0% found this document useful (0 votes)
61 views2 pages

Arrows Externalities Model

Arrow showed that public goods allocation problems can be modeled as private goods problems by defining each individual's consumption of the public good as a distinct commodity. This allows Walrasian analysis to apply. Specifically, Arrow defined an economy with n+1 goods - the public good and n private goods representing each individual's consumption of the public good. While production involves "jointness" across the private goods, individuals can only consume their own private good. This transformed the problem into a standard Walrasian framework with Lindahl equilibria, but highlighted that taking prices as given is unrealistic since each individual is the sole demander of their private public good.

Uploaded by

Naresh Sehdev
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
61 views2 pages

Arrows Externalities Model

Arrow showed that public goods allocation problems can be modeled as private goods problems by defining each individual's consumption of the public good as a distinct commodity. This allows Walrasian analysis to apply. Specifically, Arrow defined an economy with n+1 goods - the public good and n private goods representing each individual's consumption of the public good. While production involves "jointness" across the private goods, individuals can only consume their own private good. This transformed the problem into a standard Walrasian framework with Lindahl equilibria, but highlighted that taking prices as given is unrealistic since each individual is the sole demander of their private public good.

Uploaded by

Naresh Sehdev
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 2

Arrow’s Walrasian Model

of Public Goods and Other Externalities

Arrow showed that we can recast the public-goods allocation problem as one involving
only private goods, so that our Walrasian analysis applies. Arrow defined each individual’s
consumption of the public good as a distinct commodity, with a distinct market and price,
but with “jointness” in the production of these goods. Here’s how this works in our one-
public-good-one-private-good model with n consumers (where X is the public good and Y is
the private good):

We redefine the economy as having n + 1 goods X1 , . . . , Xn , Y , with quantities denoted by


x1 , . . . , xn , y. An allocation is therefore an n(n + 1)-tuple

n(n+1)
(x11 , . . . , x1n , y 1 ), (x21 , . . . , x2n , y 2 ), . . . , (xn1 , . . . , xnn , y n ) ∈ R+

.

However, both the production possibilities and the consumption possibilities in this economy
are assumed to have a special character:

(1) The X-goods are “joint products” in any firm’s production process: A production plan
for a firm is an (n + 1)-tuple (z, q) = (z, q1 , . . . , qn ) ∈ Rn+1
+ , where z is the amount of the

private good the firm uses as input and qi is the output of commodity Xi , but the firm has the
technological constraint q1 = q2 = · · · = qn . This is exactly like the classical joint products
mutton and wool that are produced by raising sheep.

(2) Consumer i’s consumption set is {(xi1 , . . . , xin , y i ) ∈ Rn+1


+ | j 6= i ⇒ xij = 0} — i.e.,
Consumer i can consume only the goods Xi and Y . So while Consumer i’s utility function
ui is technically defined on the domain Rn+1 i
+ , we can more intuitively write u as defined

on bundles (xi , y i ) ∈ R2+ . Therefore we can simplify the notation, defining an allocation to
consumers as a 2n-tuple (xi , yi )n1 ∈ R2n
+ .

Now a Lindahl equilibrium is just a Walrasian equilibrium of this joint-product economy.


Specifically (and assuming for simplicity that there is just a single producer/firm, which is
p1 , . . . , pbn , pby ) ∈ Rn+1
a price-taker), a Walrasian equilibrium is a price-list (b + , a consumption

xi , ybi )n1 ∈ R2n


allocation (b z , qb1 , . . . , qbn ) ∈ Rn+1
+ and a production plan (b + that satisfy

(U-max) xi , ybi ) maximizes ui (xi , yi ) subject to pbi xi + yi 5 ẙi + θi π(b


∀i : (b z, q
b)

b) maximizes π(z, q1 , . . . , qn ) = ni=1 pbi qi − pby z subject to q1 = · · · qn = f (z)


P
(π-max) (b
z, q

zb + ni=1 ybi 5 ni=1 ẙi , with equality if pby > 0.


P P
(M-Clr) ∀i : x
bi = qbi and
Therefore the First Welfare Theorem applies: if the utility functions and production functions
satisfy the usual assumptions, then the equilibrium allocation will be Pareto efficient.

But Arrow’s model also makes it clear that the Walrasian models’s price-taking assumption
for consumers is unrealistic here: for each of the distinct goods Xi there is only one person
on the demand side of the market. The only person who cares about the good Xi is person
i. It’s clearly unrealistic to assume that any of the participants will take their own price (or
Lindahl cost share) as given. This was Arrow’s motivation for modeling things this way —
to clarify this point.

You might also like