The Generative Enterprise
The Generative Enterprise
The Generative Enterprise
In 1982, Riny Huybregts and Henk van Riemsdijk published a long interview
with Noam Chomsky, organized as a discussion of different issues in the history and
structure of the linguistic theory. The book containing that interview was given an
extremely adequate title: ‘The Generative Enterprise’ (see Chomsky 1982a). I share the
interviewees’ opinion that the linguistic theory, proposed, developed and permanently
‘protected’ by Chomsky’s extraordinary presence can in fact be understood as an
‘enterprise’ – a collective one - having Chomsky as its unequivocal leader.
My aim here is to demonstrate that the linguistic theory widely known as
Generative Grammar (among other names it has been given at different times) is an
extremely coherent Scientific Research Program that starts to be built around the mid
XXth century and that has become, from its early days, a way of understanding the
structure of the human language that can be questioned – an appropriate procedure in
the development of scientific theories – but that cannot be ignored.
I shall consider the roughly 50 years of Generative Grammar (hereafter GG) as
a period of time in which a Scientific Research Program is constructed, with roughly
the same meaning the term has in the proposal presented by the Hungarian philosopher
Imre Lakatos for approaching the history of sciences in general (see Lakatos 1978).
Although I will not adopt an orthodox lakatosian approach, I believe Lakatos’s ideas
allow for a better quality understanding of what actually happened to GG during the last
50 years.
Therefore, the present work is not a strictly linguistic work. Better, it is a work
that fits the areas of History and Philosophy of Science3, directed to the analysis of a
specific case: the ‘internal’ history of GG.
1. Lakatos’s methodology.
I shall start the presentation of Lakatos’s methodology quoting Feyerabend:
Let me now present in its entirety the picture of science which I think
should replace Kuhn’s account.
This picture is the synthesis of the following two discoveries. Fist, it
contains Popper’s discovery that science is advanced by a critical
discussion of alternative views. Secondly, it contains Kuhn’s discovery of
the function of tenacity which he has expresses, mistakenly I think, by
postulating tenacious periods. The synthesis consists in Lakatos’
assertion … that proliferation and tenacity do not belong to successive
periods of the history of science, but are always copresent.
(Feyerabend 1974 p. 211)
1
Published in Portuguese as “O empreendimento gerativo” In Mussalim, F. & Bentes, A.C. (eds) 2004. Introdução à
Lingüística, vol 3. São Paulo: Cortez.
2
I would like to thank my colleagues Maria Cristina de Figueiredo Silva and Evani Viotti. for the comments, ever
pertinent, they made on a first version of the present work; and also the editors Fernanda Mussalim and Anna
Christina Bentes for their welcome suggestions and comments. Of course, the responsibility for the final results is
mine.
3
As Lakatos (1971:102) says, paraphrasing Kant: ‘Philosophy of Science without history of science is empty; history
of science without philosophy of science is blind’.
The Generative Enterprise 2
4
For a more detailed presentation of the present case, see Lakatos 1970, p. 50-51.
The Generative Enterprise 3
The idea I have defended for some time now is that GG is an SRP and not a
linguistic ‘theory’. I am not going to justify this position here (see Borges Neto 1991 for
details). On this line of thought, instead of discussing alternative proposals developed
by such and such linguists, it is more interesting to follow the major directions the
program assumes, through its rules and heuristics. It is also interesting to see the
creative shifts that from time to time redirect the efforts made by the scientists linked to
the SRP.
Such is the investigation we intend do carry out within the scope of the present
work.
Without further discussion, I would like to propose that the nucleus of the GG
consists of the following statements:
(1) The effective linguistic behavior (utterances) is, at least partially,
determined by states of the mind/brain.
(2) The nature of the states of the mind /brain, partially responsible for the
linguistic behavior, can be captured by the computing systems that form
and modify representations5.
I believe these two statements adequately summarize the concept of human
language that has presided the fifty years of chomskian thought.
The GG program’s heuristics determines that the linguist’s basic task is to
create computing systems that may serve as model for the speaker/hearers’ linguistic
knowledge of the language. These computing systems must be understood as
explanatory hypotheses, and their empirical consequences must be evaluated in a
deductive system.
Despite the enormous difference between the analyses actually proposed for
the natural languages phenomena at different points in time in the history of GG (the
proposed computing systems), the general aim of chomskian linguistics has been
remarkably consistent during all these years. We can say, in general terms, that
Chomsky has obsessively pursued the same objective for 50 years, although from time
to time he replaces the conceived theoretical device in order to attain the major task of
his linguistics conception.
Deep down, what generative grammar intends to do is to construct a computing
device, capable of forming and transforming representations, that can ‘simulate’ the
linguistic knowledge a speaker of a natural language has ‘registered’ in his mind/brain.
It is this ‘nucleus’, constantly present in the 50 years of generative grammar
history, that allows us to say we are before one and the same research program, in spite
of the various deep changes the theoretical device (the computing system) has
undergone.
It is largely accepted that the GG history starts in 1957, with the publication of
5
The term ‘representation’ assumes many meanings in the linguistic literature. I am using it here to refer to formal
objects of the theoretical construct that correspond to the things that belong to the modeled ‘reality’. In other words,
the states of the mind/brain are, in our case, represented by expressions of a formal language.
The Generative Enterprise 4
At this point, the nucleus of the chomskian program has already been fairly
established, although not yet fully explained. The best way of capturing this nucleus is
by investigating the main disagreements that Chomsky and some of his disciples
understood to exist between their proposals and the proposals of the mainstream
linguistics at the time: the American structuralism from a bloomfieldian lineage.
Chomsky’s proposal, embodied in the SS theory, differ from structuralism in
some important points:
First, the object of study of structuralism was language, understood as ‘the
totality of statements that can be uttered in a linguistic community’, according to
Bloomfield (1926, p.47). It was the linguist’s task to describe that language, and that
would be done from the starting point of a ‘representative corpus’ of raw language data,
which was described in detail with the tools offered by the ‘discovery procedures’.
What calls Chomsky’s attention is the need to assume the existence of something prior
to the structuralists’ language: the capacity the speakers have to produce exactly the
statements that can be produced. In other words, Chomsky moves the fundamental
question of linguistic theory to determining the rules that govern those ‘representative
corpora’, which lose their status as starting point of the linguistic theory and become its
target. For Chomsky, the linguistic community has a shared knowledge about those
utterances that can and those that cannot be produced, and it is exactly this knowledge
that must be described and explained by the linguistic theory. The ‘representative
corpus’ is the result of this knowledge and to take it as a starting point is
methodologically uninteresting. According to Chomsky, a good indication of the
existence of such knowledge lies in linguistics creativity: the speakers’ ability of
producing and understanding sentences to which they have not been exposed before.
We can then say that one could devise in Chomsky’s initial works a
psychological object for linguistic studies, although Chomsky did not put it explicitly
like that. In other words, ‘the state of mind/brain’ mentioned above had already been
glimpsed.
Another point of disagreement between American structuralism and the SS
theory concerns the definition of the aims of those theories. While the structuralist
theories were, generally speaking, explicitly descriptive, the SS theory intended to be
explanatory, in the sense that the phenomenon should be deduced from a set of general
principles8. The adoption by Chomsky of a hypothetical-deductive model of science
presents deep implications to his program’s procedures. It is no longer a question – as in
structuralism – of describing data that reveal themselves to the linguists’ perception, but
a question of finding the general principles from which the descriptions of observable
data can be logically derived. With Chomsky, the theoretical aspect takes precedence
over the empirical aspect. It is not surprising, however, that a large amount of
Chomsky’s work, at that time, discusses formal languages and tries to define the formal
nature of natural languages as compared to the languages used by logicians and
mathematicians9 . It is the program’s heuristics determining the priorities and, clearly
enough, Chomsky realizes that what is fundamental at that moment is the definition of a
8
Chomsky explicitly assumes a deductive-monological perspective in his characterization of what might be an
explanatory theory (see, for example, Chomsky 1997, p.106).
9
It is in this period that Chomsky develops a classification and a typology of languages that is still used by logicians,
mathematicians and computer scientists – the so-called Chomsky’s Hierarchy. With his hierarchy, Chomsky intends
to show that natural languages present properties that cannot be represented by grammars that would be perfectly
adequate to account for the languages used by logicians. For example, while logicians’ languages can be represented
by formal systems (free-context grammars) that construct expressions without taking the context into account (the
adjacent expressions), natural languages allow to construct expressions that can only be represented by more
powerful formal devices - the transformational grammars.
The Generative Enterprise 6
10
See, for example, Harris 1957.
The Generative Enterprise 7
(3)a. S
SV
SN SN
N V N
Pedro Viu Maria
‘Peter’ ‘saw’ ‘Mary’
The Generative Enterprise 8
Each of the words Pedro, viu, and Maria will be assigned a representation at
the morphological and phonological levels, which will allow to obtain a morphological
representation for the sentence. And so on so forth, till we end up with a fully
represented sentence in all six linguistic levels.
Each conversion must be marked somehow in order to indicate which linguistic
level it belongs to, and this can be done by grouping the conversions of the same level
and by establishing a certain order of application.
Thus we come to the well known grammar of Syntactic Structures:
E: Sentence
F: X1 Y1
⋅ ⋅
⋅ ⋅ Phrase-structure
⋅ ⋅
Xn Yn
T1
⋅
⋅ Transformations
⋅
Tj
Z1 W1
⋅ ⋅
⋅ ⋅ Morphophonemics
⋅ ⋅
Zm Wm
This, in short, is the model of analysis Chomsky proposed in the late fifties.
The hypothesis put forward then is that this linguistic analysis device would be
an adequate representation of the computing system, present in the speakers’
mind/brain, able to determine, at least partially, its linguistic components. That is,
assuming the affirmations of the nucleus, the heuristics determined the construction of a
representation hypothesis of the computing system, which, until disproved, was
The Generative Enterprise 9
11
In Portuguese, for instance, the sequence N+V+N is well formed, whereas the sequence V+N+V is not.
12
The sentence Pedro viu Maria is analyzable, from the point of view of the same syntagmatic indicator, into
<Pedro, viu Maria; N, SV>, provided we consider the SV internal structure.
13
This is just an outline of the passive transformation in Portuguese. It is necessary to underline that this type of
transformation was already abandoned in the initial revisions of the GG and, as much as I know, it has never been
The Generative Enterprise 11
Domain: N1 Aux V N2 ⇒
Effect: N2 Aux+ser V+-do por N1
‘be’ ‘-ed’ ‘by’
The domain tells us that expressions can undergo transformation (the sentence
Pedro viu Maria, for example, is within the transformation domain 14); the effect tells us
which are the changes the starting sentence (let us say, Pedro viu Maria) must undergo
in order that the target sentence can be obtained. Basically, the changes consist of the
permutation of subject (N1) and direct object (N2); the addition of verb ser ‘to be’, as
‘tense bearer’ auxiliary; the addition of the past participle ending to V; and the addition
of the preposition por ‘by’ before N1. After applying the rule to the sentence Pedro viu
Maria, we will obtain the target sentence Maria foi vista por Pedro ‘Mary was seen by
Peter’.
According to Milner, what Chomsky defines with his transformation notion…
c'est une entité spécifique, la règle de transformation et non une
classe de paires de phrases; le fait que deux phrases soient en
relation est envisagé comme une propriété de la paire, distincte
de la paire elle-même, et dont la règle prise dans son ensemble
est le symbole.
(Milner 1973, p. 104-105)
For Milner, chomskian transformations cannot be dealt with in a class language
and characterize relations-in-intention.
It is easy to see that there are many similarities between the two concepts of
transformation. According to Milner, what make them different are the approaches:
extensional in Harris and intentional in Chomsky.
In extensional terms, a transformation relation is totally determined by the pair
of sentences it relates and the task of the grammar is simply to establish those pairs.
Harris states quite clearly that, basically, transformational analysis is not a means of
determining the structure of each sentence considered separately, but rather a way of
grouping the sets of sentences into pairs (Cf. Harris 1968, p. 68).
From an intentional perspective, on the other hand, given a pair of sentences,
we can imagine various relations (rules) between them, specified differently by the
analyzable predicate. The scientist’s task is much more complex than it would be from
an extensional perspective.
We could always argue that the extensional and intentional theories are
equivalent, since it seems possible to establish corresponding tables that relate
properties and classes, relations-in-extension and relations-in-intention, etc. For
example, the statement ‘sequence t is analyzable into...’ is nothing more than the
intentional version of the statement ‘sequence t is a member of the sentence form...’.
However,
Il exist bien des cas où les paires sont parfaitement connues, mais où la
règle de transfomation intensionnelle ne peut être formulée parce que
le prédicat « analisable » ne peut être prècisé à coup sûr.
Les examples réels abondent et certains d’entre eux sont très connus :
ainsi les paires phrases actives/phrases passives sont parmi les mieux
The first ten years of generative grammar were its ‘heroic years’ in which the
combat with the forces of American structuralism dominated the scene15. The SS theory
proceeds having its presuppositions explicited and some of its theoretical devices
changed or replaced in order that it could manage - in better conditions - to carry out the
task the theory imposed, namely the description of a computing system able to define,
15
Despite being very similar, as we saw, GG and the American structuralism soon start out a dispute for space and
prestige inside the North-American academic institutions. As this dispute is a matter of sociology of science, rather
than of philosophy, and the present work intends to have a basically philosophical character, I am not making any
attempt to explore here this bias of the history of science.
The Generative Enterprise 13
generatively, natural languages. In the mid sixties one could already consider that the
battle had been won: the generative program was clearly dominating among the North-
American linguistics and began its expansion to other places, by conquering new
followers outside the USA.
Aspects of the Theory of Syntax (Chomsky 1965) is a great synthesis of the
changes that were made in the SS theory. Besides the first great clarification of the
program’s postulates - presented in the ‘Methodological Preliminaries’ 16 - Chomsky
develops a new configuration for his grammar: a model that came to be known as the
‘Standard Theory’.
This new theory changes significantly the descriptive model and clarifies a
series of postulates that, in the previous theory, had been presupposed in a rather
obscure way or, though resulting from those presuppositions, were not presented
clearly. It is during this period, for example, that the question of innatism is raised as a
working hypothesis, with the resulting strong psychologization of the grammar 17. It is
also in the same period that powerful auxiliary theories were developed, which will
allow for a better descriptive and/or explanatory performance of the program: the
lexicon becomes relevant and receives its first consistent theoretical formulation; the
‘deep structure’ appears, having as its strongest consequence the outset of a deeper
concern about semantics (concern that provided for the emergence of a series of more or
less heterodox alternative theoretical formulations)18.
It is also not surprising that a high number of discussions focused the
transformational component of the model of analysis. Given a set of linguistic
phenomena, if what differentiate a generative analysis from the one carried out by a
structuralist is the presence of transformations, it is obvious that the heuristics should
determine a more careful exam of that notion aiming at the solution of formal problems
that might emerge there.
In the standard theory, the form of grammar - which in a way represents the
image that one had at that time about the functioning of the linguistic knowledge the
speakers have registered in their mind/brain - is organized into three major components:
a syntactic component, which is generative, in as much it is the only component that
constructs representations, and two interpretive components; the semantic component;
and the phonological component19.
The process of generating sentence starts from the syntactic component, which
has the following basic structure: a base subcomponent (or simply BASE), which is the
responsible for generating the deep structures (DS); and a transformational
subcomponent, which converts the DS’s into surface structures (SS). The base
subcomponent contains (i) a set of rewriting rules (sometimes called categorical
component), which, applied to the initial axiom S, generates tree structures ‘labeled’
with the symbols of the categories whose terminal nodes are not filled in; and (ii) a
lexicon, which inserts lexical items into the terminal nodes of the tree. The base input is
the axiom S and the deep structures are the output. The transformational component is
assigned deep structures, as input, and, through transformational rules, converts them
into surface structures. In a diagrammatical form, we would have:
16
First chapter in Chomsky 1965.
17
Linguists spent a lot of time discussing the Language Acquisition Device (LAD).
18
As Generative Semantics, for example (see Lakoff 1971, Kato 1974, Dascal 1978, and Galmiche 1979, among
others).
19
The difference between the generative component and an interpretive component lies in the property that the
generative component has of creating new representations, whereas the interpretive components only associate (pair,
relate) representations among themselves.
The Generative Enterprise 14
Syntactic component
BASE
Categorial Lexicon DS Transformational SS
component component
The syntactic component generates ordered pairs <DS, SS> and the two
interpretive components associate representations to the elements of the pairs: the
semantic component associates semantic interpretations to DS’s and the phonological
component associates phonetic interpretations to SS’s. A complete diagram of it would
be the following:
BASE: Categorial c.
Lexicon DS Semantic interpretation Semantic c.
Transformational c.
After the heat of the famous sequence of clashes with the Generative
20
That is, the formulae (expressions of the formal system language) which were supposed to represent adequately the
meanings of natural language expressions.
21
As I cannot present a more detailed analysis of this period within the scope of the present work, I suggest the
interested reader to refer specially to Newmeyer 1980, Harris 1993 (and Borges Neto 1991) for details.
22
EST is initially proposed by Chomsky 1967 and developed in Chomsky 1968 and 1971.
The Generative Enterprise 16
Semantics cooled down, Chomsky and his associates could go back and think about the
development of the GG program. The greatest legacy of Generative Semantics was the
proliferation of theoretical devices and of the types of available rules. The immediate
task the chomskians had to face then was that of restricting the descriptive power of the
grammar in order to increase its explanatory power.
A certain ‘tension’ is felt in the GG program between the requirement of
descriptive adequacy and the requirement of explanatory adequacy. Chomsky says that
a theory is explanatorily adequate when it manages to successfully select a
descriptively adequate grammar from a set of possible grammars (defined by the
general theory) and from the primary linguistic data. In other words, the theory is
explanatorily adequate when it reproduces the behavior of children acquiring language:
from the raw linguistic data, they select a grammar among the possible grammars
admitted by the innate component of their linguistic competence23. Thus, in order to
attain the explanatory adequacy, the available theoretical devices in the general theory
(the grammar innate component theory) must be restricted, so that few grammars can be
obtained and one is able to understand how a child quickly selects an adequate grammar
for the data available to him/her.
On the other hand, in order to attain the descriptive adequacy, that is, in order
to construct grammars to all natural languages, the available theoretical devices must be
rich and varied enough to cover all the richness and diversity of natural languages.
The conflict between these two requisites of adequacy is obvious and the
search must go for a theory that is, at the same time, rich enough to account for the
variety of languages and restrictive enough to provide a small number of possible
grammars.
In the mid sixties it is already possible to find restrictive proposals to the
descriptive power of transformational rules. John Robert Ross’s PhD Dissertation (Ross
1967), postulating the ‘islands’ (syntactic configurations that prevented the extraction of
elements), is a good example of this concern. But it is with Peters and Ritchie’s works,
in the early seventies, in the heat of the debates between the GG and Generative
Semantics, that the need to restrict the power of those rules becomes urgent.
Peters and Ritchie (1969, 1971, 1973) demonstrate that de weak generative
capacity of a grammar that includes transformational rules, as those proposed at that
time, is equivalent to an unrestricted rewriting system (a Turing machine). This means
that a transformational grammar of any natural languages do not reveal anything about
the structural characteristics of that language, but only states that that language -
understood as a set of sentences - is recursively enumerable (and, consequently, can be
generated by calculus). Peters and Ritchie’s works show that the major problem of
transformational grammars was not the proliferation of rules or categories but the lack
of strong restrictions on the functioning of those rules. Without restrictions, the
transformations – that could eliminate, create, exchange, move, or change elements –
were useless as exposing devices of linguistic structures. Applying the adequate
deletions, movements, and additions, one could start from any sentence and arrive to
any other sentence.
The task of proposing restrictive conditions on the functioning of the rules
becomes the priority of the program. It seems clear that here we have a case of creative
change in the heuristics. The focus is not placed on the descriptive adequacy any longer
23
The innate component – Language Competence – is a set of general principles about the nature of the linguistic
representations, principles that can be manifested in a whole range of alternative realizations (the parameters).
According to Chomsky, children apply these ‘parameterized’ principles to construct the grammar of their language,
provided they are exposed to the data.
The Generative Enterprise 17
24
Translated from the Portuguese original by the author.
The Generative Enterprise 18
I am not going into long analyses within the scope of the present work. But I
would like to show just how these auxiliary theories work.
The trace theory, for example, developed in Chomsky (1976a), postulates that
all moved element leaves a trace in the place it left, and this trace acts as a full element
for the purposes of syntactic rules. For example, the analysis of sentence (4) proposes it
be derived by transformation from structure (5) through the move of the clictic nos to a
position next to the verb of the main clause25.
(4) Paulo nos viu examinar a garota
‘Paul saw us examine the girl’
(5) Paulo viu [nos examinar a garota]
‘Paul saw [us examine the girl]’
It is not possible, however, to obtain (6) from (7) because the clictic a would
have to ‘fly over’ the subject of the subordinate and this is not allowed by the
Conditions over Specified Subject26.
(6) * Paulo a viu nós examinar
‘Paul saw us examine her’
(7) Paulo viu [nós examinar a]
‘Paul saw [us examine her]’
Let us consider a fairly more complex case. Sentence (8) would be obtained
from the structure present in (9) by the move of the subordinate subject to the position
of subject of the main sentence and by the anteposition move of the clictic os.
(8) Paulo parece os ter examinado
‘Paul seems to have examined them’
(9) ∆ parece [Paulo ter examinado os]
‘∆ seems [Paul to have examined them]’
Sentence (10), however, which should behave in the same way, is not
grammatical, although there is apparently no other reasons for the application of the
specified subject condition.
(10) * Paulo os parece ter examinado.
‘*Paul seems to have examined them’
The solution to the problem brought by the trace theory suggests that between
sentence (9) and sentence (10), we should have an intermediate structure (11) that,
having its trace in subject position, hinders the move of the clictic outside the
subordinate sentence.
(11) Paulo parece [t ter examinado os]
‘Paul seems [t to have examined them]’
Clictic moves are allowed inside the subordinate sentence, and so, from
structure (9) we could obtain structures (12) and (13) with no difficulties.
(12) Paulo parece [t tê-los examinado]
‘Paul seems [t to have them examined]’
25
These analyses are borrowed from Quícoli 1976.
26
Which is one of the conditions on transformations proposed by Chomsky.
The Generative Enterprise 19
What can be perceived hereon is that it becomes impossible to admit that the
move rules are free, that is, that they are not submitted to conditions. The conditions on
moves cease to exist, and all their effects turn to be obtained through interpretive
conditions.
The main consequence of this is the substitution of what we can call derivational
perspective by a representational perspective. We are facing a new creative change in
the program’s heuristics.
From a derivational perspective, the various representations of the linguistic levels
(they may be ‘phonemes (Pm), morphemes (M), words (W), syntactic categories (C),
phrase structures (P), and transformations (T)’, as Chomsky intended in LSLT; they
may be ‘Deep structure, surface structure, phonetic form and semantic representation’,
as in the standard theory) are derived from one another through rules. The grammar is
strictly directional, that is, the various levels of linguistic analysis are approached – and
receive representations – in a given order. Thus, until the mid seventies, all proposals of
grammars made inside the GG were derivational.
From the representational perspective, on the other hand, the various
representations are not related by derivation: they are just representations of structural
properties resulting from the theories restricting grammar. P-structures, for example,
can turn to be understood as a ‘pure’ representation of the grammatical functions
relevant to the attribution of thematic roles and, in this sense, as an ‘abstraction’ of the
S-structures. Grammar is not directional. As Lobato states:
This change of approach leads to a switch in the interpretation of
what may be ‘generated by the base’. In the previous versions of the
theory, this expression meant ‘derived from S by successive
applications of syntagmatic rules e by using the lexical substitution
rule’. Now it means ‘be projected from the lexicon, from X,
according to the UG [Universal Grammar] principles and the
parameters established by a certain language’. This new perspective
allows then to consider an S-structure generated by the base, and the
move-ALPHA is a property of the S-Structures and not, from this point
of view, a rule that converts P-structures into S-structures (cf.
Chomsky 1982b: 33). Likewise, any other level of representation can
be seen as ‘derived by the base’, since any level of representation is
determined by the establishment of the UG parameters (Chomsky
1982b: 14).
(Lobato 1986, pp. 403-404)29
Having completed the cycle of substitution of rules by principles, Chomsky
finds himself involved by a grammar theory which is different enough from the
previous ones to justify a new label: Principles and Parameters Theory.
I am not going into details about the Principles and Parameters Theory (also
called, for some time, Government and Binding Theory). It suffices to say that this is the
theory used at this beginning of the XXIst century for the study of the syntax of natural
languages. However, it is worth mentioning some movements that have been observed
inside the GG program – especially the so-called Minimalist Program – the statute of
which is not yet clear to me (and not even to the generativists themselves, so it seems to
me).
29
Translated from the Portuguese original by the author.
The Generative Enterprise 21
30
Translated from the Portuguese original by the author.
31
There is a concern about showing that the human languages are themselves economical and perfect (I thank Evani
Viotti for this observation).
32
In what follows, I make strong use of Raposo 1999.
33
The question of interfaces is an old question. In the standard theory, it was up to the deep structure to make an
interface with the C-I system, and to the surface structure to make the interface with the A-P system. In the
government and binding theory the interface with the C-I system is done in Logical Form and it is up to the
Phonological Form to make the interface with the A-P system. Certainly, although the idea is very old, the devices to
actualize these interfaces have become more and more sophisticated as the time passes by.
The Generative Enterprise 22
According to Chomsky, the C-I and A-P systems have their own structure and
are independent from the human language. It is possible to assume that they impose
conditions over language. It is reasonable to think that human languages have the
articulatory and hearing capacity of human beings as their limitations, for instance34.
So, for us to use languages it is necessary that the linguistic expressions satisfy
certain conditions imposed by these two outside systems. Thus, the MP fundamental
question is the establishment of the ‘measure’ that allows the evaluation of the
‘optimality’ of the structures in satisfying the conditions imposed by the outside
systems. In other words, it will be considered ‘good’, ‘grammatical’, ‘acceptable’ the
structure that fully satisfies the interface conditions.
Now, though it can sound like big news, it seems that we are facing the same
‘movement’ that led GG to switch from rules to principles: that of obtaining the
maximum generality with the least resources. In a way, following the strong assumption
of ‘psychological reality’ of the computing systems – assumption that, in a higher or
lower degree, has been guiding the generative analysis from their first formulations –
what is being assumed is that the conditions over structures, realized in the auxiliary
theories, are imposed by performance, by ‘pragmatics’, by the ‘use’ we make of them.
And this ‘use’ involves not only the elements of comprehension of the world (the C-I
system) but also sensory-motor elements (the A-P system). The bet made by the MP is
that these general conditions, coming from performance, are capable of imposing proper
conditions to the computing system in order that it works in an ‘optimal’ manner and be
able to perform the task of the theories of the government and binding model with more
economy, considering that it does not need to postulate anything but the interfaces:
syntax is reduced to the minimum.
It is no longer necessary to postulate restrictions on structures. The ‘well-
formed conditions’ of the structures, essential in the other stages of the program,
disappear, and the guarantee that a structure is well formed (grammatical) will depend
on the degree of satisfaction of the conditions imposed by the outside systems (C-I and
A-P) that the structure presents. In other words, it will be considered more ‘adequate’,
‘acceptable’, ‘well-formed’, ‘grammatical’ that structure that best satisfies the phonetic
production/reception and semantic conditions.
From this point of view, MP is nothing more that the radicalization of the
movement that led the GG program to replace rules by principles.
3. Conclusion.
The history of GG shows three major ‘strategies’ in the delimitation of the
language competence present in the speaker’s mind/brain. At time 1 (the SS Theory),
grammar should generate the sentences of the language directly (into their surface
structures). They dealt exclusively with syntax (maybe phono-morpho-syntax), and the
notion of generative grammar was similar to the current notion in logics and
mathematics.
At time 2 (the Standard Theory), grammar begins to generate abstract objects
that are interpreted in the sentences of the language (in its phonetic form and in its
meaning), that is, the set of abstract objects generated by the grammar is projected into
the language, describing it as a set of possible signifiers linked to a set of possible
meanings (pairs <s,m>, where s is a signifier and m is a meaning). Here the notion of
generative grammar undergoes a slight modification in relation to its previous meaning:
34
The limit can also be visual, as long as we consider that sign languages of the deaf are also natural languages and
actualize from the same biological matrix than the, say, ‘audio-oral’ languages.
The Generative Enterprise 23
it does not generate the sentences of the language directly. However, the commitment
with the notion of language remains the same, since grammar will generate as many
abstract objects as there are sentences in the language and no more. This makes it
possible to go on considering grammar as a ‘system of rules that generate the sentences
- and only the sentences - of the language’35.
At time 3 (P&P), grammar generates abstract objects that explicit the
properties that the speakers take into account when they issue evaluations on the
grammaticality of linguistic objects. The sentences of any language constitute only a
sub-set of this set of linguistic objects and so it is never - and under no criterion –
possible to say that grammar generates the sentences of the language – at the most it is
possible to say that grammar allows (licensees), among other things, the sentences of a
given language36.
Using Lakatos’s terminology, we can say that such ‘strategies’ characterize
different heuristics and that the GG program has experienced two major creative shifts:
the first involving SS Theory and the Standard Theory, the second involving the
Standard Theory and P&P. We can also consider that the best periodization of the
development of the program establishes three periods: the SS period, which goes from
Chomsky’s work (around 1954) to the publication of ‘Aspects’ (1965); the Standard
Theory period, which starts with the publication of ‘Aspects’ and goes till ‘Conditions
on Rules of Grammar’ (1976a)37; and the P&P period, starting with Chomsky 1976a and
continuing till today. In its first period, the theory is still very tied to the structuralist
ways of doing linguistics and, consequently, there is a certain conflict between the
requirements of the program and its theoretical availability: it is an unstable period in
the theory. In the second period, it is the very program that faces difficulties: there is a
proliferation of alternative heuristic proposals and there are dissenters. This second
period is characterizes by disputes and by a great theoretical ebullience. The third period
is a period marked by a great development in the expansion of the empirical content of
the theory: a large number of languages are analyzed to a satisfactory degree and the
principles are established in a very consistent form.
Finally, I believe that a few words about Noam Chomsky’s role in this story are
in place.
Chomsky has always been the great leader of the Generative Community,
imposing advances, rewriting the program, rejecting and/or supporting proposals.
Chomsky acts – and he is seen like that by the community – as the ‘owner’ of the
program, the person who utters the last words about the validity of the research lines
proposed by his associates, the person who says what must and what must not be
researched, the person who from time to time carries out a ‘balance’ of profits and
losses (conquests and theoretical costs) of the theory and proposes the major syntheses
35
The SS grammar had as output of the set of conversions the very sentences of the language; the standard theory had as
its output of the set of conversions a set of structures (syntagmatic indicators) that were interpreted in the sentences of
the language.
36
In Chomsky’s words: ‘We may perfectly well think of the grammar of, say, English, as assigning a structural
description to every possible sound. Some will be characterized simply as noise, others as sounds of perhaps some
language (but not mine), others as expressions of my language with some figurative interpretation, others as paired with
strict “literal interpretations,” and so one.’ (1981, p. 5)
37
Usually we find references to the text ‘Conditions on Transformations’ (Chomsky 1973) as being the text that allows a
‘quality leap’ in the GG program. However, I believe that no matter how important this text might be in the process of
change from a system of rules to a system of principles, in fact, it does not modify any of the fundamental concepts of
the program. The text ‘Conditions on Rules of Grammar’ (Chomsky 1976a), on the other hand, because it releases the
syntactic component, allowing for the ‘overgeneration’, forces Chomsky to recognize that the program will only have a
chance if its notion of language is abandoned. In my opinion, it is this second text that opens the third period of the GG
program. The fact the critics/commentators of Chomsky’s work do not recognize in ‘Conditions on Rules of Grammar’
the importance I do, make me feel uncomfortable, but I cannot be unfaithful to my convictions.
The Generative Enterprise 24
which will provide the new directions. Without much exaggeration, we could say that
GG has always been an essentially Chomsky’s creation. All those who did not agree
with Chomsky, at some point in the history of the program, either surrendered to the
power of the ‘master’, rejoining the ‘good path’, or became dissenters, remaining
marginal to the program. No matter how interesting the proposals presented by
Chomsky’s associates were, they are only incorporated effectively to the program’s
theoretical arsenal after having been supported by Chomsky. Chomsky’s centralizing
power is so strong that it is possible to find a book of about 250 pages devoted
exclusively to a survey of the destiny – invariably unhappy – of those who dared to defy
him (Botha 1989).
Nevertheless, an interesting fact starts to unfold. The ‘cold’ reaction from the
community to the Minimalist Program proposed by Chomsky seems to indicate that we
are living a moment in which the program is reaching a certain maturity and that the
community can already walk on their own feet, dispensing with Chomsky’s custody.
Any way, it is too early to make any reliable evaluation of the course the generative
enterprise will take from here.
4. References:
Anderson, S.; Kiparsky, P. (eds.) 1973. A Festschrift for Morris Halle. New York: Holt,
Rinehart and Winston.
Bloomfield, L. 1926. A set of postulates for the science of language. Language 2, pp.
153-164.
Borges Neto, J. 1991. A Gramática Gerativa Transformacional: um ensaio de Filosofia
da Lingüística. Tese de doutorado, IEL-UNICAMP.
Botha, R. 1989. Challenging Chomsky: The Generative Garden Game. New York: Basil
Blackwell.
Chomsky, N. 1951. Morphophonemics of Modern Hebrew. University of Pennsylvania
(unpublished M.A. dissertation).
Chomsky, N. 1953. Systems of syntactic analysis. Journal of Symbolic Logic 18 (3), pp.
242-256.
Chomsky, N. 1955a. Logical syntax and semantics: their linguistic relevance. Language 31,
pp. 36-45.
Chomsky, N. 1955b. Transformational Analysis. University of Pennsylvania
(unpbublished Ph.D. thesis).
Chomsky, N. 1955c [1975]. The Logical Structure of Linguistic Theory. New York:
Plenum.
Chomsky, N. 1957. Syntactic Structures. The Hague: Mouton.
Chomsky, N. 1965. Aspects of the Theory of Syntax. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Chomsky, N. 1966. Topics in the Theory of Generative Grammar. The Hague: Mouton.
Chomsky, N. 1967. Remarks on Nominalization. In Chomsky 1972 (Spanish translation
in Sanchez de Zavala (comp.) 1974, pp. 133-187).
Chomsky, N. 1968. Deep structure, surface structure and semantic interpretation. In
Chomsky 1972 (Spanish translation in Sanchez de Zavala (comp.) 1974, pp. 276-
334).
Chomsky, N. 1971. Some empirical issues in the theory of transformational grammar.
In Chomsky 1972 (Spanish translation in Sanchez de Zavala (comp.) 1974, pp. 444-
524).
Chomsky, N. 1972. Studies on Semantics in Generative Grammar. The Hague: Mouton.
Chomsky, N. 1973. Conditions on Transformations. In Anderson & Kiparsky (eds.) 1973,
The Generative Enterprise 25
pp. 232-286.
Chomsky, N. 1976a. Conditions on rules of grammar. Linguistic Analysis 2, pp. 303-
351.
Chomsky, N. 1976b. On Wh-movement. In Culicover et. al. (eds.) 1977, pp. 71-132.
Chomsky, N. 1977. Dialogues avec Mitsou Ronat. Paris: Flammarion (tradução para o
português: Diálogos com Mitsou Ronat, São Paulo: Cultrix, s/d).
Chomsky, N. 1981. On the representation of form and function. The Linguistic Review 1
(1), pp. 3-40.
Chomsky, N. 1982a. The Generative Enterprise. Dordrecht: Foris.
Chomsky, N. 1995. The Minimalist Program. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
(Portuguese translation: O Programa Minimalista, Lisboa: Caminho, 1999)
Culicover, P; Wasow, T.; Akmajian, A. (eds.) 1977. Formal Syntax. New York:
Academic Press.
Dascal, M. (org.) 1978-1982. Fundamentos Metodológicos da Lingüística, 4 volumes,
São Paulo: Global (vol 1); Campinas: organizer’s edition (vol. 2, 3 e 4).
Dascal, M. 1978. As convulsões metodológicas da lingüística contemporânea. In Dascal
(org.) 1978, vol. 1, pp. 15-41.
Emonds, J. 1970. Root and Structure Preserving Transformations. Bloomington:
Indiana University Linguistic Club (IULC).
Feyerabend, P. 1974. “Consolations for the Specialist” in Lakatos & Musgrave (eds), p.
197-230.
Galmiche, M. 1979. Semântica Gerativa. Lisboa: Presença.
Harris, R.A. 1993. The Linguistic Wars. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Harris, Z.S. 1952. Discourse Analysis. Language 28, pp. 1-30 e 474-494.
Harris, Z.S. 1957. Coocurrence and transformation in linguistic structure. Language 33,
pp. 293-340.
Harris, Z.S. 1965. Transformational Theory. Language 41, pp. 363-401.
Harris, Z.S. 1968. Mathematical Structure of Language. New York: Intersciences.
Hockett, C.F. 1955. A manual of phonology. In Antropology and Linguistics: Memoire
11. Baltimore: Indiana University Publications.
Kato, M. 1974. A Semântica Gerativa e o Artigo Definido. São Paulo: Ática.
Lakatos, I. 1970 Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes.
In Lakatos & Musgrave (eds) 1974, p. 91-196 (republished in Lakatos 1978 p. 8-
101).
Lakatos, I. 1971. History of Science and its Rational Reconstructions. In Lakatos 1978,
pp. 102-138.
Lakatos, I. 1978. The Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes (Philosophical
Papers vol 1). Edited by John Worrall & Gregory Currie. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Lakatos, I. & Musgrave, A. (eds) 1974. Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge. (3rd
impression) London: Cambridge University Press.
Lakoff, G. 1971. On generative semantics. In Steinberg & Jakobovits (eds.) 1971, pp.
232-296.
Lees, R. 1957. Review of Noam Chomsky, Syntactic Structures. Language 33, pp. 375-
408 (reprinted in Otero, C. (ed) 1994. Noam Chomsky: critical assesment. Vol 1
London; Routledge).
Lobato, L.M.P. 1986. Sintaxe Gerativa do Português: da teoria-padrão à teoria de
regência e ligação. Belo Horizonte: Vigília.
Milner, J-C. 1973. Écoles de Cambridge et de Pennsylvanie: deux théories de la
transformation. Langages 29, pp. 98-117.
The Generative Enterprise 26
Newmeyer, F.J. 1980. Linguistic Theory in America: the first quarter century of
transformational generative grammar. New York: Academic Press
Peters, S.; Ritchie, R. 1969. A note on the universal base hypothesis. Journal of
linguistics 5, pp. 150-152.
Peters, S.; Ritchie, R. 1971. On restricting the base component of transformational
grammars. Information and Control 18, pp. 483-501.
Peters, S.; Ritchie, R. 1973. On the generative power of transformational grammars.
Information Sciences 6, pp. 49-83.
Quícoli, A.C. 1976. Conditions on clitic movement in Portuguese. Linguistic Analysis 2
(3), pp. 199-223.
Raposo, E.P. 1999. Da teoria de Princípios e Parâmetros ao Programa Minimalista:
algumas idéias-chave. Apresentação da tradução portuguesa de Chomsky 1995, pp.
15-37.
Ross, J.R. 1967. Constraints on variables in syntax. Bloomington: Indiana University
Linguistic Club (IULC).
Sanchez de Zavala, V. (comp.) 1974. Semántica y sintaxis en la lingüística
transformatoria I. Madri: Alianza.
Wells, R. 1947. Immediate Constituents. Language 36, pp. 360-367.