Jeanluc Nancy A Finite Thinking
Jeanluc Nancy A Finite Thinking
Jeanluc Nancy A Finite Thinking
Jean-Lue Naney
Edited by Simon Sparks
Nancy, Jean-Luc.
A finite thinking / Jean-Luc Nancy ; edited by Simon Sparks.
p. cm. - (Cultural memory in the present)
Includes bibliographical references.
ISBN 0-8047-3900-5 (a1k. paper)-
ISBN 0-8047-3901-3 (pbk. : a1k. paper)
1. Thought and thinking-Philosophy. 2. Sense ( Philosophy)
3. Finite, The. 1. Sparks, Simon, 1970- n.Title. Ill.Series.
B2430.N363F56 2003
I94-DC2I
2003002090
I. THINKING
, 1. A Finite Thinking 3
..... 2. Concealed Thinking 31
Il. EXISTING
, 3 . The Unsacrificeable
" 4. The Indestructible
Ill. DIFFERENCE
"' 5. Elliptical Sense 91
" 6. Borborygmi II2
IV. JUDGING
7. The Kategorein of Excess 133
8. Lapsusjudicii
" 9. Originary Ethics
V. PLEASURE
10. The Kantian Pleasure System 199
H. The Sublime Offering 2II
... 12. Shattered Love 245
1 1 111111111 111111
BOGAZic;i
UNIvERSITESi
KUTUPHANESi
470355
Vlll Contents
VI. WORLD
CODA
, Res ipsa et ultima
3II
Notes
THINKING
1
A Finite Thinking
Does existence have a sense ?-this question required several centuries even to
be understood completely and in all its profundity.
-Friedrich Nietzsche, The Gay Science!
Because philosophy opens out Onto the whole of man and onto what is
highest in him, finitude must appear in philosophy in a completely radical
way.
-Martin Heidegger, ]{ant and the Problem ofMetaphysics 2
Sense [sens] is already the least shared thing in the world. But the
question of sense is already what we share, without any possibility of its be
ing held in reserve or avoided. So, the question of sense, then, or perhaps
we should say: rather more and rather less than a question,
. a concern,
maybe, a task, a chance. 3
Of course, by "sense" I mean sense in the singular, sense taken ab
solutely: the sense of life, of Man, of the woi:ld, of history, the sense of ex
istence; the sense of the existence that is or that makes sense, the existence
without which sense would not exist; equally, the sense that exists or pro
duces existing, without which there would be no sense.
The title "a finite thinking" puts three very simple things into play:
on the one hand, it denotes that there is, for us, a thinking that's finished,
a mode of thinking that has been lost with the destruction of sense, that is,
with the completion and buckling of the West's resources of signification
and meaning (God, History, Man, Subject, Sense itself . .. ). And yet, in
its accomplishment and withdrawal, like a crashing wave whose ebb leaves
behind the lines of a new high-tide mark, this thinking leaves us with a
new configuration (its own, then its own undoing of itself at its own limit).
Equally, it suggests that a thinking equal to the significance of the end has
come our way, if I can pur it in this way, a thinking that has first of all to
measure itself against the fact that "sense" could have ended and that it
could be a question of sense's essential finitude-s�mething that would, in
turn, demand an essential finitude of thinking. In fact, and this is the third
thing raised by the title, whatever the content or the sense of what I am
calling "finitude" (and this collection of essays is concerned with nothing
else, even though it's a long way from being a treatise on the subject), we
A Finite Thinking
can at least be sure that any attempt to think such an "object" is going to
have to marry its form or condition, while also being a finite thinking: a
thinking that, without renouncing truth or universality, without renounc
ing sense, is only ever able to think to the extent that it also touches on its
own limit and its own singularity. How are we to think everything-sense
as a whole, even though it's not as if we could not do so, sense being .indi
visible-in a thinking, withiri the limit of one trifling study? And how are
we to think the fact that this limit is the limit of the whole of sense?
I've no direct answer to this, so let me simply affirm a necessity: "the
working out of the innermost essence of finitude must itself always be fun
damentally finite."4
W'hat is sense? What is the "sense" of the word "sense" and what is
the reality of this thing "sense"? What is the concept? What is the referent?
What immediately springs to mind is that the concept and the referent
must be one and the same here, since it's as a concept (or, if you like, as an
idea or a thought) that this "thing" exists. Sense is the concept of the con
cept. We can analyze this concept as signification, u�derstanding, mean'"
ing, and so forth.5 But �hat is implied, articulated, and exploited in all
these analyses is that the concept in question, across its entire extension
and the whole of its meaning, can't simply be the concept (or the sense) of
something that would stay put, set within an exterior reality, without any
intrinsic relation to its concept (at least in the way in which we tend to un
"
derstand the relation of a stone or a force to its concept). The concept of
sense implies that sense is being grasped or is grasping itself as sense. This
mode, this gesture of grasping or graSping itself as sense, is what produces
sense, the sense of all sense: like a concept that would itself have the stony
quality of the stone or the force of force, its concept and its referent are in
dissociable. (And it's this that's the absolute of sense at the very horizon of
every metaphysics of Knowledge and of the Word, of Philosophy and Po
etry.) Sense is only what it is in itself, if it is, indeed, "to itself."
The same goes for the other sense of the word "sense," for its sensible
sense: to sense is necessarily to sense that there is something like sensation.
Sensing senses nothing if it doesn't sense itself sensing, just as understand
ing understands nothing if it doesn't understand itself understanding. The
"other" sense of the word sense is only "other" in terms of this sameness.6
6 THINKING
All of which leads to a chiasmus: what senses in sense is the fact that it in
cludes what it senses, and what produces sense in sense is the fact that it
senses itself producing sense. Of course, we can always object that in this
way we have merely pushed back ad infinitum the question of the sense of
sense, or that, in this oxymoronic game, where nothing tells us what it
might mean "to sense sense" or "to understand sensing," we have even lost
any possibility of posing it.
It's doubtless no coincidence that this double aporia refers us back to
the most powerful distinction that philosophy has to offer: that between
the sensible and the intelligible. Moreover, we could easily show that there
is no philosophy, no poetry, which hasn't claimed, in one way or another,
to have overcome, dissolved, or rendered dialectical this double aporia.
This is always going to be the most extreme point of metaphysics I men
tioned a moment ago. The task that follows philosophy, our task, is the
same, altered only-bur altered in truly unlimited fashion-by the end of
sense?
. To say that being is open isn't to say that it's first this or that and
then, over and above this, marked or distinguished by openness. Being is
open-and this is what I'm trying to establish in terms of the being of
sense or in terms of being -to -the self-only in this openness as such; it
is itself the open. In the.same way, the self that is to-itself by and in alter
ity doesn't possess this (�other" as a correlate or as the term of a relation
that would happen to "relate" to itself Thought rigorously, it is not a mat
ter of "other" or of "relation." Rather, it is a matter of a diaresis or a dis
section of the "self " that precedes not only via every relation to the other
but also via every identity of the self In this diaresis, the other is already
the same, but this "being" isn't confusion, still less a fusion; no, it is the
being-other of the self as neither "self " nor "other," nor as some founding
or original relation between them. It is less than and more than an origin;
it is the to-itself as the appropriation of what cannot be appropriated in its
to-being-of its sense.
The self that lies at the origin of this being, appropriating its own
end (such is, or appears to be, the Hegelian and philosophical Self in gen
eral, even if it somehow manages to dilute this appropriation, whether in a
8· THINKING
A simple, hard, and difficult thought; then. One that appears to run
counter to all thinking. Yet one, too, that thinking knows-understands
and senses-in the same way that it thinks what lies within itself A
thought that appears to be in permanent rebellion as much against any
possibility of discourse, judgment, or signification as against intuition, evo
cation, or incantation. Yet one, too, that is only present by way of those
discourses or words that it violates-whose violence it is. This is why we
call this thought "writing," that is, the inscription of this violence and of
the fact that, through it, all sense is excribed [excrit] ceaselessly refuses to
'
come back to itself, and that all thinking is the finite thinking of these in
finite excesses.
A thought that is devoted to the thinking of a single sense, then,
since it's clear that there cannot be several senses, hierarchies, situations, or
conditions more or less "full" or more or less worthy of sense. (We'll come
back to the notion of evil, the self-suppression of sense.) What is essential
to this sense, however, always assuming that there is an "essence," absolute
sense in its absoluteness and its singularity, is that it neither grasps nor
presents its unity or its oneness. This "single" sense has neither unity nor
oneness: it is (the) "single" sense (of "a single" being) because it is sense
A Finite Thinking 9
each time. It's not sense "in general," therefore, nor is it sense once and for
all. If it were, it would be completed, reabsorbed, and senselessly insane.
Infinite and insane.
Finitude designates the "essential" multiplicity and the "essential"
nonteabsorption of sense or of being. In other words, if it is as existence
and only as existence that being comes into play, it designates the without
essence of existing: "When being is posited as infinite, it is precisely then
that it is determined. If it is posited as finite, it is then that its absence of
ground is affirmed."1O Here I transcribe groundlessness (Abgritndlichkeit) as
"sense." Groundlessness isn't a lack on the part of being that needs to be
undergone, justified, originated. Rather, it is being's reference to nothing,
either to substance or to subject, not even to "being," unless it be to a
being-to, to itself, to the world as the openness, the throw or the being
thrown qf existence.
More rigorously still: being isn't Being; it's neither substantive nor
substance. "Being" is only being, the verb-at least insofar as we can
desubstantialize the verb itself, destabilize grammar. And not the intransi
tive verb that language gives us, but the intransitive verb "be-ing," which
doesn't actually exist: 11 "being a being," in the same way that we talk about
"doing or founding or eating a being," but in such a way that it transmits
no quality or property, in such a way that it transmits itselfalone, trans
mitting to the being in question nothing other than this to of transmission,
the being-to of sense, giving existence being as sense. Not, however, in the
sense of the "meaning" or the "sense of being" as a content of signification,
but in the sense of the being-sense of being. Not, therefore, "giving" it per
se, being merely the to--the presentation, tension, direction, abandon
ment-of an offering that, with a single stroke, without any ground what
'
soever, makes a being "indebted" to or puts it in excess of its own exis
tence, having to be (existence, the self ), having to appropriate itself as the
inappropriable character of the groundlessness that would have been its be
ing, both more and less than an origin.
"Finitude" doesn't mean that the totality of sense isn't given and that
we must defer (or abandon) the appropriation to the point of infinity, but
that all sense
resides in the nonappropriation of "being," whose existence
' ,
priation (to itself ) of there being no sense to this senseless sense. This is, for
example, what a thought of death means when, rather than thinking that
death gives sense, it thinks that sense makes sense because death suspends
its appropriation and appropriates the inappropriable character of being
to, which is itself no longer to anything else. Let me put it another way:
what carries the whole weight of thinking, in an expression lik.e zum Tode
sein,being-toward- (or to-) �eath,n isn't death but the toward or the to,
"death" merely indicating that this toward or this to is maintained, as a
structure of being, "up to the end"�which is always the absence of any
"end," of any extremity at which the infinite circle of an insane appropria
tion might be completed. Being-to ''t�nds up" being-to, something that's
neither a circle nor a tautology, still less an appeal to any morbid heroism
and, "less still, an invitation to turn death into the mark of a mission or a
service. It is appropriated death that is senseless. Sense is existence that is
always being horn and always dying (being born is dying). All of which
doesn't take anything away from the hardness of death, from anxiety before
it. Nothing that I have said brings either consolation or compensation.
Rather, it simply indicates that, in finitude, there is no question of an
"end," whether as a goal or as an accomplishment, and that it's merely a
question of the suspension of sense, in-finite, each time replayed, re
opened, exposed with a novelty so radical that it immediately fails,.
The new, as the very event of sense, eludes itself. I can never say:
"Look, here, thus, the sense of my existence." By saying it, testing it out,
even, I'm already steering sense in the direction of an accomplishment. Yet
the very thing that eludes it, or the eluding that sense itself is, is something
that we have always already understood. Essentially, a finite thinking of
finitude is a thinking of the fact that we, as beings, from the m�ment that
we exist, have already "understood" the finitude of being. An ontology of
finite being describes nothing less than "what all of us, as men, always and
already understand."13 "
"Understand" doesn't mean grasping a determinate concept but en
tering into ( already being within) the very dimension of "understanding,"
that is, relating to some particular sense. It means being born to the element
of sense in the singular mode of its presence. Being born properly means
coming to a presence whose present has already escaped, is already missing
A Finite Thinking II
from the "coming to." But it is still a matter of coming. And, in this com
ing, of "understanding," of having already "understood" the coming-pres
ence or the presence-to of existence. Of l:Jeing that comes into the world;
of being that comes into sense. And being, too, that comes to sense [ au
sentir] as sense
[comme au sentir] . I can't sayany more here than what I've
already said regarding the aporetic nexus of the sense of "sense." Other
than that, it doubles the "already" of Heidegger's "already understood." We
have already understood because we have already sensed; we have already
sensed because we have understood. Or, rather, we have already come into
sense because we are already in the world; we are in the world because we
are in sense. One opens the other-this is all that is "understood."
Sense is existence in this ontological priority, whence it is reached
and whence it fails, whence it reaches its failing point. How can we turn
away from this hard, striking, obscure point? Birth has already turned us
toward it. But how can we simply open our eyes? Death has already closed
them. To obey this double constraint-the very absolute of existence-is
to enter into a finite thinking.
Or, rather, it is to enter into the finite character of all thinking be
cause, in truth, no one is unaware of this point, which lies at the heart of
all philosophy, however "metaphysical" it may be. Not a single thinker has
thought, if they have thought anything at all, without thinking this. All
that remains for us is to think this finite character as such and without in
finitizing it. This task is as finite as any other. Equally, it's certain. Yet this
doesn't mean that we have some knowledge of its accomplishment. Every
one asks: "What should we think?" (at least they. will, so long as they don't
prefer the injunction: "Don't think too much!"). Well, what we have to
think is this: that thought is never given, neither at the beginning nor at
the end. From which it follows that it is never "giveable" as such. There'�
not an "ounce" of sense that could be either received or transmitted: the
finitude of thinking is indissociable from the singularity of "understand
ing" what is, each time, a singular existence. (All of which isn't to say that
there's nothing that we might think "in common,'" as it were. I will come
back to this.)
12 THINKING
ing" does not rest on the foundation of an essence but uniquely responds to
and ftom the there is of "being." In other words, it is a matter of responding
to and ftom oneself as the exi1!ting of an existence. Finitude is the responsi
bility ofsense, and is so absolutely. Nothing else.
And so I would also want to add: finitude is the sharing of sense.
That is, sense takes place on every occasion of existence alone, on every
singular occasion of its response-responsibility; but this also means that
sense is the lot, the share of existence, and that this share is divided be
tween all the singularities of existence. (From which it follows that there is
no sense that could engage merely one being; from the outset, community
is, as such, the engagement of sense. Not of a collective sense, but of the
sharing of finitude.)
'I"::' "
16 THINKING
wickedness}.21 It does not come from outside and it is not something less
than being; rather, existence is unleashed against itself. Here, evil affirms it
self and affirms its (metaphysical, political, or technological) right. It
seems-and this is a new thought-that existence can grasp its own being
as the essence and hence as the destruction of existence and, moreover, as
the senseless insanity that closes off the aspect of existence that opens onto
.to the need for sense. Extermination doesn't just exterminate en masse or
totally; it exterminates "distress" itself. After all, the two go hand in hand:
the immensity of the mutder bringing about the negation of the singular
ity of each instance of "distress" and each "necessity" of sense; it is the
negation of the "eachness" of sense, of being-toward-self.
So from now on, we have to stay with the following implacable, per
haps even revolting, thought: finitude is so radical that it is 'equally the
opening of this possibility in which sense self-destructs. Finitude is sense as
it absents itself, up to the point where, for· a single, decisive moment, in
sanity is indistinguishable from the sense that is lacking. (No doubt we
ought also to ask: has this ultimately taken place? If it has, wouldn't every
thing already have been destroyed? But then our question would have to
be: hasn't everything already been destroyed? And if it is not, if beirig-to
ward-sense resists, and resists absolutely (and if it didn't, who would be left
to have the "sense" of "evil"?), it resists at that very realpoint where insan
ity becomes indiscernible from the sense that is lacking.)
To discern within this indiscernible: that is what freedom ultimately
boils down to. To discern senselessness without the help of 5ense,22 not
with nothing to hand, to be sure, but with that part of (the being of ) exis
tence that we already have in Out grasp. To be deprived of rules, without
being deprived of truth.
It is in this sense alone, then, that an ethics is possible. What this
means is that we can't fall back on an ethics of "misfortune" or an ethics of
"sickness," whose use can, for us, only ever be analogical and provisional.
It has to be a matter of an ethics of evil as wickedness. This doesn't require
the norm or value of some "good" or other; the access of existence to its
real sense is not a "value" that we could promise to the infinity of a good
will. Precisely because this access can never be appropriated as a "good,"
but because it is the being of existence, it is and has t� be presented in ex
istence as existence. Here, "having-to-be" is the form taken by "be�ng,"
since this being is to-be. But "duty" doesn't point to the infinite realization
of a "kingdom of ends." Instead, it obligates freedom; or, more accurately,
18 THINKING
The "philosopher"· who talks about "sense" is, along with his
thought, nothing other than a material singularity (a packet of "sel).se," a
place, a time, a point in history, a play of forces), who cannot, after all,
guarantee that we are any nearer to the "sense" that is in question. The
thinking of finitude is itself afinite thinking because it has no means of ac
cess to what it thinks, not even through thinking that it has no such access.
There is no privileged "speculative" or "spiritual" order in the experience of
sense. Yet existence alone, insofar as it is, hic et nunc, is this experience. And
the latter, always and each time, is an absolute "privilege," which, as such,
misidentifies itself qua "privilege" and qua "absolute." There's nothing to
say about when or how such an existence exists. ("To write"-and I will
come back to this-is to say this not-saying.)
But there still has to be something or some "one" who can exist.
Some being must be, hie et nunc. Existing is a here and now of being, it is
to be a here -and now of being. There are conditions in which this is not
possible-and even if existence, undoubtedly, always and without end, re
sists, even though it resists to the very end and beyond, and even though we
can never simply say "this life has no meaning," there are still circum
stances in which beings are not only abandoned, but in which they are, as
it were, stripped of the conditions of existence. When this happens, beings
are the pure instrument or object of a production, of a history, process, or
system, always deported in advance from the here and now, always and
only in the elsewhere and in the afterward of hunger, fear, and survival, or
of wages, savings, and accumulation.
All the same, not being expropriated by the hic et nunc doesn't mean
that we appropriate it for ourselves. There's no symmetry. Hie et nunc
means merely to exist; it is finite existing "itself." Granted, we can never
say that "this life" or "this moment ofIife" "makes no sense." But precisely
because we can't decide with respect to sense, we can't decide-we can
least of all decide-'-that all conditions are the same. Yes, every existence is
in sense; but no one can consequently decide that the condition of possi
bilityfor certain existences is and has to be a sacrijiceof life (of all forms of
"life"). Since the here-and-now is finitude, the inappropriability of sense,
every appropriation of the "here" by an "elsewhere:: and of the "now" by
an "afterward" (or by a "beforehand") is and does evil
How are we to decide what makes a "here and now" possible and to
decide what does not "alienate"? Nothing and no one can decide this. Each
time, however, a here and now, an existing, must be able to decide to be,
20 THINKING
and to be open to sense. Each time, being has to be allowed to be, delivered
and abandoned to its finitude.
- Is this any different from the reputedly "normal" conditions for the
exercise of basic freedoms, which presuppose life itself and a few other
guarantees? In a sense, it is not-today, at least, and for us. But it must be
so in that this "leaving," this "abandonment," is presented to beings as
their very finitude. That is to say, the gesture doesn't refer to a horizon of
"visions of the world" and of "man," one in which an essence and a sense
would already be decided and within which would be exercised the "free
choice" of a "subject," actually already "alienated" by this horizon. On the
one hand, there are basic conditions (on which civilization wreaks constant
havoc) whose empirical basis is also the "transcendental" of the here and
now of existence. On the other, there is this: in letting the finite being be,
jinitude as such must be indicated.
This demands an altogether different thinking of "alienation" or "ex
propriation" (or indeed of "exploitation"). Altogether different, yet just as
uncompromising as that of Marx when faced with the "primitive accumu
lation " of capital.
"Alienation" has often been represented as the dispossession of an
original authenticity which ought to be preserved or restored. The critique
of this notion of an original propriety, an authentic plenitude or reserve,
contributed, in large part, to the disappearance of alienation as a figure for
the loss or theft of man's original and ownmost self-production. In fact, ex
istence is not self-productive, even if it isn't the product of something else.
This is also what jinitu�e means. Nevertheless, it remains the case, as we
have seen, that beings can have their condition or conditions of existence
expropriated: their strength, labor, body, senses, and perhaps even the
space-time of their singularity. Equally, it's true that this is still happening
and is part of extermination as we've just described it, and that "capital" or
the "global market" only endutes and prospers by a massive expropriation
of this sort (and today, above all, of the South by the North, even though
we know that this isn't the only expropriation of its kind). It isn't a ques
tion, therefore, of giving up the struggle, but of determining in what name
we carry it on, in what name we desire the continued existence of beings.
Up until now, the struggle has been guided by the regulative idea of the
(original and final) self-production of man and, at the same time, by a gen
eral and generic concept of this "man." Undoubtedly the conditions of
struggle are going to change if that struggle must now be thought with ref
erence to finitude and its singularities. Access to finite sense does not pre-
A Finite Thinking 21
ing to presence of absent sense, sense coming to its absence, to the absent
ing of all presence and any present. It is a question, furthermore, of a
'
mimesis that one could try calling mimesis of appresentation, on condition
that one hears in the prefix the sense of spacing,. of distance." " Presenta-
. . . . .
" cr
A Finite Thinking 25
artisan and life in the fields (an old refrain, as old as our history), this
would be a matter of thinking the following: that all technology, over and
above the technology that it is, and in being the technology that it is, con
tains an implicit knowledge of sense as finitude, and of the sense of fini
rude. Nothing, perhaps, better bears this out than the questions, demands,
and undecidabilities which subtend the decisions that have to be taken,
each day, by the technicians of biological, ecological, energetic, and urban
manipulation.
and dislocation of the five senses and the sixth, that of the concept. A
schematism which does not return to the homogeneous. A "hidden art" for
which no secret is any longer to be awaited.
No doubt, an "art" (a "technique") is always the clear consciousness
(if it is a "consciousness") of the splitting and sharing of sense and the
senses, of their absolute difference and of the very sense of what it displays.
However, a finite thinking cannot be an aestheticizing thinking, nor aes
thetic in the sense in which every thought of the beautiful, and even of the
'I
sublime, has insisted, up until now, on extending to infinity (imprison
ment, revelation, or secret) the arc of finitude.
A finite thinking follows this outline: only to retrace it. A finite
thinking does not add to existence the seal or confirmation of its sense. It
simply takes up the challenge of that wb,ich "we understand already and
without end":. the being that we are. Thinking, here, is coextensive with ex
isting, and consists in thinking this thought: that being-for-itself does not
turn back on itself. This doesn't mean that it would be enough to "exist"
(to be there, in the most banal sense of the term) in order to think, or that
thinking (in the banal sense of forming representations) is sufficient for ex
isting. It means, rather, that the fact of existence cannot be its own truth,
which is to be the fact of a sense--and that the concept and the significa
tion of sense cannot be its own truth, which is to be the sense of this fact.
It means that existence must be thought, and thought existence, in order
that it is-'--in order, simply, to be.
We bump up against an empty circularity here, in which the mean
ing of each of these words evaporates. In truth, though, meaAing or signi
fication is being exhausted here. Here, words are no longer j�st words, lan
guage is no longer just language. It touches its limit, and displays it. There
is no longer "sense" as the meeting-point of all these meanings. In the same
way, there is no concept as the auto-conception of the concept, nor as the
presentation of a "thing in itself" And man is not the auto-production of
his essence. But sense is the sharing and splitting of language thanks to
which language does not complete itself (n9r initiate itself ): the difference
between languages, double articulation, the differance of sense, the sharing
of voices, writing, its exscription.
Yet here we discover that thought, which is language, is, however, not
language. Not because it is "something else" (something fuller, more pres
ent), but because language itself, in "essence," is not what it is, does not
confer the sense that it endlessly promises. A finite thinking inhabits, .
A Finite Thinking 29
writes (in) the finitude that language is, which it displays or exposes. We
could say, then, that a finite thinking makes itself adequate to the existence
it thinks. But this adequation is itselffinite, and it is there that access to the
missing sense, or its inappropriation, obtains.
How can and must this thought, given over as it is to what is not
sense [remise au pas-de-sens] as its ownmost object, be written? This is what
it does not and cannot know, and what it must invent for itself each time
a single invention alone is possible, all discourse being suspended.
Very quickly, we are threatened by the unbearable preposterousness
of "doctrine." The more we repeat "finite thinking," the more we risk con
juring up the specter of a "system." Or, more simply, the pitiful shadow of
the "answer to all questions." But it's precisely "answers to all questions"
that have saturated us and worn us out. No, "finitude" isn't a new response
or a new question. It is, as I've already said, a responsibility before the not
sense that affects all sense, before what has to be and has to constitute our
sense. A responsibility of thinking taken to the limit of all our meanings
and; consequently, also, as I have continually been trying to show here, the
meaning of "finitude." There is no sense .of the words "end" and "finite"
that would 'allow us to think that whose index, held out at the very limit of
our history, bears the name "finitude"-or the name the absolute ofexis
tence. There can be no doctrine or system here. Only rigor.
It's no accident that contemporary philosophy-especially in its
French singularity-has done its thinking with a formidable mobilization
of language �d writing (often called "rhetoric" or "affectation" by those
who are oblivious to the epoch and don't feel the heaviness and difficulty
of thinking). Once again, as happens with every great rupture of sense,
philosophy no longer writes in the same way. Nor does poetry. Perhaps
"philosophy" or "poetry" will no longer be written as such. These illim
itable words carry the entire weight of a question of sense, and most of all
carry the proposition that a "question" of finite sense isn't a question that
could be articulated in terms of sense, even as we can't disarticulate it in
terms of some non-sense. Hence, it's not even a question. Not "What is fi
nite sense?" but simply, "The finitude of being suspends the ' sense of that
which is sense." How do we write that?
Rimbaud: How to act, 0 stolen heart?
There is real disappointment here, and suffering: and this is why
thinking is hard. But the disappointment comes from waiting and from
expectation, and there's waiting and expectation because there is, already,
30 THINKING
sense. This isn't a promise that might or. might not be kept. Nothing is
promised to existence. Hence disappointment itself is sense.
This is what has to be thought, therefore. And it is not absurd. It
makes or constitutes existence (as well as community, history, and free
dom). Blit thinking "it through brings thought to an end: only a finite
thinking can take the measure of this extremity. The part of finite sense
that is left over is only vestigial and fragmentary. There is nothing to record
and take down; that's what sense is; that's all, end of story. We've always al- "
ready said too much, thought too much. Yet we've never said enough, be
cause each time it starts all over again. And what is this "each time" of ex
istence? A "here and now" ? What is a birth, or a death, a singular coming
to presence? How many times does this take place in a life? In a history?
And how many times in a community? And what is the "one" in a com
munity? The event of sense, insofar as it is lacking, is neither the continu
ity of a substance nor the discrete rarity of an exception. It is being, the
thinking of which is the ontological ethics of this "neither . . . nor," held in
strict abeyance, unsublated, above the abyss.
Here, thinking burrows back to its source. It knows this source, its
very being, as what is, in itself, neither thought, unthought, no� unthink
able, but the finite sense of existing. Thinking burrows back to its source
and so, as thought, opens it and drains once again as it both gathers and
scatters it. Thought has to think itself as what loses itself in thinking-nec
essarily, if the sense that it thinks is the sense of innumerable finitudes and
appropriations of nothing.
We might be tempted to · write: "If a. finite thinking never sees the
light of day, ifit doesn't find its voice in writing, then we will have failed to
think our own times." As if, in such an injunction; we knew and antici
pated an essence of finite thinking, with its form, if not its norm. But no,
a finite thinking is already working, or un-working, already prior and al
ready posterior to what we can say about it, here or elsewhere. It's written
here, but before and after this "here," finishing it off already, and not yet.
Already for yesterday and tomorrow making and carrying sense away-a
thinking that can no longer impose itself, nor even propose itself, but that
must, with all its resources, expose itselfto what is finite about sense. Mul
tiple and each time singular-.what is a "time" or "occasion" of thinking?
what is a thought?-hard, entrenched, as material as this line of ink, but
still fugitive, a finite thinking. Just one.
Translated by Edward Bullard,
Jonathan Derbyshire, and Simon Sparks
2
Concealed Thinking
give them a sense of the necessary effort and audacity of thinking itself. For
all that, however, this thinking does not sink into the pathos of skepticism
or of heroism; rather, it envisages directly the primitive and final fact of a
thinking secured by nothing outside its own freedom (neither "God" nor
"total man," nothing; then, ifwe can say that . . . ); there is no thinking, no
articulation of sense, that doesn't have something of the uncompleteable
about it, that doesn't exceed sense, like an intimation, a binding, implaca..;
ble obligation, logical as much as ethical, to conceal itself as thinking in the
very act of thinking "in order," if you'll allow me to risk the phrase, to be
thinking ("in order to make sense" and "in order to free itself"-and ifI'm
talking about "risk," it's simply in order to avoid the risk of introducing
any hint of a finality).
In the wake of the same era and the same difficulty inherent in Marx
ism thought as final liberation, both Sartre and Bataille are after what has
become necessary-what has become necessity itself-ever since truth
showed itself to reside neither in the heavens nor in the morrow, namely,
to affirm truth here and now, to be capable of a truth afthe here and now,
of us, therefore, in our world. In Sartre's own words, it is a matter of think.
ing the fact that "truth is action, my free act. Truth is not true if it is not
lived and done."2
f"!-ct that, so far as truth is concerned, Bataille doesn't disavow the term
"lived experience." (I'm not about to follow the texts, even though one
could; here, I'm not really interested in philology.) What he means by this,
though,. is the "lived experience" of a cessation of what goes under the
name "lived expedence"-we might be tempted to say: a "deadening of ex
perience" [un mouru] , if this didn't introduce a tonality that is undeniably
false and if, moreover, the "deadening of experience" weren't precisely the
concept of an insurmountable contradiction.
So let us say the same thing in a slightly different way. It is a matter
of "not-knowing" and so of nothing less than the entire modern experience
of thinking. Indeed, since Kant, a not-knowing lies at the very heart of
thinking. And already in Kant, as in Hegel and Heidegger and so also in
Sartre and Bataille, the site of not-knowing is called "freedom." Sartre en
visages not-knowing literally (and this, too, could be shown in the texts).
Yet he also says the following, a remark cited by Bataille in his response to
Sartre: "Bataille refuses to see that not-knowing is immanent to thinking.
A thinking that thinks that it does not know is still a thinking."3
Bataille doesn't challenge Sartre on this point. But the question here
is one of knowing (or of not-knowing . . . ) how to think a thinking that is
still a thinking even when its content is not-knowing.
Perhaps there's nothing more impoi:tant than thinking this "still
thinking," if it is true that we are, even more immediately than either
Sartre or Bataille realized, at an extremity where the movement of knowing
meticulously traces the contour of not-knowing. ..
Hence, when we say that the thinking of not-knowing is still a think
ing, we can also and before anything else understand by this a sustained
identity of thinking, of its subject (and this is what Sartre actually empha
sizes). In fact, though, we do so only at the· cost of seeing not-knowing it
self as an object, one that is identical to knowing: its negative identity, its
lack or its impossibility. Now this is precisely what needs to be called into
question: if not-knowing is the negative side of knowing, it marks a limit
or a powerlessness beyond whiCh the position of knowing still remains de
jure possible (future knowing or divine knowing, for example). If a final
knowing is possible, the totality of being will ultimately need to be gath
ered somewhere as the appropriated knowledge of some subject (albeit be
ing itself). Hence, somewhere, a truth subsists, at least virtually, and a 6-
nal ground for things is established.
Now, this is not what Bataille means when he speaks about non-
.
Concealed Thinking 37
The fact that thinking has no content doesn't mean that it is empty.
Or, if it does, the emptiness in question is a substantial emptiness: not a pit
or an abyss into which thinking slides, but the night, as Bataille likes to put
it, the night into which we advance and sink by seeing obscurity, itself the
privation of sight [vue] .
If thinking is generally represented as sight, what is involved here is
its representation as the sight of nothing rather than a nothingness of sight.
It is the sight of nothing, at any rate, of no object or content. Its sight is
nothing other than its penetration into the night. But what it sees as the
.'i,.
38 THINKING
night into which it penetrates is also itself: seeing nothing, and seeing that
it sees nothing, it sees tlie faculty or the power of seeing reduced to itself
Not, however, in the sense that it would be turned back on itself; the
night stands before it and presents it with sight that doesn't see anything
but merely sees. Neither self-presence in itself nor self-objectification, but
concealeq sight, sight �ubtracted but not suppressed, abducted, stolen, or
destroyed, diversified and presented as such. There's nothing to be seen,
and so neither sight itself nor a cont��dod ofthe subject in, the object, but
the power of seeing stretched to its limit, sdmulated by being concealed
; j
from sight. I (
.. !)
1
"To be concealed" is to take by sutprise, unexpectedly. Thinking
wOQ't have anticipated what is concealed, what conceals itself from think
ing but, in doing so, also conceals thinking from itself Knowing doesn't
andcipate not-knowing. Yet if knowing holds rigorously to what moves
it-to its ultimate ground, to truth and the sense or meaning of being-
•.
Concealed Thinking 39
40 THINKING
opening itself to it. And yet, essentially obscure and devoid of all founda
tion, all it opens is its closure; it leads onto the night. But it still leads; it
still opens.
Nakedness discloses the fact that "truth takes place only in passing
from one to anothd'5 (and Bataille offers a little clarification of the point:
"it begins with conversations, shared laughter, friendship, eroticism").
Night or nakedness, insofar as they give nothing to be seen, give this: the
fact that sense only gives itself by passing from one to another. In this pas
sage, sense is concealed from the "one" as much as it is from "the other." As
such, it is devoid of any sense of appropriation. Likewise, and this is actu
ally the same thing, language is what it is only between us. There is no pri
vate language. And yet, between us, there is nothing, certainly nothing .
upon which we might confer a signification without the immediate threat
of suffocation (whether the signification is that of the mystical body, com
munal race, etc., or the mutual surveillance of all too clear-sighted looks,
the "hell of other people" as Sartre has it, and between the contrasting fig
ures of himself and Bataille lies the formidable modern worry over the "be
tween-us" that conceals itself).
not see, offering the nakedness of a thinking that knows that it is con
cealed: unaccomplishing, unable to stop, unable to communicate anything
but still communicating this: the fact that thinking no longer responds to
anything, despite" its being the very movement of responding (of giving ac
counts, of giving grounds or reasons). When I read Bataille or Hegel, Des
cartes or Rimbaud, I'm always reading the fact that they're not responding
to me in any way whatsoever, that each one of them provides me with a
sense, a ground, or a reason for no more than an unstable and tenable in..:
stant (so long as I don't look to fix it in an imaginary response, in a doctri
nal lesson, in a belief). Essentially, each of them hands over to me [me passe
le relais] or, as we say, passes me the baton [le temoin] of sense. And it is
here, in this passage alone, that there is such a thing as sense.
Equally, though, the passage is a concealment, since it maintains its
sense only in this incessant passing into the other-in me outside of me to
the other. But this is the truth of sense. To seize is to seize a chance. Chance
is a nakedness,6 "it waits for us to undress it."7 This has the sense of seizure
and surprise, but it also has the sense of an anxious, feverish anticipation
that has to know that it cannot simultaneously wait and desire, since seizing
has to come as a surprise if it is to surprise chance. This agitation, this anx
iety, is the agitation and anxiety of thinking in the night that conceals it.
What is at stake here, however, is nothing more than this: chance sig
nifies that the passage doesn't obey an external necessity. It is the effect nei
ther of a transcendental law nor of the willing of a principle or an end nor
of the totalization, however tendentious it may be, of a history. Rather, it is
the absence of such a necessity that turns away from knowing. Not-know
ing is the not-knowing of the freedom of sense-that is to say, of the ne-'
cessity of chance.
Concealed Thinking 43
but the same insistence followed right to the end: to the point of account
ing for an extremity that can no longer be accounted for. Yes, it is still a
thinking; but it is one that confronts the excess of this "still."
The point of such an excess-the point of the leap, of the throw, of
shock, surprise, the point of thinking's passage to still thinking, the cross
ing over from the "still" in the sense of "in the same way' to a "still" in the
sense of a "moreover," to the still other or the still further-is the point of
concealment, the extremity at which we can think along the lines of con
cealment, thinking having already passed into the other, having already '
been absorbed by this other sense that gives it the other, but that also works
to finish off-or to begin completely anew�every conceivable sense of
the other, in excess of sense, the "flip side of all thinking. "9
In the intimacy of this excess, thinking turns back on itself; which
also means that it exposes itself to its absolure outside: the twisting and
tearing that define thinking itself, the double still of thinking. This think
ing loses itself and still thinks this loss, yet it still loses this thinking in such
a way that it no longer exists either as a thinking of loss (a philosophy of
non-sense, of grinding doubt, of nostalgia or cruel irony) or as a 1l?ss of
thinking (delirium, orgiastic delight, the paralysis of consciousness). It
doesn't exist at all, either positively or negatively, and yet it insists in the
night as an "illumination:"lo All this, though, is only the night's illumina
tion of itsel£
ity, one that is unsustainable, yes, but also ecstatic, and that is also to say:
transported, carried away, uplifted.Bataille always ends up understanding
. the mystical as a way of getting a result, getting there by virtue (and/or by
the calculation) of a -tnethod, a desired approach.Yet thinking can only be
. concealed insofar as it doesn't wish for what doesn't await it, insofar as it
doesn't calculate its arrival time, even simply in ord�r to abandon it.
This happens by not happening [cette venue vient comme ne venant
pas] . It is "what doesn't happen,"ll identical in this regard to being, simply
and as a whole.It runs alongside being and the event of being, but resem
bles it only by way of a concealed resemblance.It is, moreover, the con
cealment of all resemblance and thus of all identification.The arrival can
in no way offer its own concealment as the event of being, which, in fact,
lies outside or on the other side of the point at which it conceals itself
There's no vision here, then-merely the disappearance of vision.It's not a
matter of seeing, therefore, but of looking, of the eye opening onto the im
penetrable night. Here, there is only the imperceptible exhaustion of
thinking, sliding outside itself, a slippage, therefore, the minute and deci
sive slippage between what is still a matter of vision and what is still a look,
still blind.If we're going to think what is brought into play here, we're go
ing to have to elaborate the intimate difference, minute but also absolute,
between vision and look.
No doubt we will have to be attentive to this slippage if we are going
to give it its chance.Yet the only thinking that is able to think it is one that
has made the initial resolve to surrender to it but that has in no way re
nounced the demand of thinking, of thinking rigorously.And yet the sys
tem of this rigor does not construct itself in terms of means and end, in
struments and productions, principles and consequences. It can't, since
here means and ends, method and knowing, are confused: the not-know
ing in which thinking slides outside itself-in itself outside itself-is iden
tical to the exact coincidence of thinking and its flip side.Put differently:
of thinking and the thing that is being thought.Put differently again: not
knowing is identical to truth.
As has already been said, this truth lies in the other.It takes place as
communication to the other from out of an opening of sense that doesn't
refer back to me and of which I see simply the nocturnal void.I enter into
death or I enter into the other, it's all the same.I enter at the point at which
I cannot enter as the subject of my intention and its objects (neither theo
retical intentionality nor practical will), and so I look without seeing [jen-
Concealed Thinking 45
tre en regardant sans voir] . The "subject," if there is one, is a subject of this
look, not of a representation, concept, signification, or figuration . . .
If the end is thus beyond both objeci and subject, beyond circum
scribed and signified sense, this doesn't mean that it lies in a supra-signify
ing beyond to which I would end up being initiated (mysticism always in-.
volves initiation). It's a matter here not of signification but of what, right
up against signification, slips alongside it, next to it, prying itself from it
through a minute difference: its communi<;:ation. (And for Sartre, as for
Bataille, truth is its communication to the other.12) Communication isn't
the movement of significations; rather, it brings such significatioris into
contact with the openings of sense. Without this contact, signification
wouldn't signify. Yet whatever happens to the significations being ex
changed (whether they are transformed, lost, misunderstood, well trans
lated), with this contact it is the very possibility of sense that is illumi
nated-and its fire is a nocturnal one. Sense in the other is for me both the
truth and the night of sense. Birth and death, love and hate, signal noth
ing other than this.
I cannot speak-and that also means that I cannot think-without
this "sense in the other" .already resonating "in me," without its night al
ready standing against my eyes. "To pass from one to the othe�" isn't just
one more operation for thinking; ii: is thinking itselJinsofar as it conceals
itself in the truth of sense.
Such are the stakes of the cracked nudity that haunts Bataille's
work-not in the manner of an aroused voyeurism but in the sense of the
night of a 'clear eroticism. Beneath the removed or raised garment, and so
no longer beneath, strictly speaking, but exposed, nudity is what conceals
and what conceals itself: leading into the space that the intimacy of the
other is, not only for me but for itself as well. Leading, then, not into a
mystical union in which a knowledge of one in and through the other
might be reconstituted, but into the renewed concealment of not-knowing
that, rather than uniting us, divides us: an infinite agitation of sense. Con
cealed thinking is identical to communication, and this identity is itself the
night of not-knowing.
Bataille (who would die two years later), perhaps even more than homage,
a sign of community. However this may be, what is important here isn't his
intention per se, nor is it, as elsewhere, his attempt to correct "non-know
ing" with something more "rational" (a correction cir modulation that
Bataille doesn't simply repudiate). No, what is important here is that,
obliquely and from a distance, as it were, Sartre approaches the necessity of
thinking concealed thinking: the sense of this naked absence of sense that
we ultimately know and share as our very nudity, humbly get gladly, in the
everyday or in what is truly exceptional.
From this point on, it falls to us to approach from a new perspective
that which is neither science nor religion nor philosophy-that which, far
from providing a sense that might be exchanged, is itself the sense of the
exchange (the exchange itself as sense, even) of our existence in common.
"In a sense" this is what we call praxis, that is, action that transforms its
agent rather than its object or its matter. Far from being the mastery of a'
means with a view to an end, praxis is the endless transformation of the
subject of sense in itself: a sense that is nothing other than its communica
tion-and, by the same token, its concealment. The concealment of think
ing is its praxis: thinking that undoes its objects in order to become the
thinking that it is: we, with one another and with the world.
Tramlated by James Gilbert-Walsh
: . ...�.,.
EXISTING
3
The Unsacrificeable
Pamphile says that, having leatnt geometry from the Egyptians,Thales was
the first to inscribe a right-angled triangle, whereupon he sacrificed an ox.
-Diogenes Laertius1
The Unsacrificeable . 53
II
III
ity (or the representations of these sacrifices) does the West map �ut, so to
speak, its own "sacrifice" (perhaps, if it needs repeating, the only one that
genuinely answers to the name "sacrifice")?
Socrates and Christ show it to be a decisive and founding relation. In
both cases, it is a matter ofa simultaneously distanced and repetitive rela
tion. Both figures (the double figure of onto-theology) quite deliberately
and decisively distance themselves from sacrifice and point toward its
metamorphosis or transgression. Above all, therefore, it is a matter of a
mimesis: early sacrifice is, up to a certain point, reproduced in its form or
schema, but reproduced in such a way as to uncover within it a completely
new content, a truth previously buried or unrecognized, if not perverted.
In the same way, early sacrifice is represented as having constituted only a
previous imitation, a crude image of what transfiguredsacrifice will hence
forth bring about. Basically, though, there is perhaps precisely nothing that
we can say about "early sacrifice" except that all representations of it are
constructed on the basis of transfigured sacrifice. Yet this new sacrifice
doesn't derive from its brutish prototypes by way of a simple transmission
or natural generation: the gesture of a "mimetic rupture" is necessary to in
augurate it.
"To give one's life for something"-great effect. But people give 'their lives for
many things: emotions need to be satisfied, individually and all together. . . . How
many ha,,-e sacrificed their lives-or even worse, their health!-for a pretty
The Unsacrificeable 57
woman! When one has the temperament, one instinctively chooses what is dan
gerous: the adventure of speculation, for example, if one is a philosopher; or one
of immorality, if one is virtuous . . . we are always sacrificing. 13
.
This is how we need to understand the shift from the Catholic Eu
charist, consummated in the finite character of sensible beings, to the in
ner cult of reformed spirit. And how we need to understand its speculative ·
truth:
The negation of the finite can only take place in a finite way; with this we come to
what is generally called sacrifice. The immediate context of sacrifice is the surren
der of an immediate finitude, in the sense of my testifying that this finitude ought
not to be my own and that I do not want to keep it as such. Here, negativity can
not manifest itself through an inner process, because feeling does not yet have the
necessary depth. . . . Rather, the subject . . . is only to surrender an immediate
possession and natural existence. In this sense, sacrifice is no longer found in a
spiritual religion, and what is there called sacrifice can only be so in a figurative
sense,zz
.,
'-,7·:
60 EXISTING
tory. Yet this is how Spirit completes its infinite self-presence and the law
becomes restored and glorified.
Nietzsche, too, sometimes sees history in terms of the necessity of
sacrificing entire generations so as "to strengthen and raise higher the gen
eral feeling of human power through this sacrifice-in which we and our
neighbor are included."25 Such a sacrifice is opposed to one performed by
"the good" who, says Zarathustra, "crucify the one who writes new values
on new law-tables, and sacrifice the future to themselves."26 And yet it op
poses it only by remaining sacrifice, just as Dionysus opposes the Cruci
fied; it is the power of dismemberment against the dismemberment of
power. All this presupposes the Maenads, the orgiastic, a point of infinite
dismemberment and pain.
Such is the consequence of mimetic ruprure: sacrifice is the sublation
of its finite functions and its exteriority, yet a fascinated gaze is still fixed on
the cruel moment of sacrifice as such. We have already seen that the very
Hegel who abandons religious sacrifice also reclaims for the state the full
vruue of warlike sacrifice. (And what does Marx say of the proletariat?
Those who "possess a character of universality because of that universality .
of their sufferings. ")27 Although sublating sacrifice, the West constitutes a
fascination with and for the cruel moment of its economy. And does so,
perhaps, in parallel'with the extension and exhibition of suffering in the
world of modern war and modern technology-at least up to a certain
point, to which we will return. The "flesh that does not perish" remains the
torn flesh of a beautiful body, and the secret of this horror continues to cast
an obscure light over the central point of sublation, over the heart of the
dialectic: in truth, in spite of Hegel, it is this secret that makes this heart
beat; or, more seriously, it is the dialectical gesture itself that inaugurates
this secret. Western spiritualization/dialecticization invented the secret of
an infinite efficacy of transgression and its cruelty. After Hegel and Nietz
sche there is an eye fixed upon this secret, with the feeling of a clear, nec
essary, and unbearable consciousness-the eye of Bataille, for instance.
But what does this eye actually s�e? It sees its own sacrifice. It sees
that it can only see because of an unbearable, intolerable vision-that of
sacrificial cruelty-or it sees that it sees nothing.
Indeed, if it is always going to be a question of the ancient sacrifice
that lies at the heart of modern sacrifice, we need to acknowledge that the
mimetic rupture has made us lose sight of the ancient truth of this sacri
fice. Or, as I have already suggested, the rupture is set up by the represen-
The Unsacrificeable 61
the death of the subject and of the subject of death) is no more than an in
ept delusion.
Bataille concludes somewhat abruptly: "It is time to acknowledge
that nostalgia for the sacred necessarily comes to nothing, it is misleading:
what the contemporary world is lacking is the offer of temptation.-Or it
lacks the offer of temptations so heinous that they are useful only in so far
as they deceive those whom they tempt."32 The ambiguity is not entirely
assuaged in these. lines, whose syntax works to keep it alive: on the one
hand, the contemporary world "is lacking" truly sacred "temptations,"
given immediately and without recourse to nostalgia; on the other hand,
however, this world is itself."lacking," this time in the sense that it is at
faul�, its temptations illusory. The fact remains, therefore, that sacrifice, or
something about sacrifice, is always lacking.
Out of all of this, I want to hold onto the following yawning ambi
guity: W the inanity of sacrifice is recognized by the West, itself the inven
tor of this very sacrifice, it is perhaps only ever recognized in terms of the
idea of a sacrifice ofthis sacrifice. In this way, however, the dialectic con
tinually renews itself. Bataille knew this, and utterly despaired in the face
of such knowledge.
truth, naming "essential sacrifice" as one of the ways in which this putting
[in]to [the] work happens within art; yet in the same essay, he found it
necessary to include "offerings and sacrifice" in the heart ofbeings open
to the clearing ofbeing.33 Here, though, I can't deal any further with these
suggestions.)
A link between sacrifice and art, and no doubt literature in particu
lar, unarguably runs throughout--or doubles-the Western process of
the spiritualization of sacrifice. Book 5 of Augustine's Confessions, for ex
ample, begins: '�ccept the sacrifice of my confessions, presented by the
hand of my tongue, which you formed and exhorted to confess Y-Our
name"-and, in so doing, paves the way for everything in our literature
that concerns "confession." But is there finally any real distinction be
tween "confession," literature, and art in general? Isn't the transgressive
presentation of a subject, who thereby appropriates himself and allows
hin;tself to be appropriated, a dominant theme of art? The Kantian sub
lime unfolds in a "sacrifice" of the imagination that "sinks back into itself
but consequently comes to feel a liking that amounts to an emotion."34
The entire program of poetry is given in this note by Novalis to Heinrich
von Ofterdingen: "Dissolution of a poet in his song-he shall be sacrificed
among savage peoples."35 And, moving quickly over this in order to come
back to Bataille, who writes: "Poetry . . . is . . . the sacrifice in which words
are the victims. . . . We cannot . . . do without the efficacious relations that
words introduce between men and things. But we tear them from these re
lations in a delirium."36
More precisely, art supplements, takes over, or sublates the impasse of
sacrifice. This impasse stems from the following alternative: "If the subject
is not truly destroyed, everything remains in ambiguity. And if it is · de
stroyed, the ambiguity is resolved, but resolved in the void where every
thing is eliminated."37 The alternative, then, is that between simulacrum
and nothingness, which is also to say that between the representation of
early sacrifice and the postulation of self-sacrifice. "But," Bataille contin
ues, "it is precisely this double impasse that results in the meaning of the
moment of art, which offers man an uninterrupted rapture by throwing us
upon the path of a total extinction, and leaving us temporarily suspended
there."38 This "uninterrupted rapture" is still a dialectical formula. There is
rapture to the extent that art keeps us "suspended" on the verge of extino
tion-a way of recognizing a new form of simulacrum. But it is "uninter
rupted" because it brings with it the intense restlessness of emotion that
66 EXISTING
Art itself displaces the gaze once again: the "appearance" of cruelty is
in fact singularly ambiguous. Simultaneously restricted to simulacra and
holding for this cruelty alone, this horror that it brings to light and that
only means something (ifwe still have to speak in these terms), only has any
force, if it is not simulated. The article is entitled ''Art, an Exercise in Cru
elty." Whatever turns it takes and however short it may be, its concern is the
actual exercise of actual cruelty, at least in terms of its emotion. And yet
artistic mimesis, as mimesis and, paradoxically, despite its avowedly mimetic
character, ought to open the way to a genuine mathexis, to a genuine par
ticipation in what is revealed by the horror of the' emotion. Art is worth
while, then, only if it still refers to the sacrifice that it supplements. It can
only sacrifice sacrifice by continuing to sacrifice it to sacrifice. (Schelling, by
contrast, writes that "pure suffering can never be an object of art.")40
Bataille sees the difficulty and immediately changes direction. Speak
ing of the sacrificial events evoked throughout the text, he writes: "This is
in no way an apology for horrific events. It is not a call for their return."41
And yet he cannot but shift position once again and slip a restriction into
his refusal (and not, in this context, a"denial): "But . . . in the moment of
rapture, these moments . . . bear within themselves the whole truth of the
emotion."42 And further . on: "The movement [�f art] effortlessly places it
on a par with the worst and, reciprocally, the depiction of horror reveals
within it an opening to everything possible."43 In this reciprocity-how
could we miss it?-something about, mimesis is annulled or, rather, mime
sis reveals (and Bataille does indeed speak in terms of revelation . . . ) an
actual methexis. Through a still quite real transgression, art communes with
horror, with the pleasure of a momentary'appropriation of death.
As such, art either falls well short of what is asked of it: it still just
and only-mimes the spilling of blood, or it answers it all too well, sug
gesting the real emotion of real horror.
· .
. --,"._, �'-- .-.- " - . � , .. �.- " - -",
.-, --:... � - ." � . .. . . _" .-'-.-:,..... .;.. ..�_.,:;::. ..;_;•..-_ .... :..:.i� �_. �:.:..;�_....-;.::.·... ..� o-_,_. .-"'.,� ......:.
•:...:. "_...•
The Unsacrificeable 67
VI
Before putting this question to the test in more detail, I want to fol
low Bataille one step further. I want to follow his reflections on the Nazi
68 EXISTING
camps through the most developed of his texts on this subject (about
which, however, he wrote very little), "Reflections on the Executioner and
the Victim," a text that deals with David Rousset's The Days of Our
Death.46
This text makes �o mention of the word "sacrifice." What it does do,
however, is present the components of a sacrificial logic. First of all, the
camps display the very thing that is at stake in sacrifice: "In a universe of
suffering, of baseness and stench, we still have the luxury [le loisir} of mea
suring the abyss, its absence of limits and this truth that obsesses and fas
cinates." Yet in order to know the "depths of horror," we "must pay the
price." This price, if I understand Bataille correctly, is double: it consists,
first, in the conditions necessary for "a'senseless experience" and thus in the
very existence of the camps; second, it consists in a will that agrees to face
this horror ;J.s a human possibility. This will has to be that of the victim.
(Bataille finds it in the "exaltation" and "humor" present in Rousset.) To
refuse it would be "a negation of humanity hardly less degrading than that
of the executioner." If it isn't a matter of self-sacrifice, it at least appeals, in
spite of everything, to the position of a subject. Undoubtedly, as Bataille
goes on to say, "horror is evidently not truth: it is only an infinite possibil
ity, having no limit other than death." Yet the "fascinated" approach to
truth supposes that, "in some way," "abjection and pain reveal themselves
fully to man." Such a possibility was given by the camps. We can see this
most dearly in "the depths of horror" that "lie in the resolve of those who
demand it." This resolve on the part of the· executioners is a resolve that
seeks "to ruin the refuge that, in the founding of civilized order, re<l;Son it
self is." (We should recall that, for Bataille, the Jews at Auschwitz were "the
incarnation of reason.") And yet civilized reason is only ever a "refuge,"
limited and fragile. The "rage of the torturer" that rises up against it comes
from humanity alone, and not even from a special brand of humanity
("parties or races which, .we might suppose, are in no way human"). No,
this possibility is "ours." For reason to know this possibility as such is for
reason to be capable of "calling itself unteservedly into question," some
thing that secures no definitive victory, merely the higher human possibil
ity of "awakening': "But what would awakening be if it shed light only
upon a world of abstract possibilities? If it did not first awake to the possi
bility of Auschwitz, to a possibility of stench and of irreparable fury"?
Within the realization of this possibility comes, then, a: necessity.
For Bataille, this necessity dearly derives from the fact of the camps'
The Unsacrificeable 69
existence and from the will to face up, without any moral refuge, to what
they have shown. This isn't situated as an a priori demand. Not for a mo
ment do I want to suggest the slightest complicity, however unconscious,
on Bataille's part. No, I believe simply that we need to consider the fol
lowing:· the logic being pursued here is the dark reverse of a clear logic of
sacrifice (so long as we can isolate such a "clarity" . . . ), This logic states:
only extreme horror keeps reason awake. The logic of sacrifice says: the
only awakening is an awakening to horror, in which the instant of truth
shines through. The two statements are a long way from being conflated.
But the latter can always harbor the truth of the former. If Bataille does · not
draw the same conclusion and if the camps remain for him beyondsacrifice
(this, at least, is what he says), then isn't this because the horror of sacrifice
falls silently outside any sacrificial sense, outside any possibility of sense?
Bataille can't bring himself to say this and, despite everything, preserves
the possibility, broached at the very end of the text, of seeing "poetry" as a
form of "awakening" (although we know now to what sacrificial return
"poetry" is destined, however much it may be "on a par with the worst").
Here, sacrifice would silently fall headlong into an antithesis that is
also its culmination: a revelation of horror with no accompanying means
. 'of access, no appropriation, save that of this infi . nite or indefinite revela�
tion itself. '
A sacrificial interpretation of the camps is thus undoubtedly possible,
even necessary, but only if we're prepared to invert it into its antithesis
(from Holocaust into Shoah). Such a sacrifice leads nowhere, provides no
means of access. In a sense, though, it could be called a model of self-sac
rifice, since the victim of the camps, reason itself, is also on the side of the
executioner, as the analysis of the state-controlled and engineered mechan
ics of extermination has constantly emphasized. Bataille writes elsewhere:
"The unleashing of passions that was rife in Buchenwald or Auschwitz was
an unleashing governed by reason."47 And it wouldn't be surprising were a
certain rationality to culminate in self'sacrifice, if self-sacrifice-which we
can now, to be sute, equate with Western sacrifice as a whole-accounts
for a certain process' of Reason. As Heidegger might have put it: reason ap
propriates the abyss of its own subjecthood.
At the same time, however, and without contradiction, the camps
represent an absence of sacrifice. They bring into play an unexpected ten
sion between sacrifice and the absence of sacrifice. And it is fairly signifi
cant that the description of the privileges of the Aryan race in Mein Kamp!
70 EXISTING
This was how Himmler presented this sacrifice of duty to his Gruppen
fiihrer in 1943: the sacrifice that not only defies human strength but even
sacrifices any memorial to the glorious sacrifice that it is. In this way,
Himmler simultaneously declares that, on the side of the victims, it is a
matter of what is intolerable, while on the side of the executioners, it is a
matter of the most silent, inner sacrifice.
True, Himmler doesn't use the word "sacrifice." Indeed, that would
honor the victims far too much, would allow them to claim too great a part
The Unsacrificeable 71
VII
The Unsacrificeable 73
In the future, though, it will fall to us t6 say that there is no "true" sacri
fice, that real existence is unsacrificeable, that the truth of existence is to be
unsacrificeable.
Existence isn't to be sacrificed, and can't be sacrificed. It can only be
destroyed or shared. This is the unsacrificeable and ·finite existence that is
offered up to be shared: methexis is henceforth offered as the sharing out of
the very thing that it shares: both the limit of finitude and respect for the
unsacrificeable. The effacement of sacrifice, the effacement of communion,
the effacement of the West: this doesn't mean that the West could be re
duced to what came before it, or that Western sacrifice could be reduced to
the rites that it was supposed to have spiritualized. Rather, it means that we
are on the verge of another community, another methexis, one in which the
mimesis of sharing would efface the sacrificial mimicry of an appropriation
of the Other.61
Translated by Richard Stamp and Simon Sparks
4
The Indestructible
And yet how could there ever be a sense that wa$n't single and sover
eign? It's the inability either to avoid or to respond to this question that
leads to destruction as sense: sense busy dismantling sense.
Doubtless the destructive assault first targets the sense of the other or
the other of sense. But it also strikes the. sense of the proper. Dism�tling
an other sense isn't possible without dislocating sense in general. The prin
ciple of destruction would harbor a general renunciation of sense, there
fore, including the very sense of the act that we name thus: destroy. Again:
. this act is the final flare of sense extinguishing itself-its final scorched im
print. (Death would be something quite different, a flare of sense that eter.,.
nalizes itself.)
To destroy would be not to support sense or to despaIr of it. Once
we're left with broken structures, dislocated joints, displaced pieces, there
is no longer any sense. There is no longer any worry over sense.
Cultures other than the modern one have all been familiar with in
tentional destruction. They have always known what it was to raze a vil...
lage, to exterminate a tribe: to remove them from the various crucibles of
sense, from the points at which a sense is either emitted or concentrated.
Successful destruction has always tended to efface even the memory
of the existence that has been destroyed, and even the possibility of pos
terity (salt on the ruins of Carthage), offering only the assutance that
this-or that, this one here, that one there-never existed and would
never exist. Destruction strives not simply to annihilate a being, but to
shatter the very structure that renders it possible, reaching into its origin
and its end, tearing from it its very birth and death.
And yet the culture of destruction, driven by a will in pursuit of a
single and unalterable sense, releases an infinite sense or a nonsensical in
finity. A plan for the world, for humanity, for history, the horizon of econ
omy and right, the generalized and circular contract-form: a hateful and
desperate contempt for sense in general. Dostoyevslo/'s "anything goes."
When anything goes, it is destruction, first and foremost, exclusively, even,
that goes-including self-destruction.
The desire to destroy resents connection, interplay, assembly and its
complexity: it resents the fold (it resents not the completed structure, but
�hat which structures; not the assembled, but its assembly; not the folded,
but the fold). And in order to destroy, we fold to the extreme, we squeeze,
we break. The infant destroys because there's no question of considering or
exploring the assembly of the object, of the machine. The infantile man
The Indestructible 81
discrete grandeur of tombs; they are not monuments but distinct places,
and that is why they stand in stark contrast to the "mass grave. "
The destroyer wants to suppress this "somewhere," this plurality of
places. The destroyer dislikes places-the interplay of presences, their .
sense. The space of destruction is a dislocated space, a space without place,
undifferentiated, deserted, chaotic. In the same way, the time of destruc
tion is an annulled time, stretched out and empty: instead of the future,
what might have been is petrified, made present.as stillborn.
Put differently, the space-time of destruction would be the very op
posite of the tomb; it would be the stomach in which flesh, having been
devoured, digests itself In this instance, the mass grave would become the
body, the reopening of a sense. Cannibalism-which has occupied our re
ligions, Dionysian and Christian figures, for so long-would be the struc
turing destruction. Whether the destruction is of the heart or the stomach
of the structure, this doubtless gives us one of the most emphatic motifs for
our cwture: under the guise of mystery, this is actually the incarnation; un
der the guise of melancholy, incorporation; under the guise of finite know
ing, the madness of systems or structures.
If it's true that we have produced a culture of destruction, we need to
try to understand why. Clearly it's not enough to evoke the "evil" in man
or his destructive "instinct." Rather, we need to consider the possibility
that our culture has seized upon evil as an intrinsic possibility-neither ac
cidental nor secondary-of being itself, or that culture has pointed out a
"destructive drive," originally involved in the drive toward life and propa
gation, the two as one (moving toward two forms of perpetuation-but
not toward existence).
So our culture shelters within itself the possibility of destruction. Re
gardless of whether this means that this culture should itself be destroyed,
this is precisely what it undertakes to do. We can date-from the conquest
of the Americas-the moment when the West, by revealing a new aptitude
for destruction (unrelated, in this sense, to the conquests of the Romans,
barbarians, Arabs, and Turks, or to the Crusades), initiated its own self-de
struction. Millions of Native Americans were destroyed, along with their
cultures; so, too, were thousands of Europeans, destroying themselves in
the rage for conquest and gold as their culture began to gnaw away at itself
with doubts concerning its validity, its "Catholicism," its very "humanity, "
even. I t was a long time before this culminated i n the self-destruction of
The Indestructible 83
Europe in a "total" war whose very invention astounded itself. But, finally,
we are here; and this is history, the very construction of our history.
And we've caused this thing to spread to the globalizing rhythm of a
technology variously employed by war, by the control of war, by the de
struction of places and of histories, by the control of this destruction-al
ways more than destruction, always more than control, a control that, de
structive in its turn, spirals, indeterminate, out of control.
Self-destruction: the mark of a culture in which suicide holds a dis
tinguished place, from Socrates to Werther, to Stefan Zweig, to Primo
Levi, to so many others. I'm not talking here about Japanese suicide nor
even Stoic suicide, in which we run up against an objective limit that cuts
us short. Rather, it is a matter of a fundamentally destructive suicide that at
tacks the self, the proper as structure and as interplay, an assault on the very
pulse of existence.
Self-destruction indicates the stakes here: the self, the system that ar
ticulates itselffrom within culture. This culture is the culture of the self, of
its appropriation, its concentration-in-itselE And insofar as it involves the
self or the ego, it discovers the principle of evil. There's surely no Western
interpretation of evil that doesn't end up imputing the ego or the egologi
cal as such (including its earliest projection into a Lucifer). No more, how
ever, is there any interpretation of the "good" that doesn't situate it in. tP.e
appropriation of the self-in the autonomy and self-foundation of the free
subject, for example. The ego is both structure (the appropriation of the
self) and destruction (the concentration in the self), just as it is both the
singular and Narcissus, or the partner and the monad.
Everything happens as if destruction were inscribed upon the struc
ture-as its joints and its fissures-precisely to the extent that the str1,1c
ture programs what cannot take place: the infinite appropriation of the self
by itself The certainty of the cogito is, as we know, constitutionally blind.
Kant's "transcendental I" is an empty point..The �go of psychoanalysis suf
fers from a structural lack (or is the structural lack) of the self, a line of fil
iation that leads back to Oedipus's gouged eyes. And filiation itself, the
dominance of the theme of filiation, indicates the blind process of an ego
that pursues itself from generation to generation.
This is why the ego qualifies itself essentially as desire, desire itself be
ing understood as submission to the law of lack (rather than to the law of
a departure from the self). The ego is posed as the frustration or, rather, the
entropy of the ego itself
84 EXISTING
Today, however, can this phrase have a sense that is neither meta
physical nor metaphoric? A sense that is our own? Either way, it cannot re
spond to what Nietzsche believed still needed to be said: "In order to build
a sanctuary, a sanctuary has to be destroyed." Indeed, on the one hand, it
is no longer a matter of sanctuary (the word itself has become rather passe
in the vocabulary of nuclear war) and so no longer a matter of destroying
something in order to make room for something else; instead, it is a mat
ter of bringing the ternplum to the spacing of being. On the other hand,
though, it is no longer a matter of "building," since one doesn't build a
world; rather, one arrives there, dwells in it, departs from it. Instead, there
fore, it would be a matter of allowing ourselves to contemplate the world,
the spacing of its there is.
Not the restoration of a temple, therefore, but the consideration of
worldly places as places of eXisting. Far from being a matter of restoration,
this is revolution, properly speaking. And yet, insofar as revolution is taken
to mean "revolutionary destruction," it's also a matter of revolution against
destruction. Revolution as resistance, as the necessity and impatience of
existence; revolution as having suddenly arisen, here and now, opening his.,
tory, allowing places to "take place," as it were. Bur this isn't simply a rev
olution; it is permanent revolution, the possibility, at every moment, of
opening space (and I'm thinking here of Michelet's remark that the open
space of the Champs de Mars was the sole "monument" to the revolution).
The history of the West has revolved around four figures of the
temple:
I. The Greek temple, the source of the nascent West's contemplation
and thus what is doomed both to ruinous destruction: and to artistic
metamorphosis.
2. The Jewish temple-twice destroyed, then taken up in terms ofits
destruction, as the meaning of its own destruction and of the diaspora of
those united by no determinate sense.
3 . The Christian temple, the temple of infinite construction, the mas
tery of the spire and the dome, where technology contemplates itself.
4. The Islamic temple, whose heart, the black rock of Kaaba, is, far
from a reserved space, an impenetrable, indestructible thing.
The sort of knowledge that we need-the sort of knowledge that we
lack'-:'is the fourfold knowledge of art and technology, of disseminated
sense and indestructible nothing.
This fourfold knowledge would be a structural one-a knowledge of
.,
88 EXISTING
this entire fourfold structure and of the way in which it arranges a fourfold
space: the Mediterranean, Europe, the West, the Earth, and a fourfold
time: the "Pre-history" of the East, History itself, Decline, and the Present.
This knowledge happens, though, as not-knowing, which is neither igno
rance nor confusioit, but is certainly no longer mastery. It is sovereign
knowledge-that is, nothing, knowledge as existence.
"The world is a temple": in fact, the world is the only temple there is
if there are no longer any temples, if structure has itself deconstructed tem
ples. The world is the only carved space that remains. And what allows it
to be contemplated as such is nothing-nothing but its existence, our ex
istence, the fact that it is, appearing, disappearing.
None of this, though, is accessible to the ego. Indeed, it is always
from out ofthis that the ego emerges in order to contemplate blindly the
desert of what it has destroyed. Whoever would contemplate the world
would, .in truth, contemplate .the effacement of the ego.
Let me echo the ancient words of a Muslim reviled for having wanted
to unite, from East to West, the separate modes of contemplation: "There
is, between you and I, a 'this is me' that torments me. Ah! Take away the
'this is me' that separates US!"3
These words and the voice that utters them bespeak the dimension of
the world. But there is no one voice, since any such voice would no longer
be singular. Nor can the ego and destruction be effaced in a communal in
vocation. What we need are voices that are singular, distinct, and that do
not properly understand one another, voices that call to one another, that
provoke one another.
Translated by James Gilbert-Walsh
DIFFERENCE
5
Elliptical Sense
, "
92 D IFFERENCE
difforance. The origin differs or defers, differs from itself or defers itself.
And that is its joy or passion: a corps perdu.
The origin, or sense, if the origin is by definition the origin of sense,
contains within itself (and/or differing) the sense of the origin, its own
sense, itself being the very sense and site of sense. Nothing less than sense
itself, "all sense," as is written in "Ellipsis." (This is the only occurrence of
the word "sense" in Derrida's text. In one fell swoop, for the entire text and
its ellipsis, all sense. The slightest text of thought can expose no less.)
The condition of possibility of the origin (of sense) is called writing.
Writing isn't the vehicle or medium of sense; were this so, it wouldn't be its
condition of possibility, but the condition of its transmission. Here, "writ
ing" doesn't refer to Derrida's writing, which communicates to us the sense
and the logic of a certain discourse on the origin, sense, and writing (at
least insofar as this sense and this logic are communicable). This writing is
not that of the book which this text concludes and closes (which is entitled
Writing and Difference). Or rather, the writing of the origin is this writing
itself, and this book itself there is no other, there is nothing more to read
once the book has been closed, there are not two writings, one empirical
and one transcendental. There is a single "transcendental experience" of
"writing." But this experience attests precisely to its non-self-identity. In
other words, it is the experience of what cannot be experienced. Writing is
difforance. ,
Thus writing is said to be the "passion of and for the origin." This
passion does not arise at the origin: it is and makes the origin itself The
origin is a passion, the passion of the self in its difference, and it is that
which makes sense, allsense; All sense is always passion, in all the senses of
the word "sense." (Hegel, building on Kant, was well aware of this:
sense-the sense of being-is also the sense of sensibility. For Hegel, this
was the crux and the passion of the aesthetic in general, and hence also of
writing in its relation to philosophy, in the sense of its relation to philoso
phy.) What makes sense about sense, what makes it originate, is that it
senses itself making sense. (To sense the sense or to touch the being-sense
of sense, even if it were to be senseless-that's Derrida's passion. To touch
the body of sense. To incorporate sense. Scratching, cutting, branding.
Putting to the test of sense. I shall write about nothing else.) Sense isn't a
matter of something having or making sense (the world, existence, or this
discourse of Derrida's). It's rather the fact that sense apprehends itself,
grasps itself as sense. .
Elliptical Sense 93
This means that sense, essentially, has to repeat itself: not by being
stated or given twice in identical fashion, as is the case with the "reissuing
of a book," but by opening in itself (as itself) the possibility of relating to
itself in the "referral of one sign to another." It is in just such a referral that
sense is recognized or grasped as sense. Sense is the duplication of the ori
gin and the relation that IS opened, in the origin, betWeen the origin and
the end, and the pleasure, for the origin, of enjoying that which it origi
nates (that of which it is the origin and the fact that it originates) .
Such is the passion, the whole passion of writing: sense, in order to
be or to make sense, has to repeat itself, which is to say, in the original sense
of this word, it must make repeated demands on itself Sense is not given; it
is the demand that it be given. (This implies a giving of the demand, but
that is precisely what, in Kantian terms, ought to be termed the "transcen
dental" and not, of course, the transcendent, which would be the pure
presence of sense, "neither demanded nor capable of being demanded.)
Sense must interrogate itself anew (though it is in this "anew" that every
thing begins; the origin is not the new, but the "anew") ; it must make de
mands on itself, call to itself, ask itself, implore itself, want itself, desire it
self, seduce itself as sense. Writing is nothing other than this demand,
renewed and modified without end. Sense calls for more sense, just as, for
Valery, "it is the sense which calls for more form" in poetry. And, in effect,
it comes down to the same thing. All poetry, and all of Derrida's philoso
phy, meets this demand. Consequently there is something missing in sense,
something missin"g from the start. And "all sense is altered or exhausted by
this lack.� Writing is the outline of this alteration. " Hence, this outline is
"in essence elliptical," because it does not come back full circle to the same.
Ellipsis: the other in the return to the self, the geometral of the pas of
meaning, singular and plural.
Strictly speaking, however, nothing is altered. It's not as if there's a
"
first sense that would then be diverted and disturbed by a second writing,
doomed to lament its infinite loss or painfully to await its infinite recon
stitution. '�l sense is altered [tout le sens est altere1 ." Which means, first of
all, that sense is thirsty [altere as the opposite of desaltere, "refreshed"] . It
thirsts after itself and its own lack; that is its passion. (And it is also Der
rida's passion for language; in the word altere as he employs it here, an el
lipsis of sense makes sense, the alteration and the excess of sense.) Sense
thirsts after its" own ellipsis, for its originary trope, for that which hides it,
eludes it, and passes it by in silence. Ellipsis: the step/pas of sense passing
94 DIFFERENCE
beneath sense. What is passed over in silence, in all sense, is the sense of
sense. But there is nothing negative in tI1is, nor, in truth, anything silent.
For nothing is lost, nor anything silenced. Everything is said, and, like
every philosophical text (every text in general?), this text says everything
about the origin, says the whole origin, and presents itself as the knowledge
of the origin. ("Here" is its first word, and later on we read "we now
know.") Everything is said here and now, all sense is offered on the surface
of this writing. No thinking thinks more economically, and less passion
ately, than in thinking everything, all at once. No pleasure of thinking can
enjoy in a lesser degree than absolute enjoyment. Thus this text pronounces
itself, or the orbit that carries it, to be nothing less than a "system," the sys
tem in which the origin itself "is only a function and a locus."
Writing is the passion of this system. Broadly speaking, a system is
the conjunction that holds articulated parts together. More strictly, in the
philosophical tradition, it is the juncture, the conjoining of the organs of
the living being, its life or Life itself(this life which, according to Hegel, is
most profoundly characterized by sense, insofar as it senses and senses itself
sensing). The adjoining or conjoining of writing is the "binding joint" of
the book, or its life. The life of the book is played out-.is "in play" and "at
stake"-not in the closed book, but in the open book "between the two
hands which hold the book," this book by Jabes that Derrida holds open
and reads for us. Jabes, who writes nothing but a continuation of the book,
and on the book; this book of Derrida's which he writes to us and gives us
to read and to hold in the ellipse of our hands.
The maintenant, the now, of sense articulates itself, repeats itself and
puts itself in play in the mains tenant, the hands holding the book. These
mains tenant multiply the now (the maintenant), dividing presence, eliding
it and making it plutal. These are "our hands": it is no longer an I that is
being uttered, but the uttering and articulation of a we. This juncture goes
beyond the adjoining of a living being that reads. It prolongs and exceeds
him. It is not someone living who reads, even if it is not someone dead.
(And the book itself is neither alive nor dead.) What now holds or takes the
book in hand is a system whose systematicity differs from and defers itself
"The dijferance in the now of writing" is itself the "system" of writing,
within which the origin is inscribed merely as a "place."
Dijferance is nothing other than the infinite re-petition of sense,
which consists neither in its duplication nor in its infinite distancing from
itself Rather, dijferance is the access of sense to sense in its own demand,
, ... :.
Elliptical Sense 95
an access that does not accede, this exposed finitude beyond which, now
.
that "God is dead," there is nothing to think.
If sense were simply given, if access to it were not deferred, if sense
did not demand sense (if it demanded nothing), sense would have no more
sen,seO than water within water, stone within stone, or the dosed book in a
book that has never been opened. But the book is open, in our hands. Dif
ftrance can never, be conceptualized, but it can be written. Difforance is the
demand, the call, the request, the seduction, the imprecation, the impera
tive, the supplication, the jubilation of writing. Difforance is passion.
Such is the last page of the book, the last line of the text-the other
site of the ellipsis, after the hie et nunc of the beginning-which is what the
book, the text, never stops demanding, calling for, soliciting. The ellipsis of
"Ellipsis" closes itself off in dijferance and its own circularity, and in the
play of a recognition which never returns. In the last line Derrida inscribes
the final words of a quotation from Jabes. It is a signature, the signature on
a fragment, a pronouncement that precedes it: "Reb Derissa." All the au
thority, if not all the sense, of the text will have been altered by this move.
It will have been the thirst or the passion for putting into play the 1, the
origin, the author, the subject of this text.
Closing of the text: quotation of the other text, ellipsis. This quota
tion, almost signature. The signature marks the limit of signs. It is their
event, the propriety of their advent, their origin or sign of origin, or origin
itself as a singular sign, which no longer signals anything, which cuts sense
in two. Derrida signs and de-signates himself; his signature is repeatable. It
owes its "sense" entirely to its repetition; it has no signification. Its sense is
repetition, the demand for the singular. Derrida asks for himself, and is al
tered. Singularity is doubled and thirsts after itself insofar as it is the origin
of the text. An exorbitant thirst, the thirst of one who has already drunk,
who has drunk the entire text, the whole of writing, and whose drunken
ness asks for it all over again. Derrida is a drunken rabbi.
The mastermind that ordains the system of the text bestows his own
name on a double (itself unreal; the text has not neglected to remind us
that Jabes's rabbis are "imaginary"). The double substitutes a double "s '�
that "disseminating letter," Derrida writes later-for the "d "in the "da" of
"Derrida." An elsewhere in the guise of a here, a fictitious being in the guise
of Dasein, or existence. Derissa-- slim, razor-sharp, derisory-touches the
limits of a narrie and a body "with an animal-like, quick, silent, smooth,
brilliant, slippery motion, in the manne� of a serpent or a fish," as the text
says of a book that insinuates itself "into the dangerous hole" of the center,
filling it in.
Fills it to bursting with pleasure: because it's a game, yes, it's a laugh.
Estos de risa: this makes us laugh. Here laughter breaks out-laughter is
never anything but explosive; it never closes up again-the laughter of an
ellipsis opened like a mouth around its paired foci: Derrida, Derissa.
Mocking laughter. But mocks or mimics what? Nothing; merely its break
ing out. The origin laughs. There is such a thing as transcendental laugh
ter-and several times the text has evoked a certain "joy" of writing . . .
- --- -"-- -- - � . --- --
.: ...: . • :_ •..,.•..:.....'k • • .,'" � ... _,...... .:.:� . �:. ��� ':.'_:�';" "
.
• ".�••,� _ "
Elliptical Sense 97
theory laughs at itself. Derrida will always have laughed, with a laughter . at
once violent and light, a laughter of the origin and of writing.
In lightening itself, sense does not cast off its ballast, \does not un
burden or debauch. itself. Sense lightens itself and laughs, insofar as it is
sense, with all the intensity of its appeal and repeated demand for sense. Its
lightening (which is not a relieving), means having its own limit as a re
source and having the infinity of its own finitude for its sense.
This sense, this sense of "all sense," this totality of sense made up of
its own alteration, this totality whose being-total consists in not allowing it
self to be totalized (but in being totally exposed) is always too hastily trans
lated into "wordplay," into an acrobatics or linguistic mischief, in sum, into
meaningless surface noises. Howev�r, one would be equally wrong to seek
to "sublate" these plays on and in language in the manner of Hegel, who
sublates the dialectic itselfin a play on the word "sublate." There is no spirit
of or in language, no origin of words before words, that "living speech"
could bring to presence. Things are infinitely lighter and more serious: lan
guage is alone, and this is just what the word "writing" means. It is what re
mains oflanguage when it has unburdened itself of sense, confided it to the
living yet silent voice from which it will never depart.
"Language is alone'" doesn't means that only this exists, as is naively
and imperturbably believed by those who denounce as "philosophies im
prisoned in language" all thinking which does not offer them-that is to
say, which does not name for them-a ready-sliced "life" and "sense" of the
"concrete. " On the contrary, "1anguage IS ' alone" means that language IS . not
an existence, nor is it existence. But it is its truth. Which is to say that if ex
istence is the sense of being, the being of sense, then language alone marks
it, and marks it as its own limit.
Existence is the "there is [il y a]" of something. The fact that it is
[qu'il y a]-here is the origin and the sense, and in these words "there is"
language bursts into flames, laughs, and dies away. But for the "there is" of
anything whatsoever there is only language, and singularly so for the "there
is" of any "cl:tere is" that transports us, delights us, fills us with anguish, for
the "there is" that is " there, but out there, beyond." That is to say; the truth
of being, existence, the immanence of transcendence-or finitude as what
defies and deconstructs the metaphysical pairing of immanence and tran
scendence. This "there is" is presence itself, experience just at itself, right in
our hands and as of now. But the there of "there is" can't be put "there" or
"beyond," or anywhere else, for that matter, nor in the nearness of some in-
Elliptical Sense 99
ward dimension. "There" "signals" the place where there is no longer any
sign, save for the repetition of the demand, from sign to sign, along all of
meaning, toward the limit where existence is exposed. The there is infi
nitely light, it is juncture and brisure, the lightening of every system and
the ellipsis of every cycle, the slender limit of writing. Here we touch on
presence that is no longer present to itselfbut is repetition and supplication
of a presence to come. (Derrida will say, will write, "Come!" as the imper
ative, imperious, yet impoverished, ellipsis of an entire ontology.) The text .
says: "the future is not a future present." This is because it is to come, to
come from the there and in the there. And that is why "the beyond of the
closure of the book is not something to wait for." It is "there, bur over
there, or beyond," and it is thus to be called for, here and now, to be sum
moned at the limit. The appeal, the repeati:!d demand, the joyous supplica
tion says: "let everything come here." That everything should come here, that
all sense co�e and be altered, here, now, at the point at which I write, at
which I fail to write, at this point where we read: the passion of writing is
impassioned by nothing other than this.
II
In the "there is" of existence and in that which "comes there" to pres
ence, being is at stake, as is the sense or meaning of being. In its two ma
jor philosophical forms, the transcendental has designated something put
in reserve, a withdrawal or a retreat of being. For Aristotle, being is what
keeps itself in reserve over and ' above the multiplicity of the categories
(predicaments or transcendentals) through which it is said in "multiply."
Being offers itself and holds itself back in this multiplicity. For Kant, the
transcendental denotes the substitution of a knowledge of the mere condi
tions ofpossible experience for a knowledge of being that would subtend
this experience. Being offers itself and holds itself back in these conditions,
in a subjectivity which does not apprehend itself as substance, but which
knows itself (and judges itself) as a demand. .
When the question of th,e sense of being was reinscribed in philoso
phy, or at its limit, it was not in order to break through the transcendental,
to transcend it and thus penetrate the reserve of its withdrawal. Rather it
was, with Heidegger, in order to interrogate this withdrawal itself as the
essence and as the sense of being. Being: that which is no part of all that is,
but which is at stake in existence. Such is the "ontico-ontological differ-
100 DIFFERENCE
ence." The difference between being and everything that exists is precisely
that which exposes existence as the putting-at-stake of the sense or mean
ing of being (in and as its finitude).
In these circumstances, the opposition or complementarity between
the transcendental (as the withdrawal of the origin) and the ontological (as
the resource at the origin) loses all pertinence. What becomes necessary is
another kind of ontology altogether, or else a completely different tran
scendental; or, perhaps, nothing of the sort, but an ellipsis of the two. Nei
ther the retirement of being nor its givenness, bur presence itself, being it
self qua being, exposed as a trace or as a tracing, withdrawing presence, but
retracing this withdrawal, presenting the withdrawal as what it most prop
erly is: the nonpresentable. This propriety is nothing other than absolute
propriety itself and the propriety of the absolute. The absolute as the ab
solute of finitude-its separateness from all gathering, from all sublation
in an Infinite-gives itself in the event of the trace, the appropriation of
inappropriable propriety (Ereignis, perhaps).
(Need I emphasize the historical, ethical, and political ramifications
of this turning, of this torsion of the absolute? The question is nothing .
other than the question of the "sense of existence" now that God, along
with the Idea, Spirit, History, and Man, is dead. And, indeed, even before
this question, the whole passion of the sense of existence. From a circular
sense to an elliptical sense: How can we think and live that? At this point,
we should add that decisively, and despite what might be said, philosophy
has not failed. Derrida, and others with him, in the anxiety and collapse of
the age, will have beaten the path, a path that must always be beaten
afresh, in the quest for the sense of existence.)
The thought of writing (the thought of the letter of sense, rather
than of the sense of the letter: the end of hermeneutics, the opening and
initiation of sense) reinscribes the question of the sense of being. Ellipsis of
being and the letter. What happens with this reinscription? What happens
when we discern at the origin, as "Ellipsis" does, a "being-written" and a
"being-inscribed"? There is no question of giving a complete answer here.
What "happens" there has not finished happening, Derrida has not fin
ished making, transforming his own response. And undoubtedly the "re
sponse" comes in the very movement ofwriting, which we are bound to re
peat, writing "on" him, but also writing on "us."
What we can perhaps say here, however, is this: that in the ellipsis of
being and the letter, in the dijferance of the sense of being, 'being no longer
Elliptical Sense 101
simply withdraws into its difference from what exists, or into the gap of
that difference. If the ontico-ontological difference was once taken to be .
, its, but the expansion of nothing into nothing, if being itself is nothing.
Such is the infinity proper to finitude. This expansion is a hollowing-out
without limits, and this excavation is writing, "a void which continues to
excavate itself," as the quotation from Jean Catesson in "Ellipsis" puts it.
Thus the void nullifies itself in itself and brings itself to light. Writ
ing excavates a cavern deeper than any philosophical cave; a bulldozer and
caterpillar for tearing up the whole field: a terrain, a passion for the ma
chine, a mechanical passion, mechanical and machinated. This machine,
marked ] D., excavates to the center and the belly. The belly is the altered
void. The machine carries out an evisceration that is itself hysterical. The
hysteria of writing lies in bringing to light (a light unbearable yet simple),
through a genuine simulacrum of disemboweling and parturition, this
limit of being that no one can stomach. Writing perseveres and exhausts it
self there, a corps perdu.
But writing doesn't 'do anything; rather, it lets itself be done by a
'-
machinery, by a machination which always comes to it from somewhere
beyond itself, from being's passion for being nothing, nothing but its own
difference to come, .and which always comes ihere, there where the be
yond is.
In
Let's go back; let's repeat the text again, i:eturning to the other end of
the ellipse, and take up the altered ring at its beginning, insofar as a ring
has a beginning.
"Here or there we have discerned writing": everything is there, in one
fell swoop, in this lapidary incipit whose affirmation or affirmativity rests
on a discreet prosody. (And here, we ought to re-read this sentence with its
proper scansion.) Everything is there in a passion of language which has
overcharged with sense this simple sentence, otherwise so anodyne; which
has saturated with resonances this very brief monody, to the point that
somewhere, in some obscure place, it alters itself, fissures, and noiselessly
gives in. Derrida has always had a devouring thirst for language, and has al
ways striven passionately to make it do his will.
"Here or there": the first words of the text effect a mise en abtme, both
of this text itself and of the book it closes. What has been done (the dis
cerning of writing) has been done right here, and so it is right here: in a
present already past, jl:1st started up. When did we begin to read?-When did
he start writing? It is done; a discovery has taken place; a principle has been
laid down-this incipit is a conc.:lusion, the systematic conclusion of the
book---.:but it is here, under our very eyes, between our hands, and it never
ceases to be at stake, still and most especially when it is written "here." It
is not a "present perfect," but the passage of the present of writing (its
present, its gift, which gives nothing without also giving the giver, "on"
whom we are writing); it is the coming into presence of what is not present.
(What comes into presence does not become present.) It does not stop com
ing, and coming at a limit. Presence itself is nothing but limit. And the
limit itself nothing but the unlimited coming to presence-which is also
the unlimited gift, present, of presence, or its offering: for presence is never
given, but always offered or presented, which means offered to our decision
whether or not to receive it.
And the here is immediately redoubled: it is either here or there.
There, the there, will come at the end of the text, and will be redoubled in
turn: "there, but out there, beyond." Here or there: already the two foci of
the text, already the ellipsis. It's all there. Some years later, at the end of an
other text, accompanying once again the form and forgery of his own sig
nature (of the proper sense of the proper name, where all sense is altered in
effect), Derrida will write that he signs "here. Where? There."3 Here re-
Elliptical Sense 105
moves itself from its own place and there pierces its own place (in per
forming it). Derrida's entire text and oeuvre is altered by perforating and
performing itself. He has, he is, an inextinguishable thirst for a wild and
drunken pursuit of self-externalization of offering himself up where he is
not, of blocking himself from being where he is. He cannot bear himself,
though he is borne only by himsel£ And that sums up the violent, desper
ate, joyous errancy of the sense of the age, of our sense, disseminated in a
great gust coming from beyond the West, just as it is sedimented and
paved over by the thickness, and thus the speechlessness, of our words. All
of Derrida's text is a deaf-mute text.
It is already time to inscribe an ellipsis here-as the title (Derrida's,
and mine in repeating it) has already done. Or, more exactly, one can't do
less, but one must go to the end, the ellipsis of ellipsis.
For Derrida has neglected, by ellipsis, in accordance with the tropo
logical use of the word "ellipsis," which surely he could not have failed to
remember, making explicit the sense of this word. (And so: "Ellipsis" as a
title; the ellipsis of the title. He contrives not to entitle this text any more
than he signs it.) He will. inscribe it in Greek, and elliptically attach to it
the double value of a lack, of a decentering, and of an avoidance. Et·lipsis,
from ek-leipo, I avoid: I avoid-writing what I write. I live off writing, I
leave off writing.
And he will leave out saying (writing) that the ellipsis (as eclipse) has
as its etymon the idea of fault, of the absence of precision or exactitude. The
geometrical ellipsis was initially a generic term for figures that failed to be
identical; before being used (by Apollonius ofPergamon, in his treatise on .
106 DIFFERENCE
or else " this other hand," named, pointed to, and shown to be invisible,
unnameable-and those suspension points that follow it . . . serpent's
hand, or fish's . . . This text says all sorts of sensible things about writing
and about sense, andit says that it has something else tucked away, that it's
telling another story. But also it says that this exhibiting of a secret hides
nothing, that there isn't another story or, at least, that he doesn't know it
himself . . . This text effaces as much as it traces, effaces precisely insofar as
it traces, retracing the effacing and effacing this trace as well . . . Certainly,
we will have missed the sense. It will have changed us. The passion of]. D.
is to alter or to change his reader. What other passion could a piece of writ
ing have?
Once again, and first of all : "here or there." An ellipsis of places, of
two foci, neither ofwhich can center the text or localize the writing that we
have discerned. This double focus, these two fires, two lights, two burnt
patches, are shown to us, then removed from view. What is more, "two" is
more than two; "two" opens onto the multiple. In the "here or there" it is
the suspension, the hesitation, and the beating of the qr that counts. Of
this or [ou] which does not say where [ou] writing is. Nor when, nor how.
"Here or there" is without a definite place, it is also "sometimes, at mo
ments, from time to time," and therefore "by accident, by chance, fortu
itously." Writing can only be made out by accident. Even the calculation of
writing, to which we see Derrida give himself over to here-a calculus that
is meticulous and fierce, with ali the rigor of the geometer (is he also from
. Pergamon, the city of parchment?, this little secre't, scratched here?), a
tenacity ruled by the systematic tracking down ofwhat deregulates and dis
seminates sense-this very calculus (in fact, especially this calculus) is
given over to the vagaries of language. Here or there language might favor
the game or even make the rules. If the circle of sense did link up, the game
would take place everywhere or nowhere: no more play, nothing but sense.
But the game of sense implies the hazardous ellipsis of its rules.
Neither manifest literalness nor mise en abtme, no less manifest,
makes sense of the text. Neither the "whole" nor the "hole" of sense. But
always once more the ellipsis, which is to say: sense itself as ellipsis, as not
moving around a fixed point, but coming endlessly to the limit-here or
there-where signification is eclipsed and a presence only arrives at its
sense: a rabbi, a fish, a piece of parchment, who and what else? This sense
of a presence is the joy, the pleasure and pain of the enjoyment of this pres
ence, exposed before or beyond all presentation and any present of a sig-
ElliptiCal Sense 107
nifiable sense (of a sense present to itself?). This takes place where place
has no signifying privilege, unassuming places indifferent to all presences,
to all the differences between them: a constant sum, here or there.
Here we ai:e at this limit: the waning [accident] of sense, the disten
sion ofits foci, frees up the task of thinking (though in what sense is it still
"thinking"?) the sense of our finite existences.
Transcendental experience is right here. There is, in effect, nothing in
this incipit that does not bear the stamp of the empirical: the randomness
of place and moment, the simple facticity of discerning. The incipit gives
the origin and the principle of the system in the register of the empirical.
Here's what happened, it's happened to' us. It not only opens up discourse
to writing; but it already breaches it ("breach" will be the penultimate
word of the book). It opens up an irrepressible empiricity, in writing it, in
offering as a narrative what is, by rights, an exposition more geometrico, but
elliptically so. Thus the transcendental experience of writing is not
Husserl's "transcendental experience." Husserl's was meant to be pure ex
perience, the reduction and purification of the empirical. Here, by con- .
trast, experience is impure-and this is why, undoubtedly, the concept of
"experience" is itself inappropriate, at least insofar as it presupposes some
sort of experimental setup, as is the concept of the transcendental (which
always lays claim to an a priori purity as condition of possibility).
Instead it is a question here of putting together what befalls us, in the
non-purity of the event and the accident, the historical passage in which all
sense of History is changed: wars and genocides, collapses of representa
tion, the erosion of politics by global technology, the drifting of "un
chained peninsulas."
In that case, experience should be expressed or thought as "wander
ing," as "adventure," and as the "dance" named in the text-in short, as
passion itself: the passion of sense. What would pass as a "condition of pos
sibility" here (but also an "ontology") would be on the order of passion.
But passion is always destined to the impossible. It does not transfom it
into the possible, does not master it; rather, it is dedicated and exposed to
it, passive at the limit where the impossible comes, which is to say, where
everything comes, all sense, and where the impossible is reached as the
limit.
The impossibie is the' center, the origin, and the sense. Ellipsis is the
ellipsis of the center, its lack, its failing, and the presentation of the "dan
gerous hole" into which the "anxious desire of the book" seeks to "have in
sinuated itselE" But when it insinuates itself there it discovers or discerns
that it has plunged into nothing other than the "horizontality of a pure
surface." The circle gapes; the ellipsis surfaces. Touching the center, one
Elliptical Sense 109
touches writing. All sense is altered-but what glides across the surface
(brilliant, slippery fish . . . ) and what plunges into the hole (tightly rolled ·
parchment), would these not be the same? The same which alters, and all
sense, once again, without end? And is it the same passion to touch the
center and to touch writing? Is it the same machine which digs, fills in, and
traces anew?
IV
Undoubtedly it is the same machine: has th�re ever been more than
one passion-more than one anguish, more than one joy, even if this unic
ity is in essence plural? The passion for the center, for touching the center,
and for the touching of the center has always been J. D:s passion-the
passion of philosophy as the passion ofwriting. The one and the other, ac
cording to the two senses of the genitive, and one in the other, and one for
the other. Both completed, raised up, or cast into the depths by the passion '
for touching language, as he will have repeated. To touch language: to .
touch the trace, and to touch its effacement. To touch what moves and vi
brates in the "open mouth, the hidden center, the elliptical return." To
touch the ellipsis itself-and to touch ellipsis inasmuch as it touches, as an
orbit touches the edges of a system, whether cosmological or ocular. A
strange, orbital touch: touching .the eye, the tongue, language, and the
world. At the center, and in the belly.
It is the same passion: to discern is to see and to trace; it is to se� or to
trace at the point where the rings around the eyes touch-between the
eyes. Discerning is where touching and vision touch. It is the limit of vi
sion-and the limit of touch. To discej:n is to see what differs in touching.
To the see the center differing (from itself): the ellipsis. There is a certain
narrowing in all discerning: sight narrows to the extreme, and becomes
sharper and more strangled. It always has its two hands clenched around
the book.
It is the system, again. It is the will to system. (But what is will? Who
. knows, or th·inks he knows? Doesn't will differ in its essence?) It is the will
to touch: the wish that the hands touch, across the book, and through the
book; that its hands touch, reaching just as far as its skin, its parchment;
that our hands touch, always through the intermediary of skin, but touch
nonetheless. To touch oneself, to be touched right at oneself, outside one
self, without anything being appropriated. That is writing, love, and sense.
lIO DIFFERENCE
has always played-on stage and at stake-the body lost at the limit of all
language, the foreign body, which is the body of our foreignness.
Elliptical Sense III
That is why this body is lost in the very discourse of writing and the
deconstruction of metaphysics, insofar as that is a discourse (a philosophy
or even a thinking) . The expt':rience named "writing" is this violent ex
haustion of the discourse in which "all sense" is altered, not into another or
the other sense, but in this exscribed body, this flesh which is the whole re
source and plenitude 'of sense, even though it is neither its origin nor its
end, yet still place and the ellipsis of place.
This body is material and singular-it is also the very body of
Jacques Derrida-but it is material in a singular way: one cannot designate
it qr present it as a " [subject] matter." It is presentwith that presence of the
unavoidable withdrawal of writing, where it can be nothing but its own el
lipsis, there, out there, and beyond.
There, out there, beyond "Derrida" himself, but nonetheless here, on
his body and his text, philosophy will have moved, materially, and our his
tory will have moved. It will have inscribed/exscribed something which has
nothing to do with any of the possible transformations of ontology or of
the transcendental (even if the discourse frequently proves susceptible to
being brought back to such transformative operations). Philosophy will
have moved with a movement discreet, powerful, and trembling: the
movement of a lost body presented at the limit of language. This body is
made of flesh, of gestures, forces, blows, passions, techniques, powers, and
drives; it is dynamic, energetic, economic, political, sensuous, aesthetic
but it is· none of these meanings as such. It is the presence which has no
sense, but which is sense, its ellipsis and its advent.
Derrida "himself"-or his ellipsis-is a wild singularity of this body,
crazy for it, crazy with its presence, crazy with laughter and anguish at the
always-retraced limit where its own presence never stops coming a corps
perdu-discreet, powerful, trembling like everything which is to come.
Tramlated by Jonathan Derbyshire
6
Borborygmi
;"" .
II4 DIFFERENCE
naming itself with its own sound, so that what is proper both to it and to
us can resonate or ring out? But truth is essentially self-presentation. Truth
presents and names itsel£ All the while truth turns itself inside out, as a re
lation to itself, as the' enfolding of the innermost distance which forms it,
just as it presents itself to itself and as it presents self Can we thus imagine
a borborygmus for truth's "intestinal difference"?2
This self-presentation is so intimate and intestinal that it is also en
tirely foreign. Is it a question, then, df a barbarism, of the language of truth
being a language of the other, of the wholly foreign, and, as such, being
badly formed, mumble.<f, and stammered? A barbaric idiom? Does Derrida
think about anything else? Is Derrida naming anything else when he writes
his own name, "Derrida," when he writes this name and about this partic
ular proper name beneath his signature? Throughout his work autobiogra
phy is at issue to such an extent that all other questions appear secondary
or derived.3 Tpe philosophical order itself seems to dissolve, to capsize, or
to run mad in the erratic empiricalness of a name beyond all question or
concept. But beneath autobiography, and beneath this "outside," if not as
this outside, could it be that what is really at stake is an auto-hetero-graphy
of truth?
II
hind Derrida as such, evidently and eminently, nothing. All background, all
hypokeimenon or subjectum, disappears ipso facto: the idiomatic gesture or
tone is responsible, by itself, for this disappearance and abolition of all
wishing to speak, all intentionality, and all plan. Nothing behind and, in
consequence; everything up front. Everything pushed forward, but a for
ward with no backward, not even a phenomenon, not even a surface.
If there is nothing behind, there is nothing in front, either: nothing
ahead of itself or of us, nothing which relates to itself or to the other. Not
a manifestation or an event, not a story and thus neither a process nor a
narration. No autobiography, therefore, but the scratched outline of an au
tograph, an event, ifyou like, though with nothing occurring or arising but
the most extreme sense or truth of all sense and truth.
And all this only in a sense, of course, for there could never be sense
without the alterity which works over sense as such. That is its truth, in
fact, the truth of sense. If I say such and Derrida, and if I say One Such in
general, I could very well be said to be saying nothing, but it could not be
said that I am not saying. And that is what cannot be affected by even the
most extravagant claims of the skeptic. The most obscure and barbaric id
iom can indeed take language to the limits of meaning and communica
tion-but it is still language, it is language which is thereby stretched to
the limit. It is language that has become a thing, withdrawn from any re
lation to sense. But this thinglike language, this noise or mark, itself means,
even if it expresses nothing, if it wills to say nothing, or even if it wills not
to will. It is beyond the will. It seeks neither to communicate nor signify,
but is the pure expression of that which puts itself forward without going
outside itself, stamping its own truth on itself Dividing itself without go
ing outside itself, necessarily an auto-hetero-graph. An expression so pure
and S9 in tune with itself that it is precisely the annihilation of the will as
representation and as power to present representation. It is, in its tension,
just the triggering of self-presence.
The click of the trigger. "I cl'," he says:5 clack, lack, ale, gl, tr, infra
or intra-verbal phonemes, like the inaudible "a" of "differance" or such
parentheses, onomatopoeias, such glug-glug, tic-tak, trrr, or words that
might one. call, in their way, phone-emphatic, wink, gul, hinge, thence,
dike, tint, sing, an obsession with resonance and assonance, a poetics that
is above all sonorous, infra-significant, where one blows out of all propor
tion sonorities slipping outside the sign, drawing out the sound of the sign,
angiospermic, androeciumic, epigynetic, · petroglyphic, heliotropic, and
. .
,
Borborygmi Il7
intimate or intestinal reaches of the auto. But what is this trigger if it is not
truth? What else could it be but this alterity of the true, which grasps the
thing as such and properly names it, not in order to signify it, but to make
of it the senseless origin of sense?
The truth is that the thing names itself properly in such a way that
nothing precedes it or subordinates it; it says itself in being, if not this side
of or beyond being, but always saying itselfwith a saying before or beyond
discourse, saying or manifesting the itselfof the proper and the proper as
itself-the to-itself which opens sense itself.
Without that, would there be anything there at all? Would there be
someone, a thing or a person? In allowing the impossible idiomaticity of
the proper to proliferate in a starry madness of sub- and sur-nominations,
of hyper-nominations, like galaxies expanding around a black hole of the
proper name absorbing all sense, it is the proper which "Derrida" is stalk
ing and tracking, and trying to make melt away and implode on top, un
derneath, behind, or in front; nothing less than the totality and the archi
totality of the proper in truth, thus its absolute, singular, irreducible,
incompressible, irrefragable, irrecuperable uniqueness, but also its ab
solute, indefinitely plural, multipliable, extendable, communicable, ex
changeable generality. Such a Derrida One Such all origin, any living
= =
present of sense, the birth and death of each one as every one which rec
ognizes itself as such, as having nothing to recognize but its uniqueness
without unity.
III
Borborygmi II9
A fleet of screens [paravents] with purple sails, purple veils [voiles pourpres], a fleet
ready for ,the attack, the defense, a fleet guarding itself at the prow and· the poop,
.
gold spurs for the parade.
The parade always stays behind [derriere] .
Derriere: every time the word comes first, ifwritten therefore after a period
and with a capital letter, something inside me used to start to recognize there my
father's name, in golden letters on his tomb, even before he was there.
A fortiori when I read Derriere le rideau [Behind the curtain].
Derriere, behind, isn't it always already behind a curtain, a veil, a weaving.
A fleecing text.8 .
Behind a veil, the truth. The truth ofwhat is behind, ofwhat either can be
unveiled or remain hidden, a promised and intangible nudity, and at the
same time the back or behind of truth, the back side of the fabric, texture
itself, itself and spun out of itself, not something to be veiled or unveiled,
but something set out-something that sets sail, in the sense of taking to
the high seas and !paking for clear water, without limits, a showing that is
both exhibition and protection, ostentation and dissimulation.
What is he showing here, what truth? He shows how he already grabs
hold of himself from behind himself, or rather, he says how "something in
me" grabs hold of itself, how the very thing of the self grabs hold of itself
by itself, a self behind the self, a selflike its own origin or provenance. Not
just the active origin of the father, but an origin already originated ahead
of time and before its hour, ahead of its own emergenc;e, already, properly
speaking, corivey�d to its properness of immemorial provenance. The
deathly inscription of the name, the inscription of the death of the name,
of the name as death,' my own death, then, in my name, though a death
=�==�..."",
. . - . . . ..
- , :... ---
'. " ,. .
- --_._._-_. :;.....;; . - -.::;.;.:..!� �"-,..,"';.
' ., '. .
'':.:-'; .. "- -'- ;:.
",_. �.- - ... . . ,.: - -... " �'-';-" . -
Borborygr.ni 121
seized from behind as what was already behind the origin itselE Before me
the tombstone allows me to see the name as the obverse, as the reverse of
the origin-of its own origin, which it will never grasp or recognize, except
from behind and as the behind.9 "Derrida," therefore, picked up and
turned upside down, turned upside down and cut off from his da:1 0 da
without da, like Sein, or, who . knows, like Mit-Sein. Being alone, and be
ing-with, being-alongside-oneself, being-with-what-is-before-oneself, and
not being-there, nor even being-the-there, but being what is behind the
there, what is not there, offered, indicated, or localized, but inscribes itself
beneath.
Isn't that the truth of the there, however? The truth of each there in
and as such? For there is not one . encircled locality, determinate and op
posed to another (not the da as opposed to a fort, but rather the fort of all
da) . Da is the opening up of place before the place itself, the already-open
.
without which there would be. no place, no site of being: the hinterland of
place. The da cannot be occupied. Rather, it is a matter of being; that is,
instead of presupposing it as a given locale, presupposing oneself in and as
the ownmost presupposition of the da, in and as its taking place before and
behind the place. Da is the "essential openness" which Dasein "carries in
its ownmost Being":l1 it does not carry it in front of it, like something it
might present. Rather, it literally brings it along "all the way from home"
(von Hause aus mit), which is a way of saying "originally" or "in its own
most being," and which implies a house behind or from which one
emerges, even if, at the same time, it is the emergence which makes the
house (as the assonance Hauslaus suggests): the emerging which makes the
opening or clearing in which the house consists. The house or home: the
family, the name of the father, and, first of all, the genetic outpouring,
emergence, genealogy.
Hence da is oehind as the up-ahead'of the clearing which always pre
cedes, which is precedence itself and thus the essence of pre-sence. A
dwelling place, in which dwelling consists in opening and opening oneself,
opening a "self [soil" as such, which is to say, again, a "home [chez
soi]"which is always, infinitely, behind itself and, in consequence, also al
ways ahead of itselE
Derrida cuts off his da,12 he scotomizes it in order to substitute for it,
like a delocalization and an alteration (er, "he" in German; erring of the
trace and of errance; era of the great temporal openings): thus, he gives his
da over to its truth, he reopens it and reinitializes its ending-and this ges-
122 DIFFERENCE
of which the whole of Derrida's text, the whole text of every Derrida,
would wish itself to be nothing but a gigantic tauto-phono-grapho-crypto
phaner-ology, biting its own tail, in all senses and with all imaginable ef
fects simultaneously, fireworks and cold ashes, a madness watching over it
self in the moment that it unwinds, but arising also from this very close
'
watch.
Borborygmi 125
126 DIFFERENCE
empty ofsense: this emptiness, in truth, is the opening of all sense, in and f
to all senses and in all directions. But the opening has to be opened, slit, (
launched, burst apart, or cracked, each time, incessantly.
BorborYg7ni 127
giving of itself to itself, which In' fact m:ea�s giving itself up to what has no
other place or consistency than the "itself". of the "giving itself up" itself.
To appropriate oneself: giving oneself up, or devoting oneself, to giving
oneself up or to devoting oneself-and always, in the final analysis, sur
rendering to the infinite turning back which constitutes the structure and
the sense of self.
Behind, consequently-not what would be behind, but the being
behind-itself of the unique. Behind there is nothing for sense, but this
nothing itself is like a hard, impenetrable, resisting thing: the being-back of
the back itself, which attaches to nothing and through which nothing,
coming from elsewhere, can penetrate. Behind each "one," as its behind,
there is the primal matter of the unique: uniqueness itself, insignificant and
as ifreduced to its impenetrability. Primal matter is the back side: that is to
say, that which has. no face, that which one cannot face up to, but which
opens and which comes into the open, or as the open itself. The open as
such: that which cannot be indexed "as such," being comparable to noth
ing, not even itself, since the "self" its�lf is still, infinitely, to come. The
open as such, incomparable, bU.t which, barely open, resounds in itself as it
self, the echo of its idiomatic creaking, cracking and straining.
This is why it must be one, each time one, which impossibly passes
behind: it doesn't pass behind as one might journey to the depths, behind
appearances or into the supposed consistency of a whole. Rather, it must
pass uniquely to the unique reverse of the unique. This reverse is neither
present nor absent, it is, properly speaking, neither form nor matter,
though it has the irreducibility of matter and presence, and it has the al
. teration and torsion of absence and form. This torsion of the irreducible,
this splitting at the bottom, which does not arise from it but nonethel�ss
belongs to it just as it breaks it to pieces-this splitting which conse
quently withdraws into the depths, as unobtrusive as disruptive or diffi
cult-is a "kernel," not as a hidden presence, but as something which es
capes from "the laws of presence itsel£"18 It is the hard kernel which is not
some other thing behind the thing, but the thing itself behind itself, with
drawn into its reality. It is here just a que�tion of the real: res, the thing it
self in its own detonation. Derrida's thinking is an absolute reaiism of the
pure real, that is, of the real which springs forth froni behind everything:
realizing everything, while being nothing realized, being nothing, the res of
realization itself. Not only does this realism affirrri the real, it touches it. To
touch it is not to merge with it: it is to come into contact, to experience the
128 DIFFERENCE
Borbory�i 129
JUDGING
" . -" .�.�. - • ._-. ,.- ,,",..-.-�.- --_....__
.. , __ ,:._�-.__,...,....__,__ ___ ....._ , ,_,,_ _._. •",�__·r"'�....__
.. �__. _ .
Stark violence
Lays all walls waste; private estates are torn,
Ransacked in the public eye. We forsake
Our lone luck now, compelled by bond, by blood,
To keep some unsaid pact; perhaps concern
Is helpless here, quite extra, yet we must make
The gesture, bend and hold the prone man's head. I
• . P.' _� ,,':,�:_ ,,.'•. , ;;. ".: . • �.- . . . ... .. .,. _ . " .. _." _ � ',:.:., - .. ...::: ;...-,' _ ....... � ..... ...;-.. ..... ,.,...... .....,.. ' . _ " . �.::.
.••• .' �
::; ;., - . , . .. .
And yet it is always possible that the categorical imperative is, at the
same time, rather closer to us than we might suspect. Freedom itself, this
freedom conceived as a state-or as a being-withdrawn from every
power and from every external command, this freedom is posited as a "cat
egorical imperative," by which we mean, at the very least, that it is not
open to debate. (This is, for instance, the explicit or implicit motif in our
most general practice of defending "human rights.")
This being so, we somehow tap into and divert a certain aspect of the
word- "freedom." We claim that freedom is imposed by freedom itself, ab
solutely and unconditionally. In one way or another, we pose or suppose
that this freedom (or, if we no longer want to run the risk of determining
it in terms of an essence, then this or that collection of "freedoms" or "hu
man rights") is given, conceived, recognizable, or assignable. If freedom,
for Kant, is the ratio essendi of the moral law, this law is, in turn, the ratio
,cognoscendi of freedom (which turns the imperative into the singular -au
thority of this "knowledge"); for us, by contrast, freedom is thought and is
o�ly thinkable as being simultaneously the ratio essendi and the ratio
cognoscendi of all moral law. Self-evidently, therefore, freedom imposes or
has to impose itsel£ But this self-imposition is no longer really an imposi
tion; if it were not imposed on those who ridicule and degrade it (or if its
imposition were not sought), freedom wouldn't impose itself; it would
flourish, it would bloom spontaneously, since its nature is ultimately that
of an essential and pUre spontaneity. The imperative, then, is not exactly an
imperative. The imperative of our imperatives is that true imperatives must
not have the character of constraint, of externality, nor must they be tied to
the exercise of an injunction, an obligation or a submission.
(At the same time, an abyss opens up betWeen what we oddly persist
in calling a "subject," between what we represent as being stripped of its
spontaneity by economy, history, the unconscious, writing, technology,
and what is, in fact, the true metaphysical concept of the subject-to
which, in the last analysis, we no longer even realize we have been sub
jected in the name of freedom.)
Yet it still falls to us, like a muffled and obstinate demand, to think
something (freedom, for instance) as an unconditional prescription. Per
haps we cannot even think without insisting, in one way or another, that
this very thing---."thinking"-immediately obeys some secret intimation.
So, through or because of its very withdrawal, the imperative draws nearer
to us. And this proximity may well be closer thari everything that, under
the guise of proximity, we think of in terms of familiarity or intimacy. It
136 JUDGING
would be the proximity of that with which we are obsessed but that is lost "
to us, the proximity of that whose loss haunts us.
Now, what haunts [hante] is, according to its accepted etymological
origins, what inhabits or occupies [habite] or, on a more knowing etymo
logical reading, what returns to the stable, to the hearth, to the home.
Haunt is from the same family as Heim. The proximity of the imperative
might well be the Un-heimlichkeit that haunts our thinking, a disturbing
peculiarity that disturbs only because it is so close, so immediate in its es
trangement. But to return to the familiar abode is still to return to the
ethos. The stakes here are none other than those of an ethics, therefore2-
not in the sense of a science or a discipline, however, or in the sense of a
moral sense or sentiment, but in the sense, precisely, of a haunting.
. Now, it cannot be a matter of taming the peculiarity of the impera
tive or of pacifying its haunting. Even supposing that the imperative were
able to anticipate our future-to predict the return or the advent of an im
perative ethics-we have known since Hegel that such anticipation is not
the job of philosophy, which cannot pass beyond its own time. Which
means what, precisely? Simply that time-the element of thinking-does
not overstep itself; this limit, in short, defines it. To think is neither to pre
dict nor to prophesy nor to deliver messages, but to expose oneself to what
happens with time, in time. In the time of haunting there can and must be
a thinking and an ethics-if ethics it is-ofhaunting.
But assuming, despite everything, that such anticipation were possi
ble, it could never be the anticipation of a tamed imperative, an imperative
rendered familiar and natural. If we have indeed lost the imperative (as
sUining that such a remark makes any sense), we can rest assuted that, at
the very least, we are unlikely to recover it; its essence runs counte� to or
avoids this. The imperative cannot be domesticated-and this is again one
of the hallmarks of haunting: it is, by definition, something domestic that
cannot be domesticated. It does not enter into the economy that it haunts.
It leads us back to an abode that, as an abode, doesn't allow us to settle
comfortably into it. And yet it is still an abode. We certainly don't dwell in
the imperative, but we do dwell under it.
As such, it isn't a matter of recognizing, reevaluating, and reappro
priating the categorical impenltive, whether as a reactivation ofKant's phi
losophy or as a "resource" within it (philosophy cannot go beyond its own
time), nor even as a way of appeasing the ghosts that haunt us. It can only
be a matter of indicating the imperative's insistence for a thinking, our
thinking, that is less a "tributary of Kant" than it is one that submits to an
.
. . . .-. . --�..� . . . . . - '-.. "'.... .::" .. : .. . . ..;:.� ..�. -. . � . ' � '-- -'
imperative necessity whereby it ,is referred back, initially, from its very
opening, to Kant.3
Why, for Kant, the imperative, therefore? Why does the expression
of the moral law take place in the imperative voice? Why a prescription
rather than a description? Why an order rather than a recommendation or
an exhortation?
Kant's reply is simple: the imperative exists because evilexists in man.
There has to be the imperative because there is evil.
Immediately, this reply is one that disturbs our moral sensibility.
We're not about to tolerate Kant's imputation to man and in man of a
wholly radical evil. To the evil the spectacle of which the political scene
(and can there be, henceforth, any other scene? isn't every scene political?)
gives us a glimpse, a spectacle that we can agree is unparalleled in our his
tory due to its constancy, its technical nature, its rationality, to this evil we
want to concede only the nature of :in accident (and, reciprocally, the very ,
category of "accident" has ended up inheriting the intrinsic value of �
"evil" or a "misfortune"). Those who do not see history as the necessary
and perhaps asymptotic process of this accident's elimination see .it instead
as an accident in general, as a catastrophe having taken place on a prior or
ideal register. In either case, wouldn't the accidental character of evil be the
hidden II!-etaphysical resource underlying our paradoxical capacity to resign
ourselves to evil as such-the evil that we tend to call "banal"-so that we
can have done with it onCe and for all?
Here, though, I'm not so much raising the question of evil-which is
basically the question of its Kantian incomprehensibility-in itself as I am
evoking it from afar. Any such examination would demand a great deal of
groundwork since, in all likelihood, it couldn't really begin without sus
tained and prior consideration of the imperative. AB is the case with free
dom, the imperative is the ratio cognoscendi of evil. Concerning the latter,
let me merely say two things: first, that its question (if it is still a question
in the classical philosophical sense) is there at the very horizon of our ques
tions and, second, th�t its presence as a question does not, in the face of
the accidentality of evil, posit something that amounts to its pure and sim
ple essentiality, and thus to some modern avatar of "original sin." Not that
I want to make concessions to our sensibility, which recoils from the 'evo-
138 JUDGING
There is the imperative because there is evil. There is evil, and that is
to $ay, the possibility of transgressing the law-and the tendency to do so.
The law exists as a commandment because it can be violated. Now, this
does not mean that there is, on the one hand, the law itself (in the way that
there are physical laws, for example, laws of nature) and, on the other, the
imperative addressed to someone who, accidentally, might not direct him
or herself spontaneously according to the law. Were this the case (and this
case is typical where laws are concerned), the imperative would not be the
law itself; as an imperative, it would not be identical with it. As such, it
would have a decidedly supplemental corrective and pedagogic function. It
would address itself to the infant in man, and not to man. But the imper
ative involves neither punishment nor reward: and it's in precisely this that
we find its categorical rather than its purely hypothetical character (a dis
tinction equivalent in Kant to the distinction between moral and technical
imperatives). The law takes place only as the imperative. And so the im
perative does not prescribe that we act in accordance with th� law, since
"the law," in this sense, is given neither by the imperative nor prior to it.
Ra.ther, it prescribes acting legally, in the legislative sense. It prescribes that
the maxim of action be the founding act of a law, of the law. Without
dwelling on the formidable implications of this state of affairs, let us sup
pose that the imperative prescribes the act oflegislation (hence it prescribes
.
"umversally") .
Let us leave to one side the metaphysical or ideological model ofleg
islative sovereignty-whether originary, institutive �r constitutive
which is also involved in this thinking. The effects of this model, incon
testable though they may be, are submitted by Kant to an essential
limitation: it. can never be a matter of either producing or presenting this
originality itself Here, it is enough to recall, as a clue, that in the political
· - . ."
.,. '..•. '.. . .;.:.. ---' -;;. . ��..
realm Kant explicitly renounces any search for the originary institution of
the legal state. On the contrary, the political order is itself submitted to
the imperative:
There are thus three distinct authorities (potestas legislatoria, executoria, iudiciaria)
by which a state (civitas) has its autonomy, that is, by which it forms and preserves
itself in accordance with laws of freedom. A state's well being consists in their be
ing united (salus reipublicae suprema lex est). By the well-being of a state must not
be understood the welfare of its citizens nor their happiness; for happiness can per
haps come to them more easily and as they would like it to in a state of nature (as
Rousseau asserts) or even under a despotic government. By the well-being of a
state is understood, instead, that condition in which its constitution conforms
most fully to principles of Right; it is that condition after which reason, by a cat
egorical imperative, makes it obligatory for us to strive.4
Contrary to appearances, this doesn't concern a thinking "of the state" in
the usual sense in which we understand the term. The "state" designates,
rather, the space necessary for the legislation that demands the imperative.
The imperative wouldn't be able to prescribe if the legislation were
given. That is to say, it couldn't prescribe what it prescribes if thi:: legisla
tion were given independently of itself; it couldn't prescribe if evil were in
s�ribed in this legality independent of it. We need to distinguish between
recognized evil, localized by a law that takes it into account as a fact, and
the evil disposition implicated in law by the imperative law. if evil were a
law of nature (we tend to view it this way when we confuse the ferocity of
an animal or the devastating force of a volcano with the cruelty of human
ity), the prescription of the good would be absurd, and futile. Besides, the
possibility of violating the law has to be imputed to us.s In the necessity of
this imputation, evil is incomprehensible. But this is why evil, as an .in
comprehensible possibility, is evil, whlclI is to say, free. If it were not free, it
would not be "evil." (But this does not mean that without any evil act
there would be no freedom, since freedom would then be confused with
free will; instead, it means that without the possibility of evil and so with- .
out a disposition toward it, there would be no freedom. Freedom isn't the
free choice between "good" and "evil" since, ultimately, for such a choice,
everything is good What freedom is remains as incomprehensible as evil it
self: at the very least, however, this means that freedom
. is addressed only to
a being disposed toward evil.)
As such, the imperative corresponds to radical evil, to the evil that
corrupts the very ground of maxims.6 That this evil is not that of a
"propensity" is evident in two respects: it doesn't originate in a natural in-
140 JUDGING
clination, and it doesn't correspond with a slip, with a deviation from the
maxim (in this case, the deviation would perhaps be no more than an error
and perhaps there would be no possibility of voluntary evil; here, however,
the will itself has to be radically corruptible). Evil is the corruption of the
ground of the mari� and a maxim thus corrupted is a maxim that is no
longer law making. Evil is not a contrary law; it is the disposition contrary
to the law, the il-Iegislative disposition.
And yet it is because the law is the law ofmaking the law (or of law
making) that it reveals of itself-and, in a certain way, in itself-the in
scription of this possibility. By definition, an ordinary law sets the "outlaw"
outside the law. Yet the law of the law includes the outlaw as the one to
whom it is necessarily addressed-the one to whom, in this sense, it is
abandoned, while its addressee is, in turn, abandoned to the entire rigor of
the law.? "Act in 'such a way . . . " only makes sense if it is addressed, not
only to one who is able to refrain from acting in such a way, but first and
foremost to one who, radically, in his or her very disposition, does not act
in such a way. The law prohibits the one to whom it is addressed from
obeying it from the outset, without stumbling. It is the law of freedom,
therefore, and this is why it takes the form of an imperative. This latter
isn't an expression derived from the law, its mouthpiece, as it were. As the
imperative, it is or makes the law.
The imperative law thus differs from right. Right never says ''Act!'' It
articulates a rule and asks that a particular case be submitted to it;8 as such,
however, it does not command. Or, more exactly, it commands to the ex
tent that it is recognized as right, to the extent that it has the force of a law,
which presupposes the parceling out of a scope proper to law as such (col
lectivity, state, church, etc.). Here, though, we are dealing with the law of
all reasonable beings, all beings capable oflaw. The imperative states-but
is this still a matter of "stating" or of "saying"? And if so, in what sense?
the law's case, absolutely.
And yet, for all that, it is not an order. As with right, it differs from
the orders with which our sensibility continually confuses it. At the very
least, it differs if we understand the order as Canetti, for example, under
stands it: as the gesture or relation whose most primitive form would be
that of the threat of death that guides the fleeing deer. In fact, it could be
that every human exercise of the order arises from such a menacing com-
- � �, � . ."-. ":"',�-:•.. , ::.. ,,�.. : :� .:...:.- - : :.. ::..- , ;" ,.
mandment. But the imperative contains neither threat nor promise. In
deed, its essence lies in the fact that it contains neither. Such is the sense of
obedience out of duty, as opposed to an execution that only conforms to
duty. To obey because of duty is to obey in the interests of duty itself alone,
which is what has no interest. Moreover, duty obliges us to nothing other
than duty itself, whereas the order requires its being carried out. (Do we re
ally need to be i:eminded of the fact that, for Kant, this' has nothing to do
with a morality that is satisfied with good intentions, with a morality ex
empt from doing everything possible in order to carry out its duty?)
Duty obliges us to duty. In other words, it prescribes the legislative
act, and this act, by itself, has no option but to obligate itselfto the univer
sality of the law, since it is obligated to a universality which is precisely not
the universality of the particular contents of the law but that of its legality
or, more exactly still, that of the being-law of the law. The law of duty
obliges us to the duty of the law, this law that is not given.
Hence, although the law lies outside of the realm of orders, it does
not lie outside that of duty. The former is limited to the application of a
law with which it cannot, by itself, identify. On the contrary, it presup
poses that such a law is known, whatever it might be (for example, the law
of the strongest . . . ) . In the same way, and for the same reason, the order
isn't identified with the utterance of the law, and the act of ordering can
generally do without speech: "The order is older than language, otherwise
dogs would not be able to understand it."9 On the other hand, it makes no
sense to imagine the imperative as other than being uttered.10 The imper
ative is only a verbal or discursive form. Duty is not a mode of being-at
least not in the classical sense of the term-but a mode of language-al
though perhaps in a radically new sense. What I have to do can be pre
sented nonlinguistically; thefact that I have to do it can only ever be said.
Ultimately, moreover, the fact that I have to do it can only be said to me.
'�ct . . . " This has to be addressed to me.
The duty of the law is no more a duty of love than it is an order:
"There is no feeling of duty, although there is, indeed, a feeling from the
representation �f our duty, for the latter is a necessitation through the cat
egorical moral imperative. Duty of compulsion not duty oflove."ll Indeed:
"One can demand of man that he do what. the law commands of him, but
not that he do it voluntarily."12 If duty depended on seduction, it would no
longer be duty, strictly speaking, but would possess a power whose effect
would be a matter of what Kant calls the "pathological." In this respect,
such an effect could no longer distinguish duty from the threatening order.
142 JUDGING
When Kant writes that "in man there dwells an active principle . . .
accompanying him not as soul . . . but as spirit, one that . . . commands
. him irresistibly according to the law of moral practical reason"13 he means
that the imperative does not exi.st in the psychic substance known to us
only phenomenologically (and so never really as substance), but only in this
Gemiit whose main job is to be the unity of transcendental constitution.
The imperative does not belong to the nature of the subject; rather, it be
longs to what, although resembling a subject, exceeds, in the strongest
sense of the term, its subject status: it belongs to reason's condition of pos
sibility, to the condition of possibility of a reason that is itself practical.
More precisely: a reason that is practical in and ofitself. Not, however, in
that it shows itself to be such (it does not "reveal" itself); rather, this prac
ticality happens to it as a fact, as the factum rationis of which it is not the
subject. (This fact has no subject; it is not a subject).
The imperative provides the conditions of possibility for praxis or is
itself the transcendental of praxi�. As elsewhere, yet here, perhaps, more ·
than anywhere else, this transcendental indicates nontranscendence. The
principle of praxis isn't a transcendent reality; rather, it consists in reason's
being practical in and of itself or in the a priori practical condition of rea
sonable beings as such. For Kant (who turns back, in this respect, to the
Aristotelian tradition), praxis isn't in the first instance the order of actions
insofar as they demand submission to evaluations and norms; rather, it is
the order of action itself insofar as it imposes itself as the order of reason
and insofar as it imposes praxis, that is, action whose result is not distinct
from the agent (unlike-or :;1S opposed to-poiesis, which produces a dis
tinct result). Or, ifyou prefer, the stakes are not primarily the rationalizing
of action but the discovery that reason as such, as pure .reason, has to act.
To act as pure reason means to make law. Such is the duty of reason. On
this account, and for the first time in its history, reason no longer consists
in a given rationality in terms of which acts have to be measured; rather, as
pure practical reason it is identical with the a priori duty of being-that is,
of acting out-what it is: pure practical reason.
No doubt pure reason is not only an expression that is foreign to our
sensibility but one whose concepts need to be submitted-perhaps more
than any other concepts-to critique or to the deconstruction of meta
physics. Yet it could well be that a new task announces itself thus: the task
of thinking "pure reason" in terms ofits being-practical, in terms ofthe duty
that constitutes or enjoins it.
The Kategorein ofExcess 143
" , , .
,- .�" ' '''' -- ,.__. • l.:'•. " ' � ...-:.:_ o..:....
. .:.-'-�.� __. �
of the law: it is not a matter of the subject's giving -its -law to itself; rather,
in reason itself, an injunction is addressed to reason, from without, there
fore, from a doubly other outside that demands, addresses, and enjoins it.
What is it in us (we can ask ourselves) whereby we, beings ever dependent upon
narure through so many needs, are at the same time r;Used so far above these needs
by the idea of an original predisposition (in us) that we count them all as nothing,
and ourselves as unworthy ofexistence, ifwe cater to their satisfaction (though this
alone can make life worth desiring) in opposition to the law-a law by virrue of
which our reason commands us potendy, yet without making either promises or
threats?2G
Equally, the Sovereign Good cannot both exclude goods (or happi
ness) and require, as its very sovereignty, what can no longer be thought as
.
a "good," namely, being-obliged by the law. Kant writes:
This ultimate end of pure practical reason is the highest good, so far as this is pos
sible in the world, which good, however, is not merely to be sought in what nature
can provide; that is to say, in happiness (the greatest amount of pleasure). Instead,
it is to be sought in the supreme requirement, that is, the only condition under
which reason can award it to rational beings in the world and, of course, at the
same time in the ethical, law-abiding conduct of rational beings.27
Respect for the law concerns its sublimity: "The majesty of the moral
law (as of the law on Sinai) instils awe (not dread, which repels, nor charm,
which invites familiarity); and in this instance, since the ruler resides
within us, this respect, as of a subject toward his ruler, awakens a sense a/the
sublimity of our own destiny which enraptures us more than any beauty. "28
The feeling of the sublime in general (always assuming that it can be dis
tinguished from the feeling of the sublime involved in our destiny; in real
ity, there is only one sublime} is the feeling of the limit of our faculties. The
law exceeds absolutely the farthest limits of represenratio·n and measure
and, if it needs to be constructed, according to the second formulation of
the categorical imperative, in ter�s of the type of a universal law of nature,
it isn't in the sense of a phenomenal law but in the sense of a law of the
phenomena that does not itself appear in the phenomenal sense. In his
.... .- � ..... ... -
_7,,, _ _'I ...: .. ... .-' • .:::...
. �'; . :"_ ....... . ,';:
own copy of the Bible, next to Luke 17: 20: "the kingdom of God cometh
not with outward show," Kant wrote these words: "visible (form) ."29 The
feeling of the sublime is addressed to what exceeds form.
And yet the universal character of the law is not given as something
invisible. What exceeds form doesn't take on a superior or supersensible
form. Rather, it denotes the very formation of form; concealed in every
form that appears and delivered over to reason as a task.30 This task is en
joined because it can be neither represented nor taught in the manner of a
technical task. There is, no natural law of formation (in the same way that
life is untepresentable for us). There is simply the law oflegislating in this
absence of law; that is, there is the law of making an ethical world, of form
ing an ethical world-making it or forming it as ifthere could be a natural
one, in which we could live. So far as the formation of this ethical world
of this world under moral laws-is concerned, there is no law if not the
law of forming it.
Understood thus, the sublime character of the law indicates human
ity's "divine destination." But the "divine" doesn't name a subject (or a
project) oflaw. Granted, God is the legislator, but God exists because a cat
egorical imperative exists: "the idea of such a being . . . emerges from this
imperative and not the reverse."31 "God" isn't the God of nat�re-any
more than, for the same reason, He is the God of religion. No, "God" is
the divine destination of man insofar as this destination is enjoined by
him. "God" is not beyond representation. On the contrary, the beyond of
representation-the limit beyond which we cannot pass since, rather than
opening onto a limitlessness of form that would somehow lie beyond
form, it marks the end of form and of the world insofar as it exhausts or
withdraws' the very formation of form and of world-this beyond ofrep
resentation (and of the subject) makes the law. And the law destines to this
end in a manner that is both "divine" and "sublime."
This mode of destining is not a way of promising nor of fixing an end
or an accomplishment. Rather, it is a way of abandoning. Perhaps the cat
egorical imperative is only a transformation of tragic truth, a truth that
destiny has essentially abandoned. The law abandoned-to itself. What
haunts us, what has, haunted us ever since our loss of tragedy's representa
tion or since the imperative began to present us wi'th its irreducibility, is
this abandonment.32
Hen'ce there is a destination, an ultimate abandonment to the sense
of finitude. The sublime character of the law-which depends strictly on
150 JUDGING
its imperative nature-stems from the fact that it destines to the univer
sality, to the absolut�ly granq and to the incommensurable in finitude. On
the other hand, there can be no destination to an end thought as the ab
solute telos of the infinite development of a finite being.33
What still counts here is the beginning, then, the sending of the im
perative. The law is unsurpassable as the imperative law because it is not
the self-legislation of the subject. In the self-legislation of a substance,
which turns the substance into a subject-God, Nature, or Man-the law
sublates itself, conserves itself by suppressing itselfas a law into a submission
to its only freedom, a freedom that, moreover, it thus confers upon itself
Now, to this thought is joined the corollary of a (Christian and speculative)
con<;:eption of the law as slavery. By contrast, the imperative imposes the
law as the outermost, unrecoverable limit on the basis ofwhich the injunc
tion is addressed.
Hence the law is addressed to a freedom and not founded by it. Recip
rocally, freedom does not consist in obedience to its own law-to the law
proper to its nature-but in beginning from itself: it is an inaugural free
dom, therefore, prior to all law. And yet this freedom is, before anything
else, the recipient of the law. Here, there are always two "origins," neither
of which is recoverable and each of which seems, indefinitely and in turn,
to step over the other: the address of the la� and the free beginning. Put
differently, there are two "principles," neither of which responds strictly to
the status of a principle: the imperative and freedom. And everything un
folds as if the law prescribed to freedom the job of beginning this . side of
the law. And yet, it prescribes this to freedom, enjoins it to it, and this is
itself the ground of the imperative: there is an imperative because freedom
is the recipient and not the self-positing and self-legislative freedom of the
subject.
True, we could go with the opposite by invoking the well-known passage from the
Critique ofPractical Reason: freedom is the ratio essmdi of the moral law and the
moral law is the ratio cognoscendi of freedom. But does the expression ratio essmdi
actually indicate that freedom is, in some way, beyond the law, that it is the in
ventive power behind it, that it is nothing other than its autonomy, its self-posit
ing? In reality, it is nothing like this: freedom is the ratio essmdi of the moral law,
not as the condition of existence or manifestation, but as the condition of realiza
tion in the sense that a moral law addressed to a will not subject to the law would
•
be a contradiction.34
The Kategorein ofExcess 151
Lapsusjudicii
philQSQphy), the very negativity Qf the Self, sQmething that needs to be un
[
derstQod here as negativity turned in uPQn itself and deprived Qf its dialec
tical richness: the Self knQWS "the lQSS Qf its essence" in "the equivQcal uni
I versal exclusiQn" and the "reciprocal dissQciation" Qf cQnsciQusness that
i
I right designates by the "disdainful expressiQn" persons (Person in Hegel's
l text, the German ' renderihg Qf the Latin persona: mask and anQnymity).!
The Latin cQncept (the Etruscan wQrd) persona prQvides the strange figure
that undQes the figure Qr the Gestalt-the fQrm and the CQntent-of the
Sel£ AlthQugh the Life Qf the CQncept, here as elsewhere, is sublated, the
"state Qf right" is still a pure Qr, rather, whQlly impure lQSS Qf substance and
cQnsciousness. Spirit-philQsQphy-passes it by rather than passing
through it.
Yet in the run up to. Hegelian science, RQme had already repeated it
sel£ PhilQSQphy had already becQme juridical. It had already becQme so.
with Kant. So. CQmmQn has this currency become (with and since Hegel),
that it's sQmetimes even said that, with Kant, philQSQphy becQmes legal
ism, an entirely fQrmal, fQrmalist, and procedural discQurse. FQr a while,
Kant WQuld have been the Chicanneau Qf philQsQphf-and fQr many he
still is. Ih philQSQphy, it's Kant who. prQmpts the questiQn: What happens
when philQSQphy becQmes juridical, when it's articulate'd as jurisdictiQn?
The questiQn is a dQuble Qne, therefQre, and dQubly heterogeneQus.
If philQsophy is Greek, it's the Latin questiQn Qf philQSQphy; ifRQme is the
dissQlution Qf philQSQphy, it's the philosophical questiQn QfRQine. I want to.
try to. broach this questiQn by explaining as briefly as PQssible this recipro
cal implicatiQn, even if my explanatiQn will have to. take the fQrm Qf an as
sertiQn rather than an argument. To. the extent that it will ever be PQssible
to. justify this SQrt Qf assertiQn, that's sQmething that will have to. be dQne
later Qn by examining the Kantian QperatiQn in and Qf itsel£
If the RQman discQurse Qn right is substituted for philoSQphy Qr im
PQses its mask uPQn it, then this is perhaps because it's in RQme, and Qn
the basis Qf this, that metaphysics sets abQut declaring itself by right. Inti
�ately tied up with the specifically Greek discQurse Qf metaphysics, there
fQre, WQuld be a Latin discQurse:3 juridical discQurse. (Of CQurse, we would
need to. cQmplicate matters still further by addressJng the fact that "dis
cQurse" itself is a Latin CQncept, but we must take Qne Qr two. shQrtcuts
here.) Befalling logos bQth from within and withQut, "within" as "withQut;"
Latin jurisdictiQn WQuld say sQmething quite different. Precisely by way Qf
this substitutiQn, hQwever, Latin jurisdictiQn hQlds its ground and affirms
154 JUDGING
its right: no jus without ratio. As such, it has (always?) already been claimed
by logos. And, to the extent that logos must pass into its own history, logos
itselfis articulated by it.
But what is juridical discourse? In the Latin world-or, as we saw
earlier, here and now,' hie et nuna-the very notion of "juridical discourse"
borders on tautology. (Almost inevitably, we will repeat some well-known
facts here.) Jurisdiction is the fact of saying right. Such saying is inherent to
right-just as, reciprocally, right has to be inherent to its saying, to its be
ing said, if an element of a code is going to be determined for language and
if the statements formed within it are going to be just or even judicious;
such, indeed, is the logical duty, office, and right of "saying" . . . The basic
entanglement of speech (and language in particular) with right constitutes
Latin discourse. Discourse--in the language of the sixteenth century, both
statement and reason-takes the place of logos through the coupling ofjus
and dictio, in the twin production of the judicial and the judicious.
Hence dictio, by itself, in some way comprises a judgment even be
for� it's actually formulated. Dicere means to show and, in order to be able
to show, to discern or to fix, to establish and to point the finger at what
ever it is that is being determined (indicere). Latin saying operates by judg
ing; it is constitutively judicial: causam dicere is to establish and to show the
cause, to plead. From this point on, discourse only shows things by plead
ing their cause; and such is the program that it falls to Kant to carry out.
less substance {rather, and as Hegel points out, this is what it loses} than a
power (an ability, will, desire, potential, faculty-always, though, in terms
of right) of "action" and "daim"; a subject that shows itselfless through its
presence (its figure, what is proper to it, its Gestalt) than through the con
. tours of the area that defines its figure and its identity: the outline of the
persona. This (juridical) person, this persona, is still one who formulates,
assuming that we can indeed map onto its Etruscan origin (which carries
the sense of "mask") the popular etymology of the word: the mask per
sonat, it ainplifies the voice and lets it be heard from afar. (The subject of)
right is the one the power of whose voice (or, more precisely, whose mega
phone, whose artificial voice) establishes and circumscribes propriety. This
power itself is artificial and theatrical: (the subjeq of) right is estab
lished-or stated-on a nothingness of being and nature.
What is stated by the judge,-judex, one invested with jurisdiction
is the formula that says or makes right by setting out the relation of the law
to the case hic et nunc in question. The fact that enunciation [le dire] is in
herent to right corresponds to a specific status that I'd sum up in the fol
lowing way: casuality constitutes the essence of right; casuistry, the essence
of jurisdiction. Casus denotes the fall-the fall in or through chance,
through contingency, the fall according to opportunity (an opportunity that
constitutes the judge as much as the criminal); the fall, then, as accident.
The "essence" of right stems from the singular relation of accident to
essence. Dejure, the law ought to be the universal code whose very defini
tion implies the annulment or the reabsorption of any accident. De facto
(but this fact is itself constitutive of right, is itself the very fact ofjuris-dic
tion), cases ought to be referred and legitimated case by case. This neces
sity doesn't stem from the, pure and simple accident of an indefinite diver-
. sity of empirical conditions (of per;onal situations) that would always
overflow the inevitable limitation (itself entirely empirical) of the various
forms of right. Here, it is a matter of the necessity of the accidental. Or
rather (since what's doubtless involved here is a certain aporetic relation of
metaphysical necessity to the empirical, to the factual, to the actual or the:
evidential as such), the juridical order is the order instituted through the
formal-:-in every sense of the term-taking into account of the accident
.
itself, without ever conceiving its necessity.
Jurisdiction is articulated around a double structure, therefore. On
the one hand, it states the right �f the case, thereby making it a case: it sub
sumes it, suppresses its accidental character; picks it up [releve] after its fall;
156 JUDGING
. Since the case is not only unforeseen but has to be so, and since right
is given as the case of its own utterance, so juridical discourse shows itself
to be the true discourse of fiction. The prominent part played by the no-
, tion of "juridical fiction" in and since the Roman discourse on right is well
known, and I don't want to deal with it here. It should be enough to indi
cate the three registers on which this notion can be invoked: first, the aca
demic exercise, in which the treatment of fictitious cases (possible cases, in
other words, however counterfactual and improbable they may be: any
thing can happen) forms the handling of jurisdiction; then, the constitu
tion as a juridical cmeof a reality that is in itself concealed (the creation, if
you like, of a reality of pure signs); finally, the action of the so-called ficti
tious Roman discourse on right through which the law is extended to a case
to which it does not' actually apply (the illegitimate extension of the legiti
macy of a sign). According to this summary division, fiction would repre
. serit little more than a certain number of typical cases in the exercise of
right. In order to produce them, however, right will have to have the
generic ability of fiction.
In fact, the relation of law to case-the relation of jurisdiction
means that no case is a law and that a case only fo.lls under the law once the
law speaks of it. The accident-what happens-has to be struck by the
seal of the law (of its utterapce) in order to be not simply judged but con-
" n - -,-' _�."" >��_'_" "" � : " '''''' ' ' ' . ' � � ' ' � ' ' ' ' " _ _ _ ' �, '�" , . , ;_,_ . . . ... -' , .� . ...
ceed as if(and the Greek word for fiction, remember, is hypokrisis), this be
ing one of the central motifs that Kant introduces into philosophy.
The poetic operation-at least in the way that it's thought by meta
physicS-consists in a piitting to work (energeia) of sense. Its very princi
ple dictates that it involve the resolution of figures, that is, the signs of
sense-or,what amounts to much the same thing, the creation of a pure
and autonomous sense beyond all signs. "Veritas nullo egeat signo,"6 de
clares Spinoza, and, in this regard, Leibniz, Hegel, and Mallarme all stub
bornly insist on the same sort of poetry (poetry itself). This is the au
tonomous operation (and, in Greek, autonomy is what gives itself its law)
par excellence, and it presupposes the sovereign autonomy of its subject.
. The juridical act-it scarcely merits the name "operation"7-forms
or figures a fact whose essence or whose own sense falls, on principle, out
side of this form. It deliberately institutes the break between the sign and
the thing; more accutately, it is the act of this break or this breaking, and
it is so first of all insofar as its agent fictions or fashions him or herself into
the person of the right to utter right.
It's tempting to conclude that, beca1,lse of this self-saying, this "auto
diction" (but can we actually speak Greek and Latin at the same time?), the
judex is equivalent to the poet and so to the theoretician. Indeed, we might
well say, a little more precisely, that the juridical person figures what hap
pens-accidit-to the subject of the poem (or) of knowledge, even to the
extent that this subject wants to be and thinks itself accordingly as the ab
solute origin and propriety of an absolute right: that of creation or of truth;
·of a right, in other words, whose "area of action or claim" would be total,
unlimited, always escaping the limiting, localizing conditions of right.s
Right always proceeds from a delimitation to a localization, that is, by way
of a dislocation. The subject undergoes a dislocation; this is the limit of its
own figure. The accident that affects it or the occasion that befalls it is the
case of the absolute subject itself. Jurisdiction implies that the origin is a
case or that the inaugural gesture of right involves an "area" and thus a de
limitation, thereby contravening the logic of the subject. The .loss of the
substance of the Self is · equivalent to the de-finition of the person; to fini
tude, in other words. In much the same way, the person is neither the sub
ject nor the seat of right, unless the magistrate, on the basis of the particu
lar case, concedes the judicial action: not jus in personam, therefore, but
aCtio in personam.9
The juridical person is determined by way of the accidental, the fic-
Lapsus judicii 159
tional, and (so) by way of finitude. This is why such a person is the precise
opposite of the subject. 10 And this is also why its determinations are gath
ered in that of the "subject" o/the statement. (We've already seen that since
right is what is said, the subject is only ever going to be the subject of what
is stated.) The person is the one who states-whether on the level of accu
sation, defense, or sentence-and who states him- or herself thus; yet he or
she does so in such a way that this "self" is not a substantial identity, not a
"personality" per se; rather, it is the'judgmentof the person.
the signs specific to it (its idioms). Three things emerge with the theory of
the sign. First, the pathological possibility of error; that is, the possibility
that the accident might actually happen to knowledge rather than simply.
as a lack ofit. Second, .the role of the decision (of a gesture "over and above"
the logos) concerning the precision of the sign. Third, the role of the state
ment, at least as the attribution or predication that relates the sign to the
thing.
The decision that is stated in order (in principle) to separate out logos
from any sense ofpathos will be transcribed by the judicium. It is right that
prepares the concept for the absence of conception-or for unnatural or
nongenerative conception. The "concept" furnished by the sign isn't the
opening of the thing itself but the imposition of its idiom, won against the
danger or the risk of a fall into phantasy-a victory that always needs to be
gained and thus a risk that always needs to be run. Uncertainty is consti
tutive of judgment, since its job of adjustment needs to be understood as
essentially a division: "Judgment is an expression offinitude and, from this
point of view, things are said to be finite, because they consist in a judg
ment, because their being present and their universal nature (their body
and their soul), though certainly united (were this not the case, the things
would be nothing), are still elements that are already different enough to
be separable."1l
The judicium, then, will be determined----:through the Augustinian
tradition and the interpretation of the figures of Scripture (an interpreta
tion that, in turn, has Stoic origins)-as the specific part of an apprecia
tion, of an estimation that, in order to be ultimately certain of its result,
will have to be no less changeable and personal in the manner of its estab
lishment. Through scholasticism and the critica (the part of the dialectica
that treats ofjudgment), the judicium will be determined as the intellectual
act of a compositio as opposed to the intelligentia indivisibilium that prop
erly comprises conception. Compositio implies first and foremost assem
blage, fashioning, fiction; krisis always involves a hypokrisis; 12 then (but this
is one and the same thing) it implies the position or the imposition of the
sign for the thing .figured thus, the investiture through the sign and con
ferred by the sign of the right to say the thing.
The order of judgment is made up of the multiple, the uncertain,
and the unequal. Opus incertum, as we say in Latin to designate architec
tonic works built of irregular stone. Since the order of construction isn't
given in advance by the materials used, we're going to have to judge the
� -----� ----�-------
1. Since it has to judge itself, reason is itself a casein the sense of a de
fault from, or a lack of, right;
2. To this extent, and to the extent that reason ought to draw right
from itself alone, its jurisdiction can only be "absolute" in the paradoxically
accidental institution of its tribunal: it arises from a history that is neither
natural nor metaphysical, from a history that, far from being regulated by
the growing richness of the Concept, seems, rather, to be deregulated by
the growing entropy of reason itself (a true History can only open out on
the basis of critique).
Rather than having an essence, therefore-which would involve
knowing itself-reason has an accident, which involves having to judge it
self Reason stumbles over its own case-the case of the judge.
Surely, as the Preface to the Critiques second edition points out, there
is a model for the tribunal, or at least a criterion according to which it is
possible to judge. The "secure course of a science" is signposted by mathe-'
matics, physics, and chemistry, and the job of critique lies in leading meta
physics down this route. However, the la� thus invoked doesn't make ju
risdiction as such obsolete.ls It doesn't found the tribunal but leaves it
the-infinite-task ofjustifjing itself. All of which can be shown schemat
ically in the following three motifs:
1. The mathematico-physical sciences are not and do not constitute
.metaphysics. Kantian philosophy isn't geared toward epistemology (a dis
course that aims merely to reproduce the rigor of scientific discourse).
Equally, it is entirely different from Cartesian mathesis, which, through the
"envelope" of "vulgar mathematics," denotes the universal science that
makes up their soul or their core. Instead, then, Kantian metaphysics is an
otherscience altogether, one that appeals to the established sciences as ana
logical models (in the Analogies of Experience, remember, the mathemat
ical analogy is able to provide no more than a model that is itselfanalogical
to the philosophical analogy charged with thinking the unity of experi
ence); The exemplary character of the sciences doesn't prevent them from
being heterogeneous to metaphysics. Analogism runs all the way through
this heterogeneity"':'-but this gesture is a fictioning one, not one of identi-
, fication. Kant has no real theory of knowledge; rather; he addresses theory
insofar as it is bereft of knowledge.
2. Reason doubtless sees itselfat work in the sciences. In this sense, it
has always already recognized itself; it has always mastered from the outset
its own ration'ality; hence it has no need to judge. 1 9 And yet the fact still re-
164 JlJDGING .
rules,"30 thereby defining and concentrating in itself the very task of phi
losophy. Philosophy cannot " expand the role of the understanding" (it can
not win territory or an area) but "as critique, in order to avoid errors of
judgment (lapsusjudicii) in the use of the few pure concepts of the under
standing that we have, philosophy with all of its perspicacity and art of
scrutiny is called up (even though its use is then only a negative one)."31
The role of the Critique, therefore, is to occupy the place of the foundation
.
of right; it is, in principle, charged with saying the right of right and of
sheltering jus from the casuality of its dictio.
Now, it is precisely thisfoundational operation that shows itselfto be the
juridical act par excellence: with this, we come before the tribunal itself, at
the very heart of critique as such. For this reason, as much as the jurisdic
tion of all jurisdiction disengages from all juridical statutes (as much as it
sets itself up as the site of privilege), with this same gesture it carves into it
self the infinite flaw that leads it to fall continually upon its own case. In
other words: since philosophy thinks itself says itself-in terms of right,
-
it inevitably thinks in a way that is structured around (or affected by) lap
susjudicii, by the slipping and falling that are an intrinsic part of the lack
of substance within which jurisdiction takes place.
By way of conclusion, let me simply try to address the first function
of this constitutive and permanent lapsus: the one that concerns the very
principle of critical jurisdiction.
Because of the claim that it makes (the rights that it assigns to itself),
transcendental logic is the faculty of indicating, beyond any rule, the a pri- .
ori case to which the rule can be applied. As such, it eliminates the casual
ity of the case and forges the contradictory
. notion of a jurisprudence that
owes nothing to experience.
And yet, although this operation will already have been carried out in
the Critique, it is not under the motif of jurisprudence, but under the ju
ridical concept of deduction.32 Now, for "jurisconsults," "deduction" is
proof that responds in a cause to the question Quidjuris? Deduction is the
establishment of right. Hence the transcendental deduction of the pure
concepts of the understanding ought to establish the right of reason in
every case. .
In fact, this is what it does, finally establishing that the understand
ing "is itself the legislation for nature."33 Sheltered thus from any external
limiting condition, the understanding, from the moment that it comes to
judge, ends up falling upon its own case, on the case of its investiture as
168 JUDGING
facto-but this fact is itself the fact of right-the guarantee itself only ever
guarantees its figure or its fiction as guarantor. Moreover, the Critique will
Lapsus judicii 169
never be able to stop reason from abandoning itself de facto to the Trieb,
the impulse that leads it to judge outside the limits of experience and to
forge dangerous and dogmatic fictions (God, the self, the world) . Equally,
though, and by the same token, the irresistible character of the Trieb of rea
son will be recognized and stated by the tribunal itself, as the factual limit
of its own jurisdiction. The moral imperative alone will be capable' of mak
ing this impulse "see reason." Yet this "categorical" imperative, in which
the ultimate jurisdiction resides, can only ever offer itself up as afactum of
reason. The pure fact of a pure moral person will say the last rights of a fig
ured subject. It will say it as duty. The imperative says the duty of consti
tuting oneselfas a judge (of the universality of my maxim), even though
there's perhaps no case conforming to this judgment that could be pre
sented in experience. Yet it is precisely because no such case exists that we
have to judge in all cases. The imperative is factual; it takes the ·form of an
accident (of reason) because it is the only form that can be taken by an es
tablishment of right that is neither a foundation nor a self-foundation. The
imperative is illegitimate. Only thus does it make the law.
Postscriptum
Jean-Fran<;:ois Lyotard has honored this essay with a generous note to
which I must return (and salute in passing the rare occurrence of a genuine
disputatio).34 Lyotard wants to break with the motif of "fictioning," which
'
in his view is indebted "to a problematics of founding or origin." That
Kant, in his account of judgment, dethrones the issue of origins "in favor
of the question of ends" I wholeheartedly agree (and let me refer here to
the text "The Free Voice of Man," written for and in the spirit of the col-
,
loquium The Ends ofMan).35 But it does not necessarily follow that theju
ridical fiction (which I was careful to distinguish from poetic fiction, i.e.,
Dichtung) has to play the part of the "substitute" or "proxy" for a dislo
cated origin (I would suggest, rather, perhaps provocatively, that there is an
origin, and it is this that comprises the dis-Iocation), and that it therefore
leads back surreptitiously to the general metaphysical thematics of origin.
On the one hand, we need to determine precisely the role of proxies
in general (here we might revisit Derrida's exploration of the logic of sup
plementarity). Does proxy "conjoin . . . the fragments of an origin,
. '
ing, of the naming of being. Who would not take that position? And how
to can illusion be determined, if not from an exact and adequate point of
_ view? Next, Lyotard underlines "in the process." This "in the process"
(with everything that it entails) is unmistakably, irresistibly, a proxy: he is
under way, he has not yet finished, nor has he yet begun, but instead, in
place of his, in the process . . . he is. But what is this place? Lyotard would
doubtless say that the question is illegitimate. Let's concede that he's right.
But what is it to be right? Ultimately, no "play of sentences" is going to de
cide or articulate that. If it isn't "being," then at least it is what happens,
factually, to being, the truth of an experience, the judgment of a history.
It's not "phrases" that are "right" (although there is no being "right" with
out "phrases"). Truth is not a phrase-and yet truth happens. That means
that truth is, while "being is not," as Heidegger points out.
But Lyotard basically knows all this-and that's what makes this
disputatio possible: the debate is regula�ed by a common concern (or a
shared imperative) that is both more and less than what our respective
"sentences" say. But this does not mean that these sentences are indiffer
ent or interchangeable.
Translated by Simon Sparks
. ... ' .. ,
Originary Ethics
Second, over and above all this, there are those who think it's possi
ble to deny any ethical dimension to Heidegger's thinking, basing their
claims on his own objection to ethics as a "discipline," on the coi:respon- �
cling absence of a "moral philosophy" in his work, and on his refusal of any
moral interp�etation of the analytic of Dasein. Now, in order for the pres
ent essay to have any relevance whatsoever, we would need to begin by
demonstrating the falsity of this argument, and by reconstructing the pos
sibility of a properly ethical approach to Heidegger. However, not only is
there no space for this here, bur it can even be considered quite unneces
sary.1 Only those who have read Heidegger blindly, or not at all, could
think him a stranger to ethical preoccupations. Moreover, there are already
enough works in existence to refute this prejudice. It should be enough,
then, to spell out the following (which will be complemented by what I
have to say): there is no "morality" in Heidegger, if what is meant by that
is a body of principles and aims for conduct, fixed by authority or by
choice, whether collective or individual. In fact, however, there is no phi
losophy. that either provides or is itself a "morality" in this sense. It isn't
philosophy's job to prescribe norms or values: instead, it must think the
essence or the sense of what makes up action [l'agir] as such; it should
think, in other words, the essence or the sense of what puts action in the
position of having to choose norms or values. Perhaps, incidentally, this
understanding of philosophy is itself already l:Ieideggerian or, at least for
us, today, �necessarily Heideggerian in tone. Of course, this wouldn't pre
vent us from showing how appropriate it is to Spinoza or to Kant or to
Hegel or to Husserl, or prevent us from showing how, and doubtless for
specific historical reasons, it chimes with Heidegger's contemporaries (each
very different from the next) Bergson, Wittgenstein, or Levinas. All. of
which amounts to saying that, in general terms, there would be a case for
showing how, with Heidegger and wi;th Heidegger's period, philosophy
understood itself (once again) as "ethics" and not, let us quickly say, as
"knowledge," presupposing, in particular, a distinction between "ethics"
and "morality" inherited (if at times confusedly) by the whole of our own
time. But this isn't my concern here; rather, I want to sketch our an inter
nal interpretation [explication] of Heidegger himself, striving to be as faith
ful as possible while avoiding piety.
The third difficulty runs counter to the second. If, paradoxically,
ethics constitutes both a discreet and unobtrusive theme in Heidegger's
work and a constant preoccupation, an orientation in his thinking, then we
174 JUDGING
mulations of Being and Time-is the being for which, "in its very being,
that being is at issue for it,"4 it is because this "is at issue," this it s'agit de,
this es geht um, this "it is about," doesn't bring into play an interest that is
merely theoretical or speculative. Rather, it destroys the supposed auton
omy of.such an interest. If, in Dasein, it is being that is at issue [it s'agit de
l'hre] (and if, without playing on words more than language itself does, be
ing is a matter of action [l'etre est de t'agir]), it is because being, as the be
ing of Dasein, is what is at stake [limjeu] in its conduct, and its conduct is
the bringing into play [la mise en jeu] of being.
This point of departure-and more than that, this axiom or this
transcendental �bsolute of all thinking of being-could also be expressed
as follows: because the difference between being and beings is not a differ
ence of being (it is not the difference between two kinds of being) , it is not
a difference between two realities, but the reality of Dasein insofar as it is,
in and of itself, open and called to an essential and "active" relation with
the proper fact ofbeing.5
This relation is one of sense. In Dasein, it is a matter of giving sense to
the fact of being-or, more exactly, in Dasein the very fact of being is on�
of making sense. This "making sense" is not theoretical, nor is it practical in
a sense somehow opposed to the theoretical (on the whole, it would be
more in: keeping with Heidegger's thinking to call it practical "in the first
instance") . Knowledge or the understanding of being as sense is identical
with the action of sense or with action as sense. To be is to make sense. (In
a direct line from Kant: pure reason is practical insofar as it is theoretical.)
This "making," however, is not a "producing.". It is, precisely, acting,
or conducting oneself Conduct is the accomplishment ( Vollbringen) of be
ing. .As sense's conduct, or as the conduct of sense, it is, essentially, "think
ing." The essential act is thinking. But that doesn't close action back up on
"
a (merely) theoretical practice." If the "Letter on "Humanism,'" along
with many other texts, appears to restrict action-and with it original
ethics-to an activity that we might be inclined to call abstract, specula
tive, and only metaphorically "active" ("active" through the metaphor of
the "thinkers" and the "poets"), then this is the result of an inadequate
reading. In reality, "thinking" is the name for action because sense is at is
sue in action. Thinking (and/or poetry) is not an exceptional form of ac
tion, the "intellectual conduct" to be preferred to others, but what, in all
action, brings into play the sense (of being) without which there would be
no action.
176 JUDGING
.� . �, � ....,... .-.'-:":O',_
.
.
_._."-
...._
--::-" . �.,�_. ,-:�:"'-' •'-';"�."o.. ._.,-
.
existence, being the proper request of its being. Only on the basis of this
original request will it be possible for beings, in their action; to give them
selves ideas or values-and, what's more, this will make sense only accord
ing to the original action which is at issue in the request.
Hence, this thinking strives to take most rigorously into account the
impossibility, which has arisen with and as modernity, of presenting an al
ready given sense, with the evaluations which would be deduced from it.
(And although this is p.ot the place to do so, we ought to ask ourselves
whether this problematic is not in fact that of the whole of philosophy, al
ready present in Plato's agathon and first radicalized in Kant's imperative.)
To clarifY; we could say: the ethics engaged in this way is engaged on
the basis of nihilism-as the general 4issolution of sense-but as the exact
reverse of nihilism: as the bringing to light of making-sense as action re
quested in the essence of bei.ng.23 So it also engages itself according to the
theme of a total and joint responsibility toward sense and toward existence.
(I can only signal in passing the importance of the motif of responsibility.
Discreetly explicit, like that of ethics itself, this motif tends toward noth
ing less than "being's being-responsible towards itself, proper Being-its
self,"24 the latter having, in principle, nothing solipsistic or egoistic about
it but, on the contrary, containing the possibility and the necessity of be
ing-responsible toward others.)
being."37 We ought to pause here for a moment, since this sort of "pas
toralism" has often raised a smile. Granted, terms like "shepherd," "guard
ing," and "protective heed" aren't entirely free of evangelistic, backward
looking connotatiofl:s. They evoke a sense of preservation, a conservation of
what ought to be open and to be risked. There's a reactive if not out and
ou,t reactionary tone here, one that Heidegger wasn't alone in taking, a tone
that often befalls moral discourses ("preserving values," etc.) . It is as '
though inaugural dignity were brought to light without any acquired pro
tection, without the reassurance of any given sense, itself needing to be
protected or safeguarded. Now, what has to be "guarded" is the open
something that the "guarding" itself risks closing back up again. For the
dignity of the open we might then substitute the emblematic value of its
guardians, which will soon be identified, moreover, in terms of the deter
minate figures of the "thinker" and the "poet." All of this has to pose a
problem, one that needs to be addressed. For it's still the case that, quite
logically, the "guarding" of the "open" can only ever be the opening of the
open itself, and that the pastoral tone ought not to conceal the indication
of an absolute responsibility. Here we doubtless find the crux of a radical
thinking of ethics: in the possibility of confusing original making-sense
with an assignable origin of sense, an opening with a gift (and, again, what
is lodged here is the whole ambiguity of the "gift"; I will come back to
this) . Thinking the origin as ethos or conduct isn't the same as representing
an originary ethos, even though it is all too easy to slide imperceptibly from
the one to the other. (The difficulty here isn't specific to Heidegger and
could probably be found in Levinas or Spinoza as well.)
Be that as it may, let us recall for the moment that these very
terms-guar4ing, protective heed, the solicitousness of the shepherd-in
dicate the order of a conduct. It is less a: case of leading [conduire] a flock
than of conducting ourselves in such a way that "beings might appear in
the light of Being."38
This "appearing," however, isn't the effect of a production. Man
doesn't produce beings, nor does he produce himself; his dignity is not that
of a mastery (which, in general, is not susceptible of dignity, merely of
prestige or impressiveness) . In fact, "man dQes not decide whether and
how beings appear." This is a matter for the "destiny of being."39 That
there is something, and that there are such things-this world-is not for
us to decide. This, then, is given. But what is properly given with this gift,
or what is properly the destination of this "destiny" (and without which
- " '."
- .< :, .�!::, ' '.:..!.�
. �-r _._ ,--:. . . • "
.!
there wouid be neither "gift" nor "destiny," but factum brutum) is what is
not, in other words, the being of beings as the desire/ability of sense; What
is properly given-what being gives and that as which it gives itself-is the
need to make sense of and in beings as a whole (their "appearing in the
light of being") . It is in this sense that humans are responsible for being, or
that the Dasein in them is the being-responsible of/for being itsel£
We need to replace for "being is" the expression "Es gibt" das Sein."40
"The essence of being" is an essence "that is giving, that grants its truth."41
What being gives is being itself. Being gives of being. (The) being (of be
ings) is not a "gift" that it "gives," therefore. And therein lies the whole am
biguity of the theme of the "gift," and it is for this reason that we might
well prefer the term "letting" to that of "giving." Being lets beings be. Be
ing does not "give" anything: being is the letting-be through which some
thing is. Hence the, very being of beings, their essence, "gives" itself, "lets"
itself or "transfixes" beings as �'truth," in other words, as that which opens
onto sense-and preCisely not as a sense or as an appropriable horizon of
signification. The "gift" is inappropriable qua "gift," and this is exactly
what it "gives" or "lets" (hence, what we receive as a present doesn't be
come our property in the way that something we have acquired does; the
gift becomes "mine" without alienating its inappropriable essence qua gift;
for the essential reason that what, on aCCOUIlt of the idiomatic expression
es gibt, tends to be called the "gift," cannot designate "a gift") . The gift be
comes "mine" without alienating its inappropriable essence qua gift. Con
versely and correlatively, what is "let" becomes "mine" without retaining
any sense of a giver; where this not the case, it would not lef;-- or make-
be its own letting-be.
This is why it is a matter of corresponding to this "gift," to this "let
ting-be/-make" as such. It is a matter of responding to it and of being re
sponsible for it, of being engaged by it. It is a matter of finding the fitting
. gesture, the right conduct (das Schtckliche . . . , das diesem Geschick ent
spricht, as Heidegger says) toward the giving or the letting-be/make as
such.42 Toward being, in other words, since being is definitively not the
giver of the gift (es gibt-however we look at this, the gift has no owner;
and let me say that throughout our dealings with the motif of the gift in
Heidegger, Derrida's analyses must be borne in mind). Being is the gift it
self; or, rather, beingis letting-be, just as it is "the clearing,"43 just as it ek
sists beings. Being doesn't "give" being existence, therefore; being is, in a
transitive sense, ek-sisting.
186 JUDGING
proposition can have any real sense if thinking is nodirmly upheld in the
face ofthe possibility that making-sense might "nihilate" or destroy itself
as such. No doubt the glaring tension in this text's refusal to attempt even
the slightest determination of evil can seem a touch worrying. This would
need to be addressed" elsewhere. What has to be conceded is the fact that
any determination of evil would lead us away from the necessity of think
ing the possibility of evil as a possibility of ek-sistence. It would lead us
away from the possibility of being as ek-sistence.
This is what Heidegger indicates in the passage in which he sketches
out a recent history of negativity "in the essence of being"79 (revealing "ni
hilation" to be indissociable from "the history of being"-or from being as
hist9ry-that brings it to light in its essential character). He notes that it's
with speculative dialectics that negativity appears in being, but he does so
merely in order to observe that "being is thought there as will that wills it
self as the will to knowledge and to love";80 in other words, dialectics sub- .
lates evil in this knowledge and this love. In this, the most recent form of
theodicy, "nihilation" remains "essentially veiled." "Being as will to power
is still concealed." Hence it is as will to power that nihilation has mani
fested itself without dialectical resorption. We can gloss this indication by
thinking of the date of the text: i946. If Heidegger isn't more explicit, that
is surely because he refuses to separate the question of Nazism from that of
an essential Weltnot,81 a distress or deficiency in the modern world linked
to the unleashing of "technology" (which it's �ot enough to oppose with a
moral protest). This means, at least, that the modern world-or being in
its most recent "sending"-brings to light, to a harsh light, an unreserved
"engagement" of ek-sisting in the complete responsibility for sense (which
may mean, moreover, that the demand to which the Nazi engagement was
intended to respond was ethical and that Nazism ultimately showed itself
to be the movement of this demand over into "rage") . In this, "originary
ethics" is not only the fundamental structure or conduct of thinking, it is
also what is delivered at the end of and as the accomplishment of the his
tory of "the West" or of "metaphysics." We can no longer refer to available
senses; we have to take absolute responsibility for making-sense of the
world. We cannot ease the "distress" by filling up the horizon with the
same "values" whose inconsistency-once their metaphysical foundation
had collapsed-allowed the "will to power" to unfold. What this means,
however, is that the ground needs to be thought somewhat differently: as
ek-sistence.
Originary Ethics 193
This is how original ethical conduct encounters its law, its proper
nomos: the nomos of the "abode," of "upholding" according to ek-sistence.82
It is a matter of upholding ourselves and "bearing" or "carrying" ourselves
in a way that befits the injunction of being-the injunction to be-ek-sis
tent. Conduct, dignity, is a matter of bearing. We have to bear ourselves,
bear up before the responsibility for making-sense that has unfolded unre
servedly. Man has to understand himself according to this responsibility.
This bearing is above all that oflanguage. "Thinking" action consists
in "bringing to language." What has to be brought to language isn't of the
order of maxims. These, as such, don't need to be brought to language;
they are, at least to a certain extent, available significations. (To take up the
example once again: we can express a "respect for life," yes; but that says
nothing abour what does or does not make sense through "life" and our
"respect" for it.)
This bearing of and in language is nothing more than respect or care
for the job of making-sense; the refusal, consequently, to reduce it to facile
moralizations or aestheticizing seductions (whence, for example, the reason
why Being and Time was to dismiss interpretations of "responding to the .
call" as "wanting to have a 'good conscience'" or as "cultivating the call vol
untarily."83 None �f which rules out the fact that the "Rectoral Address"
fell into both of these traps.)
Hence it is with regard to the bearing oflanguage that the "Letter on
'Humanism'" expresses what are, properly speaking, its only maxims, the
maxims of "bearing" itself: "rigor of meditation, carefulness in saying, fru
gality with words. "84 These three maxims propose no values. Nor could
they be used simply to measure the "ethicity" of any given discourse. The
careful-even fastidious-restraint that they evoke, which has a whole ·
Kantian and Holderlinian tradition behind it,' can just as easily be turned
into puritanical affectation. The ethics of "bringing to language" should
not be confused with a morality, still less with a policing of styles. These
three maxims are merely the maxim of the measure of language in its rela
tion with the unmeasurable character of making-sense.
All of which explains why Heidegger takes as his example of "the in
conspicuous deed of thinking" the use of the expression "bring to language
itself," an expression that he has just said needs to be taken "quite liter
ally."85 If we think it, he says, then "we have brought something of the
essence of being itself to language." This means that "bringing to lan
guage" doesn't consist in expressing through words a sense laid down in the
194 JUDGING
thing that we call being (being is precisely not a thing). It means literally
(and we probably ought to say "physically," had we the time to explain our
selves on this point) bringing being itself, as ek-sisting, ro the advent or the
event that it is: to the action of making-sense. Language doesn't signify be
ing but makes it be. · But "making being being" means opening it to the
conduct of sense that it is. Language is the exercising of the principle of re
sponsibility. Hence, saying "man" or the humanitas of man--:-provided we
have "bearing"-cannot amount to expressing an acquired value. It will al
ways mean, so to speak, letting ourselves be conducted by the experience
of a question-What is man?-that is already experienced as being be
yond any question to which a signification could respond. Language is ac
tion in that it is indefinitely obligated to act. "Bringing to language"
do�sn't mean entrusting ourselves to words; on the c(;mtrary, it means en
trusting the acts of language, as all acts, to the co�duct of sense, to the fini
rude of being, in other words, to the ek-sistence in which·"man infinitely
exceeds man."
does not linger. This isn't the communication of a message (of a significa
tion), but that of making-sense-in-common, something that is quite dif
ferent from making common sense. It is finitude as sharing.
b. At the same time, the attention paid to language-particularly in
the form of poetry-is always, and above all in the Heidegger of the essays
on language, on the point of privileging a silent enunciation, one that
might well prove to have the structure, nature, and appearance of a pure
utterance of sense (and not of what I have been calling the "conduct .of
sense") as the sole and final (no longer "original") action. Poetry-and/or
thinking-would give sense, even if silently, instead of opening onto it. At
this precise' point, at the apex of the action that "brings to language," we
would need to think how the "bringing," bringing being itself, is action
properly speaking, more so than language, and how existing ex-poses itself
outside language through language itself, something that would take place,
in particular, within making-sense-in-common; .in other words, through a
language that is first and foremost an address. We might well say: ethics
would need to be "phatic" rather than "semantic." And I would also sug
gest that we put it in the following way: making-sense ex-scribes itse/frather
than being inscribed in maxims or works.
These two points amount to saying that "originary ethics" still fails
to think the responsibility for its own ex-position (to other�, to the world),
an ex-position that constitutes its true logic.
c. By claiming the title "originary ethics" and by identifying it with a
"fundamental ontology" prior to every ontological and ethical partition of
philosophy, Hridegger cannot but have kept deliberately quiet about the
only major work of philosophy entitled Ethics that is itself an "ontology" as
well as a "logic" and an "ethics." His silence about Spinoza is well known,
but it is doubtless here that it is at its most deafening. There would be lots
to say about this, but the most summary of observations will suffice: to say
that ethos is the ek-sisting of existence itself might be another way of saying
that "blessedness is not the reward of virtue, but virtue itsel£"86
Translated by Duncan Large
P LEASURE
10
sidered first as they are in themselves, that is to say, in terms of their ca
pacities and their orders of legitimation, thus their circumscriptions, their
reciprocal division, and therefore precisely the consideration of powers, in
the plural. This plurality is what constitutes the unity of pure reason and is
.
the condition of its systematicity.
The system of powers is thus secured, not by an immediate unifica
tion after the fashion of the intuitus originarius (which would not, in fact,
be a "power" in the strict sense at all, but a summary expenditure of power
suppressing all potentiality), but by another kind of power altogether. A
third power is introduced, signifying straightaway both the possibility of
connecting the other two and the desirability of maintaining their recip
rocal demarcation by means of what we might call a supplementary de
marcation: neither cognitive nor normative, the faculty ofjudgment mal{es
up for the lack of an a priori legislation of purposiveness. It will be
charged with thinking "experience as a system in term ofto empirical laws,"
that is, an experience that would not only be not the experience of an ob
ject, but also be that of the "necessity of the whole" of nature in all its di
versity and "considerable heterogeneity."3 The "necessity of the whole" is
nothing other than the connection between nature, which is given, and
freedom, which is commanded, and this connection must present itself as
purposiveness. .
Here, however, we are dealing with nothing more than the "higher
cognitive powers," which are themselves at the "basis of philosophy."4 As
such, they designate and circumscribe the different kinds of cognition: of
the object (understanding); of freedom (reason); and of purposiveness (the
faculty of reflective judgment) . But these types of philosophical knowledge
are not yet ways of apprehending representations. To each kind of knowl
edge there corresponds a state of "mind ( Gemiit)": "cognition" stricto sensu,
"desire," and the "feeling of pleasure and displeasure."5 It follows that
philosophical knowledge, in its systematic unity, will be "cognition" only
in a sense that is very broad and above all not identical to itselE Either it is
a question of ("theoretical") cognition of objects (where in cognizing one
cognizes oneself as restricted to experience), or of ("practical") cognition of
the will (where in cognizing one recognizes oneself as free), or else of a
third kind of relation to representations, which is the "feeling of pleasure
and displeasure."
The Kantian Pleasure System 201
Only the first two "powers" are actually called powers ( Vermogen)
here. The third is termed a "feeling," thereby conferring on it from the out
set, by its very name and by the disymmetry of the appellation, a distinct
tonality, which I shall term that of the "passive power." In consequence, the
tripartite distinction with which Kant opens section III of the First Intro
duction rapidly turns into a bipartite one. On the one hand, there are rep
resentations that "are referred merely to the object and to the unity of con
sciousness these representations [contain] ," just as there are representations
considered "as cause of the actuality of the object" in accordance with that
other "unity of consciousness," the will (or desire) : in both, these concern
the relation of the object to the subject. On the other hand, there are rep
resentations that are "referred merely to the subject,'? and thus to the feel
ing of pleasure and displeasure.6 Here representations are not just "mine";
although they are representations of an object and exist only in relation to
that object (nature or freedom), they have validity because of being mine.
This is to say that they vouch for nothing but themselves, since this "mine
ness" refers to no substantial subject of appropriation. Such representations
"themselves are bases merely for . . . preserving their own existence in the
subject."7 The feeling of pleasure is the maintenance of representation for
itself, without any relation either to the object (of cognition or action) or
to the subject (of cognition or action).
(The feeling of displeasure, one should note, is the refusal or rejec
tion of this maintenance, again without consideration for cognition or ac
tion. It is undoubtedly significant that Kant should characterize feeling
solely in terms of pleasure, apparently forgetting or withdrawing the sym
metrical "displeasure." Here, though, I can't deal with this any further. For
present purposes, suffice it to say that I shall speak sometimes of "feeling,"
since in Kant typically it is the Gefohl der Lust und Unlust, the feeling of
pleasure and displeasure, which amounts to Gefohl in general, and some
times of "pleasure," since Kant often restricts himself to this half of the
dyad. In any case, the examination that I want to undertake will show just
how delicate this apparently simple matter of designation is: What, exactly,
are we talking about?)
Sented as SO distinct and separate as not to merit the title "power" at all,
since it "neither is nor provides any cognition whatsoever.'.'8 Feeling is the
noncognitive mode of combining or connecting representations and at the
same time the nonlegislative mode (lacking the legality given by either the
understanding or reason).
In fact, Kant emphasizes, while it is relatively easy to recognize "em
pirically" a "connection" between cognition or will and feeling, "this
link . . . is not based on any a priori principle."9 That some act of cogniz
ing or willing should please or displease me is an entirely contingent affair.
Consequently, the incipient "organization" we can detect here, since it is
not "baSed on any a priori principle,» does not form a "system, but only an
aggregate' of faculties. 1 0
Nevertheless, Kant feels bound to add in the next sentence that "it is
true that we can show an a priori connection between the feeling of plea
sure and the other two powers." This is a matter, he explains, of the link
between our a priori cognition of freedom with the will as the basis of this
cognition: which is nothing other than the link given in the form of the
categorical imperative. Therefore, "in this objective determination"
which is objective because it refers to an object of cognition and is at the
same time engaged in the actualization of this object in experience-we
can "find . . . something subjective as well: a feeling of pleasure." ) ) But,
Kant adds, this pleasure does not precede the will: it follows it, "or perhaps
is nothing other than our sensation of this very ability of the will to be de-.
termined by reason." Thus we shouldn't speak of a new a priori principle
here, though this is precisely what is required if the autonomy of the third
"higher power" is to be established.
There are several things that merit our attention here. First, the ex
ceptional "case"12 that Kant claims to have discovered, in order immedi
ately to challenge it, is set up in a peculiar way: with respect to the first
power, he invokes an "a priori cognition," which is cognition not of an ob
ject, but of freedom. Now this cognition, as is well known, is a knowing
(wissen) without perception or comprehension (einsehen).13 It is not of the
same order as cognition of an object, even though it is itself cognition of a
fact of experience and as such scibile. 14 Only a certain distortion, therefore,
allows Kant to claim to be speaking about the first, cognitive power here.
If we are dealing with a power, then it is the power of a paradoxical "cog
nition," one lacking an object, or having an object on�y in the needing-to
be-an-object of its object itself (namely, nature under the law of freedom) .
The Kantian Pleasure System 203
The first power, therefore, appears here at best in an amputated form, lim
ited to a cognition of concepts without intuition-or else, as cognition
whose intuitions have peculiar characteristics that are not those of space
and time . . . In such a cognition, . in any event, nothing is known (and
nothing is theoretical) other than the practical determination of reason.
However, if there is something like an intuition to which some cog
nition corresponds, if there is something which can be grasped, perceived,
or felt (eingesehen), then this might well be something along the lines of the
feeling that Kant introduces here. But he adds that this feeling plays no
role in the a priori constitution of the practical determination of reason;
were it to do so, it would run counter to the autonomy of that determina
tion. The "connection" between the first two powers remains at least in
complete, or as if one-sided, and quite a lot is needed if they are to be "con
nected" with the third. (Iris worth noting that in both instances Kant uses
the word Verknupfung, '"knotting together," although the translation uses
.
"connectlon" or "1·tnk. ") .
We know that the feeling that cannot but follow from the moral law
is respect. What Kant says here about the secondary status of feeling fits
with what he says in the Critique ofPractical Reason, in the section "On the
Incentives of Pure Practical Reason."15 He also says in that section, though,
that this feeling, which belongs to "reason," is "the only one that we can
cognize completely a priori and the necessity ofwhich we can discern [ein
sehen]."16 In the Introduction, however, this eimehen seems somewhat
blurred or cOhfused by Kant's hesitation about the nature of the feeling in
question ("or perhaps [it] is nothing other than"). Moreover, respect is not
mentioned explicitly, and the allusive circumlocution that could only refer
to it seems unsatisfactory: because it concerns a "feeling ' of pleasure," a
'
quality that the second Critique seduloUsly denies to respect: "So little is re
spect a feeling ofpleasure that we give way to it only reluctantly with regard
to a human being." Equally, however, there is "so little displeasure is there
in it that . . . one can never get enough of contemplating the majesty of
this [moral] law."17
Be that as it may, respect is clearly the incentive of pure practical rea
son. In the Introduction, the anonymous feeling which stands in for or
supplements it is only the appreciation of or approbation for an "aptitude"
and does not constitute a "special feeling." From one to the other, there is
a displacement, even a discord. Respect, insofar as it is an incentive, and
thus wholly distinct from pleasure and pain, produces nothing less than an
204 PLEASURE
"interest which we call moral" This interest is pure because the feeling "de
pends on the representation of a law only as to its form and not on account
of any object of the law" :18 respect thus behaves (or structures itself) like a
pleasure, that is, like the self-relating of a representation which contains in
itself the grounds for its own continued existence . . .
In §37 of the Critique ofJudgment Kant presents the same argument
for depriving feeling of any determinate apriority:
I cannot connect a priori a definite feeling (of pleasure or displeasure) with any
representation, except in the case where an underlying a priori principle in reason
determines the will; but in that case the pleasure (in moral feeling) is the conse
quence of that principle, and that is precisely why it is not at all comparable to the
pleasure in taste.19
Though they differ in character, the two different sorts of pleasure never
theless share the same name, which suggests, despite everything, a close
natural kinship. In §I2 Kant attempts an awkward variation on this argu
ment, describing respect as "a special and peculiar modification of the feel
ing of pleasure and displeasure which does seem to differ somehow from
both the pleasure and displeasure we get from empirical objects."2o "Mod
ification" implies some commonality of substance.
Now this commonality characterizes a very odd sort of apriority, ad
umbrated in §I2. The a priori ruled out in the connection of pleasure with
representation is that causality. That some feeling is the effect of a repre
sentation is something that "can never be cognized otherwise than a poste
riori " (whether that feeling is "one arising from the pathological basis,
agreeableness," or "one arising from the intellectual basis, the conceived
good," the latter, as we know, being only the consequence of a "postu
late").21 Yet there is a pleasure which, without being the effect of a repre
sentation, is just this same representation relating to itself by means of an
"internal (final) causality." This is the "state of mind of a will determined
by something or other," and thus the state par excellence of the categorical
imperative. This state is "in itself already a feeling of pleasure," rather than
being the cause of some affection or other. Pleasure is always the delight
(jouissance) in itself of a representation, that is, of a "state of mind" in its
pure form. But this pleasure can either be "merely contemplative" or "prac
tical." Which is to say that the representation can either be that of a
"merely formal purposiveness in the play of the cognitive powers" or that
of the will.
",I
,. .
The two " a priori pleasures" are distinguished from one another
solely by two forms or states of mind, which are themselves just two modes
of self-relation: representation as an end in itself, or representation as cause
of its' own actuality. At this point, the two pleasures constitute a system in
the strongest sense: the system ofthe cause and the end of reason for itself
But it is precisely here that Kant finds it necessary to invoke once
again a rigorous distinction between the two pleasures in order to stave off
the possibility that one might contaminate the other or, rather and above
all, that a pure will might be contaminated by a pure affection. This dis
tinction entails that the apriority of respect be regarded as not comparable
with that which it most resembles. What cannot be compared to it is this:
although in respect everything takes place as with pleasure (or pain), noth
ing can be allowed to cause pleasure or pain. We find in respect the form
or structure of pleasure, but not the taste or flavor.
slightest effect upoxi our feeling of pleasure; nor can there ever be any such
effect, because the understanding proceeds with these laws unintentionally,
by the necessity of its own nature. "23 This "concurrence" with laws is a
mere Zusammentrejfen, an encounter, and not a Zusammenhang, or inter
'
nal organization (one of the leitmotivs of the First Introduction). Further
more, says Kant, "it is a fact that when we discover that two or more het
erogeneous empirical laws of nature can be unified [ VCreinbarkeit] under
one principle that comprises them both, the discovery does give rise to a
quite noticeable pleasure, frequently even admiration, even an admiration
that does not cease when we have become fairly familiar with its object."24
Thus Kant announces the motif of a supreme pleasure in purposiveness,
which reappears, in the guise of "admiration," in the dosing pages of the
third Critique.25 There, admiration, which is both the support of and sup
plement to the thinking of purposes, is said to have something about it
"similar to. a religious feeling" and, as such, seems to "affect the moral feel
ing (of gratitude and veneration toward the cause we do not know), be
cause we judge in a way analogous to the moral way."26
Cognition is thus entitled to expect a specific pleasure, constrained,
needless to say, by the conditions of the reflective judgment through which
purposes are posited, but passing beyond the theoretical so as to effect,
again in strictly analogical fashion, a kind of reinforcing of "moral feeling"
and, by extension, of the pure incentive of practical reason: as ifsomething
in the final purpose was susceptible of being cognized in order to deter
mine the will. This something is certainly not unknowable freedom-but
neither is it simply its opposite. Rather, it must be the knowledge of free
dom as a knowing delighting in itself
But th�s simple representation of purposiveness and of such a plea
sure under an analogical or "symbolic" condition cannot itself be repre
sented as a delight on the part of cognition if the latter did not, as it were,
contain the seeds of it from the very beginning. At least this is what Kant
goes on to suggest in the Introduction:
It is true that we no longer feel any noticeable pleasure resulting from our being
able to grasp nature and the unity in its division into genera and species that alone
make possible the empirical concepts by means of which we cognize nature in
terms of its particular laws. But this pleasure was no doubt there ai: one time, and
it is only because even the commonest experience would be impossible without it
that we have gradually come to mix it in with mere cognition and no longer take
any special notice of it. 27
The Kantian Pleasure System 207
There was once, there necessarily must have been, therefore, a primitive
pleasure in cognition. Granted, Kant is speaking here only about cognition
through "empirical concepts" and "particular laws," and not about the cog
nition through "universal concepts" to which he referred a few lines earlier.
But the two are not easily separated. Besides, we can liee just how hesitant
Kant's text is: he coordinates an ability to "grasp nature," which we can as
sume corresponds to a general cognition characteristic of the understand
ing, with a "unity in its [nature's] division into genera and species," which
does not stem from the understanding alone but is, on the contrary, the
occasion for the critique of the power of judgment. Here mathematico
physical cognition is distinct neither from chemico-biological cognition
nor from culture and taste, and the analogy links up in some manner to
determination . . .
If, from the point of view of the object, the cognition produced by
determinant jt!.dgments has nothing to do with the cognition that follows
from reflective judgments-no more than mechanism has to do with pur
posiveness-the purposive unity of nature nevertheless presupposes, as its
minimal condition, the unity of a nature in general, the "a priori unity
[without which] no unity of experience, thus also no determination of the
objects in it, would be possible."28
So the "commonest experience" to which Kant refers is not, in its
generality and its principle, divisible into a priori and a posteriori experi
ence (into "possible experience" and the empirical). Rather, it is a matter of
that which, in the a priori, aims from the outset at the a posteriori as such:
the givenness of the material, sensible manifold, its heterogeneity, and the
problematic character of its unity qua purposive unity. This apriority,
which is neither that of the forms of intuition nor that of the categories
nor of schematism itself-is the supplementary apriority of a feeling: of the
representation of unity in general delighting in itself. Without this we
wouldn't even have begun to be subjects of some experience or other. If the
most general condition of the cognition of the understanding is the synop
sis of intuition in conjunction with categorial synthesis,29 it is necessary
nonetheless to suppose-and this is something that the Critique ofPure
Reason doesn't do-the existence of something like an. incentive for the ac-
tivity of cognition.
Of course this incentive has to be located in cognitive activity itself,
specifically in the relation of cognition to itself, which is to say, in the rela
tion to itself of representation qua combination, or in the relation to itself
208 PLEASURE
Once the active and disruptive presence of pleasure in the two pow
ers of reason, properly so called, is recognized, we can better understand
the full implications of the "transcendental definition" Kant provides, once
he has set up aesthetic judgment as the relation of a representation to the
feeling of pleasure and displeasure:
the critical separation between the other two but also, if one can say so, with
generating reason's sole,incentive, under the auspices of a pleasure that is ir
resistibly both one and many, self-identical in its foreignness to itselE
If the concept of repression runs the risk of bringing in something
too distant or anachronistic here, and uselessly raises the question of what
it is that exercises repression, we might speak of something being given up
or relinquished: Kantian reason relinquishes or is deprived of delight in it
self-but it does so or is so precisely in order to make dear that its voca
tion lies in the act of enjoyment or delight that Spinoza terms "beatitude"
and "joy" and that shows up here as division in and of itselE
Hence pleasure organizes the system and is at the heart of it. Or,
more exactly, the heart of the system, what articulates it and puts it into
play, what gives it the internal consistency and purposiveness that makes
up genuine systematicity. is the feeling of pleasure and displeasure.33 This
is to say that, if "pleasure" is always the value of the highest vocation, its
deep structure is that of self-relating, and this self-relating, insofar as it is
not given (but rather, in a way, sets itself in motion for itself) , displays in
a fundamental way the ambivalence of the permanent possibility of discord
or disagreement. To take pleasure or displeasure in itself: Kantian reason
falls prey to this anxiety. This is why its whole predicament is summed up
in the famous formulation at the end of the Critique ofPractical Reason:
"the starry heavens above me and the moral law within me' are the twin ob
je'cts and sources of an "ever new and increasing admiration" which, at one
and the same time, "annihilates, as it were, my importance as an animal
creature, which must give back to the planet . . . the matter from which it
came" and "infiriitely raises my worth as an intelligence by my personality,
in which the moral law reveals to me a life independent of all animality."34
This anxiety can appear narcissistic, and undoubtedly it is: though
not in the sense either of a vain indulgence or an auto-eroticism. It is nar
cissistic in the sense that such identification is necessary, and to the extent
that the absence of this identification (that of an intuitus originarius)
grounds Kantian reason so dramatically in a double divestiture-a forget
ting and a forbidding-of delight in itself, its principle, and its purpose.
Translated by Jonathan Derbyshire
11
For the sake of the unity which the veil and that which is veiled comprise in it, the
Idea can be essentially valid only where the duality of nakedness and veiling does
not yet obtain: in art and in the appearances of mere nature. On the other hand,
the more distinctly this duality expresses itself, in order finally in man to reach its
greatest force, the more this becomes clear: in veil-less nakedness the essentially
beautiful has withdrawn and in the naked body �f the human being a Being be
yond all beauty is attained-the sublime, and a work beyond all images
[Gebilden]-the work of the creator. (Benjamin4)
In the work, truth is at work and 'therefore not merely something true. . . . The ap
pearance arranged in the work is the beautiful. Beauty is a mode of being and of
presence of truth qua unveiling. (Heidegger5)
The Kantian theory of the sublime describes . . . an art which shudders within it-
The Sublime Offering 213
self: it suspends itself in the name of the content of truth deprived of appearance,
but without, qua art, renouncing its character as appearance. (Adorno6)
Just as prose is not separated from poetry by any threshold, art expressive of an
guish is not truly separated from that expressive bfjoy . . . it is no longer a matter
of dilettantism: sovereign art accedes to the extremiry of the possible. (Bataille7)
but as for Kant, he had begun to recognize that what was at stake in art was
not the representation of the truth, but-to put it briefly-the presentation
offreedom. It was this recognition that was engaged in and by the thought
of the sublime. Not only was art not completed by philosophy in this
thought, but art began to tremble there, suspended over itself; unachieved.,
perhaps unachievable, On the border of philosophy-which art thus made
shudder or interrupt itself in its turn;
For Kant, the beautiful and the sublime have in common that they
have to do with presentation and only with presentation.1O In both noth
ing plays itself out but the play of presentation itself; without any repre
sented object. (There ought therefore to be a concept, or an experience, of
presentation that would not be submitted to the general logic of (re)pres
entation, that is, of the presentation by a subject and for a subject: basi
cally, the entire question is there) . Oh the occasion of an object of the
senses, the imagination-which is the faculty of presentation-plays at
finding a form in accord with its free play. It presents (to itself) this: that
there is a free accord between the sensible (which is essentially multiple or
manifold) and a unity (which is not a concept, but rather free indetermi
nate unity) . The imagination thus presents the image, or rather that there
is (such a thing as) "image" (Bild) . The image here is not the reptesenta-
tive image, and it is not the object. It is not the placing-in-form of some
thing else but form forming itself; for itself; without object: fundamentally,
art, according to Kant, represents nothing in either the beautiful or the
sublime. The "imagination" does not signifY the subject who makes an im
age of something but rather the image imaging itself; not as a figure of
. something else but as form forming itself; unity happening upon mani
foldness, coming out of a manifoldness, in the manifold of sensibility, sim
ply as unity without object and without subject-and thus without end. It
is on the basis of this general situation of free aesthetic presentation that
one must attempt to appreciate the respective stakes of the beautiful and
the sublime.
Kant calls the free Bild that precedes all images, ail representations,
and all figurations (one is tempted to say the nonfigurative Bild) a schema
in the first · Critique. He says in the third Critique that aesthetic judgment
is nothing other than the reflexive play of the imagination when it
"schematizes without concepts" : that is, when the world that forms itself;
that manifests itself; is not a universe of objects but merely a schema
(skema, "form," or "figure") , merely a· Bildthat makes a "world" on its own,
216 PLEASURE
because it forms itself, because it designs itself The schema is the figure
but the imagination that figures without concepts figures nothing: the
schematism of aesthetic judgment is intransitive. It is merely the figure that
figures itself It is not a world nor the world that takes on figure, but the
figure that makes woHd. It is perhaps indissociable from the fake, the fic
tion, and the dream of a Narcissus: but all of that comes only after the fact.
In order that there should be these figures and this scene of representa
tions, there must first be the throw, the surging and beating, of a design, a
form, which figures itselfin giving itSelf figure, in conferring upon itself a
free unity. It confers this unity upon itself, or it receives this unity-for at
first it does not have any unity at its disposal. Such is the essential charac
teristic of imagination, of Einbildung operating without a concept: imagi
nation is unity that precedes itself, anticipates itself, and manifests itself,
free figure prior to any further determination.
From this starting point-that is, barely having entered into the first
modern philosophical assignation of the aesthetic-one can finish very
quickly if one likes. By putsuing the logic of this initial constellation of the
aesthetic schematism, one can very quickly arrive at the end of ari:. Indeed,
in a sense one must pursue it if only in order to discover that it can func
tion only by ignoring the sublime, which nothing I have said thus far has
distinguished as such.
In the first Critique the schematism was said to be a "technique hid
den in the depths of the soul." Does the secret of this technique unveil it
self in the aesthetic schematism, which presents essentially the pure form
of the schematism? It is tempting to think so. The schematism would then
be aesthetic. The technique of the schema would be an art. After all, it is
the same word, ars or die Kunst. Reason would be an artist, the world of
objects a work-and art would be the first or supreme technique, the cre
ative or self-creative technique, the technique of the unity of subject and
object, unity positing itself in the work.. One can believe this and proceed
to draw the consequences.
One will very quickly obtain two versions of a thereby completed
thought of the schematism: either the version of an originary and infinite
art, a poetry never ceasing to give itself form in giving form to the world as
to thought-and this is the romantic version-or else the version of a
technique of originary judgment, which divides judgment in order to re
late it to itself as unity and so to give it its absolute figure-and this is the
Hegelian version. Either aesthetics sublates philosophy or the converse. In
The Sublime Offering 217
both cases, the schematism is understood (its secret revealed) and accom
plished: art or technique-and doubtless, according to the play of com
plicitous exchange between the tw() versions, art and technique, technique
of art and art of technique-the schema is the originary figure offiguration
itself- That which figures (or that which presents, for here, figuring is pre
senting), the faculty of figuration or of presentation has itself already a fig
ure, and has already presented itself It is reason as artist or technician,
which comes down to the same thing: Deus artifex.
Thus, the imagination that schematizes without a concept would
schematize itself of itself in aesthetic judgment. And this is certainly, in one
sense, what it does: it presents itself as unity and it presents its unity to it-
. self, presenting nothing other than itself, presenting the faculty of presen
tation in its free play, that is, again, presenting the one presenting, or rep
resenting, absolutely. Here, the presenting one-the subject-is the
presented. In the beautiful and in the sublime-which are neither things
nor qualities of objects but judgments, and more precisely, aesthetic judg
ments, i.e., the proper judgments of sensibility when it is determined nei
ther by concepts nor by empirical sensation {which constitutes the agree
able, not the beautiful)-the unity of spirit, the spirit as unity, and the
accord of the faculties operated in the imagination or, more precisely, as
imagination presents itself to itself
It is not so much that art comes to find its reason or reasons here but
rather that Reason takes possession of art in order to make of it the tech
nique ofits self-presentation. This self-presen,tation is thus the pr�sentation
of the· very technique of reason, of a technique conceived as the primary or
ultimate nature of reason, in accordance with which reason produces, op
erates, figures, and presents itself on its own. The schematism is on this ac
count the anticipation of the unity of presentation (or of that which pre
sents) in presentation itself (or in the presented), an anticipation which
doubtless constitutes the only possible technique (the only Handgriff,
"sleight of hand," as the first Critique puts it) by means of which a presen
tation, in this strict philosophiC sense, could ever take place. Bow would I
trace any figure at all, if I did not anticipate its unity, or more precisely, if!
did not anticipate myself, the one who presents this figure, as its unity?
There is a kind of fore-sight or providence at the heart of reason. The
schema is reason which fore-sees arid prefigures itself It is thus of the na
ture of the schematism, this artistic coup de main of reason, to be "hidden
in the depths of the soul": the prefiguration escapes in its anticipation. And
218 PLEASURE
it is even basically the hidden, secret character of the schematism that un
veils i.t for what it is: the technique, already dissimulated behind all visible
figures, of figurative or presentational anticipation.
. In this "schematism without concepts," in this "free legality" or in
this "sketch" of the 'Yorldl l for the free subject, the cosmetic is the antici
pation of the cosmic. The beautiful is not here a quality, intrinsic or ex
trinsic, subjective or objective, it is more than a quality. Indeed, it consti
tutes the status and the very being of the subject which forms itself and
which presents itself in order eo be able to (re)present for itself a world of
phenomena. The aesthetic is itself the anticipation of knowledge, art is the
anticipation of technical reason, and taste is the schema of experience-the
schema or the pleasure, for precisely here the two are confounded. Did not
Kartt write that a primitive pleasure must have presided over the very first
knowledge, "a remarkable pleasute, without which the most common ex
perience would not have been possible"?12 There is a pute, painless pleas
ure, then, at the philosophical origin of knowledge and world domination.
(That there is no admixture of pain in this pleasure implies �hat the sub
lime is not yet involved, a point to which I will return below.) This pleas
ure consists in the satisfaction provided by unity in general, by (re)discov
ering (re)union of the manifold, the heterogeneous, under a principle or
law. Anticipation arises out of or resides within this enjoyment (jouissance]
of unity which is necessary to reason. Without unity, the manifold is noth
ing but chaos and vertiginous danger. United with its unity-a unity
which one must therefore have anticipated in order to be able to rediscover
and (re)present it, and a unity thus technically and artistically produced
the manifold becomes enjoyment: at once pleasure and appropriation.
Enjoyment, according to Kant, belongs to the agreeable, which must
be carefully distinguished from the beautiful. The agreeable is attached to
an interest, whereas the beautiful is not. The beautiful is not linked to any
interest, for in aesthetic judgment I do not depend at all on the existence
of the object, and what is important is merely "what I discover in myself"
on the occasion of this object. 13
But does not self-enjoyment arise out of a supreme and secret inter
est of reason? The disinterestedness of the judgment of beauty, caught in
the logic of the ratio artifex, is a profound interestedness: one has an inter
est in the being-anticipated of unity, in the (pre)formation of the figure, in
the avoidance of chaos.
Here, the category of the beautiful begins to reveal itself in its ex-
-
The Sublime Offering 219
treme fragility. The. beautiful and the agreeable already have in common
that they "please immediately," in distinction to the good, on the one
hand, and the sublime, on the other. If one must also establish · a rapport
between them in terms of interest-interest in the object in the case of the
agreeable and interest in oneself in the case of the beautiful (and are these
two things really so different?)-then one will have to say that the beauti
ful too involves enjoyment, the enjoyment of anticipation and self-presen
tation. The beautiful in Kant, and perhaps all simple beauty since Kant,
arises from the enjoyment of the subject, and indeed constitutes the sub
ject as enjoying itself, its unity and its free legality, as that artist-reason
which insures itself against the chaos of sensible experience and clandes
tinely re-appropriates for itself-thanks to its "hidden ad'-the satisfac
tions that it had lost with God. Unless-even more brutally-it was the
subject-artist (the subject of art, philosophy, and technique) who ravished·
God of His enjoyment.
When it presents itself in philosophy, or rather when it anticipates it
self in philosophy (anticipating, in Kant's time, the essentially technical '
and artificial character of modern reason), aesthetics is suppressed twice in,
a single instant: once in the end of art and once in the enjoyment of imag
inative reason. The two are the same, as one can clearly see: art meets its
end, for it consists in the enjoyment in which it achieves itself Kant is not
in this the other of Hegel: in both, what is at stake in the aesthetic is pres
entation. The presentation of truth. rests on the truth of presentatiori,
which is the enjoyment of prefigured unity. The Hegelian spirit does not
enjoy itself in any other way: the Kantian imagination is what it enjoys. Or
again, the Hegelian spirit is itself the final self-appropriating enjoyment of
the Kantian imagination. And philosophy gets offon art, makes of art and
the beautiful its own enjoyment, suppresses them as simple pleasures, one
could say, and preserves them as the pure self-enjoyment of Reason. The
Aufhebung of art in philosophy has the structure of enjoyment-and in
this infinite structure, art in its turn enjoys itself: it can become, as philo
sophic art, as art or technique of philosophical presentation (for example,
dialectical, scientific, or poetic presentation), the orgiastic self-enjoyment
of Spirit itself.
Once upon a time, the beautiful was "the splendor of the true": by a
singular perversion, which it is difficult to consider without unease, the
splendor of the true has become the self-enjoyment of reason.
This is perhaps the philosophic fate of the aesthetic as well as the aes-
220 PLEASURE
thetic fate of philosophy. Art and beauty: presentations of the true, which
uses them for its own enjoyment, anticipates itself in them, and finishes
them off.
But far from finishing, we have hardly begun by proceeding thus. We
have not even begun to deal with the sublime, and art, in Kant, does not
offer itself to analysis before one has passed by way of the analysis of the
sublime, which in several respects feeds into the examination of art, in par
ticular by way of the decisive motif of genius. (This is not the place to
dwell on it, but let me at least mention here that one can only thoroughly
comprehend the Kantian theory of the arts, regardless of Kant's intentions,
if one understands its dependence upon the theory of the sublime. This
dependence is manifested, for example, by the ordering of his apparently
poorly justified table of contents, which places the theory of art within the
'�alytic of the Sublime," whereas the latter was supposed to be "a mere
appendix" to the '�alytic ofAesthetic Judgments.")
One can gain access to the sublime by passing argumentatively
through the insufficiencies of the beautiful. We have just seen beauty
thicken suddenly, if I dare put it this way, into the pleasure or satisfaction
of reason. This signifies nothing other than that the beautiful is an unsta
ble category, insufficiently contained or retained in the order that was to be
properly its own (the pure presentation of presentation). The beautiful is
perhaps not quite as autonomous as it appears and as Kant would like.
Taken literally as the pure pleasure of pure presentation, the beautiful re
veals itself to be responsive to the interest of reason, which is all the more
interested because it is hidden: it satisfies itself with and is satisfied by its
power to present and to present itself It admires itself on the occasion of
its objects, and it tends, according to what is for Kant the law of all pleas
ure, to preserve its current condition, to preserve the enjoyment of its
proper Bild and Ein-bildung. Doubtless the. beautiful, rigorously consid-
. ered, is not in this state of enjoyment, but it is always about to slide into it,
to become confused with it: and this ever imminent sliding is not acciden
tal but belongs to the very structure of the beautiful. (In the same manner,
one can apply to the judgment of taste the rule applied to moral judgment:
one can never say for certain that an acdon has been accomplished by pure
morality; likewise, one can never say that a judgment of taste is a pure
judgment of beauty: it is always possible that some interest-empirical or
not-has intruded itself Even more rildically or rigorously, it is possible
The Sublime Offiring 221
that there is no such thing as a pure judgment of taste and that its disinter
est is always interested in the profound self-enjoyment of the imagination.)
However, the same instability, the same constitutive lability that
makes the beautiful slide into the agree:ible can also carry it off into the
sublime. Indeed, the beautiful is perhaps only an intermediate, ungras
pable formation, impossible to fix except as a limit, a border, a place of
equivocation (but perhaps also of exchange) between the agreeable and the
sublime, that is, between enjoyment and joy [la jouissance et la joie], to
which I will return below.
If a transport of the beautiful into the sublime is indeed the counter
part or reversal of its sliding into the agreeable-and this is what we shall
verify-and if in the agreeable the beautiful ultimately loses its quality of
beauty (for in enjoyment, in the beautiful as satisfied or satisfying, the
beautiful is finished-and art along with it), then one must expect the
beautiful truly to attain its "proper" quality only in another sort of depar
ture from itself-into the sublime. That is, the beautiful becomes the
beautiful only beyond itself, or else.it slides into the space this side ofitsel£
By itself, it haS no position. Either it achieves itself-in satisfaction, or phi
losophy-or it suspends itself, unachieved, in the sublime (and in art, or at
least in art that has not been sublated by philosophy).
The sublime forms neither a second wing of aesthetics nor another
kind of aesthetic. After all, it is rather unaesthetic and unartistic for an aes
thetic. And in the final analysis, it would seem more like an ethics, if one
holds to the declared intentions of Kant. But Kant does not seem to see
quite what is at stake when he introduces the sublime. He treats the sub..;.
lime as a mere "appendix" to the analysis of aesthetic judgment, 14 but in re
ality, the sublime represents in the Critique nothing less than that without
which the beautiful could not be the beautiful or without which the beau
tiful could be nothing but the beautiful (which paradoxically comes down
to the same thing). Far from being a subordinate kind of aesthetic, the sub
lime constitutes a decisive moment in the thought of the beautiful and of
art as such. It does not merely add itself to the beautiful but transforms or
transfigures the beautiful. Consequently-and this is what I am attempt
ing to show-the sublime does not constitute in the general field of
(re)presentation just one more instance or problematic: it transforms or
redirects the entire motif of presentation. (And this transformation con
tinues to be at work in our own day.)
222 PLEASURE
There is nothing new about the idea that the sublime represents that
without which beauty itself would not be beautiful, or would be merely
beautiful, that is, enjoyment and preservation of the BNd. It dates from the
modern (re)naissance of the sublime. Boileau spoke of "this je-ne-sais-quoi
which charms us and without which beauty itself would have neither grace
nor beauty." Beauty without beauty is beauty which is merely beautiful,
that is, merely pleasing (and not "charming"). Fenelon writes: ,"The beau
tiful which is only beautiful, that is, brilliant, is only half-beautiful." In a
sense, all of modern aesthetics, that is, all "aesthetics," has its origin and rai
son d'etre in the impossibility of attributing beauty merely to beauty and in
the consequent skidding or overflowing of the beautiful beyond itself
What'is mere beauty? Mere beauty, or beauty alone and isolated for itself,
is form in its pure self-adequation, in its pure accord with the imagination,
the faculty of presentation (or formation). Mere beauty, without interest,
concept, or idea, is the simple accord-which is by itself a pleasure-of the
thing presented with the presentation. At least, this is what modern beauty
has been or attempted to be: a presentation, that is successful and without
remainder in accord with itsel£ (At bottom, this is subjectivity qua beauty.)
In short, i� is a matter of the schema in the pure state of a schematism with
out concepts, considered in its free accord with itself, where freedom is con
fused with the simple necessity tha,t form should be adequate to its proper
form, should present just the form that it is, or should be just the form that
it presents. The beautiful is the figure that figures itself in accord with itself,
the strict accord of its contour with its design.
Form or contour is limitation, which is the concern of the beautiful:
the unlimited, to the contrary, is the concern of the sublime.
The unlimited maintains doubtless the closest, the most intimate re
lations with the infinite. The concept of the infinite (or its differe�t possi
ble concepts) gives us in a sense the internal structure of the unlimited.
But the infinite does not exhaust, the being of the unlimited, it does not
offer the true moment of the unlimited. If the analysis of the sublime
ought to begin, as it does in Kant, with the unlimited, and if it ought to
transport into itself and replay the analysis of beauty (and thus of limita
tion), it must above all not proceed simply as the analysis of a particular
kind of presentation, the presentation of the infinite. Nearly impercepti
ble at the outset, this frequently committed error can considerably distort
the final results of the analysis. In the sublime, it is not a matter of the
presentation or nonpresentation of the infinite, placed beside the presen-
.c-;
. .. :
The Sublime Offering 223
cal functions, perhaps always frame and determine aesthetics as such, all
aesthetics. And the aesthetics of mere beauty, of the pure self-adequation of
presentation, with its incessant sliding into the enjoyment of the self, in
deed, arises out of fiction arid desire.
But it is precisely no longer a matter of the adequation of presenta
tion. It is also not a matter of its inadequation. Nor is it a matter of pure
presentation, whether this presentation be that of adequation or of inade
quation, nor is it even a matter of the presentation of the fact that there is
such a thing as the nonpresentable.17 In the sublime-or perhaps more
precisely at a certain extreme point to which the sublime leads us-it is no.
longer a matter of (re)presentation in general.
It is a matter of something else, which takes place, happens, or occurs
in presentation itself and in sum through it but which is not presentation:
this motion through which, incessantly, the unlimited raises and razes it
self, unlimits itself, along the limit that delimits and presents itself. This
motion would trace in a certain way the external border of the limit. But
this external border is precisely not an outline: it is not a second outline ho
mologous to the internal border and stuck to it. In one sense, it is the same
as the (re)presentational outline. In another sense, and simultaneously, it is
an unlimitation, a dissipation of the border on the border itself-an un
bordering or overbordering, or overboarding, an "effusion" (Ergiejfung),
Kant" says. What takes place in this going overboard of the border, what
happens in this effusion? As I have indicated above, I call it the offering,
but we need time to get there. .
greater than the greatest greatness: it designates rather that there is, ab
solutely, greatness. It is a matter of magnitudo, Kant says, and not of quan
titas. Quantitas can be measured, whereas magnitudo presides over the pos
sibility of measure in general: it is the fact in itself of greatness, the fact
that, in order for there to be forms of figures which are more or less large,
there must be, on the edge of all form or �gure, greatness as such. Great
ness is not, in this sense, a quantity, but a quality, or more precisely, it is
quantity qua quality. It is. in this way that for Kant the beautiful concerns
quality, the sublime quantity. The beautiful resides in form as such, in the
form of form, if one can put it this way, or in the figure that it makes. The
sublime resides in the tracing-out, the setting-off and seizure of form, in
dependently of the figure this form delimits, and hence in its quantity
taken absolutely, as magnitudo. The beautiful is the proper of such and
such an image, the pleasure of its (re)presentation. The sublime is: that
there is an image, hence a limit, along whose edge unlimitation makes it
self felt.
Thus, the beautiful and the sublime, if they are not identical-and
indeed, quite the contrary-take place on the same site, and in a certain
sense the one upon the other, the one along the edge of the other, and per
haps-I will come back to this-the one through the other. The beautiful
and the sublime are presentation but in such a manner that the beautiful is
the presented in itspresentation, whereas the sublime is the presentation in
its movement:-which is the absolute re-moval of the unlimited along the
edge of any limit. The sublime is not "greater than" the beautiful, it is not
more elevated [eleve1 , but in turn, it is, if ! dare put it this way, more re
moved [enleve] , in the sense that it is itself the unlimited removal of the
beautiful.
What gets removed and carried away is all form as such. In the man
ifestation of a world or in the composition of a work, form carries itself
away or removes itself, that is, at once traces itself and unborders itself, lim
its itself and unlimits itself (which is nothing other than the most strict
logic of the limit). All form as such, all figure is small with regard to the
unlimitedness against which it, sets itself off and which carries it away.
"That is sublime," writes Kant, "in comparison with which all the rest is
small." The sublime is hence not a greatness that would be "less small" and
would still take place along, even if at the summit of, a scale of compari
son: for ill this case, certain parts of the rest would not be "small," but sim
ply less great. The sublime is incomparable, it is of a greatness with relation
The Sublime Offering 227
to which all the others are "small," that is, are not of the same order what
soever, and are therefore no longer properly comparable.
The sublime magnitudo resides-or rather befalls and surprises-at
the limit, and in the ravishment and removal of the limit. Sublime great
ness is: that there is such a thing as measurable, presentable greatness, such
a thing as limitation, hence such a thing as form and figure. A limit raises
itself or is raised, a contour traces itself, and thus a multiplicity, a dispersed
manifold comes to be presented as a unity. Unity comes to it from its
limit-say, through its internal border, but that there is this unity, ab
solutely, or again that this outline should make up a whole, comes-to put
it still in the same manner-from the external border, from the unlimited
raising and razing of the limit. The sublime concerns the totality (the gen
eral concept ofwhich is the concept of unified multiplicity). The totality of
a form, of a presentation, is neither its completeness nor the exhaustive
summation Of its parts. Rather, this totality is what takes place where the
form has no parts, and consequently (re)presents nothing, but presents it
self The sublime takes place, Kant says, in a "representation of the unlim
ited to which is added nonetheless the thought of its totality" (and this is
why, as he specifies, the sublime can be found in a formless object as well
as in a form). A presentation takes place only if all the rest, all the unlim
itedness from which it detaches itself, sets itself off along its border-and
at once, in its own way, presents itself or rather sets itself off and upsets it
self all along the presentation.
The sublime totality is not at all the totality of the infinite conceived
as something other than finite and beautiful forms (and which by virtue of
this otherness would give way to a second, special aesthetics which would
be that of the sublime), nor is it the totality of an infinite that would be the
summation of all forms (and would make of the aesthetics of the sublime
a "superior" or "total"18 aesthetics). The sublime totality is rather the total
ity of the unlimited, insofar as the unlimited is beyond (or this side of) all
form and all sum, insofar as the unlimited is, in general, on the far side of
the limit, that is, beyond the maximum.
The sublime totality is beyond the maximum, which is to say that it
is beyond everything. Everything is small in the face of the sublime, all form,
all figure is small, bu� also, each form, each fig!lre is or can be the maxi
mum. The maximum (or magnitudo, which is its external border) is there
whenever the imagination has (re)presented the thing to itself, big or smalL
The imagination can do no more: it is defined by the Bildung of the BUd.
228 PLEASURE
tion is small and all greatness remains a little maximum where the imagi
nation reaches its limit.
Because it reaches this limit, it exceeds this limit. It overflows itself,
in reaching the overflowing of the unlimited, .where unjty gets carried away
into union. The sublime is the self-overflowing of the imagination. Not
that the imagination imagines beyond its maximum (and still less that it
imagines itself: we have to do here with exactly the reverse of its self-pres
entation). It imagines no longer and there is no longer anything to imag
ine, there is no Bild beyond Einbildung-and no negative BUd either, nor
the Bild of the absence of the Bild. The faculty of presentation (Le., the
imagination) presents nothing beyond the limit, for presentation is delim
itation itself. However, it gains access to something, reaches or touches
upon something (or it is reached or touched by something); union, pre
cisely, the "Idea" of the union of the unlimited, which borders upOJ? and
unborders the limit.
What operates this union? The imagination itselE At the limit, it
gains access to itself as in its speculative self-presentation. But here, the re
verse is the case: that "part" of itself that it touches is 'its limit, or it touches
itself as limit. "The imagination," Kant writes, "attains to its maximum,
and in the effort to go beyond this limit it sinks back into itself, and in so
doing is displaced into a moving satisfaction."19 {The question arises im
mediately, since there is satisfaction or enjoyment here, why is this not a
mere repetition of self-presentation? Nothing is pure here, nothing m�de
up of simple oppositions, everything happens as the reversal of itself, and
the sublime transport is the exact reverse of the dialectical sublation.}
At the limit, there is no longer either figure or figuration or form.
Nor is there the ground as something to which one could proceed or in
which one could exceed oneself, as in the Hegelian infinite, that is, as in a
nonfigurable instance which, infinite in its way, would not cease to cut a
figure. {Such is, in general, it seems to me, the concept with which one
ends up as soon as one names something like "the nonfigurable" or "the
nonpresentable": one (re)presents its nonpresentability, and one has thus
aligned it, however negatively, .with the order of presentable things.) At the
limit, one does not pass on; But it is there that everything comes to pass, it
is there that the totaiity of the unlimited plays itself out, as that which
throws into mutual reliefthe two borders, external and internal, ofallfigures,
adjoining them and separating them, delimiting and unlimiting the limit
thus in a single gesture.
It is at once an infinitely subtle, infinitely complex operation, and the
230 PLEASURE
most simple movement in the world, the strict beating of the line against
itself in the motion ofits outline. Two borders in one, union "itself," noth
ing less is required by all figures, as every painter, writer, and dancer
knows. It is presentation itself, but no longer presentation as the operation
of a (re)presenter producing or exhibiting a (re)presented. It is presentation
itselfat the point where it can no longer be said to be "itself," at the point
where one can no ionger say the presentation, and where it is consequently
no longer a question of saying either that it presents itself or that it is non
presentable. Presentation "itself" is the instantaneous division of and by
the limit, between figure and elimination, the one against the other, the
one upon the other, the one at the other, coupled and uncoupled in a sin
gle movement, in the same incision, the same beating.
What comes to pass here, at the limit-and which never gets defini
tively past the limit-is union, imagination, presentation. It is neither the
production of the homogeneous (which is in principle the ordinary task of
the schema) nor the simple and free accord of self:-recognition in which
beauty consists, for it is this side of or beyond the accord of beauty. But it
is also not the union of heterogeneous elements, which would be already
too romantic and too dialectical for the strict limit in question here. The
union with which one has to do in the sublime does not consist in cou
pling absolute greatness with finite limits: for there is nothing beyond the
limit, nothing either presentable or nonpresentable. It is indeed this affir
mation, "there is nothing beyond the limit," that properly and absolutely
distinguishes the thought of the sublime (and art) from dialectical thought
(and the end of art as its completion). Union does not take place between
an outside and an inside in order to engender the unity of a limit where
unity would present itself (according to this logic, the limit itself becomes
infinite, and the only art is that which traces the Hegelian "circle of cir
cles.") But there is only the limit, united with unlimitation insofar as the
latter sets itself off, sets itself up, and upsets itself incessantly on its border,
and consequently insofar as the limit, unity; divides itself infinitely in its
own presentation. :
For dialectical thought, the contour of a design, the frame of a pic
ture, the trace of writing point beyond themselves to the teleological ab
solute of a (positive or negative) total presentation. For the thought of the
sublime, the contour, the frame, and the trace point to nothing but them
selves-'-and even this is saying too much: they do not point at all, but
present (themselves), and their presentation presents its own interruption;
The Sublime Offering 231
the contour, frame, or trace. The union from which the presented or fig
ured unity arises presents itself as this interruption, as this suspension of
imagination (or figuration) in which the limit traces and effaces itselE The
whole here-the totality to which every presentation, every work, cannot
but lay claim-is nowhere but in this suspension itselE In truth, the whole,
on the limit, divides itself just as much as it unites itself, and the whole is -
nothing but that: the sublime totality does not respond, despite certain ap
pearances, to the supreme schema of a "total presentation," even in the
sense of a negative presentation or a presentation of the impossibility of
presentation (for that always presupposes a complement, an obje!ct of pres
e�tation, and the entire logic of re-presentation: here there is nothing to
present but merely that it [fa] presents itselE) The sublime totality does
not respond to a schema of the Whole, but rather, if one can put it this
way, to the whole of the sthematism: that is, to the incessant beating with
which the trace of the skema affects itself, the carrying away of the figure
against which the carrying away of unlimitedness does not cease to do bat
tle, this tiny, infinite pulsation, this tiny, infinite, rhythmic burst that pro
duces itself continuously in the trace of the least contour and through
which the limit itself presents itself, and on the limit, the magnituda, the
absolute of greatness in which all greatness (or quantity)-is traced, in
which all imagination both imagines and-on the same limit, in the same
beating-fails to imagine. That which indefinitely trembles at the border
of the sketch, the suspended whiteness of the page or the canvas: the expe
rience of the s.ublime demands no more than this.
In sum, from the beautiful to the sublime one more step is taken in
the "hidden art'� of the schematism: in beauty the schema is the unity of
the presentation; in the sublime, the schema is the pulsation of the unity.
That is, at once its absolute value (magnitudo) and its absolute distensio�,
union that takes place in and as suspension. In beauty, it is a matter of ac
cord; in the sublime, it is a matter of the syncopated rhythm of the trace of
the accord, spasmodic vanishing of the limit all along itself, into unlimit
edness, that is, into nothing. The sublime schematism of the totality is
made up of a syncopation at the heart of the schematism itself: simultane
ous reunion and distension of the limit of presentation-or more exactly,
and more inexorably: reunion and distension, positing-and vanishing afsi
multaneity (and thus of presentation) itself. Instantaneous flight and pres
ence of the instantaneous, grouping arid strewn division of a present. (I
will not insist further on this here, bur it is doubtless in terms of time that
232 PLEASURE
one ought finally to interpret the aestheti� of the sublime. This presup
poses perhaps the thought of a time of the limit, of a time of the fainting
of the figure, which would be the proper time of art?)
That the imag!nation-that is, presentation in the active sense-at
tains the limit, that it faints and vanishes there, \ "sinks back into itself," and
thus comes to present itself, in the foundering of a syncopation or rather as
this syncopation "itself," this exposes the imagination to its destiny. The
"proper destiny of the subject" is definitively the "absolute gre�tness" of the
sublime. What the imagination, in failing, avows to be unimaginable, is its
proper greatness. The imagination is thus destinedfor the . beyond of the
image. This beyond is not a primo�dial (or ultimate) presence (or absence)
which images would represent or of which images would present the fact
that it is not (re)presentable. Rather, the beyond of the image, which is not
"beyond," but on the limit, is in the Bildung of the Bild itself, and thus at
or on the edge of the Bild, the outline of the figure, the tracing, the sepa
rating-uniting incision, the beating of the schema: the syncopation, which
is in truth the other name of the schema, its sublime name, if there be such
things as suplime names.
The imagination (or the subject) is destined for, sent toward, dedi
cated and addressed to this syncopation. That is, presentation is dedi
cated, addressed to the presentation ofpresentation itself: this is the gen
eral destiny of aesthetics, of reason in aesthetics, as I said at the outset.
But in the sublime, it turns out that this destiny implies an unbordering
or a going overboard of the beautiful, for the presentation of presentation
itself, far from being the imagination of the imagination and the schema
of the schema, far from· being the figuration of the self-figuration of the
subject, takes place in and as syncopation, and thus does not take place,
does not have at its disposal the unified space of a figure, but rather is
given in the schematic spacing and throbbing of the trace of figures, and
thus only comes to pass in the syncopated time of the passage of the limit
to the limit.
verse, or rather (which comes down to the same thing) a sort oflogical ex
asperation, a passage to the limit: touching presentation on its limit, or
rather, being touched, attained by it. This emotion does not consist in the
sweetly proprietary pathos of what one can call "aesthetic emotion." To this
extent, it would be better to say that the feeling of the sublime is hardly an
emotion at all but rather the mere motion of presentation-at the limit
and syncopated. This (e) motion is without complacency and without sat
isfaction: it is not a pleasure without being at the same time a pain, which
constitutes the affective characteristic of the Kantian sublime. But its am
bivalence does not make it any less sensible, does not render it less effec
tively or less precisely sensible: it is the sensibility ofthefading ofthe sensible.
. Kant characterizes this sensibility in terms of striving and transport
[elan] . Striving, transport, and tension make themselves felt (and perhaps
this is their general logic or "pathetics") insofar as they are suspended, at
the limit (there is no striving or tension except at the limit), in the instant
and the beating of their suspension.20 It is a matter, Kant writes, of the
"feeling of an arrest of the vital forces" (Hemmung, "inhibition," "im
pinging upon," or "blockage"). Suspended life, breath cut off-the beat
ing heart.
It is here that sublime presentation properly takes place. It takes
place in effort and feeling: "Reason . . . as faculty of the independence of
the absolute totality . . . sustains the effort, admittedly sterile, of the spirit
to harmonize the representation of the senses with Totality. This effort and
the feeling that the Idea is inaccessible to imagination constitute in and of
themselves a presentation of the subjective purposiveness of our spiriJ: in
the use of the imagination concerning its super-sensible destiny."21
"Striving," Bestreben, is not to be understood here in the sense of a
project, an envisioned undertaking that one could evaluate either in terms
of its intention or in · terms of its result. This striving cannot be conceived
in terms of either a logic of desire and potentiality or a logic of the transi
tion to action and the work or a logic of the will and energy (even if all of
that is doubtless also present and is not to be neglected if one wishes to
provide an account of Kant's thought, which is not my intention here).
Rather, striving is to be understood on its own terms, insofar as it obeys in
itself only a logic (as well as a "pathetics" and an ethics) of the limit. Striv
ing or transport is by definition a matter of the limit. It consists in a rela
tion to the limit: a continuous effort is the continuous displacement of a
limit. The effort ceases where the limit cedes its place. Striving and exer-
I The Sublime Offering 235
I
1
I
subject, than of the tension of the limit itsel£ What tends, and what tends
here toward or in the extreme, is the limit. The schema of the image, of any
image-or the schema of totality, the schematism of total union-is ex
II tended toward and tensed in the extreme: it is the limit at the limit of its
I (ex)tension, the tracing-which is no longer quantifiable or hence trace
able-of magnitudo. Stretched to the limit, the limit (the contour of the
figure) is stretched to the breaking point, as one says, and it in fact does
break, dividing itself in the instant between two borders, the border of the
figure and its unlimited unbordering. Sublime presentation is the feeling of
this striving at the instant of rupture, the imagination still for an instant
sensible to itself although no longer itself; in extreme tension and disten-
. ("overflowmg·" or "abyss") .
S10n .
(Or again, the striving is a striving to reach and touch the limit. The
limit is the striving itself and the touching. Touching is the limit of itself:
the limit of images and words, contact-and with this, paradoxically, the
impossibility of touching inscribed in touching, since touching is the limit.
Thus, touching is striving, because it is not a state of affairs but a limit. It
is not one sensory state among others, it is neither as active nor as passive
as the others. If all of the senses sense themselves sensing, as Aristode
would have it [who, moreover, established already that there can be no true
contact, either in the water or in the air], touching more than the other
senses takes place only in touching itsel£ But more than the others also, it
thus touches its limit, itself as limit: it does not attain itself, for one touches
only in general [at] the limit. Touching does not touch itself, at least not as
seeing sees itself.)
The sublime presentation is a presentation because it gives itself to be
sensed. But this sentiment, this feeling is singular. As a sentiment of the
limit, it is the sentiment of an insensibility, a nonsensible sentiment (ap
atheia, phlegma in significatu bono, Kant says), a syncopation of sentiment.
But it is absolute sentiment as well, not determined as pleasure or as pain
but touching the one through the other, touched by the one in the other.
The alliance of pleasure with pain ought not to be understood in terms of
ease and unease; of comfort and discomfort combined in one subject by a
perverse contradiction. For this singular ambivalence has to do first of all
with the fact that the subject vanished into it. It is also not the case that the
236 PLEASURE
subject gains pleasure by means of pain (as Kant tends to put it); it does
not pay the price of the one in order to have the other: rather, the pain here
is the pleasure, that is, once again, the limit touched, life suspended, the
beating heart.
If feeling properly so called is always subjective, if it is indeed the
core of subjectivity in a primordial "feeling oneself" of which all the great
philosophies of the subject could provide evidence, including the most "in
tellectualist" among them, then the feeling of the sublime sets itself off
or affects itself-precisely as the reversal of both feeling and subjectivity.
The sublime affection, Kant affirms, goes as far as the suspension of affec
tion, the pathos of apathy. This feeling is not a feeling-oneself, and in this
sense, it is not a feeling at all. One could say that it is what remains of feel
ing at the limit, when feeling no longer feels itself, or when there is no
longer anything to feel. Of the beating heart, one can say with equal justi
fication either that it feels only its beating
. or that
. it no longer feels any-
thing at all.
On the border of the syncopation, feeling, for a moment, still feels',
without any longer being able to relate (itself) to its feeling. It loses feel
ing: it feels its loss, but this feeling no longer belongs to it: although this
feeling is quite singularly its own, this feeling is nonetheless also taken
up in the loss of which it is the feeling. This is no longer to feel but to be
exposed.
Or in other words, one would. have to construct a double analytic of
feeling: one analytic of the feeling of appropriation, and another analytic of
the feeling of exposition: one of a feeling through or by oneself and another
of a feeling through or by the other. Can one feel through the other,
through the o'utside, even though feeling seems to depend on the self as its
means and even though precisely this dependence conditions aesthetic
judgment? This is what the feeling of the sublime forces us to think.22 The
subjectivity of feeling and of the judgment of taste are converted here into
the singularity of a feeling and a judgment that remain, to be sure, singu
lar, but where the singular as such is first of all exposed to the unlimited to
tality of an "outside" rather than related to its proper intimacy. Or in other
words, it is the intimacy of the "to feel" and the "to feel oneself" that pro
duces it�elf here, paradoxically, as exposition to what is beyond the self,
passage to the (in}sensible or (un}feeling limit of the self
Can one still say that the totality is presented in this instant? If it
were properly presented, it would be in or to that instance of presentifica-
II
The Sublime Offering 237
tion (or [re]presentation) which is the subjectivity of feeling. But the un
I
limitedness that affects the exposed feeling of the sublime cannot be pre
sented to it, that is, this unlimitedness cannot become present in and for a
subject. In its syncopation, the imagination presents itself, presents itself as
unlimited, beyond (its) figure, but this means that it is affected by (its)
nonpresentation. When Kant characterizes feeling, in the striving for the
limit, as "a representation," one must consider this concept in the absence
I of the values of presence and the present. One must learn-and this is per
i
haps the secret of the sublime as well as the secret of the schematism-that
I presentation does indeed take place but that it does not present anything.
I!
Pure presentation (presentation of presentation itself) or presentation of
the totality presents nothing at all. One could no doubt say, in a certain vo
cabulary, that it presents nothing or the nothing. In another vocabulary,
i
i one could say that it presents the nonpresentable. Kant himself writes that
I the genius (who represents a parte subjecti the instance of the sublime in
1- art) "expresses and communicates the unnamable." Th� without-name is
!
named, the inexpressible is communicated: all is presented-at the limit.
But in the end, and precisely at this limit itself, where all is achieved and
where all begins, it will be necessary to deny presentation its name.
It will be necessary to say that the totality-or the union of the un
limited and the unlimitedness of union, or, again, presentation itself, its
faculty, act, and subject-is offered to the feeling of the .sublime or is of
fired, in the sublime, to feeling. The offering retains of the "present" im
plied by presentation only the gesture of presenting. The offering offers,
carries, and places before (etymologically, of-fering is not very different
from ob-ject), but it does not install in presence. What is offered remains
at a limit, suspended on the border of a reception, an acceptance-which
cannot in its turn have any form other than that of an offering. To the of
fered totality, the imagination is offered-that is, also "sacrificed" (auf
geopfert), as Kant writes.23 The sacrificed imagination is the imagination of
fered to its limit.
The offering is the sublime presentation: it withdraws or suspends
the values and powers of the present. What takes place is neither a coming
into-presence nor a gift. It is rather the one or the other, or the one and the
other, but as abandoned, given up. The offering is the giving up of the gift
and of the present. Offering is not giving-it is suspending or giving up
the gift in the face of a freedom that can take it or leave it.
What is offered is offered up-addressed, destined, abandoned-to
238 PLEASURE
been destined for the sublime: it has been destined to touch us, in touch
ing upon our destiny or destination. It is only in this sense that ' one must
comprehend, . in the end, the end ofart.
What art is 'at stake here? In a sense, one has no choice, neither be
tween particular arts nor between artistic tonalities and registers. Poetry is
exemplary-but which poetry? Quite indirectly, Kant has given us an ex
ample. When he cites "the most sublime passage of the Book of the Law of
the Jews," that which articulates the prohibition of images, the sublime, in
fact, is present twice. It is present first in the content of the divine com
mandment, in the distancing of representation. But a more attentive read
ing shows that the sublime is present also, and perhaps more essentially, in
the "form" of the biblical text. F�r this passage is quoted in the middle of
. what properly constitutes the search for the genre or aesthetics of "sublime
presentation." This presentation must attempt neither to "agitate" nor to
"excite" the imagination but ought always to be concerned with the "dom
ination of reason over sensibility." And this presupposes a "withdrawn or
separated presentation" (abgezogen, abgesondert), which will b� called a bit
further on "pure, merely negative." This presentation is the command
ment, the law that commands the abstention from images.29 The com
mandment, as such, is itself a form, a presentation, a style.
And so sublime poetry would have the style of the commandment?
Rather, the commandment, the categorical imperative, is sublime because
, it commands nothing other than freedom. And if that comprises a style, it
cannot be the muscular style of the commandment. It is what Kant calls
simplicity: "Simplicity (purposiveness without art) is so to speak the sry.le
of nature in the sublime, as of morality which is a second nature."
It is not the commandment that is simple but rather simplicity that
commands. The art of which Kant speaks-or of which, at the limit, he
does not manage to speak, while speaking of the Bible, poetry, and forms
of union in the fine arts-is the art of which the "simplicity" (or the
"withdrawal" or the "separation") commands by itself, that is, addresses or
exposes to freedom, with the simplicity of the offering: the offering as law
of style.
"Purposiveness without art" (without artifice) is the art (the style) of
purposiveness without purpose, that is, of the purposiveness of humanity
in its free destination: humans are not devoted to the servility of represen
tation but destined to the freedom of presentation and to the presentation
of freedom-to their offering, which is a withdrawn or separate presenta-
242 PLEASURE
tion (freedom is offered to them, they offer it, they are offered by it) . This
style is the style of a commandment or proscription because it is the style
of a literature that proscribes for itself to be "literature," that withdraws
from literary prestige-and pleasure (which Kant compares to the massages
of the "voluptuous orientals"): the effort by means of which it withdraws is
itself a sublime offering. In short, the offering of literature itself, or the of
fering of all art-in all possible senses of the expression.
But "style" is doubtless here already one concept too many, like "po
etry," "literature," and perhaps even "art" itself They are certainly inap
propriate and superfluous here if they remain caught up in a logic of lack
and its substitute, presence and its representation (as this logic still governs,
at least in part, the Kantian doctrine of art as a "symbol"). For nothing is
lacking in the offering. Nothing is lacking, everything is" offered: the whole
is offered (opened), the totality of freedom. But to receive the offering, or
to offer oneself to it (to joy), presupposes precisely the freedom of a ges
ture-of reception and offering. This gesture traces a limit. It is not the
contour of a figure of freedo�. But it.is a contour, ail outline, because it
arises in freedom, which is the freedom to begin, to incise, here or there, an
outline, an inscription, not merely arbitrarily, but still in a chancy, daring,
playful, abandoned manner.
Abandoned but nonetheless regulated: the syncopation does not take
place independently of all syntax, but rather imposes one, or better, it is
one itself In_ its pulsation-which assembles-in its suspension-which
establishes and extends a rhythm-, the syncopation offers its syntax, its
sublime grammar, on the edge of the language (or the drawing, or the
- song). Consequently, this trace is still or again art, this inscription still or
again style, poetry: for the gesture of freedom is each time a singular man
ner of abandoning oneself (there is no such thing as general freedom, no
such thing as general sublimity). This is not style "in the accoustico-deco
rative sense of the term" (Borges), but it is also not the pure absence of
style of which the philosopher3° dreams (philosophy as such and without
offering, as opposed to . or rather differentiated from thought): it is style,
and the thought of a "withdrawn, separated presentation." It is not a
style-there is no sublime style, and there is no simple style-but consti
tutes a trace, puts the limit into play, touches without delay all extremi
ties-and it is perhaps this that art obeys.
In the final analysis, there is perhaps no sublime art and no sublime
work, but the sublime takes place wherever works touch. If they touch,
The Sublime Offering 243
there are sensible pleasure and pain-all pleasure is physical, Kant repeats
with Epicurus. There is enjoyment, and there is joy in enjoyment. The sub�
lime is not what would take its distance from enjoyment. Enjoyment is
mere enjoyment when it does nothing but please: in the beautiful. But
there is the place (or the time) where (or when) enjoyment does not merely
please, is not simply pleasure (if there is ever such a thing as simple pleas
ure): in the sublime, enjoyment touches, moves, that is, also commands. It
is not commanded (an obligation to enjoy is absurd, Kant writes, and La
can remembered this), but commands one to. pass beyond it, beyond
pathos, into ethos, if you like, but without ceasing to enjoy: touching or
emotion qua law-and the law is necessarily a-pathetic. Here, "sovereign
art," as Bataille writes, "accedes to the extremity of the possible." This art
is indissociably "art expressive of anguish" and "that expressive of joy." The
one and the othedn an enjoyment, in a dispropriated enjoyment-that is,
in tragic joy, or in this animated joy of the "vivacity of the affects" ofwhich
Kant speaks (§54) and which extends to the point oflaughter and gaiety
they too being syncopated, at the limit of (re)presentation, at the limit of
the "body" and the ('spirit," at the limit of art itself .
. . . at the limit of art: which does not mean· "beyond" art. There is
nonetheless a beyond, as art is always an art of the limit. But at the limit of
art there is the gesture of the offering: the gesture that offers art and the
gesture through which art itself reaches, touches upon, and interferes with
its limit.
As offering, it may be that the sublime surpasses the sublime-passes
it by or withdraws from it. To the extent that the sublime still combines
pathos and �thos, art and nature, it continues to designate these conc�pts,
and this is why, as such, it belongs still to a space and problematic of
(re)presentation. It is for this reason that the word "sublime" always risks
burdening art either with pathos or morality (too much presentation or too
much representation). But the offering no longer even arises out of an al
liance of pathos and ethos. It comes to pass elsewhere: offering occurs in a
simplicity anterior to the distinction between pathos and ethos. Kant
speaks of "the simplicity which does not yet know how to dissimulate"; he
calls it "naIvete," and the laughter or rather the smile in the face of this
naIvete (which one must not confuse, he insists, with the rustic simplicity
of the one who doesn't know how to live) possesses something of the sub-
244 PLEASURE
Shattered Love
Thinking: of Love
I love you more than all that has been thought and can be thought. I give my
soul to you.
-Henriette Vogel to Heinrich von Kleist
might well have nothing more to say or to describe than this communal
indigence, these dispersed and tarnished flashes of an all-too-familiar love.
This is why, at our slightest attempt to solicit the thinking oflove, we
are invited to an extreme reticence. (Should this thinking be solicited? I
will not discuss this. As it happens, it is. As it happens, indeed, this soHci
tation regularly returns, throughout our history, to formulate its demands.
One asks what has become of love, but one does not forget to return to it
after a certain period. When, for example, as is the case today, love is no
longer the dominant theme of poetry, when it seems to be essentially rele
gated to dime-store novels instead, it is then that we inquire and question
ourselves about love, about the possibility of thinking love. As though this
possjbility were always, recurringly indispensable to the possibility of
thinking in general-that is to say, to the possibility of the lif� of a com
munity, of a time and a space of humanity-something that would not be
the case for other objects, such as God, for exaniple, or history, or litera
ture, or even philosophy.)
This reticence of thinking that beckons to us does not imply that it
would be indiscreet to deflower love. Love deflowers and is itself deflow
ered by its very essence, and its unrestrained and brazen exploitation in all
the genres of speech or of art is perhaps an integral part of this essence-a
part at once secret and boisterous, miserable and sumptuous. But this ret
icence might signifY that all, of love, is possible and necessary, that all the
loves possible are in fact the possibilities of love, its voices or its character�
istics, which are impossible to confuse and yet ineluctably entangled: char
ity and pleasure, emotion and pornography, the neighbor and the infant,
the love oflovers and the love of God, fraternal love and the love of art, the .
kiss, passion, friendship . . . . To think love would thus demand a bound
less generosity toward all these possibilities, and it is this generosity that
would command reticence: the generosity not to choose between loves, not
to privilege, not to hierarchize, not to exclude. Because love is not their
substance or their common concept, is not something one can extricate
and contemplate at a distance. Love in its singularity, when it IS grasped
absolutely, is itself perhaps nothing but the indefinite abundance of all pos
sible loves, and an abandonment to their dissemination, indeed to the dis
order of these explosions. The thinking of love should learn to yield to this
abandon: to receive the prodigality, the collisions, and the contradictions
of love, without submitting them to an order that they essentially defy.
But this generous reticence would be no different from the exercise of
Shattered Love 247
to speak, ·existential rather than categorial, or again it would name the act
of thinking as much as or more than it would its nature. (The model for
this phrase is obviously the ancient "God is love," which entailed the same
formal implications.) We know nothing more about what this means. We
only know, by a sort of obscure certainty or premonition, that it is neces
sary or that it will one day be necessary to attest this phrase: Thinking is
love. · But philosophy has never explicitly attested this.
One single time, however, the first philosopher expressly authenti
cated an identity of love and of philosophy. Plato's Symposium does not
represent a particular treatise that this author set aside for love at the heart
of his wor�, as others would do later (and often by relating to this same
Plato: Ficino, among others, or Leon·the Hebrew, as though Plato were the
unique or at least necessary philosophical reference, de amore, always pres
ent, beyond the epoch of treatises, in Hegel or in Nietzsche-"philosophy
in the manner of Plato is an erotic duel"-in Freud or in Lacan). But the
Symposium signifies first that for Plato the exposition of philosophy, as
such, is not possible without the presentation of philosophic love. The
commentary on the text gives innumerable confirmations of this, from the
portrait of Eros to the role of Socrates and to the figure-who appeared
here once and for all on the philosophical scene-of Diotima.
Although the Symposium speaks of love, it also does more than that;
it opens thought to love as to its own essence. This is why this dialogue is
more than any other the dialogue of Plato's generosity: here he invites ora
tors or thinkers and offers them a speech tempered altogether differently
from the speech of the interlocutors of Socrates. The scene itself, the gaiety
or the joy that traverses it, attests to a consideration that is unique in Plato
(to such a degree, at least)-consideration for others, as well as for the ob
ject of discourse. All the different kinds of loves are welcomed in the Sym
posium; there is discussion, but there is no exclusion. And the love that is
finally exhibited as true love, philosophical Eros, does not only present it
self with the mastery of a triumphant doctrine; it also appears in a state of
deprivation and weakness, which allows the experience of the limit, where
thought takes place, to be recognized. In the Symposium, Plato broaches
the limits, and all his thinking displays a reticence or reserve not always
present elsewhere: it broaches its own limit, that is to say, its source; it ef
faces itself before the love (or in the love?) that it recognizes as its truth.
Thus it thinks its own birth and its own effacement, but it thinks in such
a way that it restores to love, to the limit, its very task and destination. Phi-
Shattered Love 249
II
its poetics, its drama, its pathos, its mystique, from the Grand Rhetoricians
to Baudelaire, from the troubadours to Wagner or Strauss, from Saint John
of the Cross to Strindberg, and moving through Racine or Kleist, Mari
vaux or Maturin, Monteverdi or Freud. For all of them, love is double,
conflictual, or ambivalent: necessary and impossible, sweet and bitter, free
and chained, spiritual and sensual, enlivening and mortal, lucid and blind,
altruistic and egoistic. For all, these' oppositional couples constitute the
very structure and life of love, while at the same time, love carries out the
resolution of these very oppositions, or surpasses them. Or more often, it
simultaneously surpasses them and maintains them: in the realization of
love, the subject of love is dead and alive, free and imprisoned, restored to
the self and outside of the self One sentence by Rene Char best epitomizes
this thinking and its entire tradition: "The poem is the fulfilled love of de
sire remaining desire."3 This sentence, in effect, does not only speak the
truth of the poem, according to Char; it speaks the truth oflove. More pre
cisely, it intends to speak the truth of the poem by grace of the truth of
love, thus confirming, moreover, that love holds the highest truth for us:
the contradiction {desire} opposed to the noncontradiction {love} and rec
onciled with it {"remaining desire"}.
But this thinking that so profoundly and so continually inriervates so
much of our thought received its name and its concept in philosophy: it is
the thinking of the dialectic. One might say that love is the living hypoth
esis of a , dialectic, which formulates the law of its process by way of a re
turn. This law is not only the formal 'rule of the resolution of a contradic
tion that remains a contradiction: it gives, under this rule, the law and the
logic of being in general. By being thought according to the dialectic and
as the essence of the dialectic, love- is assigned to the heart of the very
movement of being. And it is not surprising that these two ideas have co
existed or have even intermixed: that "God is love" and that,God is the
Supreme Being. Love is not only subject to the ontological dialectic, it does
not only form one case of its ontic application. If one may say so-and one
may, rightly, in the most accurate or proper manner-love is the heart of
this dialectic. The idea of love is in the dialectic, and the idea of the di
alectic is in love. Hegel transcribing Christian theology into the ontology
of the statement "The Absolute wishes to be close to us" says nothing
other: The Absolute loves us-and the Absolute dialectizes itself. Love is
at the heart of being.
Again it is necessary that being have a heart, or still more rigorously,
252 PLEASURE
that being be a heart. "The heart of being" means nothing but the being of
being, that by virtue of which it is being. To suppose that "the being of be
ing," or "the essence of being," is an expression endowed with meaning, it
would be necessary to suppose that the essence of being is something like
a heart-that is to say: that which alone is capable oflove. Now this is pre
cisely what has never been attested by philosophy.
Perhaps being, in its essence, is affected by the dialectic that annihi
lates its simple position in order to reveal this contradiction in the becom
ing of reality (or of reason, of the Idea, of history)-and in this sense one
might say that being beats, that it essentially is in the beating, indeed, in
the e-motion of its own heart: being-nothingness-becoming, as an infinite
pulsation. And yet, this heart of being is not a heart, and it does not beat
from the throbbing oflove. Philosophy never says this, and above all, never
explains its implications, as close as it might come to thinking it. It is not
that love is excluded from fundamental ontology; on the contrary, every
thing summons it thither, as we have just shown. Thus, one must rather
say that love is missing from the very place where it is prescribed. Or bet
ter still, love is missing from the very place where this dialectical law oper
ates-the law that we have had to recognize as the law oflove. And there
is nothing dialectical about this loss or this "lack": it is not a contradiction,
it is not made to be sublated or resorbed. Love remains absent from the
heart of being.
That love is missing from philosophical ontology does not mean that
the'dialectical law of being is inappropriate forlove. In one sense, nothing
is false in what we have just demonstrated regarding this law and the na
ture of love. Nothing is false, but love is missing, because the heart of be
ing, which has shown itself to be commanded by the dialectic, is not a
heart. That which has the power of the dialectic is not a heart, but a sub
ject. Perhaps one could find a heart in the subject. But this heart (if there
is one) designates the place where the dialectical power is suspended (or
perhaps shattered). The heart does not sublate contradictions, since in a
general sense, it does not live under the regime of contradiction-contrary
to what poetry (or perhaps only its philosophical reading?) might allow us
to believe. The heart lives-that is to say, it beats-under the regime of
exposition.
If the dialectic is the process of that which must appropriate its own
becoming in order to be, exposition, on the other hand, is the condition of
that whose essence or destination consists in being presented: given over,
Shattered Love 253
offered to the outside, to others, and even to the sel£ The two regimes do
not exclude one another (they do not form a contradiction), but they are
not ' of the same order. The being that has become through a dialectical
process is perhaps destined to be exposed (one could show that this is what
happens, despite everything, at the end of The Phenomenology ofSpirit)
but the dialectic knows nothing of this, it believes it has absorbed the en
tire destination in the becoming-proper. The exposed being is perhaps also
" the subject of a dialectical process, but what is exposed, what makes it ex
'f
posed, is that' it is not completed by this process, and it "incompletes it
self" to the outside; it is presented, offered to something that is not it nor
its proper becoming. ,
The heart exposes, and it is exposed. It loves, it is loved, it does not
love, it is not loved. Affirmation and negation are present here as in the di
alectic. But in its modes of" affirmation and negation, the heart does not
operate by reporting its own judgment to itself (if it is a judgment). It does
not say "] love," which is the reflection or the speculation of an ego (and
which engages love neither more nor less than the cogito), but it says "I love
you," a declaration where "I" is posed only by being exposed to "you."
That is to say that the heart is not a subject, even if it is the heart of a sub
ject. The subject is one who reports to himself, as his own, his judgments
and their contradiction, in order to constitute therefrom his proper being:
for example, that he is (Descartes), that he is , not his immediate being
(Spinoza), that he becomes what he is by traversing the other (Hegel). This
resembles love; in any case it calls to and even demands love-and yet this
i� not love. The subject poses its own contradiction in order to report it to
itself and to "maintain it in itself," as Hegel says. Thus it surmounts it or
infinitely sublates it. By principle, the moment of exposition is evaded,
even though it dimly emerges. This is the moment when it is not a matter
of posing or of opposing and then of resorbing the same and the other. It
is when the affirmation "I love you" is given over to that which is neither
contradictory nor noncontradictory with it: the risk that the other does not
love me, or the risk that I do not keep the promise of my love.
The being of philosophy is the subject. The heart of the subject is
again a subject: it is the infinite rapport to the sel£ That this rapport de
mands, in turn, an infinite migration through the other, even the gift of the
self, does not in any way hinder the structure of the subject from thence
deriving all its consistency. Philosophy will not fail to retort: what is at
stake is nothing but a dialectic of the heart and the subject, oflove and the
254 PLEASURE
conscience or the reason. From Pascal to Hegel and beyond, this dialectic
is well attested. But the response of philosophy is not admissible. There is
no dialectic of the heart and the reason, not because they would be irrec
oncilable (the questiofl of their rapport, ifit be a question, cannot be posed
in these terms; the perhaps pseudo-Pascal of the Discourse on the Passions of
Lovewrites, "They have inappropriately removed the name of reason from
love, and they have opposed them without a sound foundation, since love
and reason is but the same thing"), but because the heart is not able to en
ter into a dialectic: it cannot be posed, disposed, and sublated in a superior
moment. The heart does not return to itself beyond itself, and this is not,
as Hegel would have wished, "the spirit which is attendant to the power of
the heart." Or again, there is no sublimation of the heart; nor oflove. Love
is what it is, identical and plural, in all its registers or in all its explosions,
and it does not sublimate itself, even when it is "sublime." It is always the
beating of an exposed heart.
This argument carries a corollary: because it is a stranger to the di
alectic, the heart does not maintain itself in opposition to the subject, any
more than love does to reason. But they are one in the other, and one to
the other, in a manner that is neither a mode of contradiction nor of iden
tity nor of propriety. This mode might declare itself thus: The heart ex
poses the subject. It does not deny it, it does not surpass it, it is not sub
lated or sublimated in it; the heart exposes the subject to everything that is
not its dialectic and its mastery as a subject. Thus, the heart can beat at the
heart of the subject, it can even beat in a movement similar to that of the
dialectic, but it does not confuse itself with that.
This is why love is always missed by philosophy, which nevertheless
does not cease to designate and assign it. Perhaps it cannot help but be
missed: one would not know how to seize or catch up with that which ex
poses. If thinking is love, that would mean (insofar as thinking is confused
with philosophy) that thinking misses its own essence-that it misses by
essence its own essence. In philosophy (and in mysticism, in poetics, etc.)
thinking would thus have said all that it could and all that it should have
said about love-by missing it and by missing itself Loving, and loving
love, it will have lost love. It is thence that Saint Augustine's amare amabam
draws its exemplary force of confession.
This does not at all mean that in all this tradition thinking has never
occurred, or that love has never occurred, or that thinking about love has
never occurred. On the contrary. But this does mean that love itself, in that
Shattered Love 255
Love is a series of scars. "No heart is as whole as a broken heart," said the cele
brated Rabbi Nahman ofBratzlav.
-Elie Wiesel, The Fifth Son
God, by the love ofTristan, by love in the afternoon, love on the ground,
love in flight, or by the sacred love of the fatherland, the meaning remains
the same, unchangeable and infinite: it is always the furthest movement of
a completion. .
If we take love within the Occident, and the Occident in turn within
love, how then can we hope to repeat the rendezvous that seems to have
been missed once and for all, since it is the very nature of this love
unique and universal, plenary, fulfilling-that caused the rendezvous to be
missed?
If such an undertaking will always be in vain, it is nonetheless certain
that love is not to be found elsewhere. Elsewhere (if such an "elsewhere" ex
ists, but this is not the question here), one will find, by definition, only
pleasure or desire, vows, sacrifice, or ecstasy, but "love" will not be found.
We will not be able to redirect love to the edges of the Occident, if such
edges exist, in order to abandon it to voluptuous rituals, innocent games,
or heroic communions, as certain ethnological or archaeological fictions
would like to do. For there we would instantly lose what makes "love," its
unique nomination, and the intimate communication it establishes be
tween caress and devotion, between charity and nuptials (we would, in
fact, lose the very meaning of these words, of all love's words). Nothing
leads us more surely back to ourselves (to the Occident, to philosophy, to
the dialectic, to literature) than love.
That is why one would want to separate oneself from love, free one
self from it. Instead of this law of the completion of being, one would want
to deal only with a moment of contact between beings, a light, cutting,
and delicious moment of contact, at once eternal and fleeting. In its philo
sophical assignation, love seems to skirt this touch of the heart that would
not complete anything, that would go nowhere, graceful and casual, the
joy of the soul and the pleasure of the skin, simple luminous flashes oflove
freed from itself That is Don Juan's wish, it is his fervor, it is even his suc
cess: but we can think Don Juan only condemned, unless we represent his
impunity as a diabolical or perverse challenge to the very law oflove. Thus
there is no innocent or joyous Don Juan. Mozart's, it is true, continues up
until the end merrily thwarting the condemnation. And, yet, perhaps in
spite of himself, Mozart let him be condemned. But even in hell, the fig
ure of Don Juan testifies with remarkable force and insistence that this
style of love as heart's touch obstinately haunts the thinking of love as law
of fulfilIment.
Shattered Love 257
11
The ownership condemned with such rigor by the mystics, and often called im
purity, is only the search for one's own solace and one's own interest in the jouis
sance of the gifts of God, at the expense of the jealousy of the pure love that wants
everything for God and nothing for the creature. The angel's sin was a sin of own
ership; stetit in se, as Saint Augustine says. Ownership, of course, is nothing but
self-love or pride, which is the love of one's own excellence insofar as it is one's
own, and which, instead of coming back completely and uniquely to God, still to
a small extent brings the gifts of God back to the self so that it can take pleasure
in them.
love oneself with a real love, and it might even be that one must do so
(however, it is not certain that these words, "the self," "oneself," can let us
discover, with{JUt being themselves put into play, precisely who is at issue
in this love of "self": that is a question that we will have to take up again
later). But self-love, und�rstood according to the signification the spiritual
authors gave to it, and not as a term in psychology almost synonymous I
with sensitivity, is the love (which, from this moment on, is no longer one)
of possession. It is the love of the self as property.
Property is an ontological determination. It does not designate the
object possessed, but the subject in the object. "Matter, for itself, is not
proper to itself" (Hegel), it can therefore become my possession. But in
this possession, it is I myself, as subject, who find mys�lf realized, it is my
subjectivity ( me as will, need, desire, consciousness-of me) , and in this
respect possession properly becomes property� Which is to say that prop
erty is the objectivized presence of subjectivity, its realization in the outside
world, and thus "the first existence of freedom" (Hegel). Property is the at
testat�on and the assurance of the self in the actuality of the world. The self
presents itself there outside itself, but in this presentation it is itself that it
posits. Self-love is the desire and the affirmation of this autoposition: out
side itself, in objectivity and in exteriority, the subject has the moment of
its authenticity and the truth of its fulfillment.
Thus self-love indeed has the structure of love: here also, it is a mat
ter of "having in another the moment of one's subsistence." In one sense,
the formulas of love and of property respond to each other infinitely in the
philosophical economy, each one giving to the other its stability or its
movement.
Iflove is the gift of the self, it would thus also be, dialectically, the ap
propriation ofthe self. Self-love would therefore be at the heart of love, it
would be its ' heart" the heart of love, and this implacably reconstituted
economy-the dialectical economy of fulfillment, the capitalist economy
of an absolute surplus value of the self-would proscribe love from the
heart oflove itself. The tradition knows well this absence oflove from love
itself. La Rochefoucauld, in this respect, sums it all up, or there is Nietz
sche's formula "a refined parasitism," and so on until Levinas, for example,
who writes, "To love is also to love oneself within love and thus to return
to the self." Actually, the problem has been posed since the Aristotelian dis
cussion of philautia, of the love of oneself, and it has traversed and trou
bled all Christian thought since Saint Augustine. (The question that dom-
260 PLEASURE
inated all the debates of the Middle Ages about love was the question of
knowing "if man, by nature, is capable ofloving God more than himsel£")
One coulcl' eyen explain by way of this absence the missed. rendezvous be
tween philosophy and love: if the latter always frustrates love or diverts it
to self-love, if love finally lies to itself and lacks itself, how could one fail to
forever lack it? And how could one not substitute for it sometimes its dis
membered parts (the sexual organ, sentiment . . . ) , sometimes its subli
mations (friendship, charity . . . )?
III
But this knowledge is too slight. Love frustrates the simple opposi
tion between economy and noneconomy. Love is precisely-when it is,
when it is the act of a singular being, of a body, of a heart, of a thinking
that which brings an end" to ,the dichotomy between the love in which I
lose myself without reserve and the love in which I recuperate myself, to
the opposition between gift and property.
Of course, philosophy and theology have always surmounted and di
alecticized this opposition: God's love for himself in his son brings itself
abour as a love for man on the part of this same Son, given, abandoned,
and retaken in glory, with all of creation redeemed and brought into rela
tion, through the love thus received, with its creator. But the separation is
thus surmounted only because it is annulled in its principle: God gives
only what he possesses infinitely (in a sense, he thus gives nothing), and re
ciprocally, he possesses only what he gives. (He is the proprietor par excel
lence; he appears to himself in the totality of objectivity-and that is what
the idea of the "creation," in this respect, signifies. And if our time still had
to be one of such a research, it is in an entirely different direction that we
would have to look for the mystery of the "god of love.")
Love brings an end to the opposition between gift and property with
out surmounting and without sublating it: if! return to myself within love,
I do not return to myselfJrom love (the dialectic, on the contrary, feeds on
the equivocation) . ! do not return ftom it, and consequently, something of
I is definitively lost or dissociated in its act of loving. That is undoubtedly
why I return (at least if the image of a return is appropriate here), but I re
turn broken: I come back to myself, or I come out of it, broken. The "re
turn" does not annul the break; it neither repairs it nor sublates it, for the
return in fact takes place only across the break itself, keeping it open. Love
Shattered Love 261
the subject's identity that operates this movement or this touch. But in the
other it is this movement that makes it other and which is always other
than. "itself" in its identity; that is what transcends "in me." This tran
scendence thus fulfills nothing: it cuts, it breaks, and it exposes so that
there is no domain or instance of being where love would fulfill itsel£
This does not mean that this transcendence accomplishes only what
we would call-for example, in the theory of the sublime-a "negative
presentation." (Love, certainly, has the most intimate relations with the
sublime and with this extreme mode of presentation that I have attempted
to de�ignate elsewhere as the "sublime offering" (see Chapter II); but with
the offering, it is already a question ofwhat, in fact, exceeds the sublime it
self, and within love it is perhaps a' questlon, in the final analysis, of that
which exceeds love.) When the transcendence that touches me presents the
unfulfillment of love (which becomes neither substance nor subject), it at
the same time offers its actual advent: love takes place, it happens, and it
happens endlessly in the withdrawal of its own presentation. It is an offer
ing, which is to say that love is always proposed, addressed, suspended in
its arrival, and not presented, imposed, already having reached its end.
Love arrives, it comes, or else it is not love. But it is thus that it endlessly
goes elsewhere than to "me" who would receive it: its coming is only a de
parture for the other, its departure only the coming of the other.
What is offered by transcendence, or as transcendence, is this arrival
and this departute, this incessant coming-and-going. What is offered is the
offered being itself: exposed to arrival and to departure, the singular being
is traversed by the alterity of the other, which does not stop or fix itself any
where, neither in "him," nor in "me," because it is nothing other than the
coming-and-going. The other comes and cuts across me, because it imme
diately leaves for the other: it does not return to itself, because it leaves
only in order to come again. This crossing breaks the heart: this is not nec
essarily bloody or tragic, it is beyond an opposition between the tragic and
serenity or gaiety. The break is nothing more than a touch, but the touch
is not less deep than a wound.
Transcendence will thus be better named the crossing of love. What
love cuts across, and what it reveals by its crossing, is what is exposed to the
crossing, to its coming-and-going-and this is nothing other than fini
tude. Because the singular being is finite, the other cuts across it (and never
does the other "penetrate" the singular being or "unite itself" with it or
"commune"). Love unveils finitude. · Finitude is the being of that which is
:...
Shattered Love 263
In one sense-and in a sense that will perhaps always conceal the to
tality of sense, assignable as such-love is the impossible, and it does not ar
rive, or it arrives only at the limit, while crossing. It is also for this reason
that it is missed by philosophy and no less by poetry. They do not miss
love simply because they say it and because they say that it is fulfilled,
whether by a divine force or in the splendor ofwords. It is true that in say
ing "I love you," I suspend all recourse to gods as much as I put myself
back in their power, and that I unseat the power of words as much as I af
firm that power at its peak. But philosophy and poetry still feed themselves
on these contradictions. But there is more, for in one sense, nothing hap
pens with "I love you," neither power nor effacement. "I love you" is not a
performative (neither is it a descriptive nor a prescriptive statement). This
sentence names nothing and does nothing. {"Though spoken billions of
times, I-love-you is extralexicographical; it is a figure whose definition can
not transcend the heading.")4 It is the very sentence of indigence, immedi
ately destined to its own lie, or to its own ignorance, and immediately
abandoned to the harassment of a reality that will never authenticate it
without reserve. In one sense, love does not arrive, and, on the contrary, it
Shattered Love 265
always arrives, so that in one way or another "the love boat has crashed.
against the e�eryday" (Mayakovsky).
But "I love you" (which is the unique utterance oflove and which is,
at bottom, its name: love's name is not "love," which would be a substance
or a faculty, but it is this sentence, the "I love you," just as one says "the
cogito")-the "I love you" is something else. It is a promise. The promise,
by constitution, is an utterance that draws itself back before the law that it
lets appear. The promise neither describes nor prescribes nor performs. It
does nothing and thus is always vain. But it lets a law appear, the law of the
given word: that this m!1st be. "I love you" says nothing (except a limit of
speech), but it allows to emerge the fact that love must arrive and that
nothing, absolutely nothing, can relax, divert, or suspend the rigor of this
law. The promise does not anticipate or assure the future: it is possible that
one day I will no longer love you, and this possibility cannot be talcen away
from love-it belongs to it. It is against this possibility, but also with it,
that the. promise is made, the word given. Love is its own promised eter
nity, its own eternity unveiled as law.
Of course, the promise must be kept. But ifit is not, that does not
mean .that there was no love, nor even that there was not love. Love is faith
ful only to itself The promise must be kept, and nonetheless love is not the
promise plus the keeping of the promise. It cannot be subjected in this way
to verification, to justification, and to accumulation (even if there are, in
disputably, illusory or deceitful loves, loves without faith and law, that are
no longer of love-but these are counterfeits, and even Don Juan is not
one of them). Love is the pr�mise and its keeping, the one independent
1
of
the other. How could it be otherwise, since one never knows what must be
kept? Perhaps unlike all other promises, one must keep only the promise it
self: not its "contents" ("love"), but its utterance ("I love you"). That is why
love's ultimate paradox, untenable and nonetheless inevitable, is that its
law lets itself be represented simultaneously by figures like Tristan and
Isolde, Don Juan, or Baucis and Philemon-and that these figures are nei
ther the types of a genre nor the metaphors of a unique reality, but rather
so many bursts of love, which reflect love in its entirety each time without
ever imprisoning it or holding it back.
When the promise is kept, it is not the keeping, but it is. still the
promise that makes love. Love does not fulfill itself, it always arrives in the
promise and �s the promise. It is thus that it touches and that it traverses.
For one does not know what one says when one says "I love you," and one
does not say anything, but one knows that one says it and that it is law, ab-
266 PLEASURE
solutely: instantly, one is shared and traversed by that which does not fix it
self in any subject or in any signification. (If one more proof or account
were necessary: the same holds true when one hears "I love you" said by an
other whom one does not love and whose expectations will not be met.
Despite everything, it cannot be that one is not traversed by something
that, while not love itself, is nonetheless the way in which its promise
touches us.)
II
. Love arrives then in the promise. In one sense (in another sense, al
ways other, always at the limit of sense), it always arrives, as soon as it is
promised, in words or in gestures. Tha,t is why, if we are exhausted or ex
asperated by the proliferating and contradictory multiplicity of representa
tions and thoughts oflove-which compose in effect the enclosure and the
extenuation of a history oflove-this same multiplicity still offers, how
ever, another thought: love arrives in all the forms and in all the figures of
love; it is projected in all its shatters.
There are no parts, moments, types, or stages of love. There is only
an infinity of shatters: love is wholly complete in. one sole embrace or in
the history of a life, in jealous passion or in tireless devotion. It consists as
much in taking as in giving, as much in requiring as in renouncing, as
much in protecting as in exposing. It is in the jolt and in appeasement, in
the fever and in serenity, in the exception and in the rule. It is sexual, and
it is not: it cuts across the sexes with another difference (Derrida, in
Geschlecht, initiated the analysis of this) that does not abolish them, but
displaces their identities. Whatever my love is, it cuts across my identity,
my sexual property, that objectification by which I am a masculine or fem
inine subject. It is Uranian Aphrodite and Pandemian Aphrodite; it is Eros,
Cupid, Isis and Osiris, Diane and Acteon, Ariadne and Dionysus; it is the
princesse de Cleves or the enfant de Boheme; it is Death enlaced around a
naked woman; it is the letters of Hyperion, of Kierkegaard, or of Kafka.
(It is perhaps that-a hypothesis that I leave open here-in love and
in hate, but according to a regime other than that of Freudian ambiva
lence, there would not be a reversal from hate to love, but in hate I would
be traversed by the love of another whom I deny in his alterity. Ultimately,
I would be traversed by this negation. This would be the limit oflove, but
still its black glimmer. Perverse acts of violence, or the cold rage to annihi
late, are not hate.)
Shattered Love 267
From one burst to another, never does love resemble. itsel£ It always
makes itself recognized, but it is always unrecognizable, and moreover it is
not in any one ofits shatters, or it is always on the way to not being there.
Its unity, or its truth as love, consists only in this proliferation, in this in
definite luxuriance of its essence-and this essence itself at once gives it
self and Hees itself in the crossing of th�s profusion. Pure love refuses or
gasm, the seducer laughs at adoration-blind to the fact that they each
pass through the other, even though neither stops · in the other. Plato had
encountered the nature ofEros; son ofPoros and ofPenia, of resources and
indigence, love multiplies itself to infinity, offering nothing other than its
poverty of substance and of property.
But love is not "polymorphous," and it does not take on a series of
disguises. It does not withhold its identity behind its shatters: it is itself the
eruption of their multiplicity, it is itself their multiplication in one single
act oflove, it is the trembling of emotion in a brothel, and the distress of a
desire within fraternity. Love does not simply cut across, it cuts itselfacross
itself, it arrives and arrives at itself as that by which nothing arrives, except
that there is "arriving," arrival and departure: of the other, always of the
other, so . much other that it is never made, or done (one makes love, be
cause it is never made) and so much other that it is never my love (if I say
to the other "my love," it is of the other, precisely, that I speak, and noth
ing is "mine").
There is no maSter figure, there is no major representation of love,
nor is there any common assumption of its scattered and inextricable shat
ters. That is why "love" is saturated, exhausted with philosophy and poetry
(and 't:hreatened with falling into sexology, marriage counseli'ng, newsstand
novels, and moral edification all at once, as soon as it no longer supports -its
major figures, sealed in the destiny of occidental love), if we miss what love
itself misses: that it comes across and never simply comes to its place or to
term, that it comes across itself and overtakes itself, being the finite touch
of the infinite crossing of the other.
Ill-
however, indicate what its principle would be. As a citation above recalled,
love remains equivocal for Levinas, reducing itself to egotism. Its transcen
dence lifts· the equivocation only by transcending itself intq fecundity, fili
ation, and fraternity. If!, for my pan, do not thematize such notions here,
it is because another work would be necessary to attempt to extract them
from the oriented sequence that, in Levinas, in a rather classical manner,
hierarchizes them and prescribes them to a teleology. This teleology pro
ceeds from the first given of his thought, "the epiphany of the face": love is
the movement stressed by this epiphany, a mm;ement that transcends it in
order to reach, beyond the face, beyond vision and the "you," the "hid
den-never hidden enough-absolutely ungraspable."5 From this "vertigo
that no signification any longer clarifies" (that of the Eros), the fraternity
of children, lifting its equivocation, can emerge, the fraternity of children
in which, again, the epiphany of the face is produced. Love thus retains at
least certain traits of a dialectical moment. It retains them, it seems to me,
due to the motif of the face. The latter signifies the primordial relation as
the expression of another and as signification. Because this signification is
given at the beginning, it must disappear within love and be recaptured in
its surpassing. I can, on the contrary, grasp the relation with the face only
as second and as constituted. Levinas opposes it, and pre-poses it, "to the
unveiling of Being in general," a Heideggerian theme in which he sees "the
absolute indetermination of the there is--of an existing without exis
tents-incessant negation, infinite limitation," "anarchic." I can be in sol
idarity with Levinas's distaste for certain accents, shall we say, of dereliction
in Heidegger's discourse. But in the es gibt ("it gives [itselfl") of Being, one
can see everything except "generality." There is the "each time," an-archic
in fact (or even archi-archic, as Derrida might say?), of an existing, singu
lar occurrence. There is no existing without existents, and there is no "exist
ing" by itself, no concept-it does not give itself-but there is always be
ing, precise and hard, the theft of the generality. Being is at stake there, it
is in shatters, offered dazzling, multiplied, shrill and singular, hard and cut
across: its being is there. Being-with is . constitutive of this stake-and that
is what Levinas, before anyone, understood. But being-with takes place
only according to the occurrence of being, or its posing into shatters. And
the crossing-the coming-and-going, the comings-and-goings oflove-is
constitutive of the occurrence. This takes place before the face and signifi
cation. Or rather, this takes place on another level: at the heart of being.)
Shattered Love 271
N
.
We are exposed by concern-not that which "we" "hold" for the
other, but by this concern, this solicitude, this consideration, and this re
nunciation fonhe other that cuts across us and does not come back to us,
that comes and goes incessantly, as the being-other of the other inscribed
in being itself: at the heart of being, or as the promise of being.
This concern exposes us to joying.6 To joy .is no more impossible, as
Lacan wanted it, than possible, as the sexologist would want it. To joy is
not an eventuality that one might expect, that one might exclude, or that
one might provoke. To joy is not a fuifillment, and it is not even an event.
Nonetheless, it happens, it arrives-and it arrives as it departs, it arrives in
departing and it departs in the arrival, in the same beat of the heart. To joy
is the crossing of the other. The other cuts across me, I cut across it. Each
one is the other for the other-but also for the sel£ In this sense, one joys
in the other for the self: to be passed to the other. This is the syncope of
identity in singularity. A syncope: the step marked, in a suspense, from the
other to me, neither confusion nor fading, clarity itself, the beating of the
heart, the cadence and the cut of another heart within it.
Everything has been said ofjoying, as oflove, but this word resists. It
is the verb of love, and this verb speaks the act of joy (the joi of courtly
love). Something resists, through these two words (that are only one), the
overwhelming exhaustiveness of discourses on love. It is not so much a re-
. suit, or "discharge," as Freud says and as it is said vulgarly, as an acute in
sistence, the very formation of a shatter (one might say, like Deleuze, "a
hardening that is one with love"). It is not something unspeakable; because
it ·is spoken, the joy is named, but it is something with which discourses
(narratives and poems) can never be even. They have never said it enough,
having always discoursed it too much, declared it too much.
Joy is the trembling of a deliverance beyond all freedom: it is to be
cut across, undone, it is to be joyed as much as to joy: "Love is joy accom
panied by the idea of an exterior cause," writes Spinoza, and he specifies
that with this joy it is not a matter of desire, for "this definition explains
with enough clarity the essence of love. Regarding that of the authors who
define love as the will ofhe who loves to join himselfto the loved object, it
does not express the essence oflove, but its property." But we have to push
"the idea of an exterior cause" to this: to be joyed-to face the extremity of
being, which is to say at once its completion and its limit, beyond desire or
272 PLEASURE
short of it. This is joy, and this also reflects on the essence of chagrin and
of pain. For joy is not appeasement, but a serenity without rest. To joy is
not to be satisfied-it is to be filled, overflowed. It is to be cut across with
out even being able to hold onto what "to joy" makes happen. To joy can
not contain itself Joy is not even to contain joy itself, nor the pain that con
sequently accompanies it. The joy ofjoying does not come back to anyone,
neither to me nor to you, for in each it opens the other. In the one and the
other, and in the one by the other, joy offers being itself, it makes being
felt, shared. Joy knows concern, and is known by it. Joy makes felt, andit
lets go the very essence of the sharing that is being. (Although it mearis di
verting the sentence from its proper context, I will cite Michel Henry: "Far
from coming after the arrival of being and marveling before it, joy is con
substantial with it, founds it and constitutes it.")
This puts one beside oneself, this irritates and exasperates, and the
language for saying it is exasperated. (It would be better to let another
speak, and in a language that would remain, somewhat, on the side:7
Laura the basilisk made entirely of asbestos, walking to the fiery stake with a
mouth full of gum. Hunkydory is the word on her lips. The heavy fluted lips on
the sea shell, Laura's lips, the lips of lost Uranian love. All floating shadowward
through the slanting fog. Last murmuring dregs of shell-like lips slipping off the
Labrador coast, oozing eastward with the mud tides, easirig starward in the iodine
drift. . . . I kept it up like a Juggernaut. Moloch fucking a piece of bombazine.
Organza Friganza. The bolero in straight jabs. . . . We embraced one another
silently and then we slid into a long fuck. [Henry Miller])
But this is shared too much within the other. It is not that identity,
in joying, simply loses itself It is there at its peak. There is in fact too
much ideqtity-and joying opens the enigma of that which, in the syn
cope of the subject, in the crossing of the other, affirms an absolute self To
joy poses without reserve the question of the singular being, which we are
no doubt barely on the way to broaching. It is the question ofthat which
remains "self" when nothing returns to the self. the very question of love, if
love is always proffered ( I love you") and if joy, coming from the other,
"
presence that cuts across is a burst. To joy, joy itself, is to receive the burst
of a singular being: its more than manifest presence, its seeming beyond all
appearance-ekphanestaton, Plato said. But it is by onese/falsp that he, she
who joys is bedazzled. It is in himself thus that he is delighted. But he does
not belong to himself, and 4e does not come back to himself: he is shared,
like the joy he shares.
What appears in this light, at once excessive and impeccable, what is
offered like a belly, like a kissed mouth, is the singular being insofar as it is
this "self" that is neither a subject nor an individual nor a communal be
ing, but thatr-she or he-which cuts across, that which arrives and de
parts. The singular being affirms even better its absolute singularity, which
it offers only in passing, which it brings about immediately in the crossing.
What is offered through the singular being-'-through you or me, across
this relation that is only cut across-is the singularity of being, which is to
say 'this: that being itself, "being" taken absolutely, is absolutely singular
(thus it would be that which remains "self" when nothing comes back to
the self) .
This constitution is buried at the heart of being, but it emerges in
outbursts of joy. One could say: being joys. One would thus define an on
tological necessity of love. But love is neither unique nor necessary. It
comes, it is offered; it is not established as a structure of being or as its
principle, and even less as its subjectivity. One would thus define a neces
sity without a law, or a law without nGcessity, thus: the heart of being
within love, and love in surplus of being. One could say, at the limit, the
fundamental ontology and the caprices oflove. The correlation would nei
ther be causal nor expressive nor essential nor existential nor of any other
known genre. Perhaps it would no longer be necessary to speak of correla:"
tion. But there is this brilliant, shattering constitution of being. "Love"
does not define it, but it names it, and obliges us to think it.
Postscriptum
-You wrote: "It might well be appropriate that a discourse on love
be at the same time a communication of love, a letter, a missive, since love
sends itself as much as it enunciates itsel£" But you didn't send this text to
anyone. And you know very well that that doesn't mean. that you sent it to
everyone. One can't love everyone.
-,-But a letter, a missive, once published, is no longer a missive. It is a
274 PLEASURE
I was asked to write something "in praise of mixture." What I'd like
to do is to write praise that is itself "mixed." Not in the literal sense ofwrit
ing something that is partly praise and partly blame, only to end up with a
null account ofloss and gain, nor in the sense of singing faint praise, evok
ing, an odd concept, a sort of extreme lukewarmth. Instead, it is a matter
(as everyone knows; it's there for all to see, if only we knew how to look for
it and to accept what is at stake), against wind and tide-and we know
how many of those there can be-simply a matter, of conceding nothing,
neither concerning identity nor concerning what mixes with it or mixes it
up flns et origo. What we need, then, is praise mixed with reserve, with the
reserve used when we do not want-that's the last thing we want!-our
praise to betray its object by having identified it all too well.
In truth, the most fitting and most beautiful praise of mixture
would be not to have to praise it, since it's scarcely possible to discern or
identify this notion. It presupposes isolated pure substances and then the
operation of their mixture. It's a notion th�t belongs in the laboratory. But
would it ever occur to a painter to praise the blending of colors? He or she
In Praise ofthe Melee 279
has nothing to do with the specter of pure colors; the painter has no
choice but to concern him- or herself with the infinite derivation and
melee of their nuances.
Now, because it was always possible that someone was going to coin
the detestable slogan "ethnic cleansing," this demands some sort of re
sponse. Not a response in the form of a symmetrical counter-slogan, how
ever. This is why I'm seeking, above all, to avoid conferring too much iden
tity on mixture itself. To make sure of this, we're going to need to shift
accent and genre; we're going to need to move from mixture to. melee.
Let's be clear on this from the start: the simplistic praise of mixture
may well have lead to mistakes, but the simplistic praise of purity has up
held and upholds crimes. In'this respect, we don't need to sustain any sense
of symmetry, of equilibrium. There's no happy medium here. There's noth
ing to discuss. ' Even the most meager discussion, the least second thought
about any racism or about. any "purification" whatsoever, already partici
pates in the crime. Moreover, the crime here is always double, both moral
and intellectual. Every racism is stupid, obtuse, fearful. (I always feel a cer
tain reticence when faced with long discourses and big colloquia on the
subject of racism: it seems to me that we bestow too much honor on this
trash. And this is why I am bothered by the idea of a "praise of mixture": it
is as if mixture as such were a "value" or an "�uthenticity" yet to be re
vealed, whereas it is, in fact, obvious or, rather, on closer inspection, proves'
not even to exist-if it is indeed the case that there has never been any
thing "pure" that one could or should "mix" with some other "purity.")
We're not talking about maintaining some happy medium between
these opposed theses. These theses only exist insofar as there is some sim
plification and denaturation of what's at stake.
' I'
are both always already past or both always . stiIl to come. And they are
common, shared by everyone, between everyone, as much as they are
shared by one another.
I
I
Precisely because mixture is put into the mix (mixed up in the
melee); it isn't a substance. Nor can we replace the nonsubstantiality of its
content with the supposed consistency of the container: such · is the diffi
I
,
culty with ideologies of the melting pot, which suppose the "pot" to con
tain, in every sense of the word, with all 'the virtues of its own identity, the
I hybrid [metis] that each of us in one way or another is-is someone, this
isn't due to an essence of hybridization (a contradictory notion), but is so
1- insofar as the hybrid gives a punctuation, a singular configuration, to the
without-essence of hybridization. To essentialize mixtute is already to have
I dissolved it, to have melted it into something other than itsel£ Hence, We
shouldn't claim to be speaking about mixture as such, least of all in order
to be hymning its praise.
Mixture, as such, can take two forms: that of a fusion, an accom
plished osmosis, or that of an achieved disorder. Alchemy or entropy, two
phantasmatic extremities-:-which can only join up or be identified with
one another in an apocalypse or a black hole. And yet mixture is neither
the one nor the other; nor is it a · happy medium between the two. It is
something other, or, rather, it "is'" otherwise, totally otherwise.
\
282 WORLD
, ;.
in on itself, turn toward the outside with a passionate curiosity. It is the era of voy
ages, of the exchange of gifts, of diplomatic correspondences, and of princesses
sent to be spouses to foreign kings as a token of these new "international" rela�
tions. The era when all the peoples of the Near East and the Agaean-Cretans,
Mycenaeans, Palestinians, Nubians, Canannites-begin to show up in their na
tive costumes on the frescos in Egyptian tombs.3
It's nor that there's no "identity." A culture is single and unique (al
ways assuming that we're still happy with the word "culture," which seems
to have identified in advance what is at stake in it. And yet this word iden
tifies precisely nothing. It is a way of short-circuiting all the difficulties that
crowd in when we try to say "people," "nation," "civili�ation," "spirit,"
"person ty, etc. . . .
all " ) A "culture" denotes a certaIn "umty, " a "one. " And we
cannot neglect the fact and the principle of this "one," still less deny it, in
the name of an essentialization of "mixture."
And yet, to the extent that this "one" is clearly distinct and thus dis
tinguished, it is still not its own pure and proper foundation. Avoiding
confusion between distinction and foundation is undoubtedly the whole
problem; it is this confusion and this distinction that are, philosophically,
ethically, and politically at stake in the discourse that surrounds "identity"
'
or "subjects" of all types. As such, the absolute distinction of Descartes's' ego
existo ought not to be confused with the foundation that Descartes links to
it, in the purity of a res cogitans, In the same way, for eXample, "French"
identity doesn't need to found itself in Vercingetorix or Joan of Arc in or
der to exist . . .
The unity and unicity of a culture are one and the same by way of a
mixture or of a melee. It is a melee that, within any given "culture," brings'
out a style or a tone; equally, however, it brings out ·the various voices or
vocal ranges that are needed in order for this tone t() be interpreted. There
is a French culture. But this culture has many voices and is nowhere pres
ent "in person," as it were-except for those who confuse it with the Gal
lic cock, or with Dupont-la-Joie. The voice ofVoltaire isn't the same as thilt
�\ .
284 WORLD
of Proust, nor is Proust's voice the same as that of Pasteur, Pasteur's not the
same Rita Mitsouko's. Equally, it's perhaps not as though such voices are
ever purely and simply French: what is and is not French in Stendhal, in
Hugo, in Picasso, in Levinas, in Godard, in Johnny Hallyday, in
Kat'Onoma, in Chainoiseau, in Dib? Again, this doesn't mean that there's
no "French identity" : it means that an identity of this type is never simply
identical in the way that a pencil is identically the same today as it was yes
terday (supposing, at least, that this example isn't always going to be mate
rially imprecise . . . ). The identity of the pencil leaves this precise pencil
much less identifiable as "this one here" (which is, up to a certain point,
any pencil whatsoever) than the identity of a culture leaves that particular
culture, or the identity of a person leaves that particular person. In order to
illustrate the difference, we might term the second identity an ipseity, a
"being-self-same."
An ipseity is not the pure inertia of the same remaining entirely the
same set at no distance from itself that's how we imagine the being of a
stone or of God . . . An ipseity can be identified or makes its identity
known. In order for that to occur, there needs to be a network of ex
changes, recognitions, relays from one ipseity to another, from difference
to difference. An ipseity takes on matter through and for the other, 'pro
vided that there is an other or that there are others from which, with its
singular touch, it takes and to which it gives a certain identifiable tone
that is, a tone which is unidentifiable, inimitable, unattributable to an
identity. "Ipseity" would name what precisely it is about an identity that it
is always and necessarily impossible to identify.
As a matter of fact, a pure identity would not only be inert, empty,
colorless, and flavorless (words which describe many of those who uphold
pure identities): it would be an absurdity. A pure identity annuls itself,
cannot identify itself It is solely identical to an itself that is identical to it
self, and that thus goes around in a circle and never attains existence.
Was there, for example, anyone pure enough to be worthy of the
name '�an"? We know how this question could lead a real Nazi, a Nazi
who identified absolutely with his cause or with his thing, to sterilization
or even to suicide.
'purity is a crystalline abyss in which the identical, the proper, or the
authentic collapses into itself, null, taking the other with itself so as to con
vert it into the abyss. The absolute and vertigin.ous law of the proper is that
In Praise ofthe Melee 285
it purely and simply alienates itself in appropriating its own purity. Another
form of mixture: mixing-in-itself; auto-mixture, autism, autoeroticism.
Mixture as s,uch does not exist, any more than purity as such. There
is neither pure mixture nor intact purity. Not only is there no such thing,
but this lack is itself the law of the "there is": there would be nothing if
there was anything pure and intact. Nothing "pure" exists that does not
touch otherness, not because we can't help rubbing shoulders with others,
as if this were simply an accidental condition, but because only touch ex
poses us to these limits on which identities or ipseities can sort things out
[se deme/er] between themselves or can extricate themselves from one an
other, from the midst of all the others. There is neither the simply mixed
nor the simply identical; what there is is the always-incessant mix-up of
one with the other.
The melee ' is not accidental; it's originary. It is not contingent; it's
necessary. It is not; it always happens.
Melee ofAres and melee of Aphrodite, melee of these melees: blows
and embraces, assaults and truces, rivalry and desire, supplication and de
fiance, dialogue and dispute, fear arid pity, and laughter as well. And melee
of Hermes, melee of messages and conduits, bifurcations, substitutions,
competition between codes, configurations of spaces, borders made to
cross, so that crossing becomes sharing, because there's identity only when
shared, divided, mixed, distinguished, cut off, common, substitutable, un
substitutable, withdrawn, exposed.
Why is the "passport photo," the photo most oriented toward iden
tity, the most colorless of all photos? Why is it always the worst likeness?
Equally, why are ten passport photos ofthe same person always so differ
ent from one another? When does somepne resemble him- or herself?
When the photos show what it is about him or her that is more than iden
tifiable, more than the "face," the "image," the "traits," or the "portrait" in
sofar as they are functions of the diacritical marks of an "identity" ("black
hair, blue eyes, pug-nosed, etc."), and when these give rise to an inter
minable melee, peoples, parents, kinds of work, pains, pleasures, refusals,
oblivions, wrong paths, expectations, dreams, stories, and all that shakes
and rattles at the gates of the image. Nothing imaginary, nothing but the
real: the real is the real of the melee. A true passport photo, a true "photo
of identity," would be an indefinite melee of pho�os and graphics that
would resemble nothing and beneath which the proper name would be in
scribed as a caption.
288 WORLD
Responding to Existence
For what are we responsible? For the possible effects of the space
probe that passes outside the solar system; for the fragile constitution of
Bosnia-Herzegovina; for the juridical problems posed by the Internet; for
the transformation of the objects of African rituals into art curios; for the
spread of AIDS; for the return of scurvy; for the invention of marine agri
culture; for television programs; for public supp.ort of poetry; for poetry
with or without support; for the memory and the explanation of all geno
cides; for the history of the West, now spread to the entire world, at least
in Deleuze's sense when he says that "we are not responsible for the victims
but responsible before them."! Ultimately, .we are responsible for every
thing that could possibly be said to concern action or morals, nature or his
tory; we are responsible�so we tell ourselves, and so, in any case, thinkers
and writers tell us-for being, for God, for the law, for death, for birth, for
our own existence, for beings as a whole. But which we? We, each one of
us, insofar as we know where the individual begins and ends (and it is
surely from the standpoint of responsibility that things are least deter
minable); but also we, all of us, insofar as we know what it is to be-together
(and here again responsibility makes choice into a problem). Knowing this,
and the problems or aporias that follow from it, is our �esponsibility. As for
knowing or thinking what is meant by a responsibility limited by nothing
in space or time, limited neither by imputing subjects nor by fields of ap
plication, this is, again and above all, our responsibility, a responsibility,
moreover, that faces no one but ourselves.
290 WORLD
I and even labile means. Ifwe were able to distinguish between essences, we
\,
·I ·
I might say that, in a world of guilt, relation to the law is fixed and given,
whereas in a world of responsibility, the subject's engagement precedes and
r exceeds the law. '(Between them, we might situate· the Christian world of
I sin; in which it is the sinner who is first accused rather than the crime it
I self.) This is also why the exercise of responsibility can be rewarded and
I honored as well as punished according to its outcome; in the same way, I
I can make myself responsible for something for which no other authority
I can charge me.
nor revelation, for what is not available, for what does not even have con
cept or signification.
In this way, Nietszsche's phrases punctuate what must surely be seen
as one of the most powerful traditions of modern philosophy, if not its tra
dition par excellence or its first virtue: it places at the apex or end of
thought the act of commitment to an unconditional demand, a demand
that doesn't come to it from outside itself or from outside thinking thought
as the thinking of humanity in the double sense of the genitive. In fact, this
was already present in the sense that Kant gave to the notion of freedom
and, with it, to a responsibility in which the subject-the "intelligible per
son"-is confronted in itselfas if by a "holy .being" and sees "all our duties"
as divine commands.6 These very duties, however, are properly without
end; they are the duty to treat humanity-defined not by any given ra
tionality or any nature but as the being of ends alone-as an end in itSel£
Kant's conception of humanity, to which we are all heirs, lies in being re
sponsible for oneself as an infinite end.
Were there more space we could show how this thought is deployed
and modulated in Hegel (for whom Reason is nothing given and consists
only in engaging and deciding for itself), in Schopenhauer, in Kierkegaard,
in Marx, in Husserl (who, in his marginal notes to Being and Time, ad
dresses the possibility of what he calls the philosophy of "absolute respon
sibility" ),? in Bruno Bauch or NicolaI Hartmann, in Heidegge� (for whom
ontological being-in-debt is founded upon the antic model of responsibil
ity).8 (Allow me to break of(at this point in order to point out that there
would be plenty to say about the importance of the general and generalized
thinking about responsibility that took place in the twenties and thirties, ··
just after the Great War, and about the way in which this thinking engages
in an intimate and complex discussion around the motifs of destiny, his
tory, or fatality-a discussion to which Valery's reflections, for example, are
a reliable witness). Finally, and as we know only too well, responsibility has
had a continuous hold right up to our own time, whether in Sartre {let me
cite just one remark that is perhaps emblematic in this regard: "to make
ourselves responsible for the world as ifit were our own creation"),9 Blan
chot, Adorno, Bloch, Levinas, Hans Jonas, or Derrida.
The common thread that ties together such disparate names is itself
woven into two separate strands: first, there is the prevalent motif of re
sponsibility, of being or existence ultimately defined by responsibility; sec
ond, there is the motif that philosophy or thinking is itself both responsi-
Responding to Existence 293
only in, for, and by him will actually reach the other�as well as the other
295
!
in me. As such, it's not that I grant sense because I already possess it. It's
not that I draw on a secure reserve of sense that I simply then transmit.
Rather, I promise, I anticipate a sense that is not yet there and will, in fact,
never be there as something completed and presentable, a sense that is al
ways in and according to the other, making sense only by being exposed to
the other, to the risk of not making sense, to the always, certain risk -of
changing the sense of the other and so of always being other, always being
altered, always being outside, being by itself, as sense, a being-infinitely-
'
for-of-the-other.
Without this infinity, there is no sense; as such, it is nothing less than
an unreserved responsibility for this infinity. Absolute responsibility came
to us with the absolute infinity of grounds and ends, with the moral law
and the starry sky, with the death of God and the birth of the world, that
is to say, with existence submitted to our absolute responsibility. Nothing
else counts, nothing else is seriously at stake, above all not those values,
virtues, and supplements of the soul that so�e have made a profession of
spouting and that have no sense outside the absolute break with all re
ceived horizons.
What continually precedes itself in another or-and the two are
much the same-the aspect of the other that continually precedes itself in
me and hence in all others, assuming that nothing holds this proliferation
back and fixes it, is sense: a sense that has neither direction nor signifiCa
tion, which takes every possible means [voies] of exchange, and plays with
all the references [renvois] of the sign. What makes sense is always beyond
sense, in truth: a future, an encounter, a work, an event; and, once the fu
ture has become present, once the encounter has taken place, the work re
alized, the event faded, then sense-their own sense-moves along again,
passing beyond and elsewhere. When we're given a reason to live, always
supposing that this happens, when such a reason is given, deposited and
available (whether it takes the form of the life of a child or of a just soci-
, ety), it still has to have another reason beyond it, beyond even life or jus
tice, one that is not present-this is the moment of dying, which is yet an
other way in which sense is punctuated by the truth of its referral to the
other and of its absence of certainty. Sense is only guaranteed by its own
movement of expansion or flight-or, if you prefer, its own imminent con
tagion or its own transcendent excess.
Sense, then, has the same structure as responsibility: it is engage-
296 WORLD
I to call, to "interpellate," as they say today, calling the subject of sense that
everyone is. Indeed, each one of us is this subject to such an extent that
each one of us is it infinitely, absolutely, well beyond or before all egoism,
all individual personality or community.
Hence, too, existence realizes that it is responsible "to the point of ir
responsibility," as Blanchot was to say of Bataille, or as Adorno similarly
said of art.12 It knows that what it responds to is, in the end, the absence of
response, and thus a total freedom and dispersion of responses. We have to
be able to engage ourselves to the point of play and gaiety, of promising in
toxication or of no longer promising anything.
We are responsible for. sense, since sense is not the response of a sig
nification that would saturate the announcement, the sending or the gift of
sense, thereby bringing our responsibility to an end. This is why Ernst Tu
gendhat, for example, can define responsibility in community by calling
into question what it is that defines the idea of the "good life" as an "ap
propriation (of this idea) on the model of the question of truth'" or on the
model according to which "the perspective of the good is offered to us in
the knowledge of nonknowledge."13
What's more, we can be fairly certain that no final signification-
298 WORLD
but, on the contrary, institutes and relaunches it. There must be voices,
timbres, and singular modes. These voices are in themselves, in their co-re
spondance, the creation of sense. Democratic responsibility is responsibil
ity for such a creation. But immediately and from the outset, this means
that democracy itself is not something given, an available sense. It is re
sponsible precisely for what is not given: the demos, the people; the ones
with the others.
Translated by Sara Guyer
15
hold on a passage or a rupture whose event, :while sensible, gives a poor ac
count of itself when. marked as an evidential point: "1968," for example.}
The market consumes itself. It becomes like the pure machine of the
pure subject: the return to self of the ,most abstract identity, of a general
equivalence that amounts to nothing but its own -equivalence (to the
averred nothingness of values). One way or another, the market will soon
have no choice but to find a way out of this stranglehold or else go into
convulsions.
The years of the "sixties" didn't see all this, but they did have some
inkling of the progressive, insidious erosion of the checks on and justifica
tions of capital. A fault in history opens up and widens, therefore: a sus
pension of sense.
Sense was assured by the distinction between different equivalencies
(commercial, technological, democratic) and absolute value (humanity,
dignity, community), itself articulated as the active relation between the
progression of a history and its culmination in an end (knowledge, justice,
nature). But this distinction has given way to a general circulation, a sim
ple distinction between places or moments; this no longer seems to make
sense, providing instead a combination or exchange of roles. Imperceptibly
the category of "some day" has lost its appeal. The present appears devoid
of either tradition or future; it has become an unheard-of enigma.
of the very heart of things, from out of the accomplishment-or the ex
haustion-of a certain form of existence. It took twenty years for that up
heaval to start becoming visible.
For the moment, though, none of this is available 'to us, except as a
sort of profound discomfort. Somewhere, discourse shattered, but it's hard
to say exactly where. And it's not as if we have another discourse to fall
back on. For a long time yet we will have to extend ourselves in the search
for discourses that might supplement the one we have, relay it, start it over.
And while this is going on, the nature of the rifr is only going to become
more evident. We have no other discourse; all we know is that something
has been interrupted, broken down at the heart of discourses that, once
cherished, have now become untenable {philosophies of history, moral
philosophies, and even philosophies, literatures, and poetries as a whole}.
We have no other discourse because it is undoubtedly-we're just begin-:
ning to sense this-the general function of discourse itself that's at stake
here: sense's distinction is coming to an end. It is as if all possible sense,had
been produced and, ultimately, "sense" itself turned out to be a crazed ma
chine and the demand for it a senseless one.
Speech has been severed from speech, and speech now cuts short
what it says. Language has begun to speak through and about the inter
ruption of discourse. It's not a matter of a silence, however, since silence,
along with its potential for mysticism or wisdom, has remained upstream
from the interruption. Rather, it is a matter of another regime of speech,
another concern, another way .of working speech. Speech becomes difficult
and withheld; it can no longer trust in the accomplishment of sense. It
learns another confidence, one that it sets within its t�ajectory, its tracing,
another way of being delivered over.
If language has become, in recent years, an object of an interest that
is powerful and polymorphous (perverse, say those who refuse to under
stand), this is because it needs now to be received naked, the prestige of
sense stripped away, and put back to work, to invention. There needs to be
a meticulous decomposition of the effects and articulations oflanguage; bit
by bit, other voices need to be heard, addressed differently and with dif
ferent rhythms. No longer a differential of sense but a differential of voice,
therefore: something about song renders discourse asunder (breath, mod
ulation, rhythmic transport ofwords, throat noise) . At the same time, how
ever, something strangles song.
• � . .••!.-�'. -
-I,'·
I
It .
'·
Changing ofthe World
ence (or the world) are transformed and begin to slip outside the remit of
questioning (what is it? who is it? whence? why?) and to attain a new kind
of assertion (given, withheld, withdrawn, touched). Such questions slip
outside the remit of intention and interpretation, entering into another
truth, flagrant, evanescent, pointed, suspended. This truth is no longer
the truth of objects of knowledge-these take up precise places, ever bet
ter planned and articulated, in constant circulation-but the fantastic ef
fect of Science suppresses itself. Knowledge shows itself to be endless,
since it's no longer itself an end, an exponential development of prolifer
ating technologies.
There is an unprecedented load of the real: things, matters, supports,
skins, grains, and fibers. Art is displaced, therefore; it stops seeking out new
forms and instead transforms itself and, imperceptibly, transports itself
outside its site. Its horizon is no longer that of transfiguration, therefore,
but of a patient practice this side of figures, flush against surfaces, bodies,
clays, pulps, beats, or rhythms, in the very place where objects become
strange, where the world is emptied, decomposed, or recomposed through
and through.
It is no longer a matter of the composition of forms but a matter of
touching ori grounds, ploughing them, scratching them, pinching them,
piercing them, moving thus to the far side of accomplishment, into begin
nings, nascent states, alongside unfettered energies and unleashed tensions,
the breaks and tremors of origins.
J. {
I
itself; in short, it has started to comprise a co-existence. The sense of the
world no longer lies outside of it; in it, it is its pro�mity and its strange
ness, each one infinite.
�
j This is why, in 1968, the politics of destination-of the model, of
! project or accomplishment, and might that. not also be politics as a whole
Ji (ot the politics of the "theologico-political"), if it's true that we have no
.j
;J
1
I
�
306 WORLD
as sober and as dense as the being-together of all the pieces of the world,
whose proximity, whose community, it provides.
flnds], its realizing (if not wholly rei£Ying) resource-does nothing but
provoke unrest, insurrection, even, over the question of the real, the ques
tion of the thing or of things.
In fact, it's not hard to see that there can be no "relation" without "ex
posure," nor, consequently, one thing without the other: how could a self
. not turn toward a particular face, an outside, of this same self so as to re
late to itself and thus to take place? How could a self be its thing without
also being its thing? How could it be its own thing [sa propre chose] with
out also being properly a thing [proprement chose] ? How, in short, does it
realize itself?
Conversely: how could what is exposed not be exposed to this outside
toward which it is directed but that is equally itself-endlessly the same
outside, each one of its sides folded over and again? And how, then, could
it not ultimately relate to itself? How could this "self" not end up resolv
ing itself in this, its own reduction?
Still: how could the face that the self exposes in order to be a self not
be its own outside, an outside that is nonetheless and necessarily improper
to it, an other that is more fundamenral to the self than the self itself, an
other, then, that isn't the presupposition of the self but, more accurately,
the presupposition of this very presupposition: the nonself, the surface
putted with shadows devoid of all relation, the death's head pondered and
handled by Hamlet or by the subject of the Vanities, the bony thing, hard
and glistening, that disdainfully looks my way [qui me regarde de nul re
gard] , a look with no regard for any presence that might face it but that
dives into me as ifinto nothingness, relating to me in order to withdraw all
relation and to expose me to my self-less self, which, in turn-a turn that
is no longer my turn but the turn at which I have no more turns-is itself
a glistening bone full of holes, dirt packed tight into the sockets.
Equally, however, the death's head runs the risk of distracting us from
what it manifests (and it has done so throughout modern times). The way
in which it is pondered and handled is equivocal, and this ambiguous fas
cination stems from the way in which the skull combines horror at our
own disappearance (the end of all relation) with a maintaining of what dis�
appears (the figure engaged in relation, its look and its rictus).
In this way it is still its own image that the self wants to bring before
,
Res ipsa et ultima 315
itself from and as the outside. It finds itself starting out again; it still relates
to what exposes it and to which it is exposed: the subject, then, does not
end up dialectizing its death, making death its thing after all.
But death is devoid of either figure or subject. It doesn't await me at
the end like another me who would still be me turning back toward myself
from the abyss. Rather, death is "here" from the moment that I am "here,"
at once:: and immediately my flesh and bones, the extension of what ex
poses me, the res extensa that opposes the res cogitans only to the extent that
it exposes it, exposes it to itself.
It's time to put death in its place: in things, in the general connection
and exposure of things, and so in the world, rather than in the hideous
outside of a disfigured Subject (disfigured by the very hope of its transfig
uration). Neither from within nor from without does death concern ,a self:
this is its violent paradox, the paradox of being simultaneously so intimate
and yet so improper, the paradox of having already liquidated the very in
timacy that it was supposed to effect: Equally; though, it ought to denote
the "death of God": the end of death as punishment, as annihilation
and/or redemption and resurrection. Death becomes the absolute exposure
that crosses all relation and all relations (to the self, to the other). Yet this
doesn't mean that the thought of death becomes any more bearable. What
it does mean, though, is that we have no relation to it, whether dialectical,
tragic, mystical, whatever. Death isn't something, but the exposure of all
things and-'-thereby-the condition of possibility for all relation (without
it, everything would remain wrapped up in itself, heaped, massed, sunken,
senseless). ,
There can only be relation (the return, the appropriation of a subject
to itself or between subjects, it amounts to much the same thing) if we
start with an absolute distmcing, without which there would be no possi
bility of proximity, of identity or strangeness, of subjectivity or thinghood.
First and foremost, however, this distancing distends relation to the point
of exposition: scarcely am I born before I am outside myself at an infinite
distance, outside simply tur�ed out, exposed to the rest of the world, to all
things. And the same goes for everything, each one exposing universal ex
position differently.
Every thing outside all the others, every thing according to the
stretching that spaces them and without which there would be just one in
distinct thing gathered into the point at which it would annul itself, a
thing unthinged, a de-realized res, a perfect, syncopated subject turned
316 CODA
back in on itself without its having ever reached itself, an extinct, noiseless
trinket, a one annihilated without its belng dead: every thing, then, touch
ing every part ofevery other thing, touching me in the same way, piece by
piece, here and there, always, from time to time, exposing the infinity of
our relations.
Things: the first stone that's thrown, a sheet of paper, galaxies, the
wind, my television screen, a quark, my big toe, a trapped nerve, prosthe
ses, organs planted or grafted beneath my skin, placed or exposed inside,
all things exposing themselves and exposing us, between them and be
tween us, between them and us, together and singularly.
The thing is what the res cogitans and the res extensa have in common:
it is their mutual, inextricable intrication. The early Descartes was well
aware of this when he attributed a quite different reality to the union of the
two things, from an evidence as powerful as that of the ego (c�gito), but
from an evidence that is entirely ordinary and immanent to the course of
things, from an evidence present on the very surface of the most everyday
experience of existence; an evidence that is given without thinking. There's
nothing to prove; there's nothing but the test of the real [il n'y apas a prou-
. ver, il n'y a quCt eprouver le reel] .
The fir�t and last real, the ground of the real and the ground of the
res in all its modes, ultima res, is the identity and difference of relation and
exposure: more accurately, it is this identity in its difference and this dif
ference in its identity (and here, in obviously means outside). The two are
the same, the same thing-insofar as they turn things toward one another;
but they differ absolutely-have nothing in common-since relation refers
to an inside and exposure to an outside. They never encounter one an
other; rather, they pass through one another. The fact that one moves in
the other, and vice versa, doesn't change anything; they are oblivious to one
another and exclude one another as they change roles.
All of which means, then, that the "inside" and the "outside" of the
world, the self and the outside-the-self, subject and thing, are strangely,
paradoxically e�en, the same: the same real that stems from nothing and no
one, that comes from nowhere and goes nowhere, that rests on no ground
and goes uninterpreted, that exists by the mere fact o� existing, by a perfect
necessity that equates to an equally perfect contingency or to the unprece
dented freedom of a being that is merely the chance and the risk of an on
tological surprise.
318 CODA
The thing itself, res ipsa et ultima, is not a particular thing. It is nothing.
More precisely, it is the sameness ofnothing: the nothing relates to it
self, yes, but, being precisely nothing, it is simply and immediately exposed
as something, and therein lies the reason of the world-its ultima ratio-
and its true creatio ex' nihilo: the fact that there is something as an outcome
of nothing.
By the same logic, however, the fact that there is something never
appears as such: there is no such thing as "the" thing "in itself" or for itsel£
The thing doesn't stem from itself nor do things stem from the thing, from
its essence, its origin or its substrate. Even if there is some thing, anything
whatsoever, indeterminate and indifferent, then there is still nothing, since
the.indeterminate and the undifferentiated do not exist. (They do not ex
ist, do not emerge from the pure nothingness that pure being in itself is.)
"There is something" can only mean one thing: yes, there is something, no
matter what it is, but every time that there is, this what is determined, sin
gular, different, and hence there are already more than one of them.
If there is something, then there are some things, lots of them,
whether they be shells or eyebrows, clouds or hammers: several, many, dif
ferent in number as well as quality. The profusions of nature and the pro
fusions of technology contribute to the same sort of abundance, an abun
dance that isn't an end.
Foam, erase, tooth, canvas, synapse, liquid crystal, tentacle, scale,
plank, spume, fingernail, hail, neutron, lymph . . . and so ever indefinitely
on. The time of modernity is followed by the time of things.
Translated by Steven Miller
Notes
CHAPTER 1
NOTE: This essay appeared in French as "Une Pensee finie," in Jean-Luc Nancy,
Une Pemeejinie (Paris: Galilee, 1990), 9-53.
No one is taken in. This is not just a crisis, or even an end of "ideolo
gies." It is a generalized debacle of sense. "Sense" must be understood in all
its senses: the sense [direction] of history, the sense [feeling] of community,
the sense [direction] of peoples and nations, the sense [meaning] of exis
tence, the sense of any transcendence or immanence whatsoever. And that's
not all: it is not just the contents of sense, the meanings-all our mean
ings-that are now invalidated. Rather, a strange black hole is growing at
the very site· of the formation, birth, or donation of sense. It is as if, in the
dissolution of this originary power of making or receiving sense whose many
figures make up, along the way to ourselves, the history of the modern Sub
ject (the subject of philosophy, of politics, of history, of practice, of faith, of
communication, of art), a world, or worlds, or pieces ofworlds, were emerg-
320 Notes
any knowledge of finitude's �'truth in itsel£" This requires clarification, at the very
least. We don't know finitude "in itself." However, this isn't the effect of perspec
tivism but because there is no finitude "in itself." It is with this that we need to
concern ourselves, and not the rhetoric of the modesty of thinking within which
Heidegger remains trapped.
5. Nietzsche, Hussed, Derricla's reading of Hussed, Marion's reading of
Hussed, Heidegger, and Deleuze are all presupposed here. This goes without say
ing, but "it's best to say it anyway.
6. Hegel, in the Aesthetics (of course), had already admired the double sense
of Sinn.
7. See "Elliptical Sense," below.
8. Martin Heidegger, Sein und Zeit (Tiibingen: Max Niemeyer, 1993), §31. I,
note in passing that, although this book defines the principle of a "deconstruction"
of sense, as the sense ofbeing, Heidegger still remains within a double regime, and
a classical one at that, of the presentation of sense: on the one hand, as "under
standing"; on the other, as "sensing" or "state-of-mind" (Bejindlichkeit). He repeats
that the two are indissociable, but the two remain two, and Heidegger doesn't ex
plicitly question this duality.
9. See Max Loreau, La Genese du phenomene (Paris: Minuit, 1989), 301: "There
is no being that is distinct from the sense of being."
10. Martin Heidegger, Beitrage zur Philosophie, Gesamtausgabe 65 (Frankfurt a.
M.: Vittorio Klostermann, 1989), 268-69.
H . Heidegger evokes the possibility of this in "What is Philosophy?" In this
sense, the difference between being and beings could not even be assigned as "dif
ference." Being which is (transitively) beings only differs from the latter insofar as
this very difference differs from a difference between "being" (intransitive) and be
ings. This last difference (which is most often taken to be the sense of the "ontico
ontological difference") differs, therefore, ftom itself: being does not occur as be
ing. This is what Jacques Derrida has sought to bring out with the
neither-word-nor-concept "differance." As he writes: "Finite difference is infinite"
'
(La Voix et lephenomene [Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1967], XXX; tr�s
lated by David Allison as Speech and Phenomena [Evanston: Northwestern Uni
versity Press, 1973]). "This sentence, I fear, is meaningless," he once said. Perhaps,
but it does make sense.
12. If we use the translation "for death," we introduce a finality that is wholly
foreign to the text. Alternatively, the "for," the zum, better translated as toward or
to, has to be reinterpreted. In any case, death needs to be thought here independ
ently of all sacrificial logic, a task that would also require a critique and a decon
struction of this motif in Heidegger himself. See "The Unsacrificeable," below.
13. KPM 225-6 / 154. What follows takes the whole of §41 as its point of de
parture. [Each of the citations in what follows come from § 41.-Trans.]
14. And if, as a: consequence, existence ("ek-sistence") ought not to be extended,
albeit in modal form, but understood more broadly as simply human. This is a dif-
322 Notes
rather, all events are substitutable, and all are singularities. Not. indifferent, but . .
substitutable, as singularities, as the absolute, each time, of a-singular. And how
could there be sense if an event did not communicate (with) all events? But how
could sense not be finite if this communication itself did not take place as a trans
mission of having (of qualities, of properties), but only as this universal substi
tutability of the "world-event"? The latter comes therefore from this-which is to
say, it comes from nowhere and no one; neither from atoms nor from God.
Equally, though, neither atoms (with the clinamen) ·nor God (the creator, not the
supreme being, if they can be distinguished) have doubtless ever truly been
thought otherwise than as the eventuality of the world without an assignable or
unifiable origin. '�tom" or "God" have been the infinitizing goals of the thought
of finite sense. The provenance of the world lies neither in a thoughtfulness, nor
in providence. The world comes from its event. It exists therefore right through
even though existence is not homogeneous in itself, of man, of the stone, or of the
fish. There is only sense in touching that. But in touching that, there is only finite
sense.
15; Here, we would need to go back to the whole argument of The Experience
ofFreedom, the displacement of the concept of freedom as the self-legislation of an
infinite Subject into that of the expositioJ.? of a finite being.
16. See my "Posseder la verite clans une ame et un corps," in Une Penseefinie,
325-51; translated by Rodney Trumble as "To PossessTruth in One Soul and One
Body," in The Birth to Presence, 284-306. As for Marx, and for those who find
themselves astonished to see a thinking of finitude attributed to him, let me say
that for Marx this is connected with his constant and decisive appeal to the "real,"
in particular to its materiality, to the ineffectiveness of all generality, and .even to
the contingent character of nature and. history. That man remains, for Marx,
generic man doesn't stop the beginning of the decomposition of the essence of
man, in history and in freedom.
17. Here, though, I'm not really thinking about Rimbaud, but about Nietzsche
and Bataille.
18. In speaking of access, I am, of course; thinking about Bataille-and about
a different reference from the preceding one. Whatever else may need to be said,
it's with Bataille that this demand emerges in all its nakedness.
19. See my '�I..:Histoire finie," in Jean-Luc Nancy, La Communaute desoeuvree
(Paris: Bourgois, 1990), 237-78; first published in English as "Finite History," in
The States of"Theory'': History, Art, and Critical Discourse, ed. David Carroll (New
York: Columbia University Press, 1990), 149-72; reprinted in The Birth to Presence,
143-66.
20. See "The Kategorein of Excess," below.-Ed.
21. See The Experience ofFreedom, chap. I2.-Ed.
22. And so, too, without going down the path of sacrifice. Misfortune and
sickness can call, in different ways, on sacrifice: we no longer can. See "The Un
sacrificeable," below.
324 Notes
23. Rereading Spinoza, therefore. But also Plato. The "Good," situated
epekeina tes ousias, "beyond being or beyond essence," isn't the good of a moral
norm. Rather, it is reason and the end of all things: the beginning of every thought
of the end.
24. Here one might refer to Jean-Frans:ois Lyotard's analyses of the time that
capital "does not leave untouched" (in L'Inhuman: Causeries sur le temps [Paris:
Galilee, 1989], translated by Geoffrey Bennington and Rachel Bowlby as The In
human: Reflections on Time [Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1991]) and those
of Andre Gorz in his several publications on the reduction of the workday. For the
replacement of generic "man" by "singuIarities," see Etienne Balibar, La Proposition
de l'egaliberte (Conferences du Perroquet, 1989).
25. Laziness and cowardice, once again. For a survey of the state of the
problem, see Pascal Dumontier, Les Situationnistes et mai 68 (Paris: Gerard
Lebovici, 1990). He speaks advisedly of a "concerted silence around the topic of
May '68" (13).
26. A critique carried on and then diverted or turned back by Baudrillard, who
embodies, in a sense, the limits of a critique of "simulation," itself still a tributary
of representation.
27. This is the sole question raised by the ·"end of art"-and so, toO, by the
birth of something else, for which the name "art" is perhaps no longer suited. I've
dealt with this in "Portrait de l'art en jeune fille," in Le Poids d'unepensee
. (Greno-
ble: Presses Universitaires de Gtenoble, 1991).
28. I'm borrowing the word "mimesis" from Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, at
tempting to sum up the movement of his thinking of this concept. Moreover, I
would like, and it would be useful, to demonstrate the convergence, albeit distant,
of this thinking with Gilles Deleuze's thoughts about an "image" that owes noth
ing to representation.
29. From which it follows that the Greek phusis, with its complex relation to
techne, a relation that renders the two indistinguishable, isn't "nature" in this sense.
This is one of Heidegger's central theses, although he was unable to draw out its
full consequences and instead allowed phusis to assume once again the guise of a
kind of original immanence. The reactive part of his thinking about "technology"
is entirely of a piece with this (although it's perhaps worth adding that Heidegger
wasn't confronted by the kinds of technology we know today). On the ambiguity
of Heidegger's theses about technology, see Avital Ronell, The Telephone Book
(Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1989).
30. Here we can most clearly see the error in Heidegger's conflation of the
camps with the "agricultural food industry" in a single, blanket condemnation of
"technology."
31. "Un-worked" (des-oJUvree) in Blanchot's sense, needless to say, and thus in
a necessary relation with an "unworked community." Beyond this, there would
also be a good deal to say about such an un-working in the sciences, that is, in what
should less and less be confused with the metaphysical aim of Science, with a cap
ital "S," as the completion of sense, something that it's increasingly hard to distin
guish from technologies.
Notes 325
32. Contrary, of course, to what Hegel sought not to do, and not without a
struggle. See my "Le Rire, la presence," in Une Penseefinie, 297-324; translated by
Emily McVarish as "Laughter, Presence," in The Birth to Presence, 368-92.
CHAPTER 2
I. Jean-Paul Same, Cahiers pour une morale (Paris: Gallimard, 1983), 499;
translated by David Pellauer as Notebooks for an Ethics (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1992), 483.
2. Sartre, Write et existence (Paris: Gallimard, 1989), 66-67.
3. Georges Bataille, Sur Nietzsche, in Oeuvres completes (Paris: Gallimard, 1973),
6: 197. All references to Bataille are to this edition, henceforth cited as QC, fol
lowed by volume and page number.
4. QC 12: 459.
5. QC 6: 260.
6. QC 6: 312.
7. QC 6: 318.
8. See Heidegger, Beitrage zur Philosophie (vom Ereignis), in Gesamtausgabe 65
(Frankfurt a. M.: Vittorio Klostermann, 1989).
9. QC 12: 287; see also QC 12: 316, where Bataille speaks of "laying bare the
flip side of thinking."
10. QC 12: 394.
H. QC 12: 316.
CHAPTER 3
NOTE: This essay appeared in French in Jean-Luc Nancy, Une Penseefinie (Paris:
Galilee, 1990), 65-106.
12. Augustine, The City ofGod, cited in E. Mersch, Le Corps mystique du Christ
(Paris: DescIee, 1951), 2: II4. The reference supplied at this point is imprecise.
13. Friedrich Nietzsche, �rke, ed. Karl Schlechta (Munich: Hanser, 1956), 3:
803. The citation in question is from the Nachlass, the unpublished writings.
14. Paul's Epistle to the Hebrews, 10: II-14.
15. Cited in Mersch, Le Corps mystique du Christ, 2: 6ff.
16. Hegel, Hegel's Philosophy ofMind, §546.
i7. Plato, Laws, 909d et sec. .
18. OC 7: 253.
19. Plato, Phaedo, u8.
20. Ibid., 91b-c.
21. Pascal, Pensees (Paris: Gallimard-PIeiade, 1978), §268, 569; translated by A.
Krailsheimer as Pensees (Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin, 1966), §268, 109.
22. Hegel, Lectures on the Philosophy ofReligion, ed. P. C. Hodgson, trans. R. F.
Brown, P. C. Hodgson, and J. M. Steward (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1984), I: 354 n. 178.
23. G. W. F. Hegel, Phenomenology ofSpirit, rrans. A. V. Miller (Oxford: Ox
ford University Press, 1977), §779. The context of the remark concerns Christ.
Notes 327
24· OC 7: 255·
25. Friedrich Nietzsche, Morgenrote, in Kritische Studienausgabe, ed. Giorgio
Colli and Mazzino Montinari (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 1988), vo!. 3, bk. 2, §
146; translated by R. J. Hollingdale as Daybreak (Cambridge: Cambridge Univer
sity Press, 1982), 146..
26. Nietzsche, Ecce Homo, KSA 6; translated by R. J. Hollingdale as Ecce Homo
(Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin, 1989), 129-30.
27. Karl Marx, "Critique of Hegel's Doctrine of Right," in Early Writings,
trans. and ed. Lucio Colletti (Harmondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin, 1974), 104.
28. See Thomas Aquinas, Summa theologiae, IlIa, quo 22 2 c, then IIa-IIae, quo
85 3 ad 2.
29. Cited in Gusdorf, L'Experience humaine du sacrifice, 45.
. 30. See Les Carnets de Lucien Levy-Bruhl (Paris: Presses Universitaires de
France, 1949). Generally speaking, the relation between mimesis and sacrifice re
quires an examination that I cannot undertak� here. If mimesis is an appropriation
of the other through the alteration or suppression of the proper, wouldn't it have a
structure equivalent to that of sacrifice? (See, e.g., "etre personne-ou tout le
monde" ("to be no one-or everyone"), in Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe's analysis of
Diderot's Paradox, "Diderot: Paradox et mimesis," in 1jpographies. JL' L1initation
des modemes (Paris: Galilee, 1986), 35; translated as "Diderot: Paradox and Mime
sis," in Lacoue-Labarthe, 1jpography: Mimesis, Philosophy, Politics, ed. Christopher
Fynsk (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1989), 259. As regards the links be
tween sacrifice and mimesis, see also, e.g., Jacques Derrida, "La Pharmacie de Pla
ton," in La Dissemination (Paris: SeuiI, 1972), 152-53; translated by Barbara John
son as "Plato's Pharmacy," in Dissemination (Chicago: University ofChicago Press,
1979). Should we look for a priority in this equivalence? Should we found sacrifice
on mimesis, found it, for example, on an anthropology of mimetic violence and
rivalry (along the lines proposed by Girard) that turns sacrifice into a symboliza
tion after the fact and that appeals to a "revelation" in order to suspend its vio�
lence? (In which case; and however subtle the analyses may be, the so-called posi
tive characteristic of such an anthropological "knowledge" would admittedly be as
foreign to me as that other kind of "positivity" associated with the motif of "reve
lation.") Conversely, why shouldn't we grasp mimesis on the basis of a methexis, a
communication or contagion that, outside the West, has perhaps never had the
meaning of a communion, which we have tended to give it? What escapes us, and
what "Western sacrifice" at once misses and sublates, is an essential discontinuity
of methexis, an in-communication of every community. (See, e.g., Bataille on con
tagion, OC 7: 369-71.)
31. See Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe, 1jpographies, 42: "Is mimesis sublatable?"
The question is perhaps no different from the following: Is methexis communal?
It is perhaps in the theologico-philosophicaI construction of the doctrine of
Christian double hypostasis, insofar as this is also the very site of sacrifice and of
328 Notes
all possible communion, that such questions w�uld find their most telling docu
mentation.
32. OC II: 55.
33. Heidegger, Holzwege, Gesamtausgabe 5 (Frankfurt a. M.: Vittorio Kloster
mann, 1987), 50; "Th� Origin of the Work of Art," in Basic Writings, ed. David
Farrell Krell (London: Routledge, 1993), 187. The theme of sacrifice returns many
times in Heidegger. A critical analysis of this theme would require a separate study.
Arnold Hartmann and Alexander Garcia-Diittmann will one day provide it.
34. Immanuel Kant, Kritik der Urteilskraft, in G�sammelte Schriften, ed.
Koniglich PreuBischen Akademie der Wissenschaften ( Berlin: Walter de Gruyter,
1902-), 5: 271, 252.
35. Novalis, Heinrich von Ofterdingen, in Schriften, ed. P. Kluckhohn and R.
Samuel (Stuttgart: W. Kohlhamner, 1960), 1: 337.
-36. OC 5: 156. See also, e.g., the remarks of L'Erotisme (Paris: Minuit, 1957), 98:
"In actual fact, literature is situated in succession to religion . . . Sacrifice is a novel,
it is a tale, illustrated in a gory fashion," etc. There's no need to underline the fact
that questions ofsacrifice and of myth have to be closely linked. .
37. OC II: 485.
38. Ibid.
39. Ibid.
40. F. W. J. Schelling, Siimmtliche Wi?rke, ed. K. F. A. Schelling (Stuttgart:
Cotta, 1865-61) 453. .
41. OC :II: 485.
42. Ibid.
43. OC II: 486.
44. OC n: 103.
45. ' OC 8: 300.
46. OC n: 262-67. [Subsequent quotes in the text are from this article.
Trans.] For want of space, I am leaving to one side the "Sartre" article on the Jews
and the camps (OC n: 226-28). The conclusions of these articles would converge:
BataiIle, without saying so directly, tends to view the Jews as the victims of a sac
rificial immolation of "reason." For another example, see OC 7: 376-79. See also
Jacques Lacan, Stfminaire XI (Paris: Seuil, 1977), 247, and Philippe Lacoue
Labarthe, La Fiction du politique (Paris: Bourgous, 1989); translated by Chris
Turner as Heidegger, Art, Politics (Oxford: Blackwell, 1991), who respectively affirm
and deny the sacrificial character of the camps, and Jacques Derrida, who, in the
midst of commenting on sacrifice as orality and on philosophies that "do not sac
rifice sacrifice," appears to affirm such a character; see Derrida, Shibboleth (Paris:
GaliIee, 1986), 83-85.
47. OC 7: 376-79. It is worth pointing out that a comparable discussion has
taken place on the subject of the sacrificial character of revolutionary regicide; see
Myriam Revault d'Allones, Dune mort a l'autre (Paris: Seuil, 1989), 59. There are
obviously considerable differences between such discussions. I merely want to sug-
Notes 329
gest that, under the rule ofWestern sacrifice, sacrifice started to decay a long tim�
ago.
48. Adolf Hitler, Mein Kampf(Munich, 1936), 326.
49. Ibid., 329.
50. Ibid., 330.
51. Himmler's speech of October 4, 1943, cited in Raul Hilberg, The Destruc
tion ofthe European Jews (London: Holmes & Meier, 1985), 3: 1009-10.
52. OC n: 101.
53. Hermann Broch, The Death of Virgil, trans. J. Starr Untermeyer (Har
mondsworth, Middlesex: Penguin, 2000), 172.
54. On technology, techne, art, and the work in Nazism and/or"in Heidegger's
thinking, see Lacoue-Labarthe; Heidegger, Art, Politics.
55. See, in particular, Martin Heidegger, "Die Kehre," in 10rtrage undAufiatze
(Pfullingen: Gunter Neske, 1954), 37-47; translated by Williarn Lovitt as "The
Turning," in Heidegger, The Question Concerning Technology (New York: Harper
& Row, 1977), 36-49..
56. I agree with Jean-Fran�ois Lyotard on this point; see Lyotard, Heidegger et
les juifi" (Paris: Galilee, 1988), 140; translated by Andreas Michael and Mark
Roberts as Heidegger and "thejews" (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
1990). For me, though, his argument as a whole calls for this reservation at least:
Heidegger's intended gesture here doesn't simply invalidate the thought of Ereig
nis, to which Lyotard himself, paradoxically, becomes intensely attached.
57. Lacan, Le Seminaire Xl, 247. Here, Lacan explicitly derives this definition
from the existence of the camps.
58. Martin Heidegger, Sein und Zeit (Tiibingen: Max Niemeyer, 1992), 42.
59. See Martin Heidegger, "Zeit und Sein," in Zur Sache des Denkens (Tiibin
gen: Max Niemeyer, 1969); translated by Joan Starnbaugh as "Time and Being," in .
Heidegger, On Time and Being (San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1984).
60. See The Experience ofFreedom. The theme of sacrifice was already touched
upon in this book, just as it was invoked in my "Soleil cou coupe," in Le Demon
.
des anges (Barcelona: Departarnent de Cultura, 1989).
61. Rereading these pages while editing them for their French publication as a
book (August I, 1990), I want to add the following: yesterday, between four hun
dred and six hundred people were massacred in a church in Monrovia, where they
were taking refuge from the fighting and executions of the civil war that is tearing
Liberia apart. Among them, there were many women, children, and infants. The
newspaper explains that eviscerated bodies of t\yo young children were thrown
onto the altar. I'm not passing judgment on this war, or even on this particular
episode. I'm insufficiently informed to do so. I simply want .to note the crushing
weight of this configuration of signs: in Africa, upon a Christian altar, a parody of
sacrifice-yet less than a parody, more a slaughter unsupported by any sacrifice.
i
I:
f·
330 Notes
CHAPTER 4
NOTE: This text appeared in French in Cahiers Intersignes, nos. 4-5 (Paris, au
tumn 1992): 237-49.
NOTE: While writing these pages, I'd forgotten that one of the texts included by
Blanchot in The Infinite Conversation carries the same title: "I.:Indestructible."
This was no doubt both an unconscious memory and a dialogue.
CHAPTER 5
NOTE: This text merits a place in this collection on account of its themes, par
ticularly the theme of sense. Nevertheless, it has a special status, for two reasons.
First, it was wdtten for inclusion in a festschrift for Jacques Derrida and so belongs
to a genre that is not really appropriate here. In recognition of this, I have removed
the preamble, which was devoted entirely to this "address." [The preamble is in
cluded in an earlier translation of this text by Peter Connor, in Derrida: A Critical
Reader, ed. David Wood (Oxford: BlackweIl, 1992), 36-5I.-Trans.} Second, the
original circumstances in which the piece was composed-a symposium at the
Collegium Phenomenologicum directed by Rodolphe Gasche in 1987-dictated
that I speak about a particular text by Derrida. I chose "Ellipsis," the concluding
essay of L'Ecriture et la dwrance (Paris: Seuil, 1967) , 429-36; translated by Alan
Bass as "Ellipsis," in Derrida, Writing and Difference (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1978), 295-300. This implies a reading of that text throughout this
essay. The essay in French can be found in Jean-Luc Nancy, Une Penseefinie (Paris:
Galilee, 1990), 269-96.
I. See, too, the opening pages of Nancy's Le Poids d'une pensee (Grenoble:
Presses Universitaires de Grenoble, 1991)-Ed.
2. Jacques Derrida, De la grammatologie (Paris: Minuit, 1967), 18; translated by
Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak as OfGrammatology (Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins
University Press, 1976), 23.
3. See Jacques Derrida, Marges de la philosophie (Paris: Minuit, 1972); trans
lated by Alan Bass as Margins ofPhilosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1982L 330.
Notes 331
CHAPTER 6
I. Everything that follows speaks, according to the rules of the game, of Der
rida, from Derrida, or alongside him or his r:euvre. I will keep textual references to
a minimum; there would either have been too many or too few, and my concern
here isn't a philological one. I'm searching for the extremity at which a thought be
gins or exhausts itself, at which its subject is stripped bare.
2. The expression appears in Jacques Derrida, L'Ecriture et la diffirence (Paris:
Seuil, 1967), 364; translated by Alan Bass as Writing and Difference (Chicago: Uni
versity of Chicago Press, 1978), 247. On the intestine, the brain, and the tympa
num, see Marges de la philosophie (Paris: Minuit, 1972), i-iv; translated by Alan
Bass as Margins ofPhilosophy (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982), x-xv.
3. See "Circonfession," in Geoffrey Bennington and Jacques Derrida, Jacques
Derrida (Paris: Seuil, 1991), 275; translated by Geoffrey Bennington as "Circum
fession," in Bennington and Derrida, Jacques Derrida (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1993), 298: "the question of me, with respect to which all other
questions appear derived."
4. It would be pointless to try to provide references. There are hundreds of
them, unevenly distributed across texts and perhaps even across periods. More
over, the two uses of "such," the "normal" and the "retro," often occur almost side
by side. See, e.g., Partrges (Paris: Galilee, 1986), 14.
5. Denida, Glas, 7-as for the rest, I must pass it by; I' forget it. But everybody
knows what it concerns.
6. It is worth noting that although here Nancy credits Derrida with having
raised the specter of "haunting," the term was actually part of Nancy's vocabulary
long before it waS adopted by Derrida. See "The Kategorein of Excess," below.-Ed.
7. These last two terms are employed and discussed by Philippe Lacoue
Labarthe in Le Sujet de la philosophie (Paris: Aubier-Flammarion, . 1979), 221ft: His
theme finds certain echoes here.
8. Glas (Paris: GaliIee, 1974), 79-80; translated by John P. Leavey, Jr., as Glas
(Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1990) ' 67-68.
9. See a bit further on in Glas: "everything is always attached from behind [de
dos] , written, described from behind [par derriere] . . . . Absolutely behind, the Der
riere that will never have been seen face on, the Deja preceded by nothing" (97 / 84).
10. La Carte postale: De Socrate a Freud et au-dela (Paris: Flammarion, 1980),
86; translated by Alan Bass as The Post Card: From Socrates to Freud and Beyond
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 78: the da countingfor nothing with
regard to the do or the dos, "as if behind the curtains," still.
H. Martin Heidegger, Sein und Zeit (Tilbingen: Max Neimeyer, 1993), 132.
'
12. See also "My signature . . . cut offbefore the da" (Jacques Derrida, La Write
.- , ,: .
332 Notes
CHAPTER 7
3. Here I am developing one aspect of the program of Kant analysis begun ten
tatively in Logodaedalus I: Le Discours de la syncope (Paris: GaliIee, 1976).
4. Immanuel Kant, Die Metaphysik der Sitten, in Gesammelte Schriften, ed.
Koniglich PreuBischen Akademie der Wissenschaften (Berlin: Walter de Gruyter,
1902-) '6: 316, §49. [Except in the case of the Nachlass, cited by fragment number,
and the Critique ofPure Reason, where we follow the standard A and B pagination,
all references to Kant are to this edition, henceforth cited as Ak, followed by vol
ume and page number.-Trans.]
5. Religion within the Limits ofMere Reason, Ak 6: 41-42.
6. Ibid., Ak 6: 35.
7. See my ''rEtre abandonn�," in L'ImpbatiJcategorique (Paris: Flammarion,
1983), 141-53; translated by Brian Holmes as '�bandoned Being," in Jean-Luc
Nancy, The Birth to Presence (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1992), 36-47.
8. Except in the case of right itself, in the case of the production of legality or
of the "jurisprudence" without experience that inaugurates right; see "Lapsusju-
.
dicii," below.
9. Elias Canetti; Masse undMacht (Frankfurt am Main, 1980), 335; translated
by Carol Steward as Crowds and Power (London: Gollancz, 1962), 303.
10. By this we want to understand the particular nature of the "utterance." I
have addressed this in two texts: "La Verite imperative," in L'Imperatifcategorique,
89-II2, and "La Voix libre de l'homme," in L'ImpbatiJcategorique, n5-37; trans
lated by Richard Stamp as "The Free Voice of Man," in Retreating the Politica4 ed.
Simon Sparks (London: Routledge, 1996), 32-51. If the order takes place in lan
guage, the imperative perhaps lies beyond it, even when it is uttered, and even in
its very utterance and discursiveness. "Imperativity" and the address as such don't
happen without language, but they do arise from it. Or they arise from saying as
what is not said-from a tone and a gesture. .
n. Immanuel Kant, Opus posthumum, Ak 22: n8. Whether there is still love
without duty or whether there is no law in love are questions that; for the mo
ment, are entirely separate. ,
12. Kant, Nachlass, 8105, 1799.
13. Kant, ' Opus posthumum, Ak 22: 55.
14. Here I am borrowing a term used by Jean-Franc;:ois Lyotard in his analysis
of the prescriptive in "Logique de Levinas," in Textes pour Emmanuel Levinas
(Paris: Place, 1980), n3-69. I won't go into the convergences and divergences be
tween my own path and the one taken by Lyotard. Doubtless we would both need
to pursue them further.
15. Critique ofPractical Reason, Ak 5: 31.
16. It goes without saying that, quite apart from this similarity of position, the
imperative doesn't have the nature of either space or time. What it does do, how
ever, is maintain a quite complex relationship
. with them. This will have to be ex-
amined later.
17. Kant, Critique ofPure Reason, A 19; B 33.
' ;" ,
. . . .. ,
334 Notes
18. In the French text of this essay, Nancy refers to his essays collected under
the title L1mperatiJcategorique, but the comment might serve as a summation of
the essays gathered here under the heading "Judging."-Ed.
19. Kant, Religion, Ak 6: 46.
20. Ibid., 45.
21. Emmanuel Levirias, Totalite et injini (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff. 1961),
173; translated by Alphonso Lingis as Totality and Injinity (Pittsburgh: Duquesne
University Press, 1969), 199.
22. At this point, Nietzsche, despite himself, confirms what Kant has to say.
See my "Notre probite," in L1mptfratiJcategorique, 63-86; translated by Peter Con
ner as '''Our Probity!' On Truth in the Moral Sense in Nietzsche," in Looking af
ter Nietzsche, ed. Laurence A. Rickels (Albany: State University ofNew York Press,
1990), 67-88.
23. In a manner that is no doubt analogous, Lacan, in "Kant avec Sade," Ecrits
(Paris: Seuil, 1966), 765-90, attempts to understand the law as the law that con
stitutes the subject, not as the subject of a will to pleasure, but as the instrument
of the pleasure of the other. The problem is that this reversal still maintains the
"other" in the position of a subject of pleasure. Now, pleasure is without a sub
ject-the least that we can say-such being, pel:haps, the law as well as what lays
down the law as the incommensurable injunction.
24. "The voice is recognized as coming from the other to the extent that we
.
cannot respond to it, not to the measure of what, of the other, comes from the
other. The very structure of the law dictates or obliges its transgression" (Jacques
Derrida, in the debate that followed the presentation of "La Voix libre de
l'homme," reproduced in Les Fins de l'homme, ed. Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe and
Jean-Luc Nancy [Paris: Galilee, 1981], 183; Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe and Jean-Luc
Nancy, Retreating the Political ed. Sinion Sparks [London: Routledge, 1997], 53).
To this, we would n�ed to attach the motif of the "madness of the law," brought
to light by Derrida in "La Loi du genre," in Parages (Paris: GaliIee, 1986), 249-87;
translated by Avital Ronell as "The Law of Genre," CriticalInquiry7, no. I (1980):
55-81.
25. Here, we are not so very far from the problematic of "sovereignty" in
Bataille. I have begun to address this issue in "The Unsacrificeable,"above.
26. Kant, Opus posthumum, Ak 22: 55.
27. Kant, "What Real Progress Has Metaphysics Made in Germany . . . ?" Ak
20: 294.
28. Kant, Religion, Ak 6: 49.
29. See Jean-Louis Bruch, La Philosophie religieuse de /(ant (Paris: Aubier,
1968), 269.
30. At some point, we will need to examine the relation with the aesthetic that
this motif involves (that is, with the articulation of the sublime over beauty), a re
lation in which the nonsubjective status of singularity is also at stake.
31. Kant, Opusposthumum, Ak 22: 122.
Notes 335
32. Apropos tragedy, let me draw attention to the connection with Philippe
Lacoue-Labarthe's analysis of its Holderlinian treatment in "La Cesure du specu
latif," in Tjpographies 11: L'Imitation des modernes: (Paris: GaliIee, 1986);-translated
by Robert Eisenhauer as "The Caesura of the Spectacle," in Tjpographies: Mimesis,
Philosophy, Politics, ed. Christopher Fynsk (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
1989), 208-35. This connection is essential. As is the one to my oWn analysis of
Holderlin and Kant in "La Joie d'Hyperion," Les Etudes philosophiques 2 (1983):
177-94; translated by Christine Laennec and Michael Syrotinski as "Hyperion's
Joy," in Jean-Luc Nancy, The Birth to Presence (Stanford: Stanford University Press,
1993), 58-81.
33. The Kantian notion of end does not denote the completion of a program.
It is inaugural and without end. "So far as the concept of end is concerned, it is al
ways something that we have to bring about, and the concept of an ultimate end
needs to be seen as produced a priori by reason" (Ak 20: 294; "What Real
Progress?" 123).
34. Pierre Lachieze-Rey, L'Idealisme kantien (Paris: Vrin, 1950), 197.
35. Kant, Metaphysics ofMorals, Ak 6: 222. It will be necessary to examine else
where the relation.between this address of the law and the "call" which, for Hei
degger, constitutes conscience (Gewissen), insofar as this call "comes from me and
yet from beyond me and over me"; Heidegger, Sein und Zeit (Tiibingen: Max
. Niemeyer, 1993), 275; translated by John MacQuarrie and Edward Robinson as
Being and Time (New York: Harper & Row, 1962), 320. Certain important conse
quences follow from this, as I indicate in "The Free Voice of Man," consequences
that complicate the analysis of the "sublime voice. "
CHAPTER 8
me suggest, then, that any study of these displacements would need to avoid giv
ing them the simple form of a generalization or a deviation-a slippage, even
and instead recognize within the Latin "translation," regardless of the way in
which it transmits or relays the Greek, the character of an accident, of a collision
that redistributes entir�ly differently the whole semantic and conceptual apparatus
over which it also "passes." Were we to do so, we could dispense with the vrhole
motif of the accidental constitution of the essence of modern metaphysics. (There's
.no way of countering this through the empirical fact that, right up until the end
of the empire, what was calle� "philosophy" usually spoke in Greek. Either it
wasn't philosophy that was speaking, or Greece was already philosophically Latin.)
4. Georges Dumezil, Idees romaines (Paris: Gallimard, 1969), 41. We could
hardly do better than cite Dumezil's indispensable analysis. Except perhaps to add
a question about "juice" (as in the j uice of a fruit, etc.), to which, as a homonym
ofjUs, some philologues have lent an etymological synonymy (through the senses
of "binding" and "mixing") with the jus of right. Something that might well sup.,.
port the Hegelian thesis of right as dissolution.
5. This is the problem of origin-which, it should probably be said, doesn't re
ally belong to right or, if it does, does not do so at the point at which right refers
to philosophy the question of its own origin (as at the start of a treatise on right,
for example), but only at the point, with which we are concerned here, at which it
becomes philosophy. At this point something happens to the metaphysical question
of origin. For the moment, allow me simply to say that if the authority of the
judge (his imperium) is itself a case, one whose right would need to be articulated,
this <;ase isn't an exceptional one (precisely not, in fact). Right prevents any law of
exception, any privilegium; see, e.g., Jacques ElIul, " Sur l'artificialite du droit et la
droit d'exception," Archives de philosophie du droit IQ (1965). The status ofjudex
can be conferred, by right, on anyone whatsoever, a status whose investitur.e can
not be sheltered from the law. In this, the judge is already profoundly different
from the philosopher as well as from the poet, both of whom Plato terms natures.
6. Spinoza, Tractatus de intellectus emendatione, §36: "De recta methodo
cognoscendi" ("On the Improvement of the Understanding").
7. Right says; it doesn't execute. It never "produces" anything other than it
self-or other than the fiction of its identity in the permanent mobility of its ju
risprudence.
8. The totalitarianism of the modern State comes from Rome only through a
major shift of nature and not of degree; namely, the unlimiting of a procedure
whose strictly Latin figure is (by right . . . ) that of an incessant and multiple fix
ing of limits (juridical, cultural, ethnic, linguistic, etc.). Rome tried-within the
walls of its limer-to constitute the juridical unity of an internal network of lim
its, of boundaries and differences. Ultimately [a la limite] . . . we would have to
say that right sanctions or signs for the differential divisions, whereas the State,
having transformed procedure into (organic, historical) process, absorbs them.
9. See Duguip, Traite de droit constitutionnel (Paris, 192�), vol. 2, §28; and, for
Notes 337
apart from a tribunal of exception? Here, I have not been able to dwell on the law
itsel£ Yet if it is possible to suggest that the lex is never the strict equivalent of a lo
gos, then we can't avoid saying that, in one way or another, every judicial institu
tion operates in the last instance according to a rule of exception and thus accord
ing to the form that right excludes. The troubling ambiguity of right would stem
from its having, in principle, withdrawn from the State and, at the same time,
opened the very possibility of the tribunal of exception. In many ways, Kant's en
terprise also represents, by virtue of its audacity, metaphysics' own tribunal of ex
ception. Similar ambiguities will doubtless begin to unravel only once it has be
come possible for us to think how logos constitutes our own law ofexception.
19. Do we need to point out that Kant's discourse, like every metaphysical dis
course, stems from the primitive appropriation of its reason alone--and by the
primitive warding off of any accident that might affect it? What we need to hold
onto here is that, despite all this, an accident does happen-and happens in that
primitive operation itsel£
20. Heidegger, whose reading ofKant is clearly decisive here, stands in marked
contrast. See, in particular, the debate with Cassirer; Martin Heidegger, "Davoser
Disputation zwischen Ernst Cassirer und Martin Heidegger," in Heidegger, /(ant
und das Problem der Metaphysik, Gesamtausgabe 3 (Frankfurt a. M.: Vittorio
Klostermann, 1991), 274-96; translated by Richard Taft as "Davos Disputation be
tween Ernst Cassirer and Martin Heidegger," in Heidegger, /(ant and the Problem
ofMetaphysics (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1990), 171-85.
21. Scientific "law" presents itself, so to speak, as the opposite of or as opposed
to juridical law. Whereas the latter articulates an "area of action or claim," the for
mer-which doesn't simply disobey the structure of articulation but also excludes
it to the point where its utterances are held to be valid only insofar as they are in
dependent of the one who utters them-establishes what is (regardless of the sta
tus of this "being") within a given area, the area engendered by the subject (of)
science. As a philosophical, ethical, or political question, the question of the "right
of science" is always badly put insofar as it ignores the profound heterogeneity that
exists between the two orders. Science either has all rights, or it has none.
22. KrV B xiii.
23. KrV A 712; B 740.
24. KrV B xii.
25. As well as "on paper . . . but . . . completely a priori" (KrV A 713; B 741).
Another essay would need to be devoted to a general arialysis of schematization.
26. KrV A 33; B 50.
27. KrV A 132; B 171.
28. KrV A 134; B 173-
29. KrV A 134; B 173-
30. KrV A 135; B 174.
31. KrV A 135; B 174.
32. Despite certain variations in the Kantian vocabulary (see A. de Coninck,
Notes 339
L'Anarytique transcendantale de Kant [Louvain, 1955], I: 128 ff.), one notes that the
a priori forms of sensibility are supplied,. not by deduction, but by exposition.
33. KrV A 126.
34. See Luc Ferry et al., eds., Rejouer le politique (Paris: GalliIee, 1981), 95.
35. Jean-Luc Nancy, "The Free Voice of Man," in Philippe Lacoue-Labarthe
and Jean-Luc Nancy, eds., Retreating the Politica� ed. Simon Sparks.
CHAPTER 9
. I. Besides, the editors of the dictionary for which this article was first written
have already settled the matter by commissioning it.
2. See Martin Heidegger, "Brief iiber den 'Humanismus,'" Wegmarken, Gesam
tausgabe 9 (Frankfurt a. M.: Vittorio KIostermann, 1992), 313; translated by Frank
A. Capuzzi in collaboration with J. Glenn Gray, in Martin Heidegger, Basic Writ
ings, ed. Qavid Farrel! Krel! (London: Routledge, 1993), 213; henceforth cited as
BW.
3. BW 217·
4. Martin Heidegger, Sein und Zeit (Tiibingen: Max Niemeyer, 1993). Hence
forth cited as SZ.
5. Except for two instances of authenticite, Nancy uses propre ("proper, own,
authentic") and its derivations for Heidegger's use of terms based on the root eigen
(especially eigentlich and Eigentlichkeit). The special case of Ereignis is addressed in
the text.-Trans.
6. BW 220.
7. SZ 152•
8. BW 220.
9. BW 2I8.
10. BW 217.
H. BW 220.
12. BW 218.
13.BW 225.
14.See BW 225ff.
15.See Kant und das Problem der Metaphysik, Gesamtausgabe 3 (Frankfurt a.
M.: Vittorio KIostermann, 1991), 207 and §§38-41. Henceforth cited as KPM.
16. BW 26.
-, , . �. '
340 Notes
CHAPTER 10
I. Immanuel Kant, Erste Fassung der Einleitung in die Kritik der Urteilskraft, in
Gesammelte Schriften, ed. Koniglich PreuBischen Akademie der Wissenschafren
(Berlin: Waiter de Gruyter, 1902-), 20: 195-251. [Except for the Critique ofPure
Reason, where I follow the standard A and B pagination, all references to Kant are
to this edition, henceforth cited as Ak, followed by volume and page number.
Quotes from the third Critique are taken from Immanuel Kant, Critique ofJudg-
342 Notes
ment, trans. and introd. Werner S. Pluhar (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987). Quotes
from the first Critique are taken from Immanuel Kant, Critique ofPure Reason,
trans. Norman Kemp Smith (New York: St. Martin's, 1965); those of the second
Critique are from Immanuel Kant, Critique ofPractical Reason, trans. and ed.
Mary Gregor (Cambri4ge: Cambridge University Press, 1997). The page number
of the English translation follows that of the Akademie edition; the translation has
occasionally been modified in order to correspond more closely to the French
translation that Nancy quotes.-Trans.]
2. Ak 20: 195 1 385.
3. Ak 20: 203 1 392.
4. Ak 20: 201 1 390.
5. Ak 20: 205-6 1.394.
6. Ak 20: 206 1 395.
7. Ibid.
8. Ibid.
9. Ibid.
10. Ibid.
II. Ak 20: 206-7 1 395.
12. On the question of the "case" in general in Kant (even though the word
"case [Fa!!]" does not figure explicitly in the German text), see the work in
progress of Simon Zavadil, a fragment of which appears as 'TEvenement de la
contingence, ou les limites du principe de raison," Les Cahiers Philosophiques de
Strasbourg 5 (1997), 21I-32. [See also "Lapsusjudicii," above.-Ed.]
13. See the preface to the Critique ofPractical Reason, Ak 5: 4-14 1 3-II.
14. On matters of fact (scibilia), see §91 of the Critique ofJudgment. This sec-
tion calls for a detailed commentary, which I cannot provide here.
15. Critique ofPractical Reason, Ak 5: 71-89 / 62-75.
16. Ak 5: 73 1 64·
17· Ak 5: 77 1 66-67·
18. Ak 5: 80 1 68.
19. Critique ofJudgment, Ak 5: 289 1 154.
20. Ak 5: 222 / 67.
21. Ibid.
22. We would need to move from the passages on pleasure in the Introduction
and certain other sections of the Critique
. ofJudgment to the Metaphysics ofMorals
and the Anthropology (§64f).
23. Critique ofJudgment, Ak 5: 187 / 26-27.
24. Ibid.
25. See, in particular, the "General Comment on Teleology."
26. Ak 5: 482n. 1 377n. This is the only footnote in the "General Comment."
27. Ak 5: 187 1 27·
28. Critique ofPure ReasOn,A2I6, B263 1 237.
29. See the first-edition Transcendental Deduction, second section. .
Notes 343
CHAPTER II
NOTE: This essay has been reprinted from "The Sublime Offering," by Jean-.
Luc Nancy, in Ofthe Sublime: Presence in Question, ed. Jeffrey S. Librei:t, by per
missIon of the State University ofNew York Press. © 1993 State University of New
York. All rights reserved. This book originally appeared in French as Jean-Franc;:ois
Courtine et al, Du sublime (Paris: Belin, 1988); the essay was reprinted in Jean-Luc
Nancy, Une Penstfefinie (Paris: Galilee, 1990), 147-96.
I. The sublime is in fashion in Paris and among the theoreticians, who often
refer to it in recent years (Marin, Derrida, Lyotard, Deleuze, Deguy), as well as
in Los Angeles and among the artists: for example, one of the them entitled a re
cent exposition and performance "The Sublime" (Michael Kelley, April 1984).
One finds further evidenc� of this fashion in Berlin (Hamacher), Rome, and
Tokyo. (Not to speak of the use of the word "sublime" in the most current every
day speech.) As for the texts, they are numerous and dispersed. Let it suffice to in
dicate their authors here, my indebtedness to whose works it would be impossi
ble to convey adequately. But I do not intend to add to theirs one more
interpretation of the sublime. I attempt rather to come to terms with what it is
that they share and that the epoch shares in this fashion: that offers us all up to a
thought of the sublime.
2. This perhaps excessively concise formula adopts the general perspective of
Samuel Monk's classic study The Sublime: A Study of Critical Theqries in Eigh
teenth-Century England (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1960), which
has been reconsidered with respect to France by Theo9,ore A. Litman in Le Sub
lime en France (P�ris: A. G. Nizet, 1971) from both a historical and an aesthetic
conceptual perspective. My contribution is neither historical nor aesthetic.
3. I must not omit to mention at least once the name of Nietzsche, who
thought, in one sense or several, something of the sublime, even if he hardly the-
matized it as such. .
4. Walter Benjamin, Gesammelte Schrifen t (Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp, 1980),
. .
� C ��
5. Martin Heidegger, "Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes," Holzwege (Frankfurt
a. M.: Vittorio Klostermann, 1980), 42; translated by Albert Hofstadter as "The
Origin of the Work of AIt," in Heidegger, Poetry, Language, Thought (New York:
Harper & Row, 1971), 56.
6. Theodor W. Adorno, Asthetische Theorie (Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkarnp, 1973),
292; translated by C. Lenhart as Aesthetic Theory, ed. ' Gretel Adorno and Rolf
Tiedemann (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1984), 280.
7. Georges Bataille, Oeuvres, vol. 7 (Paris: Gallimard, 1970).
8. Maurice Blanchot, "La Litteratilre et le droit a la mort," in La Part dufeu
(Paris: Gallimard, 1949), 294; translated by Lydia Davis as "Literature and the
Right to Death," in The Gaze ofOrphetts, ed. P. Adams Sitney, with a preface by
Geoffrey Hartman (Barrytown, N.Y.: Station Hill, 1981), 22.
9. This means at once that these two modes of thought are opposed to each
other and that the thought of the sublime doubtless infiltrates and secretly disqui
ets the ,thqught of the end of art. But I will not attempt to show this here. In turn,
where Hegel explicitly speaks of the sublime, he does not bring anything of the
thought of the sublime to bear (see Paul de Man, "Hegel on the Sublime," in Dis
placement: Derrida andAfer, t ed. Mark Krupnick [Bloomington: Indiana Univer
sity Press, 1983], 139-53).
10. See Critique de la foculte dejuger, trans. A. Philonenko (Paris: Vrin, 1986,
§§ 23-29, 84, H4; Critique ofJudgment, trans. J. H. Bernard (New York: Hafner,
1951), 82-120, for most of the allusions to Kant's text which follow. The reference
here is to §23, 84 / 82.
H. The word can be found, e.g., in the Critique ofJudgment, §22, 80 / 78.
12. q, §6, 34 / 24.
13· q, §2, 50 / 39.
14· q, §23, 86 / 85·
15. CJ, §27, 98 / 98. "In the aesthetic evaluation of grandeur, the concept of
number ought to be kept at a distance or transformed."
'\
16. In this sense, all that in Kant still derives from a classic theory of analogy
and the symbol does not belong to the deep logic of which I am speaking here.
l? The latter formula is Lyotard's; see Le Difftrend (Paris: Minuit, 1983),
H8-19; translated by Georges Van Den Abbeele as The Differend: Phrases in Dis
pute (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1988), 77-78. The former for
mula is Derrida's, from "Le Parergon," in La verite en peinture (Paris: Flammarion,
1978); translated by Geoffrey Bennington and Ian McLeod as The Truth in Paint
ing (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987), 131-32. They are certainly not
wrong, and they comment rigorously, together or the one against the other, upon
the text ofKant. I do not attempt to discuss them here, preferring to take a differ
ent course�along the edge of presentation, but at a distance, and because pres
entation itself distances itself from itsel£ The political function of the sublime in
Lyotard would call for a different discussion, which I shall undertake elsewhere.
18. Kant does not fail to indicate an aesthetic direction combining the two mo
tifs: a sublime genre distinct from all others, and the determination of this genre
as a kind of total work of art. He in fact evokes the possibility of a "presentation of
Notes 345
the sublime" in the fine arts in terms of the "combination of the fine arts in one
single product," and he then indicates three forms: verse tragedy, the didacticpoem,
and the oratorio. There would, of course, be much to say about this. I shall content
myself here with noting that it is not quite the same thing as Wagner's
Gesamtkunstwerk. More particularly, Kant's three forms seem to turn around poetry
as the mode of presentation of destiny, thought, and prayer, respectively, and it
does not seem to be a matter of a "total" presentation.
19 · C] §26, 174; 91.
20. One ought to analyze the relations between Kant's Bestrebung and Freud's
Vorlust, that is, this "preliminary pleasure," whose paradox consists in its tension
and which occupies an important place in Freud's theory of the beautiful and of art.
21. C], §29, 105 / 128. I prefer, on this point, the first edition.
22. Hegel provides a kind of figure of this feeling by way of the other in his
discussion of the infant in the womb of its mother: See Jean-Luc Nancy, "Identite
et tremblement," in Hypnoses (Paris: GaliIee, 1984), 13-47; translated by Brian
Holmes as "Identity and Trembling," in Jean-Luc Nancy, The Birth to Presence,
trans. Brian Holmes and others (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1993, 9-35) .
. 23. I am choosing to ignore here the economy of sacrifice, which is quite visible
in Kant's text, where the imagination acquires "an extension and power 'greater
than that which it has lost." I do not pretend that the offering is simply "pure
loss." But at the heart of the economy (of presence, art, thought), it [raJ offers it
self also, there is also offering, neither lost nor gained.
24. Gilles Deleuze, Cinema, vot I, L'Image-mouvement (Paris: Minuit, 1983),
69; translated by Hugh Tornlinson and Barbara Habberjam as Cinema, vol. I, The
Movement-Image (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1986), 46.
25. I suspend here an analysis I pursue in L'Experience de la liberte (Paris:
Galilee, 1988); translated by Bridget McDonald as The Experience of Freedom
(Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1993).
, 26. C], §29, 106 / 109-10.
27. Darbieten or Darbietung ("offering") would be the word to substitute on
the register of the sublime for Darsteltung ("presentation"). But it is in each case a
matter of the dar, of a sensible "here" or "here it is."
28. See note 18, above.
29. It is remarkable that another Biblical commandment-the Fiat lux of
Genesis-had been already a privileged example of the sublime for Longinus and
for his classical commentators. From the one example to the other as from the one
commandment to the other, one can appreciate the continuity and the rupture.
30. See Jean-Luc Nancy, Le Discours de la syncope: 1. Logodaedalus (Paris:
'
Flammarion, 1976).
CHAPTER 12
NOTE: The title of the original French text is "I:Amour eclats." The word eclat
' ,. � �
. .'. . �. , ,:. " . ' .' ; �
346 Notes
should be read in all its outbursts. The word can mean, and appears here as: shat
ter, piece, splinter, glimmer, flash, spark, burst, outburst, explosion, brilliance, daz
zle, and splendor.-Trans. .
The English translation of this essay originally appeared as "Shattered Love," in
Jean-Luc Nancy, The Inoperative Community (Minneapolis: University of Min
nesota Press, 1991), 83-109. The French text can be found in Jean-Luc Nancy, Une
Penseefinie (Paris: GaliIee, 1990), 225-68.
1. The distinction that Nancy makes here is very easy'to render in French,
where abstract nouns may or may not be preceded by the definite article, depend
ing upon the context. Hence, Nancy is able to distinguish between "la pensee est
amour" and "la pensee est l'amour." In the first instance, love qualifies or describes
thinking; in the second, it is offered more as a definition of thinking: thinking is
love; it is identical with love.-Trans.
2. The French text reads, 'Tetre dans l'amour," but it is important to remem
ber that the English expression "being in love" does not translate literally into id
iomatic French. That might, then, be one of the meanings invoked here, but it is
not necessarily the sole or dominant one.-Trans.
3. Rene Char, Hypnos Waking, trans. Jackson Mathews (New York: Random
House, 1956), 59.
4. Roland Barthes, A Lovers Discourse: Fragments, trans. Richard Howard
(New York: Farrar, Strauss and Giroux, 1978), 148.
5. See Emmanuel Levinas, Totality and Infinity, trans. Alphonso Lingis (Pitts
burgh: Duquesne University Press, 1969), 50fE
6. There is no adequate translation for the French verb jouir. Translated as "to
enjoy," jouir loses its sexual connotation; translated as "to come," it loses its rela
tion to "joy." Following a suggestion by Nancy, I have created a new verb to trans-
.
late jouir : "to joy."-Trans.
7. The citation is in English in the original.-Trans.
CHAPTER 13
Press, 1993), and, along with Glissant, all the other "creoles" of art and literature,
for whom Salman Rushdie could also be considered an emblem.
(3) The vision of a "universal" hybridization or mixed race presented in Michel
Serres's Le Tiers-Instruit (Paris: Bourin, 1991), a vision that poses many of the prob
lems elicited by Bruno Tackels in "Ou est le metis?" Corresporulances 4, "Le(s)
Metissage(s)," UFR des Arts (Strasbourg: Presses Universitaires de Strasbourg,
1993).
2. Bernardo Bertolucci, The Last Tango in Paris.
3. Fernand Braudel, La Mediterran!e (Paris: Fiammarion, 1985), 134.
4. See, but with a different value placed on the "ipse," Gerard Granel, "Ipse
Dasein?" in La Ph!nom!nologie aux confins (Mauvezin: T. E. R., 1992).
CHAPTER 14
I. GilIes Deleuze and Felix Guattari, Quest-ce que la philosophie? (Paris: Mi
nuit, 1991), 103; translated by Graham BurcheII and Hugh Tomlinson as What Is
Philosophy? (London: Verso, 1994), 108.
2. See Friedrich Nietzsche, Zur Genealogie der Moral in Kritische Studienaus
gabe, ed. Giorgio CoIli and Mazzino Montinari (Berlin: Walter de Gruyrer, 1988)
- 5: 293-94. Henceforth cited as KSA, followed by volume and page number, then
the page number of the English translation. Translated by Walter Kaufman as On
the Genealogy ofMorals (New York: Vintage, 1967), 59-60. See also KSA 5: 79-81;
translated by Walter Kaufman as Beyond Good andEvil(New York: Vintage, 1992),
74-76.
3. KSA 5: 292 1 Genealogy, 58.
4. KSA 5: 79 1 Beyond Good andEvil 72.
5. KSA 5: 81 1 Beyond Good and Evil 74.
, _
translated by Jan Plug as Jacques Derrida, Whos Afraid ofPhilosophy? Righi to Phi
losophy I (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002), 66.
12. See Maurice Blanchot, L'Amitie (l.'aris: Gallimard, 1989), 326; translated by
Elizabeth Rottenberg as Friendship (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1997),
289, 326. See, too, Thc;odor W. Adorno, Aesthetic Theory, trans. Robert Hullot
Kentor (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997), 39. .
13. Ernst Tugendhat, Self-consciousness and Self-determination, trans. Paul Stern
(Cambridge: The MIT Press, 1986), 297-98.
CHAPTER 15
Early Thought
Gianni Vanimo, Nietzsche: An Introduction
';acques Derrida:, Negotiations: Interventiom and Interviews; I97I-I998,
ed; Elizabeth Rottenberg
Bren Levinson, The Ends ofLiterature: Post-tramition and Neoliberalism in the
wrtke ofthe "Boom"
Timothy J. Reiss, Agaimt Autonomy: Global Dialectics ofCultural Exchange
Hent de Vries and Samuel Weber, eds., Religion and Media
\.-.ri _ ; '_:"···
� ',' .
.... . .
�
- NikIas Luhmann, Theories ofDistinction: Redescribing the Des'; tions
ofModernity, ed. and introd. William Rasch
-Johannes Fabian, Anthropology with an Attitude: Critical Essays
Michel Henry, IAm the Truth: Toward a Philosophy ofChristianity
GiI Anidjar, "Our Place in Al-Andalus": Kabbalah, Philosophy, Literature in Arab-
Jewish Letters
Helene Cixous and Jacques Derrida, Veils
F. R. Ankersmit, Historical Representation
F. R. Ankersmit, Political Representation
Elissa Marder, Dead Time: Temporal Disorders in the wake ofModernity
(Baudelaire and Flaubert)
Reinhart Koselleck, The Practice ofConceptual History: Timing History, Spacing
Concepts
NikIas Luhmann, The Reality ofthe Mass Media
Hubert Damisch, A Childhood Memory by Piero della Francesca
Hubert Damisch, A Theory of/Cloud/: Toward a History ofPainting
Jean-Luc Nancy, The Speculative Remark (One ofHegel's Bons Mots)
Jean-Fran�ois Lyotard, SoundproofRoom: Malraux! Anti-Aesthetics
Jan Patocka, Plato and Europe
Hubert Damisch, Skyline: The Narcissistic City
Isabel Hoving, In Praise ofNew Travelers: Reading Caribbean Migrant WOmen ..
Writers
-:- Richard Rand, ed., Futures: OfDerrida
William Rasch, Niklas Luhmann's Modernity: The Paradox ofSystem .
Differentiation
Jacques Derrida and Anne Dufourmantelle, OfHospitality
Jean-Fran�ois Lyotard, The Confession ofAugustine
Kaja Silverman, WOrld Spectators
Samuel Weber, Institution and Interpretation: Expanded Edition
Jeffrey S. Librett, The Rhetoric ofCultural Dialogue: Jews and Germans
in the Epoch ofEmancipation
Ulrich Baer, Remnants ofSong: Trauma and the Experience ofModernity
in Charles Baudelaire and Paul Celan
-Samuel C. Wheeler III, Deconstruction as Analytic Phllosophy
David S. Ferris, Silent Urns: Roma�ticism, Hellenism, Modernity
Rodolphe Gasche, OfMinimal Thing;: Studies on the Notion ofRelation
�Sarah Winter, Freud and the Institution ofPsychoanalytic Knowledge
Samuel Weber, The Legend ofFreud: Expanded Edition
- - ,:,:4l