Raz, Legal Rights

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 24
At a glance
Powered by AI
The essay discusses the relationship between legal rights and moral rights, and proposes that moral rights should be the model for a general explanation of rights.

The author aims to show that his general account of rights, where having a right means that another is under a duty, applies to legal rights. He also defends analyzing rights from a moral perspective rather than a legal one.

The author distinguishes between legal rights, which can ground duties, and legally respected rights, where the law does not impose duties that violate the right.

.

J Tj ,, r

R3Cf
;qc;lJ

ETHICS IN THE
PUBLIC DOMAIN

Essays in the Morality


of Law and Politics

REVISED EDITION

JOSEPH RAZ

CLARENDON PRESS · OXFORD


12
Legal Rights

What are legal rights? How do they relate to moral rights? It is common for
philosophers to turn to the law for a model for their analysis of rights in
general. Several leading legal philosophers, such as W. N. Hohfeld and H.
L. A. Hart, 1 have proposed explanations of legal rights without establishing
whether they apply to non-legal rights as well. They have thus assumed that
the nature of legal rights can be established independently, that the success
of an account of legal rights does not depend on its applicability (possibly
somewhat modified) to other rights. Other philosophers like L. Becker, C.
Weiman, and R. Flatham/ make some account of legal rights, usually
Hohfeld's, the starting-point for their explanation of rights in general.
This mode of approach is not, and has never been, universal. ]. Feinberg
and R. M. Dworkin are but two prominent contemporary writers who base
their analysis of legal rights on an explanation of rights in generaP Elsewhere
I have proposed a general account of rights.4 Its gist is that to say of an
individual or a group that he or it has a right is to say that an aspect of their
well-being is a ground for holding another to be under a duty. My purpose
here is to show that this account applies to legal rights and to defend my
approach, which r�gards moral, rather than legal, rights as the model for a
general explanation of the concept. The essay does not attempt a classifi­
cation of legal rights. Nor does it offer an analysis of special kinds of rights.
Its sole concern is the general idea of a legal right.

First published in the Oxford journal ofLegal Studies, 4/1 (1984) . I am grateful to P. A. Bulloch
and to the Editor for helpful comments on the draft of this essay and to Wayne Sumner for a
very useful discussion of a much earlier draft.
1 See Hohfeld, Fundamental Legal Conceptions (New Haven, Conn . : Yale Univ. Press, 1919);
Hart, Definition and Theory in jurisprudence (Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 1953); 'Bentham
on Legal Rights' in .l\ . WT. B. Sirn.pson (ed.) J Oxford Essays in jurisprudence, 2nd ser. (Oxford:
.

Oxford Univ. Press, 1973).


2 See L. Becker, Property Rights (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1977); C. Wellman,
'A New Conception of Human Rights' ir1 E. Kamenka and A. E. S. Tay (eds.), Human Rights
(London: Arnold, 1979); R. Flatham, The Practice of Rights (Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Press,
1976). Cf. also T. D. Perry, 'A Paradigm of Philosophy: Hohfeld on Legal Rights', American
Philosophical Quarterly, 14 (1977). Those deontic logicians who consider rights at all tend to
base their work on Hohfeld's.
3 See ]. Feinberg's Rights, justice and the Bounds of Liberty (Princeton, NJ: Princeton Univ.
Press, 1980), essays 6-8. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (London: Duckworth, 1977).
4 'The Nature of Rights' , Mind (1984).
Legal Rights 255
I. AGAI N S T THE I N S TITUTI O NAL M O D E L

Not all writers who have been inspired by a legally based account of rights ,
like that of Hohfeld, have chosen to base on it their explanations of rights
in general by reason of its foundation in the law. Many of them simply saw
it as a promising starting-point. Since any complete theory of rights has to
apply both to legal and to non-legal rights , it may be thought unimportant
whether a writer's source of inspiration is reflection on the law or not. The
issue does, however, suggest a few points which deserve attention.
Some non-legal rights resemble legal rights more than others . Closest
to them are institutional rights. These are rights conferred by the rules of
associations such as political parties, trade unions, educational institutions,
and sports associations. They share with the law several of its defining
characteristics . They are normative systems regulated by adjudicative institu­
tions and by rules of recognition determining membership of the system. 5
Just as the law is a particular type of institutional normative system, so legal
rights are a particular type of institutional rights.
Some other rights are custom-based. They derive from rules, customs,
and conventions observed in a certain community. Institutional rights are
custom-based. But not all custom-based rights are institutional. Many social
rules and conventions do not belong to systems of rules identified by rules
6
of recognition and enforceable in courts or tribunals.
It is at least arguable that many rights are not custom-based. People who
believe in fundamental human rights usually believe that these rights do not
derive from social practices which recognize and implement them even
where such practices exist. They further believe that people have such
rights even in societies in which the rights are neither recognized nor
respected.
It is plausible to regard the law as the model for the analysis of institu­
tional systems generally. The reason is not its greater importance but its
greater self-conscious articulateness. Modem law is not just an institutional
normative system, it is also a bureaucratic system. Its institutions are manned,
for the most part, by professionals. Its proper functioning depends on full­
time judges, barristers, solicitors, and other legal officials , their professional
associations, law schools, and the like. Though legal systems have preceded
their bureaucratization, contemporary law relies heavily on bureaucratic
processes , many of which are designed, at least in part, to give conscious,
explicit, and complete articulation to the law. This makes it a particularly
clear instance of an institutional normative system.

5 See on institutional systems generally and on the law as a special kind of such systems,
my Tbe Authority of Law, essay 6.
6 This way of distinguishing customary from other rights is crude and unsatisfactory, but will
do for present purposes.
256 Between Law and Morality
This high degree of self-conscious articulation may also incline one to
regard legal rules and institutions as a paradigmatic example of all rules and
normative arrangements. And, therefore, to view legal rights as a basis for
the analysis of all rights. This tendency is, however, not without risks. The
danger is that it will lead to an account based on the specific institutional
features of legal rights and will distort our conception of rights in general.
One family of explanations which suffer from this pitfall is that compris­
ing accounts basing rights on normative powers to enforce duties or to
apply sanctions for disregarding them. Because the law is an institutional
system, it is concerned primarily with those rights and duties which it is
willing to enforce or following the violation of which it is willing to provide
remedies or sanctions. Let us examine the reasoning leading to this conclu­
sion. Being an institutional normative system means being a system consisting
of source-based rules which certain adjudicative bodies are bound by their
rules of recognition to recognize and apply. That is, institutional systems
consist of rules which are subject to adjudication before official bodies.
Such adjudication is normally undertaken to obtain remedies or secure
sanctions for violation of rights or for breach of duties, or to prevent such
behaviour. The only important exception in modem legal systems is litigation
to obtain a declaratory judgment. But even that is usually undertaken to
facilitate or make unnecessary action for enforcement, remedies, or sanc­
tions, or in circumstances where by convention it is respected as if it were
an ordinary enforcement or remedial action.7
Since litigation is almost invariably either for the enforcement of rights or
duties or for remedies or sanctions for disregarding them, it is tempting to
think that only rights and duties which can be litigated with a view to such
results can be legal rights and duties. This is a mistake. There are legal rights
and duties which cannot be enforced and violation of which does not give
rise to action for penalties or remedies. The most important class of such
exceptional legal rights and duties is certain rights and duties of or against
officials. Rights and duties of officials and rights against them regulate the
activities of courts and other legal officials, and are therefore subject to
adjudication. That is why they can meet the conditions for being legal rights
and duties. But they are not always themselves protected by action in the
courts. The law determines what appeals the highest Court of Appeal has
a right to hear, but if it decides to hear an appeal that it has no right to hear
then no one can take legal action to stop it. I do not claim that the law must
contain unprotected rights and duties, merely that all legal systems in fact
contain them. They are, however, clearly exceptional and in a sense para­
sitical on rights and duties which are enforceable or which do give rise,
when disregarded, to actions for remedies or for sanctions. Therefore, their

7 AB is the case in action against the Crown in Britain.


Legal Rights 257
existence does not disprove the statement that the law is primarily con­
cerned with rights and duties which it is willing to enforce, or for the
violation of which it is willing to provide remedies or sanctions .
Moreover, the law typically, though not invariably, endows right-holders
with power to take legal action to enforce their rights or obtain redress for
their violations. This is normally a very sound policy. There are strong
reasons for limiting access to court. If anyone could go to court to complain
of the violation of any right regardless of whose right it was , the result
would be that individuals would often face action alleging that they had
transgressed someone's rights when the action was frivolous or malicious or
based on no evidence . Right-holders are those most directly affected. They
have in most cases the motivation to protect their rights and good access to
available evidence. It is far better to give them access to the court and deny
it to all others . We all know the flaws in any argument that the initiative for
all legal actions to protect rights should rest exclusively with the right­
holder. Our present interest is not, however, with these considerations of
legal policy, but with their unfortunate impact on certain theories of rights.
Some writers on legal rights, seeing that most legal rights are protected
by remedies, sanctions, and enforcement measures and that right-holders
normally have legal power to invoke such protective measures, have con­
cluded that to have a legal right (or at least to have one kind of legal right)
is to have control over its corresponding duty, i . e . to have legal powers to
take protective legal action. Other writers , who found their accounts of
rights generally on some such explanation of (one kind of) legal rights, have
concluded that all (or one kind of) rights are no more than the possession
of a normative power to control duties corresponding to the right. They
have , therefore , looked for non-legal analogues of legal remedies and
sanctions and of legal rules of locus standi.
The results were only too often a distorted view of morality. In the search
for analogues of legal sanctions and remedies, expressions of views about
the rightness or wrongness of actions were often interpreted as sanctions.
People's judgments that they had behaved badly were often regarded as
internal sanctions. Pangs of conscience were compared with jail sentences .8
Of course, people sometimes punish themselves or each other for wrong­
doing. Of course, we all recognize obligations to compensate the victims of
our wrongdoings. But punishment and demands for compensation are based
on and justified by judgments about wrongdoings. Neither the formation of
such judgments nor their natural expression (be it through their open avowal,
through feelings of shame or rage or whichever emotion is appropriate to
one's belief, or through the natural expression of such feelings in word or

8 See on these points P. M. S. Hacker's important article 'Sanction Theories of Duty' in


A. W. B. Simpson (ed.), Oxford Essays in jurisprudence (Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 1973).
258 Between Law and Morality
action) should be confused with punishment. Punishment is a deliberate act
intended to hurt because of a (believed) wrongdoing by the punished (or,
in the case of collective punishment, by one of the punished). It is distinct
both from the belief on which it is based and from its natural expression in
words or deeds.9
Such distortions cannot be dismissed as aberrations which do not under­
mine credence in an account of (all or some kinds of) rights as the posses­
sion of a power to control a duty. Without these aberrations this account
loses its appeal. Any sound morality recognizes rights whose purpose is not
to protect economic interests, rights whose violation does not cause harm
nor gives rise to a right to punish or to obtain compensation. Many people
believe in a right not to be deceived by members of one's family, a right not
to be insulted or treated with contempt by anyone, and many other rights
which derive from recognition of a person's dignity rather than a need to
spare his feelings or his pocket. But their belief is not merely false but
incoherent if rights consist in controlling another's duty by being able to
punish its violation or demand compensation.
Some philosophers draw an analogy between legal locus standi rules and
moral rules concerning the appropriateness of complaints about wrong­
doings. While some similarity exists, it cannot be used to provide an account
of rights as power to control duties without leading to exaggeration and
distortion. Many conventions about the propriety of poking one's nose in
other people's affairs are mere matters of etiquette or of good manners, and
cannot affect underlying moral rights. Some moralities, while recognizing
rights, impose no moral restrictions on the right to punish their violation or
to demand that compensation be given to the victims. Everyone is morally
entitled, or even required, to do so, if his action is likely to be helpful.
Where moral restrictions on the right to complain exist, they often fail to
point to the right-holder. According to certain moral theories children are
not allowed to complain of violations of (some of) their rights. Further­
more , · such restrictions may exist even where no right is violated. For
example, breach of certain religious duties or of duties to the public at large
is often not viewed as a violation of any right, and yet only the head of the
family or the priest may be allowed to punish or demand compensatory
action.

II . L E G A L J U S T I F I C AT I O N S

I have dwelt on the shortcomings of one family of explanations of rights to


illustrate the dangers in taking legal rights as the model for an explanation

9 Though, of course, people can, and occasionally do, punish each other by expressing
views in order to hurt, on the ground that the wrongdoer deserves such treatment.
Legal Rights 25 9
of rights in general, the danger of basing one's account on the institutional
features of the law which are absent in non-institutional rights . My proposed
account of rights generally as grounds for holding others to be subject to
duties is certainly free of this danger. It identifies rights by their role in
practical reasoning. They indicate intermediate conclusions between state­
ments of the right-holder's interests and another's duty. To say that a person
has a right is to say that an interest of his is sufficient ground for holding
another to be subject to a duty, i.e. a duty to take some action which will
serve that interest, or a duty the very existence of which serves such inter­
est. One justifies a statement that a person has a right by pointing to an
interest of his and to reasons why it is to be taken seriously.10 One uses the
statement that a right exists to derive (often with the aid of other premisses)
conclusions about the duties of other people towards the right-holder. 11
Such an account of rights certainly does not rely on any institutional
features of law. When coming to use it to explain legal rights, one encounters
the opposite problem. The law, one may say, like other institutional systems,
is primarily concerned with aspects of individual behaviour which can be
adjudicated in courts and tribunals . It is , consequently, a system of rules for
the guidance of behaviour. It is not a system of practical reasoning, but of
operative, action-guiding rules. An explanation of rights in terms of their
role in practical reasoning is, therefore, incapable of explaining legal rights.
To prepare the ground for applying my general account of rights to legal
rights it is, therefore, important to consider briefly the extent to which the
law, as well as other institutional normative systems, are systems of practical
reasoning. To regard them as such is compatible with thinking of them as
normative systems, i . e . as systems of rules. All that is involved is the view
that legal rules are sometimes hierarchically nested in justificatory struc­
tures. That the law is a system of practical reasoning means no more than
that it follows from this fact that belief in the normative force of some of the
legal rules commits one to belief in the normative force of some of the
others.
To say of the law that it is a system of practical reasoning is, then, to
claim that it consists of rules some of which justify some of the others. It is
a statement of the logical properties of the law. It is not a psychological or
sociological statement about people's beliefs about the law or their attitude
to it. Nor is it a moral or other value judgment about the value or merit of
the law.
Lawyers commonly conceive of the law as made of sets of nested rules

10 One cannot specify in the abstract what importance those reasons must assign to the
interest except circularly, by saying 'sufficient to justify the conclusion that that person has a
right'. One can and should, of course, develop a theory of which interests are protected by
rights and when.
11 A duty is towards a certain person if and only if it is derived from his right.
260 Between Law and Morality
linked by justificatory chains. One rule in a set justifies one or more of the
others which in tum justify a few of the rest, and so on. A rule enacted by
a Minister of the Crown derives its legal force from an Act of Parliament.
Anyone who believes that the Act of Parliament is normatively binding12 is
committed to believe that so is the ministerial rule, since that conclusion is
entailed by his premiss (together with certain true factual premisses). This
illustrates the fact that the law is a structure of authority. The authority of
some of its rules is vindicated by the fact that they were created in modes
authorized by other of its rules.
There is no reason to think that each legal system is a pyramid of author­
ity leading to one apex, to one supreme legal rule which authorizes all the
others. I am merely pointing to the familiar fact that some rules of law
authorize the creation of some others. Many legal rules can be grouped
by their common origin. In Britain statutory law, for example, derives its
authority from the authority of Parliament to make law, whereas case law
derives its authority from the power of the higher courts to do the same.
Borrowing Hart's terminology, 13 we can call the type of justificatory nexus
we have considered so far 'content-independent justification'. In our example
it was assumed that the ministerial regulation is normatively binding
regardless of its content, because it was issued by a person who had author­
ity to do so. 14 But some legal rules provide content-dependent justification
for some others.
Consider the relation between the following three (hypothetical) legal rules:
1 . Every person has a right to freedom of expression.
2. No person shall be subject to a duty restraining the publication of a
sincerely held opinion or of true information without his consent,
unless such restriction is necessary for reasons of security of state or
of the maintenance of essential public services.
3. Publication of details of the working of an essential public service
such as the water supply cannot be prohibited by law, even if posses­
sion of such information can assist anyone who may wish to disrupt
such service, unless there is a clear and immediate danger that it may
be used for such a purpose.
I should emphasize that it is not my claim that these rules either are or
should be law. They are merely useful since they resemble several actual

12 I use the expression 'normatively binding' where others may have used 'morally binding'.
Though on occasion I will refer to moral force or to moral justifications, 'moral' is often
used in a narrower sense in which 'moral' considerations are only one kind of normative
consideration.
13 H. L. A. Hart, 'Moral and Legal Obligations', in A. I. Melden (ed.), Essays in Moral Philo­
sophy (Seattle: University of Washington Press 1958), and Essays on Bentham (Oxford: Oxford
Univ. Press, 1982), 254.
14 Though his authority may be, and usually is, limited to rules which meet certain conditions.
Legal Rights 261
rules and they illustrate typical justificatory relations between rules. Each of
these rules justifies the ones that follow it. They therefore form a justifica­
tory hierarchy. The first rule is the most general. It justifies not only the
other two but many more. For example, it justifies the rules:

4. There is no legal duty protecting the reputation of the dead.


5. Journalists have a right not to disclose the sources of their information
except when this is necessary to secure prosecution and conviction for
an offence for which the maximum penalty is five years or more.

Rule 2 justifies 3 but not 4 or 5. It is, therefore, lower in the justificatory


hierarchy than I but higher than 3. The justificatory structures these rules
exemplify are content-dependent. In this they differ from structures of
authority which are content-independent justificatory structures. But other­
wise they greatly resemble them. Both determine partial ordering among
certain legal rules and yet neither is a connected relation.
They can be said to divide the law into (possibly overlapping) groups of
rules in each of which one (or several in combination) provide a justifica­
tion for the rest. When the justification is content-independent the groups
are identified by their common, direct or indirect, source. When the justi­
fication is content-dependent the groups it creates are based on doctrinal
unity. They are all articulations and implementations of one or more core
doctrines.
Let me try and explain the justificatory relation I have been referring to
more precisely. All legal statements can be expressed by 'It is the law that
P' sentences where 'P' is replaced by a (non-legal) sentence. Let us define
a relation of legal justification as follows. The statement 'It is the law that
P' legally justifies the statement 'It is the law that R' just in case 'It is the law
that P' is true and there is a set of true statements (legal or non-legal) <Q>,
such that <Q> and it is the law that P state a complete reason to believe that
R (and <Q> by itself does not state such a reason).
I shall refer to the embedded statement P of a legal statement 'It is the law
that P' as its content. The content of a legal statement may be true even if
the legal statement itself is false and vice versa. It is true that one ought to
keep one's promises but false that it is the law that one ought to do so. It
is (in many legal systems) true that it is the law that one may kill one's pets
at will but it is false that one may do so. The sentence-forming expression
'it is the law that . . . ' is not a truth functional operator. To establish the truth
of a legal statement one has to establish not that its content is true but that
it has legal status, that it has the force of law. Justifying a legal statement is
not to be confused with proving or establishing its truth. It concerns the
truth of its content. Since in normal discourse part of a reason, i.e. an
incomplete reason, is a reason, a legal statement justifies another legal
statement if it states a reason to believe in the truth of its content. But while
262 Between Law and Morality
the justifying statement provides a reason for believing in the truth of the
content of the justified one, it falls short of proving its truth. The reason it
provides need not be a conclusive reason. It may rely on inductive or on
practical (deontic) inferences both of which are defeasible.
We can define a conclusive justification as follows . One legal statement,
it is the law that P, conclusively justifies a second legal statement, it is the
law that R, if there is a set of true premisses <Q> which does not entail R
but such that <Q> and 'it is the law that P' entails 'R' . Finally a justification
should be distinguished from a complete justification. A complete justifica­
tion of a legal statement is the set of all the non-redundant premisses which
constitute a complete reason to believe in the content of the justified
statement.
As our examples illustrate, the justificatiory relation between legal rules15
is not that of a complete justification. The doctrine of free speech stated in
rule 1 is not a complete reason for believing in the content of rule 2, nor
is 2 itself a complete reason for believing in the content of 3. The route from
1 to 2 goes through additional premisses. Some elaborate and explain 1 , its
scope and its point. They may be premisses which explain what is an act
of expression and what counts as a restriction on its freedom. They also
include explanations of why it matters. They will lead to the conclusion
(which 1 by itself does · not yield) that suppression of sincerely held opinion
is worse than the suppression of the publication of opinions not held by the
speaker, or that 1 protects only unconsented-to restrictions on publication
(or at least that consent to a restriction on publication makes it less objec­
tionable) . Beside these premisses, rules such as 2 and 3 reflect the force of
other doctrines which conflict with 1 , doctrines such as:
6. The public interest in the maintenance of essential services warrants
measures necessary to guarantee their continued operation.
Rules2 and 3 reflect the legal resolution of conflicting legal doctrines . They
do not just apply their general justifying doctrines such as 1 . They also
indicate their limits and allow for certain exceptions to them.
When we refer to one rule as justifying another, we rarely have a com­
plete justification in mind. Nor do we always assume the justification to be
successful. I can reject the suggestion that 1 justifies 2 if I believe that the
additional premisses v..rhich are required to entail the contents of 2 are false .
I may then say that it i s a mistake, albeit a common one, to think that 1
justifies 2. Here 'justifies' means successfully justifies. But in another key I
can say that the rule that the suitability of a person to have custody of his
child depends entirely on the interest of the child is the justification of the
legal practice of denying custody to homosexuals, without regarding the

15 One legal rule justifies another in case the statement of the one justifies the statement of
the other.
Legal Rights 263
justification as successful. Here 'justification' means what is taken by the
courts, or the law, or by people generally, to justify. In what follows this
will be the sense in which 'justifies' will normally be used.

III . L E GAL JUSTIFI CATI O N AND VALI D ITY

A legal system can b e regarded a s a system of practical reasoning, for many


of its rules are nested in justificatory structures. Rules are so nested if, of any
two of them, one legally justifies the other. The relation of legal justification
between legal rules is just an instance of a wider relation of legal justifica­
tion between legal statements. It holds between 'it is the law that P' and 'it
'
is the law that q if and only if 'it is the law that p' is true and there is a set
of true statements <Q> such that <Q> and 'it is the law that p' are a com­
plete reason to believe that q. In other words, one legal statement justifies
a second legal statement just in case it is a reason to believe in the content
embedded in the second.
It should be obvious why the justificatory relation is said to exist between
legal statements if the justifying legal statement is a reason for accepting the
content of the justified one. A rule should have the force of law only if its
content is successfully justified-whether by another legal rule (i. e . by a
legal justification) or not is immaterial. This necessary condition can be
strengthened into a sufficient condition as follows : if p is justified and if the
matter it deals with should be regulated by law, then it should be the case
that it is the law that p . 1 6 The general justificatory relation helps in the evalu­
ation of the merit of the law. Our specific interest here is in legal justification
only, i.e. those justifications based on legal premisses. We are concerned
only with the way one legal rule justifies another.
Where the justification starts from non-legal premisses, it is clear that it
cannot establish the truth of a legal statement or the validity of a legal rule.
At best, it is part of an argument for its desirability. But where a successful
legal justification is concerned, does it not establish the validity of a legal
rule by showing that its content is entailed by another legal rule and other
true premisses? Is not this precisely the way that the validity of delegated
legislation is established? Consider 7 and 7a :
7. Everyone has a legal right to his good name (i. e . it is the law that
everyone has a right to his good name) .
7 a. Jimmy has a legal right to his good name.

Is not the fact that 7 a is legally justified by 7 the only way in which its truth
can be established?
16 This of course does not entail that it is now best to change the law to that effect. Though
it is best that p has the force of law, it may be wrong to enact it because of the consequences
of the very act of introducing the change.
264 Between Law and Morality
This crucial and difficult problem has not received as much explicit atten­
tion as it deserves. I do not know of anyone who denies that a successful
legal justification does, under certain conditions, establish the truth of the
justified legal statements. Kelsen came close to doing this. He denied that
content-dependent justification can ever establish the truth of the justified
legal statement. 17 He would have denied that the truth of 7a can be learnt
from that of 7. His reasons for this view, if consistently pursued, would,
however, lead to the conclusion that content-independent justifications
also fail to establish the truth of the justified statement. That means that the
validity of delegated legislation cannot be established by reference to the
authorizing statutes but depends on judicial declarations of their validity.
But this undermines the very emphasis on the structure of authority which
is the backbone of Kelsen's theory of law. It also raises questions about
the authority of the courts to make decisions validating delegated legisla­
tion. That authority itself rarely rests on the historically-first constitution.
It depends on the very chain of reasoning that Kelsen is committed to
reject.
I am not sure whether anyone has advocated the opposite view: that all
successful legal justifications establish the truth of the justified statement. It
is possible that this is R. M. Dworkin's view. My own view is determined by
the Sources Thesis. It says that the existence and contents of the law can be
determined without resorting to any moral argument. In its widest and
strongest interpretation, the thesis applies not merely to the existence and
content of all legal rules but, more generally, to the truth and content of all
legal statements. It follows that a successful legal justification can establish
the truth of the justified legal statement only if it does not resort to moral
arguments (i.e. if no moral premisses are among the additional premisses
<Q> which form part of the complete justification concemed). 18 Subject to
that condition, it is true that a successful legal justification establishes the
truth of the justified statement.
Therefore, content-independent justification which does not involve moral
premisses does indeed establish the validity of the delegated legal rules.
Similarly, the truth of 7a can be established by reference to 7. On the other
hand, while 1 justifies 2 it cannot establish its legal validity. If 2 is valid law,
it is so in virtue of courts' decisions which have adopted it and which have
the force of precedent, or in virtue of being incorporated into a statute. It
cannot be regarded as valid law just on account of being successfully
justified by 1 .
A successful justificatory relation between one legal statement and an­
other is of great legal significance even when it does not by itself establish
17 See H. Kelsen, 'Law and Logic' , in Essays in Legal and Moral Philosophy (Dordrecht: Reidel,
1973).
18 See The Authority of Law, ch. 3; Tbe Concept of a Legal System, 2nd edn., 210-16.
Legal Rights 265
the truth of the justified statement. 19 If the justified statement is not a true
statement of law, the justification provides a reason for changing the law so
as to make the justified statement true. As has already been noted, it is not
necessarily a conclusive reason. Though the change is shown by the justi­
fication to be desirable, its introduction may have undesirable aspects or
consequences which outweigh the reason for it. If, on the other hand, the
justified legal statement is already the law, then the justification shows that
it is a morally valid law. A morally valid law may not be a good law if its
validity derives from an authority-based, content-independent justification.
The moral validity of a rule means that it has the moral force that it purports
to have. If a rule imposing a certain duty on its subjects is morally valid,
then its subjects have the duty it imposes on them. It does not follow that
it is best that they should have it. They may have it because of the authority
of the person who made the rule, but he may have made a mistake in
making the rule, which should be rectified by changing it.
A content-dependent successful legal justification of an existing legal rule
does establish not merely that it is morally valid but also that it is good that
it exists. It is therefore a reason against changing it, but once more this is
not necessarily a conclusive reason. The very introduction of a change,
even one substituting a less satisfactory rule for the existing one, may have
aspects and consequences which make it desirable and which may out­
weigh the reasons against it.
We now have a reasonably complete picture of the sense in which law
is a system of practical reasoning. First, some legal rules justify some others.
In this they illuminate their point and purpose. The former are invaluable
guides to the interpretation of the latter, and they help decide what weight
to give the latter when these conflict with others . Secondly, legal rules
constitute legal reasons for developing the law in certain ways . The im­
portance of the fact that they are legal reasons for developing the law is that
they are reasons on which courts are required to act, given the appropriate
opportunity. Elsewhere I have likened them to directed administrative
powers.2° Consider a case in which an administrative authority is given
the power to grant certain privileges and rights (say, grant planning per­
mission) and directed to do so if certain conditions are met (e.g. the develop­
ment proposed preserves the character of the neighbourhood, meets the
required safety standards, and will not significantly increase the traffic in the
area) . The authority is required by law to use its powers as directed. The fact

19 The following remarks assume that the justification proceeds from a morally justified legal
rule. (That is, they represent the perspective of a person who is willing to make the justifying
legal statement in a committed way. I am using the distinction between committed and
detached legal statements explained in Tbe Authority of Law, essay 8.) This is normally the
point of view of the courts; hence its importance to legal analysis.
20 See Ch. 10 above.
266 Between Law and Morality
that one legal statement successfully justifies another which does not yet
have the force of law is a reason for courts, which have the power to do
so, to give it legal effect. It makes their power to change and develop the
law into a directed power.

IV . L E G A L R I G H T S A N D L E G A L J U S T I F I CATI O N S

If rights are protected interests, in that a person has a right if and only if an
interest of his is a sufficient ground for holding another to be subject to a
duty, then legal rights are legally protected interests. Such an account gives
'rights' the same sense in legal as in non-legal contexts. It presupposes that
the law is (at least in part) a system of practical reasoning. The previous two
sections explained the sense in which this is so. How do their conclusions
help to clarify the nature of legal rights?
An explanation of legal rights has to include two parts. It has to explain
how it is possible to come to have legal rights and it has to explain what
can be the legal consequences of having a right. People can come to have
legal rights in the same ways in which they can come to have duties,
powers, liabilities, or any other legal condition. Legal right-statements are
either pure or applied. A legal right-statement is pure if its truth can be
established by reference to the existence of certain laws alone. Other legal
right-statements are applied statements . Their truth can only be established
by facts which include facts other than the existence of law. It should be
remembered that both kinds of legal right-statement are subject to the con­
dition imposed by the Sources Thesis, namely that their truth can be estab­
lished without using moral argument.
Consider the following examples:
8. Everyone has a right t o damages against anyone who defames him
without lawful excuse.
8a. Jim has a right to damages against anyone who defames him with­
out lawful excuse.
9. Jim has a right to £1 , 500 defamation damages against Smith.
9a. Smith has a duty to pay Jim £1 , 500.
10. Children have a right to maintenance against their parents.
lOa. jill has a right to maintenance against her n1ott�er.
1 1 . Jill has a right that her mother pay for her piano lessons.
I l a. Jill's mother has a duty to pay for her piano lessons.
Of these, 8 and 10 are pure legal right-statements. So is 7 . 7 justifies 8. It
is wrong, however, to think that 8 is applied. Its legal force is due to the
legal sources, precedents, and statutes which establish it in law. Its justifi­
cation by 7 presupposes moral arguments and is therefore incapable of
establishing its legal force. Common lawyers are more likely to say that 7
Legal Rights 267
is inferred from 8. The common law is preoccupied with providing remedial
rights. But the reasoning used by the courts shows clearly that they regard
the remedies as justified by a right to reputation. The choice of remedies
and their adequacy is assessed (in part) by their adequacy in protecting that
right. Given the discussion of the previous section, there is no surprise in
one rule which creates a right justifying another such rule , which derives its
legal force not from that justification but from independent legal sources.
Nor is there any surprise that 7 a, 8a, and lOa, which are justified respec­
tively by the rules 7, 8, and 10 without recourse to any moral argument,
derive their very legal force from that justification, and are applied legal
statements.
The crucial question is how one can tell that an enactment or a precedent
establishes a right. We normally think that the question arises only if the
language adopted in legislation or in a judicial decision is obscure or am­
biguous. Otherwise it all depends on the language of the enacted rule. But
though, where the language is plain, the question may be easy to answer,
it still requires an answer. Why do we say that the rule made is the one
expressed by the language of the enactment understood in its ordinary
meaning, or in the meaning its language has, according to legal rules and
conventions? The reason lies, crudely speaking, in the fact that where a law
is laid down by authority its meaning is dictated by the intentions of that
authority. If it were not so, then there would have been little reason to
1
ascribe law-making power to that authority. 2 This lesson is particularly
important when the issue is, not what precisely is the duty or the right that
the law creates, but does the rule in question impose a duty or does it
merely set a condition for one's ability to achieve certain consequences?
Does it grant a power or a right? And suchlike doubts about the very type
of legal condition the law creates.
Hart has shown that one cannot tell the difference between a duty breach
of which incurs, say, a fine , and an activity one is free to undertake but has
to pay a tax if one does , except by reference to the intentions of the law,
i . e . of the legal institutions which have created and which enforce the rule. 22
In a similar vein I have argued that one cannot identify a legal power with
the ability to perform an act which has legal consequences. This would
yield the paradoxical consequence that people have legal power to break
the law. (Do we need legal powers for that?) A legal power can only be
identified by the reasons which led the law (i. e . the institutions which make
and sustain it) to attach those legal consequences to the act. The act is an
exercise of a legal power only if the reason for attributing to it the legal

21 Needless to say, this brief answer is a rough one. Among many complications let me

mention that this answer cannot be the whole story regarding old laws. But the details of a
doctrine of interpretation need not concern us here.
22 H. L. A. Hart, 'Kelsen Visited', UCLA Law Review, 10 (1963).
268 Between Law and Morality
. consequences it has is that it is held desirable to enable people to perform
that act as a means to achieve those consequences, if they so wish. 23
Similarly, a law creates a right if it is based on and expresses the view that
someone has an interest which is sufficient ground for holding another to
be subject to a duty. One way of creating a right is therefore by the use of
the term 'right' . (For example: 'An employer shall have the right to . . . ' .) This
is an obvious way for the law to confer rights, for given that 'a right' means
that an interest is sufficient for holding another to be subject to a duty, its
use is a natural way to express that thought. But, as Bentham pointed out
long ago, this is neither the only nor the most common way in which the
law creates rights. It may do so by the use of specific technical terms such
as 'a holding' or 'a share'. Or it may do so by imposing duties with the inten­
tion to protect someone's interest, thus endowing him with a legal right.
An individual has a right, if an interest of his is sufficient, to hold another
to be subject to a duty. His right is a legal right if it is recognized by law,
that is, if the law holds his interest to be sufficient ground to hold another
to be subject to a duty. This is the core of the account here proposed. It
explains why I said above that a rule is identified as a right-conferring one
by the reasons for its adoption. To be a rule conferring a right it has to be
motivated by a belief in the fact that someone's (the right-holder's) interest
should be protected by the imposition of duties on others.
The other aspect of the explanation of legal rights follows naturally from
the core idea. If a legal rule creates a legal right, its consequences are that
others have duties to protect an interest of the right holder. Such duties are
the consequences of a right in the sense that it legally justifies those duties.
This legal justification can have either of the two results we distinguished
in the previous section. If the justification does not involve any resort to
moral argument, the justification establishes the justified duty as a legal duty.
In this way, if A has a right to £5 against B, then B has a duty to give £5
to A. But very commonly the right can justify the duty only in conjunction
with other moral premisses. In this case the legal right is insufficient to
endow the duty with legal force . But the legal right is a reason for giving
that duty legal force, for making it into a legal duty.
Consider statements 9, 9a, 1 1 , and l l a above . 9a is justified by 9 and l l a
is justified by 1 1 without resort to moral argument. But while both 9 and 9a
are justified by 8, and 1 1 and l l a are justified by 10, these justifications do
involve moral judgments about the adequacy of certain payments. There­
fore the rights and duties specified in 9, 9a, 1 1 , and 1 1 a are not legally binding
until there is a decision in the court, or an agreement between the parties
to that effect. But 8 and 10 provide powerful reasons for reaching such
agreements and for rendering these judicial decisions.

23 Cf. Practical Reason and Nonns, s. 8, and Tbe Authority of Law, 17-18.
Legal Rights 269
An important part of our understanding of legal rights consists in grasping
their logical consequences. These are, as we have just seen, that they legally
justify other rights and duties. Some of these derive legal force from this
justification. Others will be legal rights and duties established by independ­
ent legal sources. Others still are not yet legally binding. These last conse­
quences of legal rights deserve special attention, since they show legal
rights to constitute legal reasons for giving the justified rights and duties
legal force. They establish the dynamic aspect of rights . Legal rights can be
legal reasons for legal change. They are grounds for developing the law in
certain directions. Because of their dynamic aspect legal rights cannot be
reduced, as has often been suggested, to the legal duties which they justify.
To do so is to overlook their role as reasons for changing and developing
the law.24

V. L E G A L R I G H T S A N D M O RA L P R I N C I P L E S

The core account of legal rights presented above requires further explanation
and refinement. These can best be supplied by examining a few of the
objections which are liable to be raised to it. This section explores two groups
of objections concerned with the relations between law and morality.

Legal Rights Need Not Be Recognized Moral Rights

The Objection. According to the account proposed above, every legal right
is a legally recognized pre-existing moral right. This assumes a stronger
connection between law and morality than in fact exists. It also miscon­
strues the nature of this connection. There are two reasons why a legal right
may not be the giving of legal force to a pre-existing moral right. First, the
law may quite deliberately create a right where none existed. There was no
right to initiate the liquidation of a company or to obtain planning permis­
sion prior to their creation by law. Secondly, while intending to recognize
a pre-existing right the law may fail to do so. It may detect an interest which
deserves protection where none exists. Alternatively, the interest may exist
but may be insufficient to be the ground of a duty on another. Where a
legal right does not recognize a pre-existing moral right, it may yet create
a moral right based not on the interest of the right-holder but on the reasons
we have or may have to obey that law. On the other hand, where such
reasons are absent or insufficient no moral right is created by the law, but
it does create a legal right, one with no moral force.
The Reply. To begin to respond to this complex objection it is useful to

24 I have discussed this point in The Concept of a Legal System, 225-7.


270 Between Law and Morality
remind ourselves of the different kinds of legal discourse. There is the
sociological description of social institutions and of people's attitudes and
beliefs which H. L. A. Hart called discourse from the external point of view.
In this way we talk of the beliefs and actions of courts and legislators.
Occasionally sentences such as 'x has a right to y' are used in such discourse
to state that legal institutions hold x to have a right to y.
Much more common is the use of such right-sentences to make statements
which Hart described as internal, or statements made from the internal
point of view, and which I called committed statements.25 Committed right­
statements state that the right-holders do have those rights, that they are, if
you like, moral rights or rights that morality recognizes as valid. (One should
remember that in this essay 'morality' is used very widely to include binding
normative considerations of any kind.) The important point is that a com­
mitted statement that someone has a legal right simply means that that
person has a right which is recognized in law, i.e. by the legal institutions.
The elucidation offered above explained 'legal rights' as used in commit­
ted statements, for they are the central type of legal discourse. First, not
only is it the type of discourse most commonly employed in discourse con­
cerning the law in countries in which the population is not estranged from
the government, but it is also the normal mode of discourse in the sense
that the law claims normative force and validity to itself. It is treated as it
requires to be treated only by people who recognize its normative force and
are therefore normally talking of it in committed discourse. Second, in every
legal system, the officials manning its legal institutions have the internal
point of view and are normally . using committed statements to describe the
law.
Finally, the non-committed modes of discourse are parasitical on the
committed discourse. This is evident in the case of external statements. It
is also true of the third common type of legal discourse, which I call
'detached discourse' . A statement is a detached normative statement if it
describes a normative situation as seen from a committed point of view
without being committed to it. A person who asserts the existence of legal
rights in a detached way is not committed to the moral or normative validity
of those rights. His statement is true if it would have been true had the law
moral or normative force. Saying that there can be legal rights which have
no moral force, or even such that are immoral, is saying that one can make
true detached statements about legal rights while morally condemning them
and being right to do so.
There is another point raised by the objection which is still to be met.
While some legal rights are legally recognized moral rights (for example,

25 See H. L. A. Hart, Tbe Concept of Law (Oxford: Oxford Univ. Press, 1 961), 55-6, 86-8;
J. Raz, Tbe Authority of Law, 140-3, 1 53-7.
Legal Rights 271
one's right to a good name) other legal rights are legally created moral
rights. They are moral rights one has because the law has granted them. The
account of legal rights which I have offered fails to explain these cases.
There are three types of case where a legal right can be thought of as
a legally created moral right. My explanation of legal rights adequately
accounts for two of them. It requires a certain natural extension to apply to
the third.
First is the case where the law changes a person's interests. Thereby
it changes his moral rights, which it then proceeds to recognize. Strictly
speaking, this is not a case where the law creates the moral right; it merely
creates the interest which is the foundation of the right. Consider the
following example. Until planning restrictions were introduced, everyone
was free to build on his land as he liked. Then the law prohibited building
without planning permission, and appointed planning authorities with powers
to grant such permission. This created for some people an interest they did
not have before, i.e. to obtain planning permission. Given general moral
principles and the circumstances of those people, it is probable that some
of them had a (moral) right to be given planning permission. In some
countries the law recognizes those rights by giving a legal right to planning
permission when certain conditions obtain, and where these conditions are
those which morally entitle the applicants to the permission. It may look as
if the law creates a moral right to planning permissions, for the whole of
planning law is the law's creation. But upon inspection we can see that the
law creates an interest which is the basis of a moral right which is in turn
recognized by the law. This combination is in fact very common in tech­
nical legal areas such as company law or licensing law.
Second, the possession of some rights depends on the consent or author­
ity of others. I have a right to be on your premises if you consent to my
being there. In such cases the right is there to protect some interest of the
right-holder. But that interest is sufficient to justify holding another subject
to a duty only if the condition is met. My interest in being on your premises
if I wish is insufficient by itself to establish a duty on you to let me do so
unless you consent to my being there. Your consent removes certain objec­
tions to holding you bound to respect my interest, and it thus enables the
interest to found a right.
Similarly, there are many cases where a moral right exists only if it is
recognized by authoritative legal institutions . Sometimes they even have a
duty to give their recognition to the right in order to bring it into existence
(both as a moral and as a legal right), just as sometimes you ought to
consent to my being on your premises, even though I do not have a right
to be there unless you consent. In all cases where the consent of a legal
authority is a moral condition for the existence of a moral right, a legal right
is a legally recognized moral right. The legal recognition is self-referential:
272 Between Law and Morality
it recognizes that once it (i.e. the legal recognition) is given, a moral right
comes into force.
The third type of case involves an extension of the core account. It
concerns legal rights which, though they purport to be recognized rights,
fail to be so, and yet they create a morally recognized legal right. Suppose
that in a certain country Parliament enacts a legal right to use contracep­
tives. Some people believe that there is no moral right to use contraceptives,
not even a moral right conditional on legal recognition. They recognize, of
course, that Parliament in granting this legal right assumes otherwise. But
they do not agree. Yet they think that Parliament's authority carries such
moral force as to entail that once the legal right is granted people are
morally bound to respect it and not to stop others from using contra­
ceptives. On my account, strictly speaking this is not a case of a moral right.
One's moral duty not to prevent the use of contraceptives which is the
consequence of the law is not based on the interest of the right-holder, but
on respect for the authority of Parliament. But since this is respect for
Parliament's mistake about moral rights, and since its moral consequences
are to give individuals all they would have had, had they a right to contra­
ceptives, it is a natural extension of the concept to regard such legislation
as conferring a (legal) right. (Though of course it is, in the eyes of the anti­
contraceptionists, a right to do wrong, and therefore one which should not
be exercised.Y6

!fRights are Subject to the Sources Thesis, Then in Many Areas


There Are No Legally justified Rights

The Objection. Legal rights have two kinds of legal implication. They justify
other existing legal rights and duties, and they are legal reasons for develop­
ing the law by creating further rights and duties where doing so is desirable
in order to protect the interests on which the justifying rights are based. The
second objection concerns the first implication-the role of legal rights in
providing legal justification for other existing legal rights and duties. The
objection arises out of the claim that, in accordance with the Sources Thesis,
all rights and duties can be identified without resort to any moral argument.
Legally justified legal rights are legally valid either because they are suc­
cessfully legally justified without recourse to moral argument or because
they have been directly enacted or acquired the force of precedent. Let us
take the first case first. Can a right ever derive legal validity from the fact
that it is successfully justified by another legal right? The objection is that
this cannot happen in a way consistent with the Sources Thesis for the

26 These objections are suggestive rather than conclusive. For an excellent detailed discus­
sion of the issue see J. Waldron, 'A Right to Do Wrong', Ethics, 92 (1981) 2 1 .
Legal Rights 273
justification of any right requires moral argument. Consider the right of a
child to be maintained by his parents. To conclude that in virtue of it he has
any more specific right (to three meals a day, to proper clothing, etc.), one
has to engage in moral argument on the purpose of the right and its place
among other moral concerns: is it a right to minimal or to optimal support,
is the level of support required relative to the parents' ability to pay, or to
their life-style (they may be rich people who lead very simple lives), is it
relative to the parents' moral beliefs (so that they may deny him certain
experiences or opportunities because they object to them)? Does it include
moral as well as material support? The right to maintenance against one's
parents has no specific implications which do not involve answering these
or some similar questions. These questions cannot be answered without
using moral argument. Therefore, no legal right has concrete legal implica­
tions if the Sources Thesis is to be believed.
Turning to the other class of legally justified legal rights, those which
derive their legal force from statute or precedent, even they cannot be
explained in conformity with the Sources Thesis. At least, such explanation
is impossible in those areas of the law where rights are liable to be over­
ridden by moral considerations. This is true, it could be claimed, of all
equitable remedies and equity-based rights. It is also true wherever consid­
erations of public policy or public morality entitle the courts to override
otherwise established rights. It is arguable that the courts have an inherent
jurisdiction to this effect in all cases brought before them. Wherever they
have this discretion, no concrete rights or duties can be attributed to the
legislated right which is thus deprived of content. Its content can be
restored only if we allow that the content of the law and of legal rights is
determined by moral considerations.
Tbe Reply. Both parts of the objections are based on simple mistakes. The
fact that a given right can be overridden by moral considerations, just like
the fact that it can be overridden by another legal right, shows nothing
except that it is not an absolute right which defeats all contrary considera­
tions. But legal rules rarely, if ever, have absolute force. In general they are
liable to be overridden by contrary legal considerations where such exist,
and where the law gives them greater force. Often, it is true, they are liable
to be overridden by certain moral considerations as well, for often the law
provides for this . But the account offered in the previous section is an
account of defeasible rights. It does not presuppose that they have absolute
force.
As to the objection concerning legal rights which derive their legal force
from being justified by other legal rights, it is simply incorrect that all such
justifications depend on moral assumptions. Suppose that it is morally right
that parents can do with tl1eir children whatever they think is in the chil­
dren's best interest (including killing them) . If so, it is false that children
274 Between Law and Morality
have a right to maintenance against their parents. One cannot argue that
this is what that right means. One cannot argue that a child's right to main­
tenance is respected by a parent who starves him because he, the parent,
sincerely but falsely believes that this is in the best interests of the child. 'A
right to maintenance' has as part of its meaning a descriptive content which
can be established without use of moral argument. It establishes the legal
force of those rights and duties which can be justified in virtue of its core
descriptive content without invoking other moral principles.

VI . F U R T H E R O BJ E C T I O N S

In order further to explain and defend my account of legal rights I will


briefly consider three other possible objections to it which, unlike the objec­
tions considered above, do not turn on the relation between legal and
moral rights.

Legal Rights as Reasons for Legal Change


The Objection. Much play was made in Section IV of the fact that legal rights
not only justify other existing legal rights and duties but also direct the
courts to develop the law in certain ways. They are legal reasons for cre­
ating new laws, new rights, and duties. They are therefore not reducible to
a compendium statement of existing duties. One may object to this and
claim that a statement that someone has a right to something is logically
equivalent to a statement of existing duties. The dynamic aspect of rights,
the fact that they are reasons for new duties, simply means that there is an
existing duty on the courts to impose certain new duties on other people
in certain circumstances. A's right to x is a reason for the court to allow him
to x, to stop others from hindering him, etc.
The Reply. The courts may have reasons to do all that they are required
to do in order to protect a right, but these reasons are based on different
grounds. They may be based on considerations of general welfare or of
public safety, or public order, etc. Sometimes their duty is grounded on A's
rights. The nature of the grounds for the courts' duties is clarified by a right
statement, but lost by the reduction. Stating the legally recognized ground
of the court's reason for certain actions is no mere rhetoric. It may, for
example, be crucial for determining the weight the court is allowed to
attribute to this reason when it conflicts with others.

Rights of Officials and Corporations


It could be objected that even if my account explains individual rights it
cannot explain official rights, nor those of corporations. Their rights are not
Legal Rights 275
meant to protect their interests, but the interests of others who are not the
right-holders. This objection is based on a misunderstanding. Rights protect
the interests of the right-holders. But these interests need not be intrinsically
valuable. The reason for protecting them may be that by doing so one does
protect the interests of others. Officials have interests . They are determined
by their powers and duties, for their interest is to be able to use their powers
and to discharge their duties. Corporations also have interests determined
similarly by their purposes, powers, and duties . It is true that protecting
these interests is not intrinsically valuable. Nevertheless, corporations and
officials have rights in the same sense as other individuals. They have rights
if and only if their interests are sufficient to justify holding others to be
subject to duties.

Liberty Rights

Some may object that at best I have explained one sense of 'rights' , that in
which they correspond to duties. But there is a second quite separate sense
of rights, i.e. the absence of duty. One has a right to x if it is neither wrong
for one to x nor is it wrong if one does not.
The issue of the so-called liberty rights is a complex one. Here I will
confine myself to a few brief and rather dogmatic observations . The
absence of duty does not amount to a right. A person who says to another
'I have a right to do it' is not saying that he has no duty not to or that it is
not wrong to do it. He is claiming that the other has a duty not to interfere.
It is not necessarily a duty not to interfere in any way whatsoever. It is,
however, a claim that there are some ways of interference which would be
wrong because they are against an interest of the right-holder. 'I have a
right to do it and you have a right to stop me if you can' is paradoxical only
if it means 'if you can with no holds barred' .
The difficulty is that, though a statement of a right to do something is not
a statement that it is right to do so, it is sometimes impossible to decide
whether the speaker claims one or the other. The difficulty is all the greater
because people rarely say, 'I am acting wrongly but I have a right to do
what I am doing'. Nevertheless, they can say this. There is no contradiction
in this statement. It is paradoxical, for if I know that I am acting wrongly
why don't I stop? Consider, however, the past tense of the same sentence:
I acted wrongly but I had a right to do what I did. This is not only in perfect
logical order, it lacks the air of paradox. In fact it is quite a common thing
to say. It is used when one concedes that one should not have done what
one did and yet claims that none the less the other had no right to interfere.
Such statements exemplify the fact that to have a right to x is not the same
as to have no duty to x or not to x.
Though the objection is based on a mistake, it points to an important
276 Between Law and Morality
distinction which is yet to be introduced. We need to distinguish between
legal rights and what I shall call 'legally respected rights' . It is arguable that
the right to privacy is respected by English law. This means that there are
no legal duties compliance with which violates the right to privacy. If this
is so, then the right to privacy fares better than the right to establish a family
because in England immigration officials have a duty to prevent entry into
the country of husbands and fiances of some women who have a right of
permanent residence in England. This duty violates the right to establish a
family. Though the right to privacy is respected (in the technical sense I
have given this expressionYin English law, it is not a legal right in England.
The courts refuse to use it as a ground for imposing duties on officials or
on other citizens to stop them from invading privacy.27 Nor is it used by the
courts to justify already existing rights.
Failure to distinguish between a legal right and a legally respected right
may lead to the view that mere absence of a duty is a right. But if so, then
privacy is a legal right in English law, and everyone agrees that this is not
so.

7:7 See Re X (a minor) [1975] 1 All ER 703 (CA) and Malone v. Comnr ofPolice of the Metropolis
(No. 2) [1979] 2 All ER 620. One important aspect of the right to privacy is at least partially
recognized as a legal right in English law: the right to confidentiality.

You might also like