The Mixed Life of Platos Philebus in Psellos The Contemplation in Saint Maximus The Confessor
The Mixed Life of Platos Philebus in Psellos The Contemplation in Saint Maximus The Confessor
The Mixed Life of Platos Philebus in Psellos The Contemplation in Saint Maximus The Confessor
UDC: 141.131:94(495.02)"10"
DOI: 10.2298/ZRVI1350399L
FREDERICK LAURITZEN
(Fondazione per le Scienze Religiose, Bologna)
the 1060s, it constitutes important evidence of the study of platonic ethics in eleventh
century Byzantium.
At first sight the passage simply proposes the aurea mediocritas, the middle of
the road attitude which is famously associated with Aristotle. A closer reading reveals
the question of neoplatonic commentaries on Plato rather than Aristotle. Psellos’ text
is the following:
Τρεῖς γὰρ μερίδας ταῖς τῶν ψυχῶν προσαρμόζω κατανοῶν καταστάσεσι, τὴν
μὲν, ὅταν αὐτὴ βιῴη καθ’ ἑαυτὴν, ἀπολυθεῖσα τοῦ σώματος, ἀτενῆ τε καὶ οὐ
πάνυ τὸ ἐνδόσιμον ἔχουσαν, τὰς δέ γε λοιπὰς μερίδας τῷ μετὰ σώματος αὐτῆς
βίῳ κατείληφα· εἰ μὲν γὰρ τὴν μέσην στᾶσα ζωὴν μεγαλοπαθής τε καὶ πολυ-
παθὴς, ὥσπερ ἐν κύκλῳ τὸ ἀκριβὲς κέντρον αἱροῖτο, τὸν πολιτικὸν ἀπεργάζεται
ἄνθρωπον, οὔτε θεία τις ἀκριβῶς γενομένη ἢ νοερὰ, οὔτε φιλοσώματος καὶ
πολυπαθής· (Psellos Chronographia 6a.8.1–9 Impellizzeri)
For when I think of three parts of the souls, I liken them to their situations. The
first, when it lives by itself, separated from the body, keeping a strict and rather
unyielding [nature]. I understand the other parts as living with the body. If the
soul with much and great suffering keeps a moderate life, as if it held the exact
centre in a circle, it forges the social (political) man. The soul is neither exactly
divine nor intellectual, nor is it attached to the body with great passions.
The first and third are defined by direct references to the Phaedo of Plato. Indeed
the expression ἀπολυθεῖσα τοῦ σώματος is a direct reference to Phaedo 65a1–2.5 Also
the expression φιλοσώματος comes from Phaedo 68c1.6 Plato is here defining the
philosopher as someone not concerned by his human passions in a base way, but is
rather superior to them. This is the solution also endorsed by Plotinus who is his de-
scription of the three types of man7, points out that the highest form is that which is
detached from bodily concerns.8 His idea is that part of the soul remains with the One
Aristotle, and the Neoplatonists, Leiden 2000.
5
Ἆρ’ οὖν πρῶτον μὲν ἐν τοῖς τοιούτοις δῆλός ἐστιν ὁ φιλόσοφος ἀπολύων ὅτι μάλιστα τὴν ψυχὴν
ἀπὸ τῆς τοῦ σώματος κοινωνίας διαφερόντως τῶν ἄλλων ἀνθρώπων; (Plato, Phaedo, 64e8–65a2, ed. J.
Burnet, Platonis opera vol. 1, Oxford 1900).
6
Οὐκοῦν ἱκανόν σοι τεκμήριον, ἔφη, τοῦτο ἀνδρός, ὃν ἂν ἴδῃς ἀγανακτοῦντα μέλλοντα
ἀποθανεῖσθαι, ὅτι οὐκ ἄρ’ ἦν φιλόσοφος ἀλλά τις φιλοσώματος; ὁ αὐτὸς δέ που οὗτος τυγχάνει ὢν καὶ
φιλοχρήματος καὶ φιλότιμος, ἤτοι τὰ ἕτερα τούτων ἢ ἀμφότερα (Plato, Phaedo, 68b8–c3).
7
Plotinus, Enneads 5.9.1, edd. P. Henry, H.-R. Schwyzer, Plotini opera, Leiden 1951–1973.
8
Τρίτον δὲ γένος θείων ἀνθρώπων δυνάμει τε κρείττονι καὶ ὀξύτητι ὀμμάτων εἶδέ τε ὥσπερ ὑπὸ
ὀξυδορκίας τὴν ἄνω αἴγλην καὶ ἤρθη τε ἐκεῖ οἷον ὑπὲρ νεφῶν καὶ τῆς ἐνταῦθα ἀχλύος καὶ ἔμεινεν ἐκεῖ
τὰ τῇδε ὑπεριδὸν πάντα ἡσθὲν τῷ τόπῳ ἀληθινῷ καὶ οἰκείῳ ὄντι, ὥσπερ ἐκ πολλῆς πλάνης εἰς πατρίδα
εὔνομον ἀφικόμενος ἄνθρωπος (Plotinus, Enneads, 5.9.1.16–21).
FREDERICK LAURITZEN: The mixed life of Plato’s Philebus in Psellos’ … 401
and therefore the rest of the soul should detach itself from the passions of the body.9
Indeed Gerd van Riel has pointed out that the interest in this mixed life described first
in the Philebus occurs starting with Iamblichus (ca. 245– ca 325).10
Psellos in Chronographia 6a8 does not limit himself to a twofold division as
seen in Phaedo 65–68, but adds an intermediary type which seems to be based on the
threefold division of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics:
τρεῖς γάρ εἰσι μάλιστα οἱ προύχοντες, ὅ τε νῦν εἰρημένος καὶ ὁ πολιτικὸς καὶ
τρίτος ὁ θεωρητικός. (Aristoteles, Ethica Nicomachea 1095b17–19, ed. I.
Bywater, Aristotelis ethica Nicomachea, Oxford 1894)
The main ones are for the most part three: the one mentioned [the one who loves
the life of pleasure], and the politician and third the contemplative [philosopher]
Psellos combines this middle type, the politician with the one which is inter-
mediary between two extremes thus establishing that the political man is also the
representative of the golden means described by Aristotle in the Nicomachean Ethics:
Ὅτι μὲν οὖν ἐστὶν ἡ ἀρετὴ ἡ ἠθικὴ μεσότης, καὶ πῶς, καὶ ὅτι μεσότης δύο
κακιῶν, τῆς μὲν καθ’ ὑπερβολὴν τῆς δὲ κατ’ ἔλλειψιν, καὶ ὅτι τοιαύτη ἐστὶ
διὰ τὸ στοχαστικὴ τοῦ μέσου εἶναι τοῦ ἐν τοῖς πάθεσι καὶ ἐν ταῖς πράξεσιν,
ἱκανῶς εἴρηται. διὸ καὶ ἔργον ἐστὶ σπουδαῖον εἶναι. ἐν ἑκάστῳ γὰρ τὸ μέσον
λαβεῖν ἔργον, οἷον κύκλου τὸ μέσον οὐ παντὸς ἀλλὰ τοῦ εἰδότος (Arist. Eth.
Nic. 1109a20–26 Bywater).
Virtue is a moral middle ground, an intermediary of two evils, one by excess
and another by defect. It is enough to say that it is such because it is aimed at
the middle in passions and actions. Therefore it is a serious matter. To seize in
each matter the middle ground, as the middle of a circle, is not of everyone, but
of he who knows.
This is the theory of the golden means, aurea mediocritas, where virtue is de-
fined by an equal distance from extremes. In both Aristotle’s passages and that of
Psellos one sees the threefold division, with the reference to the political man and the
image of the centre of a circle. Thus two passages, Phaedo 65–68 and Nicomachean
Ethics 1095b are at the root of the passage of the Chronographia. However Psellos
adds a number of qualifications:
1) strict (ἀτενή) not yielding (οὐ ἐνδόσιμον) divine (θεία) intelligible (νοερά)
2) middle of the road (μέσος)
3) attached to the body (φιλοσώματος) full of passions (πολυπαθής) loving
pleasure (φιλήδονος)
9
Καὶ εἰ χρὴ παρὰ δόξαν τῶν ἄλλων τολμῆσαι τὸ φαινόμενον λέγειν σαφέστερον, οὐ πᾶσα οὐδ’
ἡ ἡμετέρα ψυχὴ ἔδυ, ἀλλ’ ἔστι τι αὐτῆς ἐν τῷ νοητῷ ἀεί· τὸ δὲ ἐν τῷ αἰσθητῷ εἰ κρατοῖ, μᾶλλον δὲ εἰ
κρατοῖτο καὶ θορυβοῖτο, οὐκ ἐᾷ αἴσθησιν ἡμῖν εἶναι ὧν θεᾶται τὸ τῆς ψυχῆς ἄνω. (Plotinus, Enneads,
4.8.8.1–6). Against this interpretation see Proclus, Elements of Theology, proposition 211.
10
D. O’ Meara, Lectures neoplatoniciennes du Philebe, ed. M. Dixsaut, Fêlure du plaisir, vol. 2,
Paris 1999, 194; G. van Riel, Damascius, Commentaire sur le Philèbe de Platon, Paris 2009, xxxiv.
402 ЗРВИ L (2013) 399–409
One should not forget that the aim of this passage is to discredit Leo
Paraspondylos11 who seemed too strict and yet was dealing with politics, as a form of
prime minister, especially in the years 1056–1057. He seemed to be too lofty to be a
political man according to the definition of the second group. Thus the first abstract
and theoretical life is contrasted with the third type of the lowly and earthly life.
Psellos believes that political and concrete actions can be dealt with the second type
of life. This is not the result of a compromise, but rather of a different opinion about
the nature of man and philosophy. The second type of life is tied to the body but not
exclusively. Indeed it is a mixed type. It is a life which is both theoretical and practi-
cal. Plato had referred to this in the Philebus:12
νικῶντα μὲν ἔθεμέν που τὸν μεικτὸν βίον ἡδονῆς τε καὶ φρονήσεως. (Plato
Philebus 27d1–2 Burnet)
We considered earlier on that the mixed life of pleasure and wisdom is successful.
Ὅτι ὁ μὲν μικτὸς βίος ἔχει τὰς τοῦ αἱρετοῦ ἰδιότητας, μόνος γὰρ τέλεός τε καὶ
ἱκανός ἐστι καὶ ἐφετός· ὁ δὲ νοῦς τὰς γνωστικὰς ἰδιότητας ἔχει· ἡ δὲ ψυχὴ πρώ-
τη τὰς ἡδονικάς. εἰ γὰρ καὶ ἔστιν ἐν τῷ νῷ ἡ ἡδονή, ἀλλ’ οὐσία ἐστὶ τοῦ νοῦ καὶ
οἶον νόησις· οὐδὲν γὰρ ἐν αὐτῷ διῃρημένον οὕτως ὥστε κατ’ ἄλλο μὲν νοεῖν,
κατ’ ἄλλο δὲ ἥδεσθαι. (Damascius in Philebum 257 Van Riel)
The mixed way of life has the characteristics of the preferable, for it is the only
life that is perfect, adequate and desirable; intelligence has the characteristics
of cognition; while the soul is the first to show those of pleasure. It is true that
pleasure also exists in intelligence, but as the essence of intelligence and a kind
of thought; for there is, in intelligence, no division that could make thought and
pleasure distinct functions (tr. Westerink in G.L. Westerink Damascius Lectures
on the Philebus Westbury 2010)
Ὅτι οὐ τὸ ἀγαθὸν ἡδονή. ἦν γὰρ ἂν καὶ δίχα γνώσεως ἀγαθόν· νῦν δὲ οὐδεὶς ἂν
ἕλοιτο ἀνόητος ὢν ἥδεσθαι, μηδὲ τελέως ἡδόμενος· οὔτε γὰρ ἐπὶ παρελθόντι,
μνήμης οὐκ οὔσης, οὔτε ἐπὶ μέλλοντι, μὴ οὔσης ἐλπίδος, οὔτε ἐπὶ τῷ παρόντι,
11
On Leo Paraspondylos see E. Vries-van der Velden, Les amitiés dangereuses: Psellos et Léon
Paraspondylos, BSl 60 (1999) 315–350.
12
Plato, Philebus, 22d6, 25b5, 27b8, 27d1, 27d8, 61b6.
13
G. van Riel, Pleasure and the Good Life: Plato, Aristotle, and the Neoplatonists, Leiden 2000.
FREDERICK LAURITZEN: The mixed life of Plato’s Philebus in Psellos’ … 403
λογισμοῦ μὴ ὄντος· ἔπειτα οὐδὲ ἄνθρωπος ὢν οὐδὲ ζῷον αἰσθητικόν, ἀλλὰ τοι-
οῦτον οἷον ὁ θαλάττιος πνεύμων. (Damascius, In Philebum 83 Van Riel)
Pleasure is not the Good, for if it were, it would also be a good apart from
cognition. Actually, however, nobody would choose to feel pleasure without
having intelligence, even if the pleasure were perfect; for we cannot enjoy
the past without memory, nor the future without anticipation, nor the present
without reflection; and besides, one would no longer be a human being nor
an animal endowed with sense perception, but something like a sea-lung. (tr.
Westerink)
Ὅτι βιαιοτέρα ἡ τοῦ νοῦ μόνωσις καὶ ἀδυνατωτέρα· πολὺς γὰρ ὁ τῆς ἀληθεί-
ας ἔρως καὶ ἡ εὐπάθεια τῆς τεύξεως· καὶ ὅλως ἀεὶ τῇ ἀνεμποδίστῳ ἐνεργείᾳ
κατὰ φύσιν οὔσῃ σύνεστιν ἡδονή, ὥστε καὶ τῇ γνωστικῇ. ἀλλ’ ὅμως τῇ ἐπινοίᾳ
χωρισθεὶς ἀνέραστος ἔσται καὶ ἄχαρις ὁ νοῦς καὶ εὐκαταφρόνητος. δηλοῖ δὲ ἡ
γνῶσις τῶν <ἀδιαφόρων> ἀδιάφορος οὖσα καὶ ἡ τῶν <φευκτῶν> ἐναντία οὖσα
καὶ φευκτή (Damascius in Philebum 87 van Riel)
The isolation of intelligence is forced and impossible, even more so than in the
case of pleasure, for the love of truth is a strong emotion, and so is the joy of
attaining it. There is also the general rule that any undisturbed, i.e. natural
activity is attended by pleasure, so that this must be true of cognitive activity
too. Still, if divorced from pleasure at least theoretically, intelligence will be
unworthy of love, unattractive, despicable. This is proved by the fact that
knowledge of things [indifferent] is itself indifferent and knowledge of things
[to be shunned] is itself the opposite of desirable. (tr. Westerink)
These two passages represent the two extremes of Psellos’ equation. It is impor-
tant that he identifies the notion of φιλοσώματος with φιλήδονος. This is also carried
out in Proclus’ commentary on the Republic.14 He identifies the important of pleasure
as the aspect of life which is connected with passions (πάθη), and places emphasis on
great and numerous events as defining the life of the political man which implies ac-
cepting passions and what is external to the person. More interesting is that the next
step of Damascius’ commentary on the Philebus identifies the notion of mixed life
with the life described by Aristotle.
Ὅτι οὐδ’ ἂν ἀγαθὸς εἴη ὁ μὴ ἐπὶ ταῖς ἀγαθαῖς πράξεσιν ἡδόμενος οὐδὲ δίκαιος
ὁ μὴ τοῖς δικαίοις, ὥς φησιν Ἀριστοτέλης· ὥστε οὐδὲ θεωρητικός, φαίη ἄν, <ὁ
μὴ τῇ θεωρίᾳ>15 (Damascius In Philebum 88 Van Riel)
14
καὶ κατ’ αὐτὴν γίνεται φιλήδονον, πάσης ἡδονῆς εἰς φύσιν οὔσης ἀγωγῆς. (Proclus, In Rem
Publicam, 1.226.26–27, ed. W. Kroll, Procli Diadochi in Platonis rem publicam commentarii, Leipzig
1899–1901). Van Riel, Commentaire sur le Philèbe de Platon, civ.
15
<ὁ μὴ τῇ θεωρίᾳ> add. Westerink.
404 ЗРВИ L (2013) 399–409
A man cannot really be good without taking pleasure in good actions, nor just
without taking pleasure in justice, as Aristotle says [Eth. Nic. I9,1099a17–19];
and therefore not contemplative either, he may have added, [without taking
pleasure in contemplation] (tr. Westerink)
Psellos accepts the notion of the middle life of Aristotle as corresponding with
the mixed life of Plato’s Philebus and is therefore following a more platonic reading
of pleasure as an integral part of life. Moreover Damascius in his commentary on the
Philebus also defines the role of the πολιτικὸς ἄνθρωπος according to the mixed life:
Ὅτι ἡ μὲν πρώτη μίξις βίου ἐστὶ θεωρητικοῦ, ἐκ τῶν πρώτων ἡδονῶν καὶ τῶν
πρώτων γνώσεων· ἡ δὲ δευτέρα πολιτικοῦ, ὃς πασῶν δεῖται τῶν τεχνῶν καίτοι
τινὰς ἡδονὰς ἀναινόμενος (231.1–3 Westerink )
The first combination belongs to contemplative life, that of primary pleasures
and primary forms of knowledge; the second to social life, which needs all the
arts and crafts, though it rejects certain pleasures. (tr. Westerink)
This is helpful since Psellos also mentions the πολιτικὸς ἄνθρωπος as the mid-
dle ground between the hedonist and the intellectual.16 This particular passage of the
commentary on the Philbeus allows one to see that Psellos is actually proposing a
reading which is closer to that of Proclus rather than Damascius. In the commentary
to the Republic Proclus points out that pleasure is part of the ideal city.17
Psellos thought that the middle life, the social life, immersed in the natural
world was actually the one which would allow for a more precise contemplation,
since nature was a positive element in life. This is mentioned in the commentary on
the Philebus 518 and more importantly in Dionysius the Areopagite who says all crea-
tion is positive.19 One may add that a positive interpretation of nature is necessary for
the contemplation of nature endorsed by Maximus the Confessor.20 The life which is
both linked with the body and the mind is necessary both in ordinary life as well as
16
Psellos, Chronographia, 8a.7–8.
17
εἰ δέ τις τὴν μὲν εὐφροσύνην ἀφέλοι καὶ τὴν διὰ τῆς ἐνθέου μουσικῆς παιδείαν, τραπέζας δὲ
καὶ ἀπολαύσεις ἀμέτρους καὶ ἀμούσους καὶ πρὸς ἡδονὴν βλεπούσας αὐτὸν ἀποδέχεσθαι νομίζοι, πόρρω
που τὰ τοιαῦτα ὁ Σωκράτης εἰκότως εἶναί φησι τῆς ἑαυτοῦ πολιτείας· οὐ γὰρ θέμις ἐν εὐδαιμόνων πόλει
τὴν ἀπέραντον κρατεῖν ἡδονὴν καὶ τὸν τοῖς γαστριμάργοις προσήκοντα βίον. (Proclus, In rem publicam,
131.30–132.7).
18
Ὅτι ὁ σκοπὸς κατὰ Ἰάμβλιχον καὶ τοὺς περὶ τὸν Συριανὸν καὶ τὸν Πρόκλον περὶ τοῦ τελικοῦ
αἰτίου πᾶσι τοῖς οὖσιν, ὅ ἐστι περὶ τοῦ διὰ πάντων διήκοντος ἀγαθοῦ. (Damascius, In Philebum 5). See
also εἴγε κανών ἐστι Πρόκλειος τὰ ὑψηλότερα μὴ συμπαύεσθαι μήτε συνάρχεσθαι τοῖς κοιλοτέροις, ἀλλ’
ἐπὶ μείζονα πρόοδον προϊέναι, δίκην τριῶν ἀνίσων κατὰ τὴν δύναμιν τοξοτῶν καὶ τῶν ἰσχυροτέρων ἐπὶ
πολὺ τὸ βέλος ἀφιέντων. (Olympiodorus in Alcibiadem, 109.17–20, ed. L. G. Westerink, Olympiodorus,
Commentary on the first Alcibiades of Plato, Amsterdam 1956). See A. Lloyd, The anatomy of neopla-
tonism, Oxford 1988, 106–107.
19
Καὶ εἰ τὰ ὄντα πάντα ἐκ τἀγαθοῦ καὶ τἀγαθὸν ἐπέκεινα τῶν ὄντων, ἔστι μὲν ἐν τἀγαθῷ καὶ τὸ
μὴ ὂν ὄν, τὸ δὲ κακὸν οὔτε ὄν ἐστιν, εἰ δὲ μὴ οὐ πάντη κακόν, οὔτε μὴ ὄν, οὐδὲν γὰρ ἔσται τὸ καθόλου
μὴ ὄν, εἰ μὴ ἐν τἀγαθῷ κατὰ τὸ ὑπερούσιον λέγοιτο. (Dionysius Areopagita, De Divinis Nominibus,
4.19.163.20–23, ed. B. R. Suchla, Corpus Dionysiacum I: Pseudo-Dionysius Areopagita, De divinis no-
minibus, Berlin 1990).
20
Numerous essays on the subject. One may single out Ambigua 22 (Θεωρία τοῦ τε φυσικοῦ
καί τοῦ γραπτοῦ νόμου, καί τῆς αὐτῶν κατ᾿ ἐπαλλαγήν εἰς ἀλλήλους συνδρομῆς.) in PG 1128 D – 1133
FREDERICK LAURITZEN: The mixed life of Plato’s Philebus in Psellos’ … 405
contemplation.21 Psellos here is arguing a different point: that the person who wants
to understand reality and be a philosopher needs to live both with the visible and
invisible aspects of his life. Thus he endorses the mixed life in the way it had been
understood by Proclus.
The proof of such an interpretation of the mixed life is the passage which con-
cludes the paragraph and somehow explains it:
εἰ δὲ ταύτης παρατραπείη τῆς μεσότητος, καὶ μάλιστα προχωροῦσα τὴν πρὸς τὰ
πάθη κατάντη βιῴη ζωὴν, τὸ ἀπολαυστικὸν ἀποτελεῖ καὶ φιλήδονον· εἰ δέ τις
τῶν πάντων ὑπερκῦψαι δυνηθείη τοῦ σώματος καὶ τῆς νοερᾶς ἐπ’ ἄκρον σταίη
ζωῆς, τί κοινὸν αὐτῷ καὶ τοῖς πράγμασιν; «ἐξεδυσάμην γὰρ, φησὶν ἡ Γραφὴ,
τὸν χιτῶνά μου, πῶς ἐνδύσωμαι αὐτόν;» ἀναβήτω γὰρ ἐπ’ ὄρος ὑψηλὸν καὶ
μετέωρον καὶ μετὰ τῶν ἀγγέλων στήτω, ἵνα φωτὶ καταλάμποιτο μείζονι, ἀπό-
στροφον ἑαυτὸν καὶ ἀπότροπον τοῖς ἀνθρώποις καταστήσας· εἰ δ’ οὐδεὶς τῶν
πάντων τῆς φύσεως τοσοῦτον κατεκαυχήσατο, εἰ πολιτικὰς ὑποθέσεις τυχὸν
οὗτος πιστευθείη, πολιτικῶς μεταχειριζέσθω τὰ πράγματα, μηδὲ ὑποκρινέσθω
τὴν τοῦ κανόνος εὐθύτητα· οὐ γὰρ πάντες πρὸς τὴν ἰσότητα τῆς στάθμης ἀπη-
κριβώθησαν· ὅθεν εἰ τὴν λόξωσιν παραιτήσαιτο, ἀπώσατο καὶ τὸ ἑπόμενον
ταύτῃ εὐθύς. (Psellos, Chronographia 8a9–24 Impellizzeri)
If the soul turns away from this middle road and lives a life which degener-
ates towards passions, it accomplishes the pleasurable and hedonistic [way]. If
someone managed to look beyond the body and stood at the apex of the intel-
lectual life, what does it have in common with him or with reality? The Bible
says: “I shed my cloak, how I will wear it?”. May he climb on a high and lofty
mountain and may he stay with the angels, in order that he may be enlightened
by a greater light, turning away and refusing mankind. If no one boasts such a
nature, if he were to be entrusted with political affairs, may he deal with them
politically, and may he not be judged by the correctness of the law; for not all
have been precise by the accuracy of the measuring line. Therefore, if asked
something ambiguous, he immediately pushed away what followed it.
The biblical passage is from the Song of Songs 22 which Psellos quotes and which
had been used by Andrew of Crete23 and John of Damascus24 to refer to the incarnation
A. Another is Quaestiones et Dubia 64, ed. J. H. Declerck, Maximi Confessoris quaestiones et dubia,
Turnhout 1982, where the notion of the incarnation is important for the role of natural contemplation.
21
The importance of matter for contemplation is well known for Proclus since it was expressed
in Theurgy.
22
ἐξεδυσάμην τὸν χιτῶνά μου, πῶς ἐνδύσωμαι αὐτόν (Cant. 5.3.1 = Psellos, Chronographia,
6a8.14–15).
23
Τὸ πήλινον ἔνδυμα | τὸ τῆς σαρκός μου ἐξεδυσάμην· | ἀλλ’ αὐτὸς τὴν ἀφθαρσίαν σου | ἔνδυσόν
με, | ὅταν ἀναστήσῃς με, εὔσπλαγχνε, Andreas Cretensis, Canon de Requie, 147–151, ed. M. Arco Magrì,
L'inedito canon de requie di Andrea Cretense, Helikon 9–10 (1969–1970) 494–513.
24
«Ἐξεδυσάμην τὸν χιτῶνά μου, πῶς ἐνδύσομαι αὐτόν;» Ἐν τούτῳ γὰρ ὁ ὄφις οὐκ ἔσχε παρείσ-
δυσιν, οὗ τῆς ψευδοῦς ὀρεχθέντες θεώσεως τοῖς ἀνοήτοις συμπαρεβλήθημεν κτήνεσιν. Αὐτὸς γὰρ ὁ τοῦ
θεοῦ μονογενὴς υἱὸς θεὸς ὢν καὶ τῷ πατρὶ ὁμοούσιος ἐκ ταύτης τῆς παρθένου καὶ καθαρᾶς ἀρούρας
ἑαυτὸν πεπλαστούργηκεν ἄνθρωπον. Καὶ τεθέωμαι μὲν ὁ ἄνθρωπος, ὁ δὲ θνητὸς ἠθανάτισμαι καὶ τοὺς
δερματίνους χιτῶνας ἐκδέδυμαι· τὴν γὰρ φθορὰν ἀπημφίασμαι καὶ ἀφθαρσίαν περίκειμαι τῇ περιβολῇ τῆς
406 ЗРВИ L (2013) 399–409
of Christ, that God had taken a ‘human cloak’. Thus Jesus lived the mixed life, since
he combined the two natures, divine and human. The coordination of the spiritual and
bodily aspects of Christ was central to someone like Maximus the Confessor who
discusses it in the Ambigua Ad Thomam 5 among other places.25 It here where he
says that the two aspects of Jesus coexisted in his person. This was the solution given
to the question of monoergist controversy (the single activity of Christ).26 Psellos
also adds that such a person should go on a high mountain and contemplate the great
light while turning away from humans. Whatever the exact reference is27, it refers
to the distance between the physical world and that of contemplation of the divine.
Thus Psellos uses biblical interpretations to endorse the social, measured and mixed
life since it was the life of the two natures of Christ.28 One should not forget that the
intellectual and philosophical criticism contained in the neoplatonic references would
have been perceived as quite recherché. On the other hand the references to the two
natures of Christ would have been familiar to a much wider audience. Thus the bibli-
cal and theological attacks would have been immediately understood and taken as a
very direct criticism and would have made the academic understanding of the mixed
life immediately understandable.
Moreover some contemporary texts refer to the imitation of Christ, such as
poem 40 of Symeon the New Theologian (949–1022).29 In it Christ speaks in the first
person and explains how he took on ‘the cloak’ and that his followers should attempt
to suffer what he suffered as well.
ἐγὼ γὰρ ταῦτα δι’ ὑμᾶς ἔπαθον ἑκουσίως,
ἐσταυρώθην, ἀπέθανον θάνατον τῶν κακούργων,
καὶ δόξα κόσμου γέγονε ζωή τε καὶ λαμπρότης
καὶ νεκρῶν ἐξανάστασις καὶ καύχημα ἁπάντων (75)
τῶν πιστευσάντων εἰς ἐμὲ τὰ εἰς ἐμὲ ὀνείδη,
καὶ ὁ ἀσχήμων θάνατος ἔνδυμα ἀφθαρσίας
καὶ ἀληθοῦς θεώσεως πᾶσι πιστοῖς ὑπῆρξε.
διὸ καὶ οἱ μιμούμενοι τὰ ἐμὰ σεπτὰ πάθη
συμμέτοχοι ὑπάρξουσι καὶ τῆς θεότητός μου (80)
καὶ βασιλείας τῆς ἐμῆς ἔσονται κληρονόμοι
θεότητος. (John Damascenus, Oratio Secunda in in dormitionem sanctae Dei genitricis Mariae, 2.23–30,
ed. P. B. Kotter, Die Schriften des Johannes von Damaskos, vol. 5, Berlin – New York 1988).
25
B. Janssens, Maximi Confessoris Ambigua ad Thomam una cum Epistula secunda ad eundem,
Turnhout 2002.
26
F. Lauritzen, Pagan energies in Maximus the Confessor: the influence of Proclus on the Ad
Thomam 5, GRBS 52/2 (2012) 226–239
27
There may be an indirect reference to the Transfiguration on Mt. Tabor. On the question see
F. Lauritzen, Psellos the Hesychast: A Neoplatonic Reading of the Transfiguration on Mt Tabor, BSl 70
(2012) 167–180.
28
A similar argument was formulated by Psellos when writing his essays on Mt. Olympus around
1054–1055. See F. Lauritzen, Stethatos' Paradise in Psellos' ekphrasis on Mt. Olympos, VV 70 (2011)
139–151. The association of Plato with Maximus the Confessor is the topic of his letter to John Xiphilinos.
See U. Criscuolo, Michele Psello, Epistola a Giovanni Xifilino, Naples 1973.
29
H. Alfeyev, Symeon the New Theologian and the Orthodox Tradition, Oxford 1999.
FREDERICK LAURITZEN: The mixed life of Plato’s Philebus in Psellos’ … 407
Arco Magrì M., L’inedito canon de requie di Andrea Cretense, Helikon 9–10 (1969–1970) 494–513.
Burnet J., Platonis opera vol. 1, Oxford 1900
Criscuolo U., Michele Psello, Epistola a Giovanni Xifilino, Naples 1973.
Declerck J. H., Maximi Confessoris quaestiones et dubia Turnhout 1982
Gosling J. C. B., Plato: Philebus, Oxford 1975,
Henry P., Schwyzer H. R., Plotini opera, Leiden 1951–1973.
Impellizzeri S., Imperatori di Bisanzio: Cronografia di Michele Psello, Milan 1984.
Janssens B., Maximi Confessoris Ambigua ad Thomam una cum Epistula secunda ad eundem, Turnhout
2002.
Kotter P. B., Die Schriften des Johannes von Damaskos, vol. 5 Berlin New York 1988.
Kroll W., Procli Diadochi in Platonis rem publicam commentarii, Leipzig 1899–1901.
Suchla B. R., Corpus Dionysiacum I: Pseudo-Dionysius Areopagita, De divinis nominibus, Berlin 1990.
Van Riel G., Damascius, Commentaire sur le Philèbe de Platon, Paris 2009.
Westerink L. G., Olympiodorus, Commentary on the first Alcibiades of Plato, Amsterdam 1956.
Alfeyev H., Symeon the New Theologian and the Orthodox Tradition, Oxford 1999.
Frede D., Plato’s Philebus, Indianapolis 1993.
Kaldellis A., The argument of Psellos’ Chronographia, Leiden 1999.
Lauritzen, F. Psellos the Hesychast: A Neoplatonic Reading of the Transfiguration on Mt Tabor,
Byzantinoslavica 70 (2012) 167–180.
Lauritzen F., Pagan energies in Maximus the Confessor: the influence of Proclus on the Ad Thomam 5,
Greek Roman and Byzantine Studies 52/2 (2012) 226–239.
Lauritzen F., Stethatos’ Paradise in Psellos’ ekphrasis on Mt Olympos, Vizantijskij Vremennik 70 (2011)
139–151.
Lauritzen F., The depiction of character in the Chronographia of Michael Psellos, Turnhout 2013.
Lloyd A., the anatomy of neoplatonism, Oxford 1988.
O’ Meara D., Lectures neoplatoniciennes du Philebe, ed. M. Dixsaut, Fêlure du plaisir, vol. 2, Paris 1999.
O’Meara D., Political philosophy in Michael Psellos: the Chronographia read in relation to his philosophi-
cal work, ed. Börje Bydén, Katerina Ierodiakonou, The Many Faces of Byzantine Philosophy.
Papers and monographs from the Norwegian Institute at Athens, series 4, 1, Athens 2012, 153–171.
Papaioannou S., Michael Psellos: rhetoric and authorship in Byzantium, Cambridge 2013.
Pietsch E., Die “Chronographia” des Michael Psellos: Kaisergeschichte, Autobiographie und Apologie,
Wiesbaden 2005.
Van Riel G., Pleasure and the Good Life: Plato, Aristotle, and the Neoplatonists, Leiden 2000.
Vries-van der Velden E., Les amitiés dangereuses: Psellos et Léon Paraspondylos, Byzantinoslavica 60
(1999) 315–350.
FREDERICK LAURITZEN: The mixed life of Plato’s Philebus in Psellos’ … 409
Фредерик Лаурицен
(Фондација за религијске науке, Болоња)