Origen de La Vida Social
Origen de La Vida Social
Origen de La Vida Social
Life
Evolution After Science Studies
Myra J. Hird
The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science
Studies
Also by Myra J. Hird
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
18 17 16 15 14 13 12 11 10 09
Printed and bound in Great Britain by
CPI Antony Rowe, Chippenham and Eastbourne
Contents
v
vi Contents
Notes 144
Index 197
List of Figures and Tables
Figures
vii
viii List of Figures and Tables
Tables
All attempts have been made by the author and publisher to contact
copyright holders but please contact the publishers regarding any errors
and we would be pleased to correct any oversights.
Preface and Acknowledgments
This book began in 1999 when I was on study leave at the University
of Manchester in the United Kingdom. Taking a break from my writing
on Freudian pycho-analytic theory, I went for a walk and happened
upon a used bookstore. There I found, for the sum of £1, Distinguished
University Professor Lynn Margulis and Dorion Sagan’s book What is
Sex?3 With full color pictures of bacteria, fungi, prokaryotes, inverte-
brates and vertebrates, this book initiated a sea-change in my intellec-
tual horizon. At the time, my research focused on the ontology of gender
difference, employing those theories so familiar to feminist social
sciences – performativity, psychoanalysis and so on – with increasing
frustration. Versed in feminist (and more broadly social theoretical)
calls to return to ‘the body’, I wanted to engage with the materiality of
bodies, and especially nonhuman bodies. And here it was, in a book
written by an evolutionary theorist whose research I soon began to
familiarize myself with. This interest culminated, eight years and many
diversions later, in a sabbatical in the Department of Geosciences,
University of Massachusetts Amherst, where I wrote the bulk of this
book.
I am forever grateful to Liz Stanley, who not only graciously arranged
my first sabbatical at the University of Manchester, and thus inadver-
tently started me on this path, but for giving me the idea of contacting
ix
x Preface and Acknowledgments
the Margulis Laboratory. I never would have had the nerve to do this with-
out Liz’s encouragement. I thank Celeste Asikainen, Research Fellow, PhD
student and Margulis Laboratory Assistant, for using great tact and polite-
ness in her attempt, for good reason, to dissuade me from pursuing my
research. As I later came to understand, Margulis’s research has been mis-
quoted, misconstrued and manipulated out of all context, as much by
social as natural scientists. I thank and greatly appreciate the Social
Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada for awarding me a
generous grant with which to carry out the research contained in this
book, and to Queen’s University for supporting my sabbatical leave. I
thank my dedicated head of department, Rob Beamish, for keeping me
in the teaching and administrative loop, while also allowing me to
completely ignore it.
Above all, I thank Lynn Margulis, who, against her better judgment
I’m sure, graciously invited me to take her graduate course, Microbial
Communities in 2006 (which I ended up taking twice because I liked it
so much), and then to spend the 2007–2008 academic year in her labor-
atory. If her hundreds of books and articles have not inspired me,
Margulis’s dedication to science has irrevocably changed the course of
my life. She, like Horton who ‘hears a who!’, and more than anyone else
I know of, has helped microbes yell (after all, a person’s a microbe, no
matter how big). That most of us still don’t hear their vivid calling is our
own fault entirely.
The Margulis Laboratory is a place, to borrow from both Donna
Haraway and Karen Barad, where naturecultures intra-act: pictures of
Margulis amid rows of scientists at various meetings (she is typically the
only woman in these pictures); scores of honors tucked behind fridges
containing various microbial communities; scientists; cameras; termites;
Petri-dishes; theories; unwashed dishes; solar rays; janitorial staff; under-
grad and graduate students; runaway cockroaches escaping from neigh-
boring labs; a murky Miller/Urey-type vat; generous amounts of dust;
computers; music; pens and paper and so on. To all of these, I owe a debt
I am not asked to, nor could I, repay.
I thank Michael Dolan, Michael Chapman, Jim MacAllister, Sean
Faukner, Carolina Galen, Emily Case, Kendra Clark, Idalia Rodriguez and
Bruce Scofield for answering my horribly naïve questions about termite
hindgut symbionts, electron microscopes, earthworms, forams, nema-
toads, karyomastigonts, microtubule-organizing-centres (MTOCs),
and countless other subjects in the Garden of Microbial Delights. (I
apologize, Mike Chapman, for harshing your mellow several times in my
attempts to understand the microbial world.) Thank you Michael Dolan
Preface and Acknowledgments xi
and Carolina for also letting me shadow you in your termite symbiont
experiments, all the while clogging your ears with my incessant ques-
tions. Thanks also Michael Dolan for letting me audit Social Biology
– a thought-provoking course indeed. I thank Dorion Sagan too, for
graciously putting up with my nagging company. I thank Professor
James Walker at UMass for allowing me to audit Cosmos to Humanity, a
course that most definitely changed my view of the universe. My regular
lunches with Jim, in which we discussed a gamut of topics from cells to
the solar system, were certainly a highlight of my sabbatical experience.
When I began my research in the Margulis Laboratory, I was aware of
Lynn’s eminent research career. I was unaware of her dedication to teach-
ing; that is, the unstinting enthusiasm with which Lynn routinely stimu-
lates epiphanic moments. I fear these ‘ah ha’ moments are uncommon in
the jaded academic’s life. Thanks to Lynn and her colleagues, I had several
such moments while at the University of Massachusetts. Nevertheless,
I am conscious of the fact that my job as a sociologist drew me to social
theories, to ways of thinking about symbiogenesis, evolutionary theory
and Gaia, that, for natural scientists, may well seem beside the point. And
so, as is custom, I take full responsibility for the connections I make in
this book between science and social theory, and I respect that much of
what I say here is what Lynn succinctly calls ‘he said, she said’. I thank
Michael Dolan for reading through this manuscript and correcting, at
least, my most obvious misreadings of microbiology.
I am assuming that much of what I present here will invoke disagree-
ment, debate and challenge (and rightly so). My aim is not to present this
material as either all-encompassing, or from a ‘magisterial viewpoint’.
What initially drew me to What is Sex? and over the years to Margulis’s
other publications, is that her research takes matter very seriously. For a
social theorist, this is refreshing in and of itself. My overall goal in writing
this book has been to harness theories and evidence from Margulis’s
research to think through themes familiar to social scientists: paradigms,
epistemic cultures, individuality and subjectivity. Although trying to
understand and then use this research on nature has required that I inter-
rogate my reliance upon particular configurations of realism, representa-
tionalism and social constructionism, I have come to appreciate that one
can understand philosophy of science issues such as paradigms and epis-
temic cultures, and also study and appreciate nonhuman matter. Indeed,
if we want to find out anything outside of culture, what other choice do
we have?
My overall goal is to begin to think about some of the issues that pre-
occupy social scientists – identity, selfhood, the environment, sexual
xii Preface and Acknowledgments
Introduction
1
2 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
porary evolutionary theory and its valid interpretation for public diges-
tion. Each scientist makes claims about the use of evidence (fossil
records for example) and theory in ways that are dependent on socio-
political ideas that are obscured precisely because the subject matter
– evolution – is assumed to be natural.
There is a real world; its properties are not merely social con-
structions; facts and evidence do matter. What sane person
would contend otherwise? And yet, much contemporary acad-
emic theorizing consists precisely of attempts to blur these obvious
truths.4
Which bring us full swing to the side of the earth giants. The Sophists
argued that knowledge is a form of belief, and a position of skepticism
concerning the impossibility of True knowledge has filtered down through
philosophy ever since. George Berkeley, David Hume and John Locke
championed empiricism, the theory that all knowledge derives from our
After War 5
senses that formulate our experiences and knowledge of the world onto
the mind. We achieve knowledge about nature by applying reason to
‘primary sensations’ such as size and shape that belong to things-in-
themselves. Our knowledge is a derived one, based on the accumulation
of experiences, and thus can never be certain, universal, necessary and
true.
Francis Bacon’s The New Organon argued that knowledge is best
achieved through meticulous, thorough and detailed observation of the
natural world – a very practical ‘hands on’ method distinct from know-
ledge through esoteric reasoning. Bacon believed that knowledge was dis-
cerned by the ‘quieting of the mind’.12 Bacon’s idols – of the tribe, cave,
marketplace and theatre – all describe ways in which knowledge is con-
taminated through prejudices of the mind. Hume exposed this problem
through his focus on causality, which he argued did not define certainty
and truth, but rather ‘uniformities in our experience’ that we ‘project into
the future and…expect those patterns to exist in the future.’13 For Hume,
empiricism is on the slippery slope to skepticism: not surprisingly Kant
said that Hume had roused him from his ‘dogmatic slumbers’.
Moreover, the earth giants have at their disposal a social scientific
critique focused on the premise that all natural sciences depend upon
one or more initial propositions, and that, contra Plato and Socrates,
these propositions are born of the social enterprise that is science itself.
Two well-known examples from the history and philosophy of science
illustrate one of the major enterprises of contemporary science studies.
The Copernican revolution required the adoption of Copernicus’s
system of the planets and rejecting Ptolemy’s. It required a leap of,
however rationally guised, faith:
in which the earth rotates on its axis but is stationary and the sun
orbits the earth, Mercury and Venus, the inner planets orbit the sun as
it orbits the earth, and Mars, Jupiter and Saturn orbit both the sun and
the earth. History being on the side of the winners, we take Newton’s
vindication of the Copernican system (which he ironically substant-
iated by using Kepler’s ideas that were based on Brahe’s research). How-
ever, Galileo did not (nor could he have) come up with an experi-
ment that would have disproved Brahe’s system while substantiating
Copernicus’s. Although Galileo knew of both Brahe’s theory and
Kepler’s idea that the planets orbit the sun in ellipses, he ignored
both. Galileo’s Dialogue on the Two Great World Systems (1632) is a
conversation between Ptolemy and Copernicus, with Copernicus in
the clear lead. In fact, we now accept Kepler’s theory that, not only do
the planets orbit in ellipses, but that they do not move at uniform
speeds.
Retrospectively, we can reasonably say that Galileo, Newton and
Descartes were all wrong and that they did not really have a
purchase on the Truth, even though they all thought, and we
maintain today, that they engendered knowledge. So the scien-
tific enterprise is more complicated than we typically allow. Galileo
deleted some information, emphasized other ideas and based his
work on a combination of theoretical speculation, creative gedankens
and witty argument. Just as we now agree that a great deal of the
science during this period, including that of Galileo and Newton, is
erroneous, it is reasonable to assume that what we now hold to be
scientifically substantiated will, 400 years from now, be considered
incorrect.
The second example concerns the invention of the airpump. Robert
Boyle and Robert Hooke developed a series of experiments on air using
an air pump invented in the seventeenth century.15 These experiments
were widely acclaimed and caught the critical attention of Thomas
Hobbes. Hobbes argued that experiments could not reveal causes
because it is impossible to separate facts of nature from any given arti-
fact produced by the machine/experiment itself. As Goldman points
out, it is one thing to agree that an x-ray is a valid and accurate depic-
tion of a bone; it is another to agree that a particular shadow represents
an aneurysm.16 To agree on the latter requires specialized training with
the measuring instrument, which necessarily introduces a social
dimension (classification scheme and so on) into the determination of
truth. While Hobbes is usually regarded as the loser in the ‘air pump
debate’, in fact he had a rather good point. Since machines necessarily
After War 7
already embody the theories used to build them (x-ray machines are
built to provide x-ray images; air pumps were invented to create
vacuums), how can we with any certainty differentiate between the
measuring instrument and the theory? In other words, ‘the expectation
of what the machine is going to show you is already there. How can
you use that as a confirmation of the expectation?’17 And how can we
know, with certainty, that the data collected from measuring instru-
ments are a faithful, exact and consistent reflection of the object of
study? Norman Campbell notes that the fundamental laws of nature
do not correspond to the world we discern (we are moving at a rate of
24,000 miles every 24 hours).18 What we have is a network of theories
and an understanding of how the measuring instruments we have
created work.19 For this reason, Ian Hacking argues that phenomena
are created in the laboratory, and Steve Fuller writes, ‘discovery favors
the prepared mind’.20
And now?
This result has been observed with electrons, neutrons, atoms and
other matter, and even occurs when a single particle at a time is propelled
through the slits. So how does a single electron ‘interfere’ with itself, in a
wave sense? How can a single electron go through both slits at once?23
Classical Newtonian physics holds that electrons, atoms and so on
are either waves or particles, independent of their observation or other
experimental circumstances, and that experiments reveal objects in
themselves. One obvious way to try to explain these results is that they
only apply to really small things. But the Correspondence Principle
states that quantum and Newtonian mechanics must correspond – that
there cannot be two (macro and micro) conflicting realities.24 That is,
while a sense of ‘blurring’ (probability) makes sense at the microscopic
level, it makes no sense at the macroscopic level. Things measured
at the macroscopic level are not blurry or probabilistic; they produce
definite values.25
After War 9
We can either find out which path an individual electron goes through
(in which case the resulting pattern will resemble that of particles)
or we can not know which path the electron takes, and end up with a
wave pattern. What Bohr is arguing, contra Heisenberg, is that this is
not a measurement problem to be resolved with greater technologically
precise instrumentation or more objective observation procedures.
10 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
I just want to explain what I mean when I say that we should try to
hold onto physical reality… That which we conceive as existing
(‘actual’) should somehow be localized in time and space. That is,
the real in one part of space, A, should (in theory) somehow ‘exist’
independently of that which is thought of as real in another part of
space, B… What is actually present in B should thus not depend
upon the type of measurement carried out in the part of space, A; it
should also be independent of whether or not, after all, a measure-
ment is made in A… If one renounces the assumption that what is
present in different parts of space has an independent, real exist-
ence, then I do not at all see what physics is supposed to describe.
For what is thought to be a ‘system’ is, after all, just conventional,
and I do not see how one is supposed to divide up the world objec-
tively so that one can make statements about its parts.31
The crux of Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen’s argument is this: ‘If, without
in any way disturbing a system, we can predict with certainty (i.e., with
probability equal to unity) the value of a physical quantity, then there
exists an element of physical reality corresponding to this physical quan-
tity’.32 If, in other words, we can control a system such that it is either
not disturbed at all, or its total disturbance can be measured and
accounted for, we can retain a notion of causality, and thus reality, as
defined by classical physics. Put another way, quantum theory presents
an epistemological issue that could, theoretically, be overcome by tech-
nological developments in measuring instruments.
Bohr recognized Einstein’s disquiet and responded in ‘Discussion
with Einstein on Epistemological Problems in Atomic Physics’ by first
recognizing the apparent disjuncture between causality at the macro
After War 11
culture, and have coined terms aimed at, if not completely rejecting then
at the very least significantly narrowing, the matter-culture bifurcation,
for instance: Latour’s ‘parliament of things’, ‘co-production’ and ‘infra-
physics’; Callon’s ‘actor network’; Stenger’s ‘cosmopolitics’; Law’s ‘rela-
tional materialism’; Pickering’s ‘noncorrespondence realism’; Serres’s
‘quasi-object’; Kearnes’s ‘relational intersubjectivity’; Fuller’s ‘social epi-
stemology’; Bergson’s ‘to vary with’ matter itself and ‘image’; Braidotti’s
‘new materialism’ and ‘transpositions’; Irwin’s ‘co-constructions’; Fox
Keller’s ‘dynamic objectivity’; and Haraway’s ‘naturecultures’.43 In what
follows, I conduct a preliminary sketch of the elements of several of these
approaches and leave their further elaboration to subsequent chapters.
The Sociology of Scientific Knowledge’s (SSK) ‘strong program’s’ ‘sym-
metry postulate’ argues that all ideas (whether rational, irrational, true
or false) are social ‘through and through’ as opposed to the Kantian idea
that true (rational) beliefs are based on reality while false (irrational)
beliefs are based on societal influences.44 For Kant, the true belief that the
earth revolves around the sun is based on rational science (employing
the scientific method) whereas the false belief that the stars and planets
revolve around the earth was based on Christian church influences. SSK is
able to hold both true and false beliefs (as in the example above) on equal
footing because the ‘correspondence’ of beliefs to reality is itself based
on subjective assertion, imputation or acceptance. Thompson provides a
flavor of this perspective:
For the strong program, nature is more complex than observers’ attempts
to explain it: we come to understand parts of nature through an endless
refining process of observation and interpretation, and it is this contin-
uous refining process sociologists of science analyze.47 Reality possesses
causal agency, not least in its ability to stimulate the sense organs, and by
extension, the sentient analytic process itself. In order to analyze these
refining processes, sociologists must ascertain detailed knowledge about
what scientists are responding to – their stimuli – whether neutrinos,
genes or protoctists. In other words, nature centrally impacts on our beliefs
about how nature is experienced, but it does not causally explain how it
is then described (although in a strict sense and given Bloor’s assertion
that the human mind is necessarily part of nature, the description itself
must at least be, partially, causally explained by nature). As such, Bloor
describes the strong program as relativist in the sense that it is concerned
to evaluate theories and beliefs in terms of their credibility, which necess-
arily engages with the social aspects of science, consisting of the context
in which any given theories or beliefs are found (including classification,
rules, principles and so on). Interestingly, Bloor does not characterize the
subject-object as a zero-sum game in which the more we know as fact, the
less it is based on subjectivity (in the phenomenological sense), because
for Bloor, ‘all knowledge always depends on society’ and is thus necess-
arily provisional.48 Adherents argue that SSK provides a ‘third method’
that solves the problem of relying upon scientific descriptions and
explanations of nonhuman matter. However, my unease with the strong
program is that, in practice, it aims to ‘explain shared beliefs about
nature’ and nature seems to remain effectively silent.49 SSK depends upon
a knowing human subject that, as Maturala and Varela put it, ‘brings
forth a world’. Microbes, in SSK, do not bring forth a world. What Collins
and Yearley identify as a strength of SSK, to ‘…show that the appar-
After War 15
… [T]here are two and only two known and fixed repertoires of
agencies which are stocked at the two extremities – brute material
16 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
What makes the atom more real [than a ghost] is that it has more
allies, and these allies stretch well beyond humans. Experiments
testify to the atom’s existence; instruments stabilize it and make
it indirectly visible; generations of children learn of it and pass
the word along; Brownian motion shows that particles of water are
moved by it. The ghost, by contrast, has only a paltry number of
allies bearing witness to its reality. But the atom’s allies may one day
desert it too.61
The problem with the strong program, for Latour, is that it under-
determines the ability of objects to effect our understandings (beliefs,
theories) about them. Contrasting SSK’s advancement of symmetry
with regard to valid and invalid science, Woolgar refers to ANT’s
‘radical symmetry with regard to agency’.62 Indeed ANT proponents
reverse what they see as SSK’s desire to ‘strip science of its extravagant
claim to authority’ by asserting that ‘nature settles controversies’.63 Put
another way, ‘the belief system has to register the world without the
world introducing any significant difference, apart from its mute pres-
ence and insistence’.64 For ANT, the ‘things themselves are actants, not
signifieds, phenomena, or tools for human praxis’.65 Callon and Latour
After War 17
argue that ANT escapes the difficulties that natural realism and social
realism present:
Nonhumans are party to all our disputes, but instead of being those
closed, frozen, and estranged things-in-themselves whose part has
been either exaggerated or downplayed, they are actants – open or
closed, active or passive, wild or domesticated, far away or near,
depending on the result of the interactions. When they enter the
scene they are endowed with all the nonhuman powers that ratio-
nalists like them to have, as well as the warmth and uncertainty
that social realists recognize in humans.66
We do not know who are the agents who make up our world. We
must begin with this uncertainty if we are to understand how, little
by little, the agents defined one another, summoning other agents
and attributing to them intentions and strategies… There are not
only ‘social’ relations, relations between man [sic] and man. Society
is not made up just of men, for everywhere microbes intervene and
act… We cannot form society with the social alone. We have to add
the action of microbes.70
… [Latour’s] examples are drawn from the human realm, not from
general cosmology. And in this way, the more difficult cases are
left in shadow. With a bit of work, it is not difficult to see why all
objects that enter human awareness must be hybrids, why the
ozone hole or dolphins or rivers cannot be viewed as pure pieces of
nature aloof from any hybridizing networks. The harder cases involve
those distant objects in which human awareness is currently not a
factor at all. Where are the hybrids in distant galaxies? If they are
not present, then the purifying discourse of nature wins the war,
and the rule of hybrids can be viewed to some extent as a local effect
of human perception.
For this reason, Ian Hacking writes of ‘the death that follows laboratory
life and the cumulative inaction that follows science in action’.74
A nonmodern microontology
Adrian Mackenzie and Andrew Murphie argue that the social sciences
approach science in one of three ways: critique, extraction or engage-
ment.75 I hope this book participates in all three of these activities.
Critiques of science, write Mackenzie and Murphie, include the critical
theory analyses of scientific rationality (Adorno, Agamben, Popper, Kuhn
and so on) as well as social constructionist analyses of the processes
of scientific knowledge and objects. Extraction is interested in using
scientific concepts within philosophy (Deleuze, Whitehead, DeLanda
and so on). The direction of these moves is almost always from science
to social science. Finally, engagement attempts dialogue, conversation
and collaboration with science (Stengers, Haraway, Barad and so on):
‘it engages with science-in-the-making and it has had to formulate
questions about how to live in or with science collectively.’76
This microontology engages in critiques of science: those epistemic cul-
tures, gender relations, changing orders and so on that build and rebuild
the fabric of the scientific and technological enterprises. Chapter 3 pro-
vides a critique of symbiogenesis theory within evolutionary theory.
I also extract a number of concepts from science: self, other, symbiosis,
Gaia and so on, in order to contribute to the social sciences’ long-standing
theorization of these concepts within the fabric of social relations. How-
ever, my main objective is to engage with science. Microontologies requires
20 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
Numerous calls for conference papers, articles and book chapters con-
cerned with various iterations of human-animal relations circulate the
listserv highway. What invitations to consider human-animal relations
do, in effect, is adopt what Margulis calls a ‘big like us’ approach; con-
centrating on creatures that easily bear human ocular scrutiny – crea-
tures we can see unaided by the technology of microscopes, as though
creatures ‘big like us’ resemble the majority of life. Perhaps we could
imagine, as no doubt science fiction writers have already, our eyes to
have microscopic vision, enabling us to focus immediately upon the
microbial world unimpeded by what must then be unfathomably over-
sized species. Perhaps we might then overcome the myopia that defines
our natureculture border to be with animals.4
21
22 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
Quanternary Holocene
Now
11,000
Billions of
years
Pleistocene
1.8
Neogene
Tertiary Pliocene 5
Cenozoic Miocene 23
Oligocene
Paleogene
38
Eocene
54
Paleocene 65
Phanerozoic Eon
Lower (early)
Mesozoic
146
Jurasic Late
middle
208 Early
Late
Triasic Middle
245 Early
Permian 286
Carbon-
Pennsylvanian 325
iferous
mississippian 360
Paleozoic
Devonian 410
Silurian 440
Ordovician
505
Cambrian 544
.544
NeoProterozoic 900
Mesoproterozoic
Proterozoic
1600
Palioproterozoic
2500
2.5
PreCambrian Eon
Late
Archaean
2900
Archaean
Middle
Archaean
3300
Early
Ar chaean
3800
3.8
Hadean
4.5
Figure 2.1 ‘Big Like Us’ Centered Time Scale. Image courtesy of Anthony Krivan
24 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
Now
11,000
Quanternary Pleistocene 1.8
Cenozoic
Billions of
years
Paleogene Neogene
Pliocene 5
Tertiary Miocene 23
Oligocene 38
Eocene 54
Paleocene 65
Phanerozoic Eon
Upper (late)
Cretaceous 146
Lower (early)
Mesozoic
Late
Jurasic Middle
208
Early
Late
Triasic Middle
245
Early
Permian 286
Carbon-
Paleozoic
Pennsylvanian 325
iferous
mississippian 360
Devonian 410
Silurian 440
Ordovician 505
.544
Cambrian 544
NeoProterozoic
900
Mesoproterozoic
Proterozoic
1600
Palioproterozoic
2500
2.5
Late
Archaean
PreCambrian Eon
2900
Middle
Archaean
Archaean
3300
Early
Archaean
3800
3.8
Hadean
4.5
Figure 2.2 Prokaryote Centered Time Scale. Image courtesy of Anthony Krivan
Plenty of Room at the Bottom: Thinking Bacteria 25
than all plants and animals put together’.15 And as Chapters 3 and 4
will detail, animals are, both ancestrally and currently, literally made
up of bacteria. Thus my encounter with bacteria must somehow recog-
nize that bacteria do precede my relating with them. It must also
somehow recognize that ‘I’ am bacteria, that bacteria are us. It must
also somehow take on board that bacteria are not easily separated –
they are notoriously ungracious when scientists attempt to culture
them (i.e. isolate them from their communities in petri dishes) – and
that our symbiotic and symbiogenetic ancestry means, as Haraway rec-
ognizes, that it is symbionts all-the-way-down.16 The animal cell, typi-
cally understood as the smallest unit of structure and function, is
already a symbiont. And, at the same time, I must recognize the rub
that the vast majority of microbial intra-actions have nothing to do
with humans. Humans do not even know about the vast majority of
intra-actions that take place on earth. Putting this in larger evolution-
ary perspective, Carl Woese et al. remark, ‘if you wiped out all multicel-
lur life forms off the face of the earth, microbial life might shift a tiny
bit… If microbial life were to disappear, that would be it – instant
death for the planet’.17
Notwithstanding recent advertisements about ‘good’ bacteria in
yoghurt, I am schooled in recognizing my meetings with bacteria as
military encounters – invasion and defense – between my (nonbacter-
ial) individual self and disease (bacteria). That is, the pathogen matrix
overwhelmingly defines the parameters of animal meetings-with bac-
teria. Thus my not-species meeting-with must begin by exploring bac-
teria excessive to pathogen characterization.
crucial. All organisms on earth rely upon only two sources of energy:
light energy from the sun or energy derived from chemicals. One of
the major differences between bacteria and animals is that many bac-
teria do not ‘eat’ in the sense that we mean it: they convert light and/or
chemical energy. All animals and fungi by contrast are heterotrophs –
‘living off others’, relying upon the ingestion of other organisms and
their products (more on this in Chapter 7). Photoautotrophs (such as
plants, algae and cyanobacteria) use light, carbon dioxide and water to
produce their own food:
Proteobacteria
Sometimes called purple bacteria, these organisms are all gram-negative
(meaning they do not become stained with Gram’s (crystal violet) stain).
All proteobacteria are named by Greek letters based on their DNA
Plenty of Room at the Bottom: Thinking Bacteria 29
Gram-positive bacteria
Gram-positive bacteria derive their name from the blue color they
produce when dyed by Gram’s stain. They live in every possible envir-
onmental niche from fresh and salt water, soils and sediments, to the
surfaces and insides of other organisms, and they take on a variety of
shapes and sizes from rods and long filaments to helical shapes. Gram-
positive bacteria are divided into two groups: ‘high-GC’ that have pro-
portionally more guanine and cytosine than ‘low-GC’. Gram-positive
bacteria are responsible for the many diverse fermentations that change
the odor, flavor and texture of food and drink. Fermentation is actually
bacterial heterotrophic metabolism, and the flavors we love are the
bacteria’s waste products, such as lactic acid, cheese, some forms of
alcohol, monosodium glutamate, and the flavor enhancement processes
used in making chocolate, vanilla, (black and oolong) tea and coffee.
Indonesian luwak coffee is made from the beans fermented by the
gram-positive bacteria Paradoxurus hermaphroditus in the intestines of
civet cats who are fed the beans and then defecate them, to be har-
vested by humans as a drink.
Soil itself is, essentially, a microbial product: there are over a million
or more bacteria per gram of soil. Many gram-positive bacteria form
symbiotic relationships with fungi and animals. For instance, Strepto-
myces form pale crusty patches on Attine ants and secrete antibiotics
and antifungals to discourage the growth of unwanted microbes in the
gardens of fungi that these some 200 species of ants cultivate. The blue
color distilled from the blue-producing plants indigo and woad comes
from a process of fermentation using bacteria. Tobacco is also produced
by ‘sweating’ the leaves, which employs bacterial fermentation.
Human bodies are the habitat of indigenous microbes, and most are
gram-positive bacteria. As Dexter Dyer points out, from a microbial
32 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
Cyanobacteria
Cyanobacteria invented oxygeneic photosynthesis, which has come to
dominate metabolism for producing fixed carbon from carbon dioxide.
Cyanobacteria use hydrogen and electrons from water (before this
photosynthetic organisms used hydrogen sulfide) for converting carbon
dioxide into sugar, and produce oxygen as a waste product (that
animals breathe to sustain life):
Spirochetes
Spirochetes have distinctive elongated cells with which they burrow –
in corkscrew motion – into dense substances such as mud, intestinal
contents, and animal and plant tissue. Humans are most familiar with
spirochetes as syphilis and Lyme disease. Spirochetes thrive in anoxic,
cellulose-rich environments as well as places like human teeth plaque.
Treponema pallidum (we know this bacterium as the cause of syphilis)
flagella are inside the cell: they have two cell membranes separated by
a space inside which the flagella rotate. The most famous T. pallidum
may well have been those that inhabited the brain of Friedrich
Wilhelm Nietzsche. Deborah Hayden’s account of Nietzsche’s attempt
to save a flogged horse from further beating, his subsequent frenzied
post-card writing, urine drinking and incoherent rambling is a lesson
in spirochete abilities.29 Doctors were familiar with syphilis, and
Nietzsche progressed through the well-documented primary stage
immediately after infection; the pain of secondary syphilis; and finally
the intellectual impairment, personality disturbances, reflex hyper-
activity, sensory changes, slurred speech and affect changes of tertiary
syphilis.30 Research demonstrates that T. pallidum is able to rest dor-
mant in animal tissue for many years: scientists often mistook this as
evidence that antibiotics such as penicillin cured syphilis. As Margulis
notes, while spirochetes do not suddenly activate from brain-inhabit-
ing slumber but rather work over many years, Nietzsche’s record of
writing might well indicate that his spirochetes did indeed ‘awake’ on
the 3rd of January 1889, quickly proliferating in his brain. In a less
common reversal of the typical direction of infection from colonizer to
34 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
Forms of life
‘We are now nine billion because of Pasteur’, writes Bruno Latour.34
What transforms, for Latour, ‘useless matter’ (bacteria) into ‘full-blown
substance’ are taxonomy and phylogeny (122). In other words, what
made the bacteria with which Pasteur worked into actants, according
to Latour, was the series of laboratory trials that Pasteur devised to
study – to meet with – bacteria. As such, ‘Pasteur transformed our rela-
tionship with microbes’, defining these relationships as either patho-
genic or domesticated.35 I like Latour’s description of the intra-action
between Pasteur and the microbes he worked with: ‘Pasteur and the
ferment mutually exchange and enhance their properties, Pasteur
helping the ferment show its mettle, the ferment “helping” Pasteur
win one of his many medals.’36 In other words, actants (Alfred North
Whitehead’s propositions – Pasteur, lactic acid ferment, laboratory,
microscope and so on – ‘occasions given to different entities to enter
into contact’) gain and modify their definitions through the event
of the experiment.37 Of course, these relations with humans will have
been preceded by countless relations between and amongst bacteria
and other things, making ‘Pasteur’s useless matter’ already fully-fledged
actants.
Astrid Schrader’s excellent work on scientific interest in Pfiesteria
piscicida (a dinoflagellate protist thought to kill billions of fish in U.S.
mid-atlantic estuaries) is a wonderful example of the kind of actant rela-
tions of which Latour writes.38 As Schrader puts it, ‘how you get to
know a species experimentally cannot be separated from the ontological
question of what they are’. Distinguishing between what is ‘naturally’
P. piscicida and what is environmentally induced during their life cycle
is no easy task (defining the life cycle itself requires either classificatory
exclusions or nearly limitless environmental interaction, not least of
which is with symbiotic bacteria), and separating P. piscicida from their
various metabolic and reproductive transformations (i.e. through cul-
turing) produces nontoxic P. piscicida. In effect, in classifying the organ-
ism, scientists create an organism that is not the object of their study.
It is not that P. piscicida’s indeterminacy cannot be resolved. Rather, the
condition of resolvability is predicated on ‘a complete specification of
the material-discursive practices that enact [Karen Barad’s] “agential
cut”. Different “cuts” between “object” and “measurement agencies”
establish different phenomena.’39
36 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
for knowing the live organism in question, its life history and habitat.46
Natural history, life cycle details, morphology including ultrastructure,
the history of environmental change as documented in the rock
record, and good sense are all crucial elements in reconstructing the
ancient lineages on Earth’.47 There may be 416,000 possibilities, but do
these differences tell us anything practical about the bacteria under
study? Further, and as Jan Sapp notes, the question of difference has
surfaced within molecular characterization, which is based on a few
‘representative’ bacteria such as E. coli, that simultaneously (and iron-
ically) argues that prokaryotes are not monophyletic.48
With some exceptions, the majority of schemas accept Bacteria as
both base and trunk of the Tree of Life (TOL).49 Which leads to the
question of trees. Stephen Jay Gould’s Wonderful Life provides a history
and critique of the arboreal metaphor within evolutionary theory,
from the pre-arboreal Great Chain of Being, Charles Darwin’s ‘great
Tree of Life’, Ernest Haeckel’s blooming tree, Willi Hennig’s single-
branch emphasis, and computational method developments, to mole-
cular sequencing – and I need not rehearse the details here. Assembling
this TOL, as Joel Cracraft and Michael Donoghue note, has been mas-
sively facilitated (and complicated) by molecular data and increasing
computational power, producing phylogenetic studies at the rate of
nearly 15 per day.50 What bacteria essentially do is complicate the
metaphor (a metaphor based on replication and vertical inheritance),
morphing the tree into more of a tangled web, or a ring of life as some
have suggested.51 W. Ford Doolittle’s depiction of the differences
between organismal, genome, and gene phylogenies helps to illustrate
this complication (see Figure 2.3).
The complication stems from the finding that different genes yield
different family trees because genes are transmitted horizontally as well
as vertically, known as Lateral Gene Transfer (LGT).52 Essentially, this
means that the base of the Bacterial tree is a polytomy.53 Marla Rivera
and James Lake, for instance, argue that two prokaryotes fused their
genomes, closed the ring of life, and created the first eukaryote. Put
another way, ‘eliminating a fusion organism, which necessarily con-
tacts two nodes of a ring, will delete the leaf, open the ring and con-
vert it to a tree’.54 It also means that some eukaryote genes will be
related to Bacteria while others will be related to Archaea.
As I noted, the general consensus is that the Last Universal Common
Ancestor (LUCA) is bacterial. One corollary is that Eukaryotes and
Archaea shared a common ancestry separated from bacterial descend-
ants. This said, attempts to reveal a stable Archaean or Bacterial core
Bacteria Archaea Eucarya
Green Animals
non-sulfur Entamoebae Slime
bacteria molds
Euryarchaeota Fungi
Cren-
Methanosarcina Plants
Gram archaeota Methano- Halophiles
Purple positives bacterium Ciliates
bacteria Methan-
Thermoproteus ococcus
Cyanobacteria T. celer
Pyrodicticum Flagellates
Flavobacteria
Trichomonads
Thermotogales
Microsporidia
Diplomonads
Figure 2.3 Three Kingdom Tree of Life. Image courtesy of Carl Woese
39
40 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
erroneous. This is no small thing: it means that the original root, the
first two (of the eight) major branches of the bacterial line (Aquificales
and Thermotogales) as well as the first six (of the ten) branches of
Eukaryotes (Diplomonads, Microsporidia, Trichomonads, Flagellates,
Entamoebae and Slime molds) might well be wrong.63
Perception
Setting the stage for empirical studies concerned with bacterial
perception, Antonio Lazcano, Arturo Becerra and Luis Delaye’s research
suggests that the bacterial ancestors of eukaryote cells had fully
developed sensitivity-response systems, called alarmones.67 Far from
passive microbes that cannot perceive their surroundings, bacteria
monitor and respond to internal and external stimuli. Stress, defined
by environmental insults such as lack of food, temperature change,
excess salt and so on, are detected by alarmones, which are small
signal metabolities that rapidly synthesize in times of stress.68
Alarmones seem to have evolved in RNA and protein cells before
the evolution of DNA genomes. The researchers posit that LUCA had
alarmones, and therefore had an already elaborate complex sensory
system.69
42 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
(a)
(b)
Figures 2.6a and b The first image is of the ‘bushy’ branching morphology. The sec-
ond image shows the dendritic growth. Images courtesy of Eshel Ben-Jacob and the
Royal Society. See Eshel Ben-Jacob, ‘Bacterial Self-organization: Co-enhancement of
Complexification and Adaptability in a Dynamic Environment,’ Philosophical Tran-
sactions – Royal Society. Mathematical, Physical and Engineering Sciences 361, no. 1807
(2003): 1287.
46 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
Communities
identity. The ‘mother colony’ in picture (a) was used as the source of
bacteria for plates (b) and (d). They have distinctive patterns compared
to those of (c), which were taken from large vortices at the front of the
mother colony.
Social intelligence
ing of the dynamics of semiosis may in the last analysis turn out to be
no less than the definition of life’, then bacterial biosemiotics provides
a treasure trove of clues to both the origins of the life of signs, as well
as their diversity and sophistication: bacteria are capable of biosemiotic
processes that remain elusive to humans.104
vector (mode of passing on), index (first identified case) and vortex
(the coming together of seemingly unconnected events that ‘leads to a
more or less volatile intensification of speed or flows’) forces – Van
Loon argues that viruses and epidemics such as Ebola and HIV/AIDS
require a re-consideration of the traditional separation between ‘the
subject, the social and the public sphere’.116 For instance, Van Loon
argues ‘the more aggressive and virulent a virus, the more it will rely
on cultural vectors for its survival.’117 This resembles the kind of
Latourian actant relations I am interested in. Eschewing as tautological
and reductionist the argument that self-replication is the viruses’
primary motivator, Van Loon argues instead that viruses are primed for
symbiosis because they can never exist in isolation. As vectors of sym-
biosis, viruses are not dysfunctional, but rather an integral part of the
synthesizing process of life.118 Van Loon argues that parasite politics
figures a particular ethical relation to otherness, which is the subject of
the final chapter of this book.
3
Evolutionary Theory and Its
Discontents
Introduction
58
Evolutionary Theory and Its Discontents 59
Symbiogenesis theory
novelty on the scale argued by its proponents, and thus does not consti-
tute anywhere near a revolution in evolutionary theory.53 Other scien-
tists have attempted to assimilate symbiogenesis into evolutionary
theory. For instance, in The Selfish Gene, Dawkins acknowledges the
recognition of the bacterial origins of mitochondria in eukaryotic cells
was ‘one of those revolutionary ideas…whose time had come’.54 He
then redefines symbiosis as associations between members of the same
species in order to incorporate symbiosis as a strategy through which
individuals might maximize the preservation of their ‘selfish genes’ over
time. Axelrod and Hamilton attempt to assimilate symbiosis into
neoDarwinism by reasoning that while tit-for-tat game strategies rely
upon individuals’ ability to recognize each other, microorganisms (who
were thought to lack this ability) would maintain continuous contact
with one ‘player’.
Some responses also seem to be normative in character; that is, they
involve the sanction and censure of scientists themselves.55 Thomas
Cavalier-Smith’s review of Margulis and Sagan’s Acquiring Genomes:
A Theory of the Origin of Species distills the major criticism that symbio-
genesis plays a minor role in evolution. His review does more than
this however; it employs rhetorical devices to minimize, contain and
otherwise dismiss Margulis’s research. Cavalier-Smith argues that:
(1) Margulis was not the first person to generate symbiogenesis theory;
(2) Margulis has never fully appreciated his own work on symbio-
genesis; (3) Margulis’s former supervisor Hans Ris actually revived
Mereschkowski’s symbiogenesis theory; and (4) that Margulis’s books
directed at a public audience are ‘chattily written in the fashionable
mode of pop-science journalism’.56 Cavalier-Smith’s attempt to dis-
place the credit for symbiogenesis research on to other – male – scien-
tists (Mereschkowski, Ris and himself) and the derogation of that
portion of Margulis’s research written for public consumption might
certainly occupy feminist science studies scholars interested in
women’s continued struggle within science as well as science studies
scholars concerned with continued ‘top-down’ scientific approaches to
public understandings of science.57
Cavalier-Smith notwithstanding, Margulis’s recognition within the
scientific academy through honors such as the National Medal of Science
make most scientists wary of direct attacks. The majority of scientists
acknowledge the validity of Margulis’s compilation of evidence concern-
ing the symbiogenic mergers of mitochondria and chloroplasts while at
the same time denying its greater implications (and perhaps hedging their
bets in case future research tips the scales in favor of more widespread
70 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
Several decades ago, ecologists realized that bacteria have in the geo-
logical past, as well as in the present day, dominated material and
energy flow in the world’s ecosystems. Subsequently, with the advent
of molecular phylogenetic analyses, evolutionary biologists have
come to recognize that bacteria are the most diverse of all organisms.
In recent years an integration of bacterial genetics and physiology
into host cell biology has produced a remarkable insight into the bio-
chemical mechanisms that sustain the eukaryotic cell… Now is the
time for the fields of microbiology and developmental biology to
embrace a similar integration of thinking (11).
some bacterial transmissions are obligate for the animal. For instance
Asobara tabida wasps have an obligate relationship with Wolbachia
bacteria: without Wolbachia, the wasp cannot reproduce offspring.
Researchers have also found that co-evolved bacteria induce genes associ-
ated with mucosal immunity, intestine maturation and nutrient process-
ing.70 Moreover, many environmentally transmitted symbioses remain
open to the environment throughout the life of the nonbacterial sym-
biont.71 This can, for instance, help the animal to differentiate between
indigenous microbiota (that is, bacteria transmitted environmentally and
transovarianally) and ‘tourist’ bacteria, which in turn aids in immunity.72
Conrad Waddington differentiates between ‘normative’ natural selection
(based on competition) and ‘epigenetic’ natural selection based on com-
plementary cell-cell interactions during development.73 Studies of the
ubiquity of developmental symbioses suggest a need to acknowledge
epigenetic selection as systemic functioning between organisms.74
Epigenetics is gaining increasing attention within evolutionary and
development (‘evo-devo’) theory.75 Epigenetics refers to the vertical trans-
mission of information through non-DNA means. While there is no
change in the underlying DNA sequences (from this process alone;
changes occur through other means), nongenetic factors determine
gene expression. Epigenetics challenges the central dogma of genetics,
which maintains the centrality of DNA in both genetic inheritance and
organismal development. The central dogma, simplified, looks like this:
Conclusions
Each of us walks around each day carrying the DNA of several thou-
sand lineages (our parasites, our intestinal flora) in addition to our
nuclear (and mitochondrial) DNA, and all these genomes get along
76 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
pretty well under most circumstances. They are all in the same boat
after all. A herd of antelope, a termite colony, a mating pair of birds
and their clutch of eggs, a human society – these groupish entities are
no more groupish, in the end, than an individual human being, with
its trillion-plus cells, each a descendant of the ma-cell and pa-cell
union that started the group’s voyage. ‘At any level, if a vehicle is
destroyed, all the replicators inside it will be destroyed. Natural selec-
tion will therefore, at least to some extent, favour replicators that cause
their vehicles to resist being destroyed. In principle this could apply
to groups of organisms as well as to single organisms, for if a group
is destroyed all the genes inside it are destroyed too’ ([Dawkins]
p. 114). So are genes all that matter? Not at all.
Introduction
77
78 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
The Gift: The Form and Reason for Exchange in Archaic Societies, provides
the outline for contemporary debates concerned with the constitution
and limits of gifting as a fundamental cross-cultural practice.10 Mauss
begins by outlining the explicit features of gifting as the free, voluntary
giving of resources without any expectation of return. However, Mauss
Microontologies of Self 79
The rub, that an activity necessary to life (ingestion) may also lead to
such a catastrophic ending (death of the self) is the one most often
assumed to characterize relations between humans and microorganisms
– predation.35 Yet, Crist and Tauber note ‘another possible twist to the
story’ which anticipates my argument, that the bacterium (although it
would more accurately be an already entangled community of bacteria
with complex genomic lineage) may develop the ability to resist being
digested, and indeed, may further develop the ability to live within the
organism, thus developing a sort of ‘truce rather than war’.36 Again
resembling the philosophical literature’s discussion of gifting relation-
ships between people and their excess, the authors characterize micro-
biotic and animal relationships as ‘a tense proximity between self
and nonself’; a characterization that fits well with symbiosis and
symbiogenesis.37
Microontologies of Self 83
Symbionts all the way down means that we are, ancestrally, made
up of bacteria. It also means that any given human body is also a
symbiont: 600 species of bacteria in our mouths and 400 species of
bacteria in our guts, and the countless more bacteria that inhabit our
eyes, anuses, and skin. Indeed, the number of bacteria in our mouths
is comparable to the total number of human beings that have ever
lived on earth.50 The number of microbes in our bodies exceeds the
number of cells in our bodies by 100 fold. The human distal gut con-
tains more than 100 times as many genes as our human genome
(which has 2.85 billion base pairs). That is:
Every living thing that exists now, or has ever lived, is a bacterium.52
Asking what bacteria have to do with humans is, in Gould’s terms,
asking the wrong question, or as Cary Wolfe puts it referring to
humanism, ‘the “human” that we know now, is not now, and never
was, itself’.53
The incalculable interactions between bacteria and human guts,
mouths, anuses, eyelids and so on certainly exceed traditional closed-
economy, pathogen characterization. Indeed, Kitano and Oda point
out that the myriad symbiotic relationships within the human intestines
actually function to optimize robustness against pathogen attacks.54
Tauber reminds us that it is the bacteria in our colons that produce
vitamin K, an essential co-factor in producing clotting proteins.55 A
recent genomic study found that intestinal bacterial flora can mani-
pulate ‘host’ gene expression.56 The study found that the symbiotic
relationship works both ways: the ‘host’s’ genotype and immunology
reciprocally affect the bacterial flora life.
The concentration on competitive individuality, most recently arti-
culated through the genome, has been fruitfully critiqued.57 At cellular
and multicellular levels, the continued image of the go-it-alone gene/
organism/human makes little sense. To paraphrase Gilbert, the formation
of an ‘individual is actually the formation and continuity of a collegial
assemblage of organisms’ (my emphasis). Schneider and Sagan refer to
Microontologies of Self 85
The lesson to be gleaned is not that our body has learned in the
course of evolutionary history what is beneficial to it and what is
not, but rather that the boundaries of self and nonself become indi-
vidually tailored and may be blurred. What is becoming increasingly
evident is that the immune system ignores much of what it sees. It
allows the organism to engage its environment…: the self/nonself
border is ever-changing (590).
integral part of the synthesizing process of life.66 Van Loon argues that
parasite politics figures a particular ethical relation to otherness.
Van Loon characterizes viruses as (poisonous) gifts insofar as infec-
tion consists of the ‘flow of pathogen information between hosts’.67
‘The “gift” of infection’ writes Van Loon ‘is an event whose conse-
quences are ambivalent, contingent and open and hence socially and
sociologically significant…immunity of populations [is] an inherently
social phenomenon.’68 Phenomena such as parasitism, infection
and tolerance suggest the interface between an organism’s outside
(exogenous) and inside (endogenous) boundaries constitutes the
(unpredictable) excess of selfhood. Julie Theriot’s research, and
advances in immunology generally, bespeak of this corporeal generos-
ity: ‘disease… is becoming intimate with the cells of our body’, or as
Haraway writes, ‘disease is a relationship’.69 Indeed, cells actively work
with bacteria. As such, ‘disease usually results from inconclusive nego-
tiations for symbiosis, an overstepping of the line by one side or the
other, a biological misinterpretation of borders’.70
To summarize, then, we might say that there is contagion, patho-
genicity, and parasitism at work in the organism, but that it is a rather
more complicated relationship than we tend to assume. Contagion
is co-implicated: it signifies as much debility and death as it does
the possibility of flourishing. As such, bacterial gifting, especially in
symbiotic form, is certainly excessive to traditional economic para-
digms that require autonomous uncorrupted invidualism. Further-
more, failed digestion – symbiogenesis – defines not only an epistemo-
logy (symbionts all the way down) but an ontology of primordial
entanglement.
While an extended discussion of a symbiogenetic approach to envir-
onments occupies Chapter 6, it is worth noting here Margulis’s adoption
of Maturana and Varela’s concept of autopoiesis.71 Autopoiesis refers
to the ‘autonomous organization of dynamic processes occurring within
a closed operational whole’.72 Initially deployed in tandem with James
Lovelock’s term ‘geophysiology’ to describe Gaia’s biospheric self-
regulation, Margulis adapted autopoiesis – self-making – to describe life
as other-than replication. That is, Margulis argues that autopoiesis, not
vertical inheritance, defines life. In two main texts, Autopoiesis and Cog-
nition and The Tree of Knowledge, Maturana and Varela developed auto-
poiesis in response to the epistemological problem of representation.73
For Maturana and Varela, ‘everything said is said by an observer’.74 There
may be a reality ‘out there’, but it exists ‘only through interactive pro-
cesses determined solely by the organism’s own organization’.75 In other
Microontologies of Self 87
Symbiotic generosity
This in itself does not dictate the political intent of any given com-
munity. Nazi Germany, notes Esposito, likened Jews to microbes.90
Resonating with the arguments made throughout this paper, Jean-
Luc Nancy argues that ‘Being cannot be anything but being-with-one-
another, circulating in the with as the with of this singularly plural
coexistence’.91 Nick Bingham distinguishes Nancy’s ‘being with’ on
two points: first ‘it is concerned with what is always a multitude of
others rather than a singular other…and second…it is radically non-
athropocentric’.92 Levinas and Derrida contemplate this ‘being with’
relation between humans and nonhumans in terms of an ‘other friend-
ship’. John Caputo describes Derrida’s question thus: ‘Is there a gift of
friendship outside or beyond the economy of equality and reciprocity
that we have always demanded of friendship?… To what extent is the
main Western canon on friendship itself already disturbed and inter-
rupted from within by an understanding, or at least an intimation,
of this other friendship’?93 For Bingham, this ‘other friendship’ is
not characterized by what is linked together (humans and bacteria for
instance) but rather by ‘a certain quality of being open to and with
others’ – a violent openness as Derrida and Diprose remind us.94 In
other words, we push our concept of ethics to the limit when we extend
our unconditional hospitality to the radical nonhuman Other – the
‘other friend’. I return to these questions in the final chapter.
5
Microontologies of Sex
Barnacle sex
91
92 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
Wilson points out that ‘these females and hermaphrodites with many
husbands are not simply the intermediary stages in the evolution of
barnacle form; they are also evidence of the somatic diversity that
nature produces’ (284).
From a human perspective, barnacle sex and reproduction seem
peculiar indeed. A perusal of the social scientific literature suggests that
gender, sex, reproduction, replication, sexual difference and mixis are
defined from an entirely ‘big like us’ vantage point. What might we
learn from thinking about sex, reproduction, sexuality and sexual dif-
ference as the majority of the earth’s biota practice these processes?
Sharon Kinsman presciently asks:
Because most of us are not familiar with the species, and with the
diverse patterns of DNA mixing and reproduction they embody, our
struggles to understand humans (and especially human dilemmas
about ‘sex’, ‘gender’ and ‘sexual orientation’) are impoverished…
Shouldn’t a fish whose gonads can be first male, then female, help us
to determine what constitutes ‘male’ and ‘female’? Should an aphid
fundatrix (‘stem mother’) inform our ideas about ‘mother’? There on
the rose bush, she neatly copies herself, depositing minuscule, sap-
siphoning, genetically identical daughters. Aphids might lead us to
ask not ‘why do they clone?’ but ‘why don’t we?’ Shouldn’t the long-
term female homosexual pair bonding in certain species of gulls help
define our views of successful parenting, and help [us] reflect on the
intersection of social norms and biology?3
The variety of animal, plant, fungal and protoctist sex and reproduc-
tion that Kinsman refers to is diverse indeed: slime molds can produce
more than 500 different kinds of sex cells; the average male blanket
octopus is 2.5 centimeters long compared with his 1.8 meter and
40,000 times heavier female mate; green spoon worm larva become
female in the absence of other female spoon worms; male angler fish
attach to female bodies where they degenerate until their death; male
seahorses fertilize eggs inside their bodies where they are gestated until
birth; gray whale mating rituals involve two males and one female;
mangrove fish have ovo-testes and fertilize themselves; male slipper
limpets become female as they mature; star-shaped sea squirts meet on
the ocean floor and send cells (including DNA) to each other through
the blood supply they come to share; some kinds of whiptail lizards are
all female, hatching unfertilized eggs that produce more females;
female bronze-winged jacanas mate with up to four males and the males
Microontologies of Sex 93
build nests, incubate the eggs and feed the chicks when they hatch;
male sticklebacks also care for their fertilized eggs and offspring until
they are independent; male Darwin frogs keep their tadpoles inside
their vocal sacs until they develop into froglets; naked mole rat daugh-
ters help their queen mother stay infertile by smearing her with their
urine; a hatchling turtle’s sex depends on its temperature while it was
in the egg; and leopard slugs are intergender (female and male) but
fertilize each other’s eggs.4
With Kinsman, I want to attend to the diversity of sex, gender, repro-
duction, sexuality and sexual difference within the kingdoms Animalia,
Plantae, Fungi and Protoctista. But I also want to appreciate these issues
from the perspective of Monera, a vast assemblage of organisms rarely
included in discussions of the evolution and current practices of sex. We
know especially little about bacterial sex and reproduction: yet within
Monera, diversity meets its biological and human imaginative limits.
The kind of generation of offspring with which humans are most famil-
iar, mixis, has been studied since the end of the nineteenth century, by
botanists studying plant fertilization and zoologists studying the fertil-
ization of eggs with sperm. For Zuckerman and Lederberg, humans’ dis-
covery of bacterial sex was ‘post-mature’. Scientists were surprised that it
was not discovered earlier since: (1) the techniques used were available;
(2) it was understandable at the time; and (3) its implications must have
been capable of having been appreciated.5 That discoveries can be post-
mature necessarily speaks of the context of assumptions, beliefs and
values in which the questions answered by the discovery are not viewed
as important or relevant. ‘Why’, ask Zuckerman and Lederberg, ‘was
recombination in bacteria not perceived as a problem before 1946?’6
Part of the answer lies in the fact that bacteria were first assumed to be
tiny primitive plants: Ferdinand Cohen called them Schizomycetes or
‘fission fungi’. Humans also find bacteria to be difficult experimental
subjects: we might say, after Haraway, that the laboratory is not a set-
ting within which we ‘meet well’ with bacteria. Observations of bacteria
require humans to adopt the prosthetic aid of a microscope, and bac-
teria act differently in laboratory conditions than elsewhere: they are
different actants in relation to the microscope, as Latour might say.
Additionally, humans have traditionally conceived of bacteria as patho-
gens, of little interest and importance otherwise. Thus, it was not until
March 1946 that Tatum and Lederberg observed sex in E. coli.
94 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
An/Other glossary
Table 5.1 Levels of Sexual (and Para-Sexual) Unions. Table courtesy of Lynn
Margulis
Thus, compared with the minimal amount of mixis that some human
beings engage in for a very short period of time, each of us engages
in recombination (cutting and patching of DNA strands as well as the
coming together of cytoplasm, entire cells, parts of organisms and
entire organisms), merging (fertilization of cells), meiosis and mitosis.
Our human bodies live in a permanently fertilized state, with only our
egg and sperm cells qualifying as haploid: the vast majority of our cells
are diploid. And 44 of our 46 chromosomes are completely unrelated to
what we tend to think of as sexual difference. The only thing that does
not exist is a pure (Y or YY) male.29
Donna Haraway highlights a key irony that in biological terms sex
precludes reproduction:
When bacteria incorporate genes from other bacteria and then repro-
duce, their genes are passed on to their offspring without mixis. In
other words, bacteria, not humans, ‘breed true’.31 And lest we remain
sanguine about sexual forms of reproduction, we do well to remember,
with Haraway, that sexual reproduction brings death to the individual.
Since sex refers to the mixing of DNA, we need a term to describe
features that bring organisms together to share DNA and/or reproduce:
a term that describes mating types. The term I adopt here is gender.
Our human tendency to conflate sex and reproduction coupled with
our desire to accentuate difference encourages us to concentrate on
markers used to designate female and male in humans such as genitals,
chromosomes and gonads.32
For nonhumans, gender may well refer to other markers that have
nothing to do with genitals, female-to-male attraction, or male-to-female
attraction: gender is much more commonly things like H2, slime or hor-
mones. The mushroom Schizophyllum commune has 27,000 genders,
Microontologies of Sex 101
one female may kill the other female by biting her in half or eating all
the available food. When this female has had sex with a male, the male
might then turn into a female and bite her in two.35
Researchers have also found transvestism to be widespread amongst
nonhuman animals. Sometimes transvestism takes a physical form,
when animals physically resemble another gender of their species.36
Transvestism might also be behavioral, when an animal behaves in
ways associated with another mating type of their species. Some
entomologists, for instance, describe transvestism in various insect
species. For instance, the female Papilio phorcas (a type of butterfly)
takes on ‘male pattern’ wings of other male butterflies that fly faster
and are better able to avoid prey.37
Organismal meetings focused on gender often seem to obscure other
meetings-with our environments. For instance, more than 50 synthetic
chemicals flow into our bodies daily (including tinned vegetables,
cigarettes, chemical detergents, makeup, DDT) and alter our endocrine
systems.38 Endocrine-disrupting compounds have been found to be
responsible for a recently reported doubling in incidence of hypo-
spadias in the United States and Europe.39 Children are at risk of expos-
ure to over 15,000 high-production-volume synthetic chemicals; most
of them developed in the last 50 years. More than half have not yet
been tested for toxicity.40 The effects of DDT and DDE have been
studied on a diverse range of animals from Tiger Salamanders to
Cricket Frogs.41 A number of researchers are interested in the possible
causal relationship between exposure in utero to environmental chem-
icals and effects on human sexual reproduction including gender ratio,
disruption of androgen signaling, decreased sperm number and quality,
androgen insensitivity, testicular and breast cancer, decreased prostate
weight, endometriosis, decreased fertility, increased hypospadias and
undescended testes, as well as adverse effects on immune and thyroid
function.42 Again, each of these exchanges with the environment may
effect variations in gender and fertility without any recourse to sex or
mixis.
Amongst bacteria, fertilization does not occur and so bacteria have not
developed differences associated with gender. One might, indeed, stretch
this to say that bacteria defy gender altogether. Yet, it is testament to the
pervasiveness of the current paradigm of evolutionary theory that bacte-
ria, practicing sex without reproduction, have not escaped gendering
through human classification. Schiebinger shows how the history of the
study of bacteria was infused with a priori notions of sex and gender
from the outset.43 As we saw earlier, until the 1940s, bacteria were
Microontologies of Sex 103
assumed to be uniparental. After that time, the ‘sex life’ of bacteria was
described in heteronormative terms. Specifically, bacteria were defined as
female or male based on the absence or presence (respectively) of a
‘fertility’ or F-factor (females designated F-; males designated F+):
To transfer genetic material, the ‘donor’ or ‘male’ extends its sex pili
to the ‘recipient’ or ‘female’. Unlike the case in higher organisms,
the chromosomal transfer is unidirectional from male to female and
the male, not the female, produces offspring. Further when the F+
cell transfers a copy of its F– factor to an F– partner, the recipient
becomes male or F+. Because the donor cell replicates its F– factor
during conjugation, it too remains F+. Thus all cells in mixed cul-
tures rapidly become male (F+) donor cells: the females change into
males, the males remain males, and everyone is happy. A recombi-
nant F– (female) cell results only from a ‘disrupted’ or failed transfer
of DNA…. (149–150).
Except that gender change within bacterial sex is rampant. All it takes
is for the F– factor to be transferred through viral infection, and a bac-
terium changes from F– to F+ and vice versa. Heat also changes gender
in bacteria. Yet, the infusion of heteronomative ideology into analyses
of bacteria persisted until the 1990s, decelerating the recognition of
bacterial sex without reproduction and reproduction without sex.
Sexual diversity44
He may masturbate several times during the day. I have seen a stag do
this three times in the morning at approximately hourly intervals,
even when he has had a harem of hinds. This act is accomplished by
lowering the head and gently drawing the tips of the antlers to and fro
through the herbage. Erection and extrusion of the penis…follow in
five to seven seconds…Ejaculation follows about five seconds later.47
ified as abnormal that few people question. Sex between different species
is one of them. Yet findings are beginning to emerge suggesting that
sexual behavior amongst nonhumans is again much more plastic and
diverse than human culture recognizes. Sexual behavior between
flowers and various insects is so commonplace that it is rarely recog-
nized as transspecies sexual activity. And other examples have been
found. For instance, Krizek documented a sexual interaction between
two different orders of insects, a butterfly and a rove beetle. The rove
beetle was perched on a leaf with its abdomen elevated. The butterfly
approached and for several seconds explored the beetle’s anogenital
organs with its proboscis. Krizek notes that other such interactions,
between different orders of human and nonhuman animals, have been
observed. Dieter Mollenhaur and his team in Germany have amazing
footage of a Nostoc (cyanobacterium) mating with a zygomycete fungus
to produce Geosiphon pyriforme, a holobiont. This mating between
members of two different kingdoms is, indeed, ‘forbidden fertilization’.
In short ‘natural systems are driven as much by abundance and excess
as they are by limitation and practicality’ and are reflective of strong
ecosystems.51
There are many other ways of generating genetic variability and per-
forming whatever other duties mixis itself performs. Mixis was never
selected for directly. An inordinate amount of data has been collected
in attempts to prove the selective advantage of mixis, especially in ani-
mals living in unstable environments (Bell 1982). No such conclusion
is available from the evidence: neither in constant nor in varying envi-
ronments can mixis be shown to confer selective advantage over
106 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
Quiet revolutions
Evolution all the way down is nowhere more apparent than in the
concept of difference. Grosz also distinguishes between cultural and
evolutionary senses of the term origin and its relation to difference.
Culturally, ‘origin is a consequence of human, or rather, scientific
taxonomy, a function of language’ and that ‘individual differences form
continua, whose divisions remain relatively arbitrary, contingent on the
pragmatic purposes of the division’.82 Phenotypically, differences
between individuals exist on a continuum, yet these individual differ-
ences, over evolutionary time, become differences of kind rather than
degree through natural selection. It is here that my engagement with
symbiogenesis theory leads me in a different direction. For Grosz,
humans come in two nonreducible forms. She writes ‘there is an
irreducible difference between the sexes, and this difference is not only
irreducible to one of its terms, in the case of socio-biology, its repro-
ductive cells; it is also irreducible to any other level, whether cellular,
morphological, cultural or historical.’83 Grosz points to the irony of
agreement between socio-biological and feminist accounts on this
point. I see, rather, an agreement based upon an implicit endorsement,
by feminist theorists, of the neoDarwinian account of evolution, which
emphasizes species differentiation through competition. For instance,
Grosz adopts the typically neoDarwinian rhetoric of uniparental advan-
tage over sexual reproduction: ‘a large part of sexual bifurcation is the
consequence of natural selection and the evolutionary advantages that
sexual difference bestows on hermaphroditic or self-fertilizing modes of
reproduction.’84 Elsewhere Grosz writes: ‘those beings that reproduce
sexually have an evolutionary advantage over their hermaphroditic
counterparts in most but not all situations by virtue of the maximum
variation generated by sexual reproduction’.85
Symbiogenesis’s account of the haphazard and contingent develop-
ment of sexual reproduction as a by-product of multicellularity and cell
differentiation presents, to my mind, the kind of nonhuman perspec-
tive that Grosz seeks. Grosz’s detailed analyses of James, Bergson and
Nietzsche, while intending to illuminate creative ways of working
through evolution and nature eventually reduce to human agency.
I am interested in theories that help us to think about how matter
organizes itself, and how nonhuman organisms organize matter. In
other words, Darwin’s major insight that evolution is nonteleological
Microontologies of Sex 113
Introduction
116
Microontologies of Environment 117
degradation one quarter of all existing plant and animal species will
become extinct within 30 years, and half by the end of the twenty-first
century; more than half of all wild habitat has been destroyed in 49 out
of 61 old world tropical countries; we devote almost 75 percent of the
earth’s fertile land to nearly exclusive mono-agriculture (corn and beef);
60 percent of what are anthropocentrically termed ecosystem ‘services’
have been degraded; a growing consensus acknowledges that we have
already surpassed the earth’s oil supply peak; biofuels require as much or
more energy to make than fossil fuels, and so on.9 Our ‘spaceship Earth’
faces a grim reality:
The aim of this chapter is to consider the utility of engaging with Gaia
theory within the context of environmental crisis. I am not interested in
Gaia theory’s adoption within new age/spiritualist movements, but rather
Gaia theory within science. First, I outline the major principles of Gaia
theory, distil its major scientific criticisms and then précis’s how Gaia
theory defends itself against these criticisms. Following Karen Barad, I
attempt to provide an intra-active account of Gaia theory within science.
This intra-action is as much about the world before and with ‘man’ as it is
about scientific disciplinary boundaries and the carving up of space, time
and matter.13 It is also an account of epistemic cultures that define con-
cepts – the evolutionary ‘unit of selection’ for instance. I then attempt to
move the discussion forward toward a meaningful reformulation of
environmentalism within the context of present and future (animal)
environmental crises; in other words, toward ‘what then must be done’
initiatives. While I argue that Gaia theory provokes interesting ways to
regard naturecultures, it seems to get caught in the very problem of self-
hood that symbiogenesis theory challenges. As such, I argue that Gaia
theory sustains the same critique that undermines deep ecology theory,
which is the problem of difference. Taking my direction from the biophi-
losophy of difference and relation in the works of Duerr, Lingis, Deleuze,
Haraway and van Wyck, I am concerned with what Duerr refers to as two
sides of the ethical encounter: on one side nature and human are con-
nected through representation – thinking like/for microbes (sameness)
– while on the other side humans attempt to comprehend the strange,
the other – meeting/speaking with microbes (difference).14 Lingis
describes this as the difference between a ‘depth-perception’ of the other
and a ‘surface-sensitivity’ which recognizes that the other faces the same
imperative.15 With biophilosophy, I argue the former concerns what van
Wyck calls an ‘ecology of strength’ in which differences are foreclosed
through reduction to the Same, while the latter creates an ethics open to
differences within and between those who encounter each other, as well
as within the encounter itself, what van Wyck refers to as an ecology of
weakness. Here, my concern with Gaia theory’s ethical foreclosures come
to the fore. To anticipate my conclusion, I argue that Gaia theory fence-
sits between an ecology of strength and weakness, unclear as to its ethical
relation to the other.
Coining the term ‘biosphere’ in 1875, Eduard Suess recognized the co-
dependencies of life and nonlife: ‘The plant, whose deep roots plunge
120 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
into the soil to feed, and which at the same time rises into the air to
breathe, is a good illustration of organic life in the region of interaction
between the upper sphere and the lithosphere, and on the surface of con-
tinents it is possible to single out an independent biosphere’.16 Russian sci-
entist Vladimir Vernadsky elaborated the concept of the biosphere.
Taking an explicitly holistic approach, Vernadsky identified the difficulty
of studying the biosphere as a whole through traditional disciplinary spe-
cialisms: ‘among numerous works on geology, none has adequately
treated the biosphere as a whole, and none has viewed it, as it will be
viewed here, as a single orderly manifestation of the mechanism of the
uppermost region of the planet – the Earth’s crust’.17 While the basic
ideas that formulated Gaia theory are found throughout the history of
science, it is indisputably associated today with James Lovelock.
Lovelock’s route to Gaia theory was rather circuitous. Employed by
NASA to develop life-detecting equipment for the 1975 Viking mission
to Mars, Lovelock and Dian Hitchcock determined, before the mission lit-
erally took off, that the atmospheres of both Mars and Venus precluded
life.18 Mars is a very cold planet (–53 degrees Celsius) and its atmosphere
is composed of 95 percent carbon dioxide, 2.7 percent nitrogen, 1.6 per-
cent argon, 0.13 percent oxygen and no methane. Venus is very hot
(459 degrees Celsius) and is composed of 96.5 percent carbon dioxide,
3.5 percent nitrogen, 70 parts per million of argon and only a trace of
oxygen. Currently, the earth’s temperature is about 15 degrees Celsius, and
its atmosphere is composed of 0.03 percent carbon dioxide, 79 percent
nitrogen, 21 percent oxygen, 1 percent argon and 1.7 parts per million of
methane. Lovelock and Hitchcock knew from geological and astronomical
research that the earth’s atmosphere initially resembled that of Mars and
Venus. They also knew that while the Sun’s solar radiation has increased
by 30 percent over the course of earth’s existence, the earth’s temperature
has decreased from 66 degrees four billion years ago to today’s
15 degrees, a significant overall cooling of 51 degrees. Lovelock and Hitch-
cock reasoned that what makes the difference between the earth’s atmos-
phere and that of Mars or Venus (or any other planet in our solar system)
is life.19
According to Margulis, Lovelock had three choices: either God created
the atmosphere for humans (and changed it dramatically over time), the
atmosphere has changed so dramatically to support life as a matter of
pure chance (the ‘Goldilocks theory’: Mars is too cold, Venus is too hot,
and earth is just right), or life itself produces the atmosphere in which it
survives. The original Gaia hypothesis involved the biotic regulation of
the earth’s temperature, its acidity-alkalinity, and the composition of its
reactive atmospheric gases, especially oxygen. Since these initial predic-
Microontologies of Environment 121
In other words, Gaia theory proposes that the biota alters its physical
environment to maintain conditions conducive to life, despite destabiliz-
ing effects such as increasing solar energy.21 To say that the biosphere is
Gaian is to say that, since its formation, the evolution of the earth (and
all of its inhabitants) has been a consequence of a profound, immutable
and inextricable association between life and nonlife. It is also to say
that biota, oceans, atmosphere and soils – the biosphere – actually
(unconsciously) controls the chemical and thermal systems.22 As Margulis
puts it ‘one hundred percent of organisms…alter their surroundings
100 percent of the time’.23 Describing resource transfer in a way that
resonates with symbiotic and Gaian perspectives, Freese writes:
… soon after its origin, life was adapting not to the geological world
of its birth but to an environment of its own making. There was not
purpose in this, but those organisms which made their environment
more comfortable for life left a better world for their progeny, and
those which worsened their environment spoiled the survival
chances of theirs. Natural selection then tended to favour the
improvers. If this view of evolution is correct, it is an extension of
Darwin’s great vision and makes neoDarwinism a part of Gaia
theory and Earth system science.43
humans do not appear until the Neogene, 0.01 million years ago).51 On a
Gaian timeline, the most important eon is the Archaean.52 Trying to
effect an analytic orientation, Lovelock writes ‘the cuddly animals, the
wild flowers, and the people are all to be revered, but they would be
nothing were it not for the vast infrastructure of the microbes’.53 Latour
delineates the challenge: ‘…the nature whole into which politics and
human society would supposedly have to merge transcends the hori-
zons of ordinary citizens. For this Whole is not human, as is readily
seen in the Gaia hypothesis’.54
The earth is about 4.5 billion years old. Life began in the Archaean
soon after, about 3.8 billion years ago (give or take a few million years).
Before life, the planet’s atmosphere was rich in carbon dioxide, con-
tained nitrogen, traces of hydrogen, hydrogen sulfide, and very little
oxygen. The oceans held large amounts of iron, other elements and
compounds that act as reducing agents (reacting with, and thereby
removing, oxygen).
LUCA – the last universal common ancestor was bacterial, and for
85 percent of the earth’s history, the biota consisted solely of micro-
organisms.55 Four types of bacteria – fermenting, swimming, oxygen-
breathing and photosynthesizing – created all life on earth through the
natural selection of organisms created through symbiogenesis and ran-
dom mutation. Bacteria sustain the chemical elements crucial to life on
earth – oxygen, nitrogen, phosphorous, sulfur and carbon, and some
25 other gases – through ongoing (re)cycling processes that enable
flora and fauna to thrive.56 For example, photosynthesis, the ability to
split water by light energy to reduce carbon to sugar, led to what scien-
tists call the ‘oxygen Holocaust’ – the single greatest mass extinction of
living organisms on earth – that resulted when oxygen-producing bac-
teria multiplied and spread, killing the vast majority of organisms for
which oxygen was poisonous.57 Bacteria, then, not only evolved all life
(reproduction, photosynthesis and movement) on earth; they provided
(and continue to provide) the environment in which different kinds of
living organisms can exist.
Bacteria have thrived since, quite literally, life began. The key elements
of biosphere – carbon, hydrogen, nitrogen, oxygen, phosphorous and
sulfur (known as CHNOPS to science students cramming for exams) – are
all cycled by bacteria. Bacteria evolved the earth’s production economy:
phototrophs convert solar energy; chemotrophs convert chemical energy;
lithotrophs gain electrons from inorganic compounds (such as hydrogen
and sulfur) or simple organic compounds (such as water and
hydrogen sulfide); organotrophs convert complex organic substances
128 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
Gaia theory presents social theory with two challenges. First, Gaia
theory emphasizes lively biotic/abiotic co-productions that sustain the
biosphere. In so doing, it collapses the traditional social scientific dis-
tinction between living and nonliving matter. Second, Gaia theory
shifts the focus from animals to bacteria. As we have seen, for Gaia
theory, studying animals is essentially another way of studying
ourselves: humanocentric business-as-usual. The second challenge,
then, is to recognize that humans are not the central players in climate
regulation. Bacteria and microbial symbionts are far more central.
Humans might well precipitate global heating, but this is nothing com-
pared with the oxygen Holocaust. If, as Gaia theory argues, living
and nonliving matter cannot be so easily bifurcated, and if bacteria
are the primary means through which the biosphere is sustained, how
then might we proceed? In this concluding section, I focus on the
ethics of ecological concern. I am interested in our ethical relation-
ship with an environment largely made up of, and regulated by, bac-
teria. How, in other words, might we figure future meetings-with bac-
teria? Gaia theory challenges us to consider who we invite and who
we overlook when we meet the other in ethical encounters. Thus
far, we seem mainly directed toward the human protection of par-
ticular animals: flagship species such as polar and panda bears
obscure the vast number of symbiotic relations that sustain their sur-
vival.74
Yet while Gaia theory focuses on the inescapable entanglement of life
and nonlife, its own characterization of the biosphere as a superorgan-
ism invites criticisms associated with autopoiesis and self-organization.
It also, I argue, constitutes the point at which Gaia theory reveals
ambivalence towards difference. To the degree that this ambivalence
operates, it limits Gaia theory to an ecology of strength, and thereby
necessarily forecloses the form of ethical encounter, through environ-
mentalism, that it seeks.
The theoretical compass that orients my analysis is Peter van Wyck’s
thoughtful exegesis of deep ecology theory.75 In what he calls ‘the
Microontologies of Environment 131
assume too much difference, Gaia theory seems unable to think with
microbial-nonliving co-productions in terms that do not efface differ-
ence. An ecology of weakness leaves open the question of difference of
both degree and kind in encounters/meetings with microbial others.80
7
Eating Well, Surviving Humanism
H’ordeuvre
133
134 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
I love the fact that human genomes can be found in only about
10 percent of all the cells that occupy the mundane space I call my
body; the other 90 percent of the cells are filled with the genomes of
bacteria, fungi, protists, and such, some of which play in a sym-
phony necessary to my being alive at all, and some of which are
hitching a ride and doing the rest of me, of us, no harm. I am vastly
outnumbered by my tiny companions; better put, I become an adult
human being in company with these tiny messmates. To be one is
always to become with many.4
Genes are not the point, and that surely is a relief. The point is com-
panion-species making. It’s all in the family, for better or worse,
until death do us part. This is a family made up in the belly of the
monster of inherited histories that have to be inhabited to be trans-
formed. I always knew that if I turned up pregnant, I wanted the
being in my womb to be a member of another species; maybe that
turns out to be the general condition. It’s not just mutts, in or out
of the traffic of international adoption, who seek a category of one’s
own in significant otherness.7
Photoautotrophy:
crops divest the soil of its resources (such as bacteria) and make its replen-
ishment difficult; corn does not self-fertilize and requires human inter-
vention; and single crops decrease biodiversity. Most of the corn grown
in North America (about 60 percent) is used to feed cows, bulls and
steers – fed in Concentrated Animal Feeding Operations (CAFO) or what
Pollan calls ‘new animal cities’.24 The economic logic is simple: feed as
many cattle as possible in the shortest amount of time to create the
most beef possible. It is exactly opposite to the closed ecological loop
of old-style farm logic where animals were fed crop waste products, and
crops were fed animal waste products.25
Pollan’s detailed description of the lives of cattle in the beef produc-
tion industry in North America is sobering. Here, cattle are insem-
inated via mail-order semen straws. Beef cattle live with their mothers
for the first six months of their lives where they live on their mothers’
milk and field grasses. From there the cattle are moved to CAFOs (their
mothers have long since been inseminated again to produce another
cohort of beef and milk) where they are taught through a process that
Pollan describes as ‘backgrounding’ (confined to a pen and made to eat
from a trough) to eat corn. For the first time, the rumen encounters an
entirely new diet, consisting of liquefied fat (such as beef tallow – the
FDA ban on cannibalism makes exceptions in the form of blood prod-
ucts and fat) and protein supplements (including synthetic oestrogen),
antibiotics (Rumensin and Tylosin), alfalfa hay and silage (roughage)
and corn. About 37,000 cattle consume a million pounds of feed on
CAFOs per day.
This diet is not good for cattle. As Pollan describes, most cattle on
CAFOs are sick from bloating, acidosis, diarrhoea, ulcers, rumenitis,
liver disease and a weakening of the immune system which can in turn
lead to polio, enterotoxemia, coccidiosis and pneumonia.26 Cattle
spend only 150 days on feedlot diets: it is all their bodies can with-
stand before risking dire illness, and it is long enough to make their
bodies fat enough for the food industry to profit from their slaughter
for human (and cattle) consumption.
Beef itself is not good for human consumption, particularly at the rate
of three times a day as in many American diets. Corn-fed meat is worse
because it contains more saturated fat and less omega-3 fatty acids. Con-
suming CAFO-produced beef also means consuming what these cattle
consume, including liquefied fat (meaning cattle that have already gone
through CAFO production and slaughter), antibiotics, synthetic oestro-
gen, corn, feather meal, chicken litter, chicken, fish and pig meal and
faecal dust. And this is to say nothing of the microbial ecosystem found
140 The Origins of Sociable Life: Evolution After Science Studies
Some feel more grief over damages inflicted upon an animal than
over those inflicted upon a human. This is because the animal is
deprived of the possibility of bearing witness according to the
human rules of establishing damages, and as a consequence, every
damage is like a wrong and turns it into a victim ipso facto. – But, if
it does not at all have the means to bear witness, then there are not
even damages, or at least you cannot establish them… That is why
the animal is a paradigm of the victim.34
Once again, Joost Van Loon’s insightful work on viruses and ‘parasite
politics’ provides a way forward:
The parasite gives us a rather different ‘Other’ than that elusive figure
that is central to the work of Levinas…. Instead of a morally impera-
tive and highly evolved figure, the parasite ‘Other’ is other in its
lowness. It is thus more able to resist the idolatry of otherness and
total self-negation commonly found in Levinasian-inspired ethics. This
resistance is essential if we are not to be entrapped in another, inverse,
form of identity politics. In its ‘becoming-host’ the parasite does not
allude to the high ground, yet it cannot engage in survivalism either as
survival is essentially based on the negation of any form of becoming.
In becoming-host, the parasite is the most effective ethical Other to
engender a sense of ‘community-in-difference’. That is, rethinking
community through the figure of the parasite allows us to steer clear of
both the survivalism of the solitary-autonomous but authentic indi-
vidual and the mediocre identity politics of the herd collective.39
Surviving humanism
One never eats entirely on one’s own: this constitutes the rule under-
lying the statement ‘one must eat well.’ It is a rule offering infinite
hospitality. And in all differences, ruptures and wars (one might even
say wars of religion), ‘eating well’ is at stake. Today more than ever.
One must eat well – here is a maxim whose modalities and contents
need only be varied, ad infinitum… A discourse thus restructured can
try to situate in another way the question of what a human subject, a
morality, a politics, the rights of the human subject are, can be, and
should be. Still to come, this task is indeed far ahead of us.41
Chapter 1
1 William Shakespeare, Hamlet, II, 2.
2 Keith Ansell Pearson, Viroid Life: Perspectives on Nietzsche and the Transhuman
Condition (London: Routledge, 1997); Keith Ansell Pearson, Germinal Life: The
Difference and Repetition of Deleuze (London: Routledge, 1999); Bruno Latour,
The Pasteurization of France (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1988);
Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari, What is Philosophy? (New York: Columbia
University Press, 1994); Donna Haraway, When Species Meet (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 2008); Karen Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway:
Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter and Meaning (Durham: Duke
University Press, 2007); Vicky Kirby, Telling Flesh: The Substance of the Corporeal
(New York: Routledge, 1997); Manuel De Landa, A Thousand Years of Nonlinear
History (New York: Swerve, 2000); Elizabeth Wilson, Neural Geographies: Fem-
inism and the Microstructure of Cognition (New York and London: Routledge,
1998); Alphonso Lingis, Foreign Bodies (New York: Routledge, 1994); Elizabeth
Grosz, Time Travels: Feminism, Nature, Power (Durham: Duke University Press,
2005); Rosalyn Diprose, Corporeal Generosity: On Giving with Nietzsche, Merleau-
Ponty, and Levinas (New York: State University of New York Press, 2002).
3 Perhaps I shall be accused of suffering from a bad case of microbiology and
geosciences envy. If this means that I have gained a much more nuanced
appreciation of the reflexive ways in which my natural scientific colleagues
negotiate science and philosophy, then I affirm such an accusation. And yet,
might this castigation itself be a ruse to dismiss further critical reflection? I
worry that a sense of smugness pervades the social sciences generally and
licenses the false impression that natural scientists are largely ignorant of
philosophical and social studies of science (they/scientists are observed;
we/social scientists are observers) while we can proceed with social scientific
144
Notes 145
12 Steven L. Goldman, The Science Wars: What Scientists Know and How They
Know It, 31. See also the 2007 CBC podcast ‘How to Think About Science’,
interview with Steven Shapin.
13 Francis Bacon, The New Organon (New York: Bobbs Merrill, 1960), 97.
14 Steven L. Goldman, The Science Wars: What Scientists Know and How They
Know It, 44–5.
15 Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer present a finely argued exposition of
science on the side of the earth giants in Leviathan and the Air Pump: Hobbes,
Boyle, and the Experimental Life (Princeton, N.J., Princeton University Press,
1985). See also the 2007 CBC podcast ‘How To Think About Science’ inter-
view with Steven Shapin.
16 Steven L. Goldman, The Science Wars: What Scientists Know and How They
Know It.
17 Steven L. Goldman, The Science Wars: What Scientists Know and How They
Know It, 78.
18 Norman Campbell, Physics, The Elements (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Pres, 1920).
19 Ian Hacking, ‘The Self-Vindication of the Laboratory Sciences,’ in Andrew
Pickering, ed., Science as Practice and Culture (Chicago: The University of
Chicago Press, 1992), 52.
20 Steve Fuller, Philosophy of Science and its Discontents (New York: Guilford
Press, 1992), 420. See also Steven L. Goldman, The Science Wars: What Scien-
tists Know and How They Know It, 138; Ian Hacking, ‘The Self-Vindication of
the Laboratory Sciences’, 55. Another thread woven through the debates
between the gods and earth giants is termed naïve realism. This idea takes
as its starting point the contention that knowledge ‘good enough’ to make
things happen, that is to progress in science and technology, is more
important than arriving at Truth per se. ‘Another way of stating this is [to
say that] a theory can explain to the satisfaction of a group of thinkers, can
make correct predictions, and can even lead to technological applications
that work and still be wrong, still not be true of reality’, what Duhem calls
the ‘underdetermination of theory by data’. See Pierre Duhem, The Aim and
Structure of Physical Theory (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press,
1954). This approach is exemplified by Joseph Fourier’s Analytical Theory of
Heat (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1823), in which Fourier
devised a mathematical theory of heat independent of what heat actually is.
Known as ‘Fourier’s Move,’ it effectively states that understanding the truth
of heat is less important, less practical, than understanding how heat
behaves. Bacon’s theory echoes this approach insofar as he argued that a
method that delivers knowledge about how nature works, is more impor-
tant than a theory of knowledge in philosophy per se. A number of critics of
this approach, best voiced perhaps in Paul Feyerabend’s Against Method:
Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge (Atlantic Highlands: Human-
ities Press, 1975), argue that knowledge derived from method cannot be dis-
tinguished from philosophical concerns with true knowledge in this way.
21 Schrödinger formulated the equation for the wave behavior of matter, while
Heisenberg formulated the particle behavior equation.
22 Karen Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entangle-
ment of Matter and Meaning, 76.
Notes 147
23 Barad calls this paradox ‘quantum weirdness’ and Bohr wrote ‘Anyone who
is not shocked by quantum theory has not understood it’. See Karen Barad,
Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entanglement of Matter
and Meaning, 83.
24 Planck’s Constant (h = 6 × 10–34 joule-seconds) is the point at which micro
(quantum) phenomena diverges from macro (Newtonian) phenomena. In
other words, phenomena exist at the macro level when Planck’s Constant = 0.
I defer here to my father, a physicist, according to whom physics isn’t inter-
ested in why this constant exists or how the universe would look if this con-
stant was even slightly different (atoms would be a different size, and life as we
know it might not be possible). Concerned about the attraction of thinking in
terms of two worlds (the micro and the macro), Erwin Schrödinger produced
the famous gedanken known colloquially as ‘Schrödinger’s Cat’. A cat is placed
in a sealed box containing a table on which rests a Geiger counter and a
radioactive source. If the Geiger counter detects decay, it releases poison,
which kills the cat. If the machine does not detect decay, the cat remains alive.
The fate of the cat is, in Bohr’s terms, ‘entangled’ with the fate of the atom.
Schrödinger’s point is that a simultaneously alive and dead cat defies common
sense, which holds that the cat is either alive or dead but not both simultane-
ously. Schrödinger’s Cat reminds me of Margaret Lock’s fine analysis of the
differences in the concept of death between Western and Japanese cultures.
But once the test has been actualized, we have crossed the line from probabil-
ity to certainty. See Edward Norbeck and Margaret Lock, Health, Illness, and
Medical Care in Japan: Cultural and Social Dimensions (Honolulu: University of
Hawaii Press, 1987) and Sarah Franklin and Margaret Lock (2003) Remaking
Life and Death: Toward an Anthropology of the Biosciences (Santa Fe: School of
American Research Press, 2003). I also think about the scene from the film The
Princess Bride in which the wizard describes one of the characters as only
‘mostly dead’.
25 Quantum theory comes with a number of implications that are worth
making explicit. First, quantum theory does not mean chaos all the way
down. Indeed, at the quantum level we get patterns, and hence a higher
degree of order (all electrons in the known universe are the same: not
similar, but exactly the same.) Nor is quantum theory the material proof of
anarchism. Second, the universe is not divided up into two simultaneously
existing worlds – one at the quantum and one at the macroscopic level (the
division itself is anthropocentric: we think atoms are small because we have
adopted a particular size scale). Third, and contrary to strong claims about
physics as more ‘objective’ because it deals only in empiricism, physics
makes liberal use of philosophy through gedankens; practical tools used by
physicists to think the unthinkable. Moreover, discussions between Einstein,
Bohr, Heisenberg, Schrödinger and others took seriously the metaphysical
implications of quantum theory, and Bohr’s writings are replete with com-
mentaries on metaphysics.
26 Personal communication with Brian Hird (2007).
27 William I. Thompson, Gaia 2 Emergence: The New Science of Becoming (New
York: Lindisfarne Press, 1991), 14, my emphasis.
28 Niels Bohr, ‘Discussion with Einstein on Epistemological Problems in Atomic
Physics,’ The Philosophical Writings of Niels Bohr. Vol. 2 Essays 1933–1957 On
148 Notes
Atomic Physics and Human Knowledge (New York: Science Edition Inc, 1949/
1961), 72.
29 Cliff Hooker, ‘The Nature of Quantum Mechanical Reality’, in R.G. Colodny,
ed., Paradigms and Paradoxes (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press,
1972), 156.
30 Einstein, Bohr and other physicists debated the ontological and epistemo-
logical implications of quantum theory in a series of articles and face-to-
face meetings including the International Physics Congress and the Fifth
Physical Conference in 1927, the Solvay Conferences in 1930 and 1933, the
International Congress on Light Therapy in 1932, the Second International
Congress for the Unity of Science in 1936, and the International Institute of
Intellectual Co-operation of the League of Nations meeting in 1938. It was in
one of these discussions between Einstein and Bohr that Einstein’s famous
dictum ‘God does not play dice’ reflected Einstein’s concern with the onto-
logical implications of quantum theory for physicists studying matter.
31 D. Howard, ‘Einstein and Duhem’, in R. Ariew and P. Barker, eds., Pierre
Duhem: Historian and Philosopher of Science, Sythese, 83 (1989): 240–1.
Einstein, taking the side of the gods, believed that this uncertainty might
simply reflect the ‘incompleteness’ of quantum mechanics. This is some-
times referred to as the ‘hidden variable hypothesis’ because it refers to the
idea that complete knowledge is possible given the right measurement.
32 Albert Einstein, B. Podolsky, and N. Rosen, ‘Can Quantum-Mechanical
Descriptions of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?’ Physical Review 47
(1935): 777–80, 696, my emphasis. Einstein’s disquiet was evident through-
out his life. Commenting on the implications of quantum theory, he wrote:
‘To believe this is logically possible without contradiction; but it is so very
contrary to my scientific instinct that I cannot forego the search for a more
complete conception’ (Albert Einstein, ‘Physics and Reality,’ Journal of
Franklin Institute 221 (1936): 349). Einstein’s unease was not without justifi-
cation: spin-off theories such as Everett, Wheeler and Graham’s (EWG)
Model speculate that natural laws are actually probability manifolds pro-
ducing an almost infinite number of universes, so that not only is every-
thing possible, but everything conceivable will happen in at least one
universe. ‘Bell’s Theorem’ states that ‘nonlocal’ correlations exist between
any two particles that have once been in contact (see J.S. Bell, Speakable and
Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics (Cambridge University Press, 1989)).
These sorts of ideas led to Einstein’s famous comment about entanglement:
that every time a mouse looks at the universe, the universe must change
(and Wolf’s calculation that the mouse’s brain is so small as to make the
changes caused by the mouse’s observations negligible. See Robert Anton
Wilson, Quantum Psychology: How Brain Software Programs You and Your World
(Tempe, AZ: New Falcon, 1990).
33 Niels Bohr, ‘Discussion with Einstein on Epistemological Problems in
Atomic Physics,’ 41, 60–1.
34 Niels Bohr, ‘Discussion with Einstein on Epistemological Problems in
Atomic Physics,’ 50.
35 Niels Bohr, ‘Discussion with Einstein on Epistemological Problems in Atomic
Physics,’ 64; Karen Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and
the Entanglement of Matter and Meaning, 56.
Notes 149
36 Karen Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entangle-
ment of Matter and Meaning, 205.
37 Karen Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entangle-
ment of Matter and Meaning, 197. My own reading of Bohr’s work sustains
Barad’s argument that Bohr is not ‘antirealist’. What his work does suggest,
and has been reiterated by others, is that ‘[i]n all these theories there are
many quantum descriptions of the same universe. Each of them depends
on a way of splitting the universe in two parts such that one part contains
the observer and the other part contains what the observer wishes to
describe… The quantum description is always the description of some part
of the universe by an observer who remains inside it’ (Lee Smolin, Three
Roads to Quantum Gravity, (New York: Basic Books, 2001), 47–8; see also
Carlo Rovelli, ‘Relational Quantum Mechanics,’ International Journal of
Theoretical Physics 35, no. 8 (1996): 1637–78). As such, the totality of the
universe is inaccessible (in an ontological sense) from the observer.
38 Karen Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entangle-
ment of Matter and Meaning. There is insufficient space here to detail how
each physicist’s research contributed to the development of quantum
theory (see Niels Bohr, ‘Discussion with Einstein on Epistemological Prob-
lems in Atomic Physics’). Planck’s discovery of the universal quantum of
action, Einstein’s discovery that photo-effects and other physical phenom-
ena depend upon individual quantum effects, Rutherford’s discovery of the
atomic nucleus, Franck and Hertz’s experiments producing spectra through
the impact of electrons on atoms, and a host of other developments, all
contributed to what is known today as quantum theory. Quantum theory is
now a mature branch of physics with good predictive power at the micro-
level: in other words, quantum mechanics works (this was the basis of
Fourier’s description of heat: it doesn’t matter that we don’t understand the
ontology of heat; it works and that is sufficient). Applications of quantum
theory have enabled the development of cell phones, CD players and lap-
tops – about 30 percent of the US gross national product (Tim Folger,
‘Quantum Shmantum,’ Discover 22 no. 9 (2001)).
39 Karen Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entangle-
ment of Matter and Meaning, 88.
40 Karen Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the Entangle-
ment of Matter and Meaning, 37. Pickering also refers to developments in par-
ticle physics to outline his theory of post-humanist ‘noncorrespondence
realism’ in which the ‘the representational chains of science terminate not
“in the world itself” but in specific captures and framings of material
agency’ which are, in effect, closures effected by the outcome of ‘machinic,
conceptual, and social maneuverings in fields of material and disciplinary
agency’. See Andrew Pickering, The Mangle of Practice: Time, Agency, and
Science (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1995), 186, 194.
41 Niels Bohr, ‘Discussion with Einstein on Epistemological Problems in
Atomic Physics,’ 20–1.
42 Niels Bohr, ‘Discussion with Einstein on Epistemological Problems in
Atomic Physics,’ 22. While he ventured into the implications of quantum
theory for understanding metaphysical problems such as consciousness,
Bohr was cautious: ‘… I should like to emphasize that considerations of the
150 Notes
kind here mentioned are entirely opposed to any attempt of seeking new poss-
ibilities for a spiritual influence on the behavior of matter in the statistical
description of atomic phenomena’ (Niels Bohr, ‘Discussion with Einstein on
Epistemological Problems in Atomic Physics,’ 11). Social scientists recognize
this position because it challenges anthropocentric and popularized notions,
not to mention liberal humanist conceptions of the individual as ultimately
responsible for her/his willed behavior (expounded in the film What the Bleep?
and the like). A number of these applications make strong claims about the
applicability of quantum theory to human political, psychological or spiritual
concerns. These popularized accounts share a narrative route that goes like
this: quantum theory (the hardest of the hard sciences and therefore most
objective, valid and so on) proves the nonbifurcation of observer-observed
which means that people can control every aspect of their lives (getting rich,
having more sex with more attractive partners, overcoming infertility, obesity
and so on), and collectively, we can create a peaceful, environmentally respon-
sible humanity – all this by recognizing quantum theory’s ‘message’. For a
more explicit link between quantum theory and religion see M. Ricard and
T. Xuan Thuan, The Quantum and the Lotus: A Journey to the Frontiers Where
Science and Buddhism Meet (New York: Three Rivers Press, 2004). But as Barad
cautions: ‘In the popular literature, quantum physics is often positioned as
the scientific path leading out of the West to the metaphysical Edenic garden
of Eastern mysticism. Paralleling these popular renditions, one can find sug-
gestions in the literature that quantum physics is inherently less androcentric,
less Eurocentric, more feminine, more post-modern, and generally less regres-
sive than the masculinist and imperializing tendencies found in Newtonian
physics. But those who naively embrace quantum physics as some exotic
Other that will save our weary Western souls forget too quickly that quantum
physics underlies the workings of the A-bomb, that particle physics (which
relies on quantum theory) is the ultimate manifestation of the tendency
toward scientific reductionism, and that quantum theory in all its applications
continues to be the purview of a small group of primarily Western-trained
males’ (Karen Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the
Entanglement of Matter and Meaning, 67–8).
43 Bruno Latour, We Have Never Been Modern, Trans. Catherine Porter (Cam-
bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1993); Michael Callon and John Law,
‘After the Individual in Society: Lessons on Collectivity From Science, Tech-
nology and Society,’ Canadian Journal of Sociology 22, no. 2 (1997): 1–11;
Isabelle Stengers, Power and Invention: Situating Science, Trans. P. Bains (Minnea-
polis: University of Minnesota Press, 1997); John Law, Power, Action and Belief:
A New Sociology of Knowledge? (London: Routledge, 1986); Andrew Pickering,
The Mangle of Practice: Time, Agency and Science; Michel Serres, Les Cinq Sens
(Paris: Hachette, 1985); Michael Kearnes, ‘Geographies That Matter: The
Rhetorical Deployment of Physicality?’ Social and Cultural Geography 4, no. 2
(2003); Steve Fuller, Social Epistemology (Indiana University Press, 1988); Henri
Bergson. Matter and Memory, Trans. Nancy Margaret Paul and W. Scott Palmer
(London: George Allen and Unwin, 1911); Rosi Braidotti, Transpositions (Cam-
bridge: Polity Press, 2006); Alan Irwin and Brian Wynne, Misunderstanding
Science? The Public Reconstruction of Science and Technology (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1996); Evelyn Fox Keller, Reflections on Gender and
Notes 151
Science (London: Yale University Press, 1985); Donna Haraway, The Haraway
Reader (New York and London: Routledge, 2004).
44 H.M. Collins and Steven Yearley, ‘Epistemological Chicken’, in Andrew
Pickering, ed., Science as Practice and Culture (Chicago: Chicago University
Press, 1992), 304. The ‘weak program’ is defined as ‘the idea that socio-
psychological causes need only be sought for error, irrationality and devi-
ation from the proper norms and methodological precepts of science. As
such, the weak program resembles representationalism in the belief that
‘errors’ in the scientific method can be both measured and taken into
account (i.e. eliminated). See David Bloor, ‘Anti-Latour,’ Studies in History
and Philosophy of Science 30, no. 1 (1999): 113–29.
45 William I. Thompson, Gaia 2 Emergence: The New Science of Becoming, 20.
46 David Bloor, ‘Anti-Latour,’ 90.
47 This seems to come close to Bohr’s definition of objectivity: ‘… however far
the phenomena transcend the scope of classical physical explanation, the
account of all evidence must be expressed in classical terms. The argument
is simply that by the word “experiment” we refer to a situation where we
can tell others what we have done and what we have learned and that,
therefore, the account of the experimental arrangement and of the results
of the observations must be expressed in unambiguous language with suit-
able application of the terminology of classical physics’ (Niels Bohr,
‘Discussion with Einstein on Epistemological Problems in Atomic Physics,’ 39).
48 David Bloor, ‘Anti-Latour,’ 110.
49 David Bloor, ‘Anti-Latour,’ 87.
50 H.M. Collins Steven Yearley, ‘Epistemological Chicken,’ 310.
51 See the Bloor-Latour debate in Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science
and the Collins and Yearley debate with Woolgar, Callon and Latour in
Andrew Pickering (ed.), Science as Practice and Culture.
52 Bruno Latour, The Pasteurization of France, 193. Latour lists the terms he has
variously adopted to document the indivisibility of ‘nonsocial’ nature and
‘social’ nature: ‘inscription, visualization, translation, trials, mediation, names
of action, black-boxing, historicity of things’. ANT’s approach requires science
studies practitioners to take actants seriously, as, according to Latour, scien-
tists already do: ‘any scientist worth the name has been thoroughly redefined
by the actors he or she has dealt with’. Bruno Latour, ‘For Bloor and Beyond:
A Reply to David Bloor’s “Anti-Latour,”’ Studies in the History and Philosophy of
Science 30, no. 1 (1999): 121, 126.
53 Graham Harman, The Metaphysics of Objects: Latour and His Aftermath (draft
manuscript, 2008), 2.
54 Bruno Latour, The Pasteurization of France, 205–6.
55 Bruno Latour, We Have Never Been Modern, 4.
56 Steve Woolgar, ‘Some Remarks about Positivism: A Reply to Collins and
Yearley,’ in Andrew Pickering, ed., Science as Practice and Culture (Chicago:
The University of Chicago Press, 1992), 327–42, 332.
57 Michael Callon and Bruno Latour, ‘Don’t Throw the Baby Out with the
Bath School!,’ in Andrew Pickering, ed., Science as Practice and Culture
(Chicago: The University of Chicago Press), 350.
58 Graham Harman, The Metaphysics of Objects: Latour and His Aftermath, 12.
59 Graham Harman, The Metaphysics of Objects: Latour and His Aftermath, 61.
152 Notes
60 Graham Harman, The Metaphysics of Objects: Latour and His Aftermath, 20,
29.
61 Graham Harman, The Metaphysics of Objects: Latour and His Aftermath, 144.
62 Steve Woolgar, ‘Some Remarks about Positivism: A Reply to Collins and
Yearley,’ 335.
63 Michael Callon and Bruno Latour, ‘Don’t Throw the Baby Out with the
Bath School!,’ 346.
64 Bruno Latour, ‘For David Bloor… and Beyond: A Reply to David Bloor’s
“Anti-Latour,”’ 118.
65 Graham Harman, The Metaphysics of Objects: Latour and His Aftermath, 26.
66 Michael Callon and Bruno Latour, ‘Don’t Throw the Baby Out with the
Bath School!,’ 355.
67 Bruno Latour, The Pasteurization of France, 159.
68 Graham Harman, The Metaphysics of Objects: Latour and His Aftermath, 29.
69 Graham Harman, The Metaphysics of Objects: Latour and His Aftermath, 7.
Again, the strong program argues that everything is ultimately part of nature
(such as observers and consciousness), but that causal explanations for
scientific phenomena are to be found in social explanations (resonant with
Durkheim), which, by its own definition, must be already within nature.
Kearnes makes the point that ‘a reductive logic of causality haunts current
calls for a “material culture” approach or a rematerialization of contem-
porary social and cultural geography. An external materiality is acted upon
by socio-cultural consumption and thus becomes an object.’ Michael Kearnes,
‘Geographies That Matter: The Rhetorical Deployment of Physicality?,’
Social and Cultural Geography 4, no. 2 (2003): 148.
70 Bruno Latour, The Pasteurization of France, 35.
71 Graham Harman, The Metaphysics of Objects: Latour and His Aftermath, 170.
72 See H. M. Collins Steven Yearley, ‘Epistemological Chicken’; Karin Knorr-
Cetina, Epistemic Cultures: How the Sciences Make Knowledge (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1985); S. Schaffer, ‘Review of B. Latour, The Pas-
teurization of France,’ Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 22 (1991):
175–92; S. Shapin, ‘Following Scientists Around,’ Social Studies of Science 18
(1988): 533–50; Alan Sokal and J. Bricmont, Fashionable Nonsense: Post-
modern Intellectuals’, Abuse of Science (New York: Picador, 1998).
73 For an example, see Bruno Latour, ‘A Relativistic Account of Einstein’s Rela-
tivity,’ Social Studies of Science, 18 (1988): 3–44, 20. In this analysis, Latour
asks: ‘in what ways can we, by reformulating the concept of society, see
Einstein’s work as explicitly social? Latour’s answer is surprising given his
emphasis is on ‘things-in-themselves’ – which would presumably include
time/space and gravity – having their own agentic existence. Latour argues
that Einstein’s theory of special relativity is, at its root, semiotic theory. He
analyzes Einstein’s discussion of special relativity to pivot on the difference
between relativism and relativity. Relativism, defined by Latour reading
Einstein (using the example of two observers, one on a moving train and
one on the station platform), says that all observers can be ‘shifted out’ of
a space and time, but when we shift them back in, their reports (of their
location) will not be superimposable (they will not agree). Latour seems to
think that Einstein’s ‘observers’ are human, whereas Einstein’s observers are
simply measuring devices, which the other measuring devices need not
Notes 153
fear, as Latour assumes, ‘might betray, might retain privileges, and send
reports that could not be used to expand our knowledge [or require] dis-
cipline… to turn them into dependent pieces of apparatus that do nothing
but watch the coincidence of hands and notches…’ (Bruno Latour, ‘A Rela-
tivistic Account of Einstein’s Relativity,’ 22). Latour argues that Einstein’s
theory of special relativity is commensurate with semiotics in which all nar-
rators of texts must be ‘shifted out’ of that text. In other words, ‘… there is
no difference to be made in principle, between internal sociology – how to
manage the population of actants that make up the content of a text – and
external sociology’ (Bruno Latour, ‘A Relativistic Account of Einstein’s Rela-
tivity,’ 27). This seems a curious slip. Latour’s point is to demonstrate, through
special relativity, that distinguishing between observer (social) and observed
(object) is an epistemological dead end. But in practice, the material seems
to collapse into the cultural, which then occupies center-stage.
74 Ian Hacking, ‘The Self-Vindication of the Laboratory Sciences,’ in Andrew
Pickering, ed., Science as Practice and Culture, 52.
75 Adrian Mackenzie and Andrew Murphie, ‘The Two Cultures Become Multiple?
Sciences, Humanities and Everyday Experimentation,’ Australian Feminist
Studies, 23, no. 55 (2008): 87–100.
76 Adrian Mackenzie and Andrew Murphie, ‘The Two Cultures Become Multiple?
Sciences, Humanities and Everyday Experimentation,’ 89.
Chapter 2
1 Charles Darwin, The Variation of Animals and Plants Under Domestication
(New York: Organe Judd, 1868), 204.
2 R.Y. Stanier and C.B. van Niel, ‘The Concept of a Bacterium,’ Archives of
Microbiology 42 (1962): 17–35. Epitaph by permission of Archives of
Microbiology and Springer Publishing.
3 Albert Einstein. URL: < http://www.quotedb.com/quotes/2310>. Accessed
August 2008.
4 Of course, and as Latour points out, the human eye, microscopes and lab-
oratories have been key to understanding bacteria at all, at the same time
that bacteria are notoriously resistant to laboratory culturing. See Bruno
Latour, Pandora’s Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies, 113–73.
5 How small is small? Bacteria are about 1/10 to 1/100 the size of microor-
ganisms such as Paramecium and Amoeba, can only be resolved with a
microscope. How big is big? The largest bacteria is Epulsopiscium fishelsoni,
a gram-positive bacteria that inhabits surgeonfish guts. It is rod-shaped
and about 0.08 × 0.6 millimeters (half a millimeter) long, which is bigger
than most animal cells, and can be seen with the unaided human eye.
6 Betsey Dexter Dyer, A Field Guide To Bacteria (Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press, 2003), 14.
7 R.A. Lafferty, ‘Slow Tuesday Night,’ in Nine Hundred Grandmothers
(Berkeley Heights, NJ: Wildside Press, 1999), 134–42. I thank Bronislaw
Szerszynski for drawing my attention to Lafferty’s writing.
8 Stephen Jay Gould, Wonderful Life: The Burgess Shale and the Nature of
History (New York: W.W. Norton, 1989), 309–10.
154 Notes
eukaryotes that develop from embryos that are never blastular. See
Dorion Sagan and Lynn Margulis, Garden of Microbial Delights: A Practical
Guide to the Subvisible World, 86–7.
19 Dorion Sagan and Lynn Margulis, Garden of Microbial Delights: A Practical
Guide to the Subvisible World, 61.
20 Dorion Sagan and Lynn Margulis, Garden of Microbial Delights: A Practical
Guide to the Subvisible World, 61.
21 A number of scientists hypothesize that life began in these anoxic, high
alkalinity, very hot temperatures. See, for example, Michael J. Russell, ‘The
Importance of Being Alkaline,’ Science 302 (2003): 580–1; W. Martin and
Michael J. Russell, ‘On the Origin of Cells: A Hypothesis for the Evolutionary
Transitions from Abiotic Geochemistry to Chemoautotrophic Prokaryotes,
and from Prokaryotes to Nucleated Cells,’ Philosophical Transactions of the
Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 10, no. 1098 (2002): 1–27.
22 Of course, our 20 percent oxygen atmosphere oxidizes metals without
bacteria.
23 Betsey Dexter Dyer, A Field Guide To Bacteria, 118.
24 Betsey Dexter Dyer, A Field Guide To Bacteria, 127.
25 Betsey Dexter Dyer, A Field Guide To Bacteria, 147.
26 Dwayne Savage, as cited in Betsey Dexter Dyer, A Field Guide To Bacteria, 279.
27 Betsey Dexter Dyer, A Field Guide To Bacteria, 205.
28 See Betsey Dexter Dyer, A Field Guide To Bacteria.
29 Deb Hayden, Pox: Genius, Madness, and the Mysteries of Syphilis (New York:
Basic Books, 2003).
30 Lynn Margulis, ‘Spirochetes Awake: Syphilis and Nietzsche’s Mad Genius,’ in
Dazzle Gradually: Reflections on the Nature of Nature, eds. Dorion Sagan and
Lynn Margulis (White River Junction: Chelsea Green Publishing, 2007).
31 Because methane reacts completely in the presence of oxygen, the contin-
uous presence of methane on earth means that it is continuously being
manufactured. About 30 percent of atmospheric methane is produced by
grazing animals. See Dorion Sagan and Lynn Margulis, Garden of Microbial
Delights: A Practical Guide to the Subvisible World, 113–15.
32 Tyler Volk, ‘Gaia is Life in a Wasteland of By-products,’ in Scientists Debate
Gaia: The Next Century, eds. Stephen Schneider, James Miller, Eileen Crist
and Penelope Boston (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2004), 27–36.
33 Edward O. Wilson, ‘The Meaning of Biodiversity and the Tree of Life,’ in
Assembling the Tree of Life, eds. Joel Cracraft and Michael Donoghue (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2004), 539–42, 540.
34 Bruno Latour, ‘From Fabrication to Reality: Pasteur and His Lactic Acid
Ferment’ and ‘The Historicity of Things: Where Were Microbes Before
Pasteur?,’ in Pandora’s Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies, 113–44,
145–73.
35 Bruno Latour, Pandora’s Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies, 122.
36 Bruno Latour, Pandora’s Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies, 124.
37 Latour defines propositions as occasions that allow entities to modify their
definition over the course of an event. See Graham Harman, The Metaphysics
of Objects: Latour and His Aftermath, 141.
38 Astrid Schrader, ‘Phantomatic Species Ontologies: Questions of Survival in
the Remaking of Kin and Kind,’ 4S Conference, Vancouver, B.C.
(November 2006), 1–10.
156 Notes
budgets, they try desperately to keep their collections in order while eking
out enough time to publish accounts of a small fraction of the novel life
forms sent to them for identification’. Edward O. Wilson, ‘The Meaning of
Biodiversity and the Tree of Life,’ in Assembling the Tree of Life, eds. Joel
Cracraft and Michael Donoghue (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004),
540.
44 See Julie Sommerlund, ‘The Multiplicity of Classifications and Research
Practices in Molecular Microbial Ecology,’ Social Studies of Science 36, no. 6
(2006): 909–28. Sommerlund asks: ‘if you cannot test the VBNC-bacteria
– because they cannot live while being tested – how can you tell if they
are alive, or even in existence?’ (914).
45 Julie Sommerlund provides an interesting science studies analysis of the ten-
sions between phylogenetic and naturalist approaches. Part of the tension,
Sommerlund notes, is about intuition. Hippopotamus and wart hogs intu-
itively appear on nearby branches because they both have four feet. 16S
sequencing, however, reveals that hippos are more genetically related to
whales (Julie Sommerlund, ‘The Multiplicity of Classifications and
Research Practices in Molecular Microbial Ecology’).
46 Margulis needs to retain the prokaryote-eukaryote distinction because sym-
biogenesis theory is predicated on the hypothesis that all eukaryotes derive
from prokaryotic ancestors. It also recognizes that prokaryotes are
monogenomic while eukaryotes are polygenomic through symbiogenesis.
Margulis and Whittaker have devised a schema meant to acknowledge the
insights of molecular biology while retaining symbiogenesis as the major
driving force of evolution. The schema includes the superkingdom
Prokaryota, which includes the kingdom Monera (which itself contains
Bacteria and Archaea); and the superkingdom Eukaryota, which includes the
kingdoms Protoctista, Animalia, Plantae and Fungi.
47 See also Lynn Margulis, Michael Dolan, and Ricardo Guerrero, ‘The
Molecular Tangled Bank: Not seeing the Phylogenies for the Trees,’ Biology
Bulletin 196 (1999): 413–14, 414. The authors argue that partial phylogenies
can never be full phylogenies in the sense that all organisms (with the
exception of a few bacteria) have thousands of proteins required at all times
for metabolism. Others also argue against the theory that Archaea is a sepa-
rate domain. See, for example, R.S. Gupta and E. Griffiths, ‘Critical Issues in
Bacterial Phylogeny,’ Theoretical Population Biology 61, no. 4 (2002): 423–34;
R.S. Gupta, ‘Evolutionary Relationships among Bacteria: Does 16S rRNA
provide all the answers?’, ASM News 66 (2000): 189–90; R.S. Gupta, Life’s
Third Domain (Archaea): An Established Fact or an Endangered Paradigm?:
A New Proposal for Classification of Organisms Based on Protein Sequences
and Cell Structure, Theoretical Population Biology 54, no. 2 (1998): 91–104.
48 Jan Sapp, ‘The Prokaryote-Eukaryote Dichotomy: Meanings and
Mytholog,’ 302. Julie Sommerlund further adds that the gene sequencing
computer programs use assumptions about how close together the
branches should be (Julie Sommerlund, ‘The Multiplicity of Classifications
and Research Practices in Molecular Microbial Ecology’).
49 Hervé Philippe hypothesizes that prokaryotes derived from eukaryotes. See
Hervé Philippe, ‘The Origin and Radiation of Eucaryotes,’ in Assembling
the Tree of Life, eds. Joel Cracraft and Michael Donoghue (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2004), 95–106. See also Hervé Philippe, Agnès Germot
158 Notes
biotic Stress,’ Physica A 282, no. 1 (2000): 247–82; Ilan Ron, Ido Golding,
Beatrice Lifsitz and Eshel Ben-Jacob, ‘Bursts of Sectors in Expanding Bacterial
Colonies as a Possible Model for Tumor Growth and Metastases,’ Physica A:
Statistical Mechanics and its Applications 320 (2003): 485–96.
75 Richard Losick and D. Kaiser, ‘Why and How Bacteria Communicate,’
Scientific American 276, no. 2 (1997): 73.
76 Bonnie Bassler, ‘Small Talk: Cell-to-Cell Communication in Bacteria,’ Cell
109 (2002): 421–4.
77 Bonnie Bassler, ‘Small Talk: Cell-to-Cell Communication in Bacteria,’ 421.
78 Richard Losick and D. Kaiser, ‘Why and How Bacteria Communicate,’
68–73.
79 I. Cohen, I. Golding and E. Ben-Jacob, ‘Biofluiddynamics of Lubricating
Bacteria,’ Mathematical Methods Applied to Science 24 (2001): 1429–68; Mark
Lyte, ‘Microbial Endocrinology and Infectious Disease in the 21st Century,’
Trends in Microbiology 12 (2004): 14–20.
80 Eshel Ben-Jacob and Herbert Levine, ‘Self-engineering Capabilities of
Bacteria,’ 2–3.
81 For a detailed description of the biochemical processes involved in Myxo-
coccus xanthus sporulation, see J.M. Kuner and D. Kaiser, ‘Fruiting Body
Morphogenesis in Submerged Cultures of Myxococcus xanthus,’ Journal of
Bacteriology 151, no. 2 (1982): 458–61.
82 Eshel Ben-Jacob, Israela Becker, Yoash Shapira and Herbert Levine,
‘Bacterial Linguistic Communication and Social Intelligence,’ Trends in
Microbiology 12, no. 8 (2004): 366–72.
83 James A. Shapiro, ‘The Significance of Bacterial Colony Patterns,’ BioEssays
17, no. 7 (1995): 597–607. Although it goes against the traditional Kotchian
isolation of a single bacterium, studying bacteria as multicellular colonies
affords new ways to meet-with bacteria. As Ben-Jacob and Levine write,
‘the idea that bacteria act as unsophisticated uncommunicative and
uncooperative cells stems from years of laboratory experiments where the
bacteria are grown in Petri dishes under benign conditions’. Eshel Ben-
Jacob and Herbert Levine, ‘Self-engineering Capabilities of Bacteria,’ 1.
84 James A. Shapiro, ‘The Significance of Bacterial Colony Patterns,’ 597.
85 Eshel Ben-Jacob and Herbert Levine, ‘Self-engineering Capabilities of
Bacteria,’ 10.
86 Eshel Ben-Jacob and Herbert Levine, ‘Self-engineering Capabilities of
Bacteria,’ 2.
87 Eshel Ben-Jacob, ‘Bacterial Self-organization: Co-enhancement of Complex-
ification and Adaptability in a Dynamic Environment,’ 1285.
88 Eshel Ben-Jacob, Israela Becker, Yoash Shapira and Herbert Levine,
‘Bacterial Linguistic Communication and Social Intelligence,’ 367.
89 Eshel Ben-Jacob, Israela Becker, Yoash Shapira and Herbert Levine,
‘Bacterial Linguistic Communication and Social Intelligence,’ 367.
90 Greg Bear, Blood Music (New York: I Books, 2002).
91 Eshel Ben-Jacob, Israela Becker, Yoash Shapira and Herbert Levine,
‘Bacterial Linguistic Communication and Social Intelligence,’ 371.
92 Eshel Ben-Jacob, Israela Becker, Yoash Shapira and Herbert Levine,
‘Bacterial Linguistic Communication and Social Intelligence,’ 371. Trans-
posons are DNA sequences that can move to different positions within a
Notes 161
single cell’s genome. Transposons are classified into one of two classes:
retrotransposons in which RNA copy and paste sequences back into the
genome; and DNA transposons which cut and paste DNA into the genome.
93 J.P. Rasicella, P.U. Park, P.U. and M.S. Fox, ‘Adaptive Mutation in Escherichia
coli: A Role for Conjugation,’ Science 268 (1995): 418–20.
94 Eshel Ben-Jacob, ‘Bacterial Wisdom, Godel’s Theorem and Creative Genomic
Webs,’ 65. Margulis maintains that these bacterial ancestors were already
‘conscious entities’ insofar as awareness of the surrounding environment is a
condition of life. Eukaryotes’ neurons derive from symbiogenetic bacterial
mergers: as we have already seen, cells (including neurons) are hetero-
genomic, complex and with multiple ancestors. Spirochetes, Margulis theor-
izes, became the undulipodia of eukaryotic cells. With their 24-nanometer
tubules, spirochetes are homologous to the neurotubules of the neurons.
Indeed, animal sense organs – auditory, visual, tactile and gustatory – are
composed of undulipodiated cells.
95 Eshel Ben-Jacob, ‘Bacterial Wisdom, Godel’s Theorem and Creative
Genomic Webs,’ 70.
96 Gregory Bateson, ‘Form, Substance, and Difference: Nineteenth Annual
Korzybski Memorial Lecture,’ in Steps to an Ecology of Mind (New York:
Ballantine Books, 1992), 448–64.
97 C.S. Peirce, The Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Edited by
C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss (vols. 1–6) and A. Burks (vols. 7–8) (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1931–1958). Biosemiotics is also associated
with Jakob von Uexküll, Yuri Stepanov and Gregory Bateson. Zoosemiotics
concerns the scientific study of signaling behavior amongst nonhuman
animals where ‘a living animal is the transcoder in a biological version of
the traditional information-theory circuit’. While zoosemiotics has init-
iated studies much more concerned with animal communication in its
own right – inevitable comparisons with human communication are made,
with humans decidedly in the complexity and sophistication lead. See
Thomas A. Sebeok, ‘Zoosemiotics,’ American Speech 43, no. 2 (1968): 143.
See also Thomas A. Sebeok, Signs: An Introduction to Semiotics (Toronto:
University of Toronto Press, 1994) and Thomas A. Sebeok, Global Semiotics
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2001).
98 Jesper Hoffmeyer, ‘Biosemiotics,’ in Encyclopedia of Semiotics, ed. P. Bouissac
(New York: Oxford University Press, 2007), 82.
99 Jesper Hoffmeyer, ‘Biosemiotics,’ 83.
100 Alexei Sharov, ‘What is Biosemiotics?’ URL: <http://www.gypsymoth.
ento. vt.edu/-sharov/biosem/geninfo.html> Accessed September 2,
2008.
101 Karen Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway.
102 Jesper Hoffmeyer, ‘Biosemiotics,’ 84.
103 Jesper Hoffmeyer, ‘Biosemiotics,’ 84.
104 Thomas A. Sebeok, The Sign and its Masters (Texas: University of Texas
Press, 1979). See also Jesper Hoffmeyer, Signs of Meaning in the Universe
(Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 1997). I am in agreement with
Hoffmeyer’s characterization of the ‘seclusion’ of eukaryotic organisms rel-
ative to bacterial openness to foreign DNA. On the other hand, I think that
Ben-Jacob and colleagues’ research on bacterial decision-making might
162 Notes
Chapter 3
1 Joel Cracraft and Micheal Donoghue (eds.), Assembling the Tree of Life, 86.
Epitaph by permission of Oxford University Press Inc.
2 Roger Stanier, ‘Some Aspects of the Biology of Cells and Their Possible
Evolutionary Significance,’ in Organization and Control in Prokaryotic Cells,
eds. H.P. Charles and B.C. Knight. Twentieth Symposium of the Society
for General Microbiology (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970),
31. Epitaph reprinted with the permission of Cambridge University Press.
Reproduced with permission.
3 George Orwell in Michael Crichton, State of Fear (New York: HarperCollins,
2004), ix.
Notes 163
own languages and epistemes and scientists are generally not encouraged to
work outside their sub-discipline.
36 See Jan Sapp, Genesis: The Evolution of Biology. Anthony van Leeuwenhoek
(1632–1723) first described microbes, using the best microscopes that could
magnify objects 270 times. Swabbing his teeth with a stick (aka tooth-
brush), van Leeuwenhoek observed a microcosmos teeming with minute
organisms. Joseph Amato notes that it did not take long for this teeming
mass to be enveloped within a negative biopolitics of germ theory, a kind of
‘what you don’t know (and can’t see) does hurt you’. See Joseph Amato, Dust:
A History of the Small and the Invisible (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 2000), 97, 103. A number of prokaryotologists also object to bio-
logical language that describes bacteria as pathogens, as ‘simple’ life forms
compared with the ‘complexity’ of larger forms of life, while simultane-
ously obfuscating Homo sapiens’ bacterial origins and current status as sym-
bionts. See Sonea and Mathieu (2000).
37 Susan Oyama, The Ontogeny of Information: Developmental Systems and
Evolution, 143.
38 Keith Ansell Pearson, Viroid Life, 132. According to Margulis, even most mol-
ecular biologists do not explicitly recognize that they are studying symbioses.
She writes, ‘The literature of eukaryotic molecular biology grows, but the
practitioners of this science do not think of themselves as analysts of inte-
grated symbioses. That they are studying a latter-day microbial community
and its interactions has not yet been factored into their thinking’. See Lynn
Margulis and Dorion Sagan, The Origins of Sex: Three Billion Years of Genetic
Recombination, 18.
39 Luciana Parisi, Abstract Sex: Philosophy, Bio-technology and the Mutations of
Desire, 60.
40 Luciana Parisi, Abstract Sex: Philosophy, Bio-technology and the Mutations of
Desire, 35, 40.
41 Jan Sapp, Evolution by Association: A History of Symbiosis, 208. ‘Cytoplasmic
heredity’ in sexually reproducing organisms is the inheritance of genetic
traits from a single parent and independent of nuclear genes (Jinks, 1964). A
number of phenomena once considered to conform to nuclear (vertical)
inheritance principles are now known to be cases of uni-parental or
nonMendelian bi-parental transmission (see Lynn Margulis, Symbiosis in Cell
Evolution, 1981); Moraes et al., ‘Mitochondrial DNA deletions in progressive
external ophthalmoplegia and Kearns-Sayre syndrome,’ New England Journal
of Medicine 320, no. 20 (1989): 1293–9; G. Singh, M.T. Lott and D.C. Wallace,
‘A Mitochondrial DNA Mutation as a Cause of Leber’s Hereditary Optic
Neuropathy,’ New England Journal of Medicine 320 (1989): 1300–5.
42 David Hull, Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and Con-
ceptual Development of Science (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press,
1988) provides a succinct account of the gene/cell/organism/species unit of
selection debate. Symbiogenesis theory’s understanding of the symbiont
differs from Hull’s definition of ‘interactor’ (408) insofar as the ‘entity’ cannot
be distinguished from its environment (i.e. the entity is its environment). This
entity also replicates, for instance in mitosis.
43 Woese argues that the Archaean was a pre-Darwinian time in which there
were no such thing as individuals that competed. See Carl Woese, ‘A New
Notes 167
Biology for a New Century,’ Microbiology and Molecular Biology Reviews 68,
no. 2 (2004): 173–86 and Nigel Goldenfeld and Carl Woese, ‘Connections
Biology’s Next Revolution,’ Nature 445 (25 January 2007).
44 Charles Mann, ‘Lynn Margulis: Science’s Unruly Earth Mother,’ Science 252
(1991): 378–81, p. 252. See also David Stamos, The Species Problem: Biological
Species, Ontology, and the Metaphysics of Biology (Lanham, MD: Lexington
Books, 2003).
45 Nigel Goldenfeld and Carl Woese, ‘Connections Biology’s Next Revolution,’
Nature 445 (25 January 2007): 369.
46 Lewis Thomas, The Lives of a Cell: Notes of a Biology Watcher (New York:
Viking Press, 1974), 86–7.
47 Lynn Margulis, ‘Gaia is a Tough Bitch,’ in The Third Culture, ed. J. Brockman
(New York: Simon and Schuster, 1995), 135.
48 Jan Sapp, Evolution by Association: A History of Symbiosis. As Sahl wryly notes,
‘Remember that no matter how selfish, how cruel, how unfeeling you have
been today, every time you take a breath, you make a flower happy’, in
Richard Lewontin, The Triple Helix (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press, 2000), 55.
49 Newly discovered symbiotic relationships are consistently reported in scien-
tific journals. Symbiosis has been identified in monads and polymonads,
dyads and polydyads (such as mitochondria), triads and polytriads (such as
‘anaerobic’ worms, amoebae and photosynthetic animals), quadrads and
polyquadrads (such as wood-eating insects and nitrogen fixation by
legumes) and pentads and polypentads (for instance invertebrate animals
and land plants). See H. Timourian, ‘Symbiotic Emergence of Metazoans,’
Nature 226 (18 April 1970): 283–4; L. Marquez et al., ‘A Virus in a Fungus in
a Plant: Three-way Symbiosis Required for Thermal Tolerance,’ Science 63
(2007): 545–58; Lynn Margulis, ‘Genetic and Evolutionary Consequences of
Symbiosis,’ Experimental Parasitology 39 (1976): 277–349; D.J. Depew and
B.H. Weber, Darwinism Evolving: Systems Dynamics and the Genealogy of
Natural Selection (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1997); Stephen J. Gould, The
Structure of Evolutionary Theory (Cambridge, Mass. and London: The Belknap
Press of Harvard University Press, 2002); R. Law, ‘The Symbiotic Phenotype:
Origins in Evolution,’ in Symbiosis as a Source of Evolutionary Innovation, eds.
Lynn Margulis and Rene Fester (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991), 57–71;
W. Martin and T.M. Embley, ‘Early Evolution Comes Full Circle,’ Nature 431
(9 September 2004): 134–7; J. Maynard Smith, Evolutionary Genetics, Second
Ed. (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998); P. Nardon and A.M. Grenier,
‘Serial Endosymbiosis Theory and Weevil Evolution: The Role of Symbiosis,’
Symbiosis as a Source of Evolutionary Innovation, eds. Lynn Margulis and Rene
Fester (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1991), 153–69; M. Rivera and J. Lake,
‘The Ring of Life Provides Evidence for a Genome Fusion Origin of Eukary-
otes,’ Nature 431 (9 September 2004): 152–5; D.C. Smith and A.E. Douglas,
The Biology of Symbiosis (London: Edward Arnold, 1987).
50 W. Ford Doolittle, ‘Phylogenetic Classification and the Universal Tree,’
Science 284 (1999): 2124–9; Nigel Goldenfeld and Carl Woese, ‘Connections
Biology’s Next Revolution.’ H. Ochman, J.G. Lawrence and E.A. Groisman,
‘Lateral Gene Transfer and the Nature of Bacterial Innovation,’ Nature 405
(2000): 299–304.
168 Notes
63 See, for example, Richard Lewontin, The Triple Helix: Gene, Organism and
Environment; Richard Lewontin, It Ain’t Necessarily So: The Dream of the Human
Genome and Other Illusions, Second Ed. (New York: New York Review Books,
2001); Evelyn Fox Keller, Refiguring Life: Metaphors of Twentieth-Century Biology
(New York: Columbia University Press, 1995); Evelyn Fox Keller, The Century of
the Gene (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2000).
64 Carl Zimmer, ‘Now: The Rest of the Genome,’ New York Times (10 November
2008). URL: <http://www.nytimes.com/2008/11/11/science/11gene.html?_r=>.
Accessed November 11, 2008. I thank Christopher Canning for directing my
attention to this article.
65 My interest here in not in detailing intelligent design or creationist cri-
tiques of evolutionary theory.
66 For critiques of neoDarwinism that emphasize symbiosis, see Connie Barlow,
The Ghosts of Evolution: Nonsensical Fruit, Missing Partners, and Other Ecological
Anachronisms (New York: Basic Books, 2000); Robert Wesson, Beyond Natural
Selection (Cambridge, Mass.: The MIT Press, 1991); Frank Ryan, Darwin’s Blind
Spot: Evolution Beyond Natural Selection (Boston: Houghton Mifflin Company,
2002); Jaroslav Flegr, Frozen Evolution (Prague: Charles University in Prague,
2008); Christian deDuve, Singularities: Landmarks on the Pathways of Life
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005); Jan Sapp, Evolution by Asso-
ciation: A History of Symbiosis (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1994).
67 Margaret McFall-Ngai, ‘Unseen Forces: The Influence of Bacteria on Animal
Development,’ Developmental Biology 242 (2002): 1. See also L.V. Hooper,
M.H. Wong, A. Thelin, L. Hansson, P. Falk and J. Gordon, ‘Molecular Analysis
of Commensal Host-Microbial Relationships in the Intestine,’ Science 291
(2001): 881–4.
68 D.A. Relman and S. Falkow, ‘The Meaning and Impact of the Human Genome
Sequencing for Microbiology,’ Trends in Molecular Biology 9, no. 5 (2001):
206–8.
69 Margaret McFall-Ngai, ‘Unseen Forces: The Influence of Bacteria on Animal
Development,’ Developmental Biology 242 (2002): 4.
70 Lora V. Hooper, Melissa H. Wong, Anders Thelin, Lennart Hansson,
Per G. Falk and Jeffrey I. Gordon, ‘Molecular Analysis of Commensal
Host-Microbial Relationships in the Intestine,’ Science 291, no. 5505 (2001):
881–4.
71 Margaret McFall-Ngai, ‘Unseen Forces: The Influence of Bacteria on Animal
Development,’ 9. I am struggling with a terminology that doesn’t reiterate
the term ‘host’ because of its long association with pathogens.
72 Margaret McFall-Ngai, ‘Unseen Forces: The Influence of Bacteria on Animal
Development,’ 9–10.
73 Conrad H. Waddington, ‘Epigenetics and Evolution,’ in Evolution, eds.
R. Brown and J. Danielli, Evolution (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1953), 186–99.
74 Scott Gilbert, ‘The Genome in its Ecological Context: Philosophical Perspec-
tives on Interspecies Epigenesis,’ 214.
75 John Protevi’s three lectures on Deleuze and Biology provide a useful intro-
duction to ‘evo-devo’ (www.protevi.com/john). See also Eva Jablonka and
Marion Lamb, Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic, Epigenetic, Behavioral,
and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life.
170 Notes
sequence determines form and function rather than the other way around.
Interestingly, and as W. Ford Doolittle points out, this is based on the
assumption that different genes in a genome might have different phylo-
genetic histories, something that Margulis’s research on mitochondria and
chloroplasts showed to be the case: ‘the fact that [all of an organism’s
genes do not have the same phylogeny] proved the endosymbiont hypoth-
esis’. Moreover, Doolittle asserts that the majority of genes in any bacterial
or archaeic genome show different phylogenies, and are produced through
nonsymbiogenetic means, leading him to conclude that there is no unique
universal genomic tree. See W. Ford Doolittle, ‘Bacteria and Archaea,’ in
Assembling the Tree of Life, 86–94, 88.
83 Jablonka and Lamb refer to Lindegren’s research on the bread mould Neuro-
spora in which two-thirds of the mutations do not follow Mendel’s principle
in which offspring do not show intermediate characteristics but rather a segre-
gation of traits. Jablonka and Lamb argue this research, like research showing
epigenetics in bacteria, transposons (‘jumping genes’) in maize and the like
were either ignored or explained away. See Eva Jablonka and Marion Lamb,
Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic, Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Vari-
ation in the History of Life, 43–4; Carl Lindegren, The Yeast Cell, its Genetics and
Cytology (St. Louis: Educational Publishers, 1949).
84 Eva Jablonka and Marion Lamb, Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic,
Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life, 87.
85 Eva Jablonka and Marion Lamb, Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic,
Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life, 92–7.
86 James Shapiro, as cited in Eva Jablonka and Marion Lamb, Evolution in Four
Dimensions: Genetic, Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the
History of Life, 70–1.
87 Mark and Mary Anne Alliegro at the Marine Biology Laboratory in Wood’s
Hole are researching the possibility that centrosomes contain DNA. So far,
they have established that Spsula oocyte centrosomes contain RNA. See
Mark Alliegro and Mary Anne Alliegro, ‘Centrosomal RNA Correlates with
Intron-poor Nuclear Genes in Spisula Oocytes,’ Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences 105, no. 19 (5 May 2008): 6993–7.
88 Jan Sapp, Evolution by Association: A History of Symbiosis, 204.
89 P. Godfrey-Smith, ‘Is it a Revolution?’ Biology and Philosophy 22 (2007):
430.
90 Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 94.
91 Symbiogenesis is the microbial version of the historicity that Latour writes
about with regard to humans. A historicity in which there is linear time
(the symbiogenesis of nuclear material precedes the symbiogenesis of mito-
chondria) and also a Bergsonian time in which the past is inherited within
the present and future. See Bruno Latour, Pandora’s Hope: Essays on the
Reality of Science Studies, 159–62, 171, Figure 5.2.
92 Eva Jablonka and Marion Lamb, Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic,
Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life, 102.
93 Richard Dawkins, The Extended Phenotype: The Long Reach of the Gene, 133,
137, 159, 161, and 257. Dawkins used the term ‘misfirings’ to describe all of
those actions that do not fit with his selfish gene theory of natural selection
during my interview with him on 16 June 2008.
172 Notes
94 Elizabeth Grosz, Time Travels: Feminism, Nature, Power (Durham, NC: Duke
University Press, 2005). Sociobiology and the more recent evolutionary
psychology is founded upon the application of evolutionary theory to
human and animal behavior. See, for instance: Jerome Barkow, Leda Cos-
mides and John Tooby (eds.), The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and
the Generation of Culture (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1995); Margo
Wilson and Martin Daly, Homicide (Aldine Transaction, 1988); David Buss,
Evolutionary Psychology: The New Science of Mind, Third Ed. (Allyn and Bacon,
2007); David Buss, The Handbook of Evolutionary Psychology (Wiley, 2005);
Stephen Sanderson, The Evolution of Human Sociality: A Darwinian Conflict
Perspective (Lanham, Maryland: Rowman and Littlefield Publishing, Inc,
2001).
95 For examples of feminist, queer and post-colonial theories see Noreen
Giffney and Myra Hird, Queering the NonHuman (Ashgate, 2008) and Donna
Haraway, How Like a Leaf: An Interview with Donna Haraway (New York:
Routledge, 1999). For examples of engagements with symbiogenesis see
Donna Haraway, When Species Meet (University of Minnesota Press, 2007)
and Luciana Parisi, Abstract Sex: Philosophy, Bio-technology and the Mutations
of Desire (London and New York: Continuum Press, 2004).
Chapter 4
1 Marcel Mauss, The Gift. The Form and Reason For Exchange in Archaic Societies,
Translated by W.D. Halls (New York and London: W.W. Norton, 1950/1990).
2 Rosalyn Diprose, Corporeal Generosity: On giving with Nietzsche, Merleau-
Ponty, and Levinas (New York: State University of New York Press,
2002).
3 Nigel Clark, ‘Disaster and Generosity,’ The Geographical Journal 171, no. 4
(2005): 384–6.
4 Donna Haraway, The Companion Species Manifesto: Dogs, People, and Sig-
nificant Otherness; Donna Haraway, When Species Meet; Karalyn Kendall, ‘The
Face of a Dog: Levinasian Ethics and Human/Dog Coevolution,’ in Queering
the (Non-)Human.
5 Haraway does make the point that ‘“Companion species” is a bigger and
more heterogeneous category than companion animal, [which] must
include such organic beings as rice, bees, tulips, and intestinal flora, all of
whom make life for humans what it is – and vice versa’ (Donna Haraway,
The Companion Species Manifesto: Dogs, People, and Significant Otherness,
15).
6 Richard Feynman, ‘There’s plenty of Room at the Bottom,’ Journal of
Microelectromechanical Systems 1, no. 1 (1992): 60–6.
7 Maureen O’Malley and John Dupré, ‘Size Doesn’t Matter: Towards a More
Inclusive Philosophy of Biology,’ Biology and Philosophy 22 (2007): 155.
8 Maureen O’Malley and John Dupré, ‘Size Doesn’t Matter: Towards a More
Inclusive Philosophy of Biology,’ 155.
9 Nick Bingham, ‘Bees, Butterflies, and Bacteria: Biotechnology and the
Politics of Nonhuman Friendship,’ Environment and Planning A 38 (2006):
483–98, 496.
Notes 173
10 Parts of this section are taken from Myra J. Hird ‘The Corporeal Generosity of
Maternity’, Body and Society, 2007, 13 (1): 1–20. Reprinted with kind permission
from Sage Publishing.
11 Marcel Mauss, The Gift. The Form and Reason For Exchange in Archaic Societies, ix.
12 Marcel Mauss, The Gift. The Form and Reason For Exchange in Archaic Societies, 12.
13 Marcel Mauss, The Gift. The Form and Reason For Exchange in Archaic Societies, 12.
14 Morna Joy, ‘Beyond the Given and the All-giving: Reflections on Women and
the Gift,’ Australian Feminist Studies 14, no. 30 (1999): 315–32. See also M.
Godelier, ‘Some Things You Give, Some Things You Sell, But Some Things You
Must Keep For Yourselves: What Mauss Did Not Say About Sacred Objects,’ in
The Enigma of Gift and Sacrifice, eds. E. Wyschogrod; J.J. Goux. and E. Boynton
(New York: Fordham University Press, 2002), 19–37.
15 Nigel Clark, ‘Disaster and Generosity,’ 384–6; Alphonso Lingis, Excesses:
Eros and Culture (Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1983).
16 Nigel Clark, ‘Disaster and Generosity,’ 93.
17 Alphonso Lingis, Dangerous Emotions (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 2000), 174–5.
18 Jacques Derrida, Given Time (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1992).
19 Lingis refers to Nietzsche’s directive that ‘whenever you do a good deed,
you should take a stick and thrash any bystander to muddle his [sic] memory.
Then you should take that stick and thrash your own head, to muddle your
own memory’ (Alphonso Lingis, Dangerous Emotions, 179).
20 Rosalyn Diprose, Corporeal Generosity: On giving with Nietzsche, Merleau-
Ponty, and Levinas, 75.
21 Nigel Clark, ‘Disaster and Generosity,’ 7.
22 Lingis states that ‘what gifts give is the ability to give gifts’ (Alphonso
Lingis, Dangerous Emotions, 181).
23 It is precisely this tension between the generosity and violence of the cor-
poreal that leads Rackham to refer to the HIV virus inside her body as a
‘viral lover’ (2000).
24 Donna Haraway, When Species Meet, 9.
25 Karalyn Kendall, ‘The Face of a Dog: Levinasian Ethics and Human/Dog
Coevolution,’ in Queering the (Non-)Human, eds. Noreen Giffney and Myra
Hird (Aldershot: Ashgate Press, 2008), 185–204.
26 Nigel Clark, ‘Disaster and Generosity,’ 7.
27 Robert Wilson, ‘Recent work in individualism in the social, behavioral and
biological sciences,’ Biology and Philosophy 19 (2004): 397.
28 Maureen O’Malley and John Dupré, ‘Size Doesn’t Matter: Towards a More
Inclusive Philosophy of Biology,’ Biology and Philosophy 22 (2007): 156.
29 Scott Gilbert, ‘Cells in Search of Community: Critiques of Weismannism
and Selectable Units in Ontogeny,’ Biology and Philosophy 7 (1992): 478.
30 Scott Gilbert, ‘Cells in Search of Community: Critiques of Weismannism
and Selectable Units in Ontogeny,’ 478.
31 Burnet in Thomas Pradeu and Edgardo Carosella, ‘The Self Model and the
Conception of Biological Identity in Immunology,’ Biology and Philosophy
21 (2006): 235.
32 Eileen Crist and Alfred I. Tauber, ‘Selfhood, Immunity, and the Biological
Imagination: The Thought of Frank Macfarlane Burnet,’ Biology and Philo-
174 Notes
sophy 15, no. 4 (2000): 510. This genealogy of the association between
economic theories of competition, struggle and individualism on the one
hand and biology on the other has been taken up within the philosophy
and biology literature. See Scott Gilbert, ‘Cells in Search of Community:
Critiques of Weismannism and Selectable Units in Ontogeny,’ 473–87. Crist
and Tauber argue that the immunological self was not simply ‘imported
from a cultural and historical milieu into a scientific context, but rather
emerged as an immanent concept within immunology itself (Eileen Crist
and Alfred I. Tauber, ‘Selfhood, Immunity, and the Biological Imagination:
The Thought of Frank Macfarlane Burnet,’ 517).
33 Alfred Tauber, ‘Postmodernism and Immune Selfhood,’ Science in Context 8,
no. 4 (1995): 579–607, 584. In Chapter 5 I discuss Zuckerman and Lederberg’s
notion of ‘post-mature’ scientific discoveries, which refers to science’s nearly
exclusive concentration on bacteria as pathogens. See Harriet Zuckerman and
Joshua Lederberg, ‘Postmature Scientific Discovery?’ Nature 324 (December
1986): 629–31.
34 Eileen Crist and Alfred I. Tauber, ‘Selfhood, Immunity, and the Biological
Imagination: The Thought of Frank Macfarlane Burnet,’ 524.
35 In an insightful analysis, Tauber describes Nietzsche’s approach to biology in
similar terms: the ‘sovereign subject relates only to that which it constructs
or confronts’ (Alfred Tauber, ‘Postmodernism and Immune Selfhood,’ Science
in Context 8, no. 4 (1995): 581). The account of symbiogenesis in this paper
attempts to exceed Nietzsche’s characterization.
36 Eileen Crist and Alfred I. Tauber, ‘Selfhood, Immunity, and the Biological
Imagination: The Thought of Frank Macfarlane Burnet,’ 526.
37 Eileen Crist and Alfred I. Tauber, ‘Selfhood, Immunity, and the Biological
Imagination: The Thought of Frank Macfarlane Burnet,’ 526.
38 Myra J. Hird, ‘Chimerism, Mosaicism and the Cultural Construction of
Kinship,’ Sexualities 7, no. 2 (2004): 225–40.
39 Gilbert notes that the complex ongoing interaction with the changing envir-
onment means that there really isn’t such a thing as identical twins with
respect to immunity since no two individuals will have had identical inter-
actions with an identical environment. For these reasons, Pradeu and
Carosella propose their ‘continuity hypothesis’ whereby immune activation
is triggered by discontinuity of interaction. Understanding commensal
bacteria as ‘self’ becomes intelligible within the continuity hypothesis, as a
more ‘heterogeneous view of biological identity’. Scott Gilbert, ‘The Genome
in Its Ecological Context: Philosophical Perspectives on Interspecies Epi-
genesis,’ Ann. N.Y. Acad. Sci. 981 (2002): 202–18. See also Thomas Pradeu
and Edgardo Carosella, ‘The Self Model and the Conception of Biological
Identity in Immunology,’ Biology and Philosophy 21 (2006): 248.
40 Scott Gilbert, ‘The Genome in Its Ecological Context: Philosophical Perspec-
tives on Interspecies Epigenesis,’ 210.
41 Yolanda Lopez-Boado, Carole Wilson, Lora Hooper, Jeffrey I. Gordon, Scott
J. Hultgren and William Parks, ‘Bacterial Exposure Induces and Activates
Matrilysin in Mucosal Epithelial Cells,’ Journal of Cell Biology 148, no. 6
(2000): 1305–15.
42 Margaret McFall-Ngai, ‘Unseen Forces: The Influence of Bacteria on Animal
Development,’ 8; Lora V. Hooper, Melissa H. Wong, Anders Thelin, Lennart
Hansson, Per G. Falk and Jeffrey I. Gordon, ‘Molecular Analysis of Com-
Notes 175
Chapter 5
1 Sadie Plant, Zeros + Ones: Digital Women + The New Technoculture (New York:
Doubleday, 1997), 205.
2 Elizabeth Wilson, ‘Biologically Inspired Feminism: Response to Helen Keane
and Marsha Rosengarten, “On the Biology of Sexed Subjects,”’ Australian
Feminist Studies 17, no. 39 (2002): 283–5.
3 Sharon Kinsman, ‘Life, Sex and Cells,’ in Feminist Science Studies, eds.
Mayberry, Subramaniam and Weasel (New York: Routledge, 2001),
193–203, 197.
4 Lambert, D. and the Diagram Group (2005) The Secret Sex Lives of Animals
(New York: Sterling Publishing Co., Inc.).
5 Harriet Zuckerman and Josh Lederberg, ‘Postmature Scientific Discovery?’
Nature 324 (1986): 629–31, 629. Social studies of science are familiar with
premature discoveries in science – those observations made in a scientific
context that precludes their understanding. Within evolutionary theory,
perhaps the best-known example of a premature discovery was Mendel’s
theory of particulate inheritance. Only 35 years later, when Darwin had put
forth the theory of evolution through natural selection, were the implica-
tions of Mendel’s experiments contextualized.
6 Harriet Zuckerman and Josh Lederberg, ‘Postmature Scientific Discovery?’
629.
7 Janet Browne’s article, ‘Botany for Gentlemen’ provides a lively and thorough
critique of Erasmus Darwin’s poem ‘The Love of the Plants’. The poem, meant
as a vindication of Linneas’s plant taxonomy, reified very familiar and highly
normative conceptions of 19th century British femininity and masculinity.
See Janet Browne, ‘Botany for Gentlemen,’ Isis 80, no. 4 (1989): 593–621. See
also Londa Schiebinger, Nature’s Body: Sexual Politics and the Making of Modern
Notes 179
Science (London: Pandora, 1993); Myra Hird, Sex, Gender and Science (New
York: Palgrave, 2004).
8 Emile Durkheim, Suicide (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1970), 385.
9 Part of this section appears in Myra Hird, Sex, Gender and Science.
10 John Maynard-Smith, The Evolution of Sex (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1978); Charles Darwin The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to
Sex (London: John Murray, 1890); Ernst Mayr, What Evolution Is (New York:
Basic Books, 2001).
11 J.L. Mackay, ‘Why Have Sex?,’ British Medical Journal 322, no. 7286 (2001):
623.
12 Evolutionary theory’s ‘problem’ finds expression in the Red Queen Hypo-
thesis. The idea here is that evolution is not concerned with progress
because in a constantly changing environment, change is necessary just to
survive. In Alice in Wonderland, the Red Queen tells Alice that she must run
very fast in Wonderland just to stay in the same place. See Lynn Margulis
and Dorion Sagan, What is Sex? 120–1.
13 See, respectively, William Hamilton, Robert Axelrod, and Reiko Tanese,
‘Sexual Reproduction as an Adaptation to Resist Parasites,’ Proc. Natl Acad.
Sci. 87 (1990): 3566–73; Aneil Agrawal, ‘Similarity Selection and the Evolu-
tion of Sex: Revisiting the Red Queen,’ PLOS Biol. 4 (2006): 1364–71; Alexey
Kondrashov, ‘Deleterious Mutations and the Evolution of Sexual Repro-
duction,’ Nature 336 (1988): 435–40; R.A. Fisher, The Genetical Theory of Natural
Selection (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1930); Joseph Felsenstein, ‘The Evolution-
ary Advantage of Recombination,’ Genetics 78, no. 2 (1974): 737–56.
14 Graham Bell, The Masterpiece of Nature: The Evolution and Genetics of Sexuality
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1982), 99, emphasis in original.
15 Lynn Margulis and Dorion Sagan, The Origins of Sex: Three Billion Years of
Genetic Recombination. See also Judith Roof’s critique of Freud’s utilitarian
approach to protists as that ‘lowest organism’ through which a conservative
Darwinism (neoDarwinism) illustrates the universalism of the replication
drive. Although ‘obligingly stable, simple, persistent, and flexible’, protists
nevertheless exist as ‘exception[s] to evolution’s rule’ insofar as they persist
through evolutionary time ‘at their lowly level’ rather than evolving into
‘higher’ more complex organisms. Because their reproduction is uniparental,
protists defy death – side-stepping desire that all organisms have to return to
death as the originary state of quiescence through the pleasure principle
(Judith Roof, ‘From Protists to DNA (and Back Again): Freud’s Psychoanalysis
of the Single-Celled Organism,’ 105). Freud, reading Darwin, brings protists
back into the evolutionary fold by arguing that repeated cloning weakens
the organism, whilst the combining of genetic material from more than one
source strengthens the organism, providing the quid pro quo that sexual
reproduction goes hand-in-hand with ‘higher creatures’: ‘protista exception
has become the incarnation of a rule’ (109, 110).
16 Margulis and Sagan, Origins of Sex: Three Billion Years of Genetic Recombination,
235.
17 Margulis and Sagan, What is Sex?, 17.
18 Margulis and Sagan, What is Sex?, 235.
19 Lynn Margulis in Lawrence Joseph, Gia: The Growth of an Idea (New York:
St. Martin’s Press, 1990), 63.
20 Margulis and Sagan, What is Sex?, 17.
180 Notes
37 See also Denis Owen, ‘Mimicry and Transvestism in Papilio phorcas,’ Journal
of Entomological Society of Southern Africa 51 (1988): 294–6; Joan Roughgarden,
Evolution’s Rainbow: Diversity, Gender, and Sexuality in Nature and People
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 2004).
38 Theo Colborn, Dianne Dumanoski and John Peterson Myers, Our Stolen
Future (London: Little Brown and Company, 1996).
39 Leonard Paulozzi, J. David Erickson and Richard J. Jackson, ‘Hypospadias
Trends in Two American Surveillance Systems,’ Pediatrics 100 (1997): 831–4;
Helen Dolk, M. Vrijheid, B. Armstrong, L. Abramsky, F. Bianchi, E. Garne,
V. Nelen, E. Robert, J.E. Scott, D. Stone and R. Tenconi, ‘Risk of Congenital
Anomalies Near Hazardous Waste Landfill Sites in Europe: The EUROHAZ-
CON Study,’ The Lancet 352 (8 August 1998): 423–7.
40 Phillip Landrigan, Joy E. Carlson, Cynthia F. Bearer, Joan Spyker Cranmer,
Robert D. Bullard, Ruth A. Etzel, John Groopman, John A. McLachlan, Frederica
P. Perera, J. Routt Reigart, Leslie Robison, Lawrence Schell and William A. Suk,
‘Children’s Health and the Environment: A New Agenda for Prevention
Research,’ Environmental Health Perspectives 106, no. 3 (1998): 787–94.
41 Edmund J. Clark, David O. Norris and Richard E. Jones, ‘Interactions of
Gonadal Steroids and Pesticides (DDT, DDE) on Gonaduct Growth in Larval
Tiger Salamanders,’ General and Comparative Endocrinology 109 (1998): 94–105;
A.L. Reeder, G.L. Foley, D.K. Nichols, L.G. Hansen, B. Wikoff, S. Faeh,
J. Eisold, M.B. Wheeler, R. Warner, J.E. Murphy and V.R. Beasley, ‘Forms and
Prevalence of Intersexuality and Effects of Environmental Contaminants on
Sexuality in Cricket Frogs,’ Environmental Health Perspectives 106, no. 5 (1998):
261–6.
42 Ann Oliver Cheek and John A. McLachlan, ‘Environmental Hormones and the
Male Reproductive System,’ Journal of Andrology 19, no. 1 (1998): 5–10; Rober
J. Golden, Kenneth L. Noller, Linda Titus-Ernstoff, Raymond H. Kaufman,
Robert Mittendorf, Robert Stillman and Elizabeth A. Reese, ‘Environmental
Endocrine Modulators and Human Health: An Assessment of the Biological
Evidence,’ Critical Review of Toxicology 28, no. 2 (1998): 109–227; Geary Olsen,
Frank D. Gilliland, Michele M. Burlew, Jean M. Burris, Jack S. Mandel and
Jeffrey H. Mandel, ‘An Epidemiologic Investigation of Reproductive Hormones
in Men with Occupational Exposure to Perfluorooctanoic Acid,’ JOEM 40,
no. 7 (1998): 614–22; R. Santti, S. Makela, L Strauss, J. Korkman, M.L. Kostian,
‘Phytoestrogens: Potential Endocrine Disruptors in Males,’ Toxicology and
Industrial Health 14, nos. 1–2 (1998): 223–7; N. Skakkeæk, ‘Germ Cell Cancer
and Disorders of Spermatogenesis: An Environmental Connection?’ APMIS
106 (1998): 3–12; C.R. Tyler, C. et al., ‘Endocrine Disruption in Wildlife:
A Critical Review of the Evidence,’ Critical Reviews of Toxicology 28, no. 4
(1998): 319–61.
43 Londa Schiebinger, Has Feminism Changed Science? (Cambridge and London:
Harvard University Press, 1999), 149–50.
44 This section is taken from Myra J. Hird, Sex, Gender and Science.
45 Edward O. Wilson, Sociobiology: The New Synthesis (Cambridge, Massachusetts:
The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2000), 315. See also Martin
Reite and Nancy G. Caine eds., Child Abuse: The Nonhuman Primate Data (New
York: Alan R. Liss Inc., 1983).
46 Edward O. Wilson, Sociobiology: The New Synthesis.
182 Notes
Chapter 6
1 John Urry, ‘Order on the Edge of Chaos,’ American Sociological Association
Conference, (New York, 14 August 2007); James Lovelock, The Revenge of Gaia:
Earth’s Climate Crisis and the Fate of Humanity (New York: Basic Books, 2006).
2 Stepehen Schneider, James Miller, Eileen Crist, Penelope Boston, ‘Preface,’
in Scientists Debate Gaia: The Next Century, eds. S. Schneider, J. Miller,
E. Crist and P. Boston (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2004), xiii–xvii.
3 Stepehen Schneider, James Miller, Eileen Crist, Penelope Boston, Scientists
Debate Gaia: The Next Century, xiii. Lovelock defends his continued use of
the goddess symbol (and while Margulis does not herself favor the name,
she defends Lovelock) because it resonates with the public imagination,
allowing people to think about the planet as a whole. Scientists, on the
other hand, display outright hostility toward the name because of its wide-
spread appeal to lay persons who subscribe to ‘spiritual’ notions of the
earth. For instance, the Liechtenstein-based Foundation for Gaia and the
Gaia Institute of the Cathedral of St John the Divine offer massage, lifestyle
instruction and the like. For most scientists, recourse to anything other
than science on the side of Plato’s gods is too reminiscent of the long strug-
gle to free society from religious dogma. Richard Dawkins, science’s most
recent critic of religion, described Gaia theory thus: ‘the Gaia theory thrives
on an innate desire, mostly among laypeople, to believe that evolution
works for the good of all’. [It is] Profoundly erroneous… [and] sounds
exactly like the origin of a religion to me’. Dawkins quoted in Lawrence
E. Joseph, Gaia: The Growth of an Idea, 56, 69.
4 Alan Irwin, Sociology and the Environment: A Critical Introduction to Society,
Nature and Knowledge (Oxford: Polity Press, 2001), 180. Howard Newby’s
acerbic observation of sociology’s disinterest in moving beyond a social
studies agenda is no less sobering: ‘the slender contribution of sociologists
to the study of the environment has been, to put it mildly, disappointing’
(in Alan Irwin, Sociology and the Environment: A Critical Introduction to Society,
Nature and Knowledge, vi).
5 Steven L. Goldman, The Science Wars: What Scientists Know and How They Know
It. For instance, SSK’s strong program ‘symmetry postulate’ argues that all ideas
(whether rational, irrational, true or false) are social ‘through and through’.
See David Bloor, ‘Anti-Latour,’ Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 30,
no. 1 (1999): 113–29. One of the long-term points of contention between the
SSK and ANT pivots on the degree to which scientific claims are accorded
explanatory status as things-in-themselves, or more accurately perhaps, things-
in-phenomena. See also Karen Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum
Physics and the Entanglement of Matter and Meaning.
6 Alan Irwin, Sociology and the Environment: A Critical Introduction to Society,
Nature and Knowledge, 21.
7 John Urry, Sociology Beyond Societies: Mobilities for the Twenty First Century
(London: Routledge, 2000), 18. This latter concern assumes, of course, that
social scientists consider the earth to be, to a greater or lesser extent, in an
environmental crisis, that humans have precipitated this crisis, and that
humans can do something to avert or otherwise mitigate the crisis’s
effects.
186 Notes
8 Warren M. Hern, ‘Why Are There So Many of Us? Description and Diag-
nosis of a Planetary Ecopathological Process,’ Population and Environment: A
Journal of Interdisciplinary Studies 12, no. 1 (1990): 9–39.
9 See David Strahan, The Last Oil Shock: A Survival Guide to the Imminent
Extinction of Petroleum Man (London: John Murray Publishers, 2007);
Vaclav Smil, The Earth’s Biosphere: Evolution, Dynamics, and Change
(Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2002); James Lovelock, The Revenge of
Gaia: Earth’s Climate Crisis and the Fate of Humanity (New York: Basic
Books, 2006); E.O. Wilson, The Creation: An Appeal to Save Life on Earth
(New York: W.W. Norton, 2007).
10 J. MacAllister, ‘Gaia and Symbiogenesis: Communities Become Individuals,’
in Chimeras and Consciousness: Evolution and the Sensory Self, eds. L. Margulis,
C. Asikainen and W. Krumbein (White River Junction, Vermont: Chelsea
Green Publishing, forthcoming).
11 Keith Ansell Pearson, Viroid Life: Perspectives on Nietzsche and the Trans-
human Condition. For discussions of an ‘enlivened nature’ approach, see
Vicki Kirby, ‘Subject to Natural Law: A Meditation on the “Two Cultures”
Problem,’ Australian Feminist Studies 23, no. 55: 5–17; Elizabeth Wilson,
‘Introduction: Somatic Compliance – Feminism, Biology, and Science,’
Australian Feminist Studies 14, no. 29: 7–18, and Timothy Mitchell, ‘Can the
Mosquito Speak?,’ in Rule of Experts: Egypt, Techno-Politics, Modernity (Los
Angeles: University of California Press, 2002).
12 Lynn Margulis and James Lovelock, ‘The Atmosphere as Circulatory System
of the Biosphere – The Gaia hypothesis,’ CoEvolution Quarterly 6 (1975):
30–40; Lynn Margulis and James Lovelock, ‘Is Mars a spaceship, too?,’
Natural History 85 (1976): 86–90; Lynn Margulis and James Lovelock,
‘The View from Mars and Venus,’ The Sciences 17 (1977): 10–13;
Lynn Margulis and James Lovelock, ‘Atmospheres and Evolution,’ in
Life in the Universe, ed. J. Billingham (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1981),
79–100; James Lovelock and Lynn Margulis, ‘Atmospheric Homeostasis
By and for the Biosphere: The Gaia Hypothesis,’ Tellus 26 (1974): 2–10;
Andrew Watson, James Lovelock, and Lynn Margulis, ‘Methanogenesis,
fires and the regulation of atmospheric oxygen,’ BioSystems 10 (1979):
293–8.
13 For instance, geoscientists tend to obviate the role of organisms (primarily
bacteria) in environmental evolution, and biologists tend to be unaware of
the complex and intricate ways in which nonliving matter interacts with
living organisms.
14 Hans Peter Duerr, Dreamtime: Concerning the Boundary Between Wilderness and
Civilization. Trans. F. Goodman (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1987); Alphonso
Lingis, The Community of Those Who Have Nothing in Common (Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1994); Giorgio Agamben, The Open: Man and
Animal. Trans. K. Attell (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2004);
Donna Haraway, When Species Meet; Peter C. van Wyck, Primitives in the
Wilderness: Deep Ecology and the Missing Human Subject (New York: State
University of New York Press, 1997).
15 See Peter C. van Wyck, Primitives in the Wilderness: Deep Ecology and the
Missing Human Subject, 126.
16 Eduard Seuss in Vaclav Smil, The Earth’s Biosphere: Evolution, Dynamics, and
Change, 1, my emphasis.
Notes 187
Chapter 7
1 Karen Barad, Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the
Entanglement of Matter and Meaning, 380. Copyright © 2007, Duke
University Press. All rights reserved. Used by permission of the publisher.
2 John Agnew, ‘Open to Surprise,’ Progress in Human Geography 30, no. 1
(2006): 1–4. Reprinted by permission of SAGE.
3 Donna Haraway, When Species Meet.
Notes 193
to regions where they can consume living matter. In other words, auto-
trophs enjoy a much more extensive habitat. The Biosphere’s annotator,
Mark McMenamin notes that a single autotrophic cyanobacterium, with
unrestricted growth, could oxygenate the earth’s atmosphere in 40 days. See
V.I. Vernadsky, The Biosphere, ed. M. McMenamin (New York: Copernicus/
Springer-Verlag, 1926/1997), 105, fn.206.
16 Hern, in Michael Pollan, The Omnivore’s Dilemma (New York: Penguin Press,
2007).
17 Michael Pollan, The Omnivore’s Dilemma (New York: Penguin Press, 2007).
18 S. Sonea and L. Mathieu, Prokaryotology: A Coherent View (Les Presses de
L’Universite de Montreal, 2000), 16. Mice reared by scientists in a microbe-
free environment must consume about 30 percent more calories to maintain
the same body weight as mice kept in microbe-rich habitats. See Marlene Zuk,
Riddled With Life: Friendly Worms, Ladybug Sex, and the Parasites That Make Us
Who We Are.
19 Lora Hooper, Melissa Wong, Anders Thelin, Lennart Hansson, Per Falk and
Jeffrey Gordon, ‘Molecular Analysis of Commensal Host-Microbial Relation-
ships in the Intestine,’ Science 291, no. 2 (2001): 881–4.
20 See also: H. Wexler, ‘Bacteriodes: The Good, the Bad and the Nitty-Gritty,’
Clinical Microbiological Review 20 (2007): 593–621; P. Gerard, P. Lepercq,
M. Leclerc, F. Gavini, P. Raibaud and C. Juste, ‘Bacteriodes sp. Strain D8, the
First Cholesterol-Reducing Bacterium Isolated from Human Feces,’ Applied
Environmental Microbiology 73 (2007): 5742–9; B. Corthesy, H. Gaskins and
A. Mercenier, ‘Cross-Talk Between Probiotic Bacteria and the Host Immune
System,’ Journal of Nutrition 137 (2007): 781S–790S; P. Eckburg, E. Bik,
C. Bernstein, E. Purdom, L. Dethlefsen, M. Sargent, S. Gill, K. Nelson and
D. Relman, ‘Diversity of the Human Intestinal Microbial Flora,’ Science 308
(2005): 1635–8; J. Xu and J. Gordon, ‘Inaugural Article: Honor Thy
Symbionts,’ PNAS 100 (2003): 10452–9; V. Mai and J. Morris Jr., ‘Colonic
Bacterial Flora: Changing Understandings in the Molecular Age,’ Journal of
Nutrition 134 (2004): 459–64. ‘Probiotic’ drinks are based on the premise that
the bacteria in these drinks will introduce ‘good’ bacteria into the human
intestine, thereby ‘rebalancing’ the microflora. For a review of the lack of
evidence that probiotic drinks actually work, see G. Tannock, ‘A Special
Fondness for Lactobacilli,’ Applied Environmental Microbiology 70 (2004):
3189–94.
21 Vaclav Smil, The Earth’s Biosphere: Evolution, Dynamics, and Change.
22 John Urry, Sociology Beyond Societies: Mobilities for the Twenty-first Century.
23 Adam, in Michael Pollan, The Omnivore’s Dilemma.
24 Michael Pollan, The Omnivore’s Dilemma, 67.
25 Michael Pollan, The Omnivore’s Dilemma.
26 Rumenitis is good news for the bacillus Fusobacterium necrophorum, whose
presence characterizes this disease; enterotoxemia is good news for the
bacillus Clostridium perfringens, and coccidiosis is good news for the proto-
zoan (single-celled eukaryote) coccidian.
27 Zuk estimates that 75 percent of all new human emerging diseases are
spread from animals to humans (Marlene Zuk, Riddled With Life: Friendly
Worms, Ladybug Sex, and the Parasites That Make Us Who We Are).
28 Recall the footnoted discussion in Chapter 4 about Nietzsche’s contention
that true gifting involves forgetting. The only way, according to Nietzsche,
Notes 195
to truly gift is to bludgeon the gifter such that s/he doesn’t remember
giving, and to bludgeon the recipient so that s/he does not know who did
the gifting.
29 Michael Pollan, The Omnivore’s Dilemma, 10–11, 68, 84.
30 John Urry, Sociology Beyond Societies: Mobilities for the Twenty-first Century,
169.
31 Roszak in Roderick Nash, The Rights of Nature (Madison, WI: University of
Wisconsin Press, 1989), 13.
32 Mike Michael, Constructing Identities (London: Sage, 1996), 135; H. Batty
and T. Gray, ‘Environmental Rights and National Sovereignty,’ in National
Rights, International Obligations, eds. S. Caney, D. George and P. Jones
(Boulder, CO: Westview Press, 1996). I think this is to some degree what
Latour envisions will be the work of the ‘Parliament of Things’. He writes:
‘Let us again take up the two representations and the double doubt about
the faithfulness of the representatives, and we shall have defined the
Parliament of Things… Natures are present, but with their representatives,
scientists who speak in their name. Societies are present, but with the objects
that have been serving as their ballast from time immemorial… The imbrolios
and networks that had no place now have the whole place to themselves. They
are the ones that have to be represented; it is around them that the
Parliament of Things gathers henceforth’. See Bruno Latour, We Have
Never Been Modern, 144, my emphasis. In such a Parliament of Things,
the nonhuman would have responsibilities of action, of response, and of
ethics.
33 Cary Wolfe, Zoontologies: The Question of the Animal, 3.
34 J.F. Lyotard, The Differend: Phrases in Dispute, 28.
35 Derrida notes that ‘the Word, logos, does violence to the heterogeneous
multiplicity of the living world by reconstituting it under the sign of iden-
tity, the as such and in general – not “animals” but “the animal”, in Cary
Wolfe, Zoontologies: The Question of the Animal, 23.
36 Bauman in Cary Wolfe, Animal Rites: American Culture, the Discourse of
Species, and the Posthumanist Theory, xvii.
37 See Karalyn Kendall, ‘The Face of the Dog: Levinasian Ethics and Human/ Dog
Coevolution,’ in Queering the NonHuman, eds. Noreen Giffney and Myra Hird,
185–204. Of course, Bobby may not have wanted to relate to Levinas at all,
which makes the ethical encounter all that much more challenging. As Latour
writes, ‘It is not an easy task to transform the inarticulate mutterings of a mul-
titude of entities that do not necessarily want to make themselves under-
stood’. See Bruno Latour, Politics of Nature: How to Bring the Sciences into
Democracy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2004), 168.
38 Noting Daniel Dennett’s point that consciousness is not digital (i.e. it is not an
all or nothing entity), Wolfe argues that it is of little help in thinking through
the ethical differences between abusing a dog and abusing a scallop – ‘differ-
ences that would seem, to many people, to be the point, even if they are cer-
tainly not ethically the only point …’. See Cary Wolfe, Zoontologies: The
Question of the Animal, 42. Contrast this with Rosi Braidotti’s critique of deep
ecology, which pivots on a definitive separation between humans and
animals. She writes, ‘Deep ecology consequently displays the moral arrogance
that consists in granting to non-humans the same moral rights as to humans.’
See Rosi Braidotti, Transpositions: On Nomadic Ethics, 117.
196 Notes
197
198 Index