Barnett Lidsky, Lyrissa, Nobodys Fools - The Rational Audience As First Amendment Ideal
Barnett Lidsky, Lyrissa, Nobodys Fools - The Rational Audience As First Amendment Ideal
Barnett Lidsky, Lyrissa, Nobodys Fools - The Rational Audience As First Amendment Ideal
1-1-2010
Recommended Citation
Lyrissa Barnett Lidsky, Nobody's Fools: The Rational Audience as First Amendment Ideal, 2010 U. Ill. L. Rev. 799, available at
http://scholarship.law.ufl.edu/facultypub/75
This Article is brought to you for free and open access by the Faculty Scholarship at UF Law Scholarship Repository. It has been accepted for inclusion
in Faculty Publications by an authorized administrator of UF Law Scholarship Repository. For more information, please contact [email protected].
NOBODY'S FOOLS: THE RATIONAL
AUDIENCE AS FIRST AMENDMENT
IDEAL
Lyrissa Barnett Lidsky*
* Stephen C. O'Connell Chair and Professor of Law, Fredric G. Levin College of Law. The
author wishes to thank Daniel C. Friedel, Kevin Combest, and Ben (Ziggy) Williamson for invaluable
research assistance, and Bill Page and David Anderson for comments and encouragement at critical
junctures. Many thanks to Jeffrey Harrison, Elizabeth Lear, Mark Fenster, Ronald Krotoszynski, Jr.,
and Elizabeth Rowe for laboring through earlier drafts and making great suggestions for improve-
ment.
1. McConnell v. FEC, 540 U.S. 93,258-59 (2003) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in
part).
TABLE OF CONTENTS
I. INTRODUCTION
CAL. W. L. REV. 479, 493-94 (2005) ("Jury consultants predominantly rely upon the use of opinion
polls to construct a profile of the type of person that will be most receptive to a client's
case.... [D]emographic data is compiled and jury consultants look for specific correlations between
desirable traits .... ").
3. The Court has never given a precise definition of core speech, but it is clear that it includes
political speech at a minimum, and may encompass historical, literary, scientific, and even artistic
speech as well. See NAACP v. Claiborne Hardware Co., 458 U.S. 886, 913 (1982) ("[E]xpression on
public issues 'has always rested on the highest rung of the hierarchy of First Amendment values."'
(quoting Carey v. Brown, 447 U.S. 455,467 (1980))); Thornhill v. Alabama, 310 U.S. 88,101-402 (1940)
(asserting that free speech entails "the liberty to discuss publicly and truthfully all matters of public
concern," enabling citizens to "cope with the exigencies of [their] period"). Perhaps the most useful
definition is that core speech is anything that is not intermediate or low-value speech. See David A.
Strauss, Freedom of Speech and the Common-Law Constitution, in ETERNALLY VIGILANT: FREE
SPEECH IN THE MODERN ERA 33, 37 (Lee C. Bollinger & Geoffrey R. Stone eds., 2002) (noting that
the "default category," for First Amendment purposes, is "high-value speech"). "Speakers need not
establish that their speech is political, or artistic, or scientific, or otherwise high value; they need only
establish that it is not in one of the low-value categories." Id. For further explanation, see Lyrissa
Barnett Lidsky & Thomas F. Cotter, Authorship, Audiences, and Anonymous Speech, 82 NOTRE
DAME L. REV. 1537, 1581-89 (2007).
4. In fact, these characteristics vary so much from person to person that it makes little sense to
speak of any particular speech or text as if it had a single interpretation. For discussion of how as-
sumptions about hypothetical or "implied" readers influence the interpretation of literary texts, see
infra Part II. For discussion of how judges' assumptions about readers shape the interpretation of
whether a statement is defamatory in a tort context, see Lyrissa Barnett Lidsky, Defamation,Reputa-
tion, and the Myth of Community, 71 WASH. L. REv. 1, 36-49 (1996).
5. The Court has at times acknowledged that vulnerable audience members may be without
judicial recourse against speech protected by the First Amendment. See, e.g., Org. for a Better Austin
v. Keefe, 402 U.S. 415, 419 (1971) (stating that "so long as the means are peaceful," speech cannot be
brought down to the level of the most vulnerable audience member). But cf. FCC v. Pacifica Found.,
438 U.S. 726, 748-51 (1978) (allowing channeling of indecent broadcast programming). For more dis-
cussion, see infra Part II.
6. See, e.g., Org.for a Better Austin, 402 U.S. at 418 ("It is elementary, of course, that in a case
of this kind the courts do not concern themselves with the truth or validity of the publication.").
7. Although these assumptions can be decoupled, this Article will refer to them jointly as the
rational audience assumption.
8. This scholarship often criticizes the influence of the marketplace of ideas metaphor in First
Amendment scholarship. See, e.g., Stanley Ingber, The Marketplace of Ideas: A Legitimizing Myth,
1984 DUKE L.J. 1, 5; see also discussion infra Part III.A. The marketplace metaphor neatly encapsu-
lates the assumptions of the rational audience ideal, and it remains the dominant metaphor of First
Amendment jurisprudence. I have chosen to refer to the rational audience ideal, in addition to the
more common marketplace metaphor, because this terminology brings out the often hidden or over-
looked assumptions of the marketplace metaphor.
9. See discussion infra Part III.B. I have chosen to use the term behavioral economics here.
The body of scholarship that attempts to apply the insights of cognitive psychology is often referred to
as "behavioral analysis" or "behavioral economics." The scholarly literature of "behavioral law and
economics" is particularly rich. See, e.g., Cass R. Sunstein, Introduction to BEHAVIORAL LAW AND
ECONOMICS 1, 1 (Cass R. Sunstein ed., 2000). The common thread in all of this scholarship is an at-
tempt to understand and model how humans make decisions.
10. See discussion of this critique in Part III.B, infra.
11. David Brooks, The BehavioralRevolution, N.Y. TIMES, Oct. 27,2008, at A31.
12. Id.
13. Derek E. Bambauer, Shopping Badly: Cognitive Biases, Communications,and the Fallacy of
the Marketplace of Ideas, 77 U. COLO. L. REV. 649,651 (2006).
14. In FEC v. Wisconsin Right to Life, Inc., 551 U.S. 449,457-58 (2007), Wisconsin Right to Life
(WRTL) asserted that it wished to run ads from its general treasury funds criticizing the stance of Wis-
consin Senators on the filibustering of judicial nominees. These ads did not urge Wisconsin voters to
elect or defeat the Senators; nonetheless, the ads met the definition of "electioneering communica-
tions" under section 203 of the BCRA (Bipartisan Campaign Reform Act of 2002), therefore making
it a federal crime to air them within thirty days of a federal primary or sixty days of a general election.
that the First Amendment requires the line between protected and un-
protected political speech to be drawn based on the reasonable interpre-
tation of such speech rather than "the actual effect speech will have... on
a particularsegment of the target audience."5 Justice Roberts' primary
argument for ignoring the actual effect of speech on real audiences is a
practical one. An actual-effect test would "typically lead to a burden-
some, expert-driven inquiry, with an indeterminate result. Litigation on
such a standard.., will unquestionably chill a substantial amount of po-
litical speech. ' 16 In other words, the cumbersome and expensive process
of gathering evidence about audience effects will chill political speech to
an unacceptable degree. But this rationale rests on the unexplained as-
sumption that the hypothetical risk of chilling speech outweighs the ben-
efits of examining the real effects of speech. Standing alone, expediency
is an insufficient explanation for why First Amendment jurisprudence
should continue to indulge the rational audience assumption and the
more-is-better assumption. Moreover, it does not explain why the Court
allows for the possibility that vulnerable audience members may need
protection from their own poor judgment in the realm of commercial17
Id. at 460. WRTL sought declaratory and injunctive relief in district court, alleging that the applica-
tion of the "electioneering communications" provisions to their ads violated the First Amendment. Id.
Five Supreme Court Justices-Scalia, Kennedy, Thomas, Alito, and Chief Justice Roberts-ultimately
held that the application of the "electioneering communications" provisions to WRTL's ads violated
the First Amendment, though they could not agree on a single rationale for this holding. Id. at 457,
481 (principal opinion supported by two votes); id. at 482-83 (Alito, J., concurring); id. at 504 (Scalia,
J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgment). Three of the five Justices who upheld the as-
applied challenges would have simply overturned the Court's prior holding in McConnell v. FEC, 540
U.S. 93 (2003), with regard to the facial constitutionality of the electioneering communications provi-
sions. Justice Scalia, joined by Justices Kennedy and Thomas, contended that the Court should reject
McConnell because it "sets us the unsavory task of separating issue-speech from election-speech with
no clear criterion." Wis. Right to Life, 551 U.S. at 484 (Scalia, J., concurring in part and concurring in
the judgment). Justice Scalia, while not exactly praising Buckley's "magic words" test for separating
issue ads from express advocacy, observed that "[i]f a permissible test short of the magic-words test
existed, Buckley would surely have adopted it." Id. at 495. Chief Justice Roberts and Justice Alito,
however, would have decided the case on a narrower ground. Chief Justice Roberts wrote that the
BCRA's provisions could be constitutionally applied to ads that constitute "express advocacy" and ads
that are the "functional equivalent" of express advocacy. Id. at 482 (principal opinion supported by
two votes). However, Chief Justice Roberts wrote, "[A] court should find that an ad is the functional
equivalent of express advocacy only if the ad is susceptible of no reasonable interpretation other than
as an appeal to vote for or against a specific candidate." Id. at 469. Applying this test, he determined
that the WRTL's ads were not the functional equivalent of express advocacy because they dealt with a
genuine issue-the filibuster of judicial nominees-and they "d[id] not mention an election, candidacy,
political party, or challenger; and they d[id] not take a position on a candidate's character, qualifica-
tions, or fitness for office." Id. at 470.
15. Wis. Right to Life, 551 U.S. at 469-70 (principal opinion supported by two votes) (emphasis
added). Chief Justice Roberts and Justice Alito would have adopted a test requiring a court to protect
the campaign speech at issue only if "no reasonable interpretation" of it would place it within the un-
protected category of "express advocacy" under BCRA section 203. Id. at 470. Justices Scalia, Ken-
nedy, and Thomas believed that even this test failed to draw a bright enough line to protect core polit-
ical speech. See id. at 492, 499 n.7 (Scalia, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgment).
16. Id. at 469 (principal opinion supported by two votes).
17. See discussion infra Part II.B.
and other non-core speech,18 but not in the realm of core speech. This
Article therefore explores more fully the justifications for continuing to
presume that audiences of core speech are rational in the face of growing
evidence to the contrary.
First, though, the stage must be set. Part II draws on literary theory
to illuminate the process by which the Court constructs an implied au-
dience in First Amendment cases. In the realm of core speech, this im-
plied audience is composed of rational and skeptical citizens who are ca-
pable, when left to their own devices, of sorting through masses of
information to discover truth.19 Thus, governmental intervention in the
speech marketplace is almost always unjustified. In the realm of com-
mercial and other non-core speech, however, the Court sometimes
(though not consistently) applies a credulous consumer model of the im-
plied audience. 20 This alternate model, which posits that many audience
members are naive and easily misled, provides justification for paterna-
listic governmental intervention in the realm of commercial speech. Part
II thus demonstrates that assumptions about audiences shape outcomes
of First Amendment cases but leaves unanswered which set of assump-
tions courts ought to adopt.
Part III addresses scholarship that calls for more paternalistic inter-
ventions in the speech marketplace, giving prominence to the still largely
implicit critique posed by cognitive psychology and behavioral econom-
ics. 21 This new vein of criticism suggests that the marketplace of ideas is
flawed because humans are flawed: they are not rational information
processors, and more information often leads to worse decisions instead
of better ones. Yet the implications of this evidence for First Amend-
ment doctrine are unclear. Government actors are not immune from the
constraints on rationality affecting their fellow citizens. And even if in-
dividuals are only rational in fits and starts, the evidence is not at all clear
that this irrationality infects aggregate decision making.
More importantly, Part IV contends that clinging to an admittedly
flawed ideal of audience rationality is better than the alternative. As the
18. For example, the Court's electoral speech jurisprudence is, to put it generously, inconsistent
in this assumption about the ability of the voting public to make rational decisions when presented
with masses of highly biased information. An excellent article by Daniel Ortiz traces competing mod-
els of political decision making that underlie campaign speech decisions. See generally Daniel R. Or-
tiz, The Engaged and the Inert: Theorizing Political Personality Under the First Amendment, 81 VA. L.
REV. 1 (1995). Under one model, the Court treats the citizen as a "civic smarty" who "make[s] highly
informed political choices." Id. at 4. Under the other, the Court treats the citizen as a "civic slob"
who is "passive and uninformed." Id.; see also Daniel R. Ortiz, The Paradox of Mass Democracy, in
RETHINKING THE VOTE: THE POLITICS AND PROSPECTS OF AMERICAN ELECTION REFORM 210, 211
(Ann N. Crigler et al. eds., 2004).
19. See discussion infra Part ll.B.
20. See discussion infra Part II.C.
21. Although there is a large and growing body of literature on behavioral economics and cogni-
tive psychology, only two scholars seem to have applied this literature in the First Amendment con-
text. See Bambauer, supra note 13, at 651; Paul Horwitz, Free Speech as Risk Analysis: Heuristics,Bi-
ases, and Institutions in the First Amendment, 76 TEMP. L. REV. 1, 6-7 (2003).
Court has noted, concerns of judicial economy support the rationality as-
sumption.22 But rationality is also important as an aspirational norm.
First Amendment doctrine encourages us to develop our capacities to
engage in the level of public discourse democratic theory demands.23
Failure to apply a rational audience standard would reduce public dis-
course to the level of the least sophisticated audience, while punishing
speakers who are unable to predict what that level is. Perhaps more sig-
nificantly, both the rationality assumption and the more-is-better as-
sumption serve as a check on government's increasingly powerful at-
tempts to use its agenda-setting power to manipulate public discourse.
Finally, a State that indulges an irrationality assumption, or even a
bounded rationality assumption, fails to respect the autonomy of its citi-
zens, an autonomy upon which a self-governing democracy depends.
22. See, e.g., FEC v. Wis. Right to Life, Inc., 551 U.S. 449, 469 (2007) (Roberts, C.J. & Alito, J.,
dictum).
23. As opposed to consumers, for example. Although this argument will be explained more fully
in Part IV, infra, suffice to say that if citizens are incapable of rational decision making through partic-
ipation in public discourse, they are equally incapable of self-governance, the hallmark of democracy.
24. See supra notes 6, 14-16 and accompanying text.
25. I have attempted previously to illuminate how common law doctrines in defamation cases
allow judges to construct the implied audience of allegedly defamatory speech. See Lidsky, supra note
4, at 16-17.
26. Important works in the area include STANLEY FISH, IS THERE A TEXT IN THis CLASS?: THE
AUTHORITY OF INTERPRETIVE COMMUNITIES (1980); WOLFGANG ISER, THE ACT OF READING: A
THEORY OF AESTHETIC RESPONSE (Wolfgang Iser & David Henry Wilson trans., Johns Hopkins Un-
iv. Press 1978) (1976) [hereinafter ISER, THE ACT OF READING]; WOLFGANG ISER, THE IMPLIED
READER: PA-ITERNS OF COMMUNICATION IN PROSE FICTION FROM BUNYAN TO BECKEIT (Wolfgang
Iser & David Henry Wilson trans., Johns Hopkins Univ. Press 1974) (1972) [hereinafter ISER, THE
IMPLIED READER]; HANS ROBERT JAUSS, TOWARD AN AESTHETIC OF RECEPTION (Timothy Bahti
trans., Univ. of Minn. Press 1982) (1970). For two good summaries of reader-response criticism as a
whole, see TERRY EAGLETON, LITERARY THEORY: AN INTRODUCTION 47-78 (2d ed. 1996) and LoIs
TYSON, CRITICAL THEORY TODAY: A USER-FRIENDLY GUIDE 153-96 (1999). For application of the
insights of reader-response theory to the question of what is fair use in copyright law, see generally
Laura A. Heymann, Everything Is Transformative: Fair Use and Reader Response, 31 COLUM. J.L. &
ARTS 445 (2008).
27. TYSON, supra note 26, at 162; see also EAGLETON, supra note 26, at 64-65 ("Literary texts do
not exist on bookshelves: they are processes of signification materialized only in the practice of read-
ing. For literature to happen, the reader is quite as vital as the author."); ISER, THE IMPLIED READER,
supranote 26, at xiii ("The reader discovers the meaning of the text .... TYSON, supra note 26, at
");
157 ("[A] written text is... an event that occurs within the reader, whose response is of primary im-
portance in creating the text.").
28. A similar test is used in First Amendment Establishment Clause cases. In Establishment
Clause cases, the Supreme Court makes quite explicit its reliance on the "reasonable observer" as the
benchmark by which the Court decides if a person would perceive a statute as a state endorsement of
religion. In Wallace v. Jaifree, 472 U.S. 38, 76 (1985), Justice O'Connor's concurrence focused on
"whether an objective observer, acquainted with the text, legislative history, and implementation of
the statute, would perceive it as a state endorsement." See also Zelman v. Simmons-Harris, 536 U.S.
639, 655 (2002) (applying an adult community member to the reasonable objective observer standard);
Santa Fe Indep. Sch. Dist. v. Doe, 530 U.S. 290, 308 (2000) (applying the reasonable observer test to
determine if there was a perception of government promotion of religion but specifying that the rele-
vant observer is a high school student). In Elk Grove Unified School District v. Newdow, 542 U.S. 1,
36 (2004), Justice O'Connor described the reasonable observer in the context of the use of the phrase
"under God" in the Pledge of Allegiance:
For centuries, we have marked important occasions or pronouncements with references to God
and invocations of divine assistance.... The reasonable observer..., fully aware of our national
history and the origins of such practices, would not perceive these acknowledgments as signifying
a government endorsement of any specific religion, or even of religion over nonreligion.
For criticism of the test, see Susan Hanley Kosse, A Missed Opportunity to Abandon the Reasonable
Observer Framework in Sacred Text Cases: McCreary County v. ACLU of Kentucky and Van Orden
v. Perry, 4 FIRST AMENDMENT L. REV. 139,141-42 (2006).
the text.29 And yet reader-response critics do not attempt to take surveys
about how readers decode texts. Rather, they posit an idealized reader30
who is educated and conversant with stylistic and literary conventions.
The critic then tries to see the text through the eyes of its "implied read-
er," in the words of Wolfgang Iser, 31 in order to make the "correct" or
"best" meaning of the text emerge.32 In First Amendment decisions,
courts play the role of critics, stepping into the shoes of implied reason-
able readers in order to fix the meaning of the disputed text.
A final insight of reader-response criticism is simply that although
there may be a best interpretation of a text, there is no universal inter-
pretation of a text. Meaning is not fixed by the author's intent or the text
itself; rather, meaning is an interactive process, a continuing dialogue be-
tween text and reader, a dialogue that changes over time. 33 Nonetheless,
in courts if not in the classrooms of literature professors, the disputed
text must be definitively decoded so that a final judgment can be ren-
dered. Although different readers will decode texts differently, courts
must settle upon a meaning; that meaning, in turn, determines whether
the speaker, author, publisher, or broadcaster receives the shelter of the
First Amendment. 4
These insights have ready application to actual cases. Consider, for
example, the famous case of Cohen v. California. 35 Cohen involved an
apparently simple text in the form of a jacket bearing the words "Fuck
the Draft." 6 Is "Fuck the Draft," when inscribed on a jacket worn in the
hallways of a courthouse, a heart-felt protest against the mandatory con-
scription of young men to serve in Vietnam?3 7 Or is the text on and of
the jacket a puerile epithet with little, if any, communicative value? In
order to decide the case, the Supreme Court was forced to decide which
"a hypothetical coterie of the violent and lawless."' The State was not
entitled to assume the worst about its citizens.4 7 Even if the State feared
a breach of the peace, it could not censor speech absent "evidence that
substantial numbers of citizens are standing ready to strike out physically
at whoever may assault their sensibilities with execrations like that ut-
tered by Cohen." ' This, of course, created a procedural imbalance that
favors free speech; the State must provided strong evidence that its pre-
dictions of audience reactions are not speculative, but the Court is free to
speculate at will. More to the point, the Court's speculation provided the
definitive decoding of Cohen's jacket. The Court determined that rea-
sonable viewers would interpret the jacket as asserting an "evident posi-
tion on the inutility or immorality of the draft,"'49 and that, in turn, meant
that the State could not criminalize his speech.'
As Cohen illustrates, First Amendment jurisprudence accords
courts the role of disinterested critics of the disputed texts of First
Amendment cases. The Court (and by extension lower courts) claims
superior authority vis-A-vis the legislative and executive branches in pre-
dicting the effects of speech. It may be that the courts are granted this
authority due to some institutional superiority,51 but there is no indica-
tion that courts are superior to the other branches of government in pre-
dicting the responses of audiences to speech. Indeed, courts appear to
project an idealized construct of readers, listeners, and viewers into First
Amendment cases with little regard for the "facts on the ground." 2 Even
if empirical research were practical, the construct allows courts to claim
to be speaking for a broader audience than just themselves when they in-
terpret disputed speech. Moreover, as this Article ultimately shows, the
characteristics imputed to this idealized audience aid judges in advancing
the broader ideals of the First Amendment. First, however, it is impor-
tant to develop a more well-rounded portrait of the implied audience of
First Amendment speech.
minimum political speech 3 and speech dealing with issues of public con-
cern. 4 This speech lies at the core of the First Amendment because po-
litical speech in a democracy is essential to democratic self-governance;
without this information, citizens cannot play their assigned roles in
choosing and instructing their representatives and in participating in the
formation of public policy. Yet core speech also includes speech that
enables citizens to develop their critical faculties and understand the ex-
igencies of their eras, such as literary, artistic, historical, and scientific
speech. Built into the very concept of core speech, then, is the idea that
it appeals to its audience in their capacities as citizens first and foremost,
rather than appealing purely to economic, sexual, or other forms of self-
interest. The assumptions courts make about the audiences of core
speech, therefore, mirror the assumptions courts make about citizens.
In envisioning the implied audience of core speech, courts might as-
sume that audience members are na've and credulous, lacking the educa-
tion or sophistication necessary to critically assess the messages they re-
ceive. The modern trend for core speech, however, has been to assume
that audiences are savvy and sophisticated, capable of sorting through
masses of information to discover truth, however provisional or con-
tested. Indeed, these assumptions underpin two articles of faith in mod-
ern First Amendment theory: (1) audiences are capable of rationally eva-
luating the truth, quality, credibility, and usefulness of core speech
53. Some would include only political speech in the definition of core speech. See, e.g., Robert
H. Bork, Neutral Principlesand Some First Amendment Problems, 47 IND. L.J. 1, 29 (1971) (defining
"the core of the first amendment" as "speech that is explicitly political").
54. See discussion supra note 3. The Court's distinction between core and non-core speech owes
a debt to the work of Alexander Meiklejohn, who defined the core of the First Amendment to include
speech of "governing importance." Justice Black's concurrence in the seminal case of New York
Times Co. v. Sullivan, for example, cited Meiklejohn for the notion that "[a]n unconditional right to
say what one pleases about public affairs is... the minimum guarantee of the First Amendment."
N.Y. Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 297 (1964) (Black, J., concurring). Although initially it ap-
peared that Meiklejohn's theory would protect only political speech, he later broadened his theory to
include literary, historical, and scientific speech, based on the notion that these types of speech fos-
tered the development of our capacities as citizens to make informed public decisions. ALEXANDER
MEIKLEJOHN, POLITICAL FREEDOM: THE CONSTITUTIONAL POWERS OF THE PEOPLE 26-28, 76-84,
144-47 (1948). The lines between core and non-core speech can be blurred at the margin, and it is
sometimes easier to define core speech by what it is not. Commercial speech, for example, is not core
speech; it does not sufficiently advance public discussion on issues of governing importance. But
commercial speech receives significant First Amendment protection because it provides important
information to citizens in their roles as consumers. See Cent. Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Pub. Serv.
Comm'n, 447 U.S. 557, 563-64 & n.6 (1980). Fighting words are not core speech; they do not advance
public discussion and are designated as "low-value speech" because of their tendency to bypass cogni-
tive processes and produce immediate violence. See Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.S. 568, 572
(1942). Defining core First Amendment speech creates troublesome issues at the margins, but it is
clear, at a minimum, that core speech includes discussions of political, literary, artistic, historical, cul-
tural, and social concerns. See Harry Kalven, Jr., The New York Times Case: A Note on "The Central
Meaning of the First Amendment," 1964 SUP. CT. REV. 191, 208 ("The Amendment has a 'central
meaning'-a core of protection of speech without which democracy cannot function, without which, in
Madison's phrase, 'the censorial power' would be in the Government over the people and not 'in the
people over the Government."'); see also Boos v. Barry, 485 U.S. 312, 318 (1988).
without the aid of government intervention; and (2) more speech is bet-
ter than less.
to which citizens could set aside self-interest to favor rational public poli-
cy. 9 Indeed, the constitutional system they designed contains measures
designed to prevent state legislatures from embracing irrational populist
measures:
Though the Founders espoused a'democratic theory rooted in ra-
tionalism, it was not until the twentieth century that courts began to fa-
shion a modern, libertarian First Amendment around the notion of the
rationality of citizen audiences. The clear and present danger doctrine
became the building block of this modern First Amendment, but its be-
ginnings were not auspicious. The test debuted in Schenck v. United
States, which involved a felony conviction under the Espionage Act of
1917 for distributing pamphlets critical of World War I to men who had
been drafted.6 The Court framed the issue as whether the speaker's
words "create[d] a clear and present danger"62 of "bring[ing] about the
substantive evils that Congress had a right to prevent."63 Yet in applica-
tion, the Court focused on the "tendency" of the defendant's pamphlet to
interfere with the draft without demanding proof of actual interference.'
The focus on the "tendency" of the speech suggested that it could be
suppressed if someone somewhere might respond badly to it. Thus, the
maiden voyage of the clear and present danger test served to suppress
rather than defend radical speech.65
From this inauspicious beginning the clear and present danger test
eventually became a bulwark protecting dissident speech. As is well
known, 66 Justice Holmes, under prompting by Judge Hand and other li-
bertarian thinkers,67 recalibrated the clear and present danger test. The
new, protective version of the test emerged in Justice Holmes' dissent in
Abrams v. United States.68 There, the government prosecuted five Rus-
sian immigrants under the Espionage Act for distributing pamphlets crit-
ical of U.S. involvement in World War 1.69 Though a majority of the
88. Bork, supra note 53, at 23 (observing that free speech law today "grows out of" the dissent-
ing (or concurring) opinions of Justices Holmes and Brandeis).
89. Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.S. 568, 574 (1942) (defining fighting words as those
"likely to provoke the average person to retaliation, and thereby cause a breach of the peace"); see
also RONALD J. KROTOSZYNSKI, JR. ET AL., THE FIRST AMENDMENT: CASES AND THEORY 93 (2008)
("The fighting-words decisions... involve[] a determination of whether words are abusive or so akin
to an assault that they are likely to cause a violent response.").
90. See Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U.S. 444, 447-48 (1969); see also Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S.
397, 408 (1989) (stating that First Amendment jurisprudence does not presume "an audience that
takes serious offense at particular expression is necessarily likely to disturb the peace").
91. See Brandenburg,395 U.S. at 448-49.
92. Id.at 447.
93. Brandenburg, for example, involved a Ku Klux Klan member urging other members, some
armed, to "[b]ury the niggers." Id. at 445-46, 446 n.1. The Court found the circumstances of the
speech, however, evidenced the audience would not respond with violence. Id. at 448-49.
94. Garrison v. Louisiana, 379 U.S. 64, 78 (1964) (requiring knowledge of falsity and reckless
disregard on the speaker's part).
95. N.Y. Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254,268,270 (1964).
96. Id. at 270-71,273.
97. See Texas v. Johnson, 491 U.S. 397,417-19 (1989).
98. The Court has repeatedly relied on the marketplace metaphor. For a recent example, see
New York State Boardof Elections v. Lopez Torres, 552 U.S. 196, 208 (2008) (unanimous) ("The First
Amendment creates an open marketplace where ideas, most especially political ideas, may compete
without government interference. It does not call on the federal courts to manage the market by pre-
venting too many buyers from settling upon a single product." (citation omitted)). As Professor Stan-
ley Ingber has noted, "Content-based restrictions leave the public with an incomplete, and perhaps
inaccurate, perception of the social and political universe. Thus, these restrictions can undermine the
search for truth and distort the process by which citizens make critical decisions." Stanley Ingber, The
First Amendment in Modem Garb: Retaining System Legitimacy, 56 GEO. WASH. L. REv. 187, 191
(1987) (book review).
99. 250 U.S. 616,630 (1919) (Holmes, J., dissenting).
100. Id. (emphasis added).
101. Id. Compare Justice Holmes' assertion with Justice Brandeis' contention that the Framers
"believed that freedom to think as you will and to speak as you think are means indispensable to the
discovery and spread of political truth...." Whitney v. California, 274 U.S. 357, 375 (1927) (Brandeis,
J., concurring).
102. Dennis v. United States, 341 U.S. 494, 584 (1951) (Douglas, J., dissenting). "When ideas
compete in the market for acceptance, full and free discussion exposes the false and they gain few ad-
herents. Full and free discussion even of ideas we hate encourages the testing of our own prejudices
and preconceptions." Id.
more information rather than less. Even rational actors might make bet-
ter decisions when they are not overwhelmed by unlimited options.
Nonetheless, First Amendment decisions have consistently tied the two
assumptions together, and nowhere is this more evident than in the mar-
ketplace metaphor itself.
The marketplace metaphor justifies the assumption that more is
better on several bases, only one of which is that more information might
aid decision making. The marketplace of ideas ostensibly leads to the
emergence of Truth."3 The best decisions, of course, are based on truth,
and the search for truth is fostered by "the dissemination of news from as
many different sources, and with as many different facets and colors as is
possible."' 1 The more competitors who jockey for dominance in the
marketplace of ideas, the better the ideas that will ultimately triumph,
though of course this assumes that those judging the quality of ideas are
rational information consumers.
That said, the primary justification for the assumption that more-is-
better is not that it leads to better democratic decision making. 105 Con-
sider Judge Hand's oft-quoted 1° assertion that "right conclusions are
more likely to be gathered out of a multitude of tongues, than through
any kind of authoritative selection."1°7 It is not that right conclusions will
always emerge from discourse that includes a "multitude of tongues."
Rather, a diverse discourse is preferable to a discourse whose parameters
are dictated by the State. l 0s
(1995) (striking government-mandated disclosure for author of anonymous political pamphlets), with
Meese v. Keene, 481 U.S. 465, 485 (1987) (upholding mandatory disclosure for foreign "political prop-
aganda" films).
109. FREDERICK SCHAUER, FREE SPEECH: A PHILOSOPHICAL ENQUIRY 81-86 (1982) (giving
numerous examples, including the persecution of Galileo).
110. Id. at 86.
111. Riley v. Nat'l Fed'n of the Blind of N.C., Inc., 487 U.S. 781, 791 (1988).
112. See, e.g., First Nat'l Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U.S. 765, 791 n.31 (1978) ("The First
Amendment rejects the 'highly paternalistic' approach of statutes ...which restrict what the people
may hear."); Dale Carpenter, The Antipaternalism Principlein the FirstAmendment, 37 CREIGHTON L.
REv. 579, 582-83 (2004) (noting the dominance of the antipaternalism principle in First Amendment
jurisprudence); Daniel A. Farber, Free Speech Without Romance: Public Choice and the First Amend-
ment, 105 HARV. L. REV. 554, 557-58 (1991) ("[T]raditional First Amendment jurispru-
dence ... assumes that people are ordinarily the best judges of their own interests."); Geoffrey R.
Stone, Content Regulation and the First Amendment, 25 WM. & MARY L. REV. 189, 212 (1983) ("The
Court has long embraced an 'antipaternalistic' understanding of the first amendment.").
113. Professor Dale Carpenter defines paternalism in the First Amendment context as regulation
of speech "justified by the government's belief that speaking or receiving the information in the speech is
not in citizens' own best interests." Carpenter, supra note 112, at 582-83. Philosopher Joel Feinberg
has written: "[Paternalism] suggests the view that the state stands to its citizens as a parent.., stands
to his children .... 3 JOEL FEINBERG, HARM TO SELF: THE MORAL LIMITS OF THE CRIMINAL LAw 4
(1986).
114. "When men govern themselves, it is they-and no one else-who must pass judgment upon
unwisdom and unfairness and danger. And that means that unwise ideas must have a hearing as well
as wise ones...." MEIKLEJOHN, supra note 54, at 27. In the context of commercial speech, see Vir-
ginia State Board of Pharmacyv. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc., 425 U.S. 748,756-57 (1976)
("Freedom of speech presupposes a willing speaker. But where a speaker exists, as is the case here,
the protection afforded is to the communication, to its source and to its recipients both.... If there is a
right to advertise, there is a reciprocal right to receive the advertising ....
").In Lamont v. Postmaster
General, 381 U.S. 301, 307 (1965), the Court upheld the First Amendment rights of citizens to receive
political publications sent from abroad. More recently, in Kleindienst v. Mandel,408 U.S. 753, 762-63
information from which they may draw to decide their collective fates."'
Respect for autonomy thus demands that the State adopt a vision of the
core-speech audience that sees them as capable of sorting through the in-
formation that bombards them in the marketplace to discern what is use-
ful and what is true. This vision wavers, however, when it comes to other
speech contexts, as the following Section reveals.
(1972), the Court acknowledged a First Amendment right to "receive information and ideas." And in
Procunierv. Martinez, 416 U.S. 396, 408 (1974), in examining the constitutionality of a restriction on
prisoners' mail, the Court stated, "Both parties to the correspondence have an interest ... and censor-
ship of the communication between them necessarily impinges on the interest of each."
115. See, e.g., Hurley v. Irish-Am. Gay, Lesbian & Bisexual Group of Boston, Inc., 515 U.S. 557,
573 (1995) ("[T]he fundamental rule of protection under the First Amendment [is] that a speaker has
the autonomy to choose the content of his own message."). Speaker autonomy underpins many First
Amendment doctrines. For example, in Miami Herald Publishing Co. v. Tornillo, 418 U.S. 241, 256
(1974), the Court upheld the right of a newspaper to exercise editorial discretion in determining the
newspaper's contents. Even in the broadcast context, the government may interfere with speaker au-
tonomy only because, in a medium that requires government allocation to be viable, "the right[s] of
the viewers and listeners" are "paramount." Red Lion Broad. Co. v. FCC, 395 U.S. 367, 390 (1969).
116. The Court's electoral speech cases also provide a good example of how it veers back and
forth between assumptions about the intelligence and sophistication of the audience of campaign-
related speech and information. For more, see the excellent discussion by Raleigh Hannah Levine,
The (Un)Informed Electorate: Insights Into the Supreme Court's Electoral Speech Cases, 54 CASE W.
RES. L. REV. 225 (2003).
117. In Valentine v. Chrestensen, 316 U.S. 52. 54 (1942), the Court held that the First Amendment
does not protect "purely commercial advertising." For additional discussion, see Alex Kozinski &
Stuart Banner, The Anti-History and Pre-Historyof CommercialSpeech, 71 TEX. L. REV. 747 (1993).
118. Va. State Bd. of Pharmacy v. Va. Citizens Consumer Council, Inc., 425 U.S. 748, 770 (1976)
(holding that the First Amendment protects commercial speech).
119. Since 1976, states have attempted, mostly unsuccessfully, to use a "demand reduction" argu-
ment to justify bans on advertising in a variety of contexts. See, e.g., Bates v. State Bar of Ariz., 433
U.S. 350, 355, 376 (1977) (ban on lawyer advertising); Carey v. Population Servs. Int'l, 431 U.S. 678,
689, 700 (1977) (ban on contraceptive advertising); Linmark Assocs., Inc. v. Twp. of Willingboro, 431
U.S. 85, 92-94 (1977) (ban on "For Sale" signs). Even after 1976, the Court upheld a ban on casino
advertising despite the "reduction of demand for casino gambling." Posadas de P.R. Assocs. v. Tour-
ism Co. of P.R., 478 U.S. 328, 341 (1986). For further discussion, see infra text accompanying notes
121-28.
120. The State made, and the Court rejected, this argument made in Bates v. State Bar of Arizona,
433 U.S. 350, 373-74, 384 (1977). The Court refused to find that price advertising by attorneys was
inherently misleading. Id. at 372. Instead, the Court believed the absence of attorney advertisements
would leave many consumers poorly equipped to seek legal services. Id. at 370. The Court described
advertising as a boon to "informed and reliable decisionmaking." Id. at 364.
121. Va. State Bd. of Pharmacy,425 U.S. at 765.
122. Id. at 769-70.
123. Id.
124. Id. at 769.
125. Linmark Assocs., Inc. v. Twp. of Willingsboro, 431 U.S. 85, 97 (1977) (quoting Whitney v.
California, 274 U.S. 357, 377 (1927) (Brandeis, J., concurring)).
126. Id. at 95-97.
127. Cent. Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Pub. Serv. Comm'n, 447 U.S. 557, 566 (1980). The test
for intermediate scrutiny is often called the Central Hudson test, after the case which established it.
See id. Commercial speech is considered less valuable than core political speech, and greater regula-
tion is permitted because commercial speech is more "durable" and hardy and more verifiable than
core speech. Va. State Bd. of Pharmacy, 425 U.S. at 771 & n.24.
128. See, e.g., United States v. Edge Broad. Co., 509 U.S. 418, 429 (1993) (prohibitions on lottery
advertising); Posadas de P.R. Assocs. v. Tourism Co. of P.R., 478 U.S. 328, 342 (1986) (restrictions on
casino advertising).
129. Indeed, as Professor Mitchell Berman has noted, "constitutional protection for commercial
speech remains mostly predicated on ... listener interests." Mitchell N. Berman, Commercial Speech
and the UnconstitutionalConditionsDoctrine: A Second Look at "The Greater Includes the Lesser," 55
VAND. L. REV. 693, 724 (2002); see also Robert Post, The ConstitutionalStatus of Commercial Speech,
48 UCLA L. REV. 1, 14 (2000) ("Commercial speech doctrine.., is sharply audience oriented.").
Thus, commercial speech doctrine may be a particularly appropriate realm for application of a con-
struct that focuses on assumptions about audiences latent in the text of judicial opinions.
130. It is more troublesome when the government forces ignorance on its citizens by withholding
information than when it forces knowledge on them through disclosure requirements. Mandatory dis-
closure does not compromise autonomy in the same way as withholding information.
131. 478 U.S. at 328.
132. 517 U.S. 484 (1996).
133. 44 Liquormart,Inc., 517 U.S. at 514; Posadasde P.R. Assocs., 478 U.S. at 332.
134. Posadasde P.R. Assocs., 478 U.S. at 332-33.
135. Id. at 342.
136. Id. at 341 (citation omitted).
137. Id. at 332.
138. Id. at 341.
citizens, but the Court glossed over this obvious point.'39 The Court, hav-
ing found a substantial governmental interest, also found that Puerto Ri- '4
co's chosen statute directly advanced it. Puerto Rico was "reasonable"'
in assuming that shielding citizens from targeted advertising would de-41
crease their demand for casino gambling, inevitably benefitting them.'
Finally, and perhaps most controversially, the Court held that Puerto Ri-
co satisfied the last hurdle of intermediate scrutiny: its restrictions were
"no more extensive than necessary" to decrease citizen demand. 42 In
reaching this conclusion, the Court expressed little faith in the market-
place of ideas as a solution to the State's problem. The Court left it "up
to the legislature to decide whether or not such a 'counterspeech' policy
would be as effective in reducing the demand for casino gambling as a re-
striction on advertising.' 41 3 In other words, the State gets to decide
whether its citizens should be trusted to apply their rational faculties to
the issue and decide their own best interests, even when presented with
truthful "information"'" from conflicting viewpoints.
Posadas turns standard First Amendment assumptions on their
heads. The restrictions in Posadasbanned truthful speech to an audience
of Puerto Rican residents based on the assumption that they would be
seduced into "overconsuming" casino gambling. 145 The restrictions as-
sumed, and the Court accepted, that Puerto Ricans as a whole, and not4
merely a small subset of them, would misapprehend their own interests.
The Court allowed the State to manipulate its consumers by limiting
their stock of information about gambling, and did so, ironically, in the
name of protecting them from manipulation by casino advertisers. Posa-
139. Indeed, the Court later accepted the argument that since Puerto Rico could have banned
casino gambling (but chose not to do so), it could take the "lesser" step of banning advertisements
promoting casino gambling. Id. at 345-46.
140. Id. at 342.
141. Id. at 341-42.
142. Id. at 343.
143. Id. at 344. In addition, the Court concluded that because Puerto Rico could prohibit gam-
bling altogether, it could certainly take the lesser step of prohibiting advertisements for gambling. Id.
at 346 ("[I]t is precisely because the government could have enacted a wholesale prohibition of the
underlying conduct that it is permissible for the government to take the less intrusive step of allowing
the conduct, but reducing the demand through restrictions on advertising.").
144. Some scholars have pointed out that much advertising is not truly "informational" and does
not contribute to rational decision making. See, e.g., Ronald K.L. Collins & David M. Skover, The
First Amendment in an Age of Paratroopers,68 TEx. L. REv. 1087, 1100-03 (1990). But arguably a
rational consumer can disaggregate the informational and non-informational components of an adver-
tisement and make his own determination of value. In the realm of core speech, the First Amendment
fully protects some works whose value is not purely or even predominantly informational, but protec-
tion of core speech is justified by an interest in fostering individual self-fulfillment that is not present
in the realm of commercial speech. Cf Hurley v. Irish-Am. Gay, Lesbian & Bisexual Group of Bos-
ton, Inc., 515 U.S. 557, 569 (1995) (noting that forms of art like music and songs are protected by the
First Amendment).
145. See Posadasde P.R. Assocs., 478 U.S. at 344.
146. See id.
das rejects not just the rational consumer assumption,147 but also the as-
sumption "that some accurate information is better than no information
at all."'" Posadas, in fact, assumes that citizens would be better off if
they did not know that casino gambling existed.1 49 The implied audience
in Posadas is a group of unsophisticated and credulous consumers in
need of paternalistic intervention.
It is hard to reconcile this model of the implied audience with the
one more commonly applied in core speech cases, and in fact the Court
has never tried. Yet the modern trend, even in commercial speech cases,
is to give more credit to the targets of commercial speech. Indicative of
this trend is 44 Liquormart,Inc. v. Rhode Island,5 " which held unconsti-
tutional a ban on advertising retail prices of alcoholic beverages, 1 '
though the Justices had trouble agreeing on a single rationale for the
holding. A majority of Justices believed that the ban on price advertising
failed the Central Hudson test,152 although at least four Justices suggested
that intermediate scrutiny was insufficiently protective of the speech in-
terests involved in the case.'53 The State's reason for the ban on price ad-
vertising was to inhibit alcohol consumption among its citizens.15 4 Al-
147. There was a five member majority. Justice Brennan was joined in his dissent by Justices
Marshall and Blackmun. Id. at 348 (Brennan, J., dissenting). Justice Stevens dissented separately in
an opinion joined by Justices Marshall and Blackmun. Id. at 359 (Stevens, J., dissenting).
148. Id. at 358 (Brennan, J., dissenting) (quoting Cent. Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Pub. Serv.
Comm'n, 447 U.S. 557, 562 (1980)). The dissenters likewise contended that "[t]he First Amendment
presupposes that 'people will perceive their own best interests if only they are well enough informed,
and ... the best means to that end is to open the channels of communication, rather than to close
them."' Id. (quoting Va. State Bd. of Pharmacy v. Va. Citizens Consumer Council, Inc., 425 U.S. 748,
770 (1976)).
149. See id. (Brennan, J., dissenting) ("I would hold that Puerto Rico may not suppress the disse-
mination of truthful information about entirely lawful activity merely to keep its residents ignorant.");
see also Daniel Halberstam, Commercial Speech, Professional Speech, and the ConstitutionalStatus of
Social Institutions,147 U. PA. L. REV. 771, 858 (1999) ("In... Posadas .... the reason for keeping the
information from potential consumers was not based on a concern about such information coming
from any seller, but simply on a desire to keep such information from the audience as a general mat-
ter.").
150. 517 U.S. 484 (1996). In Rubin v. Coors Brewing Co., 514 U.S. 476, 478 (1995), the Court
held, 9-0, that a ban on truthful advertising of alcohol content on beer labels violated the First
Amendment. The Court rejected the notion that a different constitutional standard should apply to
"vice" advertising than to other forms of commercial speech. Id. at 489-90.
151. 44 Liquormart,Inc., 517 U.S. at 489.
152. Id. at 508 (principal opinion supported by four votes); see also id. at 517-18 (Scalia, J., con-
curring in part and in the judgment) (expressing disapproval of the Central Hudson test as "hav[ing]
nothing more than policy intuition to support it," but agreeing that it "would prohibit the challenged
regulation"); id. at 523 (Thomas, J., concurring in part and in the judgment) ("I do not join the prin-
cipal opinion's application of the Central Hudson balancing test because I do not believe that such a
test should be applied to a restriction of 'commercial' speech, at least when, as here, the asserted inter-
est is one that is to be achieved through keeping would-be recipients of the speech in the dark."); id. at
528-29 (O'Connor, J., with whom Rehnquist, C.J., Souter and Breyer, JJ., join, concurring in the
judgment) (concluding that the ban failed Central Hudson).
153. See id. at 501 (principal opinion supported by three votes) (arguing that bans on commercial
speech "for reasons unrelated to the preservation of a fair bargaining process" deserved more "rigor-
ous" First Amendment review); id. at 523 (Thomas, J., concurring in part and in the judgment) (ar-
guing that a stricter standard than intermediate scrutiny should apply).
154. See id. at 492-94 (majority opinion).
155. Id. at 528-29 (O'Connor, J., concurring in the judgment) (stating that all parties agree the
State's interest was substantial and that the ban directly advanced it, but holding that the ban nonethe-
less was unconstitutional because it was more extensive than necessary).
156. Id. at 494 (majority opinion).
157. See id. at 504-05 (principal opinion supported by four votes) (emphasis omitted).
158. Id. at 507.
159. Id.
160. Id. at 503 (principal opinion supported by three votes). One can also read in the opinion a
respect for the processes of democratic self governance. An increase in taxes on alcoholic beverages
will make citizens aware of the State's temperance policy in a way that a ban on price advertising of
alcoholic beverages will not.
161. Id. at 507-08 (principal opinion supported by four votes).
162. Id. at 503 (principal opinion supported by three votes). Though Justice Thomas did not sign
on to this portion of the principal opinion, he agreed with its sentiments. See id. at 518 (Thomas, J.,
concurring) (contending that restrictions on speech are "per se illegitimate" when based on an asserted
interest "to keep legal users of a product or service ignorant in order to manipulate their choices in the
marketplace"). Thus, at least four Justices explicitly disavowed paternalism as a basis for regulating
commercial speech.
163. Id. (Thomas, J., concurring).
core speech jurisprudence might look different without the reigning as-
sumptions of rationalism and anti-paternalism.
2 F.C.C.R. 5043, 5058 (1987) ("[T]he dramatic transformation in the telecommunications marketplace
provides a basis for the [Supreme] Court to reconsider its application of diminished First Amendment
protection to the electronic media."); see also Telecomm. Research & Action Ctr. v. FCC, 801 F.2d
501, 508 (D.C. Cir. 1986) (rejecting the scarcity rationale). The Supreme Court has declined to extend
the broadcast paradigm to other media. See Reno v. ACLU, 521 U.S. 844, 868-70 (1997) (declining to
apply the Red Lion paradigm to the Internet because it is not characterized by scarcity and has not
been historically subject to regulation"); Turner Broad. Sys., Inc. v. FCC, 512 U.S. 622, 637 (1994) (de-
clining to extend Red Lion to cable television); Miami Herald Publ'g Co. v. Tornillo, 418 U.S. 241, 258
(1974) (holding unconstitutional a statute granting political candidates the right to reply to attack on
their records in newspapers). For a good survey of the Court's jurisprudence in this area, read Chris-
topher S. Yoo, The Rise and Demise of the Technology-Specific Approach to the First Amendment, 91
GEO. L.J. 245 (2003).
181. See, e.g., C. Edwin Baker, Scope of the First Amendment Freedom of Speech, 25 UCLA L.
REv. 964, 965-66 (1978); Jerome A. Barron, Access to the Press-A New FirstAmendment Right, 80
HARV. L. REV. 1641, 1644-47 (1967); Kent Greenawalt, Free Speech Justifications,89 COLUM. L. REV.
119, 135 (1989).
182. Pew Research Ctr. for the People & the Press, Candidates' Policy Positions Still Not Widely
Known, PEwRESEARCHCENTERPUBLICATIONS, July 16, 2008, http://pewresearch.org/pubs/899/
candidates-policy-positions-still-not-widely-known.
183. PEW RESEARCH CTR. FOR THE PEOPLE & THE PRESS, POLITICAL KNOWLEDGE UPDATE:
AWARENESS OF IRAQ WAR FATALITIES PLUMMETS 2 (2008), http://people-press.org/reports/pdf/401.
pdf.
184. Id. Many Americans are ignorant of basic political information. A 2004 study, for example,
revealed that only thirty-one percent of Americans knew that William Rehnquist was Chief Justice of
the Supreme Court (though eighty-six percent knew that Dick Cheney was Vice President). Stephen
Earl Bennett, Political Ignorance Revisited, PUBLIC OPINION PROS, Dec. 2005, http://www.
publicationopinionpros.norc.org/features/2005/dec/bennett.asp.
185. See Mark Fenster, The Opacity of Transparency, 91 IOWA L. REV. 885, 928 (2006) (citing "[a]
vast body of empirical studies demonstrat[ing] citizens' lack of political knowledge," but observing
that public choice theory explains why "the public's ignorance is rational").
186. Michael Dimock, Belief that Obama Is Muslim Is Durable,Bipartisan-ButMost Likely to
Sway Democratic Votes, PEWRESEARCHCENTERPUBLICATIONS, July 15, 2008, http://pewresearch.org/
pubsI898/belief-that-obama-is-muslim-is-bipartisan-but-most-likey-t-sway-democrats.
ported in the New York Times, "Americans are as likely to believe in fly-
ing saucers as in evolution."' 1 7 And eighteen percent of Americans be-
lieve the sun orbits the earth. 18
Cognitive psychology provides a new window on these lamentable
statistics and, in the process, raises questions about the ideal of rationali-
ty and whether most citizens would be better off even if the marketplace
ideal became a reality. "Cognitive psychology is concerned with internal
processes, mental limitations, and the way in which the processes are
shaped by the limitations."' 189 One of the basic insights of cognitive psy-
chology is that human decision making is not perfectly rational. 19 This
insight, which is also the basis for behavioral economics,19' is incorpo-
rated in a concept known as "bounded rationality."'" According to Her-
bert Simon, "boundedly rational agents experience limits in formulating
and solving complex problems and in processing (receiving, storing, re-
trieving, transmitting) information.' '193 Individuals become boundedly
rational when complex decision-making environments tax their cognitive
faculties. In the face of complexity, individuals typically employ heuris-
tics-i.e., "mental shortcuts"' 94-to aid their decision making, but these
heuristics can cause decision making to depart from what strict rationali-
ty would dictate. Though my aim here is not to delve deeply into the rich
literature of cognitive psychology and behavioral economics, a couple of
examples of how heuristics might impede fully rational decision making
187. Nicholas D. Kristof, 'With a Few More Brains... ,'N.Y. TIMES, Mar. 30, 2008, at WK14.
188. Sam Wang & Sandra Aamodt, Your Brain Lies to You, N.Y. TIMES, June 27,2008, at A19.
189. Daniel Kahneman et al., Preface to JUDGMENT UNDER UNCERTAINTY: HEURISTICS AND
BIASES xi, xii (Daniel Kahneman et al. eds., 1982). In addition to cognitive biases, emotion can also
cloud humans' abilities to make rational decisions. For further discussion, see Jeremy A. Blumenthal,
Emotional Paternalism,35 FLA. ST. U. L. REV. 1, 3-4 (2007) (discussing the ways in which emotions
distort decision making).
190. For these purposes, a decision is rational if it (1) "is based on the decision maker's current
assets," monetary as well as psychological; (2) "is based on the possible consequences of the choice";
(3) calculates the likelihood of uncertain consequences "according to the basic rules of probability
theory"; and (4) is chosen with regard for the "constraints" of probable outcomes and the "values or
satisfactions associated" with those outcomes. REID HASTIE & ROBYN M. DAWES, RATIONAL
CHOICE IN AN UNCERTAIN WORLD: THE PSYCHOLOGY OF JUDGMENT AND DECISION MAKING 18
(2001). Based on this definition, research in psychology shows that not only do people often make
"patently irrational" decisions, they are "irrational in systematic ways-ways related to their automatic
or 'bounded' thinking habits." Id. at 22.
191. See Jeffrey L. Harrison, Happiness, Efficiency, and the Promise of DecisionalEquity: From
Outcome to Process, 36 PEPp. L. REv. 935, 937 (2009) ("[Clonventional economics is based on beha-
vioral assumptions that have over the last twenty-five years come under increasing scrutiny. Principal
among these assumptions is that people are rational and motivated by self-interest alone.").
192. See Herbert A. Simon, Introductory Comment, in ECONOMICS, BOUNDED RATIONALITY
AND THE COGNITIVE REVOLUTION 3,3-7 (Herbert A. Simon et al. eds., 1992).
193. Oliver E. Williamson, The Economics of Organization: The Transaction Cost Approach, 87
AM. J. SOC. 548, 553 (1981) (citing HERBERT A. SIMON, MODELS OF MAN: SOCIAL AND RATIONAL
198-99 (1957)).
194. See BARRY SCHWARTZ, THE PARADOX OF CHOICE: WHY MORE Is LESS 57 (2004); see also
HASTIE & DAWES, supra note 190, at 95 ("People rely on cognitive strategies that 'work' most of the
time; are cognitively economical; and are robust in the sense that they are durable in the face of in-
complete information, changing situations, and momentary distraction. But most of these strategies
also produce signature errors and biases .... ").
may help the reader understand the emerging challenge to the market-
place of ideas.
One example is the framing effect: research reveals that how a ques-
tion is framed fundamentally affects peoples' answers. In a well-known
experiment, Nobel Prize winners Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky
asked research subjects to fill out questionnaires about how to handle a
disease outbreak.195 Subjects were asked to imagine that 600 people
would contract a life-threatening illness for which there are two possible
treatments. They were then told: "If Program A is adopted, 200 people
will be saved.... If Program B is adopted, there is a 1/3 probability that
600 people will be saved, and 2/3 probability that no people will be
saved. ' 196 In this scenario, seventy-two percent of respondents chose
Program A, preferring saving 200 lives for certain to the risk of saving no
one. 19 Kahneman and Tversky then refrained the question and told res-
pondents: "If Program C is adopted 400 people will die.... If program D
is adopted there is [a] 1/3 probability that nobody will die, and [a] 2/3
probability that 600 people will die." 198 This question presented respon-
dents with exactly the same choice as before, but this time seventy-eight
percent chose treatment D. 99 When asked who they would save, respon-
dents made one choice; when asked who they would let die, respondents
made another. The disparity in results is explained by risk aversion and
the different ways humans perceive losses and gains.2m The first scenario
focuses on the saving of 200 people as a sure gain; the second focuses on
the death of 400 as a sure loss. The results are the same, but respon-
dents' perception of risk changes when the options are described diffe-
rently.
Framing highlights the extent to which human decision making de-
parts from the ideal of rationality. In Kahneman and Tversky's study,
195. Amos Tversky & Daniel Kahneman, The Framing of Decisions and the Psychology of
Choice, 211 SCIENCE 453, 453 (1981) [hereinafter Tversky & Kahneman, Framing]. This example is
used by HASTIE & DAWES, supra note 190, at 303; SCHWARTZ, supra note 194, at 64-65; and Bambau-
er, supra note 13, at 682. See also Barbara McNeil et al., On the Elicitation of Preferencesfor Alterna-
tive Therapies,306 NEW ENG. J. MED. 1259, 1259 (1982) (demonstrating that people respond different-
ly to treatments when presented in terms of survival rates versus mortality rates, even where the
outcomes of the treatments are exactly the same). For more on the framing effect, see David A. Ar-
mor & Shelley E. Taylor, When PredictionsFail: The Dilemma of UnrealisticOptimism, in HEURISTICS
AND BIASES: THE PSYCHOLOGY OF INTUITIVE JUDGMENT 334, 334-35 (Thomas Gilovich et al. eds.,
2002), or Daniel Kahneman & Amos Tversky, Choices, Values, and Frames, 39 AM. PSYCHOL. 341, 343
(1984).
196. Tversky & Kahneman, Framing,supra note 195, at 453.
197. Id.
198. Id.
199. Id.
200. Id. ("Inconsistent responses to [the] problems ... arise from the conjunction of a framing
effect with contradictory attitudes toward risks involving gains and losses."). Tversky and Kahneman
refused to label the "preference reversals" seen in the differing responses to the two scenarios as "nec-
essarily irrational." Id. at 458. Instead, "[l]ike other intellectual limitations, discussed.., under the
heading of 'bounded rationality,' the practice of acting on the most readily available frame can some-
times be justified by reference to the mental effort required to explore alternative frames and avoid
potential inconsistencies." Id.
201. See Chris Guthrie et al., Inside the Judicial Mind, 86 CORNELL L. REv. 777, 783 n.26 (2001)
(listing sources supporting the assertion that experts are subject to framing and other cognitive biases).
Tversky and Kahneman note that "[t]he reliance on heuristics and the prevalence of biases are not
restricted to laymen. Experienced researchers are also prone to the same biases-when they think
intuitively." Amos Tversky & Daniel Kahneman, Judgment Under Uncertainty: Heuristicsand Biases,
in JUDGMENT UNDER UNCERTAINTY: HEURISTICS AND BIASES, supra note 189, at 3,18.
202. Bambauer, supra note 13, at 683.
203. Another fallacy in this regard that may have relevance for public policy decisions is the op-
timism bias that leads humans to consistently view their own odds of avoiding an unpleasant outcome
as better than they actually are. Armor & Taylor, supra note 195, at 336. Another fallacy of relevance
to public discourse is the herd mentality, in which individuals may go along with what they believe to
be the majority consensus. This fallacy helps explain stock market bubbles and crashes. See ROBERT
J. SILLER, IRRATIONAL EXUBERANCE 148-55 (2000) (discussing overconfidence in market beha-
viors); see also David Hirshleifer & Siew Hong Teoh, Thought and Behavior Contagion in Capital
Markets, in HANDBOOK OF FINANCIAL MARKETS: DYNAMICS AND EVOLUTION 1, 1-46 (Thorsten
Hens & Klaus Reiner Schenk-Hopp6 eds., 2009). Crime may even increase crime in response to high
prosecution rates. Dan M. Kahan, Social Influence, Social Meaning, and Deterrence, 83 VA. L. REv.
349, 354 (1997) ("[Tlhe perception that one's peers will or will not disapprove exerts a much stronger
influence than does the threat of a formal sanction on whether a person decides to engage in a range
of common offenses .... ").
204. Tversky & Kahneman, supra note 201, at 11-14.
205. Id.
206. See Timur Kuran & Cass R. Sunstein, Availability Cascades and Risk Regulation, 51 STAN. L.
REv. 683, 728 (1999).
207. Troy A. Paredes, Blinded by the Light: Information Overload and Its Consequences for Se-
curities Regulation, 81 WASH. U. L.Q. 417, 456-57 (2003) ("Studies show that by trying to evaluate
more information, individuals who are accountable often overinterpret information, focus too much
on less relevant information while ignoring key (or 'diagnostic') information, and pay too much atten-
tion to conflicting information in anticipation of criticism from the party they are accountable to.").
208. Cass R. Sunstein & Richard H. Thaler, LibertarianPaternalismIs Not an Oxymoron, 70 U.
CHI. L. REv. 1159, 1196 (2003); see also GERALD DWORKIN, THE THEORY AND PRACrICE OF
AUTONOMY 62, 80 (1988); SCHWARTZ, supra note 194, at 3. This also means that people are easily
manipulated by propaganda.
209. Sheena S. Iyengar & Mark R. Lepper, When Choice Is Demotivating: Can One Desire Too
Much of a Good Thing?, 79 J. PERSONALITY & SOC. PSYCHOL. 995,996-97 (2000).
210. Id. at 997.
211. Sheena Iyengar et al., How Much Choice Is Too Much?: Contributions to 401(k) Retirement
Plans 9 (Pension Research Council, Working Paper No. 2003-10). Even experienced professionals fall
prey to decision paralysis when faced with numerous options. See Bambauer, supra note 13, at 683.
212. See SCHWARTZ, supra note 194, at 1-8. Increased information-in the form of exposure to
both sides of an issue-may even lead to increased polarization of attitudes. For additional discussion,
see Lee Sigelman & Carol K. Sigelman, Judgments of the Carter-Reagan Debate: The Eyes of the Be-
holders,48 PUB. OPINION Q. 624,624 (1984).
213. Mark Kelman et al., Context-Dependencein Legal Decision Making, 25 J. LEGAL STUD. 287,
290-91 (1996).
ty percent chose each one. 214 But when participants were asked to choose
between three cameras-low-end, mid-level, and high-end-seventy-two
percent chose the mid-level camera.215 In these contexts, more informa-
tion obviously affected decisions but did not make them more rational.
That said, it is certainly not always the case that more information leads
to worse decisions. "[I]ncreased quantities of irrelevant information"
impede decision making, but "increased amounts of relevant informa-
tion" improve it.2 6 The trick, of course, is sorting the relevant from the
irrelevant, a task which the marketplace metaphor leaves to the people
themselves, at least in the realm of core speech.
214. Id. at 288 (citing Itamar Simonson & Amos Tversky, Choice in Context: Tradeoff Contrast
and Extremeness Aversion, 29 J. MARKETING RES. 281,290 (1992)).
215. Id.
216. Charles A. O'Reilly, III, Individuals and Information Overload in Organizations:Is More
NecessarilyBetter?, 23 ACAD. MGMT. J. 684,685 (1980); see also id. at 692 (confirming these findings).
When information is limited, a menu of countless options increases the costs of decisions without
increasing the likelihood of accuracy. But when choosers are highly informed, the availability of
numerous options decreases the likelihood of error and does not greatly increase decision costs,
simply because informed choosers can more easily navigate the menu of options.
Sunstein & Thaler, supra note 208, at 1197-98.
217. Bambauer, supra note 13, at 696. As I shall contend in the next section, ideals have uses
even if they are never fully realized. See infra Part IV.B.7.
218. Like Bambauer, Paul Horwitz suggests that behavioral analysis may "sweep aside some of
the prevailing metaphors of First Amendment theory." Horwitz, supra note 21, at 8-9.
sion-making costs in the face of complexity and uncertainty. 219 This helps
explain, in part, why "democracy seems to be working pretty well" de-
spite citizens' "widespread ignorance" of many basic political facts.120 As
political scientists Richard Lau and David Redlawsk have noted, even if
American voters cannot always articulate reasoned positions on policy
issues, they may still be able to "vote[] 'correctly"' and "'in accordance
with what their fully informed preferences would be.' 2 1 In the political
realm, voters use traits such as a candidate's party affiliation or ideology
as proxies for the candidate's policy positions; 2 as a result, voting deci-
sions may end up being more rational than the relatively low levels of po-
litical knowledge amongst the citizenry would predict. While such cogni-
tive strategies are not always effective, there is no evidence that
irrationality so pervades voter decision making that we must give up on
democracy.
Moreover, it is by no means clear that one can generalize from evi-
dence that individuals are subject to cognitive biases in some settings to
the conclusion that decision making in society at large is fundamentally
flawed in a way that demands government action. There are clearly in-
stances in which aggregate decisions are more rational than individual 22 4
decisions 23 and in which the group "knows" more than the individual.
James Surowiecki wrote about this phenomenon in his book, The Wis-
dom of Crowds. Drawing on a number of studies of group decision mak-
ing, Surowiecki showed that "[i]f you ask a large enough group of di-
verse, independent people to make a prediction or estimate a probability,
and then average those estimates, the errors each of them makes in com-
ing up with an answer will cancel themselves out. ' 25 The result is that
groups of individuals acting independently of one another are very good
predictors of certain phenomena, such as whether a horse is likely to win
a race, 226 or whether a company is likely to prosper. 227 Indeed, this is why
financial markets as a whole tend to outperform all but a handful of indi-
vidual investors. 2 8 Though it is easy to point to examples of irrationality
in markets -particularly in the spring of 2010-the point is that irratio-
A. ProceduralConcerns
speech at issue only if "no reasonable interpretation" of it would place it within the unprotected cate-
gory of "express advocacy" under BCRA § 203. Id. at 469-70. Justices Scalia, Kennedy, and Thomas
believed that even this test failed to draw a bright enough line to protect core political speech. Id. at
492 (Scalia, J., concurring in part and concurring in the judgment).
232. Id. at 469 (principal opinion supported by two votes) (emphasis added) (citing Buckley v.
Valeo, 424 U.S. 1, 43 (1976) (per curiam)).
233. Id.
234. See RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF UNFAIR COMPETITION § 23 cmt. c (1995) ("Consumer sur-
veys can be helpful in establishing whether confusion is likely."); see also, e.g., Sally Beauty Co. v.
Beautyco, Inc., 304 F.3d 964, 974 (10th Cir. 2002) ("[E]vidence [of actual confusion] may be intro-
duced through surveys, although their evidentiary value depends on the methodology and questions
asked."); CAE, Inc. v. Clean Air Eng'g, Inc., 267 F.3d 660, 685 (7th Cir. 2001) ("[E]vidence of actual
confusion, if available, is entitled to substantial weight in the likelihood of confusion analysis .. ");
Rust Env't & Infrastructure, Inc. v. Teunissen, 131 F.3d 1210, 1218 (7th Cir. 1997) ("Actual confusion
can be shown by either direct evidence or by survey-evidence."); Michael J. Allen, The Role of Actual
Confusion Evidence in Trademark Infringement Litigation, 83 TRADEMARK REP. 267, 267-68 (1993)
("[M]ost courts agree that actual confusion is one of the most important factors, if not the most impor-
tant factor, considered in determining the likelihood of confusion ... .
235. 15 U.S.C. § 1114(1)(a) (2006).
236. McGregor-Doniger, Inc. v. Drizzle, Inc., 599 F.2d 1126, 1130 (2d Cir. 1979). Although the
Second Circuit references the ordinarily prudent purchaser, the very same opinion states that it is rele-
vant that purchasers may be "unknowledgeable" and "unsophisticated" and that the "purchasing pub-
lic must be credited with only a modicum of intelligence." Id. at 1138 (quoting Carnation Co. v. Cal.
Growers Wineries, 97 F.2d 80, 81 (C.C.P.A. 1938)). Similarly, courts have also noted that the test de-
pends on whether a person "with a not very definite or clear recollection as to the real trade-mark, is
likely to become confused or misled." Northam Warren Corp. v. Universal Cosmetic Co., 18 F.2d 774,
775 (7th Cir. 1927). Even so, the court need not apply the likelihood of confusion test "merely to pro-
tect the most gullible fringe of the consuming public." Indianapolis Colts, Inc. v. Metro. Bait. Football
Club Ltd., 34 F.3d 410,414 (7th Cir. 1994).
237. Colburn v. Puritan Mills, Inc., 108 F.2d 377, 378 (7th Cir. 1939).
the strength of [the prior owner's] mark, the degree of similarity be-
tween the two marks, the proximity of the products, the likelihood
that the prior owner will bridge the gap, actual confusion, and the
reciprocal of defendant's good faith in adopting its own mark, the
quality of defendant's product, and the sophistication of the buy-
38
ers.2
All this, and courts "may have to take still other variables into ac-
count. "239
In applying these factors, courts rely on their own assumptions
about how the presumed audience of purchasers would respond to the
competing trademarks, but they frequently bolster these assumptions
with the testimony of "professionals in marketing or applied statistics to
conduct surveys of consumers. ' 24 Nonetheless, this empirical evidence
does little to simplify the task of deciding whether consumers would be
likely to be confused. In the words of Judge Posner, "The battle of ex-
perts that ensues is frequently unedifying. ' '241 Not only does the "bat-
tle"-the fact that the experts are in complete disagreement as to their
"findings"-undermine judicial confidence, but judges typically are hard
pressed to assess the proffered data due to lack of expertise in statistics
or survey methodology.2 2 Moreover, the use of survey evidence raises
the question of how many members of the consuming public must be
likely to be confused to justify a finding of infringement. Is 7.6 percent
an "appreciable" number of confused purchasers, as one court was asked
to decide? 243 Considering these difficulties, both judges and scholars
have concluded that surveys regarding "actual confusion" amongst "real"
purchasers provide little benefit and add significant costs to infringement
cases. 244 If the state of affairs with regard to such evidence is unsatisfac-
tory in trademark law, there is certainly no reason for First Amendment
law to borrow it.24 This is especially true because trademark law does
not really worry about the chilling effect of expensive and protracted liti-
238. Polaroid Corp. v. Polaroid Elecs. Corp., 287 F.2d 492, 495 (2d Cir. 1961). These factors are
called the Polaroidformula. See also PAUL GOLDSTEIN & R. ANTHONY REESE, COPYRIGHT, PATENT,
TRADEMARK AND RELATED STATE DoCrRINES: CASES AND MATERIALS ON THE LAW OF
INTELLECTUAL PROPERTY 364 (6th ed. 2008) (noting, however, that "[e]ach circuit has adopted its
own factors," though the tests tend to overlap).
239. PolaroidCorp., 287 F.2d at 495.
240. IndianapolisColts, Inc., 34 F.3d at 414.
241. Id. at 415.
242. See id. at 415-16 (noting a more fundamental problem common to consumer survey research;
namely, "that people are more careful when they are laying out their money than when they are ans-
wering questions").
243. See Gen. Mills, Inc. v. Kellogg Co., 824 F.2d 622,626 (8th Cir. 1987).
244. See Harvey S. Perlman, The Restatement of the Law of Unfair Competition: A Work in
Progress,80 TRADEMARK REP. 461,472-73 (1990).
245. It is worth mentioning here that First Amendment jurisprudence dealing with religious free-
doms employs a reasonable observer test, which again rejects the use of empirical data about the real
audience. See, e.g., Van Orden v. Perry, 545 U.S. 677, 682-83 (2005).
B. FirstAmendment Values
Although courts have procedural justifications for relying on the
reasonable interpretation of core speech rather than its actual
interpretation, there are also compelling philosophical and pragmatic
justifications for doing so. The rational audience model constrains
paternalistic speech regulation, thereby protecting autonomy interests
and the foundations of democratic self-governance. 2" Moreover, the
rational audience model helps prevent the dumbing down of public
discourse by refusing to regulate based on the needs of the least educated
or least sophisticated audience members. Finally, the rational audience
model checks government abuse of its agenda-setting power to drown
out other speakers and dominate public discourse.249 In effect, this final
argument is an overlooked facet of the distrust of government strain in
First Amendment scholarship, and one that has added emphasis given
the current state of the mass media.
246. See Lisa P. Ramsey, Increasing First Amendment Scrutiny of Trademark Law, 61 SMU L.
REV. 381,417 (2008).
247. See Susan M. Gilles, Taking FirstAmendment ProcedureSeriously: An Analysis of Process in
Libel Litigation, 58 OHIO ST. L.J. 1753, 1789 (1998) ("[lI]t is now clear that chill on speakers
comes.., from concern about the costs of litigation."); Lyrissa Barnett Lidsky, Silencing John Doe:
Defamation and Discourse in Cyberspace, 49 DUKE L.J. 855, 890-92 (2000) (discussing the chilling ef-
fect of protracted litigation on free speech).
248. Both autonomy and democratic self-governance are pillars of First Amendment theory,
though they are offered to justify the protection of expression generally, rather than the embrace of
rationalism and the preference for unrestricted entrance into the marketplace of ideas. See supra
notes 16, 105 and accompanying text.
249. See supraPart IV.B.2-3.
250. Doubtless this is part of the reason that contract law presumes that parties to a contract are
capable of making rational decisions about their own ends, that tort law assumes people generally are
capable of behaving reasonably, and that the rationality assumption pervades law generally. "Many
regulatory schemes, including the federal securities laws, assume that people, at least for the most part,
are rational. Consequently, people simply need more information to better evaluate their options and
make better decisions. If this is the case, more information is always better than less." Paredes, supra
note 207, at 435.
251. THE DECLARATION OF INDEPENDENCE para. 2 (U.S. 1776); see also Owen M. Fiss, Free
Speech and Social Structure,71 IOWA L. REV. 1405, 1407 (1986) (discussing the process of "collective
self-determination").
252. Even where the Constitution imposes restraints on majoritarian decision making, deference
to majority will is the rule, not the exception. Yet deference to majority will make little sense if one
assumes that citizens are pervasively and ineluctably irrational.
253. See supra note 54 and accompanying text.
254. See, e.g., First Nat'l Bank of Boston v. Belotti, 435 U.S. 765, 783 (1978) ("[T]he Court's deci-
sions involving corporations in the business of communication or entertainment are based not only on
the role of the First Amendment in fostering individual self-expression but also on its role in affording
the public access to discussion, debate, and the dissemination of information and ideas."); Red Lion
Broad. Co. v. FCC, 395 U.S. 367,390 (1969).
255. As Robert Post has pointed out, First Amendment doctrine clears a space for "a process of
critical interaction." ROBERT C. POST, CONSTITUTIONAL DOMAINS: DEMOCRACY, COMMUNITY,
MANAGEMENT 143 (1995). Participation in discourse arguably fosters citizens' abilities to make ra-
tional decisions, not through the intervention of an "enlightened elite." "Rather, the people educate
themselves" through the "exchange of opinions, refereed by the public." Bernard Manin, On Legiti-
macy and Political Deliberation,in 4 LIBERALISM: CRITICAL CONCEPTS IN POLITICAL THEORY 247,
261 (G.W. Smith ed., 2002).
256. The anti-paternalism of First Amendment doctrine heightens the need for development of
critical faculties, making education a critical component of participation in public discourse. See
RONALD J. KROTOSZYNSKI, JR., THE FIRST AMENDMENT IN CROSS-CULTURAL PERSPECTIVE: A
COMPARATIVE LEGAL ANALYSIS OF THE FREEDOM OF SPEECH 14-15, 170 (2006) (discussing the im-
portance of education to democratic self-governance). This was a principle forwarded by Thomas Jef-
ferson in a letter to John Tyler in 1810, in which he contended that "no republic can maintain itself in
strength" without a program of "general education, to enable every man to judge for himself what will
secure or endanger his freedom." Letter from Thomas Jefferson to John Tyler (May 26, 1810), in 12
THE WRITINGS OF THOMAS JEFFERSON 393 (Andrew A. Lipscomb & Albert Ellery Bergh eds., 1903).
257. See C. EDWIN BAKER, HUMAN LIBERTY AND FREEDOM OF SPEECH 47-50 (1989).
258. Cohen v. California, 403 U.S. 15, 24 (1971) (emphasis added).
259. See BAKER, supra note 257, at 47-50 ("[T]he practices of democratic decision making or wel-
fare maximization [and utilitarianism] can often be understood as properly implementing equal re-
spect for persons as autonomous agents."); Mark G. Yudof, In Search of a Free Speech Principle,82
MICH. L. REv. 680, 695 (1984) (book review) ("[T]he dignity argument merges with the normative
argument from democracy.").
260. See BAKER, supranote 257, at 47-50.
261. See Laura A. Heymann, The Public's Domain in Trademark Law: A First Amendment
Theory of the Consumer, 43 GA. L. REv. 651, 660 (2009) (observing that a Kantian theory of autonomy
values choices because it "is personal to the individual," whereas a Millian theory "takes the conse-
quentialist view that society should prefer autonomy because it leads to the overall well-being of socie-
ty").
262. Greenawalt, supra note 181, at 150-52. But cf. Yudof, supra note 259, at 695 (arguing that
people gain just as much dignity from economic factors as from expression of ideas).
263. 418 U.S. 405 (1974).
264. Id. at 406-07.
265. Id. at 408.
266. Id. at 415.
267. For extensive discussion of the constitutional privilege for opinion, see generally Lidsky, su-
pra note 247.
268. 398 U.S. 6 (1970).
tions with the city council as "blackmail. 2 69 The Court held that the First
Amendment barred the developer's action, observing: "It is simply im-
possible to believe that a reader who reached the word 'blackmail' in ei-
ther article [published by the newspaper] would not have understood ex-
actly what was meant: it was Bresler's public and wholly legal negotiating
proposals that were being criticized." 70 Though the Court's interpreta-
tion clearly contemplated how the word blackmail would be read by a
reasonable reader, the Court found that "even the most careless reader"
would have interpreted the word as "no more than rhetorical hyperbole"
in the context in which it appeared. 7 1 Nevertheless, the Court clearly
endorsed the principle that speakers should not be held liable for "mis-
readings" of their speech by idiosyncratic or unsophisticated audience
members. Thus, the Court correctly described Bresler as playing a cen-
tral role in providing breathing space for freedom of expression.272 This
breathing space allows speakers latitude because they do not have to
concern themselves with unsophisticated audience members who will not
understand the nuances of their speech.
A second way that the rational audience model prevents the dumb-
ing down of public discourse is by acting as an exhortation to audience
members who do not reasonably decode the texts that comprise public
discourse. From this perspective, the reasonable audience model in First
Amendment law performs a function analogous to the reasonable person
in tort law. It sets a minimum standard of reasonableness to which all cit-
izens are expected to conform regardless (for the most part) of their ac-
tual capacity to do so. As the classic case of Vaughan v. Menloe 273 ex-
plains, the reasonable person standard guards against a collapse of
standards by refusing to allow negligence liability to become "co-
extensive with the judgment of each individual, which would be as varia-
ble as the length of the foot of each individual." 274 Just as the negligence
standard encourages citizens to come up to the standard of the reasona-
ble person if they do not already meet it, the effect of the rational au-
dience model is to call citizens to develop their capacities to participate
in rational discourse, and to exercise, as it were, their better natures.
Negligence law also points to another function of legal standards based
on the assumptions that people generally behave rationally. Although
the reasonable person standard seems unfair or unjust because it holds
individuals to cognitive standards which they cannot meet, it makes the
269. Id. at 7.
270. Id. at 14.
271. Id.
272. Milkovich v. Lorain Journal Co., 497 U.S. 1, 19 (1990) (finding that existing doctrine, includ-
ing Bresler, gives breathing space to free expression "without the creation of an artificial dichotomy
between 'opinion' and fact").
273. (1837) 132 Eng. Rep. 490 (C.C.P.).
274. Id. at 493 (Tindal, C.J.).
277. See, e.g., Cent. Hudson Gas & Elec. Corp. v. Pub. Serv. Comm'n, 447 U.S. 557, 563 (1980)
("The government may ban forms of communication more likely to deceive the public than to inform
it ....").
278. See MANFRED WEIDHORN, THE PERSON OF THE MILLENNIUM: THE UNIQUE IMPACT OF
GALILEO ON WORLD HISTORY 155 (2005). See generally MAURICE A. FiNoccmARo, THE GALILEO
AFFAIR: A DOCUMENTARY HISTORY (Maurice A. Finocchiaro ed. & trans., 1989).
279. FINOCCHIARO,supra note 278, at 36-37.
280. Id. at 35-39.
281. Id. at 38-39.
ry-from the Sedition Act of 1798m until the present-have come in re-
sponse to perceived threats to national security. Public policy based on
fear, and particularly the government's fear of its own citizens, is particu-
larly likely to rely on cognitively flawed reasoning.3 The Red Scare cas-
es are but one example. The Russian Revolution sparked the first "Red
Scare" in the United States. This period of "antiradical hysteria,"' be-
ginning in 1917, led to the enactment of federal and state laws to sup-
press the speech of Communists, socialists, and anarchists. "[A]t least 27
states passed 'red flag' laws (laws barring the display of flags as a sign of
opposition to organized government), 16 states passed criminal syndical-
ism laws (laws prohibiting the advocacy of overthrow of the govern-
ment), and 12 states passed anarchy and sedition laws." 5 The result of
all this "Red Scare" legislation was over 1400 arrests and 300 convic-
tions.a 6 The Supreme Court acquiesced in the suppression of dissent,8 7
deferring to state determinations of the dangers presented by radical
speech and affirming convictions based on nothing more than abstract
advocacy of the overthrow of the government "at some date necessarily
' 8
far in the future." 8
Why do First Amendment principles often succumb to irrational
fears in time of war or when there are other perceived threats to securi-
ty? During such periods, citizens and their governments may place un-
due weight on vivid events that provoke a fear response. In hindsight, it
is hard to see how Americans thought an event akin to the Russian Rev-
olution could take place in America because the underlying social condi-
tions were so dramatically different in the two countries. But the "avail-
ability" heuristic 289 undoubtedly made the "evidence" more relevant to
policy makers trying to protect "the American way of life." Moreover,
the widespread discussion of the threat may have led to an availability
cascade, convincing a significant segment of the population that the
threat was widespread and imminent. The very same pattern has been
repeated over and over throughout history, which bespeaks the need for
doctrines to help shield against even the most benevolently motivated
282. Sedition Act of 1798, 1 Stat. 596, 596-97; see also N.Y. Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254,
276 (1964) ("Although the Sedition Act was never tested in this Court, the attack upon its validity has
carried the day in the court of history." (footnote omitted)).
283. See Horwitz, supra note 21, at 36-37.
284. MURRAY B. LEVIN, POLITICAL HYSTERIA IN AMERICA: THE DEMOCRATIC CAPACITY FOR
REPRESSION 29 (1971).
285. KROTOSZYNSKI ET AL., supra note 89, at 43-44; see also PATRICIA CAYO SEXTON, THE WAR
ON LABOR AND THE LEFT: UNDERSTANDING AMERICA'S UNIQUE CONSERVATISM 135 (1991).
286. KROTOSZYNSKI ET AL., supra note 89, at 44.
287. See Whitney v. California, 274 U.S. 357, 363, 372 (1927) (affirming criminal syndicalism con-
viction for organizing and being a member of the Communist Labor Party of America, which advo-
cated the "overthrow of capitalist rule").
288. Id. at 379 (Brandeis, J., concurring). The defendant in Whitney helped organize the Com-
munist Labor Party of California, whose constitution advocated overthrow of the government. Id. at
363 (majority opinion).
289. See supra Part nI.B.
290. BERNARD GROFMAN ET AL., MINORITY REPRESENTATION AND THE QUEST FOR VOTING
EQUALITY 8 (1992) (noting that in the 1890s states used constitutional conventions to adopt means to
disenfranchise black voters). "Even as late as 1960, voter registration rates among whites in the South
were more than twice those of blacks.... " Id. at 1.
291. W. Sherman Rogers, The Black Quest for Economic Liberty: Legal, Historical and Related
Considerations,48 How. L.J. 1, 74 n.581 (2004) (noting the "desire to prevent blacks from voting" in
imposing literacy tests). States also used literacy tests to disenfranchise other groups of voters thought
to be incapable of voting intelligently, such as recent immigrants. For an extended discussion, see Le-
vine, supra note 116, at 239-40.
292. ALEXANDER KEYSSAR, THE RIGHT TO VOTE: THE CONTESTED HISTORY OF DEMOCRACY
IN THE UNITED STATES 142 (2000). The states also used residency requirements and poll taxes to con-
strict the franchise. See Levine, supra note 116, at 237.
293. See Voting Rights Act Amendments of 1970, Pub. L. No. 91-285, 84 Stat. 314, 314-19. The
nationwide ban originally was in place for five years. See id. at 315. In 1975, Congress made the ban
permanent. See Voting Rights Act Amendments of 1975, Pub. L. No. 94-73, § 102, 89 Stat. 400, 400
(codified as amended at 42 U.S.C. § 1973aa (2006)).
294. Daniel S. Goldman, Note, The Modem-Day Literacy Test?: Felon Disenfranchisement and
Race Discrimination,57 STAN. L. REv. 611, 616 (2004). This disproportion was a natural result of the
systematic deprivation of educational opportunities to black Americans. Id. at 619.
295. Williams v. Mississippi, 170 U.S. 213,221,225 (1898).
296. Id. at 222.
weak and vicious to racist state officials. Even as late as 1959, the Court
could be sanguine in its assertion that the use of facially non-
discriminatory literacy tests was constitutional, accepting the premise
that "[t]he ability to read and write ...has some relation to standards de-
signed to promote intelligent use of the ballot. ''297 Again the Court con-
ceded that state officials might apply such tests in a racially discriminato-
ry fashion, 298 but the Court failed to understand that literacy tests -which
assume at the outset that many citizens are too dumb to vote-positively
invite state officials to act on their own prejudices about their fellow citi-
zens. This is not to say that a "rational voter" assumption would have
prevented the widespread disenfranchisement of black voters. But, it
would have deprived racist state officials of the cloak of legitimacy pro-
vided by the Court's acceptance of a paternalistic justification for admin-
istration of voter literacy tests.
There is good reason to be especially suspicious of the government
when it seeks to suppress information or choices it believes to be "bad"
for its citizens because the government already manipulates citizen prefe-
rences through its role in setting the agenda of political discourse in the
United States. The federal government is a "'major source of informa-
tion,""'299 and "information is a source of power."3 °° The government, par-
ticularly the executive branch, has a variety of tools and methods to get
its message out. Government officials can gather and release data sup-
porting a particular policy agenda. High government officials can hold
press conferences, confident in the knowledge that members of the mass
media will actually show up prepared to convey some version of the gov-
ernment's message. They can also grant exclusive interviews to get their
message out, with the implicit threat that the privilege of access will be
revoked if the coverage is not to their liking.30° Government leaders can
also shape discourse by refusing to provide information: by refusing to
hold press conferences, to discuss a policy choice beyond certain agreed
upon talking points, or to allow access to documents and news sites with-
in its control? °
The government also has at its disposal more ethically questionable
ways of manipulating public discourse. It is worthwhile to consider some
297. Lassiter v. Northampton County Bd. of Elections, 360 U.S. 45, 51 (1959). However, the
Court has also recognized that such tests can be applied in a manner that violates a citizen's right to
equal protection of the laws. Id. at 53-54.
298. Id. at 53.
299. Lori Robertson, In Control, AM. JOURNALISM REV., Feb.-Mar. 2005, at 26, 28 (citation omit-
ted).
300. MALCOLM MITCHELL, PROPAGANDA, POLLS, AND PUBLIC OPINION: ARE THE PEOPLE
MANIPULATED? 46 (2d ed. 1977).
301. Robertson, supra note 299, at 30 (discussing the fact that New York Times reporters were
banned from then Vice President Dick Cheney's campaign plane as punishment for unfavorable cov-
erage).
302. See Ann Scott Tyson, Hundreds of Photos of Caskets Released-Pentagon Action Is in Re-
sponse to Lawsuit, WASH. POST, Apr. 29, 2005, at A10 (discussing the Bush administration's policy
banning photographs and videotapes of coffins at Dover Air Force Base).
303. Robert Pear, Buying of News by Bush's Aides Is Ruled Illegal, N.Y. TIMES, Oct. 1, 2005, at
Al.
304. Id.
305. Id.
306. CHALMERS JOHNSON, THE SORROWS OF EMPIRE: MILITARISM, SECRECY, AND THE END OF
THE REPUBLIC 229-30 (2004); PAUL RUTHERFORD, WEAPONS OF MASS PERSUASION: MARKETING
THE WAR AGAINST IRAQ 196 (2004).
307. See Murray Waas, Cheney "Authorized" Libby to Leak Classified Information, NAT'LJ., Feb.
9,2006, http://www.nationaljournal.com/about/njweekly/stories/2006/0209njl.htm.
308. David Barstow, PentagonSuspends Briefings for Analysts, N.Y. TIMES, Apr. 26, 2008, at A15.
309. See Potter Stewart, "Or of the Press," 26 HASTINGS L.J. 631,634 (1975).
310. Five Years On: Media's Role in Iraq, CHRISTIAN SCI. MONITOR, Mar. 19, 2008, at 8 ("The
press already stands accused of not doing enough before the war to probe the Bush administration's
arguments for the invasion, whether it was Saddam Hussein's alleged weapons or the prospects of im-
planting democracy in Iraq."); see also SCOTr MCCLELLAN, WHAT HAPPENED: INSIDE THE BUSH
WHITE HOUSE AND WASHINGTON'S CULTURE OF DECEPTION 125 (2008) (criticizing media for accept-
ing President Bush's propaganda without enough investigation); Sherry Ricchiardi, Whatever Hap-
pened to Iraq?: How the Media Lost Interest in a Long-Running War with No End in Sight, AM.
JOURNALISM REv. June-July 2008, at 20 (criticizing the lack of coverage after the initial phase of the
Iraq War). On the other hand, the Bush administration criticized the media for being unduly negative
V. CONCLUSION
in its coverage of the war in Iraq. See Michael O'Hanlon, Misplaced Blame, WASH. TIMES, Apr. 11,
2006, at A14.
311. See, e.g., Steve Fainaru, Cutting Costs, Bending Rules, and a Trail of Broken Lives: Ambush
in Iraq Last November Left Four Americans Missing and a String of Questions About the Firm They
Worked For, WASH. POST, July 29, 2007, at A01; Anthony Shadid, In Revival of Najaf Lessons for a
New Iraq: Shiite Clergy Build a Spiritual Capital,WASH. POST, Dec. 10, 2003, at A01.
312. See, e.g., Tribune Will Cut Hundreds of Jobs as Businesses Weaken, N.Y. TIMES, Feb. 14,
2008, at C9.
313. McConnell v. FEC, 540 U.S. 93, 258 (2003) (Scalia, J., concurring in part and dissenting in
part).
314. John Updike, All Things Considered: Testing the Limits of What I Know and What I Feel
(NPR radio broadcast Apr. 18, 2005), availableat http://thisibelieve.org/essay/14/ ("To guarantee the
individual maximum freedom within a social frame of minimal laws ensures-if not happiness-its
hopeful pursuit.").
315. Id.