243. For an account of these experiments see vol. III (May 26, 1836 – Nov. 9, 1839) of Faraday’s
diary, being the various philosophical notes of experimental investigation made by Michael
Faraday, etc., edited by T. Martin (G. Bell and Sons, London, 1933).
244. P. Kellaway (1946; citation is in note 237), also gives some graphic descriptions of treatment
of various ailments in South America using the electric eel, which he refers to as ‘heroic
remedies’ (p. 136). Moreover, a report in B. Kramer (1996; citation is in note 246) says that
‘according to natives, the puraqué (local name for electric eel) is said to harvest palm fruit
which it has been observed to eat, by electroshocking the base of a tree’, p. 18.
245. The phylogenetic relationships of the gymnotids and mormyrids are addressed by J. A. Alves-
Gomes in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 202, pp. 1167–1183, 1999, and a detailed
assessment of the gymnotids is provided by J. S. Albert in Miscellaneous Publications
Museum of Zoology, University of Michigan, no. 190, vi + 127 pp., 2001. As Alves-Gomes
points out ‘these two lineages of fish separated more than 140 × 106 years ago, and current
evidence suggests that their common ancestor was neither electroreceptive nor electrogenic.
It is quite remarkable, therefore, that after this prolonged period of independent evolution,
these two fish clades have evolved a number of very elaborate similarities associated with
their sensory and motor biology, completely independently of one another. The electrogenic
and electrosensory systems . . . are used for electrolocation and communication, and the
design, physiology and modus operandi of the two systems are extraordinarily similar, if not
identical, in several ways’, p. 1180.
246. The topic of electric fish and mormyrids specifically has attracted many outstanding
scientists, but specific mention should be made of Hans Lissman, a refugee from Nazi
Germany and a distinguished Cambridge physiologist, who pioneered this field; see, in
particular, his papers in Nature, vol. 167, pp. 201–201, 1951, and Journal of Experimental
Biology, vol. 35, pp. 156–191 (in which he emphasizes the various convergences) and
pp. 457–486, 1958, the latter with K. F. Machin. Otherwise, the key reference to this topic is
the book Electroreception, edited by T. H. Bullock and W. Heiligenberg (Wiley, New York,
1986). Also helpful are special issues of Journal of Comparative Physiology, vol. 173A,
pp. 657–763, 1993, and Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 202, pp. 1167–1458, 1999; see
also B. Kramer’s Electroreception and communication in fishes, as vol. 42 of Progress in
Zoology (Fischer, Stuttgart, 1996). The topic of electrical generation in fish is an area of
considerable research activity; key groups include those led by C. D. Hopkins (see, for
example, papers in American Zoologist, vol. 21, pp. 211–222, 1981; Current Opinion in
Neurobiology, vol. 5, pp. 769–777, 1995); M. Kawasaki (see Journal of Neuroscience, vol. 17,
pp. 1761–1768, 1997; American Zoologist, vol. 33, pp. 86–93, 1993; Journal of Comparative
Physiology, vols. 173A, pp. 9–22, 1993 and 174A, pp. 133–144, 1994 respectively; Journal of
Neuroscience, vols. 16, pp. 380–391, 1996 and 18, pp. 7599–7611, 1998 respectively); and
B. Kramer (see, for example, Ethology, vol. 103, pp. 404–420, 1997, and Naturwissenschaften,
vol. 84, pp. 119–121, 1997).
247. This is with reference to the active detection of objects near the fish; see G. von der Emde in
Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 202, pp. 1205–1215, 1999.
248. This ability to deceive the fish was established by Hans Lissman in 1951 (citation is in note
246), where he fed the fish’s own electrical pulses back into the tank, eliciting an attack on
the electrodes. Concerning the employment of an artificial dipole, see Chapter 10 by
P. Moller and J. Serrier, in P. Moller (1995, citation is in note 236).
249. In one group of gymnotids, known as the apteronotids, the electric organ derives from the
nervous system; see S. G. Waxman et al. in Journal of Cell Biology, vol. 53, pp. 210–224, 1972.
250. A general introduction to the process of electrogeneration in fish can be found in M. V. L.
Bennett’s chapter (pp. 347–491) in vol. 5 of Fish physiology, edited by W. S. Hoar and D. J.
Randall (Academic Press, New York, 1971). Also helpful is Zakon and Unquez (1999; citation
is in note 236).
394 notes to pp. 185–186
251. Comments on the four principal types of electric organ in the mormyrid fish and their
evolution are provided by J. Alves-Gomes and C. D. Hopkins in Brain, Behavior and
Evolution, vol. 49, pp. 324–351, 1997. The question of the phylogenetic relationships within
the mormyrids and the evolution of the various electrocytes is pursued further by S. Lavoué
et al. in Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution, vol. 14, pp. 1–10, 2000, and J. P. Sullivan
et al. in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 203, pp. 665–683, 2000.
252. Much of the literature cited in this section of the book is directly relevant to the type of
electrical signals generated by these fish, but a thorough overview is given by Moller (1995;
citation is in note 236).
253. This possibility is explored by P. A. Aguilera et al. in Journal of Experimental Biology,
vol. 204, pp. 185–198, 2000.
254. The role of predation in gymnotid, and probably mormyrid, diversification is addressed by P.
K. Stoddard in Nature, vol. 400, pp. 254–256, 1999.
255. The detection by catfish of a mormyrid, the bulldog fish, is discussed by S. Hanika and B.
Kramer in Naturwissenschaften, vol. 86, pp. 286–288, 1999, and Behavioral Ecology and
Sociology, vol. 48, pp. 218–228, 2000. In the latter paper, they discuss (pp. 226–227) the
inferences drawn by Stoddard (1999) on electric fish diversification but are evidently more
sceptical, at least so far as the mormyrids are concerned.
256. P. K. Stoddard (1999; citation is in note 254) points out that in this example of signalling there
is a parallel in the ctenuchine moths. These insects use an ultrasonic acoustic signal to
advertise themselves to bats, who evidently associate the sound with the disgusting taste of
the moths (they are wasp mimics and contain toxic chemicals), but in addition the signalling
has been co-opted for sexual attraction. This ultrasonic signalling has in turn evolved
independently several times in this group of moths; see papers by W. E. Conner et al. in
Journal of Insect Behavior, vol. 8, pp. 19–31, 1995 and vol. 9, pp. 909–919, 1996 respectively,
as well as a helpful overview (W. E. Connor, 1999; citation is in note 226) on acoustic
communication in moths.
257. See, for example, the paper by P. Belbenoit in Journal de Physiologie (Paris), vol. 59,
pp. 344–345, 1967. The ‘electric images’ that the fish senses are both depicted and discussed
in Journal of Experimental Biology by C. Assad et al. (in vol. 202, pp. 1185–1193, 1999) and
R. Budelli and A. A. Caputi (in vol. 203, pp. 481–492, 2000) respectively, as well as by G. von
der Emde and S. Schwarz in Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B,
vol. 355, pp. 1143–1146, 2000.
258. In a series of experiments on mormyrid fish P. Cain et al., in Ethology, vol. 96, pp. 33–45,
1994, found that once accustomed to a novel environment they no longer depended on active
electrolocation, with the interesting implication that familiar environments are stored within
the brain as a sort of cognitive map (see also Kawasaki (1997; citation is in note 263) for
evidence of ‘an internal representation’ (p. 474) with respect to the processing of electrical
signals in the context of jamming avoidance. Subsequently P. Cain (in Ethology, vol. 99,
pp. 332–349, 1995) extended this work, and suggested that the relative hydrostatic pressure,
and thereby water depth was an important cue in mormyrid navigation.
259. See the chapter (pp. 313–393) by M. V. L. Bennett in the book Lateral line detectors, edited by
P. H. Cahn (Indiana University Press, Bloomington, 1967). In describing these receptors he
writes ‘The similarities of tonic [for d.c. reception] and phasic [a.c. reception] electroreceptors
in gymnotids and mormyrids constitute an instance of convergent evolution as remarkable as
that of the electric organs themselves’ (p. 386). His earlier contribution in Cold Spring Harbor
Symposia on Quantitative Biology, vol. 30, pp. 245–262, 1965 is also helpful.
260. An apt phrase used by C. D. Hopkins in his review of electrical signals in a mormyrid fish
community, published in American Zoologist, vol. 21, pp. 211–222, 1981, see p. 216.
261. See the paper by P. K. McGregor and G. W. M. Westby in Animal Behaviour, vol. 43, 977–986,
1992. There is also evidence, in at least one gymnotid, for plasticity in the electrical signal;
produced, most probably as a sexual signal; see C. R. Franchina et al. in Journal of
Comparative Physiology, vol. 187A, pp. 45–52, 2001.
notes to pp. 186–187 395
289. Concerning aspects of the potentially radical transformations between aquatic sound pressure
perception and subaerial hearing from a neurological perspective, see B. Fritsch in Brain,
Behavior and Evolution, vol. 50, pp. 38–49, 1997.
290. See the overview by J. A. Clack in Brain, Behavior and Evolution, vol. 50, pp. 198–212, 1997,
as well as J. A. Clack (2002; citation is in note 288).
291. See, for example, the article by R. Nobili et al. entitled ‘How well do we understand the
cochlea?’ in Trends in Neurosciences, vol. 21, pp. 159–167, 1998.
292. Concerning these sensory cells, G. A. Manley et al., in Journal of Comparative Physiology,
vol. 164A, pp. 289–296, 1989, wrote ‘Considering the independent evolutionary origin of
these two vertebrate classes from different groups of reptile ancestors, it is remarkable to find
indications of a clear functional parallel between avian and mammalian hair-cell populations.’
They then continue with the important observation that ‘The parallel evolution of such
hair-cell populations suggests that there are fundamental properties of hair cells which lend
themselves to a particular kind of division of labour.’ An update and overview is given by G.
A. Manley and C. Köppl in Current Opinion in Neurobiology, vol. 8, pp. 468–474, 1998.
293. The question of the adaptive optimal sound for vocal communication in the tunnels of the
blind mole-rat is addressed by G. Heth et al. in Experientia, vol. 42, pp. 1287–1289, 1986.
294. Seismic communication is reviewed by E. Nevo in Mosaic evolution of subterranean
mammals: Regression, progression, and global convergence (Oxford University Press, Oxford,
1999), see especially pp. 105–107; see also M. J. Mason and P. M. Narins, in American
Zoologist, vol. 41, pp. 1171–1184, 2001.
295. The similarities in the method of sound conduction is addressed by H. Burda et al. in Journal
of Morphology, vol. 214, pp. 49–61, 1992. A notable exception to this example of convergence
is the stapes ear-bone, which shows remarkable shape variation, even within a genus.
296. See the paper by T. Lindenlaub et al. in Journal of Morphology, vol. 224, pp. 303–311, 1995.
See also note 200.
297. The astonishing acoustic sensitivity of the mosquito, especially in the male to whom the
wing-beats of the female spell a special magic, is reported by M. C. Göpfert and D. Robert in
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 267, pp. 453–457, 2000. Göpfert and
Robert also point out that while the female’s hearing is less acute, it still far outstrips that of
most other insects.
298. See their paper, ‘Active auditory mechanics in mosquitoes’, in Proceedings of the Royal
Society of London B, vol. 268, pp. 333–339, 2000.
299. M. C. Göpfert and D. Robert (2000; citation is in note 298), pp. 337–338.
300. See the paper by J. de Wilde in Archives Neerlandaises de Physiologie de l’homme et des
animaux, vol. 25, pp. 381–400, 1941.
301. For an overview see R. R. Hoy and D. Robert in Annual Review of Entomology, vol. 41,
pp. 433–450, 1996. Hoy and Robert also touch on the question of convergence, a conclusion
well supported by the remarkably diverse positions of the tympanal organ across the body
surface of the insect.
302. Interestingly, the chordotonal organ (see L. H. Field and T. Matheson in Advances in Insect
Physiology, vol. 27, pp. 1–228, 1998) appears to have been co-opted from its primary function,
which is to act as a stretch receptor for movement of various parts of the body, e.g. segments.
Concerning this derivation see G. S. Boyan in Journal of Insect Physiology, vol. 39,
pp. 187–200, 1993, and M. J. van Staaden and H. Römer in Nature, vol. 394, pp. 773–776, 1998.
303. See, for example, the discussion of tympanal (and atympanal) hearing in hawkmoths, by M.
C. Göpfert et al. in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 269, pp. 89–95, 2002.
This example is relevant to the discussion of convergence because these ears ‘evolved
independently on the basis of homologous structures’, p. 93.
304. Although this is not to say that crickets cannot defend themselves from digger wasps that are
attempting to parasitize them by one of several mechanisms, including kicking; see W.
Gnatzy and R. Heusslein in Naturewissenschaften, vol. 73, pp. 212–215, 1986.
398 notes to pp. 192–193
305. See the paper by D. Robert et al. in Science, vol. 258, pp. 1135–1137; 1992. As they aptly
remark ‘This example of convergent evolution in a hearing organ demonstrates the
constraints on morphological design that are imposed by behavioral function as well as by
principles of physical acoustics’ (p. 1135). An analysis of this ear’s morphological origins from
pre-existing structures is provided by R. S. Edgecomb et al. in Cell & Tissue Research,
vol. 282, pp. 251–268, 1995, and in a subsequent issue (vol. 301, pp. 447–457) D. Robert and U.
Willi discuss the histological architecture of the ormiinid ear, and also echo the earlier
remarks when they comment ‘It is quite remarkable that in insects the sense of hearing has
probably evolved many times independently in at least seven orders, and that, in each
instance, however diverse the auditory organs are, they are of the chordotonal type endowed
with scolopidial mechanoreceptors’, pp. 454–455.
306. D. Robert et al. (1992; citation is in note 305), p. 1137.
307. A suggestion made by D. Robert et al. in Cell & Tissue Research, vol. 284, pp. 435–448, 1996.
308. See the paper by A. C. Mason et al. in Nature, vol. 410, pp. 686–690, 2001, and the
accompanying commentary by P. M. Narins on pp. 644–645.
309. Thus D. Robert et al. (1996; citation is in note 307) note ‘Remarkably, morphological and
behavioral evidence points to the presence of prosternal hearing organs in two calyptrate fly
species from another big family of parasitoids, the Sarcophagidae . . . Hence, it is likely that
acoustic parasitism evolved twice independently within calyptrate flies’, p. 446.
310. See the paper by R. G. Walker et al. in Science, vol. 287, pp. 2229–2234, 2000. Their specific
example touches on mechanosensory transduction in the fruit-fly and a homologue in worms
(i.e. C. elegans), but the link to vertebrate hair cells is also addressed.
311. The role of Math 1 in the generation of the inner hair cells is addressed by N. A. Bermingham
et al. in Science, vol. 284, pp. 1837–1841, 1999.
312. For the activity of atonal as a proneural gene, see A. P. Jarman et al. in Development, vol. 121,
pp. 2019–2030, 1995.
313. The role of atonal in the glomeruli of the olfactory lobe is addressed by D. Jhaveri and V.
Rodriques in Development, vol. 129, pp. 1251–1260, 2002.
314. The literature on the Pax-6 gene is very extensive; it includes the following papers: R. L.
Chow et al. in Development, vol. 126, pp. 4213–4222, 1999; A. Cvekl and J. Piatigorsky in
BioEssays, vol. 18, pp. 621–630, 1996; C. Desplan in Cell, vol. 19, pp. 861–864, 1997;
G. Halder et al. in Science, vol. 267, pp. 1788–1792, 1995; R. Quiring et al. in Science,
vol. 265, pp. 785–789, 1994; S. I. Tomarev et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, USA, vol. 94, pp. 2421–2426, 1997; and C. Punzo et al. in Genes & Development,
vol. 15, pp. 1716–1723, 2001.
315. For this suggestion, and a consideration of the early evolution of the Pax genes see D. J. Miller
et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 97, pp. 4475–4480, 2000.
316. The role of Pax-6 in nasal development is addressed by J. C. Grindley et al. in Development,
vol. 121, pp. 1433–1442, 1995; see also M-D. Franco et al. in Journal of Experimental Biology,
vol. 204, pp. 2049–2061, 2001, who among other matters point out that Pax-6 appears to play
different roles in development of olfactory epithelia in frog and mouse (see p. 2059).
317. Pax-6 expression in the brain is addressed by M. Takahashi and N. Osumi in Development,
vol. 129, pp. 1327–1338, 2002; P. Callaerts et al. in Journal of Neurobiology, vol. 46,
pp. 73–88, 2001; and several earlier papers in Development, see vol. 113, pp. 1435–1450, 1991
(C. Walther and P. Gruss), vol. 126, pp. 5569–5579, 1999 (P. Chapouton et al.), vol. 127,
pp. 2357–2365 (E. Matsunaga et al.), and vol. 127, pp. 5267–5178, 2000 (R. Pratt et al.),
as well as M. Schwarz et al. in Mechanisms of Development, vol. 82, pp. 29–39,
1999.
318. See C. Kioussi et al. in Proceedings of National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 96,
pp. 14378–14382, 1999.
319. The role of Pax-6 in the glucagon producing α cells of the pancreas is addressed by L. St-Onge
et al. in Nature, vol. 387, pp. 406–409, 1997.
notes to pp. 193–199 399
320. D. Arendt et al. in Development, vol. 129, pp. 1143–1154, 2002, present some interesting data
on polychaete eyes, noting Pax-6 activity only in the larval eyes, and not those of the adult.
321. See, for example, D. A. Nelson and P. Marler’s discussion of categorical perception of birdsong
in wild swamp sparrows in Science, vol. 244, pp. 976–978, 1989.
322. See R. A. Wyttenbach et al. in Science, vol. 273, pp. 1542–1544, 1996.
323. R. A. Wyttenbach et al. (1996; citation is in note 322), p. 1543.
324. See R. Nieuwenhuys and C. Nicholson’s chapter (pp. 107–134) in Neurobiology of cerebellar
evolution and development, edited by R. Llinás (American Medical Association, Chicago,
1969). The following chapter (pp. 135–169), by the same authors, provides details of the
histology of the mormyrid brain. More recent discussions are in the chapter (pp. 375–421) by
C. C. Bell and T. Szabo in Bullock and Heiligenberg (1986; see note 246 for citation), and an
article by Szabo in Acta Morphologica Hungarica, vol. 31, pp. 219–234, 1983.
325. R. Nieuwenhuys and C. Nicholson (1969; citation is in note 324), p. 107.
326. See the paper by G. E. Nilsson in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 199, pp. 603–607,
1996. He stresses that the extraordinary energetic cost in the mormyrids is not only because
of a large brain, but also because the fish are ectothermic. Moreover, given that these fish may
find themselves in poorly aerated water, it is not surprising to learn of their ability to
scavenge oxygen effectively, although L. J. Chapman and K. G. Hulen (in Journal of Zoology,
London, vol. 254, pp. 461–472, 2001) question whether even increase in gill size is really
sufficient.
327. See J. S. Albert et al. on pp. 647–656 of Proceedings of the 5th Indo-Pacific Fish Conference,
Nouméa, 1997, edited by B. Séret and J-Y. Sire (Société Française d’Ichtyologie, Paris, 1999).
Interestingly, among the fish it is the chondrichthyans, notably the galeomorph sharks and
batoid rays, which have proportionally the largest of brains.
328. See the chapter (pp. 319–373) by C. E. Carr and L. Maler in T. H. Bullock and W. Heiligenberg
(1986; citation is in note 246).
329. See C. Bell et al. (1997; citation is in note 284).
8. alien convergences?
1. These two genera belong to a larger group of ants, known as the attines (Tribe Attini), all of
which are fungus-growers. This section very largely concentrates on the advanced leaf-cutters.
2. Useful introductions are available in K. Dumpert’s book The social biology of ants (Pitman,
Boston, 1981); the masterly work by B. Hölldobler and E. O. Wilson entitled simply The ants
(Springer, Berlin, 1990); R. C. Buckley’s overview on pp. 111–114 (excluding bibliography) of
Ant–plant interactions in Australia, edited by R. C. Buckley (Junk, The Hague, 1982); N. A.
Weber’s article forming vol. 92 of Memoirs of the American Philosophical Society,
Philadelphia (1972); and J. K. Wetterer’s chapter (pp. 309–328) in Nourishment and evolution
in insect societies, edited by J. H. Hunt and C. A. Nalepa (Westview Press, Boulder, CO,
1994).
3. More primitive attine species are more opportunistic and collect a wide variety of other
material, including flowers, seeds, faeces, and insect corpses; see I. R. Leal and P. S. Oliveira
in Insectes Sociaux, vol. 47, pp. 376–382, 2000.
4. See the article on Acromyrmex in the Arizona desert by J. K. Wetterer et al. in Sociobiology,
vol. 37, pp. 633–649, 2001.
5. The species in question is found in Paraguay, and details are given by H. G. Fowler and S. W.
Robinson in Ecological Entomology, vol. 4, pp. 239–247, 1979. Further information is
provided by S. P. Hubbell et al. in Biotropica, vol. 12, pp. 210–213, 1980. These researchers
noted that almost never did the tree-top harvesters carry any material back down to the
ground, and that the ants lugging the plant material back to the nest were significantly more
robust than their companions dropping the pieces from above. F. Roces, in Biological
Bulletin, vol. 202, pp. 306–313, 2002, has an interesting discussion of the balance between
colony-wide activity and individual autonomy.
400 notes to pp. 199–200
6. See Hubbell et al. (1980). The adaptive benefits of this leaf transfer, in the context of speeds of
locomotion, are addressed by C. Anderson and J. L. V. Jadin in Insectes Sociaux, vol. 48,
pp. 404–405, 2001. An overview of insect ‘bucket brigades’, which have evidently evolved
independently several times, is given by C. Anderson et al. in Insectes Sociaux, vol. 49,
pp. 171–180, 2002.
7. The benefits and drawbacks of leaf caching by the ant Atta are addressed by A. G. Hart and F.
L. W. Ratnieks in Animal Behaviour, vol. 62, pp. 227–234, 2001.
8. Concerning the energetic cost to the colony of clearing and maintaining these trails, see J. J.
Howard’s analysis in Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 49, pp. 348–356, 2001.
9. The highway patrol undertaken by the attine minors is documented by W. O. H. Hughes and
D. Goulson in Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 49, pp. 503–508, 2001.
10. See T. A. Linksvayer et al. in Biotropica, vol. 34, pp. 93–100, 2002.
11. Although the cut surfaces do provide a source of nutriment via the plant sap; see, for example,
M. Littledyke and J. M. Cherrett in Bulletin of Entomological Research, vol. 66, pp. 205–217,
1976.
12. See R. J. Quinlan and J. M. Cherrett in Ecological Entomology, vol. 2, pp. 161–170, 1977.
13. Interestingly, but perhaps not surprisingly, the enzymatic activity of the fungi and that in the
ants’ digestive system are distinct, each tending to attack different substrates. Such a lack of
overlap is consistent with this mutualism system being ancient. It is also possible that one of
the enzymatic properties the larvae possess has been transferred from the fungus. See P.
D’Ettorre et al. in Journal of Comparative Physiology, vol. 172B, pp. 169–176, 2002.
14. Details of this process are given by C. R. Currie and A. E. Stuart in Proceedings of the Royal
Society of London B, vol. 268, pp. 1033–1039, 2001. Weeding makes horizontal (or lateral)
transmission between nests substantially more difficult, but helps to ensure vertical
transmission (from generation to generation) within the nest; see A. N. M. Bot et al. in
Evolution, vol. 55, pp. 1980–1991, 2001.
15. As F. Roces and C. Kleineidam observe in Insectes Sociaux (vol. 47, pp. 348–350, 2000)
‘Relocation of fungus gardens to promote [fungal] growth, like the repotting of flowering
plants by humans, clearly illustrates the skill of leaf-cutting ants as true “gardeners”,’
p. 350.
16. At least on the basis of experimental work; see M. Bollazzi and F. Roces in Insectes Sociaux,
vol. 49, pp. 153–157, 2002.
17. See M. Bass and J. M. Cherrett in Functional Ecology, vol. 10, pp. 55–61, 1996.
18. Manuring is addressed by M. M. Martin on pp. 163–166 of his chapter reviewing the use of
ingested enzymes in insects in Invertebrate–microbial interactions, edited by J. M. Anderson
et al. (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1984).
19. The last of these compounds includes sterols that are essential for hormone synthesis; see
P. Maurer et al. in Archives of Insect Biochemistry and Physiology, vol. 20, pp. 13–21, 1992.
20. The threats posed to the attine ant colonies by this parasitic fungus are graphically brought
out by C. R. Currie in Oecologia, vol. 128, pp. 99–106, 2001. See also C. R. Currie et al. in
Science, vol. 299, p. 386–388, 2003. Smaller colonies are at particular risk, whereas the larger
ones remain clear of infection.
21. In fact the use of antibiotics is widespread in the social insects and termites; see R. B.
Rosengaus et al. in Journal of Chemical Ecology, vol. 26, pp. 21–39, 2000.
22. For more details see the paper by C. R. Currie et al. in Nature, vol. 398, pp. 701–704, 1999, as
well as the overview by C. R. Currie in Annual Review of Microbiology, vol. 55, pp. 357–380,
2001.
23. These include secretions from the metapleural glands, which are especially well developed in
the attines. See, for example, the papers by D. Ortius-Lechner et al. in Journal of Chemical
Ecology, vol. 26, pp. 1667–1683, 2000; A. N. M. Bot et al. in Insectes Sociaux, vol. 48,
pp. 63–66, 2001; and M. Poulsen et al. in Behavioural Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 52,
pp. 151–157, 2002. Experiments in which a fungicide is introduced quickly lead to a change in
notes to pp. 200–201 401
foraging behaviour, which may in addition lead to this behaviour being transmitted to
another colony; see R.D. North et al. in Physiological Entomology, vol. 24, pp. 127–133,
1999.
24. See M. Poulsen et al. in Insectes Sociaux, vol. 49, pp. 15–19, 2002, who document these
alternative defence mechanisms in two species of Acromyrmex.
25. This case of agro-predation by the ant Megalomyrmex is described by R. M. M. Adams et al.
in Naturwissenschaften, vol. 87, pp. 549–554, 2000. In this situation these ants have, of
course, to manipulate the fungi, and perhaps not surprisingly their ‘behavior closely
resembles that of attine ants when they add substrate to or reconstruct gardens . . . suggesting
that it has been convergently derived in Megalomyrmex sp. ants’ (p. 551). These authors also
point out that the continued health of the occupied gardens suggests that ‘Megalomyrmex sp.
may have evolved a similar repertoire of maintenance behaviors and chemical secretions’
(p. 550) to those of the attine ants.
26. For a graphic account of the defence and eventual overwhelming of an attine colony by the
army ant Nomamyrex see the article by M. B. Swartz in Biotropica, vol. 30, pp. 682–684, 1998.
27. See, in particular, W. H. Gotwald’s Army ants: the biology of social predation (Cornell
University Press [Comstock], Ithaca; 1995). The best-documented convergence of army ant
adaptive syndrome is between the New World Eciton and Old World taxa such as Dorylus and
Aenictus. Gotwald also draws attention to at least two more instances of army ant-like
behaviour, these being in two species of Pheidologeton where his comments include the
observation that ‘their foraging behavior is uncanny in its resemblance to that of army ants’
(p. 38), and also in the minuscule leptanillinine ants. A helpful summary of the behaviour of
leptanillinine ants and Pheidologeton is given on pp. 590–592 and pp. 593–594 of B.
Hölldobler and E. O. Wilson (1990; citation is in note 2).
28. The reality versus the folklore of army ants is addressed by Gotwald (1995), see pp. 237–238,
249, 252. In agriculture army ants may be helpful in pest-control, but they can also be
destructive of crops. One should note that the mandibles of ants have been used to suture
both natural and surgical wounds, pp. 249–250.
29. See N. R. Franks’ article ‘Army ants: A collective intelligence’ in American Scientist, vol. 77,
pp. 138–145, 1989. So, too, S. C. Pratt et al. (in Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 52,
pp. 117–127, 2002) describe how in the context of colony emigration another ant
(Leptothorax) society behaves ‘as a single information-processing unit’, (p. 117). These
authors draw attention to similar quorum sensing, not only in other social insects, notably
bee (see note 36), but even bacteria and immune response T-cells.
30. Well, not all of them, because the army ants have their own predators, including birds and
such anteaters as the pangolins.
31. As N. R. Franks et al. (in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 266,
pp. 1697–1701, 1999) show, the net result in New World Eciton and Old World Dorylus is
achieved by rather different means. In essence Dorylus uses more and smaller workers to
carry collectively larger loads, but at a slower speed. Further insights into the convergent
teamwork in Eciton and Dorylus are provided by N. R. Franks et al. in Animal Behaviour,
vol. 62, pp. 635–642, 2001. Here they show that the division of labour typically involves a
team with an unusually large and unusually small ant. As the authors point out, an analogy
for this exists in the form of the penny-farthing bicycle, where each wheel has a separate
sub-task, the ‘penny’ providing load-bearing and drive, the ‘farthing’ stability. The net result
is a synergistic contraption whose effectiveness is more than the sum of the parts.
32. This is only one example of the recurrent property of self-assembly in social insects, a topic
reviewed by C. Anderson et al. in Insectes Sociaux, vol. 49, pp. 99–110, 2002. These workers
identify at least 18 different ways in which insect individuals link themselves together to
form structures as disparate as bivouacs, bridges, ladders, and rafts. Not only are many of
these behaviours convergent, but, as importantly, they reflect new levels of complexity
unavailable to simpler societies.
402 notes to pp. 201–203
33. This topic is addressed by N. R. Franks in Physiological Entomology, vol. 14, pp. 397–404,
1989.
34. See G. P. Boswell et al. in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 268,
pp. 1723–1730, 2001.
35. See, for example G. J. Vermeij’s article in American Naturalist, vol. 120, pp. 701–720, 1982,
especially pp. 710–713.
36. The complexity and sophistication of the bee colony is probably still underestimated, and
their degree of integration with selection operating at the group level of the colony (see, for
example, the article by T. D. Seeley in American Naturalist, vol. 150, pp. 522–541, 1997)
makes them, at least potentially, an interesting evolutionary alternative to the emergence of
advanced cognizance. Consider, for example, how a bee swarm dispatches scout bees to
numerous sites that are then ‘assessed’ before a collective decision is arrived at; see
S. Camazine et al. in Insectes Sociaux, vol. 46, pp. 348–360, 1999 and T. D. Seeley and
S. C. Buhrmann in Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 45, pp. 19–31, 1999.
37. For example, T. S. Collett et al., in Journal of Comparative Physiology, vol. 181A,
pp. 343–353, 1997, present evidence for contextural learning in honey-bees, and M. Giurfa
et al. (in Nature, vol. 410, pp. 930–933, 2001) show that not only can bees place the outside
world in a context and memorize it, but engage in higher-order functions, that is they can
‘master abstract interrelationships, such as sameness and difference’, p. 930.
38. See the papers by W. Kaiser in Nature, vol. 301, pp. 707–709, 1983 (with J. Steiner-Kaiser) and
Journal of Comparative Physiology, vol. 163A, pp. 565–584, 1988. In the latter paper Kaiser
remarks how four characteristics – decreased motility, lowered body temperature, reduced
muscle tone, and raised reaction threshold – ‘strongly resemble [those] characteristic features
of sleep in humans, mammals and birds’ (p. 565). So do bees dream?
39. See, for example, G. Buzsaki in Journal of Sleep Research, vol. 7 (Supplement 1), pp. 17–23,
1998, as well as more recent contributions in Nature Neuroscience, vol. 3, pp. 1237–1238 (R.
Stickgold et al.) and pp. 1335–1339 (S. Gais et al.), 2000. A useful overview of the adaptive
contexts of sleep is given by J. L. Kavanau in Animal Behaviour, vol. 62, pp. 1219–1224, 2001,
and in his earlier article in Brain Research Bulletin, vol. 42, pp. 245–264, 1997, where the
potential importance of endothermy (see p. 223 of this Chapter) is stressed.
40. The honey bees themselves show an interesting convergence with another eusocial species,
the common wasp. This entails so-called ‘worker policing’ in which any eggs laid by the
workers, which will be parthenogenetic and male, are quickly destroyed by other members of
the squad – egg production of course being the prerogative of the queen. As K. R. Foster and F.
L. W. Ratnieks, in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 268, pp. 169–174, 2001,
remark ‘The worker policing by mutual egg-eating in V. vulgaris (the common wasp) is
strikingly similar to that found in the honeybee A. mellifera . . . This is not due to common
ancestry since the vespine wasps and honeybees belong to lineages that have evolved
eusociality independently’ (p. 172). There are, however, differences between these insects in
terms of their genetic relatedness of the workers: effectively honeybee queens are
polyandrous, that is they receive multiple matings on their nuptial flights, so workers are not
closely related and there is a premium in destroying any workers’ eggs (‘not your genes,
destroy! destroy!’). In the wasps, however, relatedness of the workers is higher, and so another
explanation for the policing has to be found. Here Foster and Ratnieks suggest that the benefit
may arise from reducing intra-colony reproductive aggression. They also remark that such
policing may well be a feature of leaf-cutter and other ant colonies; see also remarks by
P. Villesen et al. (in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 269, pp. 1541–1548,
2002) on the convergent emergence of multiple matings in leaf-cutter ants and other very
advanced social insects.
41. Stingless they may be, but they are highly effective in defending the colony, ‘locking their
mandibles in catatonic spasms so that before the grip is broken, their heads tear loose from
the body. The Trigona flaveola group of species in tropical America also eject a burning liquid
notes to pp. 203–205 403
from their mandibles which in Brazil has earned them the name cagafogos, meaning ‘fire
defecators’, p. 89 of E. O. Wilson’s The insect societies (Belknap, Cambridge, MA; 1971). For
an interesting account of the highly sophisticated methods of communication in the stingless
bees, see the article by J. C. Nieh in American Scientist, vol. 87, pp. 428–435, 1999, which he
notes has probably evolved independently of the honey-bee; see also note 43.
42. On this topic see the paper by M. S. Engel in Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, USA, vol. 98, pp. 1661–1664, 2001.
43. See the paper by S. A. Cameron and P. Mardulyn in Systematic Biology, vol. 50, pp. 194–214,
2001. Their conclusions are highly resonant with the thrust of this book: ‘If indeed the highly
eusocial behavior of Apini and Meliponini evolved twice independently – the hypothesis we
support as being more likely – then the comparative behavior of these bees takes on an added
interest from an evolutionary perspective. The apparent convergent similarities in behavior
between these two tribes suggest that highly eusocial organization has limited permutations.
Each tribe has been channeled along a similar behavioral track, responding in similar fashion
to similar contingencies’, p. 209. The notion of convergence in advanced eusocial behaviour
actually goes back many years, see, for example, M. L. Winston and C. D. Michener in
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 74, pp. 1135–1137, 1977. These
authors are also struck by the implications of convergence; they write, ‘The development of
such [highly social] behavior, probably the most elaborate of any invertebrate, is remarkable
enough; independent parallel development of two highly eusocial systems would be even
more noteworthy’ (p. 1135). Engel (2001), however, regards advanced eusociality in bees as
monophyletic (as does F. B. Noll in Cladistics, vol. 18, pp. 137–153, 2002). He bases his
analysis on the fossil record, especially amber preservation. S. A. Cameron and P. Mardulyn
(2001) come to the same conclusion on the basis of morphological data, but this is in conflict
with molecular data.
44. The general consensus is that advanced eusocial species, with such features as division of
labour and colony homeostasis, are effectively ‘locked in’ to this arrangement. It should be
pointed out that there is evidence that in the case of less organized social behaviours this does
not preclude a return to a solitary mode of life and that this has occurred independently a
number of times. See, for example, the papers by R. Gadagkar (in Current Science, vol. 72,
pp. 950–956, 1997) and W. T. Wcislo and B. N. Danforth (in Trends in Ecology & Evolution,
vol. 12, pp. 468–474, 1997), as well as the useful overview by B. J. Crespi, on pp. 253–287 of
Phylogenies and the comparative method in animal behavior, edited by E. P. Martins (Oxford
University Press, New York, 1996).
45. M. S. Engel (2001; citation is in note 42); see p. 1663. This writer is careful to emphasize that
competition need not be the sole cause of extinction in the eusocial bees, and that climate
cooling might also play some role.
46. Part of the title of G. P. Boswell et al. (2001; citation is in note 34).
47. N. R. Franks (1989; citation is in note 29), p. 139.
48. Ulrich Mueller reminds me that pheromones are not the only currency of exchange in ant
communication, and that tactile contact and food exchange can also be important.
49. N. R. Franks (1989; citation is in note 29), p. 144.
50. See his chapter (pp. 281–298) in Insect movement: mechanisms and consequences, edited by
I. P. Woiwod et al. (CABI, Wallingford, 2001, p. 286, his emphases). See also the papers by E.
Bonabeau entitled ‘Social insect colonies as complex adaptive systems’ in Ecosystems, vol. 1,
pp. 437–443, 1998, and B. J. Cole in Biological Bulletin, vol. 202, pp. 256–261, 2002.
51. See the stimulating article by A. D. M. Rayner and N. R. Franks on ‘Evolutionary and
ecological parallels between ants and fungi’ in Trends in Ecology & Evolution, vol. 2,
pp. 127–133, 1987.
52. C. Kleinidam et al. (in Naturwissenschaften, vol. 88, pp. 301–305, 2001) have confirmed that
the ventilation is wind-induced, a not surprising necessity given the large quantities of
oxygen required by the inhabitants and their fungi.
404 notes to pp. 205–208
53. See, for example, the remarkable photograph (Fig. 20c) in the paper on nest structure
by J. C. M. Jonkman in Zeitschrift f ür Angewandte Entomologie, vol. 89, pp. 217–246, 1980.
54. See A. G. Hart and F. L. W. Ratnieks in Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 49,
pp. 387–392, 2001, and also Behavioral Ecology, vol. 13, pp. 224–231, 2002.
55. Waste dumps are frequently infected with the parasitic fungus Escovopsis (see note 20) and
mortality of the workers can be significantly increased if the waste material is not quickly
cleared; see A. N. M. Bot et al. in Ethology, Ecology and Evolution, vol. 13, pp. 225–237, 2001.
Bot et al. also remark that ‘There are a number of interesting parallels between waste
management in agricultural societies of ant and human. Both isolate waste in specific places:
ants use refuse chambers or piles where we use landfill sites . . . natural selection has probably
led to a series of general attitudes of disgust towards different types of waste products . . .
Apparently, natural selection and evolution have produced converged methods by which
to address these problems in both human and insect societies,’ p. 235.
56. See the paper by U. G. Mueller et al. in Science, vol. 281, pp. 2034–2038, 1998, as well as the
stimulating commentary by J. Diamond on pp. 1974–1975, where he explores the similarities
to and differences from human agriculture. The likely origins of the attine ant-fungus
association are addressed by U. G. Mueller et al. in Quarterly Review of Biology, vol. 76,
pp. 169–197, 2001.
57. See The origins of agriculture: An international perspective, edited by C. W. Cowan and
P. J. Watson (Smithsonian, Washington, DC, 1992). In particular, the chapter (pp. 143–171) by
E. M. de Tapia specifically rejects the generally popular notion of population increase in the
instance of Mesoamerica.
58. See U. G. Mueller et al. (2001; citation is in note 56).
59. N. A. Weber (1972; citation is in note 2), p. 1.
60. J. C. M. Jonkman in Zeitschrift f ür Angewandte Entomologie, vol. 89, pp. 135–143, 1980
provides some interesting figures on both population sizes and biomass accumulated by the
colony.
61. This topic is addressed by R. M. M. Adams et al. in Naturwissenschaften, vol. 87, pp. 491–493,
2000; see also A. M. Green et al. in Molecular Ecology, vol. 11, pp. 191–195, 2002.
62. Quoted (p. 763) in the article by L. Ariniello in Bioscience, vol. 49, pp. 760–763, 1999.
63. See B. D. Farrell et al. in Evolution, vol. 55, pp. 2011–2027, 2001, and the review by R. A.
Beaver on pp. 121–143 in Insect–fungus interactions, edited by N. Wilding et al. (Academic
Press, London, 1989). See also C. C. Labandeira et al. in American Journal of Botany, vol. 88,
pp. 2026–2039, 2001.
64. See A. R. Berryman’s chapter (pp. 145–159) in Wilding et al. (1989).
65. A. R. Berryman (1989), p. 149.
66. See the overview by T. D. Paine et al. in Annual Review of Entomology, vol. 42, pp. 176–206,
1997.
67. Evolution of defensive compounds, such as resin and latex in plants, is rampantly convergent.
B. D. Farrell et al., in American Naturalist, vol. 138, pp. 881–900, 1991, estimate that ‘Canal
systems containing latex or resin appear to have originated at least 40 times,’ p. 889.
68. B. D. Farrell et al. (2001; citation is in note 63), p. 2017.
69. See the chapter (pp. 105–130) by J. P. E. C. Darlington in J. H. Hunt and C. A. Nalepa (1994;
citation is in note 2). See also D. K. Aanen et al. (in Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, USA, vol. 99, pp. 14887–14892, 2002), who document the evolution of this
mutualism, as well as the differences and similarities between termites and attine ants, and
J. Korb and D. K. Aanen in Behavioural Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 53, pp. 65–71, 2003).
70. See the description by J. P. E. C. Darlington in Journal of Zoology, London, vol. 198,
pp. 237–247, 1982, which together with Darlington (1994) provides the information given
here; see also G. Schuurman and J. M. Dangerfield in Sociobiology, vol. 27, pp. 29–38, 1996.
71. The example of convergent evolution between the Echidnophora and Termitoxeniiae is given
by R. H. L. Disney in Systematic Entomology, vol. 20, pp. 195–206, 1995.
notes to pp. 208–213 405
94. This is known as transformational mimicry. For example, A. P. Mathew, in Journal of the
Bombay Natural History Society, vol. 37, pp. 803–813, 1935, explains how the hemipteran
bug Riptortus pedestris, in a series of moults, successively resembles the ant Prenolepis
longicornis (‘almost indistinguishable’, p. 804), then Plagiolepis (‘mimicry at this stage is
almost perfect’, p. 804), and then the already encountered Oecophylla smaragdina ‘which
presented a very perfect resemblance to the Red Ant . . . even more perfect than the mimicry
which I was observing and studying in the Attid ants’ (p. 803). J. D. McIver and G. Stonedahl
(1993; citation is in note 93) provide an overview on this topic, with further citations.
95. See J. D. McIver and G. Stonedahl (1993), pp. 364–365.
96. A helpful overview is given by L. E. Gilbert in his chapter (pp. 263–281) in Coevolution,
edited by D. J. Futuyama and M. Slatkin (Sinauer, Sunderland, MA, 1983), who concludes by
remarking ‘Mimicry is possibly the most compelling evidence that community patterns are
more than random noise,’ p. 281.
97. But see, for example, the paper by J. Berger and J. Kaster (in Evolution, vol. 33, pp. 511–513,
1979). Berger and Kaster argue that a striking resemblance between a caddisfly larva
(Helicopsyche borealis) and an aquatic snail (Physa integra) arises from a common selection
pressure imposed by the hydrodynamic regime rather than a mimicry imposed by
predation.
98. See the interesting overview by C. Anderson and D. W. McShea in Insectes Sociaux, vol. 48,
pp. 291–301, 2001. One might draw attention to the ant equivalent of ‘cow-sheds’ to house
honeydew-yielding aphids, and ‘pens’ to look after caterpillars. In their conclusion the
authors remark, ‘What is certainly needed is more detail about construction mechanisms.
Where such information was available, we observe a good example of convergent evolution:
trenches and arcades appear to be similar in both structure and construction behavior in new
world army ants, such as Labidus, old world African driver ants, such as Dorylus, and Asian
marauder ants, Pheidologeton. Arcade construction [in the last genus] has certainly arisen
independently,’ p. 299.
99. See K. Wada in Ethology, vol. 96, pp. 270–280, 1994 and Crustaceana, vol. 68, pp. 524–526,
1995 (with J. K. Park); and J. Kitaura et al. in Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 15,
pp. 626–637, 1998.
100. See the paper by G. A. Croll and J. B. McClintock in Journal of Experimental Marine Biology
and Ecology, vol. 254, pp. 109–121, 2000.
101. As an aside on the topic of convergence, I cannot resist the example of the discharge of ink by
various cephalopods to baffle their attackers. And the parallel? The discharge of a reddish
cloud by dwarf sperm-whales, albeit from the anus; see M. D. Scott and J. G. Cordaro in
Marine Mammal Science, vol. 3, pp. 353–354, 1987.
102. A useful review of the brains of octopuses and other advanced cephalopods is given by B. U.
Budelmann on pp. 115–138 of The nervous system of invertebrates: An evolutionary and
comparative approach edited by O. Breidbach and W. Kutsch (Birkhäuser, Basel, 1995); see
also the chapter (pp. 399–413) by B. U. Budelmann et al. in Cephalopod neurobiology:
Neuroscience studies in squid, octopus, and cuttlefish, edited by N. J. Abbott et al. (Oxford
University Press, Oxford, 1995) and J. Z. Young’s monograph The anatomy of the nervous
system of Octopus vulgaris (Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1971). In describing the cerebellum-like
structure in the squid brain, J. Z. Young (in Nature, vol. 264, pp. 572–574, 1976) remarked
how the pattern of nervous control associated with movement of the eye as well as the whole
animal ‘shows remarkable similarities between cephalopods and vertebrates, in spite of the
fact that the gross anatomical entities are totally different’, p. 574.
103. See the stimulating paper by A. Packard entitled Cephalopods and fish: the limits of
convergence in Biological Reviews 47, 241–307, 1972. The question of relative brain sizes is
addressed on pp. 265–267. Packard’s overall conclusion is that the cephalopods are good, but
not as good as the fish. Even so, if the fish eventually win out it is going to take time. J. J.
Madan and M. J. Wells also point out, in Nature, vol. 380, p. 590, 1996, that the deep-sea
notes to pp. 214–215 407
squid have a refuge of sorts by inhabiting sea water with low levels of oxygen, a mode of life
made possible by having very thin – and delicate – gills.
104. See chapter 27 (pp. 446–457) by M. Bundgaard et al. in N. J. Abbott et al. (1995; citation is in
note 102), as well as two companion papers by N. J. Abbott et al. in Journal of Physiology,
vol. 368, pp. 197–212 and 213–226, 1985.
105. M. Bundgaard et al. (1995; citation is in note 104), p. 446.
106. See H. Jaaro et al. in Trends in Neurosciences, vol. 24, pp. 79–85, 2001. Interestingly, the most
advanced sort of brains in the arthropods, found in the insects, apparently lack neurotrophins,
at least to judge from a survey of the fruit-fly genome. This is not to say that insect brains are
simple; the reverse is very much the case. Jaaro et al. suggest, however, that neurotrophins
predetermine the ‘differences between a “plastic” nervous system with a potential for
evolving complexity, versus a more constrained nervous system that cannot evolve beyond
certain limitations’ (p. 84). It may be unwise, however, to underestimate the plasticity of
insect brains; see, for example, the overview by I. A. Meinertzhagen in Advances in Insect
Physiology, vol. 28, pp. 84–167, 2001.
107. Chromatic expression is controlled by a specific area of the brain and is achieved by
pigmented areas known as chromatophores; see, for example, the papers by E. Florey in
American Zoologist, vol. 9, pp. 429–442, 1969; R. T. Hanlon and J. B. Messenger in
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 320, pp. 437–487, 1988, and
Cephalopod behaviour (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1996); and A. Packard in
chapter 21 (pp. 331–367) of Abbott et al. (1995; citation is in note 102). J. B. Messenger (in
Biological Reviews, vol. 76, pp. 473–528, 2001) remarks ‘Cephalopods are such complex and
behaviourly advanced animals . . . that they must be able to transmit messages of a far subtler
kind [than straightforward messages] and it seems likely that future work will reveal this’
(p. 520). See also A. C. Crook et al. (in Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of
London B, vol. 357, pp. 1617–1624, 2002), who note that in contrast to other animal
communication systems (see note 140, Chapter 9)) the visual signals of cuttlefish do not
follow Zipf’s law.
108. Relevant literature includes papers by G. Fiorito and P. Scotto in Science, vol. 256,
pp. 545–547, 1992; J. Z. Young in Biological Bulletin, vol. 180, pp. 200–208, 1991a, Visual
Neuroscience, vol. 7, pp. 1–12, 1991b; and J. G. Boal et al. in Journal of Comparative
Psychology, vol. 114, pp. 246–252, 2000. Fiorito and Scotto show how one octopus can learn
by observing the activities of another octopus. J. Z. Young in his 1991a paper demonstrates
how there are effectively two memory systems, one chemo-tactile and one visual. He remarks
on the complexity of the brain structure, noting that the learning ability ‘is distributed with
high redundancy in a series of matrices networks, with recurrent circuitry, up to a late stage
where funneling to a few cells occurs’ (p. 206). Elsewhere (in chapter 26 (pp. 432–443) of
N. J. Abbott et al. (1995; citation is in note 102)), Young remarks that ‘The information
already available shows that the octopus memory involves selection during learning among
large number of parallel pathways. The capacity to set up and hold the memory is distributed
among many distinct matrices. This seems to be the case also in the complex memories of
mammals, birds, and insects’, p. 442.
109. T. Moriyama and Y-P. Gunji (in Ethology, vol. 103, pp. 499–513, 1997), show how the octopus
can choose a seemingly inefficient action (e.g. reduced swimming speed) the more easily to
achieve its final objective, say a tasty piece of shrimp.
110. On octopus living on coral atolls in French Polynesia, see J. W. Forsythe and R. T. Hanlon in
Journal of Experimental Marine Biology and Ecology, vol. 209, pp. 15–31, 1997.
111. J. W. Forsythe and R. T. Hanlon (1997; citation is in note 110), p. 26.
112. See the paper by J. A. Mather and R. C. Anderson in Journal of Comparative Psychology,
vol. 107, pp. 336–340, 1993. Their analysis depends on the difference between octopus
individuals, their patent ability to learn in the face of novel environments, and
temperamental behaviour, which also define in part human personality. This work is
408 notes to pp. 215–216
extended by D. L. Sinn et al. in the same journal (vol. 115, pp. 351–364, 2001). They suspect
that the range of octopus temperaments may not be fully explored, while Mather and
Anderson comment that there may be commonalities across phyla; addressing an octopus by
name need not be completely daft.
113. The rubber-like proteins in the octopus aorta are documented by R. E. Shadwick and
J. M. Gosline in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 114, pp. 239–257, 1985. Such proteins,
of which the vertebrate elastin, insect resilin, and bivalve mollusc abductin are another three
examples, are possibly convergent. These authors note that ‘The tremendous variation in
amino acid composition among the four known protein rubbers . . . suggests to us that each
protein arose independently during evolution in response to selection for similar mechanical
design’, p. 256.
114. R. E. Shadwick notes in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 202, pp. 3305–3313, 1999, that
‘In animals as different as Nautilus [a cephalopod] and the rat, there is a striking similarity in
the microscopic appearance of the aortic wall’, p. 3309. See also his earlier articles in Marine
Behavior and Physiology, vol. 25, pp. 69–85, 1994, and Journal of Experimental Biology,
vol. 114, pp. 259–284, 1985 (with J. M. Gosline); and R. Schipp et al. in Zoomorphology,
vol. 118, pp. 79–85, 1998. It is also worth mentioning that the convergence in arterial wall
structure also extends to the crustaceans; see R. E. Shadwick et al. in Physiological Zoology,
vol. 63, pp. 90–101, 1990.
115. Helpful reviews of the circulatory system of cephalopods are given by M. J. Wells in
pp. 239–290, volume 5 of The Mollusca, edited by A. S. M. Saleuddin and K. M. Wilbur
(Academic Press, New York, 1983), and in Experientia vol. 43, pp. 487–499, 1987 (with
P. J. S. Smith), where they remark, ‘The basic design of the molluscan circulatory system
was . . . well suited to a slow-moving animal . . . but a disaster for large, high-metabolic rate
invertebrates, competing with fish and other vertebrates. Natural selection works on the
material available, and the cephalopod circulatory system is a miracle of making the best of a
bad lot’ (pp. 497–498). They continue, ‘Jet propulsion is inescapably expensive . . . It costs a
squid . . . something like twice as much energy, to travel half as fast, as a salmon. The
difference would be even more extreme if comparisons were made with mackeral or tuna . . .
Add to these problems the appallingly low carrying capacity [of oxygen] of cephalopod blood,
and it is evident that the circulatory pumps must be achieving something rather remarkable
in terms of cardiac output’ (p. 498). A similar conclusion is reached by R. E. Shadwick et al.
(in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 130, pp. 87–106, 1987) where they also note that
amongst the large squids the arterial haemodynamics is likely to be much more similar to
that of the active vertebrates. R. Schipp also has a short, but helpful, update in Vie et Milieu,
vol. 47, pp. 111–116, 1997.
116. The topic of these branchial hearts is addressed in the literature cited in note 115, and also by
A. Fielder and R. Schipp in Experientia, vol. 43, pp. 544–553, 1987.
117. These are not the only differences. Despite the systemic heart in the cephalopods, many of
the other veins are also muscular and contractile. They also lack true capillaries, but this
might be because the blood protein consists of aggregates of haemocyanin, whereas in the
vertebrates the squeezing of the red blood corpuscles through the narrow capillaries
facilitates oxygen release.
118. This perichondrial tissue is described by A. Bairati et al. in Tissue & Cell, vol. 27,
pp. 515–523, 1995. In a general review of invertebrate cartilages, P. Person and D. E. Philpott,
in Biological Reviews, vol. 44, pp. 1–16, 1969, remark of cephalopod cartilage ‘The cell
processes penetrate the matrix, and often give rise to extensive systems of intercellular
canaliculae, very similar to those seen in vertebrate bone and cartilage’, p. 8.
119. A helpful overview is given in The mechanosensory lateral line: neurobiology and evolution
edited by S. Coombs et al. (Springer, New York, 1989).
120. The lateral line analogue in the cephalopods is known as the epidermal lines; see
G. Sundermann in Cell and Tissue Research, vol. 232, pp. 669–677; 1983. Confirmation of a
sensory role was given by B. U. Budelmann and H. Bleckmann in Journal of Comparative
notes to pp. 216–218 409
Physiology, vol. 164A, pp. 1–5, 1988, where they noted it is ‘another fascinating example,
beside the eyes [see notes 22–27, Chapter 7] and equilibrium receptor systems [see note 28,
Chapter 7], of convergent evolution between a sophisticated cephalopod and vertebrate
sensory system’ (p. 4). More details were given by H. Bleckmann et al. in vol. 168A,
pp. 247–257, 1991 of the same journal. More recent contributions are an overview by B. U.
Budelmann in Marine and Freshwater Behaviour and Physiology, vol. 25, pp. 13–33, 1994;
S. Lenz et al. in Zoologisches Anzeiger, vol. 234, pp. 145–157, 1995; and S. Lenz in Vie et
Milieu, vol. 47, pp. 143–147, 1997.
121. See S. Coombs et al. in Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B,
vol. 355, pp. 1111–1114, 2000.
122. See R. L. Reep et al. in Brain, Behavior and Evolution, vol. 59, pp. 141–152, 2002.
123. See E. J. Denton and J. Gray in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 226,
pp. 249–261, 1985.
124. See Jared Diamond’s chapter (pp. 3–8) in Ecological restoration of New Zealand islands,
edited by D. R. Towns et al. (Conservation Sciences Publication, No. 2, 1990).
125. J. Diamond (1990; citation is in note 124), p. 3.
126. See the review by R. A. Cooper and P. R. Millener in Trends in Ecology & Evolution, vol. 8,
pp. 429–433, 1993.
127. The quotation, which paraphrases a sentence in the article ‘Invertebrate mice’ by G. W.
Ramsay in New Zealand Entomologist, vol. 6, p. 400, 1978, is from a stimulating review
paper by C. H. Daugherty et al. in Trends in Ecology & Evolution, vol. 8, pp. 437–442, 1993,
see p. 439.
128. Further information on the amazing wetas is available in a paper by A. M. Richards in Journal
of Zoology, vol. 169, pp. 195–236, 1973. One weta, Deinacrida heteracantha, can grow up to
82 mm and thus is one of the largest insects in the world. See also The biology of wetas, king
crickets and their allies, edited by L. H. Field (CAB International, Wallingford, 2001), where
the mouse-like characters of wetas are remarked upon by M. McIntyre, on p. 226 of her
chapter (pp. 225–242). I should emphasize, however, that the editor, Larry Field, is dismissive
of wetas being regarded as ecological analogues of mice (personal communication).
129. J. Diamond (1990, citation is in note 124), p. 4. This wren is extinct, eaten by a cat.
J. Diamond also remarks on the attempts of short-tailed bats and wetas to ‘become’ mice.
130. See C. H. Daugherty et al. (1993; citation is in note 127). C. H. Daugherty et al. also remark
on the other parallels, with large flightless birds occupying the niches elsewhere taken by
browsing and grazing mammals.
131. A brief account of this flightless parrot, which can however glide, is available in A field guide
to the birds of New Zealand and outlying islands (Collins, London, 1966) by R. A. Falla et al.
(see pp. 170–171).
132. An overview of moa species and their ecological impact is given by A. Cooper et al. in Trends
in Ecology & Evolution, vol. 8, pp. 433–437, 1993, and a general account is given by A.
Anderson in Prodigious birds: Moas and moa-hunting in prehistoric New Zealand
(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1989).
133. See A. Cooper et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 89,
pp. 8741–8744, 1992, and also A. Cooper et al. in Nature, vol. 409, pp. 704–707, 2001. Cooper
et al. suggest that the kiwis and moas represent separate colonizations, with kiwis arriving
earlier. Giant, flightless birds have evolved repeatedly. Other examples in addition to those in
New Zealand include the Madagascan elephant birds and the fearsome South American
phorusrhacids. Another independent development, from the Eocene of Egypt, is reported by
D. T. Rasmussen et al. in Palaeontology, vol. 44, pp. 325–337, 2001. This occurrence is
important because Africa appeared to be the only significant landmass without an endemic
large, ground-dwelling bird (the ostriches migrated to Africa from Asia in the Miocene).
134. Despite earlier scepticism there is now little doubt that the Maoris were an important
element in the extinction of the moa, by both direct and profligate hunting, and also burning
of forest habitats. See the chapters by M. Trotter and B. McCullock (pp. 708–727) and
410 notes to pp. 218–220
145. An extensive review of reptile placentation is given by Z. Yaron on pp. 527–603 in vol. 15 of
Biology of the Reptilia, edited by C. Gans and G. Billett (Wiley, New York, 1985). See also
D. G. Blackburn in Journal of Experimental Zoology, vol. 266, pp. 414–430, 1993, where he
remarks that ‘The evolution of placentomes in three separate lineages [of squamate]
represents an extraordinary manifestation of convergence’ (p. 427). It has long been
recognized that the development of the reptile placenta is quite independent of the mammals
and might also indicate how it arose in the latter group. See also D. N. Reznick et al. in
Science, vol. 298, pp. 1018–1020, 2002 (with commentary by V. Morell on p. 945) who
document the independent evolution of a placenta in the fish Poeciliopsis, and also make
some interesting remarks on the rapid emergence of complex biological structures.
146. Daniel Blackburn and his colleagues’ paper is published in Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 81, pp. 4860–4863, 1984.
147. D. G. Blackburn et al. (1984; citation is in note 146), p. 4862.
148. Concerning the placenta and viviparity of Mabuya bistriata, see L. J. Vitt and
D. G. Blackburn in Copeia, for 1991, pp. 916–927, 1991. A helpful overview of reproduction in
Mabuya is given by D. G. Blackburn and L. J. Vitt on pp. 150–164 of Reproductive biology of
South American vertebrates, edited by W. C. Hamlett (Springer, New York, 1992), where they
write, ‘The independent evolution of these features among mammals and lizards represents
one of the most striking cases of evolutionary convergence in reproductive specializations to
be documented among terrestrial vertebrates’, p. 161.
149. See D. G. Blackburn in Amphibia–Reptilia, vol. 3, pp. 185–205, 1982.
150. See D. G. Blackburn (1992, citation is in note 142). Further details of this remarkable placenta
are given by D. G. Blackburn in Journal of Morphology, vol. 216, pp. 179–195, 1993.
151. J. P. Wourms and J. Lombardi (1992; citation is in note 144), p. 290, as well as earlier remarks
by J. P. Wourms and colleagues in the first chapter (pp. 1–134) of Fish physiology, vol. XIB,
edited by W. S. Hoar and D. J. Randall (Academic Press, San Diego, 1988). In the latter work
they remark ‘The selachian yolk-sac placenta has probably obtained the pinnacle of its
evolutionary development in the spadenose shark . . . Here it appears to function with the
same degree of efficiency as a mammalian placenta.’ (p. 69). See also note 154.
152. D. G. Blackburn (1992; citation is in note 142), p. 320.
153. D. G. Blackburn (1992; citation is in note 142), p. 320.
154. See the paper by N. K. Dulvy and J. D. Reynolds in Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London B, vol. 264, pp. 1309–1315, 1997. See also M. S. Y. Lee and R. Shine, in Evolution,
vol. 52, pp. 1441–1450, 1998, who present evidence for reversals in the tendency towards
viviparity in the reptiles. While such reversals are not ruled out absolutely, in reality there are
only a handful of possible examples. Such entrenchments impose a strong directionality on
the history of life.
155. See D. G. Blackburn (1982; citation is in note 149). See also R. M. Andrews (in Physiological
and Biochemical Zoology, vol. 75, pp. 145–154, 2002), who explores the link between
coolness and oxygen availability in determining the likelihood of viviparity, and especially
R. Shine (in American Naturalist, vol. 160, pp. 582–593, 2002), who presents sound adaptive
reasons why cooler thermal regimes favour in utero development of reptile eggs.
156. N. K. Dulvy and J. D. Reynolds (1997; citation is in note 154), p. 1314.
157. See B. Heinrich’s The hot-blooded insects. Strategies and mechanisms of thermoregulation
(Springer, Berlin, 1993), and The thermal warriors: Strategies of insect survival (Harvard
University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1996).
158. See the papers by B. A. Block et al. in Science, vol. 260, pp. 210–214, 1993 (and commentary
by T. Watson on pp. 160–161), and B. A. Block and J. R. Finnerty in Environmental Biology of
Fishes, vol. 40, pp. 283–302, 1994.
159. See the paper by F. G. Carey et al. in Memoirs, Southern California Academy of Sciences,
vol. 9, pp. 92–108, 1985, where they also note similarities with tuna.
160. Reviewed in B. A. Block and J. R. Finnerty (1994; citation is in note 158).
412 notes to pp. 224–227
161. See the paper by B. A. Block and F. G. Carey in Journal of Comparative Physiology, 156B,
pp. 229–236, 1985.
162. B. A. Block and F. G. Carey (1985; citation is in note 161), p. 234.
163. B. A. Block et al. (1993; citation is in note 158), p. 213.
164. The grim topic of malignant hyperthermia in humans and its equivalent in pigs (porcine
stress syndrome) is addressed by D. H. MacLennan and M. S. Phillips in Science, vol. 256,
pp. 789–794, 1992.
165. The similarities between malignant hyperthermia and ‘tuna burn’ are reviewed by B. A. Block
in Annual Review of Physiology, vol. 56, pp. 535–577, 1994; see also B. A. Block and
J. R. Finnerty (1994; citation is in note 158).
166. C. G. Farmer’s paper, entitled ‘Parental care: The key to understanding endothermy and other
convergent features in birds and mammals’ was published in American Naturalist, vol. 155,
pp. 326–334, 2000.
167. C. G. Farmer (2000; citation is in note 166), p. 330; as given here the quotation has been
rewritten by combining parts of a paragraph.
168. Convergences of maternal care also occur within the mammals, such as between the
placental ungulates and macropod marsupials, e.g. kangaroo. See D. O. Fisher et al., in
Evolution, vol. 56, pp. 167–176, 2002.
169. C. G. Farmer (2000; citation is in note 166), p. 330.
170. The descent of Man, and selection in relation to sex (Murray, London, 1889, second edition),
p.181. Or is this an ‘urban myth’, like the last Cornish monoglot, Dolly Pentreath (d. 1777)
and her apocryphal posthumous parrot?
171. See P. M. Gray et al. in Science, vol. 291, pp. 52–54, 2001.
172. This concerns the male palm cockatoo that selects a fresh stick and shapes it (by removing
foliage, chewing the ends off and stripping bark) into a drumstick suitable for drumming on a
hollow log; see G. A. Wood in Corella, vol. 8, pp. 94–95, 1984.
173. P. M. Gray et al. (2001; citation is in note 171), p. 52.
174. See I. M. Pepperberg in Animal Learning and Behavior, vol. 27, pp. 15–17, 1999 (citations are
in notes 137 and 139 of Chapter 9).
175. Allison Doupe and Patricia Kuhl’s paper, entitled ‘Birdsong and human speech: Common
themes and mechanisms’ is in Annual Review of Neuroscience, vol. 22, pp. 567–631; 1999.
The realization that there are important parallels between birdsong and human speech
include, for example, second language acquisition (or bilingualism) (see I. M. Pepperberg and
D. M. Neapolitan in Ethology, vol. 77, pp. 150–168, 1988), and evidence for cultural
transmission (see R. B. Payne et al. in Behaviour, vol. 77, pp. 199–221, 1981).
176. A. Doupe and P. Kuhl (1999; citation is in note 175), p. 567.
177. A. Doupe and P. Kuhl (1999; citation is in note 175), p. 597.
178. A. Doupe and P. Kuhl (1999; citation is in note 175), p. 594.
179. A. Doupe and P. Kuhl (1999; citation is in note 175), p. 567.
180. See G. F. Striedter in Journal of Comparative Neurology, vol. 343, pp. 35–56, 1994;
subsequently, E. D. Jarvis et al. (in Nature, vol. 406, pp. 628–632, 2000) reported striking
similarities in the forebrain region of hummingbirds, songbirds, and parrots. This idea is
further developed by M. A. Farrier in Brain, Behavior and Evolution, vol. 58, pp. 80–100,
2001, who writes, ‘nature has conducted what are in effect three independent experiments in
the evolution of vocal learning in birds: parrots, hummingbirds, and songbirds. By studying
the evolution of similar behavioral capacities from similar starting points, it might be
possible to address some important questions in evolutionary biology . . . For example, how
much freedom does evolution have to find different solutions to the same problem?’ p. 96.
181. There are plenty of examples of convergence in such grinding teeth, such as those between
the molars of the rhinoceros Elasmotherium and horses (see W. B. Scott in Journal of
Morphology, vol. 5, pp. 301–406, 1891), and within the elephants (see M. O. Thomas et al. in
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 267, pp. 2493–2500, 2000).
notes to pp. 227–229 413
182. In passing, one should note an emphasis on a mammal-like occlusion in the teeth of a much
more primitive group of chordates, the extinct conodonts; see P. C. J. Donoghue and
M. A. Purnell in Paleobiology, vol. 25, pp. 58–74, 1999. This example is interesting because
the marine conodonts, whose precise taxonomic position is controversial, lack anything like
a jaw. See also P. C. J. Donoghue in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 268,
pp. 1691–1698, 2001.
183. The tribosphenic molar is typically of the primitive marsupial and placental mammals, and
their immediate forebears. Z-x. Luo et al. (in Nature, vol. 409, pp. 53–57) argue that the
tribosphenic condition evolved twice, both in the aforementioned groups and independently
in the ancestors of the monotremes (whose extant representatives are toothless); see also
T. H. Rich et al. (in Journal of Vertebrate Paleontology, vol. 22, pp. 466–469, 2002) for possible
qualification of this conclusion. The arrangement of interlocking cusps permits precise
occlusion and shearing, and not surprisingly there are further examples of convergence,
J. P. Hunter and J. Jernvall, in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA,
vol. 92, pp. 10718–10722, 1995, estimate that the evolution of an additional cusp, the
hypocone, happened more than 20 times, and regard it as a key pre-adaptation to evolutionary
success. See also J. Jernvall’s follow-up paper in the same journal (vol. 97, pp. 2641–2645,
2000).
184. See the paper by R. L. Nydam et al. in Journal of Vertebrate Paleontology, vol. 20,
pp. 628–631, 2000, although the authors are careful not to over-emphasize the rather striking
similarity. See also R. L. Nydam and R. L. Cifelli in a subsequent issue, vol. 22, pp. 276–285,
2002. A somewhat similar occurrence is also known in the living lizard Uromastyx, which
shows a dramatic change in dentition in its life as the animal moves from a diet of small
animals to plants when an adult. More unusually, the enamel of these teeth has convergently
evolved a prismatic structure, also with tubules, that is reminiscent of the mammals, but is
otherwise unknown in the reptiles; see J. S. Cooper and D. F. G. Poole in Journal of Zoology,
London, vol. 169, pp. 85–100, 1973.
185. See J. M. Clark et al. in Science, vol. 244, pp. 1064–1066, 1989, and X-C. Wu et al. in Nature,
vol. 376, pp. 678–680, 1995.
186. See O. Kuhn’s description of remarkably preserved material from the famous site at Geiseltal
in Germany, in Nova Acta Leopoldina, vol. 6 (N.F.), pp. 311–329, 1938, p. 323.
187. See P. C. Sereno et al. in Science, vol. 282, pp. 1298–1302, 1998.
188. ‘Spinosaurs as crocodile mimics’ is the title of the commentary by T. R. Holtz that
accompanies Sereno et al. (1998); see pp. 1276–1277. This ‘intriguing case of convergence’
(p. 1277) is evidently a result of a shift by this dinosaur to a piscivorous diet.
4. In The meaning of evolution: a study of the history of life and of its significance for man
(New Haven, Yale University Press, revised edition, 1967) Simpson devoted a good part of
Chapter 12 to a discussion of convergences.
5. Very similar views are expressed by E. Mayr in his essay ‘The probability of extraterrestrial
intelligent life’, reprinted on pp. 67–74 (Essay four) of Toward a new philosophy of biology:
Observations of an evolutionist (Belknap, Cambridge, MA, 1988). Mayr’s view is that for all
intents and purposes intelligence is a fluke; see his article ‘Does it pay to acquire high
intelligence?’, in Perspectives in Biology and Medicine, vol. 37, pp. 337–338, 1994. Effectively
identical sentiments were expressed in his chapter (pp. 152–156) in Extraterrestrials: Where
are they?, edited by B. Zuckerman and M. H. Hart (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge,
1995 [Second edition]).
6. This being the title of the paper in Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, vol. 950,
pp. 276–288, 2001. This article, however, seems over-concerned with the specifics of history
as against the emergence of general biological properties. This volume, entitled Cosmic
questions, and edited by J. B. Miller, has a number of other interesting chapters, notably those
by A. Case-Winters (pp. 154–168) and S. Via (pp. 225–240).
7. Simpson (1964a; see note 2 for citation), p. 774. Very similar sentiments are expressed by Carl
Sagan in his Cosmos (Macdonald, London, 1981), where he writes of those who try to imagine
extraterrestrial life that ‘They seem to me to rely too much on forms of life we already know.
Any given organism is the way it is because of a long series of individually unlikely steps. I do
not think life anywhere else would look very much like a reptile, or an insect or a human’
(p. 40). Subsequently, Sagan remarked in Scientific American, vol. 271 (4), pp. 70–77, 1994,
that given life on Earth had a single origin then ‘we have no way of knowing which aspects of
terrestrial life are necessary (required by all living things anywhere) and which are merely
contingent (the results of a particular sequence of happenstances that, had they gone
otherwise, might have led to organisms having very different properties),’ p. 71.
8. See George Beadle’s 11th Annual Arthur Dehon Little Memorial Lecture, entitled ‘The place
of genetics in modern biology’ (MIT Press, Boston, 1959).
9. G. Beadle (1959; citation is in note 8), p. 20.
10. The origins and genomic organization of the animal sodium channels are discussed by
J. D. Spafford et al. in Receptors and Channels, vol. 6, pp. 493–506, 1999.
11. Concerning the sodium pump see the paper by W. D. Stein in Philosophical Transactions of
the Royal Society of London B, vol. 349, pp. 263–269, 1995. See also R. D. Keynes and F.
Elinder in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 266, pp. 843–852,
1999.
12. See Sponges by P. R. Bergquist (London, Hutchinson, 1978), pp. 63, 67–69. Even so, sponges
possess contractile cells (the myocytes) and they evidently contain neurotransmitters; see for
example the paper by T. L. Lentz in Journal of Experimental Zoology, vol. 162, pp. 171–179,
1966. In the hexactinellids there is also indirect evidence for electrical conduction, albeit
non-nervous and probably controlled by calcium; see G. O. Mackie et al. in Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 301, pp. 401–418, 1983. For a more
general discussion of conductance in sponges see G. O. Mackie in American Zoologist,
vol. 30, pp. 907–920, 1990.
13. See the paper by C. Febvre-Chevalier et al. in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 122,
pp. 177–192, 1986. Although there is also a small calcium component, this heliozoan ‘is thus
the first exception to [the] generalization that sodium-requiring action potentials are
unknown outside the metazoan animals’ (p.189). See also the chapter by C. Febvre-Chevalier
et al. (pp. 237–253) in Evolution of the first nervous system, edited by P. A. V. Anderson
(Plenum, New York, 1990). Here the principal dependence of Actinocoryne on sodium is
regarded as ‘puzzling’ (p. 249), yet the authors also emphasize the ‘remarkable sensitivity and
contractility’ (p. 239) of this organism.
14. For an exhaustive review of ion transport mechanisms, including sodium, see M. H. Saier in
Microbiology and Molecular Biology Reviews, vol. 64, pp. 354–411, 2000.
notes to pp. 230–233 415
15. See the series of seven papers, forming a mini-review, on bacterial sodium energetics in
Journal of Bioenergetics and Biomembranes, vol. 21, pp. 633–740, 1989.
16. See the paper by D. Ren et al. in Science, vol. 294, pp. 2372–2375, 2001, and accompanying
commentary by W. A. Catterall on pp. 2306–2308.
17. See the helpful overview of ion channels and their possible phylogenies by P. A. V. Anderson
and R. M. Greenberg in Comparative Biochemistry and Physiology B, vol. 129, pp. 17–28,
2001. They support the idea that the sodium channel derived from a low voltage-activated
T-type calcium channel.
18. Concerning the origins of electrical excitability and the evolution of the sodium pump see the
article by M. Strong et al. in Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 10, pp. 221–242, 1993.
Interestingly, the bacterial sodium channel (note 16) also seems to have an evolutionary
connection to the calcium channel, but a convergent origin seems likely.
19. See the paper by S. H. Heinemann et al. in Nature, vol. 356, pp. 441–443, 1992. For other
ways of altering a sodium channel so that it allows the passage of calcium, see L. F. Santana
et al. in Science, vol. 279, pp. 1027–1033, 1998 (and the commentary by D. Hanck on p. 1004).
20. See J. D. Spafford et al. (1999; citation is in note 10), p. 494.
21. See Milton Saier’s paper in BioEssays, vol. 16, pp. 23–29, 1994.
22. M. Saier (1994; citation is in note 21), p. 28.
23. The Drake equation is given as N = R ∗ fp ne fl fi ft L, where N is the number of communicative
civilizations, R ∗ is the rate of star formation, fp is the fraction of stars possessing a planetary
system, ne is the number of planets suitable for habitation, fl is the number of planets on
which life arises, fi is the fraction of biospheres where intelligence emerges, ft is the number
of civilizations that develop advanced communication, and L is the lifetime of a civilization.
24. For an excellent account of this early attempt at SETI and much else concerning life in the
Universe see S. J. Dick’s The biological universe: the twentieth century extraterrestrial life
debate and the limits of science (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1996).
25. Leonard Ornstein’s wide-ranging and stimulating paper was published in Physics Today,
vol. 35 (March), pp. 27–31, 1982.
26. See T. F. Smith and H. J. Morowitz in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 18, pp. 265–282,
1982.
27. L. Ornstein (1982; citation is in note 25), p. 27 (his emphasis).
28. L. Ornstein (1982; citation is in note 25), p. 29.
29. The proposal put forward by Ornstein is biologically a bit muddled, but in essence argues that
both cephalopod and vertebrate eyes derive from a common ancestor, also with a camera-eye.
A corollary of this suggestion is that supposedly primitive eyes, as seen in various molluscs,
are really regressive. On present evidence this seems decidedly less likely.
30. Robert Bieri’s article ‘Huminoids on other planets?’ was published in American Scientist,
vol. 52, pp. 452–458, 1964. Bieri’s work has also caught the attention of others interested in
the wider issues of evolution and the probabilities of extraterrestrial life; see, for example,
R. Puccetti’s absorbing discussion of humanoid convergences in Persons: A study of possible
moral agents in the universe (Macmillan, London; 1968) and N. J. Berrill’s Worlds apart: a
reflection on planets, life, and time (Sidgwick & Jackson, London; 1966), especially
chapter 10 where he remarks ‘Given the right encouragement, brains and minds are as likely
a natural evolutionary creation as legs, hearts, or wings . . . Wherever life may be . . . mind will
follow.’ (p. 149). See also Michael Ruse’s Can a Darwinian be a Christian? The relationship
between science and religion (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2001), pp. 145–147.
Ruse also addresses the ideas of Simpson, noting ‘Sounding like a forerunner of Gould,
Simpson argues that it is chance and contingency all the way’, p. 147.
31. R. Bieri (1964; citation is in note 30), p. 452.
32. R. Bieri (1964; citation is in note 30), p. 457.
33. See Philip Morrison’s chapter (pp. 571–583) in Astronomical and biochemical origins and the
search for life in the universe, edited by C. B. Cosmovici et al. (Proceedings of the 5th
International Conference on Bioastronomy: Editrice Compositori, Bologna, 1997).
416 notes to pp. 233–236
34. P. Morrison (1997; citation is in note 33), p. 572. See also T. J. Grove and B. D. Sidell (in
Canadian Journal of Zoology, vol. 80, pp. 893–901, 2002), who document myoglobin
deficiency in the hearts of a variety of benthic fish of sluggish habit.
35. Interestingly, when a modification of the photosynthetic process evolves, notably emergence
of the so-called the C4 mechanism, it too shows rampant convergence, a topic which is
returned to in Chapter 10.
36. See A. Eschenmoser in Science, vol. 284, pp. 2118–2124, 1999, as well as discussion in
Chapter 2.
37. See S. J. Freeland and L. D. Hurst in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 47, pp. 238–248,
1998, as well as discussion in Chapter 1.
38. In the description of a primitive rhizodont fish from Australia, Z. Johanson and P. E. Ahlberg
(Nature, vol. 394, pp. 569–573, 1998) note how limb-like are the fins, especially in the case of
the pectoral pair, and further note ‘similarities between rhizodont fins and tetrapod limbs are
thus probably convergent’, p. 569. See also their subsequent discussion in Nature, vol. 395,
pp. 792–794, 1998, of how the tetrapods arose out of one of several similar evolutionary
experiments among the osteolepiform fish.
39. See note 81 of Chapter 6 concerning the conversion of a caecilian amphibian to the
hydrostatic equivalent of a worm.
40. Concerning the distribution of the haemoglobins see the papers by R. C. Hardison in
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 93, pp. 5675–5679, 1996 and
Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 201, pp. 1099–1117, 1998, as well as an overview in
American Scientist, vol. 87, pp. 126–137, 1999. Although emphasizing invertebrates the
review by R. E. Weber and S. N. Vinogradov in Physiological Reviews, vol. 81, pp. 569–628,
2001 is also helpful with updates of the occurrences of haemoglobin in prokaryotes and
protistans. A recent report, by S. Hou et al. (in Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, USA, vol. 98, pp. 9353–9358, 2001) explores the role of these globins in bacteria, in
the context of oxygen sensors.
41. See Our molecular nature: The body’s motors, machines and messages (Copernicus, New
York, 1996), pp. 76–77.
42. For an overview of acetylcholine as ‘a universal cell molecule’ see I. Wessler et al. in Clinical
and Experimental Pharmacology and Physiology, vol. 26, pp. 198–205, 1999.
43. Concerning the cholinergic system in the ciliate Paramecium see, for example, the papers by
F. Trielli et al. in Journal of Experimental Zoology, vol. 279, pp. 633–638, 1997 and M. U.
Delmonte Corrado et al. in Journal of Experimental Biology, vol. 204, pp. 1901–1907, 2001.
44. See D. LeRoith et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 79,
pp. 2086–2090, 1982, as well as B. Zipser et al. in Brain Research, vol. 463, pp. 296–304, 1988,
for further information on β-endorphin in the ciliate Tetrahymena. Concerning dopamine see
the papers in Biochimica et Biophysica Acta by M. E. Goldman et al. and R. E. Gunderson
and G. A. Thompson in vol. 676, pp. 221–225, 1981 and vol. 755, p. 186–194, 1983
respectively. Another neuropeptide, a somatostatin-like molecule, has been described by M.
Berelowitz et al.; see Endocrinology, vol. 110, pp. 1939–1944, 1982. The glycoprotein
choriogonadotropin, a hormone associated with mammalian pregnancy, is also reported from
the womb-free bacteria, albeit showing a much lower activity; see T. Maruo et al. in
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 76, pp. 6622–6626, 1979. A
similar occurrence is reported in yeast, see E. Loumaye et al. in Science, vol. 218,
pp. 1323–1325, 1982; in this case it is intriguing to note the peptide in yeast is responsible for
mating and the formation of the zygote.
45. Thus, signalling mechanisms involving glutamate receptors evidently evolved before the
divergence of plants and animals; see J. Chiu et al. in Molecular Biology and Evolution,
vol. 16, pp. 826–838, 1999. Signalling for disease resistance is also very primitive, given the
shared occurrence of a zinc-binding protein in protistans, plants, and animals; see K. Shirasu
et al. in Cell, vol. 99, pp. 355–366, 1999.
notes to pp. 236–239 417
61. See her paper in Journal of Experimental Zoology (Molecular Development and Evolution),
vol. 285, pp. 19–26, 1999.
62. S. F. Gilbert et al. (in Developmental Biology, vol. 173, pp. 357–372, 1996) point out that
hitherto curious examples of linked malformations, such as those affecting both limbs and
kidneys, are now more comprehensible because of shared genetic proximity early in
development.
63. Relevant papers include those by M. Koyanagi et al. in FEBS Letters, vol. 436, pp. 323–328,
1998; K. Ono et al. and H. Suga et al. respectively in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 48,
pp. 654–662 and pp. 646–653, 1999; H. Suga et al. in Gene, vol. 280, pp. 195–201, 2001; and J.
Zhang et al. in Development, vol. 128, pp. 1607–1615, 2001.
64. Citation is in note 316, Chapter 7.
65. See papers in Development by C. Walther and P. Gruss in vol. 113, pp. 1435–1449, 1991; and
T. Yamasaki et al. in vol. 128, pp. 3133–3144, 2001; see also note 317, Chapter 7.
66. Citation is in note 318, Chapter 7.
67. See L-I. Larsson et al. in Mechanisms of Development, vol. 79, pp. 153–159, 1998.
68. Citation is in note 319, Chapter 7.
69. See A. D. Chisholm and H. R. Horvitz (pp. 52–54) and Y. Zhang and S. W. Emmons (pp. 55–59)
in vol. 377 of Nature (1995).
70. See E. Saló et al. in Gene, vol. 287, pp. 67–74, 2002. See also note 320, Chapter 7.
71. See A. Cvekl and J. Piatigorsky in BioEssays, vol. 18, pp. 621–630, 1996.
72. See G. Sheng et al. in Genes & Development, vol. 11, pp. 1122–1131, 1997.
73. See, for example, G. R. Merlo et al. in International Journal of Development Biology, vol. 44,
pp. 619–626, 2000, and R. I. Schwartz and E. N. Olson in Development, vol. 126,
pp. 4187–4192, 1999.
74. See the paper by F. Loosli et al. in Mechanisms of Development, vol. 74, pp. 159–164;
1998.
75. See, for example, C. Desplan in Cell, vol. 91, pp. 861–864, 1997.
76. This unease is well articulated by E. H. Davidson and G. Ruvkun in Journal of Experimental
Zoology (Molecular Development and Evolution), vol. 285, pp. 104–115, 1999, and is taken a
bit further in a review I wrote in Cell, vol. 100, pp. 1–11, 2000.
77. See Lisa Nagy’s article in American Zoologist, vol. 38, pp. 818–828, 1998.
78. L. Nagy (1998; citation is in note 77), pp. 818–819.
79. See B. Mittmann and G. Schultz in Development, Genes and Evolution, vol. 211,
pp. 232–243, 2001.
80. See, for example, A. Simeone et al. in Current Opinion in Genetics & Development, vol. 12,
pp. 409–415, 2002.
81. See Nic Williams and Peter Holland’s article in Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 15,
pp. 600–607, 1998.
82. N. Williams and P. Holland (1998; citation is in note 81), p. 606.
83. Again and again we see that a trivial change, sometimes a single substitution of an amino
acid at a key site in a protein, can have major consequences for its function. Not surprisingly,
given this sensitivity examples of molecular convergence are more frequent than sometimes
realized. This topic is returned to in Chapter 10.
84. See the two papers in Science dealing with chimp/human immunochemistry and genes
respectively by V. M. Sarich and A. C. Wilson (vol. 158, pp. 1200–1203, 1967) and M. C. King
and A. C. Wilson (vol. 188, pp. 107–116, 1975). An overview is given by P. Gagneaux and
A. Varki in Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution, vol. 18, pp. 2–13, 2001.
85. Appropriately entitled ‘Jack of all trades’, further details of this amazing story can be found in
Nature, vol. 347, p. 704, 1990. I am most grateful also to Euan for a copy of an original
newspaper clipping from South Africa, from which some of the information is taken.
86. For an overview see the chapter (pp. 216–244) by H. J. Jerison in Handbook of intelligence,
edited by R. J. Sternberg (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2000).
notes to pp. 246–249 419
87. See H. J. Jerison’s Evolution of the brain and intelligence (Academic Press, New York, 1973),
especially his Fig. 3.6 (p. 7) and Table 10.3 (p. 219), and chapter 21 (pp. 275–283) and
Appendix 6 of J. F. Eisenberg’s The mammalian radiations: An analysis of trends in
evolution, adaptation, and behaviour (Athlone Press, London, 1981).
88. His article entitled ‘Fast tracks to intelligence (considerations from neurobiology and
evolutionary biology)’ is on pp. 237–245 of Bioastronomy – The next steps, edited by G. Marx
(Kluwer, Dordrecht, 1988). See also note 99.
89. Concerning the primates see S. M. Reader and K. N. Laland in Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 99, pp. 4436–4441, 2002. The evidence for a correlation
between brain size and behavioural flexibility in birds is given by the group led by L. Lefebvre,
see articles in Oikos, vol. 90, pp. 599–605, 2000; Behaviour, vol. 139, pp. 939–973, 2002; and
vol. 137, pp. 1415–1429, 2000; and Animal Behaviour, vol. 63, pp. 495–502, 2002.
90. Although the following section emphasizes the dolphins, it is worth mentioning that there
are other fascinating convergences. One such involves an extinct Peruvian whale, probably
related to the monodontids (beluga, narwhal), that has become strikingly convergent on the
Northern Hemisphere walrus, referred to as ‘startling’ by C. de Muizon in Nature, vol. 365,
pp. 745–748, 1993; see also C. de Muizon et al. in Comptes Rendus de l’Académie des
Sciences, Paris; Sciences de la Terre et des Planètes, vol. 329, pp. 449–455, 1999, and C. de
Muizon and D. P. Domning in Zoological Journal of the Linnean Society, vol. 134,
pp. 423–454, 2002.
91. See L. Marino in Brain, Behavior and Evolution, vol. 51, pp. 230–238, 1998.
92. See the article by L. Marino in Evolutionary Anthropology, vol. 5, pp. 81–85, 1996.
93. The section that follows owes much to L. Marino’s paper ‘Convergence of complex cognitive
abilities in cetaceans and primates’ in Brain, Behavior and Evolution, vol. 59, pp. 21–32,
2002.
94. See L. Marino et al. in Journal of Mammalian Evolution, vol. 7, pp. 81–94, 2000.
95. See, for example, the papers by J. G. M. Thewissen et al. in Nature, vol. 413, pp. 277–281,
2001, with accompanying commentaries by C. de Muizon and H. Gee on pp. 259–260 of the
same issue, and J. Gatesy and M. A. O’Leary in Trends in Ecology & Evolution, vol. 16,
pp. 562–570, 2001. Also of direct relevance is The emergence of whales: Evolutionary
patterns in the origin of Cetacea, edited by J. G. M. Thewissen (Plenum, New York, 1998).
96. Lori Marino, personal communication (03/01/02).
97. In humans the brain accounts for about 2% of the body weight, but consumes 20% of the
total metabolic energy; see J. W. Mink et al. in American Journal of Physiology, vol. 241,
pp. R202–R212, 1981 and E. Armstrong in Science, vol. 220, pp. 1302–1304, 1983.
98. In a molecular phylogeny of the cetaceans M. Nikaido et al. in Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 98, pp. 7384–7389, 2001, identify a rapid radiation of this
group at about 30 Ma, with the dolphins diversifying at about 20 Ma.
99. Thus, in sceptical vein, Calvin (1988; see note 88 for citation) remarks of the standard
Darwinian view how it is that it continues to bask in optimism, ‘And thus, in this caricature
of evolutionary thought, progress towards intelligence seems inevitable (and indeed a
soothing counter to the inevitable disorder predicted by entropy) as long as variations keep
exploring the possibilities.,’ p. 238.
100. See R. E. Fordyce in Palaeogeography, Palaeoclimatology, Palaeoecology, vol. 31,
pp. 319–336, 1980, and his chapter (pp. 368–381) on cetacean evolution in Eocene–Oligocene
climatic and biotic evolution, edited by D. R. Prothero and W. A. Berggren (Princeton
University Press, Princeton, 1992).
101. The process by which deeper, nutrient-rich waters are brought to the surface. There are
several mechanisms by which this can occur, although the most familiar is persistent wind
shear that displaces surface waters, so allowing the ascent of the deeper waters.
102. This possibility is reviewed by several authors in Paleoclimate and evolution, with emphasis
on human origins, edited by E. S. Vrba et al. (Yale University Press, New Haven, 1995). See
420 notes to pp. 249–251
also J. Chaline et al. in Special Publications of the Geological Society of London vol. 181,
pp. 185–198, 2000.
103. See the chapter by R. C. Connor et al. (pp. 415–443) in Coalitions and alliances in humans
and other animals, edited by A. H. Harcourt and F. B. M. de Waal (Oxford University Press,
Oxford, 1992), and Cetacean societies: Field studies of dolphins and whales, edited by J.
Mann et al. (University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 2000).
104. D. Reiss et al., in Trends in Cognitive Science, vol. 1, pp. 140–145, 1997, p. 141. The extent of
the convergence between dolphin and chimp societies is reviewed by R. C. Connor et al. in
their chapters (pp. 91–126 and 247–269) in Mann et al. (2000).
105. See p. 91 of R. C. Connor et al. in J. Mann et al. (2000; citation is in note 103).
106. A similar fission–fusion society is also found in the northern bottlenose whale; see p. 217 of
R. C. Connor (in J. Mann et al. 2000; citation is in note 103).
107. L. Marino (2002; citation is in note 93), p. 27.
108. See, for example, the paper by R. C. Connor et al. in Behaviour, vol. 133, pp. 37–69, 1996.
109. See B. Würsig in Biological Bulletin, vol. 154, pp. 348–359, 1978, p. 355.
110. See the paper by R. C. Connor et al. in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B,
vol. 268, 263–267, 2001.
111. Thus R. C. Connor et al. (in J. Mann et al. 2000; citation is in note 103) remark that at one
spot ‘in southern Brazil fishermen line up in murky thigh-deep water, holding weighted
throw nets, in pursuit of fish they cannot see. One or two dolphins, facing seaward several
metres offshore of the fisherman . . . come to an abrupt halt 5–7 m from the fisherman, diving
with a surging roll that cues the fisherman to toss their nets’ (p. 98). On pp. 211–212 R. C.
Connor notes similar cooperation on the coast of Mauritania.
112. See the paper by L. Weilgart et al. appropriately entitled ‘A colossal convergence’ in American
Scientist, vol. 84, pp. 278–287, 1996; see also R. C. Connor et al. in Trends in Ecology &
Evolution, vol. 13, pp. 228–232, 1998, and H. Whitehead and L. Weilgart (in J. Mann et al.
2000; citation is in note 103). This example has attracted the attention of those interested in
extraterrestrial intelligences; see P. Morrison on p. 573 of his chapter in Astronomical and
biochemical origins and the search for life in the Universe, pp. 571–583, edited by C. B.
Cosmovici et al. (Editrice Compositori, Bologna, 1997). Morrison here emphasizes the
similarities in their long-distance communication.
113. L. Weilgart et al. (1996; citation is in note 112), p. 278.
114. Concerning the long-distance communication by elephants (and some other large mammals)
see C. E. O’Connell-Rodwell et al. in American Zoologist, vol. 41, pp. 1157–1170, 2001. See
also discussion by B. T. Arnason et al. of elephants’ response to various geophysical fields in
Journal of Comparative Psychology, vol. 116, pp. 123–132, 2002.
115. H. P. Whitehead in Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 38, pp. 237–244, 1996.
116. See B. McCowan and D. Reiss on pp. 178–207 of Social influences on vocal development,
edited by C. Snowdon and M. Hausberger (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1997).
The likely importance of communication in the fission–fusion communities is emphasized
by R. A. Smolker et al. in Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 33, pp. 393–402, 1992,
and L. S. Sayigh et al. in Animal Behaviour, vol. 57, pp. 41–50, 1998, who remark ‘Overall,
what is known of bottlenose dolphin behaviour and social structure supports the idea that
individuals do have concepts of one another as individuals and that they track the history of
their individual relationships,’ p. 48.
117. See D. Reiss and B. McCowan in Journal of Comparative Psychology, vol. 107, pp. 301–312,
1993, as well as P. L. Tyack in Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 18, pp. 251–257,
1986, and D. G. Richards et al. in Journal of Comparative Psychology, vol. 98, pp. 10–28, 1984.
118. See V. M. Janik in Science, vol. 289, pp. 1355–1357, 2000, and commentary by P. L. Tyack on
pp. 1310–1311.
119. Their paper on ‘The fallacy of the signature whistle hypothesis’ (p. 1159) is published in
Animal Behaviour, vol. 62, pp. 1151–1162, 2001.
notes to pp. 251–252 421
120. This is briefly reviewed by P. L. Tyack et al. in their chapter (pp. 333–339) in J. Mann et al.
(2000; citation is in note 103).
121. Thus Tayler and Saayman in Annals of the Cape Provincial Museums (Natural History),
vol. 9, pp. 11–49, 1972 note ‘It is remarkable that our dolphins [held in the Port Elizabeth
Oceanarium] have not learned to receive or to repeat – and the latter is possible by means of
their sonar system, there being no vocal chords – the complex harmonic composition of
human Afrikaans words,’ p. 46.
122. See K. Ralls et al. in Canadian Journal of Zoology, vol. 63, pp. 1050–1056, 1985.
123. K. Ralls et al. (1985; citation is in note 122), p. 1051.
124. See the article ‘A Beluga whale imitates human speech’ by R. L. Eaton in Carnivore, vol. 2,
pp. 22–23, 1979.
125. Among aquatic mammals at least two whales (beluga, humpback) and the Harbour seal show
evidence of vocal learning; see P. L. Tyack’s chapter (pp. 270–307) on cetacean communication
in J. Mann et al. (2000; citation is in note 103). He remarks, ‘Evidence for vocal learning
among seals . . . is particularly interesting from an evolutionary perspective, because the
pinnipeds evolved from a different terrestrial ancestor than the cetaceans. This suggests that
there were at least two independent origins of vocal learning among marine mammals,’ p. 306.
126. See B. McCowan and D. Reiss in Journal of Comparative Psychology, vol. 109, pp. 242–260,
1995, and B. McCowan et al. in Animal Behaviour, vol. 57, pp. 409–419, 1999.
127. B. McCowan and D. Reiss in Ethology, vol. 100, pp. 194–209, 1995, as well as comparisons to
Zipf’s Law by McCowan et al. (1999). See also the chapter by R. C. Connor et al. (pp. 91–126)
in J. Mann et al. 2000; citation is in note 103.
128. Thus in the pygmy marmoset, a New World monkey, the young also engage in a similar
‘babbling’. See A. M. Elowson et al. and C. T. Snowdon and A. M. Elowson in Behaviour,
vol. 135, pp. 643–664, 1998, and vol. 138, pp. 1235–1248, 2001 respectively. In an overview in
Trends in Cognitive Sciences, vol. 2, pp. 31–37, 1998 A. M. Elowson et al. remark ‘social
parallels make the Callitrichids [the group that includes the pygmy marmoset] a more
compelling analogous group [to humans] to study than the phylogenetically closer, but
socially dissimilar, apes,’ p. 32.
129. See their chapter (pp. 663–680) in Phonological development: Models, research, implications,
edited by C. A. Ferguson et al. (York Press, Timonium, MA, 1992); quotation is on p. 669.
130. Quotation is on p. 253 of the chapter (pp. 253–264) by D. Reiss in Marx (1988; citation is in
note 88) entitled ‘Can we communicate with other species on this planet? (Pragmatics of
communication between humanoid and non-humanoid species)’. See also B. McCowan et al.
1999 (citation is in note 126).
131. These famous ‘songs’ are produced only by the male. P. M. Gray et al. (2001; citation is in
note 171, Chapter 8) remark, ‘The undersea songs of humpback whales are similar in
structure to bird and human songs and prove that these marine mammals are inveterate
composers . . . humpback whale songs are constructed according to laws that are strikingly
similar to those adopted by human composers,’ p. 52.
132. Thus P. M. Gray et al. (2001; citation is in note 171, Chapter 8) comment ‘Is there a universal
music [as part of Mathematical Platonism] awaiting discovery, or is all music just a construct
of whatever mind is making it, human, bird, whale? The similarities among human music,
bird song, and whale song tempt one to speculate that the Platonic alternative may exist –
that there is a universal music awaiting discovery,’ p. 54.
133. The paper on ‘Comprehension of sentences by bottle-nosed dolphins’ is by L. M. Herman
et al., and is published in Cognition, vol. 16, pp. 129–219, 1984, while in Journal of
Experimental Psychology: General, vol. 122, pp. 184–194, 1993, L. M. Herman et al. report
responses by dolphins to syntactically anomalous sequences. In the same year L. M. Herman
et al. published a parallel paper, as Chapter 20 (pp. 403–442) in Language and
communication: Comparative perspectives, edited by H. L. Roitblat et al. (Lawrence Erlbaum
Associates, Hillsdale, NJ, 1993), where they remarked that it appeared that dolphins can
422 notes to pp. 252–254
generate ‘a mental representation of the grammatical structure of their language’ (p. 408) in a
way directly analogous to humans who when presented with grammatical novelties in an
artificial language are then in a position to decode other novel strings to at least a reasonable
degree of accuracy.
134. See L. M. Herman et al. in Animal Learning and Behavior, vol. 29, pp. 250–264, 2001.
135. L. Marino (2002, citation is in note 93), p. 28.
136. In a more general review on the evolution of intelligence E. MacPhail and J. J. Bolhuis, in
Biological Reviews, vol. 76, pp. 341–364, 2001, remark ‘that there are no qualitative
differences in cognition between animal species in the processes of learning and memory’
(p. 341). Interestingly, they also conclude that human language is a unique attribute,
concluding, ‘Unlike Darwin, we believe that there is a qualitative difference between human
and non-human intelligence; but we know of no convincing evidence that language evolved
to “solve” some novel “problem” posed by a niche invaded by an initially pre-linguistic
ancestor, nor any analysis of that niche’s demands that promises to throw light on the
mechanisms of language,’ p. 361.
137. See the discussion by E. Kako in Animal Behavior and Learning, vol. 27, pp. 1–14, 1999,
where he also addresses the question, in a moderately sceptical tone, of similar
comprehension by African Grey parrots and chimps. The response, on pp. 18–23, by L. M.
Herman and R. K. Uyeyama on the grammatical competency of bottlenose dolphins is an apt
counterpoint to Kako’s paper, to which he replies (pp. 26–27). The cases for African Grey
parrots and chimps are put forward respectively by I. M. Pepperberg (pp. 15–17) and S. G.
Shanker et al. (pp. 24–25).
138. Nor should we forget other attributes in birds such as tool-making (notes 176–178), and
remarkable accounts of coordinated hunting, such as in pied currawongs summoning
assistance to dispatch a rat; see M. G. O’Neill and R. J. Taylor in Corella, vol. 8l, pp. 95–96,
1984.
139. A point stressed by both I. M. Pepperberg (1999) and L. M. Herman and R. K. Uyeyama
(1999).
140. See the paper ‘Evolution of a universal grammar’ by M. A. Nowak et al., in Science, vol. 291,
pp. 114–118, 2001. B. McCowan et al. (in Journal of Comparative Psychology, vol. 116,
pp. 166–172, 2002) emphasize basic similarities in Zipf’s coefficient (see note 5, Chapter 1)
and Shannon’s measure of entropy between human words, bottlenose whistles, and squirrel
monkey calls at different stages of development. In each case communication has arisen for
specific adaptational reasons, but it is also convergent.
141. See R. K. Thompson and L. M. Herman in Science, vol. 195, pp. 501–503, 1977.
142. See E. Mercado et al. in Animal Learning & Behavior, vol. 26, pp. 210–218, 1998.
143. Their paper is in Journal of Experiment Psychology: General, vol. 124, pp. 391–408, 1995;
quotation is on p. 391.
144. ‘Half-awake to the risk of predation’ is the title of the paper by N. C. Rattenborg et al. in
Nature, vol. 397, pp. 397–398, 1999; a more general review of unihemispheric sleep in birds
(as well as cetaceans and some other marine mammals) is given by the same group in
Neuroscience and Biobehavioural Reviews, vol. 24, pp. 817–842, 2000. The origins of such
sleep may lie deeper than the birds, as some evidence suggests equivalent states in the
reptiles. Its evolution in two or three groups of marine mammals (and possibly the elephants,
p. 833), however, is almost certainly independent and regained from primitive Mesozoic
mammals that may have lost this ability when their mode of life was largely nocturnal and/or
burrowing.
145. See the paper by P. D. Goley in Marine Mammal Sciences, vol. 15, pp. 1054–1064, 1999, as
well as Rattenborg et al. (2000).
146. As reported by H. Elias and P. Swartz in Science, vol. 166, pp. 111–113, 1969; see also Jerison
(2000; citation is in note 86, pp. 222–223).
147. See L. Marino et al. in Brain, Behavior and Evolution, vol. 56, pp. 204–211, 2000.
notes to pp. 256–259 423
148. Thus in assessing the question of convergences in the dolphin brain, with the subtitle ‘Does
evolutionary history repeat itself?’ P. Manger et al. (in Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience,
vol. 10, pp. 153–166, 1998) emphasize how both the modularity of the brain and the
underlying constraints of neural architecture may lead to similar end points.
149. Helpful summaries are given by L. Marino (1996, 2002; see notes 92 and 93 for citations). See
also L. Marino et al. in Anatomical Record, vol. 264, pp. 397–414, 2001. Other key references
are by P. J. Morgane et al. in Brain Research Bulletin, vol. 5 (Supplement 3), pp. 1–107, 1980,
and I. I. Glezer et al. in Behavioral and Brain Sciences, vol. 11, pp. 75–89 (and succeeding
discussion on pp. 89–116), 1988.
150. L. Marino (2002, citation is in note 93), p. 24.
151. See L. Marino (1996; citation is in note 92), pp. 84–85.
152. L. Marino (2002; citation is in note 93), p. 25.
153. See the paper on the scalable architecture of mammal brains by D. A. Clark et al. in Nature,
vol. 411, pp. 189–193, 2001, as well as the commentary by J. H. Kaas and C. E. Collins on
pp. 141–142.
154. L. Marino (2002, citation is in note 93), p. 25.
155. See, for example, the paper on mosaic evolution of brain structure in mammals by R. A.
Barton and P. H. Harvey in Nature, vol. 405, pp. 1055–1058, 2000. The thrust of their
argument is that the mosaic evolution of the brain, with emphasis on those sections, e.g.
neocortex, that are functionally significant, will transcend developmental constraints.
156. See I. I. Glezer et al. on pp. 1–38 of Marine mammal sensory systems, edited by J. A. Thomas
et al. (Plenum, New York, 1992).
157. See the paper by B. McCowan et al. in Journal of Comparative Psychology, vol. 114,
pp. 98–106, 2000.
158. See the two chapters in the book Self-awareness in animals and humans: Developmental
perspectives, edited by S. T. Parker et al. (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1994),
respectively by K. Marten and S. Psarakos (pp. 361–379) and L. Marino et al. (pp. 380–391).
159. See D. Reiss and L. Marino in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA,
vol. 98, pp. 5937–5942, 2001.
160. D. Reiss and L. Marino (2001; citation is in note 159), p. 5942.
161. See, for example, L. von Ferson et al. on pp. 753–762 in Thomas et al. (1992; see note 156 for
citation), and also B. McCowan et al. (2000; citation is in note 157).
162. Particular attention has been paid to the killer whales (see, for example, J. K. B. Ford in
Canadian Journal of Zoology, vol. 69, pp. 1454–1483, 1991, and more recently P. J. O. Miller
and D. E. Bain in Animal Behaviour, vol. 60, pp. 617–628, 2000), as well as the sperm-whales
(see L. Weilgart and H. Whitehead in Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 40,
pp. 277–285, 1997). Information on elephant seals and Weddell seals can be found in papers in
Animal Behaviour, vol. 22, pp. 656–663, 1974 by B. J. Le Boeuf and L. F. Petrinovich (elephant
seals) and Canadian Journal of Zoology, vol. 61, pp. 2203–2214, 1984 by J. A. Thomas and I.
Stirling (Weddell seals).
163. The extent to which birds can be said to have cultural attributes is another fascinating (and
contentious) topic; the brief remarks (pp. 341–342) by S. K. Lynn and I. M. Pepperberg in L.
Rendell and H. Whitehead (2001, citation is in 164) are a forceful plea to take some birds as
seriously as killer whales and humans. The existence of dialects is also well known. T. F.
Wright and G. S. Wilkinson, in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 268,
pp. 609–616, 2001, present evidence in a parrot, the Yellow-naped Amazon, for emergence of
dialects despite gene flow between populations. See also P. Enggist-Dueblin and U. Pfister in
Animal Behaviour, vol. 64, pp. 831–841, 2002.
164. Key papers are those by H. Whitehead in Science, vol. 282, pp. 1708–1711, 1998 (with a
commentary by G. Vogel on p. 1616); V.-B. Deecke et al. in Animal Behaviour, vol. 60,
pp. 629–638, 2000, and L. Rendell and H. Whitehead in Behavioral and Brain Sciences,
vol. 24, pp. 309–382, 2001 (which includes a series of commentaries and critiques) and
424 notes to pp. 259–262
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 270, p. 225–231, 2003. Vertical cultural
transmission in stable matrilineal groups is reviewed by H. Whitehead and J. Mann in their
chapter (pp. 219–246) on female reproductive strategies in J. Mann et al. (2000; citation is in
note 103) where they comment: ‘it seems possible that cetacean societies . . . such as those of
killer, sperm, and pilot whales, contain cultures that are qualitatively more similar to human
cultures than are those of most terrestrial mammals . . . [and] may therefore explain curious
attributes of these species, such as nonadaptive mass strandings, low genetic diversity, and
menopause,’ pp. 243–244.
165. See H. Whitehead and J. Mann in J. Mann et al. (2000; citation is in note 103), pp. 219–246,
who remark, ‘It is notable that the cetacean species in which menopause has been found,
pilot and killer whales, possess matrilineally based social systems. There is some evidence
that cultural processes are very important within the matrilineal groups of these animals . . .
If an older female’s role as a source of information significantly increases her descendants’
fitness, and reproduction towards the end of her life decreases survival, menopause could be
adaptive,’ p. 233.
166. See K. McComb et al. in Science, vol. 292, pp. 491–494, 2001, as well as the commentary by
E. Pennisi on pp. 417–418.
167. Moreover, as Whitehead and Weilgart (2000; citation is in note 112) note, ‘Evidence is
beginning to accumulate that sperm whale units have distinctive vertically transmitted
cultures: functionally important information learned maternally or within matrilineal units.
Units have characteristic coda repertoires, which are unlikely to be genetically determined,’
p. 169.
168. Whitehead and Weilgart (2000) remind us the sperm whale ‘was the subject of two massive
hunts. The first of these, peaking in about 1840, greatly reduced sperm whale populations
throughout the world . . . while providing the oil that lubricated the Industrial Revolution’
(p. 155), while in the 1960s more than 20 000 a year were killed.
169. Their paper is published in Animal Behaviour, vol. 60, pp. 617–628, 2000.
170. Miller and Bain (2000), p. 626.
171. ‘Cultural revolution in whale songs’ is the title of the paper by M. J. Noad et al. in Nature,
vol. 408, p. 537, 2000.
172. For this, the first report of tool use by dolphins, see the paper by R. Smolker et al. in Ethology,
vol. 103, pp. 454–464, 1997.
173. This ‘bubble-feeding’ is reviewed by P. J. Clapham in his chapter (pp. 173–196) on the
humpback whale in J. Mann et al. (2000; citation is in note 103). There is also some
suggestion that unweaned calves blowing small bubble-clouds next to their feeding mothers
may be learning the technique.
174. His book is entitled Nature’s destiny: How the laws of biology reveal purpose in the Universe
(The Free Press, New York, 1998); see his Chapter 11. Denton’s work shows a number of
valuable parallels to this book but Nature’s destiny has, however, a distinct anti-evolutionary
bias (see my review ‘Awe, wonder and gene committees’ in the Times Higher Education
Supplement, p. 25 of the December 24/31, 1999 issue).
175. See, for example, J. Boswall in Avicultural Magazine, vol. 89, pp. 94–108 and 170–181, 1983.
176. See G. R. Hunt in Nature, vol. 379, pp. 249–251, 1996 (with commentary by C. Boesch on
pp. 207–208), and Emu, vol. 100, pp. 109–114, 2000 and vol. 102, pp. 349–353, 2002.
177. See also the report of hook manufacture in laboratory-kept New Caledonian crows by
A. A. S. Weir et al. in Science, vol. 297, p. 981, 2002.
178. Concerning this, see G. R. Hunt in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 267,
pp. 403–413, 1999, and G. R. Hunt et al. in Nature, vol. 414, p. 707, 2001.
179. G. R. Hunt (1999; citation is in note 178), p. 412. See also G. R. Hunt and R. D. Gray in
Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 270, pp. 867–874, 2003.
180. See I. M. Pepperberg’s The Alex studies: cognitive and communicative abilities of Grey
Parrots (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1999).
notes to pp. 262–263 425
181. See C. Caffrey in The Wilson Bulletin, vol. 112, pp. 283–284, 2000 and vol. 113, pp. 114–115,
2001.
182. See The use of tools by human and non-human primates, edited by A. Berthelet and J.
Chavaillon (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1993), especially the chapters by C. Boesch and H.
Boesch (pp. 158–174) and Y. Sugiyama (pp. 175–190), and also W. M. McGrew’s Chimpanzee
material culture: Implications for human evolution (Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 1992).
183. See N. Toth et al. in Journal of Archaeological Science, vol. 20, pp. 81–91, 1993.
184. N. Toth et al. (1993; citation is in note 183), p. 89.
185. See W. C. McGrew in Science, vol. 288, p. 1747, 2000.
186. See T. S. Stoinski and B. B. Beck in Primates, vol. 42, pp. 319–326, 2001.
187. See, for example, G. C. Westergaard and S. J. Suomi in Current Anthropology, vol. 35,
pp. 75–79 and pp. 468–470, 1994; International Journal of Primatology, vol. 16,
pp. 1017–1024, 1995; and Journal of Archaeological Sciences, vol. 22, pp. 677–681, 1995; as
well as E. Visalberghi on pp. 118–135 of A. Berthelet and J. Chavaillon (1993; citation is in
note 182). In addition, as an extension of S. M. Reader and K. N. Laland (2002; citation is in
note 89), S. M. Reader has looked at plots of behavioural plasticity among the primates,
including tool use. Here too, with chimp and bonobo Cebus stands out. See his paper in
Towards a biology of traditions: models and evidence, edited by D. Fragaszy and S. Perry
(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, in press).
188. See S. Chevalier-Skolnikoff in Behavioral and Brain Sciences, vol. 12, pp. 561–627,
1989.
189. See G. C. Westergaard and S. J. Suomi in Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 27, pp. 399–404,
1994.
190. G. C. Westergaard and S. J. Suomi (1994; citation is in note 189), p. 403.
191. See their paper in Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 6, pp. 623–641, 1977, see p. 634.
192. See Gregory Westergaard and colleagues’ paper in International Journal of Primatology,
vol. 20, pp. 153–162, 1999.
193. G. C. Westergaard et al. (1999; citation is in note 192), p. 161.
194. See S. Chevalier-Skolnikoff in Primates, vol. 31, pp. 375–383, 1990. K. A. Phillips (in
American Journal of Primatology, vol. 46, pp. 259–261, 1998) reports the use of ‘leaves as
cups to retrieve water from tree cavities’, p. 259.
195. E. Visalberghi (1993; citation is in note 187; see also note 182), see pp. 127–128.
196. The nature of the food resources may also be important; see M. A. Panger in American
Journal of Physical Anthropology, vol. 106, pp. 311–321, 1998.
197. See G. C. Westergaard and S. J. Suomi in Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 30, pp. 291–298,
1996.
198. G. C. Westergaard and S. J. Suomi (1996; citation is in note 197), p. 296.
199. See E. Visalberghi and L. Limongelli in their chapter (pp. 57–79) of Reaching into thought:
The minds of the great apes, edited by A. E. Russon et al. (Cambridge University Press,
Cambridge, 1996). Capuchins in the context of primate mentalities are reviewed by R. Byrne
in his chapter (pp. 110–124) in Creativity in human evolution and prehistory, edited by S.
Mithen (Routledge, London, 1998).
200. E. Jalles-Filho et al., in Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 40, pp. 365–377, 2001. They point
out that there may be cognitive limits that militate against such key activities as carrying the
tools to the food, although this may also be a consequence of a social structure whereby
access to food is largely controlled by aggression. Hence it makes little sense to wander off
looking for a suitable tool and leave the food unattended. However, food and tool exchanges
are known; see G. C. Westergaard and S. J. Suomi in American Journal of Primatology,
vol. 43, pp. 33–41, 1997, where they note, ‘we propose that tool- and food-sharing came into
existence through convergent evolution in large-brained, extractive foraging primate genera,
including Cebus, Pan and Homo’ (p. 40).
426 notes to pp. 263–267
201. See S. W. Williston, in Entomological News and Proceedings of the Entomological Section of
the Academy of Natural Sciences of Philadelphia, vol. 3, pp. 85–86, 1892.
202. S. W. Williston (1892; citation is in note 201), pp. 85–86.
203. For a review of parallel homoplasies in the mammalian neocortex, see R. G. Northcutt and
J. H. Kaas in Trends in Neurosciences, vol. 18, pp. 373–379, 1995.
204. Willem de Winter and Charles Oxnard’s paper is published in Nature, vol. 409, pp. 710–714,
2001.
205. The essay, by Thomas Nagel, entitled ‘What it is like to be a bat’, may be found in The
Philosophical Review, vol. 83, pp. 433–450, 1974.
206. T. Nagel (1974; citation is in note 205), p. 438.
207. T. Nagel (1974; citation is in note 204), pp. 439–440.
208. A similar point is made by R. Dawkins on pp. 33–35 The blind watchmaker (Norton, New
York, 1987) The emergence of novel functions in brain evolution in the context of
convergence is well addressed by K. C. Nishikawa (in Bioscience, vol. 47, pp. 341–354, 1997).
Thus he writes, ‘Convergent evolution of neural circuits that serve similar functions may
provide insights into the functional architecture of nervous systems. For example, features
such as parallel, distributed processing and population coding (in which a signal is encoded in
the activity of a population of neurons instead of a single cell) have evolved convergently in
distantly related species throughout the animal kingdom; these features likely represent
analogous solutions to similar problems in different animals,’ p. 342.
209. T. Nagel (1974; citation is in note 204), p. 441.
210. See U. M. Norberg and M. B. Fenton in Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, vol. 33,
pp. 383–394, 1988.
211. Concerning this, see the convergent evolution of trichromacy (Chapter 7, notes 122–124) and
the enzyme lysozyme (Chapter 10, notes 88, 89).
212. W. de Winter and C. Oxnard (2001, citation in note 204), pp. 713–714. Similar conclusions
were reached by F-J. Lapointe et al. (in Brain, Behavior and Evolution, vol. 54, pp. 119–126,
1999) where they noted ‘obvious adaptive convergences of the brain to trophic niches . . . one
could clearly distinguish a folivorous, an insectivorous/carnivorous, and a frugivorous/
nectarivorous clade based on size-corrected brain data,’ p. 122.
213. See also the example of convergence in echolocation between a Neotropical species of Myotis
and the temperate pipistrellids by M. Siemers et al. in Behavioural Ecology and Sociobiology,
vol. 50, pp. 317–328, 2001, who emphasize evolutionary flexibility over phylogenetic
constraint in response to particular ecological challenges.
214. See L. Krubitzer’s discussion of convergences in the mammalian neocortex in Trends in
Neurosciences, vol. 18, pp. 408–417, 1995.
215. L. Krubitzer (1995; citation is in note 214), p. 416.
216. The convergence between locomotory gaits of primates and the South American didelphid
Caluromys (the woolly opossum) is addressed by D. Schmitt and P. Lemelin in American
Journal of Physical Anthropology, vol. 118, pp. 231–238, 2002, and thus reinforces the various
other convergences already noted between this marsupial and the prosimian primates; see, for
example, P. Lemelin in Journal of Zoology, vol. 247, pp. 165–175, 1999 and D. T. Rasmussen
in American Journal of Primatology, vol. 22, pp. 263–277, 1990.
217. See the paper by J. G. Fleagle in Folia Primatologica, vol. 26, pp. 245–269, 1976.
218. J. C. Fleagle (1976; citation is in note 217), p. 264.
219. These are the platyrrhines, and include the capuchins (Cebus), the spider monkeys (Ateles),
the howlers (Alouatta), marmosets (Callithrix), and owl monkeys (Aotus); see M. Moynihan’s
The New World primates; Adaptive radiation and the evolution of social behavior,
languages, and intelligence (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1976). These monkeys
evidently represent invaders from the Old World, arriving about 30 Ma ago (see R. F. Kay et al.
in Journal of Vertebrate Paleontology, vol. 18, pp. 189–199, 1998), most probably by rafting
across the Atlantic from Africa; see A. Houle in American Journal of Physical Anthropology,
notes to pp. 267–269 427
vol. 109, pp. 541–559, 1999. Concerning their interrelationships, see I. Horowitz and A.
Meyer on pp. 189–224 of Molecular evolution and adaptive radiation, edited by T. J. Givnish
and K. J. Sytsma (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1997) and I. Horovitz in American
Museum Novitates, no. 3269, pp. 1–40, 1999, with inclusion of more fossil taxa. The
present-day fauna may be markedly impoverished in comparison to the fossil diversity. W. C.
Hartwig and C. Cartelle describe (in Nature, vol. 381, pp. 307–311, 1996) a giant Pleistocene
Brazilian monkey (Protopithecus) with a rather puzzling mixture of howler monkey-like
(cranial) and spider monkey-like (postcranial) anatomy.
220. See the papers in Folia Primatologica by R. A. Mittermeier in vol. 30, pp. 161–193, 1978, and
J. G. H. Cant in vol. 46, pp. 1–14, 1986. Concerning convergent evolution within the ateline
monkeys see C. A. Lockwood in American Journal of Physical Anthropology, vol. 108,
pp. 459–482, 1999. This paper is important, not only because of its implications for
convergence with the Old World apes, but also because of Lockwood’s emphases on the
importance of adaptation (Chapter 10, note 1) and the difficulty of discerning a reliable
phylogenetic signal in the face of rampant convergence. The evolutionary position of the New
World monkeys (platyrrhines) in the general scheme of primate phylogenies is addressed by
S. M. Ford on pp. 595–673 of Anthropoid origins, edited by J. G. Fleagle et al. (Plenum, New
York; 1994). She notes that the ancestral form was very generalized, readily diversified in a
number of directions, and that ‘The hominoids, in particular, and Pliopithecus [a Miocene
primate], demonstrate numerous convergences with atelines’ (p. 656); see also D. R. Begun in
Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 24, pp. 373–402, 1993.
221. See D. A. Clark et al. (2001; citation is in note 153), where they note that ‘neocortical volume
fractions have become successively larger in lemurs and lorises, New World monkeys, Old
World monkeys, and hominoids, lending support to the idea that primate brain architecture
has been driven by directed selective pressure,’ p.189.
222. Details of the convergences (and divergences) between atelines (and capuchins and squirrel
monkeys) with Old World primates is given by J. G. Robinson and C. H. Janson (pp. 69–82) in
Primate Societies, edited by B. B. Smuts et al. (University of Chicago Press, Chicago; 1987),
see pp. 80–82. A more general overview of convergences and divergences is in the chapter
(pp. 158–170) by P. M. Kappeler in Primate communities, edited by J. G. Fleagle et al.
(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1999).
223. See the paper by C. A. Chapman et al. in Behavioral Ecology and Sociobiology, vol. 36,
pp. 59–70, 1995. Quotation is on p. 59. These workers are careful to point out that the
similarities, while strong, are not precise.
224. M. Moynihan (1976, citation is in note 219); quotations on pp. 107 and 108
respectively.
225. Thus G. C. Westergaard and S. J. Suomi (1999; citation is in note 192) draw attention to
bipedalism in capuchin monkeys, interestingly in connection with food loads.
226. One of the curiosities of tool use in the primates is that given they are all pretty intelligent,
then why is the employment of tools so sporadic? Thus W. C. McGrew has observed that ‘All
great apes are smart enough to use tools but they only do so in useful circumstances’, see
p. 470 of his chapter (pp. 457–472) in Comparative socioecology: The behavioural ecology of
humans and other mammals, edited by V. Standen and R. A. Foley (Blackwell, Oxford, 1989).
And these ‘useful circumstances’ seem to be best correlated with access to animal material, a
point returned to in his chapter (pp. 143–157) in A. Berthelet and J. Chavaillon (1993; citation
is in note 182).
227. See the paper by F. Spoor et al. in Nature, vol. 369, pp. 645–648, 1994, as well as further
discussion in Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 30, pp. 183–187, 1996. The crux of their
argument involves the structure of the vestibular system (semicircular canals) of the inner
ear, which in the obligatory bipeds has to be very finely tuned to permit balance (not least on
a bicycle). They conclude that bipedality was less well developed in early hominids, but
certainly present by Homo erectus times.
428 notes to pp. 269–270
228. See P. E. Wheeler in Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 13, pp. 91–98, 1984, vol. 14, pp. 23–28,
1985, vol. 21, pp. 107–116 and 117–136, 1991, and vol. 23, pp. 379–388, 1992. A critique of
some of these ideas is presented by L. Q. Amaral in vol. 30, pp. 357–366, 1996.
229. For an overview, see A. Gibbons in Science, vol. 295, pp. 1214–1219, 2002.
230. B. Wood in Nature, vol. 418, pp. 145–151, 2002.
231. B. Wood (2002; citation is in note 230), p. 134.
232. Dating of the beds that yield Oreopithecus is reported by L. Rook et al. in Journal of Human
Evolution, vol. 39, pp. 577–582, 2000.
233. The phylogenetic position of this animal is difficult to resolve on account of its peculiar
anatomy. S. Moyà Solà and M. Köhler, in Comptes Rendus de l’Académie des Sciences, Paris,
vol. 324 (Ser. IIa), pp. 141–148, 1997, place Oreopithecus close to such apes as Dryopithecus.
On the other hand T. Harrison and L. Rook in their chapter (pp. 327–362) in Function,
phylogeny and fossils: Miocene hominoid evolution and adaptations, edited by D. R. Begun
et al. (Plenum, New York, 1997), tentatively conclude that Oreopithecus is very close to, if
not actually, a hominid, but they emphasize also specific features that make convergence an
alternative possibility; see also E. E. Sarmiento in American Museum Novitates, no. 2881,
pp. 1–44, 1987.
234. See R. L. Bernor et al. in Bollettino della Società Paleontologia Italiana, vol. 40, pp. 139–148,
2001.
235. See M. Köhler and S. Moyà-Solà in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA,
vol. 94, pp. 11747–11750, 1997.
236. M. Köhler and S. Moyà-Solà (1997; citation is in note 235), p. 11747.
237. See L. Rook et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 96,
pp. 8795–8799, 1999, which examines the bone structure of the hip bone known as the iliac,
and specifically the cancellous bone architecture that orientates itself according to the
prevailing stress regime, which is characteristic for bipedal activity.
238. See S. Moyà-Solà et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 96,
pp. 313–317, 1999, where they remark ‘The functional resemblances with the
australopithecine pattern suggests for Oreopithecus similar manipulative skills, with
improved finger control and the capability to hold objects securely and steadily between the
pads of thumb and index finger . . . This strongly suggests that the hand morphology of
Oreopithecus is derived for apes and convergent with that of early hominids,’ p. 316.
239. See M. Köhler and S. Moyà-Solà (1997, citation is in note 235). They remark ‘insular
ecosystems . . . are characterized by lack of predators and limitation of space and thus of
trophic resources . . . Whereas the absence of predation removes the need for adaptations
related to predator avoidance, intraspecific and interspecific competition for food resources
increases . . . Both factors impose specific selective pressures that favor . . . adaptations . . .
related to energetically less expensive locomotor activities . . . and to reduction of bone mass
in the locomotor apparatus at the expense of mobility and speed. On the other hand they
select for feeding strategies that increase the efficiency of resource utilization . . . These
adaptations are universally found in all mammal faunas of small islands. These selective
pressures probably played a crucial role in the evolution of Oreopithecus . . . the lack of
predators may have led to a decrease of energetically expensive . . . and risky . . . climbing
activities, while favoring significant terrestriality’ (pp. 11749–11750). Some support for this
also comes from the reduction in canine size. As D. M. Alba et al. (in Journal of Human
Evolution, vol. 40, pp. 1–16, 2001) discuss whether this decrease could represent diminished
levels of agonistic behaviour, especially in the males, itself a reflection of the relaxation of
selective pressures that result from insularity and the absence of predators.
240. Being marooned on islands has other evolutionary consequences. Such environments, most
famously in the case of the Galápagos and Hawaiian island chain, have long been famous as
natural evolutionary ‘laboratories’. Indeed, while the island habitat is a rich source of
evolutionary novelty, so, too, are they of convergence. The mammal-like kiwis and mice-like
notes to pp. 270–273 429
wetas of New Zealand (Chapter 8) are splendid examples. Island faunas show other types of
convergence, of which one of the most fascinating examples is how big animals get small, and
small animals big. Thus, in the various Mediterranean islands, for example, the fossil record
shows dwarf elephants (a metre high and weighing little more than a large human) and
hippopotamuses, along with mice the size of rabbits. For a further discussion of this topic, see
for example, the papers by P. Y. Sondaar on pp. 671–707 of Major patterns of vertebrate
evolution, edited by M. K. Hecht et al. (New York, Plenum, 1977); L. R. Heaney in Evolution,
vol. 32, pp. 29–44, 1978; M.V. Lomolino in American Naturalist, vol. 125, pp. 310–316, 1985;
V. L. Roth in Oxford Surveys in Evolutionary Biology, vol. 8, pp. 259–288, 1992; and J.
Damuth in Nature, vol. 365, pp. 748–750, 1993.
241. Part of the problem of assigning an appropriate phylogenetic position (citation is in note 233)
is the substantial modification of the skull that shows Oreopithecus had a jaw structure and
teeth consistent with it being a dynamic vegetarian.
242. The origin of skilled forelimb movement is reviewed by A. N. Iwaniuk and I. Q. Whishaw in
Trends in Neurosciences, vol. 23, pp. 372–376, 2000. They produce an impressive catalogue of
examples, and argue that these manipulative abilities are primitive and drawn upon by
various tetrapod vertebrates as and when appropriate.
243. Enthusiasts for the intriguing ‘aquatic ape’ hypothesis, originally put forward by Alister
Hardy and revived by Elaine Morgan, may find an echo in this idea of an insular origination.
244. See M. G. Leakey et al. in Nature, vol. 410, pp. 433–440, 2001, with a thoughtful commentary
on pp. 419–420 by D. E. Lieberman. Interestingly, in discussing where best to place this fossil,
Lieberman remarks ‘At present, it is hard to believe any reconstruction of hominin
relationships because of the abundance of independently evolved similarities in the hominin
fossil record. The complex mosaic of features seen in the new fossil will only exacerbate the
problem’ (p. 419).
245. See M. Brunet et al. in Nature, vol. 418, pp. 145–151, 2002; see also note 229.
246. See B. Senut et al. in Comptes Rendus de l’Académie des Sciences, Paris, Sciences de la Terre
et des Planètes, vol. 332, pp. 137–144, 2001. See also the commentary on both Kenyanthropus
and Orrorin by L. E. Aiello and M. Collard in Nature, vol. 410, pp. 526–527, 2001.
247. The importance of homoplasy in hominid evolution is addressed by H. M. McHenry and L. R.
Berger in Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 35, pp. 1–22, 1998.
248. Robust convergence is documented by R. R. Skelton and H. M. McHenry in Journal of
Human Evolution, vol. 23, pp. 309–349, 1992. They remark that a robust chewing habit also
emerged in a number of extinct primates, including the Madagascan Hadropithecus, and
Gigantopithecus, apparently as adaptations to xeric (i.e. desert) vegetation.
249. See Rob Foley’s commentary on Skelton and McHenry (1992), published in Trends in
Evolution & Ecology, vol. 8, pp. 196–197, 1993.
250. R. Foley (1993; citation is in note 249), p. 196.
251. See pp. 31–42 of Structure and contingency: Evolutionary processes in life and human
society, edited by J. Bintliff (Leicester University Press, London, 1999).
252. R. Foley (1999; citation is in note 249), p. 40.
253. R. Foley (1999; citation is in note 249), p. 36.
254. R. Foley (1999; citation is in note 249), pp. 40–41.
255. See the paper by S. Semaw et al. in Nature, vol. 385, pp. 333–336, 1997 with accompanying
commentary by B. A. Wood on pp. 292–293, as well as S. Semaw in Journal of Archaeological
Science, vol. 27, pp. 1197–1214, 2000, where he suggests that the oldest of the artefacts may
have been made by an australopithecine species (A. garhi).
256. See H. Roche et al. in Nature, vol. 399, pp. 57–60, 1999 (with an accompanying review by J.
Steele on pp. 24–25). Although written before these important discoveries were made an
interesting overview of the earliest hominid stone cultures is given by J. W. K. Harris and
S. D. Capaldo on pp. 196–220 of Berthelet and Chavaillon (1993; citation is in note 182).
While the vast bulk of our understanding of early hominid technology is based on lithic
430 notes to pp. 273–274
material, evidence dating back to c. 1.8 Ma suggests that bone tools were being used for
termite foraging; see L. R. Backwell and F. d’Errico in Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences, USA, vol. 98, pp. 1358–1363, 2001, with commentary by P. Shipman on pp. 1335–
1337.
257. Fragmentary remains of early hominids and frequently complex cave stratigraphies with
recurrent roof falls make definitive conclusions difficult, not to mention that rather too
seldom is a skeleton found grasping a stone tool. Even so, K. Kuman and R. J. Clarke, in
Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 38, pp. 827–847, 2000, present evidence for tool-making by
late (c. 2 Ma) Paranthropus. Somewhat older evidence for use of tools is given by T. R.
Pickering et al. in American Journal of Physical Anthropology, vol. 111, pp. 579–584, 2000.
Substantially older finds, from about 2.5 Ma ago, include bones with cut marks and percussive
damage that are almost certainly the product of intentional fleshing and marrow extraction.
Whether, however, these activities were at the hands of early Homo or australopithecines is
not known; see J. de Heinzelin et al. in Science, vol. 284, pp. 625–629, 1999.
258. See S. Elton et al. in Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 41, pp. 1–27, 2001.
259. S. Elton et al. (2001; citation is in note 258), pp. 23–24.
260. D. E. Lieberman et al. in Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 30, pp. 97–120, 1996.
261. D. E. Lieberman et al. (1996; citation is in note 260), p. 115.
262. See Gerrit van Vark’s paper in Perspectives in Human Biology, vol. 4, pp. 237–243, 1999.
263. G. van Vark (1999; citation is in note 262), p. 241.
264. See, however, H. Roche et al. (1999; citation is in note 256), who question the notion of
technological stasis in very early tool material; see also Semaw (2000; citation is in note 255)
for a somewhat different view (p. 1209).
265. See H. Thieme in Nature, vol. 385, pp. 807–810, 1997; and commentary by R. Dennell on
pp. 767–768.
266. A useful overview concerning the difficulties in establishing the use of fire by ancient
hominids is given by S. J. James in Current Anthropology, vol. 30, pp. 1–26, 1989. It is
important also to distinguish between levels of utility in fire use, and not to assume that fire
indicates spit-roasts, gravy pans, and a neat stack of logs.
267. Evidence from the famous Swartkrans Cave in South Africa is used by C. K. Brain and A.
Sillen in Nature, vol. 336, pp. 464–466, 1988 for use of fire as far back as 1–1.5 Ma. Similarly
R. V. Bellomo, in Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 27, pp. 173–195, 1994, identifies the
controlled use of fire by hominids from 1.6 Ma sediments in Kenya, but notes that they ‘did
not use fire for the purpose of hunting, cooking, preserving food, intentional plant selection,
vegetation clearing, or improving the flaking characteristics of lithic materials . . . [but]
primarily as a source of protection against predators, as a source of light, and/or a source of
heat’ (p. 173). However, S. Weiner et al. argue against the controlled use of fire by the
half-million-year-old Homo erectus inhabitants of the Zhoukoudian caves near Beijing in
Science, vol. 281, pp. 251–253, 1998; see also the accompanying commentary by B. Wuethrich
on pp. 165–166, as well as the interesting article by N. T. Boaz and R. L. Ciochon in Natural
History, vol. 110(2), pp. 46–51, 2001.
268. See A. Walker et al. in Nature vol. 296, pp. 248–250, 1982. An accessible account is also given
in The wisdom of the bones: In search of human origins by A. Walker and P. Shipman (Knopf,
New York, 1996); see pp. 158–167.
269. O. Bar-Yosef, in Cambridge Archaeological Journal, vol. 8, pp. 141–163; 1998, provides a
useful overview. The best evidence for this dramatic event is from Europe, but its origins
were possibly in either East Africa or the Levant, unless these are independent?
270. These, of course, are almost entirely lithic, but rare, and to some extent enigmatic, use of
bone tools is also known; see S. Gaudzinski in Journal of Archaeological Science, vol. 26,
pp. 125–141, 1999.
271. See the report by I. Turk et al. report (in L’Anthropologie, vol. 101, pp. 531–540, 1997) of a
possible flute from a Mousterian culture in Slovenia dated at c. 45 000 years bp. A common
notes to pp. 274–276 431
explanation, that the perforations, in this case in the femur of a cave bear, are the product of a
chomping carnivore, are dismissed by these researchers; see also M. Otte in Current
Anthropology, vol. 41, pp. 271–272, 2000, who supports the musical interpretation.
272. P. M. Gray et al. (2001; citation is in note 171, Chapter 8), p. 53. Recall also that the parallels
in the songs of birds and humpback whales suggest convergence, and possibly access to a
universal music.
273. Evidence for rather advanced cultures, including the manufacture of bone points, and possibly
dating back to c. 90 000 years bp, from Katanda in Zaire is reported by A. S. Brooks et al. and J.
F. Yellen et al. in Science, vol. 268, pp. 548–553 and pp. 553–556 respectively, 1995 (see also
accompanying commentary by A. Gibbons on pp. 495–496, which casts some doubts on the
reliability of these dates). Certainly the appearance of some of the artefacts, such as the
well-crafted harpoon points, is astonishingly modern, and J. E. Yellen (in African
Archaeological Review, vol. 15, pp. 173–198, 1998) argues for an effective continuity in an
African context, albeit not in terms of a specific culture.
274. See the lengthy arguments by S. McBrearty and A. S. Brooks in Journal of Human Evolution,
vol. 39, pp. 453–563, 2000. See also the overview by R. Foley and M. M. Lahr in Cambridge
Archaeological Journal, vol. 7, pp. 3–36, 1997, with an emphasis on the so-called Mode 3
(c. 250 000 years ago) technology as a key step in hominid behaviour.
275. Sites in southern Africa, such as Blombos Cave, located east of Cape Town, are of particular
importance in providing evidence for the emergence of modern human behaviour, and by
implication language, c. 70 000 years ago. See C. S. Henshilwood et al. in Journal of Human
Evolution, vol. 41, pp. 631–678, 2001.
276. A. Marshack in Current Anthropology, vol. 37, pp. 357–364, 1996, describes an intriguing find
from the Quneitra Mousterian site on the Golan Heights, consisting of a flat flint cortex with
regular incised lines, including nested semicircles. And its significance? Removing our
preconceptions is practically impossible, but Marshack tentatively suggests the pattern
represents a rainbow, but of ‘spiritual’ rather than pictorial significance.
277. See F. d’Errico et al. in Antiquity, vol. 75, pp. 309–315, 2001). These authors argue that the
striations were not the result of butchery, but rather were constructed as a series of
intentional strokes.
278. See C. S. Henshilwood et al. in Science, vol. 295, pp. 1278–1280, 2002.
279. Excellent introductions are: The Neandertals: Changing the image of mankind by E.
Trinkaus and P. Shipman (Pimlico, London, 1994); The Neanderthal legacy: an archaeological
perspective from western Europe by P. Mellars (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1996);
and In search of the Neanderthals: solving the puzzle of human origins by C. Stringer and
C. Gamble (Thames and Hudson, London, 1993).
280. See, for example, J. H. Schwartz and I. Tattersall, in Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, USA, vol. 93, pp. 10852–10854, 1996, on a peculiarity of the nasal structure in the
form of a prominent bony projection extending into the cavity; a commentary by J. T.
Laitman et al. on pp. 10543–10545, focuses on implications of air-flow through the nose, and
what this might tell us about respiratory adaptations and vocalizations.
281. See M. S. Ponce de Leon and C. P. E. Zollikofer in Nature, vol. 412, pp. 534–538, 2001; as well
as remarks on cranial form by D. E. Liebermann et al. in Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 99, pp. 1134–1139, 2002.
282. See M. Krings et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 96,
pp. 5581–5585, 1999, and Nature Genetics, vol. 26, pp. 144–146, 2000, as well as I. V.
Ovchinnikov et al. in Nature, vol. 404, pp. 490–493, 2000, and R. W. Schmitz et al. in
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 99, pp. 13342–13347, 2002. A
somewhat critical review of the present state of play, however, is offered by N. Caldararo and
S. Gabow in Ancient Biomolecules, vol. 3, pp. 135–158, 2000, and G. Gutiérrez et al. in
Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 19, pp. 1359–1366, 2002. Rob Foley, who agrees that
Neanderthals are probably a separate species, reminds me that the DNA evidence is equivocal
432 notes to pp. 276–278
inasmuch as the comparison refers to that of modern human genetic variation, which is
remarkably limited and probably reflects an evolution bottleneck (‘mitochondrial Eve’),
c. 150 000 years ago.
283. C. W. Marean in Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 35, pp. 111–136, 1998 questions the widely
held view that these hominids were principally scavengers, a view broadly shared by J. J.
Shea, who argues in Current Anthropology, vol. 39 (Supplement), S45–S78, 1998, that the
Neanderthals had a variety of hunting strategies but were possibly greater carnivores than
modern humans, albeit replying on close-quarter intercepts (see also note 285). Their role as
top-level carnivores is reinforced by isotopic study of their bones, especially with respect to
nitrogen (δ 15 N), see M. P. Richards et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
USA, vol. 97, pp. 7663–7666, 2000; see also H. Bocheren et al. in Journal of Archaeological
Science, vol. 26, pp. 599–607, 1999, and V. Balter in Comptes Rendus de l’Académie des
Sciences, Paris: Sciences de la Terre et des Planètes, vol. 332, pp. 59–65, 2001.
284. A. Defleur et al. present convincing evidence from a site in southern France, reported in
Science, vol. 286, pp. 128–131, 1999; see also the accompanying commentary on pp. 18–19 by
E. Culotta.
285. For an engaging account of the excavations at Shanidar, see R. S. Solecki’s Shanidar: The
humanity of Neanderthal man (Penguin [Allen Lane], London, 1972), as well as the more
technical account in E. Trinkaus’s The Shanidar Neandertals (Academic Press, New York,
1983).
286. See E. Trinkaus and M. R. Zimmerman in American Journal of Physical Anthropology,
vol. 57, pp. 61–76, 1982. Evidence for care in more primitive Neanderthals, dating back to
about 170 000 years, is given by S. Lebel et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, USA, vol. 98, pp. 11097–11102, 2001, where the discovery of a mandible with
evidence for an abscess may indicate preparation of softer food for the sufferer, a reasonable
assumption given that Neanderthal teeth typically show extensive wear suggesting heavy-
duty use in daily activities.
287. See T. D. Berger and E. Trinkaus in Journal of Archaeological Science, vol. 22, pp. 841–852,
1995.
288. T. D. Berger and E. Trinkaus (1995; citation is in note 287); both quotations are on p. 849.
289. For evidence of interpersonal violence and the likelihood of subsequent assistance, see C. P. E.
Zollikofer et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 99, pp. 6444–
6448, 2002.
290. The paper, whose full title is ‘Grave shortcomings: the evidence for Neandertal burial’, by
R. H. Gargett in Current Anthropology, vol. 30, pp. 157–190, 1989. Gargett remounts his
sceptical attack in Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 37, pp. 27–90, 1999. See also note 291.
291. The claim for flowers in a Neanderthal burial in the Shanidar caves in Iraq is made by A.
Leroi-Gourhan in Science, vol. 190, pp. 562–565, 1975, but the evidence is based on the
abundance of flower pollen in the associated sediments, for which there could be alternative
explanations. The description of the excavation of the skeleton (Shanidar IV) is well described
in R. S. Solecki (1972; citation is in note 285), see pp. 173–178. Scepticism of this claim can be
found in Gargett (1989), p. 176, although in the discussion Leroi-Gourhan provides a short
response (p. 182), to which Gargett replies on p. 185.
292. B. Vandermeersch in Comptes Rendus de l’Académie des Sciences, Paris D, vol. 270,
pp. 298–301, 1970, however, interprets deer bones in association with a Neanderthal child at
Qafzeh as evidence of grave goods.
293. This includes the famous Kebara burial in Israel, see O. Bar-Yosef et al. in Current
Anthropology, vol. 27, pp. 63–64, 1986, and H. Valladas et al. in Nature, vol. 330, pp. 159–160,
1987. The latter paper provides an estimated age of c. 60 000 years. Other reports include
those by L. V. Golovanova et al. from the Mezmaiskaya cave in the northern Caucasus,
reported in Current Anthropology, vol. 40, pp. 77–86, 1999.
294. The hyoid is located in front of the larynx, and muscles attached to it help to control the
shape of this part of the vocal tract and thereby sound production. The Neanderthal hyoid is
notes to pp. 278–279 433
very similar to our own, leading some, e.g. A. B. Arensburg et al. in American Journal of
Physical Anthropology, vol. 83, pp. 137–146, 1990, to argue that their speech was effectively
the same as ours. In addition to the hyoid bone, much has been made of the so-called
‘descended larynx’ and its importance in the production of articulate speech. Interestingly,
this feature, thought to be unique to humans, is now known to occur in such mammals as the
red deer, famous for the stag’s roaring, and as such is another example of independent
evolution; see W. T. Fitch and D. Reby in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B,
vol. 268, pp. 1669–1675, 2001. This is not to say that one day deer will speak, but as Fitch and
Reby point out it is possible that originally the human descended larynx was associated with
sexual display, specifically so-called size exaggeration (the bull-roarer effect), even though we
now associated this feature with the pleasures of hearing the male baritone.
295. See for example D. Lieberman et al. in Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 23, pp. 447–467,
1992. For an accessible and more popular introduction to the topic, inter alia, of Neanderthal
fluency, see P. Lieberman’s Eve spoke: Human language and human evolution (Macmillan
[Picador], London, 1998).
296. See R. F. Kay et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 95,
pp. 5417–5419, 1998.
297. See A. M. MacLarnon and G. P. Hewitt in American Journal of Physical Anthropology,
vol. 109, pp. 341–363, 1999.
298. That may be true to the first approximation, but still requires qualification. Marshack (1996;
citation is in note 276), for example, draws attention to the example of a Neanderthal carving
of ‘an exquisite nonutilitarian oval plaque from a lamella of a compound mammoth molar at
Tata, Hungary, dated ca. 100,000 B.P.’ (p. 361); see also the article in Yearbook of Physical
Anthropology, vol. 32, pp. 1–34, 1989.
299. While taking a somewhat different slant on various matters the review on the origins of the
Aurignacian by S. E. Churchill and F. H. Smith in Yearbook of Physical Anthropology, vol. 43,
pp. 61–115, 2000 is of great value. In addition, what appear to be shell beads dating back to
about 40 000 years have been described from caves near the Mediterranean coast of Turkey
and Lebanon; see S. L. Kuhn et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA,
vol. 98, pp. 7641–7646, 2001.
300. The youngest Neanderthals are dated at about 28 000 years bp, see F. H. Smith et al. in
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 96, pp. 12281–12286,
1999.
301. For a helpful introduction see S. E. Churchill and F. H. Smith (2000; citation is in note 299),
pp. 76–77.
302. These spectacular examples of Châtelperronian expertise are discussed by A. Leroi-Gourhan
and A. Leroi-Gourhan in Gallia Préhistoire, vol. 7, pp. 1–64, 1965, and Marshack (1989;
citation is in note 298); other occurrences from Lot and Dordogne are reviewed by J. Pelegrin
in Cahiers du Quaternaire 20 (Technologie lithique le Châtelperronien de Roc-de-Combe
(Lot) et de la Côte (Dordogne) (CNRS Editions, Paris, 1995)). Unequivocal evidence of the
association of the Châtelperronian culture with Neandertal skeletal material is given by J-J.
Hublin et al. in Nature, vol. 381, pp. 224–226, 1996.
303. See J. J. Hublin et al. in Comptes Rendus d’Académie des Sciences, Paris, vol. 321 (IIa),
pp. 931–937, 1995. R. N. E. Barton et al. in Antiquity, vol. 73, pp. 13–23, 1999 provide a
preliminary report on the Neanderthals from Gibraltar, with dates as young as c. 32 000 years
BP, but still showing Mousterian technology. An overall review of the Iberian occurrences is
also given by F. d’Errico et al. in Current Anthropology, vol. 39 (Supplement), 1998,
pp. S19–S20 in the context of the identification of the Châtelperronian cultures. It is evident
that in Iberia the newly arriving Upper Palaeolithic industries of Homo sapiens made little, if
any impact, and d’Errico et al. use this finding to support their thesis (citation is in note 308)
that elsewhere in Europe the shift by Neanderthals to the Châtelperronian cultures was
independent of our species’ technological progression. In passing one should also remember
that occasional Châtelperronian artefacts have been found in Iberia, and as Hublin et al.
434 notes to pp. 279–281
(1995) remark ‘The occurrence of these artefacts is still puzzling’ (p. 934); perhaps
Neanderthal trade?
304. As suggested, for example, by R. White (in Annual Review of Anthropology, vol. 21,
pp. 537–564, 1992).
305. In his response as part of the discussion concerning Neanderthal acculturation in Current
Anthropology, vol. 39 (Supplement), pp. S1–S44, 1998, where Mellars remarks, ‘no one has
ever suggested that the copying of airplane forms in the New Guinea cargo cults implied a
knowledge of aeronautics or international travel’ (p. S26), a point he reiterates in a
continuation of the debate in a subsequent issue, vol. 40, pp. 341–364, 1999; see p. 350.
306. For an engaging and intriguing account of the John Frum cult in Tanna see Chapter 13 of
David Attenborough’s Quest in paradise (Lutterworth, London, 1960), with an illustration of
a cultic turboprop opposite p. 154. A useful overview of cargo cults is given by I. C. Jarvie on
pp. 133–137 of Encyclopedia of Papua and New Guinea (Melbourne University Press,
Melbourne, 1972).
307. From my chapter (pp. 329–347) in God and design: The teleological argument and modern
science, edited by N. A. Manson (Routledge, London, 2003), p. 340.
308. The key paper is by J. Zilhâo and F. d’Errico in Journal of World Prehistory, vol. 13, pp. 1–60,
1999; see also the short article by J. Zilhâo in the July/August 2000 issue of Archaeology on
pp. 24–31.
309. See, for example, the extended debates in two issues of Current Anthropology, vol. 39
(Supplement), pp. S1–S44, 1998 and vol. 40, pp. 341–364, 1999. See also D. Richter et al. in
Journal of Archaeological Science, vol. 27, pp. 71–89, 2000 (see pp. 84–86), and F. B. Harrold in
Journal of Anthropological Research, vol. 56, pp. 59–75, 2000, who provides a historical
overview (see especially pp. 68–69).
310. See E. Trinkhaus et al. in Journal of Archaeological Science, vol. 26, pp. 753–773, 1999, who
suggest that the massive proportions of the body are a reflection of a continuing existence in a
near-Arctic environment rather than a phylogenetic ‘baggage’.
311. This point is emphasized by d’Errico et al. in Current Anthropology, vol. 39 (Supplement);
1998, see pp. S11–S13; see also note 314.
312. See I. Karavanić and F. H. Smith in Journal of Human Evolution, vol. 34, pp. 223–248, 1998.
Subsequently these authors, with colleagues (citation is in note 264) obtained new, and
younger, dates. These indicated that in this region of Europe (Croatia) Neanderthals and
modern humans had not overlapped. Moreover, re-dating of an associated bone of a modern
human (a mere 5000 years bp) together with consideration of other dates, suggest that
modern humans arrived even later (c. 32 000 years bp) in Europe than thought. While this
does not rule out trade, it certainly strengthens the case for cultural independence.
313. A view in support of Neanderthal genetic assimilation into European populations is given by
S. E. Churchill and F. H. Smith (2000; citation is in note 299).
314. D. Kaufman weighs up the possibilities of contacts between H. sapiens and Neanderthals,
especially in the Levant, in Oxford Journal of Archaeology, vol. 20, pp. 219–240, 2001. He
notes that the Châtelperronian culture has certain hallmarks such as abundant use of
colouring and particular types of incised stones and pendants that were possibly adopted by
our ancestors.
315. S. E. Churchill and F. H. Smith (2000; citation is in note 299), pp. 105–106.
316. What L. G. Straus tartly refers to as ‘A review of reality’ concerning the likelihood that
Solutrean people crossed to North America is reviewed in American Antiquity, vol. 65,
pp. 219–226, 2000.
317. This strange occurrence from Tecaxic-Calixtlahuaca has been known for many years (see the
chapter (pp. 5–53) by S. C. Jeff in Man across the sea: Problems of Pre-Columbian contacts,
edited by C. L. Riley et al. (University of Texas Press, Austin, 1971)), and was brought back to
prominence by R. Hristov and S. Genovés, in Ancient Mesoamerica, vol. 10, pp. 207–213,
1999. Questions of the dating, using the techniques of thermoluminescence (TL), were
notes to pp. 281–284 435
subsequently raised by P. Schaaf and G. A. Wagner in the same journal (vol. 12, pp. 79–81,
2001), to which the original authors robustly reply (pp. 83–86). The principal point is that the
TL date is of relatively little use in establishing the authenticity of this find, but it still does
not support a colonial, i.e. a post 1492 ad date. Hristov and Genovés emphatically reject the
suggestion that the head was ‘planted’ and remind us that, given that the Canary Islands were
colonized by at least the fifth century bc, a chance crossing of the Atlantic more than a
thousand years in advance of Columbus is not inconceivable.
318. Interestingly, this is not the only possible evidence for transatlantic pre-Columbian contact
(excluding of course the well-known Viking forays). Jeff (1971) reviews a number of other
possible examples. The whole question of cultural contacts, ‘Diffusion versus independent
development’ to use Jeff’s chapter title, is, of course, relevant to cultural convergences. Do the
many striking similarities found between far-flung societies indicate independent innovation,
which in turn might reflect a ‘limitation of possibilities’ (p. 32), or the sharing of ideas?
319. In his justly famous introduction to English literature in the sixteenth century excluding
drama (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1954), C. S. Lewis recalls how the great essayist Montaigne
‘passionately asks why so noble a discovery [of the Americas] could not have fallen to the
Ancients who might have spread civility where we have spread only corruption’ (p. 17).
7. See L. M. Meffert et al. in Journal of Evolutionary Biology, vol. 12, pp. 859–868, 1999. Their
principal conclusion is also of wider interest, because it appears that the convergence
overrides the founder-flush effect, whereby tiny populations pass through evolutionary
‘bottlenecks’ before rediversifying on the basis of a restricted genetic diversity.
8. See C. S. Henry et al. in Evolution, vol. 53, pp. 1165–1179, 1999, where they demonstrate
‘songs that are strikingly similar’ (p. 1165) in species of the green lacewing Chrysoperla in
western North America and Kyrgyzstan in central Asia. The degree of similarity is such that
North American representatives can be fooled by an Asian song.
9. For a possible example in the Hawaiian cricket Laupala, which like many groups in this
mid-ocean archipelago demonstrates a major adaptive radiation, see K. L. Shaw in Evolution,
vol. 50, pp. 237–255, 1996. Convergence of song in the more familiar field-cricket Gryllus is
discussed by R. G. Harrison in Evolution, vol. 33, pp. 1009–1023, 1979; see also R. G. Harrison
and S. M. Bogdanowicz (in Journal of Evolutionary Biology, vol. 8, pp. 209–232, 1995).
10. See R. Kusmierski et al. in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 264,
pp. 307–313, 1997, with an emphasis on the lifting of phylogenetic constraints.
11. A helpful overview of the bowers is given by M. Hansell in Bird nests and construction
behaviour (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2000). Hansell draws attention
(pp. 212–213) to the independent development of elaborate display and so-called court objects
in other birds, as well as cichlid fish. In this context it is also interesting to note the positive
correlation between bower complexity and brain size; see J. Madden in Proceedings of the
Royal Society of London B, vol. 268, pp. 833–838, 2001.
12. See Chapter 9 of The rise and fall of the third chimpanzee (Radius, London, 1991).
13. See C. Sturmbauer et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 93,
pp. 10855–10857, 1996. They remark that ‘adaptations to higher intertidal life, such as
excellent vision, deep burrowing, rapid locomotion, and water retention preceded and allowed
the rise of extensive periods of subaerial reproductive displays. Sexual selection on
morphology and behavior may also have been directional, resulting in strikingly similar
solutions irrespective of the phylogenetic position’ (p. 10857).
14. See G. F. Striedter and R. G. Northcutt in Brain, Behavior and Evolution, vol. 38,
pp. 177–189, 1991.
15. A. M. Paterson et al. in Evolution, vol. 49, pp. 974–989, 1995, take a positive, if not upbeat,
view of the use of behavioural data in helping to establish bird phylogenies. So, too, do M.
Kennedy et al. in Animal Behaviour, vol. 51, pp. 273–291, 1996, although some of their
results are qualified by subsequent work; see Kennedy et al. in Molecular Phylogenetics and
Evolution, vol. 17, pp. 345–359, 2000.
16. ‘Why are some protein structures so common?’ ask S. Govindarajan and R. A. Goldstein in
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 93, pp. 3341–3345, 1996, and
provide an answer in the context of highly optimizable structures.
17. See, for example, C-I. Brändén in Current Opinion in Structural Biology, vol. 1, pp. 978–983,
1991, as well as G. K. Farber in the same journal, vol. 3, pp. 409–412, 1993.
18. See, for example, the essay by J-F. Gibrat et al. in Current Opinion in Structural Biology,
vol. 6, pp. 377–385, 1996.
19. See, for example, the review by T. Takagi in Current Opinion in Structural Biology, vol. 3,
pp. 413–418, 1993. See also R. A. Watts et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences, USA, vol. 98, pp. 10119–10124, 2001, who document a haemoglobin common to
plants and various microorganisms. This protein possesses unique biochemical properties,
and is absent from animals (and fungi).
20. See the paper by L. Moens et al. in Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 13, pp. 324–333,
1996.
21. See A. Pesce et al. in EMBO Journal, vol. 19, pp. 2424–2434, 2000, p. 2432.
22. See T. Burmester in Journal of Comparative Physiology, vol. 172B, pp. 95–107, 2002.
Although the arthropod haemocyanin appears to have a single origin, there is a diversity of
notes to pp. 288–290 437
sub-unit forms and evidently these have emerged by convergence; see J. Markl and H. Decker
in Advances in Comparative and Environmental Physiology, vol. 13, pp. 325–376, 1992.
23. See C. P. Mangum in Proceedings of the Biological Society of Washington, vol. 103,
pp. 235–247, 1990; K. E. van Holde and K. I. Miller in Advances in Protein Chemistry, vol. 47,
pp. 1–81, 1995; and Burmester (2002). In their review K. E. van Holde et al. (in Journal of
Biological Chemistry, vol. 276, pp. 15563–15566, 2001) acknowledge the differences between
arthropod and molluscan haemocyanins, but suggest that despite their independent
evolution they may both derive from a primitive copper protein (see also A. Volbeda and W.
G. M. Hol in Journal of Molecular Biology, vol. 206, pp. 531–546, 1989).
24. For a review of the evolution of myoglobin see the paper by T. Suzuki and K. Imai in Cellular
and Molecular Life Sciences, vol. 54, pp. 979–1004, 1998.
25. See, for example, the paper by S-G. Hou et al. in Nature, vol. 403, pp. 540–544, 2000, where
they report the presence of myoglobin-like proteins in both the Archaea and Eubacteria that
serve to monitor oxygen levels.
26. The report of myoglobin in cyanobacteria is by M. Potts et al. in Science, vol. 256,
pp. 1690–1692, 1992. For its occurrence in the protistan Tetrahymena, and an overview of the
earlier literature, see S. Korenaga et al. in Biochimica et Cosmochimica Acta, vol. 1543,
pp. 131–145, 2000. Korenaga et al. conclude ‘that the contracted or truncated globins from
various types of unicellular organisms have a separate, distinct origin from conventional
globins’, p. 143.
27. See, for example, C. Busch in Comparative Biochemistry and Physiology, vol. 86A,
pp. 461–463, 1987. A. J. Lechner (in Journal of Applied Physiology, vol. 41, pp. 168–173, 1976)
also documents high levels of muscle myoglobin in the burrowing pocket gophers, and
remarks on the parallels with the deep-diving mammals.
28. See K. A. Joysey et al. on pp. 167–178 of Myoglobin, edited by A. G. Schnek and C.
Vandecasserie (Editions de l’Université de Bruxelles, Brussels, 1977); A. M. Gurnett et al. in
Journal of Protein Chemistry, vol. 3, pp. 445–454, 1984; and K. A. Joysey on pp. 34–48 of
Molecular evolution and the fossil record; Short Courses in Paleontology 1, edited by B.
Runnegar and J. W. Schopf (Paleontological Society, Knoxville, TN, 1988). These data are
preliminary, but we should note Joysey’s (1988) prescient remark, ‘it is my view that many
other examples of adaptation in molecular evolution will emerge in due course’, p. 47.
29. See T. Suzuki and T. Takagi in Journal of Molecular Biology, vol. 228, pp. 698–700, 1992; T.
Suzuki and K. Imai in Comparative Biochemistry and Physiology, vol. 117B, pp. 599–604,
1997; and the review by T. Suzuki et al. in Comparative Biochemistry and Physiology B,
vol. 121, pp. 117–128, 1998.
30. See T. Shimizu et al. in Journal of Biological Chemistry, vol. 253, pp. 4700–4706, 1978.
31. See F. Hirata et al. in Journal of Biological Chemistry, vol. 252, pp. 4637–4642, 1977.
32. The details of the gene structure of the IDO are reviewed by T. Suzuki et al. in Biochimica et
Biophysica Acta, vol. 1308, pp. 41–48, 1996. They posit a gene duplication in the IDO gene
that allowed the protein to be recruited for oxygen carrying.
33. See several papers by T. Suzuki et al. in Journal of Protein Chemistry, vol. 14, pp. 9–13, 1994,
and vol. 17, pp. 651–656 and 817–826, 1998 respectively.
34. See N. Maeda and W. M. Fitch in Journal of Biological Chemistry, vol. 257, pp. 2806–2815,
1982. See also T. J. Grove and B. D. Sidell in Canadian Journal of Zoology, vol. 80, pp.
893–901, 2002.
35. The knock-out experiments in mice are described by D. J. Garry et al. in Nature, vol. 395,
pp. 905–908, 1998.
36. See J. Gatesy et al. in Science, vol. 291, pp. 2603–2605, 2001.
37. See, for example, K. B. Storey and J. M. Storey in Annual Review of Physiology, vol. 54,
pp. 619–637, 1992.
38. Notothenioid fish show spectacular evidence for an adaptive radiation, as reviewed by J.
Montgomery and K. Clements in Trends in Ecology & Evolution, vol. 15, pp. 267–271, 2000.
438 notes to pp. 290–294
These authors also touch on such topics as loss of haemoglobin and myoglobin (see above
p. 289).
39. See L. Chen et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 94,
pp. 3817–3822, 1997. This example of molecular convergence has received justifiably wide
attention, and J. M. Logsdon and W. F. Doolittle provide a thoughtful commentary of what
they describe as ‘a cool tale’, on pp. 3485–3487.
40. Details of this gene are given by L. Chen et al. in the paper preceding L. Chen et al. (1997), on
pp. 3811–3816. Further information on the glycoprotein itself is provided by A. N. Lane et al.
in Biophysics Journal, vol. 78, pp. 3195–3207, 2000.
41. Further details of the evolutionary steps from a trypsinogen-like protein to one with an
antifreeze function are given by C. H. C. Cheng and L. Chen in Nature, vol. 401, pp. 443–444,
1999.
42. G. L. Fletcher et al. in Annual Review of Physiology, vol. 63, pp. 359–390, 2001. Fletcher
et al. also suggest another example of molecular convergence among the antifreeze proteins,
this time involving C-type lectins in sea raven, herring, and smelt.
43. See P. L. Davies et al. in Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London B,
vol. 357, pp. 927–935, 2002. As part of a general review Davies et al. draw attention to a
striking convergence in spruce budworm and mealworm beetle antifreeze proteins,
specifically at the ice-binding sites. Concerning antifreeze proteins in insects, with
comments on the equivalents in the fish, see also N. Li et al. in Journal of Experimental
Biology, vol. 201, pp. 2243–2251, 1998.
44. See W. J. Swanson and C. F. Aquadro in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 54, pp. 403–410,
2002.
45. See M. Pitts and M. Roberts’s Fairweather Eden: Life in Britain half a million years ago as
revealed by the excavations at Boxgrove (Century, London, 1997).
46. See, for example, the papers by J. R. Petit et al. and K. M. Cuffey and F. Vimeux in Nature,
vol. 399, pp. 429–436, 1999 and vol. 412, pp. 523–527, 2001 respectively.
47. See, for example, the papers by S. Bains et al. in Science, vol. 285, pp. 724–727, 1999; G. R.
Dickens et al. in Geology, vol. 25, pp. 259–262, 1997; and M. E. Katz et al. in Science,
vol. 286, pp. 1531–1533, 1999. It is sobering to realize that the recovery time of the planet
after the LPTM was about 100 000 years. Massive methane release has also been implicated in
Quaternary events (see J. P. Kennett et al. in Science, vol. 288, pp. 128–133, 2000 (with
commentary by T. Blunier on pp. 68–69)) and the end-Cretaceous firestorm (see M. D. Max
et al. in Geo-Marine Letters, vol. 18, pp. 285–291, 1999).
48. See C4 plant biology, edited by R. F. Sage and R. K. Monson (Academic Press, San Diego,
1999), especially the introductory chapter (pp. 3–16) by the senior editor, and the overview by
R. F. Sage in Plant Biology, vol. 3, pp. 203–213, 2001.
49. The expansion of C4 ecosystems is documented by T. E. Cerling et al. in Nature, vol. 361,
pp. 344–345, 1993 and vol. 389, pp. 153–158, 1997, and Journal of Vertebrate Paleontology,
vol. 16, pp. 103–115, 1996.
50. See R. F. Sage (2001; citation is in note 48), and Y. Huang et al. in Science, vol. 293,
pp. 1647–1651, 2001, with commentary by R. A. Kerr on pp. 1572–1573.
51. See N. R. Sinha and E. A. Kellogg, in American Journal of Botany, vol. 83, pp. 1458–1470,
1996, where they remark, ‘Such complexity should be difficult to evolve, yet the [C4 ] pathway
has evolved multiple times in the history of the flowering plants’ (p. 1458). See also Kellogg’s
chapter on pp. 411–444 in R. F. Sage and R. K. Monson (1999; citation is in note 48).
52. See E. V. Voznesenskaya et al., in Nature, vol. 414, pp. 543–546, 2001; and H. Freitag and
W. Stichler in Plant Biology, vol. 2, pp. 154–160, 2000, as well as an overview by R. F. Sage in
Trends in Plant Science, vol. 7, pp. 283–285, 2002.
53. See the chapter by R. K. Monson, on pp. 377–410 of R. F. Sage and R. K. Monson (1999;
citation is in note 48). Some of the necessary antecedents to C4 photosynthesis are discussed
by J. Hibberd and W. P. Quick in Nature, vol. 415, pp. 451–453, 2002 (with commentary by
J. A. Raven on pp. 375 and 377).
notes to pp. 294–295 439
68. See J. La Roche et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 93,
pp. 15244–15248, 1996.
69. See P. Robson et al. in Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 17, pp. 1739–1752, 2000.
70. See Z. C. Shen and M. Jacobs-Lorena in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 48, pp. 341–347,
1999.
71. See K. A. Crandall et al. in Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 16, pp. 372–382, 1999.
72. See K. H. Roux et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 95,
pp. 11804–11809, 1998.
73. See G. E. Schulz in Current Opinion in Structural Biology, vol. 2, pp. 61–67, 1992; see also
the discussion of convergence among nucleic acid binding molecules by P. Graumann and M.
A. Maraherl in BioEssays, vol. 18, pp. 309–315, 1996.
74. See J. Hodgkin in Genes & Development, vol. 16, pp. 2322–2326, 2002, forming a
commentary on the paper by R. Lints and S. W. Emmons on pp. 2390–2407.
75. See C. S. Thummel and J. Chory in Genes & Development, vol. 16, pp. 3113–3129, 2002.
76. See E. Stebbins and J. E. Galán in Nature, vol. 412, pp. 701–705, 2001.
77. This is just one example, referring to the pathogen Yersinia pseudotuberculosis. In the case of
another bacterium, Salmonella, not only does the pathogen use a molecular convergence to
allow it to enter through the cell wall, but once inside the host cell the bacterium helps to
repair the damage to protect its new niche, again using methods of molecular mimicry.
78. E. Stebbins and J. E. Galán (2001; citation is in note 76), p. 703.
79. E. Stebbins and J. E. Galán (2001; citation is in note 76), p. 705.
80. See Y. Nakamura in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 53, pp. 282–289, 2001. He
comments, ‘What’s so remarkable in molecular mimicry is the fact that the three proteins
structurally known as a tRNA mimic possesses completely different protein folds with
unrelated primary and secondary structures of protein’ (p. 287). Protein-DNA mimics have
also been recognized, see for example, the papers in Cell by D. C. Mol et al., vol. 82,
pp. 701–708, 1995 and D. Liu et al., vol. 94, pp. 573–583, 1998.
81. See K. Salehi-Ashtiani and J. W. Szostak in Nature, vol. 414, pp. 82–84, 2001. (See also note
46, Chapter 4).
82. K. Salehi-Ashtiani and J. W. Szostak (2001; citation is in note 81), p. 84.
83. See, in particular, the article by Doolittle (1994; citation is in note 63), with the title
‘Convergent evolution – the need to be explicit’.
84. See T. Bauchop and R. W. Martucci in Science, vol. 161, pp. 698–700, 1968. Ruminant-like
digestion is also known in the macropod marsupials, e.g. kangaroos (see D. W. Dellow et al. in
Australian Journal of Zoology, vol. 31, pp. 433–443, 1983), and possibly the sloths (see the
chapter (pp. 329–359) by G. G. Montgomery and M. E. Sunquist in The ecology of arboreal
folivores, edited by G. G. Montgomery (Smithsonian Institution Press, Washington, DC,
1978)). So far as I am aware there is no evidence whether the digestive system of at least the
macropods shows the molecular convergence of lysozymes.
85. The hoatzin is evidently fairly closely related to the cuckoos; see S. B. Hedges et al. in
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 92, pp. 11662–11665, 1995. E. S.
Morton, in his chapter (pp. 123–130) in Montgomery (1978) also draws attention to various
similarities between the hoatzin and New Zealand Owl Parrot, remarking ‘Both species are
highly convergent in ways directly attributable to their leaf-eating habits,’ p. 125.
86. Concerning its fore-gut fermentation systems, see A. Grajal et al. in Science, vol. 245,
pp. 1236–1238, 1989. The parallels with the system in ruminant mammals is emphasized by
A. Grajal in The Auk, vol. 112, pp. 20–28, 1995, and his remark that ‘Fore-gut fermentation in
a 680-g flying endotherm is theoretically unexpected’ (p. 26) is an important reminder of how
principles of convergence leap both phylogenetic barriers and sometimes our expectations.
87. These similarities include functional wing claws in the juveniles that enable them to climb
trees. It now seems that the limited flight abilities of the hoatzin are more to do with the need
to accommodate the massive fermentation chambers at the expense of the flight muscles.
notes to pp. 298–303 441
88. See C. B. Stewart and A. C. Wilson in Cold Spring Harbor Symposia on Quantitative Biology,
vol. 52, pp. 891–899, 1987.
89. See J. R. Kornegay et al. in Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 11, pp. 921–928, 1994.
90. See R. F. Doolittle (1994; citation is in note 63).
91. See C. B. Stewart and A. C. Wilson (1987; citation is in note 88), and also further evidence for
adaptive evolution of these langur monkey lysozymes in the paper by W. Messier and C. B.
Stewart in Nature, vol. 385, pp. 151–154, 1997 (with a commentary by P. M. Sharp on
pp. 111–112) and (with certain provisos) by Z. Yang in Molecular Biology and Evolution,
vol. 15, pp. 568–573, 1998 (see also the subsequent paper by Z. Yang and R. Nielsen in the
same journal, vol. 19, pp. 908–917, 2002). In addition, evidence exists in the langur monkey
for adaptive evolution in the ribonuclease enzyme, produced in the pancreas and involved
with digestion of the fore-gut bacteria. See J. Zhang et al. in Nature Genetics, vol. 30,
pp. 411–415, 2002, and commentary by S. Yokoyama on pp. 350–351. The evolution of the
enzyme is due to a few critical amino acid substitutions that allow the ribonuclease to
process large quantities of bacterial RNA in a lower pH environment. It will be interesting to
see if parallel substitutions occur in other ruminant species, in a way analogous to the ‘five
site rule’ of colour vision (note 168, Chapter 7).
92. See, for example, N. G. C. Smith and A. Eyre-Walker and J. C. Fay et al. in Nature, vol. 415,
pp. 1022–1024 and pp. 1024–1026 respectively, 2002, as well as overviews by Z. Yang and J. P.
Bielawksi in Trends in Ecology & Evolution, vol. 15, pp. 496–507, 2000 and M. Kreitman and
H. Akashi in Annual Review of Ecology and Systematics, vol. 26, pp. 402–422, 1995.
93. See M. Harry et al. in Molecular Phylogenetics and Evolution, vol. 9, pp. 542–551,
1998.
94. See T. B. Patterson and T. J. Givnish in Evolution, vol. 56, pp. 233–252, 2002.
95. Their paper is published in American Naturalist, vol. 146, pp. 349–364, 1995, where they
specifically address the topic of seed size.
96. See S. J. Gould and R. C. Lewontin in Proceedings of the Royal Society of London B, vol. 205,
pp. 581–598, 1979.
97. Not that every example of convergence is necessarily adaptive; see for example the important
paper by D. B. Wake in American Naturalist, vol. 138, pp. 543–567, 1991.
98. See Kirk Winemiller’s paper in Ecological Monographs, vol. 61, pp. 343–365, 1991; See also
note 134; Chapter 6.
99. K. Winemiller (1991; citation is in note 98), p. 361.
100. See Rob Foley’s chapter Pattern and process in hominid evolution, on pp. 31–42 of Structure
and contingency: Evolutionary processes in life and human society, edited by J. Bintliff
(Leicester University Press, London, 1999).
101. R. Foley (1999; citation is in note 100), p. 40. Oddly, in the same volume S. J. Gould writes of
Foley’s work that it ‘suggests a much chancier, much less guaranteed, much less repeatable
story replete with dominating contingency,’ p. xx. Did Gould actually read what Foley wrote,
I wonder?
102. See Eviator Nevo’s Mosaic evolution of subterranean mammals: Regression, progression and
global convergence (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1999).
103. E. Nevo (1999), p. 208.
104. Notably his The blind watchmaker: why the evidence of evolution reveals a universe
without design (Norton, New York, 1987). Given Dawkins’s emphasis on adaptation and a
specific section on convergence, it is not surprising that a number of the examples given here
are also discussed in his book.
105. See for example, the papers by B. D. Patterson (in Journal of Mammalogy, vol. 80,
pp. 345–360, 1999) and S. B. Emerson (in Biological Journal of the Linnean Society, vol. 73,
pp. 139–151, 2001).
106. See, for example, G. Balavoine in Compte Rendu d’Académie des Sciences, Paris, Science de
la Vie, vol. 320, pp. 83–94, 1997. It should be noted, however, that the acoels are probably
442 notes to pp. 303–307
genuinely primitive within the triploblastic metazoans; see I. Ruiz-Trillo et al. in Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 99, pp. 11246–11251, 2002.
107. See the paper in Nature, vol. 401, p. 762, 1999, by M. Kobayashi et al.
108. See note 113, chapter 7.
109. See, for example, M. H. Tai et al. in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA,
vol. 90, pp. 1852–1856, 1993. Similarly, in reviewing the Wilms’ tumour suppressor gene
(WT1), N. D. Hastie (in Cell, vol. 106, pp. 391–394, 2001) noted that the two principal
isoforms (−KTS, +KTS) have very distinct functions, but differ by only three amino
acids.
110. See M. Rosenquist et al. in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 51, pp. 446–458, 2000.
111. See the overview by G. B. Golding and A. M. Dean in Molecular Biology and Evolution,
vol. 15, pp. 355–369, 1998, and more specifically papers by S. Brogna et al. in the same
journal, vol. 18, pp. 322–329, 2001; Y-H. Lee and V. D. Vacquier in Biological Bulletin,
vol. 182, pp. 97–104, 1992; W. J. Swanson and V. D. Vacquier in Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 92, pp. 4957–4961, 1995 and Science, vol. 281, pp. 710–712,
1998; J. Vieira and B. Charlesworth in Genetics, vol. 155, pp. 1701–1709, 2000; J. Vieira et al.
in Genetics, vol. 158, pp. 279–290, 2001; X. Gu et al. in Genetica, vol. 102/103, pp. 383–391,
1998; L. S. Jermiin et al. in Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 12, pp. 558–563, 1995; N.
A. Singhania et al. in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 49, pp. 721–728, 1999; C. S. Willett
in Molecular Biology and Evolution, vol. 17, pp. 552–562, 2000. See also note 92.
112. See, for example, Evolutionary trends, edited by K. J. McNamara (Belhaven, London, 1990),
where a variety of views are expressed, as well as specific examples such as those concerning
the hinge mechanism of articulate brachiopods (S. J. Carlson in Paleobiology, vol. 18,
pp. 344–366, 1992) and suture complexity in Palaeozoic ammonoids (W. B. Saunders et al. in
Science, vol. 286, pp. 760–763, 1999). Also germane to this area is G. J. Vermeij’s interesting
essay in American Naturalist, vol. 153, pp. 243–253, 1999.
113. Janis and Damuth in K. J. McNamara (1990; citation is in note 112), p. 313.
114. Janis and Damuth in K. J. McNamara (1990; citation is in note 112), p. 337.
115. See his paper in Journal of Paleontology, vol. 62, pp. 319–329, 1988; see also S. C. Wang in
Evolution, vol. 55, pp. 849–858, 2001 for an analysis of passive and driven evolutionary
trends. A. H. Knoll and R. K. Bambach, in Paleobiology, vol. 26 (Supplement), pp. 1–14, 2000,
offer an outstanding critique on this issue.
116. See his paper in Nature, vol. 385, pp. 250–252, 1997, as well as the chapter (pp. 256–289) in
Evolutionary biology: in honor of James W. Valentine, edited by D. Jablonksi et al.
(University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1996).
117. See J. Trammer and A. Kaim in Historical Biology, vol. 13, pp. 113–125, 1999.
118. See J. Alroy in Science, vol. 280, pp. 731–734, 1998.
119. J. Alroy (1998; citation is in note 118), p. 732.
120. See B. A. Maurer in Evolutionary Ecology, vol. 12, pp. 925–934, 1998.
121. B. A. Maurer (1998; citation is in note 120), p. 925.
122. Their paper is published in Evolution, vol. 46, pp. 939–953, 1992.
123. Maurer et al., p. 951; on p. 949 they argue that ‘Contrary to Gould’s (1988; citation is in note
115) assertion, more than random cladogenetic events are required to account for
evolutionary trends such as Cope’s rule.’
124. See Peter Wagner’s paper in Evolution, vol. 54, pp. 365–386, 2000. Also directly relevant is the
exploration by C. K. Boyce and A. H. Knoll (in Paleobiology, vol. 28, pp. 70–100, 2002) of
plant leaf form and the exhaustion of potentiality, leading to widespread convergence.
125. P. Wagner (2000; citation is in note 124), p. 382.
126. See S. J. Gould’s chapter (pp. 319–338) in Evolutionary progress, edited by M. H. Nitecki
(University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1988).
127. Or more specifically ‘Progress is a noxious, culturally embedded, untestable, nonoperational,
intractable idea that must be replaced if we wish to understand the patterns of history,’
notes to pp. 307–313 443
p. 319. For a polite, short, and devastating demolition of this canard of Gould, see the letter by
F. K. McKinney in Science, vol. 237, p. 575, 1987.
128. In this context see the discussion by D. H. Geary et al. (in Paleobiology, vol. 28, pp. 208–221,
2002) discussion of iterative evolution in gastropods, with a wide-ranging and intelligent
analysis of the alternative explanations.
129. See, for example, G. B. West et al. in Science, vol. 284, pp. 1677–1679, 1999, and papers by K.
J. Niklas and B. J. Enquist and J. H. Marden and L. R. Allen, in Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 98, pp. 2922–2927; 2001 and vol. 99, pp. 4161–4166, 2002
respectively.
130. See also my paper in Astronomical Society of the Pacific Conference Series, (IAU Symposium
213) (in press).
131. See Lee Cronk That complex whole: Culture and the evolution of human behaviour
(Westview, Boulder, CO, 1999).
132. L. Cronk (1999; citation is in note 131), p. 26.
133. The question of such ‘navigation’ is not, of course, new; see, for example, K. J. Niklas in
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, vol. 91, pp. 6772–6779, 1994, and a
series of papers by S. Gavrilets, e.g. in Trends in Ecology & Evolution, vol. 12, pp. 307–312,
1997; American Naturalist, vol. 154, pp. 1–22, 1999; and Proceedings of the Royal Society of
London B, vol. 266, pp. 817–824, 1999.
134. L. Cronk (1999; citation is in note 131) invokes such an analogy when he writes, ‘we are in
search of the Great Attractor of human culture, the unseen mass that pulls human cultures
toward it and so limits their diversity,’ p. 26.
135. So L. Cronk (1999; citation is in note 131) writes ‘Maybe the problem is that only certain
pathways through ethnographic hyperspace are actually possible,’ p. 26.
8. The blue cross, the first story in The innocence of Father Brown (Cassell, London, 1940),
p. 22.
9. See A. Peacocke’s chapter (pp. 101–130) of Darwinism and divinity: Essays on evolution and
religious belief, edited by J. Durant (Blackwell, Oxford, 1985).
10. A. Peacocke (1985; citation is in note 9), p. 123
11. An example comes from a review (published in the Times Literary Supplement, 24 December,
1999) by Philip Kitcher of Matt Ridley’s book Genome where he remarks, ‘Ridley obviously
has a fine time sharing his delight [of the genome]. Indeed, perhaps he has too good a time. For
the booming voice of conviction that sounds through the chapters, from the initial discussion
of the origins of life to the philosophically limp conclusions about free will, is utterly certain
about everything. Like the village squire to the Victorian parson with “doubts”, Ridley
prescribes fresh air and exercise. He seems quite unworried by the thought that some of the
scientific claims he reports might be controversial or even unfounded, and even less
disconcerted by the possibility that . . . scientific truths might lead to social harm,’
p. 24.
12. J. C. Greene’s Debating Darwin: Adventures of a scholar (Regina Books, Claremont, 1999).
13. J. C. Greene (1999; citation is in note 12), p. 42.
14. J. C. Greene (1999; citation is in note 12), p. 43.
15. See, in particular, J. C. Greene (1999; citation is in note 12) and his essay ‘Huxley to Huxley’
in his Science, ideology, and world view. Essays in the history of evolutionary ideas
(University of California Press, Berkeley, 1981).
16. Published by Penguin (London, 1998).
17. See my review in Geological Magazine, vol. 136, pp. 601–603, 1999.
18. Julian Huxley Evolution in action: Based on the Patten Foundation Lectures delivered at
Indiana University in 1951 (Chatto & Windus, London, 1953).
19. J. Huxley (1953; citation is in note 15), p.12; for its discussion in the context of process
theology, see J. C. Greene (1981; citation is in note 15), pp. 164–165.
20. J. Huxley (1953; citation is in note 19), pp. 152–153.
21. J. C. Greene (1981; citation is in note 15); both quotations are on p. 165.
22. J. C. Greene (1981; citation is in note 15), p. 168; see also in note 1.
23. Daniel Gasman The scientific origins of national socialism: Social Darwinism in Ernst
Haeckel and the German Monist League (Macdonald and American Elsevier, London and
New York, 1971).
24. D. Gasman (1971; citation is in note 23), explanation to Plate I, facing p. 8.
25. The close connection between Haeckel’s monistical phantasies and the rise of European
fascism, including not only Germany but Italy and France, is returned to by D. Gasman in
Haeckel’s Monism and the birth of fascist ideology, Studies in modern European history,
vol. 33, edited by F. J. Coppa (Peter Lang, New York, 1998).
26. Chapter 1 (pp. 9–32) of Structure: In science and art, edited by W. Pullan and H. Bhadeshia
(Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2001).
27. D. Gasman (1971; citation is in note 23), p. 61.
28. S. Conway Morris (2001; citation is in note 26), pp. 30–31.
29. Concerning this trial see K. Tierney’s Darrow: A biography (Crowell, New York, 1979) and
E. J. Larson’s Summer for the gods: The Scopes trial and America’s continuing debate over
science and religion (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 1997).
30. K. Tierney (1979; citation is in note 29), p. 341.
31. K. Tierney (1979; citation is in note 29), p. 357.
32. K. Tierney (1979; citation is in note 29), p. 359.
33. K. Tierney (1979; citation is in note 29), p. 393.
34. K. Tierney (1979; citation is in note 29), p. 358, taking a quote from W. Herberg.
35. K. Tierney (1979; citation is in note 29), p. 365
36. K. Tierney (1979; citation is in note 29), p. 393.
notes to pp. 323–330 445
37. See Susan Oyama’s article ‘The accidental chordate: contingency in developmental systems’
in South Atlantic Quarterly, vol. 94, pp. 509–526, 1995.
38. S. Oyama (1995; citation is in note 37), p. 512.
39. See Peter Koslowski’s chapter on pp. 301–328 in Sociobiology and bioeconomics: The theory
of evolution in biological and economic theory, edited by P. Koslowski (Springer, Berlin,
1999).
40. P. Koslowski (1999; citation is in note 39), p. 308.
41. But see W. J. Alonso and C. Shuck-Paim in Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences,
USA, vol. 99, pp. 6843–6847, 2002.
42. See Eva Neumann-Held’s article on pp. 105–137 of Kowslowski (1999; citation is in note 39).
43. Consilience: The unity of knowledge (Knopf, New York, 1998).
44. As one reviewer of Consilience, the philosopher John Dupré, wrote, ‘the central thesis of the
book is vague, and many of the opinions expressed are quite eccentric’; see Science, vol. 280,
pp. 1395–1396, 1998.
45. See his Beyond evolution: Human nature and the limits of evolutionary explanation
(Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1997); in particular pp. 156–158.
46. The title of one of C. S. Lewis’s most influential books, first published in 1943.
47. See J. C. Greene’s article on Darwin and religion in Proceedings of the American
Philosophical Society, vol. 103, pp. 716–725, 1959.
48. J. C. Greene (1959; citation is in note 47), p. 725.
49. J. C. Greene (1959; citation is in note 47), p. 725.
50. See T. F. Smith and H. J. Morowitz in Journal of Molecular Evolution, vol. 18, pp. 265–282,
1982.
51. T. F. Smith and H. J. Morowitz (1982; citation is in note 50), p. 281.
52. C. S. Lewis’s That hideous strength: a modern fairy tale for grown-ups (Bodley Head, London,
1946).
53. C. S. Lewis (1946; citation is in note 52), pp. 46–48.
54. The title of his extraordinary book, the full title of which is Forbidden knowledge: From
Prometheus to pornography (Harcourt, Brace [Harvest], San Diego, 1997).
55. See R. S. Noel’s The mythology of Middle-Earth (Thames and Hudson, London, 1977), and
recall the power of the One Ring, whose property is to enthrall its owner and to lead him or
her to a damnation that ultimately may not be of their own choosing.
56. See Howard Van Till’s contribution on pp. 188–194 in Science & Christianity: Four views,
edited by R. F. Carlson (InterVarsity Press, Downers Grove, 2000).
57. H. Van Till (2000; citation is in note 56), p. 192 (his emphases).
58. Michael Polanyi Personal knowledge: Towards a post-critical philosophy (Routledge and
Kegan Paul, London, 1962).
59. M. Polanyi (1962; citation is in note 58), pp. 284–285.
60. See my book The crucible of creation: The Burgess Shale and the rise of animals (Oxford
University Press, Oxford, 1998), p. 223, and S. R. Taylor’s Destiny or chance: our solar system
and its place in the cosmos (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1998), p. 204.
61. See notably D. A. Griffin’s Animal minds: Beyond cognition to consciousness (Chicago,
University of Chicago Press, 2001), as well as the discussion in Chapter 9.
62. See G. K. Chesterton’s ‘A defence of humility’ in The defendant (Dent, London, 1922).
63. G. K. Chesterton (1922; citation is in note 62), pp. 134–135.
64. Asked what most struck him of God’s creation, J. B. S. Haldane is said to have replied: an
inordinate fondness for beetles.
General index
α-helices 167, 170, 230, 357n55 343n61; proline 13; racemic mixture
α-proteobacteria 352n6 40–41, 60; serine 16; tryptophan 288,
abalone 289 n.12/1
absorption spectra 109, 289, 110 ammonia (NH3 ) 25, 62
acetylcholine 235–236 ammonites n.35/6
ACLU see American Civil Liberties Union amphibians 120, 190, 216, 220, 270,
Acromyrmex 198 289
Actinocoryne 230 amphioxus 6, 7, 180, 7
adenine 4, 13, 28, 30, 63, 64 Amyciaea 212–213
African golden moles 141 angiosperms 135–138
African Grey parrot 225–6, 253 annelids 154, 193; eyes 154
agriculture 2, 197–200, 205–207, 208–209, anthropic principles 327
210, 275, 401n25; ‘agro-predation’ 200, antibiotics 200, 207
207; ant ‘cartons’ 210; ‘bucket brigade’ ants 2, 8, 116–117, 143, 197–201, 208, 210,
198, 400n6; caches 198; climate change 212–213, 284, 388n201
206; cropping 199; division of labour aphids 114
198; dump-pits 205, 206; exchange 207; apinid honey bees 203
fertilizer 199, 210; fungus gardens 116, Apollo 11 70
197–200, 205–207, 206; herbicide 200; aporrhaids 157
Mesoamerica 206; monocultures 207, Arachnocampa 116
210; mulch 199; pathogens 200; Archaea 170, 171
pruning 199; waste disposal 205–206; archaeogastropods 289
weeding 199, 209, 210 Archaeopteryx 298
alanine 13, 16, 115, 340n32 Ardipithecus 271
albatrosses 2, 14, 3 argyrolagids 145–146
algae 62, 95, 107, 173, 294 army ants 116, 200–201, 203–205, 207,
Allan Hills meteorite (ALH 84001) 33–34, 210–211, 202, 406n98
75 arthropods 116, 193, 284, 288
ambrosia beetles 207–208 Asian swiftlets 181–182
American Civil Liberties Union asteroids 95, 96, 97
(ACLU) 320, 321 atmosphere 61–62, 72, 76, 107, 109;
amino acids 4, 5, 8, 9, 10, 13–14, 16, 18, 23, clouds 66
27, 35, 36, 40–41, 46, 53, 57, 59, 60, 61, 63, atonal gene 193
77, 115, 167, 168, 171, 287, 296, 298; ATP (adenosine triphosphate) 25, 49, 113,
α-amino isobutyric acid 37; alanine 13, 170
16, 115, 340n32; arginine 13, 288, 296; Atta 198
artificial 335n22; aspartic acid 41, 296; attine ants 116, 198–200, 205–207, 208,
dextral (d-) amino acids 340n30; 198
enantiomorphs 39–41, 60, 65; glycine Aurignacian culture 275, 278, 279, 280
13, 16, 33, 60, 115; impact origin 339n25; Australopithecus 269, 271
isovaline 37; left-handedness 40;
lysine 126; oligomerization 53–54, baboons 242–243, 244
general index 447
bacteria 1, 2, 18, 26, 34, 56, 74, 94, 99, 107, 256; Pax-6 gene 193, 240; scombrid fish
113, 114, 121, 124, 166, 170, 200, 230, 235, 223; sharks 399n327; size 245–248,
236, 288, 307; bacteriome 114; flagellum 245; size increases 248, 273–274, 436n11,
111, 230; genome 238; motor 111, 230 245; structural organization 265,
bacteriorhodopsin 170–172 266–268; teleost 194; temporal 256;
Barbourofelis 130 tenrec 246; toothed whales 246–247;
barnacles 119 torus semicircularis 196; valvula
bats 173, 181, 182, 192, 218, 256, 257, cerebelli 194; vertebrate 6, 179–180
265–268 Branchiostoma 6
bees 143, 202, 205, 207, 284 brittle-stars 155, 159–160, 406n75
beetles 143, 147, 149, 292, 372n4 bryozoans 126
beluga whale 251 bubble-rings 257–258, 257
bennettitaleans 137 budgerigars 219
biosynthetic pathways 16, 18, 336n39 butterflies 169
birds (see also cultures, sounds) 96, byssus threads 289
138–139, 190, 194, 223, 225–226, 246, 254,
269, 306, 387n170 C-value paradox 417n53
bivalves 158–159, 289, 159 C3 109, 293–294
bladder kelp 355n37 C4 109, 293–294
Blainville’s beaked whale 15 cactus 134–135, 134
Bombardier beetle 372n4 caddis-flies 116
Borszczowia 294 Caenorhabditis 4, 238
bottlenose whale 420n106 calcite 41, 159
bowerbirds 285–286 Callisto 348n49
Boxgrove Man 291, 292 camouflage 168, 215
brain (see also mental functions) 243, Campylomormyrus 184
244–249; amphioxus 6; bird 226, cancers 173, 240
412n180; blood–brain barrier 214; carbohydrates 9, 24, 27, 135
cephalopod 214; cerebellum 194, 195, carbon dioxide 55, 62, 76, 99, 108, 109, 216,
254, 256; cetacean 254; chimp 247; 292–293, 294, 295
cortical cytoarchitecture 256; cortical carbon monoxide 62, 63, 113, 356n38
structure 267; dolphin 247–249, 291, carrot 141
247, 255; dorsal cochlear nucleus castes 199
396n284; electrosensory line lobe 189; cats 147–148, 177–178, 181
encephalization 248, 273–274; Cebus 262, 263, 268
encephalization quotient (EQ) 245, 247; cells (see also ion channels) 38, 46, 47;
environmental triggers 248–249, 291; endosymbiosis 352n6; secondary
folding 195, 256; frontal 256; great endosymbiosis 352n6; sodium transport
apes 248; gymnotids 195–196; 230
hippocampus 265; hominids 273; cellulose 27, 135, 199, 298, 311, 373n5
Homo erectus 249; humans 246, 254, cephalopods 150, 151–154, 169, 214, 303
255; insects 179–180, 407n106; Cephalorhynchus 251
inter-hemispheric independence 254; cerebellum 194, 195, 254, 256
laterality 254; mammals 226; Chalcides 221
metabolic costs 195, 419n97; Chamaesyce 294
microchiropteran bats 256; mormyrid chameleons 164
fish 194–196, 245, 256, 195; Châtelperronian culture 278–281, 279,
multi-layered cortex 226; neocortex 434n314
195, 254, 256, 265, 267; occipital 256; chenopodiacean 294
olfactory bulbs 265; optic tectum chimpanzees 5–6, 242, 247, 249, 262
n.284/7; orthodenticle (otd) 241; otx chironomids 116
gene 242; paralimbic 254; parietal chitin 27
448 general index
Chlamydomonas 165, 171 fences 214; ‘fire zone’ 210; plugs 214;
chlorophyll 106–111, 135, 233, 298, 110 rafts 401n32; sheds 406n98; tents
chloroplasts 352n6 116–117, 212, 358n70; termite nests
cichlids 133, 215–216, 224, 364n136, 208; tracks 199; tunnels 208
436n11 convergences see Convergences index
ciliates 150, 235, 236, 287, 288, 356n44, Cope’s rule 304–306
374n17 corals 112, 154
circadian rhythms 172–173, 385n138 cows 113, 298
circulatory systems 215–216 crab spider 212
Circumstellar Habitable Zone (CHZ) 83, crabs 138, 150–151, 214
99–100, 100 crayfish 169
citric acid cycle 57 creation ‘scientists’ xv, 301, 316, 322
cladistics 299, 353n21, 367n169 crested auklet 139
clover 235 crickets 192, 218, 285
Clovis culture 281 crocodiles 227
coccoideans 149 crows 246
cockroaches 208 crustaceans 126, 130, 143–144, 158, 180,
comets 36, 42, 43, 94–99 214, 217, 129
commelinoids 365n142 cryptochromes 11, 172–173
common dolphin 247; Pacific white-sided crystallins 163, 166–167, 172, 173, 240, 312
dolphin 247; Tucuxi dolphin 247 cubozoans 154–155, 157, 160
communication (see also mental functions, cultures 258–260; apprenticeships 286;
sounds); ant 203–204; artificial language Aurignacian 275, 278, 279; beads 274;
252–253; babbling 251–252; bacterial bicycles 111, 112, 270, 289, n.227/9;
236; categorical perception 194; birds’ nest soup 181; bowers 436n11;
categories 259; chemical signals 236; burial 276, 278, 277; cargo cults 279;
chromatic signals 215; courtship 190; carvings 275, 280; Châtelperronian
dialects 258, 423n163; distress cries 278–281, 279; Clovis 281; ‘cultural
210; electrical 184–188, 190; gestures revolution’ 260; destruction 359n83;
252; grammar 253; head drumming figurines 275; gin and tonic 193,
209; language 278; ‘language space’ 253; 334n12; instruction 259, 260; John Frum
learned signals 252; microbial 236; cult 279; language 278; Mousterian
mimics 225, 250–251; pheromones 179, 275, 278; musical instruments 274–275;
203–204, 209; re-amplification 210; necklaces 279, 280, 279; ochre 275,
rule-based systems 253; seismic 141, 276; paintings 275, 281; Roman 281;
144, 190, 209–210; semantics 252; Solutrean 281; symbolic compositions
‘signature whistles’ 251; speech 194, 275; Szeletian 280; terracotta head 281;
251–252, 278; steroid signalling 295; transmission 258, 259–260, 261, 286;
subterranean mammals 141, 190–191; Uluzzian 280
symbolic 252–253, 258; syntax cuttlefish 214–215
252–253; termite 209–210; tutors 260; cyanobacteria 107, 113, 235, 287, 288,
vocal capabilities 278; vocalizations 352n6
223, 225–226, 249, 250–252, 258, n. 140/9; cytosine 13, 28, 29
whistles 250–251; ‘whistle matching’
251; Zipf’s law 334n5, 407n107, Darwinian selection 385n149, 441n91
421n127, 422n140 Deimos 349n72
conifers 137 developmental biology 238–242;
constructions (see also cultures, tools); appendages 179, 239; atonal gene 193;
ant-gardens 210; attine ant nests cervical vertebrae 239–240; distal-less
205–206, 206; birds’ nests 358n72; gene 179, 241–242; dorso-ventrality
bivouacs 201, 202; bowers 285–286; 239; eyes 239; heart 239; Hox gene
bridges 201, 401n32; ‘cartons’ 210, 214; 239; Math 1 gene 193; otd gene 242; otx
general index 449
Page numbers in italics indicate Figures. [Notes] are listed by [page number].