Mariana Mazzucato - The Value of Everything. Making and Taking in The Global Economy (2018, Penguin)
Mariana Mazzucato - The Value of Everything. Making and Taking in The Global Economy (2018, Penguin)
Mariana Mazzucato - The Value of Everything. Making and Taking in The Global Economy (2018, Penguin)
T H E VA L U E O F E V E RY T H I NG
Making and Taking in the Global Economy
2018
Contents
Notes
Bibliography
Acknowledgements
Follow Penguin
Preface: Stories About Wealth Creation
The barbarous gold barons – they did not find the gold, they did not mine the gold, they
did not mill the gold, but by some weird alchemy all the gold belonged to them.
Big Bill Haywood, founder of the Unites States’ first industrial union1
The vital but often muddled distinction between value extraction and value
creation has consequences far beyond the fate of companies and their
workers, or even of whole societies. The social, economic and political
impacts of value extraction are huge. Prior to the 2007 financial crisis, the
income share of the top 1 per cent in the US expanded from 9.4 per cent in
1980 to a staggering 22.6 per cent in 2007. And things are only getting
worse. Since 2009 inequality has been increasing even more rapidly than
before the 2008 financial crash. In 2015 the combined wealth of the
planet’s sixty-two richest individuals was estimated to be about the same
as that of the bottom half of the world’s population – 3.5 billion people.8
So how does the alchemy continue to happen? A common critique of
contemporary capitalism is that it rewards ‘rent seekers’ over true ‘wealth
creators’. ‘Rent-seeking’ here refers to the attempt to generate income, not
by producing anything new but by overcharging above the ‘competitive
price’, and undercutting competition by exploiting particular advantages
(including labour), or, in the case of an industry with large firms, their
ability to block other companies from entering that industry, thereby
retaining a monopoly advantage. Rent-seeking activity is often described
in other ways: the ‘takers’ winning out over the ‘makers’, and ‘predatory’
capitalism winning over ‘productive’ capitalism. It’s seen as a key way –
perhaps the key way – in which the 1 per cent have risen to power over the
99 per cent.9 The usual targets of such criticism are the banks and other
financial institutions. They are seen as profiting from speculative activities
based on little more than buying low and selling high, or buying and then
stripping productive assets simply to sell them on again with no real value
added.
More sophisticated analyses have linked rising inequality to the
particular way in which the ‘takers’ have increased their wealth. The
French economist Thomas Piketty’s influential book Capital in the
Twenty-First Century focuses on the inequality created by a predatory
financial industry that is taxed insufficiently, and by ways in which wealth
is inherited across generations, which gives the richest a head start in
getting even richer. Piketty’s analysis is key to understanding why the rate
of return on financial assets (which he calls capital) has been higher than
that on growth, and calls for higher taxes on the resultant wealth and
inheritance to stop the vicious circle. Ideally, from his point of view, taxes
of this sort should be global, so as to avoid one country undercutting
another.
Another leading thinker, the US economist Joseph Stiglitz, has explored
how weak regulation and monopolistic practices have allowed what
economists call ‘rent extraction’, which he sees as the main impetus
behind the rise of the 1 per cent in the US.10 For Stiglitz, this rent is the
income obtained by creating impediments to other businesses, such as
barriers to prevent new companies from entering a sector, or deregulation
that has allowed finance to become disproportionately large in relation to
the rest of the economy. The assumption is that, with fewer impediments
to the functioning of economic competition, there will be a more equal
distribution of income.11
I think we can go even further with these ‘makers’ versus ‘takers’
analyses of why our economy, with its glaring inequalities of income and
wealth, has gone so wrong. To understand how some are perceived as
‘extracting value’, siphoning wealth away from national economies, while
others are ‘wealth creators’ but do not benefit from that wealth, it is not
enough to look at impediments to an idealized form of perfect competition.
Yet mainstream ideas about rent do not fundamentally challenge how
value extraction occurs – which is why it persists.
In order to tackle these issues at root, we need to examine where value
comes from in the first place. What exactly is it that is being extracted?
What social, economic and organizational conditions are needed for value
to be produced? Even Stiglitz’s and Piketty’s use of the term ‘rent’ to
analyse inequality will be influenced by their idea of what value is and
what it represents. Is rent simply an impediment to ‘free-market’
exchange? Or is it due to their positions of power that some can earn
‘unearned income’ – that is, income derived from moving existing assets
around rather than creating new ones?12 This is a key question we will look
at in Chapter 2.
WHAT IS VALUE?
Value can be defined in different ways, but at its heart it is the production
of new goods and services. How these outputs are produced (production),
how they are shared across the economy (distribution) and what is done
with the earnings that are created from their production (reinvestment) are
key questions in defining economic value. Also crucial is whether what it
is that is being created is useful: are the products and services being
created increasing or decreasing the resilience of the productive system?
For example, it might be that a new factory is produced that is valuable
economically, but if it pollutes so much to destroy the system around it, it
could be seen as not valuable.
By ‘value creation’ I mean the ways in which different types of
resources (human, physical and intangible) are established and interact to
produce new goods and services. By ‘value extraction’ I mean activities
focused on moving around existing resources and outputs, and gaining
disproportionately from the ensuing trade.
A note of caution is important. In the book I use the words ‘wealth’ and
‘value’ almost interchangeably. Some might argue against this, seeing
wealth as a more monetary and value as potentially a more social concept,
involving not only value but values. I want to be clear on how these two
words are used. I use ‘value’ in terms of the ‘process’ by which wealth is
created – it is a flow. This flow of course results in actual things, whether
tangible (a loaf of bread) or intangible (new knowledge). ‘Wealth’ instead
is regarded as a cumulative stock of the value already created. The book
focuses on value and what forces produce it – the process. But it also looks
at the claims around this process, which are often phrased in terms of
‘who’ the wealth creators are. In this sense the words are used
interchangeably.
For a long time the idea of value was at the heart of debates about the
economy, production and the distribution of the resulting income, and
there were healthy disagreements over what value actually resided in. For
some economic schools of thought, the price of products resulted from
supply and demand, but the value of those products derived from the
amount of work that was needed to produce things, the ways in which
technological and organizational changes were affecting work, and the
relations between capital and labour. Later, this emphasis on ‘objective’
conditions of production, technology and power relationships was replaced
by concepts of scarcity and the ‘preferences’ of economic actors: the
amount of work supplied is determined by workers’ preference for leisure
over earning a higher amount of money. Value, in other words, became
subjective.
Until the mid-nineteenth century, too, almost all economists assumed
that in order to understand the prices of goods and services it was first
necessary to have an objective theory of value, a theory tied to the
conditions in which those goods and services were produced, including the
time needed to produce them, the quality of the labour employed; and the
determinants of ‘value’ actually shaped the price of goods and services.
Then, this thinking began to go into reverse. Many economists came to
believe that the value of things was determined by the price paid on the
‘market’ – or, in other words, what the consumer was prepared to pay. All
of a sudden, value was in the eye of the beholder. Any goods or services
being sold at an agreed market price were by definition value-creating.
The swing from value determining price to price determining value
coincided with major social changes at the end of the nineteenth century.
One was the rise of socialism, which partly based its demands for reforms
on the claim that labour was not being rewarded fairly for the value it
created, and the ensuing consolidation of a capitalist class of producers.
The latter group was, unsurprisingly, keen on the alternative theory, that
price determined value, a story which allowed them to defend their
appropriation of a larger share of output, with labour increasingly being
left behind.
In the intellectual world, economists wanted to make their discipline
seem ‘scientific’ – more like physics and less like sociology – with the
result that they dispensed with its earlier political and social connotations.
While Adam Smith’s writings were full of politics and philosophy, as well
as early thinking about how the economy works, by the early twentieth
century the field which for 200 years had been ‘political economy’
emerged cleansed as simply ‘economics’. And economics told a very
different story.
Eventually the debate about different theories of value and the dynamics
of value creation virtually vanished from economics departments, only
showing up in business schools in a very new form: ‘shareholder value’,13
‘shared value’,14 ‘value chains’,15 ‘value for money’, ‘valuation’, ‘adding
value’ and the like. So while economics students used to get a rich and
varied education in the idea of value, learning what different schools of
economic thought had to say about it, today they are taught only that value
is determined by the dynamics of price, due to scarcity and preferences.
This is not presented as a particular theory of value – just as Economics
101, the introduction to the subject. An intellectually impoverished idea of
value is just taken as read, assumed simply to be true. And the
disappearance of the concept of value, this book argues, has paradoxically
made it much easier for this crucial term ‘value’ – a concept that lies at the
heart of economic thought – to be used and abused in whatever way one
might find useful.
First, the disappearance of value from the economic debate hides what
should be alive, public and actively contested.17 If the assumption that
value is in the eye of the beholder is not questioned, some activities will be
deemed to be value-creating and others will not, simply because someone
– usually someone with a vested interest – says so, perhaps more
eloquently than others. Activities can hop from one side of the production
boundary to the other with a click of the mouse and hardly anyone notices.
If bankers, estate agents and bookmakers claim to create value rather than
extract it, mainstream economics offers no basis on which to challenge
them, even though the public might view their claims with scepticism.
Who can gainsay Lloyd Blankfein when he declares that Goldman Sachs
employees are among the most productive in the world? Or when
pharmaceutical companies argue that the exorbitantly high price of one of
their drugs is due to the value it produces? Government officials can
become convinced (or ‘captured’) by stories about wealth creation, as was
recently evidenced by the US government’s approval of a leukemia drug
treatment at half a million dollars, precisely using the ‘value-based
pricing’ model pitched by the industry – even when the taxpayer
contributed $200 million dollars towards its discovery.18
Second, the lack of analysis of value has massive implications for one
particular area: the distribution of income between different members of
society. When value is determined by price (rather than vice versa), the
level and distribution of income seem justified as long as there is a market
for the goods and services which, when bought and sold, generate that
income. All income, according to this logic, is earned income: gone is any
analysis of activities in terms of whether they are productive or
unproductive.
Yet this reasoning is circular, a closed loop. Incomes are justified by the
production of something that is of value. But how do we measure value?
By whether it earns income. You earn income because you are productive
and you are productive because you earn income. So with a wave of a
wand, the concept of unearned income vanishes. If income means that we
are productive, and we deserve income whenever we are productive, how
can income possibly be unearned? As we shall see in Chapter 3, this
circular reasoning is reflected in how national accounts – which track and
measure production and wealth in the economy – are drawn up. In theory,
no income may be judged too high, because in a market economy
competition prevents anyone from earning more than he or she deserves.
In practice, markets are what economists call imperfect, so prices and
wages are often set by the powerful and paid by the weak.
In the prevailing view, prices are set by supply and demand, and any
deviation from what is considered the competitive price (based on
marginal revenues) must be due to some imperfection which, if removed,
will produce the correct distribution of income between actors. The
possibility that some activities perpetually earn rent because they are
perceived as valuable, while actually blocking the creation of value and/or
destroying existing value, is hardly discussed.
Indeed, for economists there is no longer any story other than that of the
subjective theory of value, with the market driven by supply and demand.
Once impediments to competition are removed, the outcome should
benefit everyone. How different notions of value might affect the
distribution of revenues between workers, public agencies, managers and
shareholders at, say, Google, General Electric or BAE Systems, goes
unquestioned.
Third, in trying to steer the economy in particular directions,
policymakers are – whether they recognize it or not – inevitably influenced
by ideas about value. The rate of GDP growth is obviously important in a
world where billions of people still live in dire poverty. But some of the
most important economic questions today are about how to achieve a
particular type of growth. Today, there is a lot of talk about the need to
make growth ‘smarter’ (led by investments in innovation), more
sustainable (greener) and more inclusive (producing less inequality).19
Contrary to the widespread assumption that policy should be
directionless, simply removing barriers and focusing on ‘levelling the
playing field’ for businesses, an immense amount of policymaking is
needed to reach these particular objectives. Growth will not somehow go
in this direction by itself. Different types of policy are needed to tilt the
playing field in the direction deemed desirable. This is very different from
the usual assumption that policy should be directionless, simply removing
barriers so that businesses can get on with smooth production.
Deciding which activities are more important than others is critical in
setting a direction for the economy: put simply, those activities thought to
be more important in achieving particular objectives have to be increased
and less important ones reduced. We already do this. Certain types of tax
credits, for, say, R&D, try to stimulate more investment in innovation. We
subsidize education and training for students because as a society we want
more young people to go to university or enter the workforce with better
skills. Behind such policies may be economic models that show how
investment in ‘human capital’ – people’s knowledge and capabilities –
benefits a country’s growth by increasing its productive capacity.
Similarly, today’s deepening concern that the financial sector in some
countries is too large – compared, for example, to manufacturing – might
be informed by theories of what kind of economy we want to be living in
and the size and role of finance within it.
But the distinction between productive and unproductive activities has
rarely been the result of ‘scientific’ measurement. Rather, ascribing value,
or the lack of it, has always involved malleable socio-economic arguments
which derive from a particular political perspective – which is sometimes
explicit, sometimes not. The definition of value is always as much about
politics, and about particular views on how society ought to be
constructed, as it is about narrowly defined economics. Measurements are
not neutral: they affect behaviour and vice versa (this is the concept of
performativity which we encountered in the Preface).
So the point is not to create a stark divide, labelling some activities as
productive and categorizing others as unproductive rent-seeking. I believe
we must instead be more forthright in linking our understanding of value
creation to the way in which activities (whether in the financial sector or
the real economy) should be structured, and how this is connected to the
distribution of the rewards generated. Only in this way will the current
narrative about value creation be subject to greater scrutiny, and
statements such as ‘I am a wealth creator’ measured against credible ideas
about where that wealth comes from. A pharmaceutical company’s value-
based pricing might then be scrutinized with a more collective value-
creation process in mind, one in which public money funds a large portion
of pharmaceutical research – from which that company benefits – in the
highest-risk stage. Similarly, the 20 per cent share that venture capitalists
usually get when a high-tech small company goes public on the stock
market may be seen as excessive in light of the actual, not mythological,
risk they have taken in investing in the company’s development. And if an
investment bank makes an enormous profit from the exchange rate
instability that affects a country, that profit can be seen as what it really is:
rent.
In order to arrive at this understanding of value creation, however, we
need to go beyond seemingly scientific categorizations of activities and
look at the socio-economic and political conflicts that underlie them.
Indeed, claims about value creation have always been linked to assertions
about the relative productiveness of certain elements of society, often
related to fundamental shifts in the underlying economy: from agricultural
to industrial, or from a mass-production-based economy to one based on
digital technology.
There is one sort of labour which adds to the value of the subject upon which it is
bestowed: there is another which has no such effect. The former, as it produces a value,
may be called productive; the latter, unproductive labour.
Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations (1776)
Since ancient times, humanity has divided its economic activity into two
types: productive and unproductive, virtuous and vile, industrious and
lazy. The touchstone was generally what kind of activity was thought to
further the common good. In the fourth century BC, Aristotle distinguished
a variety of more or less virtuous jobs, depending on the class (citizen or
slave) of the ancient Greek polis dweller.1 In the New Testament, the
apostle Matthew reported that Jesus said it was ‘easier for a camel to go
through the eye of a needle than for a rich man to enter into the Kingdom
of God’.2 During the Middle Ages, the Church disparaged and even
denounced moneylenders and merchants who ‘bought cheap and sold
dear’;3 while they may not have been lazy, they were considered
unproductive and vile.
Pre-modern definitions of what work was or was not useful were never
clear-cut. With the onset of colonialism in the sixteenth century these
definitions became even more blurred. European colonial conquest and the
protection of trade routes with newly annexed lands were expensive.
Governments had to find the money for armies, bureaucracies and the
purchase of exotic merchandise. But help seemed to be at hand:
extraordinary amounts of gold and silver were discovered in the Americas,
and a vast treasure poured into Europe. As these precious metals
represented wealth and prosperity, it seemed that whoever bought, owned
and controlled the supply of them and the currencies minted from them
was engaged in productive activities.
Scholars and politicians of the time who argued that accumulating
precious metals was the route to national power and prosperity are called
mercantilists (from mercator, the Latin word for merchant), because they
espoused protectionist trade policies and positive trade balances to
stimulate the inflow, and prevent the outflow, of gold and silver. The best-
known English advocate of mercantilism was a merchant and director of
the East India Company called Sir Thomas Mun (1571–1641). In his
influential book England’s Treasure by Forraign Trade, Mun summed up
the mercantilist doctrine: we must, he said, ‘sell more to strangers yearly
than wee consume of theirs in value’.4
Mercantilists also defended the growth of national government as
necessary to fund wars and expeditions to keep trade routes open and to
control colonial markets. In England, Holland and France, mercantilists
advocated shipping Acts, such as England’s Navigation Act of 1651,
which forced their countries’ and colonies’ trade exclusively into ships
flying the national flag.
As mercantilist thinking developed, and people started to conceive of
wealth production in national terms, the first estimates of national income
– the total amount everyone in the country earned – started to appear.
Seventeenth-century Britain saw two groundbreaking attempts to quantify
national income. One was by Sir William Petty (1623–87), an adventurer,
anatomist, physician and Member of Parliament, who was a tax
administrator in Ireland under Oliver Cromwell’s Commonwealth
government.5 The other was by the herald Gregory King (1648–1712), a
genealogist, engraver and statistician whose work on enacting a new tax on
marriages, births and burials provoked his interest in national accounting.
Petty and King were ingenious in their use of incomplete and messy
data to generate surprisingly detailed income estimates. They had to work
with rudimentary government tax figures, estimates of population and
patchy statistics on the consumption of basic commodities such as corn,
wheat and beer. What their estimates lacked, however, was a clear value
theory: Petty and King were concerned only with calculating the nation’s
output, not with how that output came about. Nevertheless, their attempts
at national accounting were unprecedented and laid the foundations for
modern national accounts.
In the 1660s, as Petty worked on his income studies, England was
emerging from its experiment with republicanism, and was struggling with
Holland and France for supremacy at sea. Petty wanted to find out whether
England had the resources to survive these threats to its security: as he put
it, to ‘prove mathematically that the [English] State could raise a much
larger revenue from taxes to finance its peace and wartime needs’,6
because he believed the country was richer than commonly thought.
Petty made a decisive breakthrough. He realized that income and
expenditure at the national level should be the same. He understood that, if
you treat a country as a closed system, each pound one person spends in it
is another person’s income of one pound. It was the first time anyone had
grasped and worked with this fundamental insight. To make up for the lack
of available statistics, Petty worked on the assumption that a nation’s
income is equal to its expenditure (omitting savings in good times,
although he was aware of the potential discrepancy).7 That meant he could
use expenditure per person, multiplied by population, to arrive at the
nation’s income. In so doing he started, implicitly, to impose a production
boundary, including within it only money spent on the production of
‘Food, Housing, Cloaths, and all other necessaries’.8 All other
‘unnecessary expenses’, as defined by Petty, were omitted.
In this way, by extension, Petty came to see any branch of the economy
that did not produce those necessities as unproductive, adding nothing to
national income. As he worked, his idea of the production boundary began
to crystallize further, with ‘Husbandmen, Seamen, Soldiers, Artizans and
Merchants … the very Pillars of any Common-Wealth’ on one side; and
‘all the other great Professions’ which ‘do rise out of the infirmities and
miscarriages of these’ on the other.9 By ‘great professions’ Petty meant
lawyers, clergymen, civil servants, lords and the like. In other words, for
Petty some ‘great professions’ were merely a necessary evil – needed
simply for facilitating production and for maintaining the status quo – but
not really essential to production or exchange. Although Petty did not
believe that policy should be focused on controlling imports and exports,
the mercantilists influenced him heavily. ‘Merchandise’, he argued, was
more productive than manufacture and husbandry; the Dutch, he noted
approvingly, outsourced their husbandry to Poland and Denmark, enabling
them to focus on more productive ‘Trades and curious Arts’.10 England, he
concluded, would also benefit if more husbandmen became merchants.11
In the late 1690s, after the first publication of Petty’s work Political
Arithmetick, Gregory King made more detailed estimates of England’s
income. Like Petty, King was concerned with England’s war-making
potential and compared the country’s income with those of France and
Holland. Drawing on a wide variety of sources, he meticulously calculated
the income and expenditure of some twenty different occupation groups in
the country, from the aristocracy to lawyers, merchants to paupers. He
even made forecasts, for example of population, predating the arrival of
the forecasting ‘science’ some 250 years later, and estimated the crop yield
of important agricultural items.
As in Petty’s work, an implicit production boundary began to emerge
when King assessed productivity, which he defined as income being
greater than expenditure. King thought merchant traders were the most
productive group, their income being a quarter more than their
expenditure, followed by the ‘temporal and spiritual lords’, then by a
variety of prestigious professions. On the boundary were farmers, who
earned almost no more than they spent. Firmly on the ‘unproductive’ side
were seamen, labourers, servants, cottagers, paupers and ‘common
soldiers’.12 In King’s view, the unproductive masses, representing slightly
more than half the total population, were leeches on the public wealth
because they consumed more than they produced.
Figure 2 shows that there were discrepancies between the ‘productive’
professions Petty and King identified. Almost all the professions Petty
deemed unproductive King later saw as productive, while several of those
producing value for Petty – seamen, soldiers and unskilled labourers – did
not make the cut in King’s analysis. Their different views may have
stemmed from their backgrounds. A man of humble origins and republican
instincts, Petty started out serving Oliver Cromwell; moving in aristocratic
and court circles, King was perhaps less inclined to think that Petty’s
‘great professions’ were unproductive. Both, however, classed ‘vagrants’
as unproductive, an analysis that has parallels today with people receiving
welfare from governments financed by taxes on the productive sectors.
Some of Petty’s and King’s ideas have proved remarkably durable.13
Perhaps most importantly, in what they both called ‘Political Arithmetick’
they laid the basis for what we today call the ‘national accounts’ to
calculate GDP, the compass by which countries attempt to steer their
national economic ships.
Figure 2. The production boundary in the 1600s
The first efforts to find a formal theory of value came in the mid-
eighteenth century from the court of Louis XV of France, in the twilight –
so it turned out – of that country’s absolute monarchy. There, François
Quesnay (1694–1774), often described as the ‘father of economics’, was
the king’s physician and adviser. He used his medical training to
understand the economy as a ‘metabolic’ system. Crucially, in metabolism,
everything must come from somewhere and go somewhere – and that, for
Quesnay, included wealth. Quesnay’s approach led him to formulate the
first systematic theory of value that classified who is and is not productive
in an economy, and to model how the entire economy could reproduce
itself from the value generated by a small group of its members. In his
seminal work Tableau Économique, published in 1758, he constructed an
‘economic table’ which showed how new value was created and circulated
in the economy. In it he continued the metabolic analogy: pumps were
drawn to signify the ways in which new value was introduced, and
outgoing tubes illustrated how value left the system.
At the time Quesnay wrote, French society was already facing the
problems that would lead to the French Revolution fifteen years after his
death. French agriculture was in a bad state. Farmers were choked by high
taxes, imposed by their usually noble landlords to fund their lavish
lifestyles and by central government to finance war and trade. Adding to
this burden, the French government’s mercantilist policy, faced with a now
aggressively expanding Britain, kept the prices of agricultural produce low
to provide cheap subsistence to domestic manufactures, which could in
turn be cheaply made and exported in exchange for the highly coveted
gold, still generally believed to be a measure of national wealth. Faced
with this situation, Quesnay and his followers built a powerful argument in
favour of the farmers and against the mercantilists. Though they came to
be known as the physiocrats, after one of Quesnay’s publications, they
called themselves something else: ‘Les Économistes’.
Contrasting sharply with the prevailing mercantilist thinking that gave
gold a privileged place, Quesnay believed that land was the source of all
value. Figure 3 illustrates how for him, in the end, everything that
nourished humans came from the earth. He pointed out that, unlike
humans, Nature actually produced new things: grain out of small seeds for
food, trees out of saplings and mineral ores from the earth from which
houses and ships and machinery were built. By contrast, humans could not
produce value. They could only transform it: bread from seeds, timber
from wood, steel from iron. Since agriculture, husbandry, fishing, hunting
and mining (all in the darker blob in Figure 3) bring Nature’s bounty to
society, Quesnay called them the ‘productive class’. By contrast, he
thought that nearly all other sectors of the economy – households,
government, services and even industry, lumped together in the lighter
blob – were unproductive.
Quesnay’s classification was revolutionary. Breaking away from the
mercantilists, who placed exchange and what was gained from it – gold –
at the centre of value creation, he now linked value creation inextricably
with production. Developing his classification of productive and
unproductive work, Quesnay grouped society into three classes. First came
farmers and related occupations working on the land and water; according
to Quesnay, this was the only productive class. Next were manufacturers,
artisans and related workers who transform the materials they receive from
the productive class: wood and stone for furniture and houses, sheep’s
wool for clothing and metals from the mines for tools.15 Yet, argued
Quesnay, this class did not add value; rather, their work merely
recirculated existing value. The third class was the unproductive
‘proprietor’, ‘distributive’ or ‘sterile’ class, which was made up of
landlords, nobility and clergy. Here, ‘distributive’ was meant pejoratively:
this class redistributes value, but only to itself, for the sole reason that it
owns the land and does not give anything in return.16
Figure 3. The production boundary in the 1700s
Most significant is how the table neatly shows, from row to row, that as
long as what is produced is greater than what is consumed, an amount will
be left over at the end to be reinvested, thereby allowing the economy to
continue reproducing itself. If any of the unproductive members of society
take too much, reducing the amount the farmer can reinvest in production,
the economy will grind to a halt. In other words, if value extraction by the
unproductive members exceeds value creation by the productive members,
growth stops.
Though he himself did not use the term, Quesnay’s theory of value
incorporates a very clear production boundary, the first to be drawn with
such precision, which makes it clear that the surplus the ‘productive’
sectors generate enables everyone else to live.
Other economists quickly weighed in with analysis and criticism of
Quesnay’s classification. Their attack centred on Quesnay’s labelling of
artisans and workers as ‘sterile’: a term that served Quesnay’s political
ends of defending the existing agrarian social order, but contradicted the
everyday experience of a great number of people. Refining Quesnay’s
thinking, his contemporary A. R. J. Turgot retained the notion that all
value came from the land, but noted the important role of artisans in
keeping society afloat. He also recognized that there were other ‘general
needs’ that some people had to fulfil – such as judges to administer justice
– and that these functions were essential for value creation. Accordingly,
he re-labelled Quesnay’s ‘sterile’ class as the ‘stipendiary’, or waged,
class. And, since rich landowners could decide whether to carry out work
themselves or hire others to do so using revenues from the land, Turgot
labelled them the ‘disposable class’. He also added the refinement that
some farmers or artisans would employ others and make a profit. As
farmers move from tilling the land to employing others, he argued, they
remain productive and receive profits on their enterprise. It is only when
they give up on overseeing farming altogether and simply live on their rent
that they become ‘disposable’ rent collectors. Turgot’s more refined
analysis therefore placed emphasis on the character of the work being
done, rather than the category of work itself.
Turgot’s refinements were highly significant. In them, we see the
emergent categories of wages, profits and rents: an explicit reference to the
distribution of wealth and income that would become one of the
cornerstones of economic thought in the centuries to come, and which is
still used in national income accounting today. Yet, for Turgot, land
remained the source of value: those who did not work it could not be
included in the production boundary.19
Quesnay and Turgot’s almost complete identification of productivity
with the agricultural sector had an overriding aim. Their restrictive
production boundary gave the landed aristocracy ammunition to use
against mercantilism, which favoured the merchant class, and fitted an
agricultural society better than an industrial one. Given the physiocrats’
disregard for industry, it is hardly surprising that the most significant
critique of their ideas came from the nation where it was already clear that
value was not just produced in agriculture, but in other emerging sectors: a
rapidly industrializing Britain. The most influential critic of all was
Quesnay’s contemporary, a man who had travelled in France and talked at
length with him: Adam Smith.
These insights were original and profound. Smith was writing while the
Industrial Revolution introduced machines into factories on a large scale.
When harnessed to the division of labour, mechanization would radically
increase productivity – the principal engine of economic growth. But even
the simple reorganization of labour, without machinery, by which each
worker specialized and developed skills in a specific area, enabled Smith
to make this critical point.
Equally significant was Smith’s analysis of how the ‘market’ determines
the way in which consumers and producers interact. Such interaction, he
contended, was not down to ‘benevolence’ or central planning.21 Rather, it
was due to the ‘invisible hand’ of the market:
Every individual is continually exerting himself to find out the most advantageous
employment for whatever capital he can command. It is his own advantage, indeed, and
not that of the society which he has in view. But the study of his own advantage
naturally, or rather necessarily, leads him to prefer that employment which is most
advantageous to society … He intends only his own gain, and he is in this, as in many
other cases, led by an invisible hand to promote an end which was not part of his
intention.22
Like Quesnay, Smith launched a more general attack on mercantilist
policies which, he argued, restricted competition and trade. He also argued
strongly for policies that would increase savings, and hence the amount of
capital available for investment rather than unproductive consumption
(say, on luxuries). But for Smith, industrial workers – not, as for Quesnay,
farmers – were at the heart of the productive economy. Manufacturing
labour, not land, was the source of value.23 The labour theory of value was
born.
Smith has become the figurehead of much modern economic theory
because of his ideas about how capitalism is founded on supposedly
immutable human behaviour, notably self-interest, and competition in a
market economy. His metaphor of the ‘invisible hand’ has been cited ad
nauseam to support the current orthodoxy that markets, left to themselves,
may lead to a socially optimal outcome – indeed, more beneficial than if
the state intervenes.
Smith’s book is actually a collection of recipes for politicians and
policymakers. Far from leaving everything to the market, he thinks of
himself as giving guidance to ‘statesmen’ on how to act to ‘enrich both the
people and the sovereign’24 – how to increase the wealth of nations. This is
where Smith’s value theory enters the picture. He was convinced that
growth depended on increasing the relative share of ‘manufactures’ –
factories employing formerly independent artisans or agricultural workers
as dependent wage labourers – in the overall make-up of industry and
believed that free trade was essential to bring this about. He felt that the
enemies of growth were, first, the protectionist policies of mercantilists;
second, the guilds protecting artisans’ privileges; and third, a nobility that
squandered its money on unproductive labour and lavish consumption. For
Smith (as for Quesnay), employing an overly large portion of labour for
unproductive purposes – such as the hoarding of cash, a practice that still
afflicts our modern economies – prevents a nation from accumulating
wealth.
Value, Smith believed, was proportional to the time spent by workers on
production. For the purposes of his theory, Smith assumed a worker of
average speed. Figure 5 shows how he drew a clear line (the production
boundary) between productive and unproductive labour. For him, the
boundary lay between material production – agriculture, manufacturing,
mining in the figure’s darker blob – and immaterial production in the
lighter blob. The latter included all types of services (lawyers, carters,
officials and so on) that were useful to manufactures, but were not actually
involved in production itself. Smith said as much: labour, he suggested, is
productive when it is ‘realized’ in a permanent object.25 His positioning of
government on the ‘unproductive’ side of the boundary set the tone for
much subsequent analysis and is a recurring theme in today’s debates
about government’s role in the economy, epitomized by the Thatcher–
Reagan reassertion in the 1980s of the primacy of markets in solving
economic and social issues.
… the distribution of the income of society is controlled by a natural law … this law, if it
worked without friction, would give to every agent of production the amount of wealth
which that agent creates.
J. B. Clark, The Distribution of Wealth: A Theory of Wages, Interest and Profits1
Prices, then, reflect the utility that buyers get from things. The scarcer they
are – the higher their marginal utility – the more consumers will be willing
to pay for them. These changes in the marginal utility of a product came to
be known as consumer ‘preference’. The same principle applies to
producers. ‘Marginal productivity’ is the effect that an extra unit of
produced goods would have on the costs of production. The marginal cost
of each extra Mars Bar that rolls off the production line is lower than the
cost of the previous one.
This concept of marginalism lies at the heart of what is known today as
‘neoclassical’ theory – the set of ideas that followed the classical theory
developed by Smith and Ricardo and was extended by Marx. The term
neoclassical reflected how the new theorists stood on the shoulders of
giants but then took the theory in new directions. Microeconomic theory,
the theory of how firms, workers and consumers make choices, is based on
the neoclassical theory of production and consumption which rests on the
maximization of profits (firms), and utility (consumers and workers).
As a mathematician, Marshall used mathematical calculus, borrowed
from Newtonian physics, to develop his theory of how an economy
worked. In his model, the point at which a consumer’s money is worth
more to him or her than the additional (marginal) unit of a commodity
(that next Mars Bar) that their money would purchase, is where the system
is in ‘equilibrium’, an idea reminiscent of Newton’s description of how
gravity held the universe together. The smooth, continuous curves of these
equilibrating and evolutionary forces depict a system that is peaceful and
potentially ‘optimal’. The inclusion of concepts like equilibria in the
neoclassical model had the effect of portraying capitalism as a peaceful
system driven by self-equilibrating competitive mechanisms – a stark
contrast to the ways in which the system was depicted by Marx, as a battle
between classes, full of disequilibria and far from optimal, whose resulting
revolutions would have been better described by Erwin Schrödinger’s
concept of quantum leaps and wave mechanics.
So keen was Marshall to emphasize the equilibrating and evolutionary
forces in economics, with their smooth, continuous curves that could be
described by mathematical calculus, that the epigraph of his 1890
Principles of Economics was the Latin tag Natura non facit saltum, a nod
to its use by Darwin in his 1859 On the Origin of Species to make the point
that Nature, rather than progressing in leaps and bounds, evolves in
incremental steps, building on previous changes.
The equilibrium concept had a lot of appeal at the start of the twentieth
century, when the rise of socialism and trade unions in Europe threatened
the old, often autocratic, order and the conventional wisdom was that
capitalism was largely self-regulating and government involvement was
unnecessary or even dangerous.
Equilibrium was predicated on the notion of scarcity, and the effect of
scarcity on diminishing returns: the more you consume, the less you enjoy
each unit of consumption after a certain amount (the maximum
enjoyment); and the more you produce, the less you profit from each
marginal unit produced (the maximum profit). It is this concept of
diminishing returns that allows economists today to draw smooth curves in
diagrams, using mathematical calculus, so that maxima and minima points
(e.g., the bottom of a U-shaped curve showing how costs change with
increased production) provide the equilibrium targets and utility
maximization.
Nineteenth-century economists liked to illustrate the importance of
scarcity to value by using the water and diamond paradox. Why is water
cheap, even though it is necessary for human life, and diamonds are
expensive and therefore of high value, even though humans can quite
easily get by without them? Marx’s labour theory of value – naïvely
applied – would argue that diamonds simply take a lot more time and
effort to produce. But the new utility theory of value, as the marginalists
defined it, explained the difference in price through the scarcity of
diamonds. Where there is an abundance of water, it is cheap. Where there
is a scarcity (as in a desert), its value can become very high. For the
marginalists, this scarcity theory of value became the rationale for the
price of everything, from diamonds, to water, to workers’ wages.
The idea of scarcity became so important to economists that in the early
1930s it prompted one influential British economist, Lionel Robbins
(1898–1984), Professor of Economics at the London School of Economics,
to define the study of economics itself in terms of scarcity; his description
of it as ‘the study of the allocation of resources, under conditions of
scarcity’ is still widely used.8 The emergence of marginalism was a pivotal
moment in the history of economic thought, one that laid the foundations
for today’s dominant economic theory.
What we measure affects what we do; and if our measurements are flawed, decisions
may be distorted.
Joseph Stiglitz, Amartya Sen and Jean-Paul Fitoussi, Mismeasuring Our Lives (2010)
After the Second World War, formal international rules were drawn up,
standardizing national accounting for production, income and expenditure.
The first version of the SNA, compiled by the United Nations, appeared in
1953.12 The SNA describes itself as ‘a statistical framework that provides a
comprehensive, consistent and flexible set of macroeconomic accounts for
policymaking, analysis and research purposes’.13 It defines national
accounting as measuring ‘what takes place in the economy, between which
agents, and for what purpose’; at its heart ‘is the production of goods and
services’.14 GDP is ‘[i]n simple terms, the amount of value added
generated by production’.15 It is defined explicitly as a measure of value
creation. It can therefore be said that the national accounts, too, have a
production boundary.
The SNA’s emergence in the early post-war years owed much to recent
economic, political and intellectual developments. The experience of
depression and war weighed heavily on policymakers’ minds. Many
countries saw wartime planning, which was based on unprecedented
amounts of economic information, as a success. Political pressures were
important too. In the US, the New Deal of the 1930s and full employment
during the war led many voters to believe that government could intervene
benignly and progressively in the economy. In Europe, the strength of left-
wing parties after the war – exemplified by the Labour Party’s 1945
election victory in the UK – also changed, and marked a change in,
people’s attitudes, and made fuller and more accurate national accounts
essential. The crucial question was, and remains: on what theory of value
were they based?
‘Simple’ national income estimates had to add up the price of
production (minus intermediate goods) in the economy, or incomes, or the
expenditure of all economic actors on final goods: National Production =
National Income = National Expenditure. In order to carry out this
estimate, we might have expected the SNA’s authors to use as their
methodology the prevailing economic theory of value, marginal utility.
But they didn’t – or, at least, not fully. In fact, the resulting model was,
and is, a strange muddle in which utility is the major, but not the only,
ingredient.
The SNA brings together various different ways of assessing the
national income that had developed over centuries of economic thinking.
Decisions about what gets included in the production boundary have been
described as ‘ad hoc’,16 while national accountants admit that the SNA
rules on production are ‘a mix of convention, judgment about data
adequacy, and consensus about economic theory’.17 These include devising
solutions based on ‘common sense’; making assumptions in the name of
‘computational convenience’ – which has important consequences for the
actual numbers we come up with when assessing economic growth; and
lobbying by particular economic interests.
In fairness, there have always been practical reasons for this ad hoc
approach. Aspects of the economy, from R&D and housework to the
environment and the black economy, proved difficult to assess using
marginal utility. It was clear that a comprehensive national accounting
system would have to include incomes from both market exchange and
non-market exchange – in particular, government. With market-mediated
activity lying at the heart of the marginalist concept of value, most
estimators of national income wanted to adopt a broader approach.18
For simplicity’s sake we will ignore the contribution of net exports. Two
observations are in order: first, on the expenditure side, companies only
appear as investors (demanding final investment goods from other
companies). The remainder of spending (aggregate demand) is split
between households and the government. Government expenditure is only
what it spends itself; that is, excluding the transfers it makes to households
(such as pensions or unemployment benefits). It is its collective
consumption expenditure on behalf of the community. By focusing on
government only in terms of the spending, it is by definition assumed to be
‘unproductive’ – outside the production boundary.
Apart from this curious view of government, the national accounts expose
a number of other accounting oddities. GDP, for instance, does not clearly
distinguish a cost from an investment in future capacity, such as R&D;
services valuable to the economy such as ‘care’ may be exchanged without
any payment, making them invisible to GDP calculators; likewise, illegal
black-market activities may constitute a large part of an economy. A
resource that is destroyed by pollution may not be counted as a subtraction
from GDP – but when pollution is cleaned up by marketed services, GDP
increases. And then there’s the biggest oddity of all: the financial sector.
Does the financial sector simply facilitate the exchange of existing
value, or does it create new value? As we will see in Chapters 4 and 5, this
is the billion-dollar question: if it’s answered wrongly, it may be that the
growing size of the financial sector reflects not an increase of growth, but
rent being captured by some actors in the economy. First, however, there
are some other inconsistencies to be considered.
Investment in Future Capacity
First, let’s look at how R&D is dealt with in the national accounts. Before
2008, the SNA considered in-house R&D to be an input into production24
– in other words, a company’s spending on R&D (research equipment,
laboratories, staff and the like) was treated as a cost and subtracted from
the company’s final output. However, in the 2008 version of the SNA, in-
house R&D was reclassified as an investment in the company’s stock of
knowledge, to be valued ‘on the basis of the total production costs
including the costs of fixed assets used in production’.25 It became a final
productive activity rather than just an intermediate cost towards that
activity.
The SNA’s decision to reclassify R&D was justified less by value
theory than by ‘common-sense’ reasoning: the contribution of ‘knowledge’
to production seemed to be significant, and should therefore be recognized.
R&D was made productive because it was considered important.
As a result, since 2008 GDP has been enlarged by the annual cost of
R&D, including the depreciation of fixed assets used. When in 2013 the
US implemented this change, the value from R&D added $400 billion –
2.5 per cent of US GDP – to national income overnight.26 Of course, those
sectors with the largest R&D contributions improved their share of GDP,
making them look more important than others.
If the UK financial system thrives in the post-Brexit world, which is the plan, it will not
be ten times GDP, it will be fifteen to twenty times GDP in another quarter of a century.
Mark Carney, Governor of the Bank of England, 3 August 2017
A large and growing financial sector has long been presented as a sign of
UK and US success, credited with mobilizing capital to drive their
economic development and generating exports at a time when
manufacturing and farming had declined into net import. In the 1990s,
comparable financial-sector expansion became an ambition for other
countries seeking to follow the development path of these early
industrializers, and to lessen dependence on the import of capital and
services from the world’s ‘financial centres’ located in the UK and the US.
Underpinning this expansion is the belief that a country benefits from an
ever-growing financial sector, in terms of its growing contribution to GDP
and exports, and as total financial-sector assets (bank loans, equities,
bonds and derivatives) become an ever-larger multiple of GDP.
The celebration of finance by political leaders and expert bankers is,
however, not universally shared among economists. It clashes with the
common experience of business investors and households, for whom
financial institutions’ control of the flow of money seems to guarantee the
institutions’ own prosperity far more readily than that of their customers.
For those without large fortunes and for many with ‘assets under
management’, the notion of finance adding value has rung increasingly
hollow in the long shadow of the global financial crisis that began in 2008.
This required governments around the world to rescue major banks whose
‘net worth’ had turned out to be fictitious; with the bailouts continuing to
impose heavy social costs, ten years on, in the form of squeezed public
budgets, heavy household debt and negative real returns for savers.
But for much of recent human history, in stark contrast to the current
enthusiasm for financial-sector growth as a sign of (and spur to)
prosperity, banks and financial markets were long regarded as a cost of
doing business. Their profits reflected added value only to the extent that
they improved the allocation of a country’s resources, and cross-subsidized
a reliable payments system. Recurrent financial crises exposed the
regularity with which they threw resources in unproductive directions
(basically to other parts of the financial sector itself), ultimately disrupting
the flow of money and goods in the real economy. The fastest-growing
financial activities in 1980–2008 were asset management (making more
money by investing in liquid financial assets and property, for the segment
of the population earning enough to save) and lending to households,
rather than to businesses. Finance also diverted many highly trained
scientists and engineers away from work in direct production, by offering
them on average 70 per cent more pay than other sectors could afford. The
improbable level to which financial-sector profits rose, before and after the
latest crisis, reflects a deliberate decision during the twentieth century to
redraw the production boundary, so that previously excluded financial
institutions were now included within it – and, having redesignated finance
as productive, to strip away the regulations that had previously kept its
charging and risk-taking under control.
The current chapter looks at the expansion of banking, and the way in
which political decisions to recognize its value in national accounts
(although based on economically contentious assumptions) helped to drive
a deregulation which fuelled its ultimately over-reaching growth. In the
next two chapters I explore the relationship between this growth and the
financialization of the rest of the economy.
Back in the mid-1980s, to try to prevent the banking system from moving
to speculative finance, Hyman Minsky formulated an economic recipe that
can be summarized as ‘big government, big bank’. In his vision,
government creates jobs by being the ‘employer of last resort’ and
underwrites distressed financial operators’ balance sheets by being the
‘lender of last resort’.28 When the financial sector is so interconnected, it is
very possible for one bank’s failure to become contagious, leading to the
bankruptcy of banks all over the world. In order to avoid this ‘butterfly
effect’, Minsky favoured strong regulation of financial intermediaries. In
this he followed his mentor Keynes, who, as the post-war international
order was being devised at Bretton Woods in 1944, advocated ‘the
restoration of international loans and credit for legitimate purposes’, while
stressing the necessity of ‘controlling short-term speculative movements or
flights of currency whether out of debtor countries or from one creditor
country to another’.29
According to Keynes and Minsky, the possibility of financial crisis was
always present in the way that money circulated – not as a means of
exchange, but as an end in itself (an idea based predominantly on Marx’s
thinking). They believed that government had to intervene to avert or
manage crises. Although controversial in the 1930s (due to its undertones
of ‘socialism’ and central planning) and later (after the revival of free-
market economics, including the idea of unregulated ‘free’ banking), the
idea of intervention in markets was hardly novel or radical. Back in the
eighteenth century, Adam Smith’s belief that a free market was one free
from rent implied government action to eliminate rent. Modern-day free
marketeers, who have gagged Smith while claiming his mantle, would not
agree with him.
Financial regulators have focused on introducing more competition –
through the break-up of large banks and the entry of new ‘challenger
banks’ – as an essential step towards preventing another financial crisis.
But this ‘quantity theory of competition’ – the assumption that the problem
is just size and numbers, and not fundamental behaviour – avoids the
uncomfortable reality that crises develop from the uncoordinated
interaction of numerous players.
There is danger in a complex system with many players. Greater
stability might be achieved when a few large companies serve the real
economy, subject to heavy regulation in order to make sure that they
concentrate on value creation and not value extraction. By contrast,
deregulation designed to reinvigorate a part of the financial sector may
well promote risk-taking behaviour – the opposite of what is intended.
Lord Adair Turner, who took over as Chair of the UK financial regulator
(then called the Financial Services Authority) in 2008, just as the system
was crashing around it, reflected when the dust settled that: ‘financial
services (particularly wholesale trading activities) include a large share of
highly remunerated activities that are purely distributive in their indirect
effects … the ability of national income accounts to distinguish between
activities that are meaningfully value-creative and activities that are
essentially distributive rent extraction is far from perfect’.30
Neither William J. Baumol (1922–2017), whose descriptions of
‘unproductive entrepreneurship’ could account for much financial activity
but who is now a leading contributor to mainstream portfolio and capital-
market theory, nor Turner, despite his subsequent leading role in the
Institute for New Economic Thinking, discuss finance much in terms of
value theory. Yet their thinking implies that finance should be
fundamentally reformed to create value inside the production boundary,
and that those of its elements outside the boundary should be drastically
reduced, eliminated or competed away. Lord Turner’s more considered
verdict, ten years on from the start of the crisis, was to bemoan the ever
larger amount of debt needed to add an extra dollar to GDP, but then trace
much of this to the bad aggregate effects of essentially good lending,
which ‘private lenders do not and cannot be expected to take into account’.
His prescriptions, requiring more and smarter financial regulation to
monitor and control the system’s aggregate risks, actually imply additional
and permanent effort by public authorities to make the marketplace safe
for private bank (and shadow-bank) profit.
Over the past decades, Keynes’s and Minsky’s insights and warnings
about the potentially destructive nature of an unbridled financial sector
have been totally ignored. Today, the economic mainstream continues to
argue that the bigger (measured by the number of actors) or ‘deeper’
financial markets are, the more likely they are to be efficient, revealing the
‘true’ price and therefore value of an asset in the sense defined by the
Nobel Prize-winning US economist Eugene Fama.31 An ‘efficient’ market
is, in Fama’s definition, one that prices every asset so that no further profit
can be made by buying and reselling it. This way of thinking reconciles the
case for large financial markets with the high incomes paid to employees
in financial services, because incomes supposedly reflect the huge benefits
of financial services to the economy.32
From the perspective of marginal utility, therefore, the expansion of
finance is highly desirable and should increase its value added, and hence
its positive contribution to GDP growth,33 even though it was only a
convenient decision to treat finance as productive in the national accounts
in the first place.34
But it is impossible to understand the rise of finance without analysing
the background dynamics which allowed it to thrive: deregulation and
rising inequality.
Since the 1970s, the growing inequality of wealth and income has
profoundly shaped the way in which finance has developed. The growth of
finance has also fed the growth of inequality, not least by adding to the
influence and lobbying power of financiers who tend to favour reduction
of taxes and social expenditures, and promoting the financial-market
volatility that boosts the fortunes of those who serially buy low and sell
high.
Following deregulation, the enormous increase in finance available to
households was the main reason for the rise in banks’ profits. Commercial
banks profited from direct loans for anything from cars to homes to
holidays, and from credit cards. Investment banks made money by
securitizing commercial-bank ‘products’ and trading the derivatives they
‘manufactured’. Legislators allowed financial intermediaries to regulate
themselves, or imposed only minimal regulation because their operations
were too complex to be understood. Markets (following the marginalists)
were considered to be ‘efficient’ – healthy competition would deter
financial intermediaries from reckless behaviour.
As previously prudent banks bombarded customers with offers of credit
– the age of tempting credit card promotions dropping almost daily
through millions of letter boxes had arrived – household borrowing began
to rise inexorably. Across the financial sector more broadly, the relaxation
of controls on mortgage lending became another source of profit and also
fuelled the increased household borrowing. Whereas in the 1970s
mortgages had been rationed in the UK, by the early 2000s house buyers
could borrow 100 per cent or even more of the value of a property. By
2016, total cumulative household borrowing in the UK had reached £1.5
trillion – about 83 per cent of national output, and equivalent to nearly
£30,000 for each adult in the land – well above average earnings.39
Governments rejoiced when banks offered mortgages to low-paid,
marginally employed home buyers on the assumption that their debt could
be ‘securitized’ and quickly resold to other investors. It seemed less a
reckless gamble and more a social innovation, helping to broaden property
ownership and boosting the ‘property-owning democracy’, while
increasing the flow of income to an already buoyant investor class. Greater
revenue from financial-sector incomes and associated high-end purchases
even pushed the US and UK government budgets into rare surpluses
around the turn of the twenty-first century.40
Loosening the availability of credit to sustain consumption is not in
itself a bad thing. But there are dangers. One is cost. It seemed to make
sense to relax controls on lending when interest rates were low or falling.
It makes less sense if borrowers, lulled into a sense of false security, are
caught out when interest rates rise. Another fundamental danger is the
tendency of the system to overexpand: for credit to become too readily
available, as the Bank for International Settlements has recently
recognized.41 The system is stable when the growth in debt is matched by
the growth in the value of assets whose purchase is financed by that debt.
As soon as people begin to have doubts about the assets’ value, however,
the cracks appear. That is what happened when US property prices
collapsed after the crash of 2008. Home owners may find themselves in
negative equity and even have their property repossessed, although not
before lenders have extracted rent in interest and loan repayments. But
banks can always choose to provide other services than loans. When
uncertainty about the future is high, they can even decide to hoard cash
rather than invest it – often a sound decision, as high interest rates are
associated with a high risk of not obtaining enough for the investment.
The rise in private debt in the US and UK has resulted in household
savings falling as a percentage of disposable income – income minus taxes
– especially in periods of sustained economic growth (during the 1980s,
the late 1990s and the beginning of the 2000s). Simultaneously, household
consumption expenditure has been buoyant. It has outpaced any rise in
disposable income, and its contribution to GDP has grown.42
Income inequality has been on the rise in most advanced economies,
especially in the US and in the UK, over the past four decades. Increasing
inequality in the US has taken three complementary forms.43 First, real
wages have fallen or stagnated for many low- and middle-income
households. For instance, OECD data on the US economy indicate that the
annual real minimum wage (in 2015 US dollars) fell from $19,237 in 1975
to $13,000 in 2005 (in 2016 it was $14,892). Second, in almost every
OECD country wage shares have declined by several percentage points in
favour of rising profit shares, even when real employee compensation has
gone up.44 As Figure 9 below shows, this was the result of average
productivity growth rising faster than average or median real-wage growth
in many countries, especially in the US.
Third, personal distribution of income and wealth has become more and
more unequal. In both the US and the UK, and in many other OECD
countries, those with the highest incomes have enjoyed an increasing share
of total national income ever since the 1970s, as can been seen in Figure
10. Furthermore, income distribution is extremely skewed towards very
high incomes, not just the top 10 per cent and 1 per cent, but especially the
top 0.1 per cent.45 Wealth distribution reveals a similar pattern. A 2017
Oxfam report, An Economy for the 99%, found that in 2016 eight men own
the same wealth as the poorest half of the world’s population. In a report
published a year earlier, An Economy for the 1%, Oxfam calculated that
the club of the wealthiest 1 per cent of individuals globally shrank from
388 members in 2010 to just sixty-two in 2015; in other words, the very
richest were getting even richer relative to others who were also by any
sensible standard very rich. The wealth of the sixty-two very richest
individuals increased by 45 per cent in the five years to 2015, a jump of
more than half a trillion dollars in total. Over the same period, the wealth
of the bottom half fell by just over a trillion dollars – a drop of 38 per
cent.48
Figure 9. Labour productivity and wages in the US since 1974 (left) and the UK since 1972
(right)46
Figure 11. Household debt and income in the US and the UK, 1995–200549
CONCLUSION
By the late twentieth century, finance was perceived as being much more
productive than before. Finance, too, became increasingly valuable to
policymakers, in order to maintain economic growth and manage
inequality of wealth and income. The cost was mounting household debt
and increasing government dependence on tax revenues from the financial
sector.
To ignore the question of value in relation to finance is, then, highly
irresponsible. But in the end, the real challenge is not to label finance as
value-creating or value-extracting, but to fundamentally transform it so
that it is genuinely value-creating. This requires paying attention to
characteristics such as timeframe. Impatient finance – the quest for short-
term returns – can hurt the productive capacity of the economy and its
potential for innovation.
Indeed, the crash of 2008 vindicated the warnings of Keynes, Minsky
and others about the dangers of excessive financialization. Yet while the
crash and the ensuing crisis weakened banks, it still left them in a
dominant position in the economy, sparing the embarrassment of those
who had extolled the value of financial services in the years before they
imploded into bankruptcy and fraud.
In the intervening years, there has, unsurprisingly, been a regulatory
reversal – or at least a partial one. Under political pressure, and
recognizing that they may have gone too far in allowing commercial and
investment banks to share the same roof, regulators in the US and Europe
have since 2008 sought to distance one from the other. Reforms such as
the US Dodd–Frank Act of 2010 attempt to prevent investment banks from
using the deposits of their commercial-bank parents (which are ultimately
backed by government under deposit insurance schemes) to finance their
riskier income-generating activities. New rules have tried, at least partly,
to steer investment banks back to their original function of using borrowed
money raised in wholesale markets to finance risky transactions – which
even mainstream economists sometimes liken to a casino.
Yet today financialization appears to be thriving again despite its
questionable productivity. Financialization remains a powerful force and
its capacity for value extraction is scarcely diminished. Attempts to end
excessively dangerous and socially useless financial processes, or at least
shine a light on them, have merely displaced them into darker corners.
Tighter regulation of the activities that caused the last crash has
encouraged banks to seek ways around the new curbs, while still lobbying
to relax them (except where they conveniently keep out new competitors).
It has led less regulated ‘non-bank financial institutions’ or ‘shadow
banks’ to expand where banks were forced to contract. What we must now
look at is the wider web of different financial intermediaries that have
cropped up, with their desire to make a quick, high return and their effect
on company organization and the evolution of industry.
5
The Rise of Casino Capitalism
Rather than the financial conservatism that pension funds, mutual funds and insurance
companies were supposed to bring, money manager capitalism has ushered in a new
era of pervasive casino capitalism.
Hyman Minsky, 19921
When we talk about finance, we should bear in mind its many different
forms. While traditional activities like bank lending remain important, they
have been eclipsed by others. One is ‘shadow banking’, a term coined in
2007 to describe diverse financial intermediaries that carry out bank-like
activities but are not regulated as banks.2 These include pawnbrokers,
payday lenders, peer-to-peer lenders, mortgage lenders, investment banks,
mobile payment systems and bond-trading platforms established by tech
firms and money market funds. Between 2004 and 2014, the value of
assets serviced by the ‘informal lending sector’ globally rose from $26
trillion to $80 trillion and may account for as much as a quarter of the
global financial system. Shadow-banking activities – borrowing, lending
and asset-trading by firms that are not banks and escape their more
onerous regulation – all have one thing in common: they funnel finance to
finance, making money from moving existing money around. Another
significant boost to finance has been the rise of the asset management
industry and its different components, from widely marketed retail
investment funds to hedge funds and private equity. While average
incomes have grown, enabling a build-up of savings especially by the
better-off, rising longevity and governments’ reduced appetite for social
insurance and pension provision have put pressure on households around
the world to make their savings work harder. Those who ‘manage’
investments on their behalf can often claim a fee – often a percentage of
the funds under management – whether or not their stock-picks and
strategies have demonstrably added value. Taken together with traditional
banking, and released from the regulations that previously kept financial
firms’ size and risk appetite in check, these forces caused the sector to
grow disproportionately large.
There are two key aspects to the long-term growth of the financial sector
and its effect on the real economy. These two aspects of financialization
are covered in this and the next chapter. I will focus on the UK and the US,
where both forms of financialization have been developing most. The first,
covered in this chapter, is its expansion in absolute terms and as a share of
total economic activity. Today, the sector has sprawled way beyond the
limits of traditional finance, mainly banking, to cover an immense array of
financial instruments and has created a new force in modern capitalism:
asset management. The financial sector now accounts for a significant and
growing share of the economy’s value added and profits. But only 15 per
cent of the funds generated go to businesses in non-financial industries.3
The rest is traded between financial institutions, making money simply
from money changing hands, a phenomenon that has developed hugely,
giving rise to what Hyman Minsky called ‘money manager capitalism’.4
Or, put another way: when finance makes money by serving not the ‘real’
economy, but itself.
The second aspect, covered in the next chapter, is the effect of financial
motives on non-financial sectors, e.g. industries such as energy,
pharmaceuticals and IT. Such financialization can include the provision of
financial instruments for customers – for example, car manufacturers
offering finance to their customers – and, more importantly, the use of
profits to boost share prices rather than reinvest in actual production.
Both these aspects of financialization show how, in the growth of the
financial sector, value creation has been confused with value extraction,
with serious economic and social consequences. Finance has both
benefited from and partly caused widening inequality of income and
wealth, initially in the main ‘Anglo-Saxon’ countries, but spreading since
the 1990s to previously less financialized European and Asian economies.
Rising inequality might be ‘justified’ by economic gains if it promotes
faster growth that raises basic or average incomes, for example by giving
richer entrepreneurs the means and incentive to invest more. But recent
increases in inequality have been associated with slower growth,5 linked to
its social impact as well as the deflationary effect of reducing already-low
incomes. The key issue is: what role does finance, in all its complexity,
play in the economy? Does it justify its size and pervasiveness? Are the
sometimes huge rewards that can be earned from financial activities such
as hedge funds (an investment fund that speculates using borrowed capital
or credit) or private equity proportional to the actual risks taken?
Such questions are not new. Back in 1925, Winston Churchill, then
Chancellor of the Exchequer, had begun to get itchy about the way in
which finance was changing. He famously claimed that he would ‘rather
see finance less proud and industry more content’.6 The suspicion
troubling policymakers (and their newly emerging economic advisers) was
that financiers were positioned in relation to industrial producers in the
same way as pre-industrial landowners related to agricultural producers –
extracting a significant share of the revenue, without playing any active
part in the process of production. Investors who passively collected
interest on loans and dividends from shares were ‘rentiers’ in the classic
sense, exploiting their (often inherited) control over large sums of money
to generate unearned income, which – if not used for conspicuous
consumption – added to their wealth, especially in an age of low taxation.
The profits extracted by lenders and stock market investors could not be
used for investment in industrial expansion and modernization. This was a
growing concern, especially in the UK, whose inexorable fall behind the
industrial power of Germany and America (especially in industries that
could convert to military use) had been the subject of increasingly anxious
parliamentary enquiries since the late nineteenth century. The inclination
of British-based banking families and trusts to channel funds abroad in
search of higher returns, while foreign-based investors brought British
assets through its stock market, amplified these concerns as more of the
country’s colonies began to agitate for independence, and the storm clouds
that had heralded the First World War began to gather again. Churchill’s
Chancellorship had also alerted him to rent-seeking behaviour – lobbying
government for rules and entry barriers that would enhance financial
profit, and making loans to investors who expected to repay out of share
price gains – which was soon to rebound internationally in the Wall Street
Crash of 1929.
Yet at the time he wrote, the financial sector in the UK was only 6.4 per
cent of the entire economy.7 Finance trundled along at the same pace in the
first thirty years after the Second World War. Then, after a process of
deregulation begun during the 1970s, and the shifts in the production
boundary reviewed in the previous chapter, it powered ahead of the real
economy – manufacturing and the non-financial services provided by
private-sector companies, voluntary organizations and the state. By
reclassifying them from collectors of rent to creators of financial ‘value
added’, the newly ignited bundle of finance, insurance and real estate
(FIRE) was transformed into a productive sector at which economists of
the eighteenth, nineteenth and even the first half of the twentieth century
would have marvelled.
In the US, from 1960 to 2014, finance’s share of gross value added
more than doubled, from 3.7 to 8.4 per cent; over the same period,
manufacturing’s share of output fell by more than half, from 25 per cent to
12 per cent. The same happened in the UK: manufacturing’s share fell
from over 30 per cent of total value added in 1970 to 10 per cent in 2014,
while that of finance and insurance rose from less than 5 per cent to a peak
of over 9 per cent in 2009, dropping slightly to 8 per cent in 2014.8 So in
the three decades following deregulation, the financial sector
comprehensively outpaced the ‘real’ economy. This can be seen clearly for
the UK in Figure 14.
As regulations started to be lifted in the early 1980s, US private-sector
financial corporations’ profits as a share of total corporate profits – stable
at around 10–15 per cent in the first forty years after the Second World
War – rose to over 20 per cent, peaking at 40 per cent at the beginning of
the twenty-first century (Figure 15).
How does finance extract value? There are broadly three related answers:
by inserting a wedge, in the form of transaction costs, between providers
and receivers of finance; through monopoly power, especially in the case
of banks; and with high charges relative to risks run, notably in fund
management.
In certain areas of the economy, such transaction costs are regarded as
reducing efficiency and destroying value, not creating it. Governments are
accused of inefficiency whenever they impose an income tax – which puts
a wedge between what people receive for work and the value they place on
leisure – or when they try to finance social security through a payroll tax,
which disconnects wage costs from total labour costs. When they secure a
pay rise for their members, trade unions are accused of increasing workers’
pay while their contribution to production remains the same.
As far as banks are concerned, their efficiency as useful intermediaries
between borrowers and lenders might reasonably be judged by their ability
to narrow the ‘wedge’, or cost gap, between the two. Maximum efficiency,
friction-free capitalism, would in theory be reached when the interest
differential disappears. Yet the ‘indirect’ measure of financial
intermediation services adopted by national accounts (FISIM, explained in
Chapter 4) assumes that a rise in added value will be reflected in a wider
wedge (or, if the wedge narrows, by increased fees and charges through
which intermediaries can obtain payment directly). The point, of course, is
not to eliminate interest but – if interest is the price of financial
intermediation – to make sure that it reflects increased efficiencies in the
system, driven by appropriate investments in technological change, as
some fintech (financial technology) developments have done.
Banks stand in sharp contrast to supermarkets. As we have seen, the cost
of financial services probably rose in the twentieth century, despite the
dramatic growth of the financial industry, suggesting that financial
consumers did not benefit from economies of scale in the same way as
they did with supermarkets, epitomized by Walmart in the US and Tesco
in the UK. A large part of the explanation for the difference is the
monopolistic – or more strictly, oligopolistic – nature of banking.
In 2010, five big US banks controlled over 96 per cent of the derivative
contracts in place.26 In the UK, ten financial institutions accounted for 85
per cent of over-the-counter derivatives turnover in 2016, and 77 per cent
of foreign exchange turnover.27 Only the biggest banks can take the risk of
large-scale writing and trading in derivatives, since they need a
comfortable cushion of equity between the value of their assets and
liabilities to stay solvent if asset prices fall. Only a few banks worldwide
have grown big enough to sustain the high risks of proprietary trading –
trading on their own account rather than for a client – and to be worthy of
state-supported rescue if the risks prove too great.
As a result, there are few banks with whom governments and large
corporations can place new bond or share issues and expect subsequent
market-making in those securities. The paucity of players, even in large
financial centres such as London and New York, inevitably gives each
bank considerable price-setting power, irrespective of whether or not they
collude among themselves to do so. In retail markets, minimum core
capital requirements for banks (raised after 2008, to 4.5 per cent of risk-
weighted assets in 2013, 5.5 per cent in 2015 and 6 per cent from 2016)28
and the need for prudential regulation limits the number of banking
licences that governments and central banks can issue, and confers
significant market power on the few banks who hold such licences. This
power enabled banks to secure 40 per cent of total US corporate profits in
2002 (up from 13 per cent in 1985). They still enjoyed 23 per cent in 2010
and almost 30 per cent in 2012 – just two years after rebounding after a
brief plunge to 10 per cent in 2008, in a period when corporate profits
were growing much faster than labour income or GDP.29
The high degree of monopoly in wholesale and retail banking is closely
linked to its continuing ability to extract rents from the private and public
sectors, even when these were shrinking in the aftermath of the 2008 crash.
In the UK, since the financial crisis regulators have aimed to promote new
banks and alternative forms of financial intermediation, such as peer-to-
peer lending, in order to spur competition. The handful of new banks
started in the UK since the crisis are somewhat optimistically called
‘challenger banks’ – a challenge that so far has not put much of a dent in
the oligopoly of UK ‘high street’ banks. Nor are alternative forms of
financial intermediation effective substitutes for the dominant banks. Only
licensed banks can create money through loans,30 as distinct from merely
shifting money between savers and borrowers. Once banks’ profitability
has been swelled by the market power that allows them to extract rents
from other sectors, their top employees can in turn exert internal labour-
market power to channel a share of those rents to themselves, helping to
give the financial sector its unique and entrenched bonus culture.
On top of monopoly rent, financial markets give investment banks and
other professional ‘players’ another significant route to high financial
returns, divorced from the high risk that is traditionally understood to
justify those returns. Financial markets instantly adjust the price of
company shares and bonds to the future profits those companies are
expected to make. They can therefore instantly capture (and ‘capitalize’)
the jump in expected future profit when, for example, a new drug wins
approval for hospital use, a social media platform finds a way to monetize
its millions of users, or a mining company learns that its once-exotic metal
is to be used in the next generation of mobile phones. Owning an asset that
suddenly jumps in value has always been a faster way to get rich than
patiently saving and investing out of income;31 and the speed differential
of asset ‘revaluation’ over asset accumulation has been amplified in the
present era of historically low interest rates.
Revaluation gains in the ‘real’ economy are widely hailed as
economically efficient and socially progressive. Entrepreneurs who cash in
on a genuinely useful invention can claim to have reaped just rewards from
genuinely productive risk-taking, especially when they are shown to have
displaced hereditary landowners in the charts of ultra-high net worth. But
when – as is usually the case by the time the revaluation occurs – shares
have passed beyond the original inventors and become owned by private
equity or quoted on financial markets, it is passive rather than active
inventors who capture most of the revaluation gains. Financialization
enables investment bankers and fund managers who picked the right stock
– often by chance – to make profits that would previously have gone to
those who built the right product, by painstaking design. And, having
captured this value, they invariably race to extract it – channelling the gain
into real estate or other financial investments designed to hold their ‘value’
– rather than reinvesting it in more innovative production, which rarely
yields a comparable crock of gold a second time.
The relationship between finance’s share of employment and its share of
income gives an idea of what has happened. Until 1980, finance’s share of
employment and income in the US were almost identical (the ratio is 1).
But, as Figure 17 reveals, by 2015 it had almost doubled to 1.8. This steep
rise in average income per employee – scarcely interrupted by the crash of
2008 – was, according to its supporters, a sign of the financial sector’s
rising productivity and a justification for channelling more resources into
finance. But the productivity gain was, as seen in Chapter 4, highly
dependent on a redefinition that boosts banks’ and other lenders’ ‘value
added’. An alternative explanation for the rising income-to-employment
ratio is that finance was reinforcing its power to extract value, and gain
monopoly rents from other private-sector activities.
Figure 19. US mutual fund assets and charges 1951 and 2015
The striking and perhaps surprising conclusion is that over more than
sixty years, expense ratios, even among the same firms, have not gone
down but have gone up – and significantly. Why has this happened?
Fund managers deserve much of the blame. First, fund management’s
strategy of divide and conquer is part of the explanation. In the interest of
diversification and providing investors with plenty of choice in investment
strategies, fund managers have multiplied the number of funds they
manage. They have also handed control of funds to individual portfolio
managers who take a more short-term view of returns than investment
committees of, say, a whole fund management group, which on the whole
takes a broader view. The result has been much more aggressive investing
and a significant increase in asset turnover as managers buy and sell stocks
to try to boost returns. According to Bogle, portfolio turnover rose from 30
per cent in the 1950s and 1960s to 140 per cent in the last decades.40
Another measure of asset management quality is volatility: the degree of
uncertainty or risk about the size of fluctuations in a share’s value. Just as
turnover has risen, so the volatility of funds has increased significantly
from 0.84 to 1.11 over the same period.
Second, there are transaction costs. Greater turnover – buying and
selling more shares – keeps fees higher than they might have been, adding
to transaction costs without adding to investors’ capital gains given the
zero-sum nature of the market. Crucially for the investor, additional fees
reduce returns by increasing the cost of managing money. While
transaction costs for each trade have fallen over the last thirty years, the
frequency of trading has increased exponentially in recent years. Thus, the
total amount of fees has risen as well. As Bogle notes:
When I entered this business in 1951, right out of college, annual turnover of U.S.
stocks was about 15 per cent. Over the next 15 years, turnover averaged about 35 per
cent. By the late 1990s, it had gradually increased to the 100 per cent range, and hit 150
per cent in 2005. In 2008, stock turnover soared to the remarkable level of 280 per cent,
declining modestly to 250 per cent in 2011. Think for a moment about the numbers that
create these rates. When I came into this field 60 years ago, stock-trading volumes
averaged about 2 million shares per day. In recent years, we have traded about 8.5
billion shares of stock daily – 4,250 times as many. Annualized, the total comes to more
than 2 trillion shares – in dollar terms, I estimate the trading to be worth some $33
trillion. That figure, in turn, is 220 per cent of the $15 trillion market capitalisation of
U.S. stocks.41
The fund management industry naturally argues that the returns it can
make – seeking ‘alpha’ – for clients justify the fees it charges. In an
influential article,46 Joanne Hill, a Goldman Sachs partner, identifies
conditions in which trying to achieve alpha need not be a zero-sum game –
conveniently showing that investment banks’ proprietary trading might
have some social and economic value. But these conditions include an
assumption that the market is divided into traders with short- or long-term
horizons, who are pursuing alpha over different time periods and
measuring it against different benchmarks. Without this artificial
separation, alpha is indeed zero-sum – and turns into a negative-sum game
once active managers deduct the extra fees they must charge for selecting
stocks rather than just buying them in proportion to the relevant index.
CONCLUSION
Asset management has grown into one of modern capitalism’s defining
characteristics. If nothing else, its sheer scale and central importance to the
financial security of many millions of men and women have given
financial management its influence. But at least as significant is that many
of its activities extract value rather than create it. Financial markets merely
distribute income generated by activity elsewhere and do not add to that
income. Chasing alpha – selecting and over- or under-weighting stocks so
as to outperform an index – is essentially a game that will produce as many
losers as winners. This is why actively managed funds frequently fail to
beat the performance of passive funds. Much of fund management is a
massive exercise in rent-seeking of a sort that would have caused raised
eyebrows among the classical economists.
Reform is not impossible. Financial regulation can be used to reward
long-termism and also help to direct finance towards the real economy, as
opposed to feeding on itself. Indeed, the point of the financial transaction
tax – which has yet to be implemented – is precisely to reward long-term
investments over quick millisecond trades.
Furthermore, the fees being earned by asset managers should reflect real
value creation, not the ‘buy, strip and flip’ strategy common in PE, or the
‘2 and 20’ fee model common to PE, VC and hedge funds. Were the fees
more accurately to reflect risks run (or not run – such as the large
taxpayer-funded investments that often precede the entrance of VCs), the
percentage of realized and unrealized profits retained would be lower than
the customary 20 per cent. It is not that financial actors should not make
money, or that they do not create value; but that the collective effort
involved in the value-creation mechanism should be reflected in a more
equitable share of the rewards. This is tied to Keynes’s notion of
‘socialization of investment’. He argued that the economy could grow and
be better stabilized, and hence guarantee full employment, if the quantity
and quality of public investment was increased. By this he meant that
funding investment in infrastructure and innovation (capital development)
ought to be done by public utilities, public banks or co-operatives which
direct public funds towards medium- and long-term growth rather than
short-term returns.
But rent-seeking is not limited to the financial sector. It has pervaded
non-financial industries as well – through the pressures that financial-
sector profitability, exaggerated by monopoly power and implicit public
guarantees, place on the corporate governance of non-financial firms. If
investors can expect a certain return by putting their money into a fund,
spreading the risks across a wide range of money-making instruments,
they will only sink the same funds into one industrial project if it offers a
much higher return. The return on financial-sector investment sets a
minimum for the return on ‘real’ fixed investment, a floor which rises as
financial operations become more profitable. Non-financial companies that
cannot beat the financial investors’ return are forced to join them, by
‘financializing’ their production and distribution activities.
6
Financialization of the Real Economy
On the face of it, shareholder value is the dumbest idea in the world.
Jack Welch, former General Electric CEO, 20091
Figure 21. Top ten stock repurchasers in the US (2004–2012), ranked by the absolute amount of
share buy-backs8
Share buy-backs boost executive pay. To defend the idea that incentive
pay realigns executive and shareholder interests, it is often claimed that
share buy-backs maximize shareholder value (MSV) and thus improve the
efficiency of companies.9 Financial techniques, it is argued, are a
legitimate way for managers to improve productivity and therefore benefit
workers and customers as well as shareholders. If a company can earn a
higher return at any given time from putting capital to work financially
rather than directly selling cars or software, it is behaving rationally and in
the best interests of the business. Having a choice between a financial or a
productive use for capital helps to keep the (supposedly) core business of
cars or software on its toes because it has to produce returns which
compete with financial alternatives. By extension, it is argued that making
it easier for customers to obtain credit, especially to buy your own
products, is a service to ordinary people. There is something to this – but
not much. Where did these ideas come from? And do they have validity?
Back in the 1970s, as the economic crisis and stagnation of the decade
impaired the performance and profitability of the corporate sector,
shareholder dissatisfaction made shareholder returns the principal aim of
the corporation. In 1970, Milton Friedman published in the New York
Times Magazine an article which became the founding text of the
shareholder value movement and, in many ways, of corporate management
in general. Titled ‘The Social Responsibility of Business Is to Increase its
Profits’, Friedman’s article advanced the idea that America’s economic
performance was declining because a cardinal principle of mainstream
economics – that firms maximize profits – was being violated. There was
no longer any punishment for managers who failed to profit-maximize.
Shareholders could not inflict such punishment because they were too
dispersed and uncoordinated; and markets could not do so, because listed
companies had monopoly power and would not be assailed by new
competitors if their costs and prices drifted upwards. Some 1960s
economists had viewed ‘managerialism’ as potentially good for society, if
bosses allowed profit to be eroded by paying better wages to employees,
meeting higher environmental or health and safety standards and investing
more in new products. Friedman reset the debate by suggesting that bosses
were more likely to be sacrificing profit to their own expense accounts and
luxury lifestyles; and that even letting costs rise through ‘corporate social
responsibility’ was fundamentally wrong. The piece spawned an academic
literature that would become known as ‘agency theory’.
Friedman’s idea was developed further by the University of Chicago-
trained Michael Jensen, who was steeped in its ‘free market’ ideas. In 1976
Jensen, now a professor at the University of Rochester, wrote a paper with
the Dean of Rochester’s business school, William Meckling (who, like
Jensen, was a student of Friedman at Chicago), on how to implement
Friedman’s idea. It was called ‘Theory of the firm: Managerial behavior,
agency costs, and ownership structure’. The key argument was that
managers (the agents) were not being disciplined by competitive financial
markets or product markets, since they could misallocate resources or run
up unnecessary expenses without incurring losses or endangering their
jobs, and so it was hard for investors (the principals) to keep them
accountable. The only way to do so was through strengthening the
‘market’, which was neutral and objective enough to make sure the
company thrived. The result was a body of theory that argued that the only
way for companies to be well run was if they maximized their ‘shareholder
value’. In this way, investors would indirectly keep company managers
accountable.
In the decades that followed, an entire intellectual apparatus was created
around ‘maximizing shareholder value’, with new developments in law,
economics and business studies. It became the dominant perspective of
leading business schools and economic departments. The overriding goal
of the corporation became that of maximizing shareholder value, as
captured in the corporation’s share price.
However, far from being a lodestar for corporate management,
maximizing shareholder value turned into a catalyst for a set of mutually
reinforcing trends, which played up short-termism while downplaying the
long-term view and a broader interpretation of whom the corporation
should benefit. In the name of MSV, managers sought profits anywhere
they could, directly fuelling globalization and outsourcing production to
locations from China to Mexico. Jobs were lost and communities wrecked.
Meanwhile, the added external pressures on corporate management did
little to enhance its quality. Rather than become properly trained managers
with sectoral expertise, who could make decisions on what to produce and
how to produce it, top graduates in business schools preferred to go to
Wall Street. While in 1965 only 11 per cent of Harvard Business School
MBAs went into the financial sector, by 1985 the figure had reached 41
per cent and has risen since then.
Figure 22 shows how the influence of PE, one of the most aggressive
manifestations of MSV, grew in the US in the first decade and a half of the
twenty-first century. The arguments of Friedman, Jensen and Meckling
suggested that shareholder value was going to waste. So a new type of
investor that could capture this leaking value would be instantly rewarded,
through bigger dividends or share price gains. PE funds and acquisition
vehicles led the pack of new, value-hungry investors that now assailed the
world’s stock markets.
PE is MSV turbo-charged. Many of the companies in which PE firms
invest are not financial ones; often, indeed, they can be found on the
productive side of the production boundary. But whereas traditional
institutional investors were often satisfied to ‘buy and hold’, and to await
share price gains via profit being reinvested rather than paid out, PE seeks
to buy and resell at a higher price within a few years. What this means is
that many firms owned by PE funds are pushed into taking a significantly
shorter-term view than they might have done otherwise – the exact reverse
of ‘patient capital’ and raising productivity to benefit society in the long
run. If the influence of PE on the productive economy seems exaggerated,
consider this: Blackstone, one of the largest PE companies, has a portfolio
of over seventy-seven companies, which together generate over $64 billion
in combined annual revenues and employ more than 514,000 people
globally.11
Figure 22. PE-backed companies as a percentage of all US companies (by enterprise size)10
The recent history of the care home and water industries in the UK
shows how PE can change a business – and not necessarily for the better.
Until the mid-1990s the country’s care homes were owned either by small
family firms or by local authorities.12 Today, for a combination of political
and financial reasons, many local authority homes have closed. A new
breed of financial operator has moved into the market, largely following a
PE model, often ‘selling’ many of its places to local authorities but also
generating private profit. In 2015, the five biggest care home chains
controlled about a fifth of the total number of care home beds in the UK.
These operators were attracted by stable cash flows, part of which came
from local authorities, and opportunities for financial engineering: cheap
debt; property which could be sold and leased back; tax breaks on debt
interest payments and carried interest; and – ultimately – frail and
vulnerable residents whom the state would have to look after if the
business failed. The corporate structures of some care home owners
became exceedingly complex and often hidden in tax havens, while
corporation tax payments were low or nil. Given that local authorities still
funded many care home placements and that the nurses employed in the
homes had been state-trained, opaque corporate structures and minimal tax
payments are hardly the way to provide an essential public service.
Four Seasons Health Care displays many of these characteristics. The
company owns the biggest chain of care homes in the UK, with 23,000
beds in 2015. But it was only a small Scottish chain until its acquisition by
Alchemy Partners, a PE firm, in 1999. Having enlarged the company,
Alchemy sold it in 2004 to Allianz Capital Partners, another private firm,
which two years later sold it to Three Delta, yet another PE firm. By 2008,
during this game of pass the parcel, the company’s external debt had
ballooned to £1.5 billion, carrying an annual interest charge of over £100
million – or an unsustainable £100 per bed per week. In 2012 the company
was bought by Terra Firma – you’ve guessed it, a PE firm – controlled by
Guy Hands, a well-known British financier who had cut his teeth at
Goldman Sachs. Despite a financial restructuring involving losses for
equity holders, bondholders and banks before Terra Firma acquired the
business, by 2014 Four Seasons was losing money, and a pre-tax loss of
£70.1 million in 2015 deepened to £264 million in 2015.13 The cost of
debt-servicing was at least partly to blame. The company blamed local
authorities for freezing the amount they would pay for residents, although
the authorities themselves were suffering severe budget cuts under the
Conservative-led government’s austerity programme. The Care Quality
Commission, the government body which monitors standards in care
homes, was sufficiently concerned about the business health of Four
Seasons that at one point it embargoed twenty-eight of Four Seasons’
homes, meaning that they could not take in new residents.
Similar patterns can be seen in England and Wales’s water industry,
which was privatized in 1989.14 The ten water and sewerage companies
(WSCs) were listed on the London Stock Exchange as part of the then
government’s policy of creating a ‘shareholder democracy’. Today, only
two remain listed. Asian infrastructure conglomerates own three of the
companies; another is a mutual company (Welsh Water, or Dŵr Cymru);
and PE firms own four – Anglian Water, Thames Water (the biggest water
company), Southern Water and Yorkshire Water.
As with care homes, the ratio of debt to equity in the water companies
has increased sharply: a typical feature of companies owned by PE firms,
as we saw in the previous chapter. Between 2003 and 2013 average net
debt rose by 74 per cent while equity fell by 37 per cent in nine of the
companies: Anglian, Thames, Northumbrian, Severn Trent, Southern,
South West, United Utilities, Wessex and Yorkshire. The companies with
the highest net debt – about 80 per cent of capital or more – were all PE-
owned. Net interest payments by the nine English WSCs went up from
£288 million in 1993 to an eye-watering £2 billion in 2012. Interestingly,
the company with the lowest gearing (ratio of debt to equity) and the
highest credit rating was Welsh Water, which is mutually owned. The four
companies with the highest gearing and the lowest credit ratings were all
PE-owned.
Just like some of the care home groups, WSC ownership structures are
often opaque. The combination of shadowy corporate structures and
complex financial engineering may well explain high payouts to water
company owners. Between 2009 and 2013 Anglian, Thames, United
Utilities, Wessex and Yorkshire paid out more in dividends than they made
in after-tax profits. Directors saw their share of the companies’ income rise
from 0.1318 per cent in 1993 to 0.2052 per cent in 2013. Over the same
period the share of the water companies’ income going to salaries and
wages fell from 15.37 per cent to 10.22 per cent: in other words, the
workers’ loss seemed to be diametrically opposed to the owners’ gain. It is
true that the water companies have invested more than £100 billion in the
country’s water and sewerage infrastructure since privatization. But the
financialization of the industry was not anticipated in 1989, and neither
price controls nor limits to returns on capital imposed on the companies by
the Water Services Regulation Authority (Ofwat), the industry’s economic
regulator, appear to have prevented what looks like value extraction.
The cases of care homes and water in Britain are not a blanket argument
against PE or financialization. But they do illustrate how financial
engineering of socially essential services can change the nature of an
industry. It is at the very least debatable whether the opaque ownership
and excessive financialization which characterize these PE-owned
businesses serve their customers more than their owners.
One of the key precepts of MSV, as we’ve seen, is that the incentives of
management and shareholders need to be aligned, and that the best way to
do this is to compensate management by awarding them shares. Senior
managers soon embraced MSV when they realized how it could help them
to increase their pay (Figure 23). The original spirit of MSV has been
perverted: the massive share options which have been a major part of
many CEOs’ pay packages do not really align with managers’ and
shareholders’ interests. Managers – depending on the terms on which they
are granted options – enjoy an almost free upside, with no downside. They
are partly insulated against the ups and downs of share prices that are the
lot of long-term investors via anti-takeover devices such as the ‘golden
parachute’, a cash reward if they lose their job, or ‘poison pills’, which
trigger an event such as the sale of a valuable corporate division to reduce
the company’s value when faced with an unwelcome takeover attempt.
Figure 23. Median CEO pay in the US ($m, constant 2011 $)27
Figure 27. Private-sector firm vs public firm investment rates (percentage of total assets)31
Figure 28. Non-financial sector public company profitability (GMO)32
So, if margins are high but investment is low, what have companies
done with their profits? Following the money leads us directly to
shareholders. As we can see from Figure 29, corporations have largely
returned profits to shareholders in the form of dividends and share buy-
backs. Having averaged 10–20 per cent in the 1970s, the percentage of
cash flow returned to shareholders has remained above 30, and sometimes
substantially more than that for most of the past thirty years, although it
dipped during the tech boom in the early 2000s when companies were
investing.
What emerges from the evidence presented so far is that, just like
finance, the financialization of the productive sector extracts value –
objectively, rent. But not only in the productive sector. In recent years a
wide range of businesses in the UK, from social providers like care homes
to utilities such as water, both of which had previously been regarded as
steady and unexciting investments, have been subject to financial
engineering by new owners, often PE firms. The result is a transformation
of public goods into private goods.
Figure 29. Percentage of cash flows returned to shareholders (US non-financials five-year moving
average)33
CONCLUSION
Sky-rocketing rewards for the lucky few have widened social divisions and
increased inequality in much of the Western world, notably in the US, the
home of financialization.
This state of affairs can be – and is – attacked on moral grounds.
Inequality reveals what we think of millions of our fellow humans. The
economic issue with value extraction is not normative, however. As we
have seen, in a capitalist economy some rent is necessary: there is an
unavoidable price tag to maintaining the circulation of capital in the
economic system. But the scale of the financial sector and of
financialization generally has increased value extraction to the point where
two critical questions must be answered: where is value created, extracted
and even destroyed? And how can we steer the economy away from
excessive financialization towards true value creation? Proposals such as
taxing away very high incomes and accumulations of wealth may treat
some of the symptoms of excessive finance. They do not, however, treat
the causes, which lie deep in a system of value extraction which has grown
up over the last forty years or so.
If the objective is long-term growth, the private sector must be rewarded
for making decisions that target the long-term over the short-term. While
some companies might be focusing on boosting their stock prices through
share buy-backs, aimed at increasing stock prices and hence stock options
(through which executives are paid), others may be taking on the difficult
investments to increase the training needed for workers, introduce risky
new technology, and investment in R&D, eventually leading, with luck, to
new technology and more likely leading to nowhere. Companies could be
rewarded for doing more of the latter and less of the former.
Executive pay should be kept in check through an understanding that
there are many other stakeholders who are critical to value creation, from
workers and the state to civil society movements. Reinvestment of profits
back into the real economy – rather than hoarding or engaging in share
buy-backs – should be a condition attached to any type of government
support, whether through subsidies or government grants and loans.
The British-Venezuelan scholar Carlota Perez has argued that the
decoupling of finance from the real economy is not ‘natural’ but an
artefact of deregulation and excess belief in the power of free markets. Her
groundbreaking work has identified a pattern of intense financialization
followed by its reversal in each technological revolution.39 She shows that
the early decades of each of the five revolutions to date (from the steam
engine to the IT revolution) have been times of financial mania and
increasing inequality. But after the financial bubbles collapse, and amid
the ensuing recession and social turmoil, governments have tended to rein
in finance and promote a period that favours the expansion of production,
benefiting society more broadly and making finance serve its real purpose.
But if and when government does not step in and play its part,
financialization can have no end.40
The next chapter turns to the world of innovation, a glamorous arena of
inspired inventors and fearless entrepreneurs where ‘wealth creation’ is not
all it is claimed to be.
7
Extracting Value through the Innovation Economy
First, only invest in companies that have the potential to return the value of the entire
fund.
Peter Thiel, Zero to One: Notes on Startups, or How to Build the Future (2014)
FINANCING INNOVATION
In the case of venture capitalists, their real genius appears to lie in their
timing: their ability to enter a sector late, after the highest development
risks had already been taken, but at an optimum moment to make a killing.
While many such investments fail, the few that succeed can make the
investment fund in question a fortune, as exemplified by the success of the
VC company Kleiner Perkins. In 1976, Kleiner Perkins invested $100,000
in the biotechnology company Genentech, which four years later, during
its initial public offering on the stock market, was valued at $300 million.
In 2009, Genentech was acquired by a Swiss-based healthcare company,
Roche, for $47 billion, making a fortune for the investors. Similarly, Peter
Theil’s $500,000 investment in Facebook back in 2004, which bought him
a 10.2 per cent stake in the company, made him £1 billion when he sold
the majority of his shares in 2012. These early investors are doubtless
crucial to the innovation process. The critical question here is: are their
rewards proportionate to the risks they take?
You might imagine, in the instances where public funds have made the
initial risky investments – the private VC only entering at the point where
investment looks more of a sure bet – that these funds would receive
appropriate remuneration for their boldness. But in fact, the opposite is
true. In these cases, the private VC industry’s share of the rewards tends to
be about 20 per cent, excluding other fees and charges; by contrast, the
public sector’s direct share is close to nil. The public sector is generally
deemed to reap its rewards in other, more indirect ways: through taxation
or from the benefits of products with high quality and low cost. Not only is
this a way of thinking that all but ignores the crucial and risky early
investments made by public funds in innovation; it disproportionally
privileges the later, private investors in terms of rewards.
Let’s look at this a bit more closely.
VC – Timing is All
The VC industry began in the USA in 1946 when the American Research
and Development Corporation (ARD) was set up to raise funds from
wealthy people and college endowments to invest in entrepreneurial start-
ups in technology-based manufacturing. It was soon making eye-catching
investments. In 1957, ARD invested a total of $70,000 in DEC, a computer
company; nine years later, this same investment was already valued at $37
million. Nevertheless, the VC industry’s growth was sedate until the
1980s, when it boomed, the role of pension funds upboosting its capital.
From the start of the VC industry, entrepreneurs and venture capitalists
had often surfed on a wave created by decades of government investment.
Starting after the Second World War, government investment in high-tech
ventures grew significantly in the 1950s as part of the military-industrial
complex, largely due to the Cold War.8 Before becoming famous around
the world as ‘Silicon Valley’, a name coined in 1971, the San Francisco
Bay area was producing technology for military use or, from the 1960s,
spin-offs of military technology for commercial purposes.9 The first formal
VC firm in Silicon Valley – Draper, Gaither and Anderson – was headed
by two former US Army generals and the author of a secret report to
President Eisenhower on how the US should respond to the USSR’s
launching of Sputnik.10
Much of the work to commercialize military technology was done in the
research labs of established ICT companies like General Electric, Texas
Instruments, AT&T, Xerox and IBM. Employees of these companies left
to found their own start-ups. The Small Business Investment Company, set
up in 1958 by the government’s Small Business Administration, itself
founded in 1953, helped many of the start-ups to raise capital.
The establishment in 1971 of NASDAQ – a new stock market that did
not have the stringent listing requirements of the New York Stock
Exchange – complemented the government’s programmes. The creation of
a highly liquid national market for more speculative corporate securities
was important for attracting venture capitalists to invest in the IT industry,
secure in the knowledge that there was now a feasible exit route from their
investments.11 Venture capitalists typically look to exit from investments
within three to five years, impatient to make a buck in one enterprise and
start again elsewhere.
In 1972, the Silicon Valley VC industry began to coalesce at 3000 Sand
Hill Road in Palo Alto; a year later the National Venture Capital
Association (NVCA) was formed. The NVCA quickly became an
influential lobby. By the early 1980s it persuaded Congress to halve capital
gains tax rates, arguing that it would be an incentive to greater VC
investment. Warren Buffett became a lead critic of this policy, admitting
that he and most investors don’t look at tax, they look at opportunities.12
Indeed, the VC industry, from when it began, followed the opportunities
created by direct ‘mission-oriented’ government investments in areas like
the Internet, biotech, nanotech and cleantech.
As we saw in Chapter 5, another crucial success for the NVCA came
when it persuaded the US government to relax the interpretation of the
‘prudent man’ investment rule (keeping pensions funds out of high-risk
investments) to allow pension fund managers to invest up to 5 per cent of
pension funds in riskier investments like VC ones. It meant that, from
1979 onwards, large sums of workers’ pensions savings flowed into VC
funds – funds on which venture capitalists typically received a
management fee of 2 per cent of total volume, as well as 20 per cent
‘carried interest’ of profits (i.e. the share of the profits that go to those
managing the funds), like private equity.13
In 1984, during a tour of Silicon Valley by the then French President,
François Mitterrand, the discrepancy between the venture capitalists’
newfound bullishness and their actual achievements was picked up in an
exchange between Paul Berg, one of the winners of the Nobel Prize in
Chemistry that year, and Tom Perkins (the co-founder of Kleiner-Perkins)
boasting about his sector’s role in biotech. Berg said: ‘Where were you
guys in the ’50s and ’60s when all the funding had to be done in the basic
science? Most of the discoveries that have fuelled [the industry] were
created back then.’14 For the venture capitalists, however, the prospect of
astonishing profits now lay before them. Nothing summed up this new
spirit of enterprise better than the upstart company that went public the
same year: Apple.15
The second key way in which value has been extracted from the
innovation economy is by the appropriation of returns through the patent
system (IPR). In the last century patents, and associated tools like
copyrights and trademarks, have gone from being devices to stimulate
innovation to means of blocking it.
Patents are protections granted to inventions that are novel, inventive
(non-obvious) and suitable for industrial application. In theory they protect
the innovator from having his or her idea copied. In practice, however,
most innovations are not patented, which in itself shows that patents are
not really necessary, as there are other ways to protect innovations,
including lead-times and trade secrecy. One study found that between
1977 and 2004, only 10 per cent of ‘important’ innovations were
patented.22 Patents tend to be granted for two reasons, which must be held
in constant tension for the system to function effectively. The first is to
reward and incentivize inventors for developing new ideas by granting
them a time-limited monopoly entitlement over their inventions,23 or what
is known as the appropriability function of patents. In exchange for this
monopoly entitlement, the inventor must reveal detailed information about
his or her invention. Which brings us to the second reason: once the patent
has expired, the invention can diffuse rapidly through the economy in a
process known as the disclosure function of patents. If the system works
well, the appropriability function is properly balanced against the
disclosure function and the public gains from the rapid diffusion of this
new knowledge through the economy.24
Looked at in this light, patents are best understood not as intellectual
property ‘rights’ in the sense of something that is universal or immutable,
but as a contract or deal based on a set of policy choices. Something is
given up (information about the invention) in exchange for something
gained (the ability to exploit the invention exclusively for a limited
period). In balancing the private benefits with the broader public good,
policymakers must make trade-offs. Granting patents can help increase the
incentives for inventors, which in the long run can result in higher rates of
technical progress. But such grants also increase the market power of
patent holders, resulting in less ‘economic efficiency’ during the time
patents are enforceable, and slower knowledge diffusion.
The original purpose of patents is value creation. Patenting your
brilliantly cheap and effective innovation is meant to ensure that the hard
work you put into the invention is protected for a period during which it
earns profits until others are allowed to copy it. That period is currently
twenty years. Not all industries make equal use of patents; they tend to be
less important for areas like software25 and more so for science-based
industries like pharmaceuticals. Indeed, there are also other ways to
maintain market dominance, for example through first-mover advantages
and secrecy.
To understand how patents relate to the dynamics of value extraction,
we must look both at what exactly is being patented and at the structure of
the patents themselves. The current dominance of the narrative of
entrepreneurs as wealth creators has, I would contend, shifted the balance
of the patent system away from an emphasis on the diffusion of knowledge
towards private reward.26
UNPRODUCTIVE ENTREPRENEURSHIP
PRICING PHARMACEUTICALS
The high price of specialty drugs – the argument goes – is justified by how
beneficial they are for patients and for society in general. In practice, this
means relating the price of a drug to the costs that the disease would cause
to society if not treated, or if treated with the second-best therapy. So we
read, in a ‘fact sheet’ prepared by the US industry trade body PhRMA to
justify high prices, that ‘every additional dollar spent on medicines or
adherent patients with congestive heart failure, high blood pressure,
diabetes and high cholesterol generated $3 to $10 in savings on emergency
room visits and in patient hospitalizations’, that ‘a 10 per cent decrease in
the cancer death rate is worth roughly $4.4 trillion in economic value to
current and future generations’ and that ‘research and medicines from the
biopharmaceutical sector are the only chance for survival for patients and
their families’.56 While these claims may be true, it is striking that they are
used as an explanation (or justification) for high drug prices.
Critics have replied that there is in fact no discernible link between
specialty drug prices and the medical benefits they provide. They have
some evidence on their side. Case studies have shown no correlation
between the price of cancer drugs and their benefits.57 One 2015 study,
based on a sample of fifty-eight anti-cancer drugs approved in the US
between 1995 and 2013, illustrates that their survival benefits for patients
do not explain their mounting cost. Dr Peter Bach, a renowned oncologist,
put online an interactive calculator with which you can establish the
‘correct’ price of a cancer drug on the basis of its valuable characteristics –
increase in life expectancy, side effects and so on. The calculator shows
that the value-based price of most drugs is lower than their market price.58
Unfortunately, however, most of the pharmaceutical industry’s critics
fight its arguments on the field big pharma has chosen. In other words,
they implicitly accept the idea that prices should be linked to some
intrinsic value of a drug, measured by the monetary value of the benefits –
or avoided costs – to patients and society. This is not as odd as it might
sound.
The idea of value-based pricing was initially developed by scholars and
policymakers to counteract rising drug prices and to allocate public
healthcare budgets more rationally. In the UK, for example, the National
Institute for Health and Care Excellence (NICE) calculates the value of
drugs in terms of the number of quality-adjusted life years (QALY) that
each class of patients receives. One QALY is a year of perfect health; if
health is less than perfect, QALYs accrue at less than one a year. Cost-
effectiveness is assessed by calculating how much per QALY a drug or
treatment costs. Generally, NICE considers a pharmaceutical product cost-
effective if it costs less than £20,000–£30,000 per QALY provided. A
price-based assessment of this sort is powerful: NICE advises the UK
National Health Service (NHS) on its choice of drugs.
A cost-effectiveness analysis like the one NICE conducts makes sense
for allocating a national healthcare system’s finite budget. In the US,
where there is no cost-effectiveness analysis and the national insurance
system is forbidden by law from bargaining with drug companies, drug
prices are much higher than in the UK and are increasing more rapidly.
The outcome is that, measured by a yardstick such as QALY, specialty
drug prices in the US are not related to the medical benefits they provide.
Basic mainstream analysis of elasticity of demand (that is, how sensitive
consumers are to changes in prices, depending on the characteristics of
goods) is sufficient to explain the very high prices of specialty drugs,
which makes pharma’s vague and rhetorical arguments about value all the
more unconvincing. Specialty drugs like Sovaldi and Harvoni are covered
by patents, so their producers are monopolists and competition does not
constrain the prices they set. Normally, however, you would expect the
elasticity of demand to be a constraint: the higher the price, the lower the
demand for the monopolist’s product. But the elasticity of demand for
specialty drugs is of course very low: peoples’ lives are at stake. They
need these drugs to have some chance of surviving, and medical insurers,
whether public or private, are under an obligation to pay for them.
The logical outcome of a combination of monopoly and rigid demand is
sky-high prices, and this is precisely what is happening with specialty
drugs. It explains why pharmaceutical companies enjoy absurdly high
profit margins: in addition to the normal profit rate, they earn huge
monopoly rents.59 A value-based assessment of the kind NICE carries out
can be helpful because it reduces demand for the monopolists’ drugs and
prevents them from charging whatever price they choose. The downside,
however, is that increased elasticity of demand for drugs comes at the cost
of leaving some patients without the medicines they need, because
pharmaceutical companies may not cut their prices enough to treat
everyone who needs the drug if doing so would reduce profit margins by
more than the companies want. This is already happening in the UK,
where NICE has rejected some cancer drugs for use in the NHS because of
their price. It is also happening in the US, where some private and public
insurers refused to provide Harvoni to insured patients until they reached a
very advanced stage of the disease.
What is not being pointed out, however, is that the principle that a
specialty drug’s price should equal the costs it saves society is
fundamentally flawed. If we took such a principle seriously, basic
therapies or vaccines should cost a fortune. For that matter, how high
should the price of water be, given its indispensable value to society?
The con around drug pricing has created a constant battle between
government-funded healthcare systems (where they exist), private and
public insurance programmes, and the big pharmaceutical firms. Only by
debunking the ideas about value underpinning these drugs can a long-
lasting solution be found which results in access to genuinely affordable
drugs.
Networking Profits
All this sounds fine until you ask yourself what it might mean for the size
of companies. A strong source of increasing returns to scale necessarily
expands companies. Google’s size is a direct result of the network effects
typical of Internet-based services. Google is not just a search engine. It is
also an email address (Gmail), a conference call maker (Google Hangout),
a document creator and editor – all designed to maximize the advantages
of sticking to Google: you cannot use Google Hangout without a Gmail
address.
What’s the problem? Giant online firms like Facebook, Amazon and
Google are often portrayed by their managers and by their apologists as
‘forces for good’ and for the progress of society rather than as profit-
oriented businesses.61 Excited advocates have talked of a rising and
revolutionary ‘sharing economy’, or even of ‘digital socialism’,62
advancing a rosy view according to which digital platforms ‘empower’
people, giving us free access to a wide range of services, from social
networking to GPS positioning and health-monitoring. Silicon Valley is
starkly and favourably contrasted with Wall Street. The Valley bridges the
consumption gap by providing services that everyone can access, almost
independently of their income; the Street intensifies the concentration of
power and wealth in the hands of the 1 per cent.63
Of course the Internet giants are valuable to their users, sometimes
greatly so. They can add to people’s well-being and in some cases increase
their productivity, for instance by making it easier and faster to find some
web content, route, person or book. But the view that these services are
offered to everyone for free out of Silicon Valley’s goodwill, with the aim
of ‘empowering’ people and creating a more open world, is exceedingly
naïve. A more realistic analysis should start from a grasp of how these
firms work and where their profits come from, with an eye to assessing
their overall social impact in terms of value creation and value extraction.
Firms like Google, Facebook and Amazon – and new ‘sharing-
economy’ firms like Airbnb and Uber – like to define themselves as
‘platforms’. They don’t face a traditional market, in which the firm
produces a good or service and sells it to a population of potential
consumers. They operate, instead, in what economists call two-sided
markets, developing the supply and demand sides of the market as the
lynchpin, connector or gatekeeper between them. On the one side, there is
a service offering to users. On the other side, there is a market offering to
other firms – from sales to advertising space to information on users’
behaviour. Firms have long operated in more than one market. The
peculiarity of two-sided markets, however, lies in how the two sides are
connected. As the number of users on one side of the market (using a
search engine or joining a social network) rises, clicks on ads and
information on consumers’ behaviour also increases, boosting profitability
in the other side of the market. It suits Google and Facebook to charge
their users nothing: they need as many people as possible to join to make
the product they sell to firms on the other side of the market more
attractive. ‘Socialism’, digital or otherwise, doesn’t come into it.
We should not see Google, for example, as providing services for free to
its users. Rather, it is users who provide Google with necessary inputs for
its production process: their looks on ads and, most importantly, their
personal data. In return, they obtain online searches and other services.
The bulk of Google’s profits come from selling advertising space and
users’ data to firms. If something is free online, you are not the customer,
you are the product.64 Facebook’s and Google’s business models are built
on the commodification of personal data, transforming through the
alchemy of a two-sided market our friendships, interests, beliefs and
preferences into sellable propositions. The so-called ‘sharing economy’ is
based on the same idea. For all the hype about ‘sharing’, it is less about
altruism and more about allowing market exchange to reach into areas of
our lives – our homes, our vehicles, even our private relationships – that
were previously beyond its scope and to commodify them.65 As Evgeny
Morozov has warned, it risks turning us all into ‘perpetual hustlers’,66 with
all of our lives up for sale, while at the same time undermining the basis
for stable employment and a good standard of living.
Standing on Platform Capitalism
‘Platform capitalism’ is often referred to as the new way in which goods
and services are produced, shared and delivered – more horizontally, with
consumers interacting with each other, and less intermediation by old
institutions (e.g. travel agents). The so-called sharing economy, based on
this framework, works by reducing the frictions between the two sides of
the market: connecting buyers to sellers, potential customers to advertisers,
in more efficient ways. It is presented as a radical transformation in the
way that goods and services are produced, shared and delivered. It adds
value by taking what was previously peripheral to the service – in Uber’s
case, ordering, selecting, tracking and paying for a cab – into its core. But
when disabled users have complained to Uber about their drivers refusing
to put wheelchairs in the boot of the car, Uber has sought to evade
responsibility on the basis that it is not a taxi company, merely a
platform.67 Likewise, there is increasing evidence that Airbnb is similarly
reluctant to take responsibility for such matters as the safety of premises
offered on its site or racial discrimination against renters by property
owners.
Furthermore, Uber’s pursuit of economies of scale (based on the size of
the network) and economies of scope (based on the breadth of different
services, including UberEats) has led to higher profits on the backs of the
key contributors to value creation for the company: the drivers. Indeed,
while costs have been falling for the consumer, they have been rising for
the drivers: in 2012 Uber Black (one of the company’s car services) cost
riders in San Francisco $4.90 per mile or $1.25 per minute. When, in 2016,
charges fell to $3.75 per mile or $0.65 per minute, consumers gained. But
the result of this sharing economy is that Uber Black drivers are paid less,
‘standards’ rise (with pressure for drivers to offer ‘pool’ services to
customers) and competition from Uber’s other services intensifies.68 While
drivers are increasingly complaining, Uber’s market reach is higher than
ever and growing every day: as of October 2016 it had 40 million monthly
riders worldwide.69 In 2016 it had 160,000 drivers in the US, with millions
more spread across 500 cities globally – all working as ‘independent
contractors’, so that Uber does not have to provide them with the kind of
healthcare and other benefits which they would receive as full-time
employees.
Uber, like Google, Facebook and Amazon, seems to have no limit to its
size. The network effects that pervade online markets add an important
peculiarity: once a firm establishes leadership in a market its dominance
increases and becomes self-perpetuating almost automatically. If everyone
is on Facebook, no one wants to join a different social network. As most
people search on Google, the gap between Google and its competitors
grows wider because it can elaborate on more data. And as its market share
rises, so does its capacity to attract users, which in turn increases its
market dominance.70
Contrary to the pious pronouncements of Internet pioneers, network
effects are increasingly centralizing the Internet, thereby placing an
enormous concentration of market power in the hands of a few firms.
Google alone accounts for 70 per cent of online searches in the US, and 90
per cent in Europe. Facebook has more than 1.5 billion users, a quarter of
the planet’s population and streets ahead of its competitors. Amazon now
accounts for around half of the US books market, not to mention e-books.
Six firms (Facebook, Google, Yahoo, AOL, Twitter and Amazon) account
for around 53 per cent of the digital advertising market (with just Google
and Facebook making up 39 per cent).71 Such dominance implies that
online giants can impose their conditions on users and customer firms.
Many book publishers, for example, are unhappy with the conditions
Amazon insists upon and are asking for better ones. But they have no
leverage at all, because – as Evgeny Morozov puts it – ‘there is no second
Amazon they can turn to’.72 The powerful network effects in the two-sided
market have entrenched these companies’ position. Companies like
Google are de facto monopolies.73 But they are not recognized as such and
have not attracted the kind of anti-trust legislation that large companies in
more traditional industries – tobacco, autos, food – have done.
The dominant position of a platform provider in core markets can then
be used to favour their products and services in satellite markets, further
extending the company’s reach. The European Commission is
investigating Google precisely because it is alleged systematically to tilt its
search results in favour of its own products. By the same token, many
users are not happy about Facebook appropriating, storing, analysing and
selling to third parties so much of their personal data. But as long as all
their friends are on Facebook, there is no equivalent competitor they can
turn to. The standard defence of companies such as Facebook that
‘competition is just one click away’ is simply false in markets where
network effects are so important.
A recent study by researchers at the University of Pennsylvania
surveyed 1,500 American Internet users to understand why they agree to
give up some privacy in return for access to Internet services and
applications. The standard explanation is that consumers compare the cost
of losing some privacy with the benefit of accessing these services for free,
and accept the deal when benefits exceed costs. A competing explanation
is that many users are simply unaware of the extent to which online
companies invade their privacy. But, interestingly, the results of the
Pennsylvania survey are inconsistent with both explanations. Instead, they
suggest that consumers accept being tracked and surrendering their
personal data, even if ideally they would prefer not to, not because they
have happily embraced this quid pro quo, but out of resignation and
frustration.
It is understandable that people feel they have no choice. In today’s
society, it is hard to live and work without using a well-functioning search
engine, a crowded social network and a well-supplied online shopping
platform. But the price of accessing these services is to accept the
conditions the dominant provider imposes on a ‘take it or leave it’ basis,
given that there are no comparable alternatives.
The digital giants’ enormous market power raises critical issues about
privacy protection, social control and political power. But what concerns
us here is the impact of this market power on the relationship between
value creation and value extraction.
The particular dynamics of innovation – the power of early adoption of
standards and associated network effects tending towards market
dominance – have profound consequences for how the value created is
shared and measured.
The first major consequence is monopoly. Historically, industries
naturally prone to being monopolies, for example railways and water, have
been either taken into public ownership (e.g. in Europe) or heavily
regulated (e.g. in the US) to protect the public against abuses of corporate
power. But monopolistic online platforms remain privately owned and
largely unregulated despite all the issues they raise: privacy, control of
information and their sheer commercial power in the market, to name a
few. In the absence of strong, transnational, countervailing regulatory
forces, firms that first establish market control can reap extraordinary
rewards. The low rates of tax that technology companies are typically
paying on these rewards are also paradoxical, given that their success was
built on technologies funded and developed by high-risk public
investments.74 If anything, companies owing their fortunes to taxpayer
investment should be repaying the taxpayer, not seeking tax breaks.
Moreover, the rise of the ‘sharing economy’ is likely to extend market
exchange into new areas, where the dynamics of market dominance look
set to repeat themselves.
The second major consequence of the dynamics of innovation is about
how value is created, how this is measured, and how and by whom this
value is extracted. If we go by national accounts, the contribution of
Internet platforms to national income (as measured for example by GDP)
is represented by the advertisement-related services they sell to firms. It is
not very clear why advertisements should contribute to the real national
product, let alone social well-being, which should be the aim of economic
activity. But national accounts, in this respect, are consistent with standard
neoclassical economics, which tends to interpret any voluntary market-
based transaction as signalling the production of some kind of output –
whether financial services or advertising, as long as a price is received, it
must be valuable.75 That is misleading: if online giants contribute to social
well-being, they do it through the services they provide to users, not
through the accompanying advertisements.
The classical economists’ approach appears much more fruitful for
analysing these new digital markets. As discussed in Chapter 1, they
distinguished between ‘productive’ labour, which contributes to an
increase in the value of what is produced, and ‘unproductive’ labour,
which does not. The activities which make profits for online platforms –
advertising and analyses of users’ private information and behaviour – do
not increase the value of what is produced, which is services to users such
as posting a message on Facebook or making a search on Google. Rather,
these activities help firms competing against one another to appropriate,
individually, a larger share of the value produced.76 The confused and
misleading approach to the concept of value that is currently dominating
economics is generating a truly paradoxical result: unproductive
advertising activities are counted as a net contribution of online giants to
national income, while the more valuable services that they provide to
users are not.
The rise of big data is often talked about as a win-win opportunity for
both producers and consumers. But this depends on who owns the data and
how it is ‘governed’. The fact that IPR has become wider and stronger, and
more upstream, is due to the way it is governed – or not. Markets of any
type must be actively shaped in order for knowledge to be governed in
ways that produce the market outcomes that we as a society want. Indeed,
regulation is not about interference, as is commonly perceived, but about
managing a process that produces the results that are best for society as a
whole. In the case of big data, the ‘big five’ – Facebook, Google, Amazon,
IBM and Microsoft – virtually monopolize it. But the problem is not just a
question of competition – the size and number of firms in the sector. It
could be argued that a few large companies can achieve the economies of
scale required to drive down costs and make data cheaper – not a bad thing
given falling real incomes.
The key issue is the relationship between the Internet monopolies and
these falling incomes. The privatization of data to serve corporate profits
rather than the common good produces a new form of inequality – the
skewed access to the profits generated from big data. Merely lowering the
price monopolists charge for access to data is not the solution. The
infrastructure that companies like Amazon rely on is not only publicly
financed (as discussed, the Internet was paid for by tax dollars), but it
feeds off network effects which are collectively produced. While it is of
course OK for companies to create services around new forms of data, the
critical issue is how to ensure that the ownership and management of the
data remains as collective as its source: the public. As Morozov argues,
‘Instead of us paying Amazon a fee to use its AI capabilities – built with
our data – Amazon should be required to pay that fee to us.’77
CONCLUSION
The important thing for Government is not to do things which individuals are doing
already, and to do them a little better or a little worse; but to do those things which at
present are not done at all.
John M. Keynes, The End of Laissez-Faire, 19261
The January 2010 edition of The Economist was devoted to the dangers of
big government. A large picture of a monster adorned the magazine’s
cover. The editorial opined: ‘The rich world has a clear choice: learn from
the mistakes of the past, or else watch Leviathan grow into a true monster.’
In a more recent issue, dedicated to future technological revolutions, the
magazine was explicit that government should stick to setting the rules of
the game: invest in basic goods like education and infrastructure, but then
get out of the way so that revolutionary businesses can do their thing.2
This, of course, is hardly a novel view. Throughout the history of
economic thought, government has long been seen as necessary but
unproductive, a spender and regulator, rather than a value creator.
Previous chapters revealed how actors in both the financial sector and
Silicon Valley have been particularly vociferous in their self-aggrandized
claims about wealth creation, using these claims to lobby for favourable
treatment that has in turn enabled them to reap rewards disproportionate to
the value they actually created. By the same token, others have widely but
mistakenly been regarded as ‘unproductive’.
As we have seen, finance has, ultimately, been less productive than it
claims to be. In this chapter I want to look at government, an actor that has
done more than it has been given credit for, and whose ability to produce
value has been seriously underestimated – and this has in effect enabled
others to have a stronger claim on their wealth creation role. But it is hard
to make the pitch for government when the term ‘public value’ doesn’t
even currently exist in economics. It is assumed that value is created in the
private sector; at best, the public sector ‘enables’ value.
After the 2008 financial crash – a crisis chiefly brought about by private,
not public, debt – governments saved the capitalist system from
breakdown. Not only did they pump money into the financial system: they
took over private assets. A few months after Lehman Brothers collapsed,
the US government was in charge of General Motors and Chrysler, the
British government was running high street banks and, across the OECD,
governments had committed the equivalent of 2.5 per cent of GDP to
rescuing the system.
And yet, even though the crisis was caused by a combination of high
private debt and reckless financial-sector behaviour, the extraordinary
policy conclusion was that governments were to blame – despite the fact
that, through bailouts and counter-cyclical stimulus, they had saved the
financial system from crumbling. Instead of being seen as the heroes that
stepped in to fix the mess created by private finance, they became the
villains. Of course there had been failings on all sides – abnormal interest
rates had contributed to the rise in debt – but the narrative became twisted
out of all recognition. This distortion was enabled by a view held since the
1970s that somehow the public sector is less able to engineer growth than
the private sector. What followed was a drive towards austerity across
Europe. And tragically, instead of being allowed to invest their way back
to pre-recessionary levels of output and employment, weaker European
countries were repeatedly told by the ‘troika’ (the IMF, European Central
Bank and European Commission) to cut public spending to the bone. Any
country whose budget deficits rose beyond the level stipulated in the
Maastricht Treaty were penalized severely, with conditions placed on
bailouts that even the pro-austerity IMF later admitted were self-defeating.
In a nutshell, austerity assumes that public debt is bad for growth, and
that the only way to reduce it is to cut government spending and debt by
running a budget surplus, irrespective of the possible social cost. With debt
down to an unspecified level and government finances ‘sound’, the private
sector will be freed to reignite prosperity.
The politics of ‘austerity’ has framed the policies of successive UK
Chancellors of the Exchequer and European finance ministers for almost a
decade. In the US, from Newt Gingrich in the 1990s to the legally
mandated spending cuts – sequestration – after the last financial crisis,
Congress has threatened periodically to shut down the Federal government
unless lower budget targets are met.
But this fixation on austerity to reduce debt misses a basic point: what
matters is long-run growth, its source (what is being invested in), and its
distribution (who reaps the rewards). If, through austerity, cuts are made to
essential areas that create the capacity for future growth (education,
infrastructure, care for a healthy population), then GDP (however ill
defined) will not grow. Moreover, the irony is that just cutting the deficit
may have little effect on the debt/GDP if the denominator of the ratio is
being badly affected. And if the cuts cause more inequality – as the
Institute for Fiscal Studies has shown was the case with the UK austerity
measures of the last years – consumption can only grow through debt (e.g.
credit cards), which maintains purchasing power. Instead, if public
investment is made in areas like infrastructure, innovation, education and
health, giving rise to healthy societies and creating opportunities for all,
tax revenues will most likely rise and debt fall relative to GDP.
It is crucial to understand that economic policy is not scientifically
ordained. You can impose austerity and hope the economy grows, even
though such a policy deprives it of demand; or you can focus on investing
in areas like health, training, education, research and infrastructure with
the belief that these areas are critical for long-run growth in GDP. In the
end, the choice of policy depends heavily on one’s perspective on the role
of government in the economy – is it key to creating value, or at best a
cheerleader on the sidelines?
Magic Numbers
The current debate about austerity has avoided any mention of public
value. Neither budget doves nor budget hawks have seriously questioned
the theory of value that underpins much ‘common-sense’ understanding of
market processes. A major reason for this lack of curiosity is that both
camps seem to have been in thrall to the so-called ‘magic’ numbers which
have framed the debate.
When, in 1992, European integration came into being through the
Maastricht Treaty, there were various obligations that the signatory
countries signed up to, one of which was to keep spending in check. Total
public debt was to be limited to 60 per cent of GDP, with annual deficits
(debt is the accumulation of deficits) not larger than 3 per cent of GDP.
These numbers purport to set objective limits to government indebtedness.
But where do they come from? You might imagine they are arrived at
through some kind of scientific process – but if so, you’d be wrong. These
numbers are taken out of thin air, supported by neither theory nor practice.
Let’s start with debt. In 2010 the American Economic Review published
an article by two top economists, professors at Harvard University:
Carmen Reinhart, ranked the following year by the Bloomberg Markets
magazine among the ‘Most Influential 50 in Finance’; and Kenneth
Rogoff, a former chief economist of the IMF.4 In this piece the pair
claimed that when the size of government debt (as a proportion of GDP) is
over 90 per cent (much higher than the 60 per cent of the Maastricht
Treaty, but still lower than that of many countries), economic growth falls.
The results showed that rich countries whose public debt exceeded that
percentage experienced a sharp drop in growth rate for the period 1946–
2009. This was a very important finding, as so many countries’ public debt
levels are close to or exceed this percentage. According to IMF data the
US debt/GDP ratio stood at 64 per cent in 2007, and 105 per cent in 2014.
For the UK the equivalent numbers were 44 per cent and 81 per cent; for
the European Union 58 per cent and 88 per cent, and for the Eurozone 65
per cent and 94 per cent.
Aware that the argument clearly gave ammunition to advocates of the
smaller state, the authors hastened to reassure their readers that they had
no skin in the game: that their argument had no ideological foundation, but
was based purely on empirical data. They even went so far as to stress that
their research had no underlying theory of government: ‘our approach
here’, they emphasized, ‘is decidedly empirical’.5
Predictably enough, politicians and technocrats eager to ‘balance’ public
spending seized on Reinhart and Rogoff’s research, which proved highly
influential in the post-2008 crisis debate about austerity measures. In his
Federal Budget Plan for 2013, passed by the US House of Representatives,
the Republican Congressman Paul Ryan cited the study as evidence for the
negative impact of high government debt on economic growth. It also
informed austerity policies proposed by then UK Chancellor George
Osborne and the EU Economy Commissioner, Olli Rehn.
Also in 2013, as part of his PhD studies, Thomas Herndon, a twenty-
eight-year-old student at the University of Massachusetts Amherst, tested
Reinhart and Rogoff’s data.6 He couldn’t replicate their results: his
calculations showed no steep drop in growth rates when debt was high.
Examining the professors’ data sheet, Herndon found a simple spreadsheet
error. He also discovered inconsistencies in the countries and data cited.7
In two articles in the New York Times,8 the professors defended their
general results, but accepted the spreadsheet error. Magic numbers were
not so magic after all.
Now on to the other magic number held so dear by EU economists: the
number 3. The ‘periphery’ countries of the Eurozone have been urged to
restore their competitiveness by downsizing the state. In line with the
Maastricht criteria, bailouts for countries like Cyprus, Greece, Ireland and
Portugal have been conditional on their cutting spending. If that spending
goes above 3 per cent of GDP then bailouts are jeopardized. Between 2010
and 2017, Greece received €260 billion in bailout aid, in exchange for
cutting state expenditure. However, since its problems were too structural
to be solved by a simple ‘austerity’ measure, the cuts pitched it into a deep
recession, turning into full-blown depression. And, rather than decreasing
Greece’s debt, the lack of growth has caused the debt/GDP ratio to rise to
179 per cent. The cure is killing the patient.
This obsessive focus on countries’ deficits ignores a stark reality. Some
of the weakest Eurozone countries have had lower deficits than the
stronger countries – Germany, for instance. What matters is not the deficit
but what government is doing with its funds. As long as these funds are
invested productively in sectors like healthcare, education, research and
others that increase productivity, then the debt/GDP denominator will rise,
keeping the ratio in check.
Italy is another glaring example of how magic numbers don’t work. For
the last two decades Italy’s budget deficit has been lower than Germany’s,
rarely exceeding the 3 per cent limit specified for euro membership.
Indeed, Italy has been running a primary budget surplus since 1991, the
only exception being 2009. And yet Italy has a high and rising debt/GDP
ratio: 133 per cent in 2015,9 way above the 60 per cent ceiling. The ratio is
less affected by the numerator (the budget deficit) than by the lack of
public and private investment determining the denominator (growth of
GDP). After three successive years of austerity, GDP grew by just 1 per
cent in 2015 (0.1 per cent in 2014, 0.9 per cent in 2016). (In fact, the
austerity years were responsible for an outstanding fall in real GDP: −2.8
per cent in 2012, −1.7 per cent in 2013.) So why has the economy
stagnated? The answer is complicated, but in part it is the result of
inadequate investment in areas that raise GDP, such as vocational training,
new technology and R&D. To make matters worse, a prolonged squeeze
on government spending has weakened demand in the Italian economy and
lowered the incentive to invest.
Yet Eurozone policy blindly persists in the conventional view that
austerity is the solution, and that inadequate growth indicates insufficient
austerity. Back in 2014, in a stinging attack on Eurozone political
economy,10 Joseph Stiglitz wrote: ‘Austerity has failed. But its defenders
are willing to claim victory on the basis of the weakest possible evidence:
the economy is no longer collapsing, so austerity must be working! But if
that is the benchmark, we could say that jumping off a cliff is the best way
to get down from a mountain; after all, the descent has been stopped.’ The
austerity policy of cutting taxes and government spending does not revive
investment and economic growth, when the real problem is weak demand.
And in countries like Greece and Spain, where 50 per cent of young people
cannot find work, pursuing policies that don’t actually affect investment –
and hence jobs – means that an entire generation can lose its right to a
prosperous future.
Questions of government debt and budget deficits are often also
confused with ones about the size of government, usually measured as the
ratio of government spending to the size of the economy. And yet there are
no magic numbers for what is too big or too small. France, frequently
touted as an example of ‘big government’, has a government
expenditure/GDP ratio of 58 per cent. The UK government’s spending is
also often regarded as quite big, but at about 40 per cent its ratio is not
much different to that of the US at 36 per cent – although the US is often
cited as an example of ‘small government’. Surprisingly, China, often
perceived as a state-run economy, has a ratio of only 30 per cent.
However, recent research into the impact of government size on
economic growth has found almost unanimously that small government is
‘bad’ if, for example, it cannot even maintain basic infrastructure, rule of
law (e.g. funding of police) and the educational needs of the population.
Conversely, the same research concludes that bigger government might be
‘bad’ if it is a result of activity that ‘crowds out’ (reduces) the private
sector11 or unduly restricts private-sector activity and interferes too much
in people’s lives.12 But within these rather obvious limits, the ideal size of
government is hard to quantify – not least because it depends heavily on
what you want government to do and how you value government activity.
And here we have a problem: there has been a dearth of thinking by
economists – both historically and in recent decades – about the value
created by government.
Multiplying Value
National accounts do not consider the interaction between public
expenditure and other components of output, consumption, investment and
net exports.
In order to understand this interconnection, economists estimate the
value of what is called the ‘multiplier’. The multiplier was an important
reason for Keynes’s positive view of government. Developed by Keynes’s
Cambridge student and colleague Richard Kahn (1905–1989) and used by
Keynes himself, it formalized the idea that government spending would
stimulate the economy. Quite literally: every pound that the government
spent would be multiplied, because the demand it created would lead to
several rounds of additional spending. Importantly, the Keynesian
approach also quantified the size of the multiplier, so policymakers – who
quickly took up the idea – could support their arguments for stimulus
spending with hard numbers.35
More precisely, the multiplier refers to the effect that an increase in
expenditure (demand) has on total production. Its significance lies in the
fact that, in the view of Keynes and Kahn, government spending benefits
the economy way beyond the amount of demand that spending generates.
The company from whom the government purchases its additional goods –
let’s say concrete for motorways – pays incomes to its workers, who go
out and spend those extra incomes on new goods – let’s say wide-screen
TVs – which another company produces, and that company’s employees
have more to spend – let’s say on holidays in Cornwall – and so it goes on
multiplying through the economy. Additional government demand creates
several subsequent rounds of spending, multiplying the original amount
spent. Government spending in recession was seen as especially powerful
in getting the economy back on track, since its effect on overall output was
much greater than the actual amount invested.
This powerful and important idea has inevitably attracted controversy,
particularly over the size of the multiplier – that is, how much £1 of
government spending generates in the economy. The sizeable literature on
the subject can be divided into two schools of thought: the ‘new classical’
and the Keynesian.
According to the ‘new classicals’, the proponents of fiscal austerity
measures, the multiplier’s value is less than one, or even negative.36 On
this basis they can argue that public expenditure has a non-Keynesian
effect on output. In other words, an increase of £1 of public expenditure is
supposed to generate less than £1 or even have a negative effect on total
GDP because it crowds out private investment. In the case of a negative
multiplier they assume that public expenditure destroys value, since the
increase of £1 in public expenditure is more than offset by a decrease in
the other components of GDP: consumption, investment and net exports.
However, the Keynesian view has been revived recently, since it has
been shown that austerity measures implemented in, for example, southern
European countries have led to a fall in total output and consequently a
rise in unemployment, rather than GDP growth and increased employment.
The poor economic performance of these countries calls into question the
austerity prescription of the ‘new classical’ authors. Recent IMF studies
have also suggested that government spending has a positive effect on
output37 and that the value of the multiplier is greater than one – to be
precise, 1.5.38 An increase of £1 of public expenditure leads to an increase
in total output of £1.50. In short, more credence is being given to the view
that government expenditure does not destroy private value but can create
value added by stimulating private investment and consumption.
Over its almost seventy years of existence, the NHS has become one of the
most efficient and equitable healthcare systems in the world, as recognized
by the World Health Organization46 and also more recently by the
Commonwealth Foundation.47 In the UK it is considered a national
treasure, sharing its place in the pantheon with the Queen and the BBC.
The NHS is also among the cheapest healthcare systems in advanced
economies: according to OECD figures from 2015,48 health expenditure
relative to GDP in the UK was only 9.9 per cent, almost half of what the
US has spent (16.9 per cent) on its far less efficient semi-private system.
The NHS owes much of its past successes to its public mission and to its
universality principle, translated into an efficient central provision of
healthcare services aimed at reducing transaction costs. UK citizens have
repeatedly recognized the importance of its public nature: currently, 84 per
cent of them think that it should be run in the public sector.49 Even Prime
Minister Thatcher stated: ‘The National Health Service is safe with us’
during the 1982 Conservative Party conferences, temporarily discarding
plans for outright privatization set out by the Central Policy Review Staff
within the Cabinet Office.
Nevertheless, such positive rhetoric on the merits of the NHS soon
became the cover for a long series of reforms that have progressively
introduced elements of private provision in the British healthcare system.
With the National Health Service and Community Care Act of 1990,
management and patient care were forced to behave as part of an ‘internal
market’, with health authorities and general practitioners becoming
autonomous purchasers of services under a limited budget. Hospitals were
transformed into self-governing NHS trusts and their resources became
dependent on contracts stipulated with purchasers. Contracting out to the
lowest bidder was also introduced as a first element of outsourcing, with
the NHS progressively moving away from its role of provider towards
becoming a mere customer. Since 1992, the outsourcing process created by
the Private Financing Initiative (PFI) has involved also the building of
NHS hospitals. Through PFI, private companies were allowed to build
hospitals which were then rented back to the NHS for a substantially high
price. PFI was widely used throughout the ‘New Labour’ governments to
save on infrastructure investment, with the renting price of hospitals
subsequently burdening the NHS budget. Finally, the 2012 Health and
Social Care Act de facto abolished the second principle of the original
NHS, by introducing user charges and an insurance-based system that
resembles the US healthcare model, passing costs and risks to patients,
now customers in a market for healthcare provision. This final reform has
also further increased the scope for outsourcing in many different areas,
such as cleaning, facilities management, GP ‘out of hours’ services,
clinical services, IT and so on.50
Those reforms were aimed at producing a more efficient and cost-
effective NHS, through the introduction of market elements in the
provision of healthcare. In reality the efficiency has hardly improved,
while ever-scarcer resources are largely misallocated. This is what Colin
Crouch has called ‘the paradox of public service outsourcing’.51 Market-
oriented reforms of healthcare fail to appreciate the evidence that there is
no such thing as a competitive market for those services: contracts run for
several years and they are granted to a small number of firms which come
to dominate the outsourcing market. Those firms become effectively
specialized in winning contracts from the public sector across different
fields in which they do not have a corresponding expertise. As a result, the
market is highly concentrated and the diversity of tasks makes it difficult
to obtain a quality-efficient outcome in all the services provided.
A study by Graham Kirkwood and Allyson Pollock shows that increased
private-sector provision is associated with a significant decrease in direct
NHS provision, a reduction in quality, and costs being propped up by the
public sector.52 There are many examples of inefficient outcomes created
by the outsourcing process, for example Coperform with the NHS’s South
East Coast ambulance service and Serco with out-of-hours GPs contracts
in Cornwall;53 in some cases the public had to cover losses when private
contractors withdrew from their obligations. Moreover, the whole system
of contracting out has a distortive effect on the activities of NHS
personnel. As noted by Pollock, ‘clinicians, nurses, managers and armies
of consultants and lawyers spend their days preparing multiple bids,
tenders and awarding contracts, instead of providing patient care’.54
Finally, outsourcing appears to be immensely cost-inefficient.
Contracting activities create a ‘new market bureaucracy’ that has to deal
with the cumbersome process. These administrative burdens are
effectively transaction costs that in the US represent around 30 per cent of
total healthcare expenditure, while in the UK the actual figure is not
known, although it was in the order of 6 per cent in the pre-marketization
NHS.55 Yet, perhaps the elephant in the room will be the huge burden for
the public that the PFIs will have created by the time their contracts expire.
Especially in the case of NHS hospitals, that cost is estimated to be several
times higher than the actual worth of the underlying assets.56
Although reaching a more efficient provision of healthcare services for a
lower cost has always been the stated purpose of outsourcing in the NHS,
recent evidence seems to suggest that this might just be the second phase
of what Noam Chomsky has called the ‘standard technique of
privatization: ‘defund, make sure things don’t work, people get angry, you
hand it over to private capital’.57
Once we recognize that the state is not just a spender but an investor and
risk taker, it becomes only sensible to ensure that policy leads to the
socialization not only of risks but also of rewards. A better realignment
between risks and rewards, across public and private actors, can turn
smart, innovation-led growth into inclusive growth.
As we have seen, neoclassical value theory for the most part disregards
the value created by government, such as an educated workforce, human
capital and the technology which ends up in our smart products.
Government is ignored in microeconomics – the study of production –
except in regulating the prices of inputs and outputs. It plays a bigger part
in macroeconomics, which deals with the economy as a whole, but at best
as a redistributor of the wealth created by companies and an investor in the
‘enabling’ conditions companies need – infrastructure, education, skills
and so on.
The marginal theory has fostered the idea that collectively produced
value derives from individual contributions. Yet, as the American
economist George Akerlof, who shared the Nobel Prize in Economics in
2001, said: ‘Our marginal products are not ours alone’71 – they are the
fruits of a cumulative process of learning and investment. Collective value
creation entails a risk-taking public sector – and yet the usual relationship
between risks and rewards, as taught in economics classes, does not seem
to apply. So the crucial question is not just about accounting for
government value but also rewarding it: how should rewards from
investment be divided between the public and private sectors?
As Robert Solow showed, most of the gains in productivity of the first
half of the twentieth century can be attributed not to labour and capital but
to the collective effort behind technical change. And this is due not only to
improved education and infrastructure, but also, as discussed in the
previous chapter, to the collective efforts behind some of the most radical
technical changes where the public sector has historically taken a lead role
– ‘the entrepreneurial state’.72 But the socialization of risks has not been
accompanied by socialization of rewards.
The issue, then, is how the state can reap some return from its successful
investments (the ‘upside’) to cover the inevitable losses (the ‘downside’) –
not least, to finance the next round of investments. This can be done in
various ways, as discussed in Chapter 7, whether through equity-holding,
conditions on reinvestment, caps on prices, or the need to keep patents as
narrow as possible.
The global financial crisis, which began in 2008 and whose repercussions
will continue to echo round the world for years to come, has triggered
myriad criticisms of the modern capitalist system: it is too ‘speculative’; it
rewards ‘rent-seekers’ over true ‘wealth creators’; and it has permitted the
rampant growth of finance, allowing speculative exchanges of financial
assets to be compensated more than investments that lead to new physical
assets and job creation. Debates about unsustainable growth have become
louder, with concerns not only about the rate of growth but also its
direction.
Recipes for serious reforms of this ‘dysfunctional’ system include
making the financial sector more focused on long-run investments;
changing the governance structures of corporations so they are less
focussed on their share prices and quarterly returns; taxing quick
speculative trades more heavily; legally and curbing the excesses of
executive pay.
In this book, I have argued that such critiques are important but will
remain powerless – in their ability to bring about real reform of the
economic system – until they become firmly grounded in a discussion
about the processes by which economic value is created. It is not enough to
argue for less value extraction and more value creation. First, ‘value’, a
term that once lay at the heart of economic thinking, must be revived and
better understood.
Value has gone from being a category at the core of economic theory,
tied to the dynamics of production (the division of labour, changing costs
of production), to a subjective category tied to the ‘preferences’ of
economic agents. Many ills, such as stagnant real wages, are interpreted in
terms of the ‘choices’ that particular agents in the system make, for
example unemployment is seen as related to the choice that workers make
between working and leisure. And entrepreneurship – the praised motor of
capitalism – is seen as a result of such individualized choices rather than of
the productive system surrounding entrepreneurs – or, to put it another
way, the fruit of a collective effort. At the same time, price has become the
indicator of value: as long as a good is bought and sold in the market, it
must have value. So rather than a theory of value determining price, it is
the theory of price that determines value.
Along with this fundamental shift in the idea of value, a different
narrative has taken hold. Focused on wealth creators, risk taking and
entrepreneurship, this narrative has seeped into political and public
discourse. It is now so rampant that even ‘progressives’ critiquing the
system sometimes unintentionally espouse it. When the UK Labour Party
lost the 2015 election, leaders of the party claimed they had lost because
they had not embraced the ‘wealth creators’.1 And who did they think the
wealth creators were? Businesses and the entrepreneurs leading them.
Feeding the idea that value is created in the private sector and redistributed
by the public sector. But how can a party that has the word ‘labour’ in its
title not see workers and the state as equally vital parts of the wealth
creation process?
Such assumptions about the generation of wealth have become
entrenched, and have gone unchallenged. As a result, those who claim to
be wealth creators have monopolised the attention of governments with the
now well-worn mantra of: give us less tax, less regulation, less state and
more market.
By losing our ability to recognize the difference between value creation
and value extraction, we have made it easier for some to call themselves
value creators and in the process extract value. Understanding how the
stories about value creation are around us everywhere – even though the
category itself is not – is a key concern of the book, and essential for the
future viability of capitalism.
To offer real change we must go beyond fixing isolated problems, and
develop a framework that allows us to shape a new type of economy: one
that will work for the common good. The change has to be profound. It is
not enough to redefine GDP to encompass quality-of-life indicators,
including measures of happiness,2 the imputed value of unpaid ‘caring’
labour and free information, education and communication via the
Internet.3 It is also not enough to tax wealth. While such measures are
important in themselves, they do not address the greatest challenge:
defining and measuring the collective contribution to wealth creation, so
that value extraction is less able to pass for value creation. As we have
seen, the idea that price determines value and that markets are best at
determining prices has all sorts of nefarious consequences. To sum up,
four stand out.
First, this narrative emboldens value extractors in finance and other
sectors of the economy. Here, the crucial questions – which kinds of
activities add value to the economy and which simply extract value for the
sellers – are never asked. In the current way of thinking, financial trading,
rapacious lending, funding property price bubbles are all value-added by
definition, because price determines value: if there is a deal to be done,
then there is value. By the same token, if a pharma company can sell a
drug at a hundred or a thousand times more than it costs to produce, there
is no problem: the market has determined the value. The same goes for
chief executives who earn 340 times more than the average worker (the
actual ratio in 2015 for companies in the S&P 500).4 The market has
decided the value of their services – there is nothing more to be said.
Economists are aware that some markets are not fair, for example when
Google has something close to a monopoly on search advertising; but they
are too often enthralled by the narrative of market efficiency to worry
whether the gains are actually justly earned profits, or merely rents.
Indeed, the distinction between profits and rents is not made.
Price-equals-value thinking encourages companies to put financial
markets and shareholders first, and to offer as little as possible to other
stakeholders. This ignores the reality of value creation – as a collective
process. In truth, everything concerning a company’s business – especially
the underlying innovation and technological development – is intimately
interwoven with decisions made by elected governments, investments
made by schools, universities, public agencies and even movements by
not-for-profit institutions. Corporate leaders are not telling the whole truth
when they say that shareholders are the only real risk takers and hence
deserve the lion’s share of the gains from doing business.
Second, the conventional discourse devalues and frightens actual and
would-be value creators outside the private business sector. It’s not easy to
feel good about yourself when you are constantly being told you’re
rubbish and/or part of the problem. That’s often the situation for people
working in the public sector, whether these be nurses, civil servants or
teachers. The static metrics used to measure the contribution of the public
sector, and the influence of Public Choice theory on making governments
more ‘efficient’, has convinced many civil-sector workers they are second-
best. It’s enough to depress any bureaucrat and induce him or her to get up,
leave and join the private sector, where there is often more money to be
made.
So public actors are forced to emulate private ones, with their almost
exclusive interest in projects with fast paybacks. After all, price determines
value. You, the civil servant, won’t dare to propose that your agency could
take charge, bring a helpful long-term perspective to a problem, consider
all sides of an issue (not just profitability), spend the necessary funds
(borrow if required) and – whisper it softly – add public value. You leave
the big ideas to the private sector which you are told to simply ‘facilitate’
and enable. And when Apple or whichever private company makes
billions of dollars for shareholders and many millions for top executives,
you probably won’t think that these gains actually come largely from
leveraging the work done by others – whether these be government
agencies, not-for-profit institutions, or achievements fought for by civil
society organizations including trade unions that have been critical for
fighting for workers’ training programmes.
Third, this market story confuses policymakers. By and large,
policymakers of all stripes want to help their communities and their
country, and they think the way to do so is to put more trust in market
mechanisms, with policy just a matter of tinkering at the edges. The crucial
thing is to be seen as progressive while also ‘business-friendly’. But with a
very limited understanding of where value comes from, politicians and all
too many government employees are like putty in the hands of those who
claim to be value creators. Regulators end up being lobbied by businesses
and induced to endorse policies which make incumbents even richer –
increasing profits but with little effect on investment. Examples include
ways in which governments across much of the Western world have been
persuaded to reduce capital gains tax, even though there is no reason to do
so if the aim is to promote long-term investments rather than short-term
ones. And lobbyists with their innovation stories have pushed through the
Patent Box policy, which reduces tax on the profits generated from 20-year
patent-based monopolies – even though the policy’s main impact has been
merely to reduce government revenue, rather than increasing the types of
investments that led to the patents in the first place.5 All of which serves
only to subtract value from the economy and make for a less attractive
future for almost everyone. Not having a clear view of the collective value
creation process, the public sector is thus ‘captured’ – entranced by stories
about wealth creation which have led to regressive tax policies that
increase inequality.
Fourth, and last, the confusion between profits and rents appears in the
ways we measure growth itself: GDP. Indeed, it is here that the production
boundary comes back to haunt us: if anything that fetches a price is value,
then the way national accounting is done wont be able to distinguish value
creation from value extraction and thus policies aimed that the former
might simply lead to the latter. This is not only true for the environment
where picking up the mess of pollution will definitely increase GDP (due
to the cleaning services paid for) while a cleaner environment won’t
necessarily (indeed if it leads to less ‘things’ produced it could decrease
GDP), but also as we saw to the world of finance where the distinction
between financial services that feed industry’s need for long-term credit
versus those financial services that simply feed other parts of the financial
sector are not distinguished.
Only with a clear debate about value can rent-extracting activities in
every sector, including the public one, be better identified and deprived of
political and ideological strength.
MARKETS AS OUTCOMES
The concept of value must once again find its rightful place at the centre of
economic thinking. More fulfilling jobs, less pollution, better care, more
equal pay – what sort of economy do we want? When that question is
answered, we can decide how to shape our economic activities, thereby
moving activities that fulfill these goals inside the production boundary so
they are rewarded for steering growth in the ways we deem desirable. And
in the meantime we can also make a much better job of reducing activities
that are purely about rent-seeking and calibrating rewards more closely
with truly productive activity.
I began the book stating that the goal was not to argue that one value
theory is better than another. My aim is for the book to stir a new debate,
putting value back at the centre of economic reasoning. This is not about
drawing firm and static fences around the production boundary, arguing
that some actors are parasitic or takers, while others are glorious producers
and makers. Rather we should have a more dynamic understanding of what
making and taking are in the context of the societal objectives we have.
Both objective and subjective factors will no doubt come into play, but the
subjective ones should not reduce everything to an individual choice,
stripped from the social, political and economic context in which decisions
are made. It is those very contexts that are affected by the (objective)
dynamics of technological change and corporate governance structures.
The latter will affect the way that income distribution is determined, as
will the strength of workers to bargain their share. These structural forces
are results of decision-making inside organizations. There is nothing
inevitable or deterministic about it.
I have tried to open the new dialogue by showing that the creation of
value is collective, that policy can be more active around co-shaping and
co-creating markets, and that real progress requires a dynamic division of
labour focused on the problems that twenty-first-century societies are
facing. If I have been critical, it’s because such criticism is badly needed;
it is, moreover, a necessary preliminary to the creation of a new
economics: an economics of hope. After all, if we cannot dream of a better
future and try to make it happen, there is no real reason why we should
care about value. And this perhaps is the greatest lesson of all.
Notes
PREFACE
1. https://www.ft.com/content/294ff1f2-0f27-11de-ba10-0000779fd2ac
2. These figures give an approximate idea of the weight of large
companies in the economy. On the one hand, some companies do not
report their turnover, so total revenues are underestimated. On the
other hand, the list includes the biggest banks.
3. G. Mukunda, ‘The price of Wall Street’s power’, Harvard Business
Review, June 2014.
4. E. Hadas, ‘Seeing straight: Why buybacks should be banned’,
Breakingviews, 14 December 2014:
https://www.breakingviews.com/features/why-buybacks-should-be-
banned/
5. W. Lazonick, ‘Profits without prosperity’, Harvard Business Review,
September 2014.
6. Ibid.
7. http://online.wsj.com/public/resources/documents/blackrockletter.pdf
8. Source: Adapted from Lazonick, ‘Profits without prosperity’.
9. Jensen and Meckling, ‘Theory of the firm’, pp. 305–60.
10. Source: Bain & Co., Global Private Equity Report (2015), fig. 2, p. 43.
11. https://www.blackstone.com/the-firm/asset-management/private-equity
12. D. Burns, L. Cowie, J. Earles, P. Folkman, J. Froud, P. Hyde, S. Johal,
I. Rees Jones, A. Killett and K. Williams, Where Does the Money Go?
Financialised Chains and the Crisis in Residential Care, CRESC
Public Interest Report, March 2015.
13. G. Ruddick, ‘Four Seasons Health Care reports £264m annual loss’,
the Guardian, 27 April 2016.
14. K. Bayliss, ‘Case study: The financialisation of water in England and
Wales’, FESSUD (Financialisation, Economy, Society and Sustainable
Development), Working Paper series no. 52 (2014).
15. W. Lazonick, ‘Innovative enterprise or sweatshop economics? In
search of foundations of economic analysis’, ISIGrowth Working
Paper no. 17 (2016).
16. P. Aghion, J. Van Reenen and L. Zingales, ‘Innovation and
institutional ownership’, American Economic Review, 103(1) (2013),
pp. 277–304.
17. Bogle, The Clash of the Cultures.
18. J. M. Keynes, The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money
(London: Macmillan, 1936), p. 154.
19. Ibid., p. 155.
20. S. Patterson, Dark Pools: The Rise of AI Trading Machines and the
Looming Threat to Wall Street (New York: Random House, 2012).
21. Amy Or, ‘Average private equity hold times drop to 5.5 years’, Wall
Street Journal, 10 June 2015.
22. D. Barton and M. Wiseman, ‘Focusing capital on the long term’,
Harvard Business Review, January–February 2014.
23. Ibid.
24. Keynes, General Theory of Employment, pp. 161–2.
25. Return on Invested Capital is a measure of profitability. It is calculated
by dividing net (after tax) operating profits by invested capital (less
cash and cash equivalents).
26. J. P. Morgan, ‘Bridging the gap between interest rates and
investments’, JPM Corporate Finance Advisory, September 2014.
27. K. J. Murphy, ‘Executive compensation: Where we are, and how we
got there’, in G. M. Constantinides, M. Harris and R. M. Stulz (eds),
Handbook of the Economics of Finance, vol. 2 (Amsterdam: Elsevier,
2013), pp. 211–356.
28. L. Mishel and J. Schieder, CEO Pay Remains High Relative to the Pay
of Typical Workers and High-wage Earners (Washington, DC:
Economic Policy Institute, 2017).
29. The Conference Board, CEO Succession Practices: 2017 Edition,
https://www.conference-board.org/publications/publicationdetail.cfm?
publicationid=7537
30. Fig. 26 depicts data retrieved from the Bureau of Economic Analysis
website.
31. J. Asker, J. Farre-Mensa and A. Ljungqvist, ‘Comparing the
investment behavior of public and private firms’, NBER Working
Paper No. 17394 (September 2011).
32. Author’s elaboration of data from the Bureau of Economic Analysis.
33. Author’s elaboration of data from the Bureau of Economic Analysis.
34. Bogle, The Clash of the Cultures, pp. 22–3.
35. M. Friedman, Capitalism and Freedom (Chicago: University Press,
1962), p. 133.
36. R. E. Freeman, J. S. Harrison, A. C. Wicks, B. L. Parmar and S. de
Colle, Stakeholder Theory: The State of the Art (Cambridge:
University Press, 2010), p. 268.
37. https://www.kfw.de/KfW-Group/About-KfW/Identität/Geschichte-der-
KfW/
38. C. Leggett, ‘The Ford Pinto case: The valuation of life as it applies to
the negligence-efficiency argument’, Law & Valuation, Spring 1999.
39. C. Perez, Technological Revolutions and Financial Capital: The
Dynamics of Bubbles and Golden Ages (Cheltenham: Edward Elgar,
2002).
40. C. Perez, ‘The Double bubble at the turn of the century: Technological
roots and structural implications’, Cambridge Journal of Economics
33(4) (2009), p. 801.
7. EXTRACTING VALUE THROUGH THE INNOVATION ECONOMY
1. https://www.netmarketshare.com/search-engine-market-share.aspx?
qprid=4&qpcustomd=0
2. R. Solow, ‘Technical change and the aggregate production function’,
Review of Economics and Statistics, 39 (3) (1957), pp. 312–20: JSTOR
1926047; R. R. Nelson and S. G. Winter, An Evolutionary Theory of
Economic Change (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 2009).
3. D. J. Teece, ‘Profiting from technological innovation’, Research
Policy, 15(6) (1986), pp. 285–305.
4. https://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/2015/11/we-need-an-
energy-miracle/407881/
5. https://www.washingtonpost.com/opinions/americas-miracle-machine-
is-in-desperate-need-of-well-a-miracle/2017/05/05/daafbe6a-30e7-
11e7-9534-00e4656c22aa_story.html?utm_term=.b38348fbc471
6. https://hbr.org/2014/05/why-germany-dominates-the-u-s-in-innovation
7. M. K. Block and F. Keller, ‘Explaining the transformation in the US
innovation system: The impact of a small government program’,
Socioeconomic Review 11(4) (2013), pp. 629–56:
https://doi.org/10.1093/ser/mws021
8. S. W. Leslie, The Cold War and American Science: The Military-
Industrial-Academic Complex at MIT and Stanford (New York:
Columbia University Press, 1993).
9. See W. Lazonick, Sustainable Prosperity in the New Economy?
Business Organization and High-Tech Employment in the United
States (Kalamazoo, MI: W. E. Upjohn Institute for Employment
Research, 2009), ch. 2: doi: https://doi.org/10.17848/9781441639851
10. Business Week, 1960, cited in H. Lazonick, Sustainable Prosperity in
the New Economy? Business Organization and High-tech Employment
in the United States (Kalamazoo, MI: Upjohn Press, 2009), p. 79.
11. W. Lazonick and M. Mazzucato, ‘The risk–reward nexus in the
innovation–inequality relationship: Who takes the risks? Who gets the
rewards?’, Industrial and Corporate Change, 22(4) (2013), pp. 1093–
128: https://doi.org/10.17848/9781441639851 The structure of this
market is particularly important in understanding where innovation risk
truly lies. Liquidity is provided by market makers, who underwrite
IPOs and ensure the instant sale and purchase of stock at close to
market prices. In this way, investor risk is transferred to market
makers. Market makers are backed by investment banks, which – as it
turns out – are underwritten by the government (K. Ellis, R. Michaely
and M. O’Hara, ‘When the underwriter is the market maker: An
examination of trading in the IPO aftermarket’, Journal of Finance,
55(3) (1999), pp. 1039–74.
12. ‘I have worked with investors for 60 years and I have yet to see anyone
– not even when capital gains rates were 39.9 per cent in 1976–77 –
shy away from a sensible investment because of the tax rate on the
potential gain. People invest to make money, and potential taxes have
never scared them off. And to those who argue that higher rates hurt
job creation, I would note that a net of nearly 40 million jobs were
added between 1980 and 2000. You know what’s happened since then:
lower tax rates and far lower job creation.’, The New York Times, 14
August 2011: http://www.nytimes.com/2011/08/15/opinion/stop-
coddling-the-super-rich.html?_r=2&hp
13. Lazonick and Mazzucato, ‘The risk–reward nexus in the innovation–
inequality relationship’.
14. N. Henderson and M. Schrage, ‘The roots of biotechnology:
Government R&D spawns a new industry’, Washington Post, 16
December 1984:
https://www.washingtonpost.com/archive/politics/1984/12/16/government-
r38/cb580e3d-4ce2-4950-bf12-a717b4d3ca36/?
utm_term=.27fd51946872. I am grateful to William Lazonick for
pointing me to this article.
15. This section on the role of venture capital and the following section on
executive pay draw heavily on Lazonick and Mazzucato, ‘The risk–
reward nexus in the innovation–inequality relationship’.
16. Ibid.
17. Ibid.
18. P. A. Gompers and J. Lerner, The Venture Capital Cycle (Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press, 2002).
19. See S. Davidoff, ‘Why I.P.O.s get underpriced’, Dealbook, New York
Times, 27 May 2011; J. Ritter, IPO data website, 2012:
http://bear.warrington.ufl.edu/ritter/ipodata.htm; M. Gimein, E. Dash,
L. Munoz and J. Sung, ‘You bought. They SOLD’, Fortune, 146(4)
(2002), pp. 64–8, 72, 74.
20. Gary P. Pisano, Science Business: The Promise, the Reality, and the
Future of Biotech (Boston, MA: Harvard Business School Press,
2006).
21. W. Lazonick and Ö. Tulum, ‘US biopharmaceutical finance and the
sustainability of the US biotech business model’, Research Policy,
40(9) (2011), pp. 1170–87.
22. R. Fontana, A. Nuvolari, H. Shimizu and A. Vezzulli, ‘Reassessing
patent propensity: Evidence from a dataset of R&D awards, 1977–
2004’, Research Policy 42(10) (2013), pp. 1780–92.
23. More formally, a patent holder is awarded a ‘probabilistic’ right to
exclude others from using and commercializing an invention (M. A.
Lemley and C. Shapiro, ‘Probabilistic patents’, Journal of Economic
Perspectives, 19(2) (2005), pp. 75–98: doi:
10.1257/0895330054048650). The patentee must be willing and able to
enforce its rights against infringement of the patent. The patentee can
license others to use the invention in exchange for royalties.
24. The intensity of patenting activity and the importance of patents – both
in relation to appropriability and disclosure – varies in importance
across countries, sectors, technologies, and by firm size. Firms in
pharmaceuticals, biotechnology and ICT, for example, tend to patent
more than firms in other areas. Patents are the most important
appropriability mechanism for pharmaceutical companies, for example,
whereas in other sectors firms may rely more on secrecy, lead-times to
production, trademarks and additional complementary assets to gain
from their inventions. Similarly, patents play a far more important role
in the diffusion of information for R&D labs in manufacturing firms in
Japan compared with those in the US, where publication and informal
information exchange is more important (W. M. Cohen, A. Goto, A.
Nagata, R. R. Nelson and J. P. Walsh, ‘R&D spillovers, patents and the
incentives to innovate in Japan and the United States’, Research
Policy, 1(8–9) (2002), pp. 1349–67: doi: http://doi.org/10.1016/S0048-
7333(02)00068-9
25. According to M. A. Lemley, in ‘Software patents and the return of
functional claiming’, Wisconsin Law Review, 2013(4), pp. 905–64, the
costs of software innovation are lower than innovation in the life
sciences. Software is also protected by copyrights, which already
provide for effective prevention of copying by others. Network effects
may help innovators to capture returns regardless of intellectual
property protection (more on this later in this chapter). There is, in
addition, the open-source community, which suggests that patents may
not be a necessary condition for innovation in the sector. Finally,
software patentability varies across regions and countries (for example,
it is limited in Europe and India, and broad in the US), which also
suggests that patent protection may reflect a policy choice.
26. Baumol, ‘Entrepreneurship: Productive, unproductive, and
destructive’.
27. R. Mazzoleni and R. R. Nelson, ‘The benefits and costs of strong
patent protection: A contribution to the current debate’, Research
Policy, 27(3) (1998), pp. 273–84.
28. M. Kenney and D. Patton, ‘Reconsidering the Bayh–Dole Act and the
current university invention ownership model’, Research Policy, 38(9)
(2009), pp. 1407–22.
29. http://www.nybooks.com/articles/2004/07/15/the-truth-about-the-drug-
companies/
30. L. Burlamaqui and R. Kattel, ‘Development as leapfrogging, not
convergence, not catch-up: Towards Schumpeterian theories of finance
and development’, Review of political Economy, 28(2) (2016), pp.
270–88.
31. Mazzoleni and Nelson, ‘The benefits and costs of strong patent
protection’.
32. S. Haber and S. H. Werfel, ‘Why do inventors sell to patent trolls?
Experimental evidence for the asymmetry hypothesis’, Stanford
University Working Paper, 27 April 2015.
33. J. Bessen and M. J. Meurer, ‘The Patent Litigation Explosion’, Loyola
University Chicago Law Journal, 45(2) (2013), pp. 401–40:
http://lawecommons.luc.edu/luclj/vol45/iss2/5
34. J. E. Bessen et al., ‘Trends in private patent costs and rents for
publicly-traded United States firms’(March 2015). Boston University
School of Law, Public Law Research Paper no. 13–24: SSRN:
https://ssrn.com/abstract=2278255 or
http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2278255
35. C. V. Chien, ‘Startups and patent trolls’, Stanford Technology Law
Review, 17 (2014), pp. 461–506.
36. W. J. Baumol, Entrepreneurship, Management and the Nature of
Payoffs (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993), ch. 2, p. 25; see also ch.
4.
37. Foley, ‘Rethinking financial capitalism and the “information”
economy’.
38. The Economist, 8 August 2015:
http://www.economist.com/news/leaders/21660522-ideas-fuel-
economy-todays-patent-systems-are-rotten-way-rewarding-them-time-
fix
39. C. Forero-Pineda, ‘The impact of stronger intellectual property rights
on science and technology in developing countries’, Research Policy
35(6) (2006), pp. 808–24.
40. E. M. F. t’Hoen, The Global Politics of Pharmaceutical Monopoly
Power: Drug Patents, Access, Innovation and the Application of the
WTO Doha Declaration on TRIPS and Public Health (Diemen: AMB,
2009).
41. M. Mazzucato, The Entrepreneurial State: Debunking Private vs.
Public Sector Myths (London: Anthem Press, 2013).
42. Source: US Department of Health and Human Services:
http://www.hhs.gov/opa/reproductive-health/stis/hepatitis-c and World
Health Organization: http://www.euro.who.int/en/health-
topics/communicable-diseases/hepatitis/data-and-statistics
43. Sovaldi is, however, more costly than Harvoni overall, because it
needs to be taken in combination with other drugs.
44. The letter is available at
http://www.finance.senate.gov/imo/media/doc/Wyden-
Grassley%20Document%20Request%20to%20Gilead%207-11-
141.pdf
45. A. Hill, S. Khoo, J. Fortunak, B. Simmons and N. Ford, ‘Minimum
costs for producing hepatitis C direct-acting antivirals for use in large-
scale treatment access programs in developing countries’, Clinical
Infectious Diseases, 58(7) (2014), pp. 928–36: doi: 10.1093/cid/ciu012
46. M. Mazzucato, ‘High cost of new drugs’, British Medical Journal,
354: i4136 (2016):
http://www.bmj.com/cgi/content/full/354/jul2710/i4136
47. D. W. Light and J. R. Lexchin, ‘Pharmaceutical research and
development: What do we get for all that money?’, British Medical
Journal 345:e4348 (2012): http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/bmj.e4348
48. A. Swanson, ‘Big pharmaceutical companies are spending far more on
marketing than research’, Washington Post, 11 February, 2015:
http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/wonkblog/wp/2015/02/11/big-
pharmaceutical-companies-are-spending-far-more-on-marketing-than-
research/
49. Lazonick, ‘Profits without prosperity’.
50. Mazzucato, The Entrepreneurial State.
51. H. Kantarjian and S. V. Rajkumar, ‘Why are cancer drugs so expensive
in the United States, and what are the solutions?’, Mayo Clinic
Proceedings, April 2015, report that 85 per cent of basic cancer
research in the US is funded by the government.
52. J. Sachs, ‘The drug that is bankrupting America’, Huffington Post, 16
February 2015: http://www.huffingtonpost.com/jeffrey-sachs/the-drug-
that-is-bankrupt_b_6692340.html
53. V. Roy and L. King, ‘Betting on hepatitis C: How financial speculation
in drug development influences access to medicines’, British Medical
Journal, 354:i3718 (2016).
54. P. Barrett and R. Langreth, ‘Pharma execs don’t know why anyone is
upset by a $94,500 miracle cure’, Bloomberg Businessweek, 3 June
2015: https://www.bloomberg.com/news/articles/2015-06-
03/specialty-drug-costs-gilead-s-hepatitis-c-cures-spur-backlash
55. LaMattina’s article on Forbes is available at:
http://www.forbes.com/sites/johnlamattina/2014/08/04/politicians-
shouldnt-question-drug-costs-but-rather-their-value-lessons-from-
soliris-and-sovaldi/
56. R. Zirkelbach, ‘The five essential truths about prescription drug
spending’, March 2015, available on PhRMA website at:
http://catalyst.phrma.org/the-five-essential-truths-about-prescription-
drug-spending
57. See for example Hilner and Smith, ‘Efficacy does not necessarily
translate to cost effectiveness’.
58. Peter Bach’s interactive calculator can be accessed at
www.drugabacus.org
59. According to the ranking compiled by Forbes for 2014, on average the
ten largest pharmaceutical companies enjoy a 19 per cent net profit rate
– the highest of all industries included in Forbes’ worldwide analysis.
Pfizer leads the group with a remarkable 41 per cent net profit margin.
Only large banks, which are well known to enjoy rents because of their
size and political influence, earn a profit rate comparable to that of
large pharmaceutical companies, while for example the ten largest
automobile companies – also one of the most profitable industries in
the world – have on average a 6 per cent net profit rate.
60. P. David, ‘Clio and the Economics of QWERTY’, American Economic
Review, 75(2), Papers and Proceedings of the Ninety-Seventh Annual
Meeting of the American Economic Association (May 1985), pp. 332–
7; G. Dosi, ‘Sources, procedures, and microeconomic effects of
innovation’, Journal of Economic Literature, vol. 26 (1988), pp. 1120–
71.
61. According to its own mission statement, for example, ‘Facebook’s
mission is to give people the power to share and make the world more
open and connected’ (investor.fb.com/faq.cfm). Sergey Brin, one of
Google’s founders and President of its parent company Alphabet, has
often talked about Google as trying to be against evil, and a ‘force for
good’. http://www.businessinsider.com.au/best-quotes-google-sergey-
brin-2014-7#to-me-this-is-about-preserving-history-and-making-it-
available-to-everyone-1
62. K. Kelly, ‘The new socialism: Global collectivist society is coming
online’, Wired magazine, 17 June 2009.
63. E. Morozov, ‘Silicon Valley likes to promise “digital socialism” – but
it is selling a fairy tale’, the Guardian, 28 February 2015.
64. Variously attributed. Common attribution is to Andrew Lewis, as
blue_beetle on MetaFilter 2010, ‘If you’re not paying for it, you’re not
the customer; you’re the product being sold’:
http://www.metafilter.com/95152/Userdriven-discontent#3256046
65. M. J. Sandel, What Money Can’t Buy: The Moral Limits of Markets
(London and New York: Allen Lane and Farrar, Straus and Giroux,
2013).
66. Evgeny Morozov, ‘Don’t believe the hype, the “sharing economy”
masks a failing economy’, the Guardian, 28 September 2014:
http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2014/sep/28/sharing-
economy-internet-hype-benefits-overstated-evgeny-morozov; Evgeny
Morozov, ‘Cheap cab ride? You must have missed Uber’s true cost’,
the Guardian, 31 January 2016:
http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2016/jan/31/cheap-cab-
ride-uber-true-cost-google-wealth-taxation
67. Evgeny Morozov, ‘Where Uber and Amazon rule: welcome to the
world of the platform’, the Guardian, 7 June 2015:
http://www.theguardian.com/technology/2015/jun/07/facebook-uber-
amazon-platform-economy
68. https://www.bloomberg.com/news/articles/2017-02-28/in-video-uber-
ceo-argues-with-driver-over-falling-fares
69. http://fortune.com/2016/10/20/uber-app-riders/
70. A useful distinction can be made between direct and indirect network
effects. When a higher number of participants increases the benefit to
each individual member – as in the case of Facebook – the effect is
direct. Where, instead, a higher number of members (for example,
buyers) increases the convenience of using the platform, not for the
members but for another group (for example, the sellers), we talk of
indirect network effects.
71. Source: Statista database (www.statista.com), and
http://uk.businessinsider.com/facebook-and-google-winners-of-digital-
advertising-2016-6?r=US&IR=T
72. Morozov, ‘Where Uber and Amazon rule’.
73. See note 70 for the distinction between direct and indirect network
effects.
74. Mazzucato, The Entrepreneurial State.
75. Foley, ‘Rethinking financial capitalism and the “information”
economy’.
76. See ibid. for a rigorous but accessible explanation of the classical
theory of surplus value and how it can be used to provide an alternative
interpretation of the so-called ‘new economy’.
77. https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2016/dec/04/data-
populists-must-seize-information-for-benefit-of-all-evgeny-morozov
78. H. A. Simon, ‘Public administration in today’s world of organizations
and markets’, PS: Political Science and Politics, December 2000, p.
756.
79. https://www.theguardian.com/technology/2016/jun/09/uber-suffers-
legal-setbacks-in-france-and-germany
https://www.theguardian.com/technology/2016/jun/08/berlin-ban-
airbnb-short-term-rentals-upheld-city-court
https://www.theguardian.com/media/2016/may/25/netflix-and-amazon-
must-guarantee-20-of-content-is-european
80. For a discussion of the criteria and implementation issues behind
mission-oriented policies see my recent report, M. Mazzucato,
Mission-oriented research & innovation in the European Union – A
problem-solving approach to fuel innovation-led growth, European
Commission, 2018.
81. Such thinking is indeed what has inspired Mission Innovation (MI;
http://mission-innovation.net), an alliance of twenty-two ministers and
the European Union to combat climate change through national
commitments (around $20 billion) to invest in clean energy innovation.
The coalition was announced on 30 November 2015 during the COPS
meeting in Paris. On the private-sector side the Breakthrough Coalition
is committing an equal amount of money. Since 2014 I have been
leading a project on the need for such mission-oriented thinking in
innovation: http://marianamazzucato.com/projects/mission-oriented-
innovation-policy/
8. UNDERVALUING THE PUBLIC SECTOR
1. https://www.gov.uk/government/speeches/mansion-house-2015-
speech-by-the-chancellor-of-the-exchequer
2. ‘The third industrial revolution’, The Economist, 21 April 2012:
http://www.economist.com/node/21553017
3. K. Polanyi, The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic
Origins of Our Time (1944; Boston MA: Beacon Press, 2001), p. 144.
4. C. M. Reinhart and K. S. Rogoff, ‘Growth in a time of debt’, American
Economic Review, 100(2) (2010), pp. 573–8.
5. Ibid., p. 573.
6. T. Herndon, M. Ash and R. Pollin, ‘Does high public debt consistently
stifle economic growth? A critique of Reinhart and Rogoff’,
Cambridge Journal of Economics, 38(2) (2014), pp. 257–79:
http://doi.org/10.1093/cje/bet075, p. 5.
7. Ibid., pp. 7–8.
8. Reinhart and Rogoff:
http://www.nytimes.com/2013/04/26/opinion/debt-growth-and-the-
austerity-debate.html?_r=0 and Reinhard and Rogoff:
http://www.nytimes.com/2013/04/26/opinion/reinhart-and-rogoff-
responding-to-our-critics.html
9. http://www.focus-economics.com/countries/italy
10. https://www.theguardian.com/business/2014/oct/01/austerity-
eurozone-disaster-joseph-stiglitz
11. Crowding out usually refers to the negative effect that government
spending or investment may have on private investment, primarily
because either government borrowing pushes up interest rates (making
it harder for business to take out loans) or because government moves
into activities that were in the private sector. Analyses on crowding out
have been problematic due to the lack of proper analysis of what the
private sector is willing to do.
12. A. Bergh and M. Henrekson, ‘Government size and growth: A survey
and interpretation of the evidence’, Journal of Economic Surveys,
25(5) (2011), pp. 872–97: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-
6419.2011.00697.x
13. P. Steiner, ‘Wealth and power: Quesnay’s political economy of the
“Agricultural Kingdom” ’, Journal of the History of Economic
Thought, 24(1) (2002), pp. 91–110.
14. The ‘sterile class’ comprised city dwellers or artisans. In Schumpeter’s
History of Economic Analysis, p. 239, the same word is used to
describe the ‘bourgeoisie’. ‘Disposable class’ is the name that Turgot
gave to the class of landowners (classe
propriétaire/souveraine/distributive).
15. Quesnay, quoted in Steiner, ‘Wealth and power’, p. 99.
16. Schumpeter, History of Economic Analysis, p. 230; Steiner, ‘Wealth
and Power’, p. 100.
17. Smith, The Wealth of Nations, Book IV, Introduction.
18. Ibid., Book I, ch. 1.
19. Ibid., Book V, ch. 1.
20. Ibid.
21. David Ricardo, The Works and Correspondence of David Ricardo, ed.
P. Sraffa with the collaboration of M. H. Dobb, vol. 1: On the
Principles of Political Economy and Taxation (Cambridge: University
Press, 1951), p. 150.
22. Ibid., p. 151.
23. Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The Communist Manifesto (1848;
London: Penguin Classics, 2010), ch. 1.
24. A. Marshall, Principles of Economics (1890; London: Macmillan,
1920), Book I, ch. 4, para. 4.
25. Ibid.
26. B. Snowdon and H. Vane, A Macroeconomics Reader (London:
Routledge, 1997), p. 3.
27. Keynes, The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money, p.
249.
28. This and the following are from the Preface to the French edition of
The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money.
29. R. Reich, ‘Economist John Maynard Keynes’, TIME magazine, 29
March 1999.
30. McLeay, Radia and Thomas, ‘Money creation in the modern
economy’, p. 14.
31. BEA, Measuring the Economy: A Primer on GDP and the National
Income and Product Accounts (Washington, DC: Bureau of Economic
Analysis, US Department of Commerce, 2014), pp. 9–4:
http://www.bea.gov/national/pdf/nipa_primer.pdf
32. T. Atkinson, Atkinson Review: Final Report. Measurement of
Government Output and Productivity for the National Accounts
(Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005).
33. M. G. Phelps, S. Kamarudeen, K. Mills and R. Wild, ‘Total public
service output, inputs and productivity’, Economic and Labour Market
Review, 4(10) (2010), pp. 89–112:
http://doi.org/10.1057/elmr.2010.145
34. ONS (Office for National Statistics), Public Service Productivity
Estimates: Total Public Services, 2012 (2015):
http://www.ons.gov.uk/ons/dcp171766_394117.pdf
35. The multiplier looks at how much total increase in GDP results from
an initial increase in government spending. The calculation assumes a
known marginal propensity to save and consume, i.e. how much of
every pound or dollar earned a consumer will spend and how much he
or she will save. If 80 per cent is consumed, then the GDP will increase
by an amount of 1/(1−0.8) multiplied by the stimulus; so if the initial
extra spending was £1 million, GDP will increase by £5 million.
36. ‘Fiscal policy as a countercyclical tool’, World Economic Outlook, ch.
5 (Washington DC: International Monetary Fund, October 2008); L.
Cohen, J. Coval and C. Malloy, ‘Do powerful politicians cause
corporate downsizing?’, Journal of Political Economy, 119(6) (2011),
pp. 1015–60: doi:10.1086/664820; R. J. Barro and C. J. Redlick,
‘Macroeconomic effects from government purchases and taxes’,
Quarterly Journal of Economics 126(1) (2011), pp. 51–102: doi:
10.1093/qje/qjq002
37. D. Leigh, P. Devries, C. Freedman, J. Guajardo, D. Laxton and A.
Pescatori, ‘Will it hurt? Macroeconomic effects of fiscal
consolidation’, IMF World Economic Outlook (Washington, DC:
International Monetary Fund, 2010), pp. 93–124.
38. D. Leigh and O. J. Blanchard, ‘Growth forecast errors and fiscal
multipliers’, Working Paper no. 13/1 (Washington, DC: International
Monetary Fund, 2013).
39. A. O. Krueger, ‘The political economy of the rent-seeking society’,
The American Economic Review, 64(3) (June 1974), pp. 291–303.
40. G. Tullock, A. Seldon and G. L. Brady, Government Failure: A Primer
in Public Choice (Washington, DC: Cato Institute, 2002).
41. B. M. Friedman, ‘Crowding out or crowding in? Economic
consequences of financing government deficits’, Brookings Papers on
Economic Activity, 3 (1979), pp. 593–654.
42. J. M. Buchanan, ‘Public choice: The origins and development of a
research program’, Champions of Freedom, 31 (2003), pp. 13–32.
43. J. E. Stiglitz, Economics of the Public Sector (New York: W. W.
Norton, 3rd edn, 2000).
44. National Audit Office, ‘Memorandum on managing government
suppliers’, 12 November 2013.
45. NHS, ‘Principles and values that guide the NHS’ (2018):
http://www.nhs.uk/NHSEngland/thenhs/about/Pages/nhscoreprinciples.aspx#
46. WHO, ‘The world health report 2000 – Health systems: improving
performance’ (2000): http://www.who.int/whr/2000/en/whr00_en.pdf?
ua=1
47. E. C. Schneider, D. O. Sarnak, D. Squires, A. Shah and M. M. Doty
(2017). Mirror, Mirror 2017: International Comparison Reflects
Flaws and Opportunities for Better U.S. Health Care, The
Commonwealth Fund.
48. OECD, ‘Health expenditure and financing’ (2017):
http://stats.oecd.org/index.aspx?DataSetCode=HEALTH_STAT
49. YouGov, ‘Nationalise energy and rail companies, say public’ (2013):
https://yougov.co.uk/news/2013/11/04/nationalise-energy-and-rail-
companies-say-public/
50. J. Lethbridge, Empty promises: The Impact of Outsourcing on NHS
Services, technical report, UNISON (London, 2012).
51. C. Crouch, ‘The paradoxes of privatisation and public service
outsourcing’, in Jacobs and Mazzucato (eds), Rethinking Capitalism.
52. G. Kirkwood and A. M. Pollock, ‘Patient choice and private provision
decreased public provision and increased inequalities in Scotland: A
case study of elective hip arthroplasty’, Journal of Public Health, 39(3)
(2017), pp. 593–60.
53. We Own It, ‘We love our NHS – keep it public’:
https://weownit.org.uk/public-ownership/nhs
54. A. Pollock, ‘This deadly debt spiral was meant to destroy the NHS:
There is a way to stop it’, the Guardian, 5 July 2016:
https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2016/jul/05/debt-spiral-
destroy-nhs-health-social-care-act-bill
55. A. Pollock, ‘The NHS is about care, not markets’, the Guardian, 3
September 2009:
https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2009/sep/03/nhs-
business-markets
56. J. Davis, J. Lister and D. Wringler, NHS for Sale: Myths, Lies &
Deception (London: Merlin Press, 2015).
57. N. Chomsky, ‘The state-corporate complex: A threat to freedom and
survival’, lecture given at the University of Toronto, 7 April 2011:
https://chomsky.info/20110407-2/
58. L. MacFarlane, Blueprint for a Scottish National Investment Bank
(New Economics Foundation, 2016):
http://allofusfirst.org/tasks/render/file/?fileID=3B9725EA-E444-
5C6C-D28A3B3E27195B57
59. Ibid.
60. C. Crouch, The Knowledge Corrupters: Hidden Consequences of the
Financial Takeover of Public Life (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2016).
61. https://www.theguardian.com/society/2016/apr/15/g4s-fined-100-
times-since-2010-prison-contracts
62. https://www.washingtonpost.com/news/wonk/wp/2013/07/16/meet-
serco-the-private-firm-getting-1-2-billion-to-process-your-obamacare-
application/?utm_term=.0ffc214237a8
63. United States Government Accountability Office, ‘Contracting data
analysis; Assessment of government-wide trends’, March 2017:
https://www.gao.gov/assets/690/683273.pdf.
64. As reported in J. A. Sekera, The Public Economy in Crisis: A Call for
a New Public Economics (Springer International Publishing, 2016); J.
Dilulio, Bring Back the Bureaucrats: Why More Federal Workers Will
Lead to Better (and Smaller!) Government (West Conshohocken, PA:
Templeton Press, 2014); and Paul R. Verkuil, (2007) Outsourcing
Sovereignty: Why Privatization of Government Functions Threatens
Democracy and What We Can Do about It (Cambridge: University
Press, 2007), p. 128.
65. http://www.pogo.org/our-work/reports/2011/co-gp-
20110913.html#Executive%20Summary
66. Crouch, The Knowledge Corrupters.
67. https://er.jsc.nasa.gov/seh/ricetalk.htm
68. R. Wood, ‘Fallen Solyndra Won Bankruptcy Battle but Faces Tax
War’, Forbes, 11 June 2012.
69. G. Owen, Industrial Policy in Europe since the Second World War:
What Has Been Learnt? ECIPE Occasional Paper no. 1 (Brussels: The
European Centre for International Political Economy, 2012):
http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/41902/
70. J. M. Poterba, ‘Venture capital and capital gains taxation’, in L. H.
Summers (ed.), Tax Policy and the Economy, Vol. 3 (Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press, 1989), pp. 47–68.
71. G. Akerlof, ‘Comment’ on the chapter by William J. Baumol in G. L.
Perry and James Tobin (eds), Economic Events, Ideas, and Policies:
The 1960s and After (Washington, DC: Brookings Institution Press,
2010).
72. Mazzucato, The Entrepreneurial State.
73. See https://www.project-syndicate.org/onpoint/growth-and-public-
sector-investment-by-mariana-mazzucato-2017-12?
barrier=accesspaylog
74. J. Gertner, The Idea Factory: Bell Labs and the Great Age of American
Innovation (London and New York: Penguin, 2013).
9. THE ECONOMICS OF HOPE
1. Both Tony Blair, the former British Prime Minister, and Chuka
Umunna, considered a rising star in the Labour Party, argued that the
Labour Party needed to embrace business, calling them the wealth
creators
https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2015/may/09/tony-blair-
what-labour-must-do-next-election-ed-miliband and Chuka Umunna
https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2015/may/09/labours-
first-step-to-regaining-power-is-to-recognise-the-mistakes-we-made
2.
http://ec.europa.eu/eurostat/documents/118025/118123/Fitoussi+Commission+repo
3. D. Elson, Macroeconomics and Macroeconomic Policy from a Gender
Perspective, Public Hearing of Study Commission on Globalization of
the World Economy-Challenges and Responses, Deutscher Bundestag,
Berlin, 18 February 2002.
4. https://www.theguardian.com/us-news/2016/may/17/ceo-pay-ratio-
average-worker-afl-cio
5. https://www.ifs.org.uk/publications/5362
6. P. Evans, Embedded Autonomy: States and Industrial Transformation
(Princeton, NJ: University Press, 1995).
7. E. Morozov, ‘Democracy, Technology and City’, transcript of CCCB
lecture, Barcelona, 2014.
8. C. Perez, ‘Capitalism, technology and a green global golden age: The
role of history in helping to shape the future’, in M. Jacobs and M.
Mazzucato (eds), Rethinking Capitalism: Economics and Policy for
Sustainable and Inclusive Growth (Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell,
2016).
Bibliography
Aghion, P., Van Reenen, J. and Zingales, L., ‘Innovation and institutional
ownership’, American Economic Review, 103(1) (2013), pp. 277–304.
Alperovitz, G. and Daly, L., ‘Who is really “deserving”? Inequality and
the ethics of social inheritance’, Dissent, Fall 2009, p. 90.
Arrow, K., Social Choice and Individual Values (New Haven: Cowles
Foundation, 1951).
Atkinson, T., Atkinson Review: Final Report. Measurement of Government
Output and Productivity for the National Accounts (Basingstoke and
New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005).
Barba, A. and Pivetti, M., ‘Rising household debt: Its causes and
macroeconomic implications – A long-period analysis’, Cambridge
Journal of Economics, 33(1) (2009), pp. 113–37.
Barba, A. and de Vivo, G., ‘An “unproductive labour” view of finance’,
Cambridge Journal of Economics, 36(6) (2012):
http://doi.org/10.1093/cje/ber022
Barrett, P. and Langreth, R., ‘Pharma execs don’t know why anyone is
upset by a $94,500 miracle cure’, Bloomberg Businessweek, 3 June
2015: https://www.bloomberg.com/news/articles/2015-06-03/specialty-
drug-costs-gilead-s-hepatitis-c-cures-spur-backlash
Barro, R. J. and Redlick, C. J., ‘Macroeconomic effects from government
purchases and taxes’, Quarterly Journal of Economics, 126(1) (2011),
pp. 51–102: https://doi/org:10.1093/qje/qjq002
Barton, D. and Wiseman, M., ‘Focusing capital on the long term’, Harvard
Business Review, January–February 2014.
Baumol, W. J., ‘Contestable markets: An uprising in the theory of industry
structure’, American Economic Review, 72(1) (1982).
Baumol, W. J., ‘Entrepreneurship: Productive, unproductive, and
destructive’, Journal of Political Economy, 98(5) (1990), pp. 893–921.
Baumol, W. J., Entrepreneurship, Management and the Nature of Payoffs
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1993).
Bayliss, K., Case Study: The Financialisation of Water in England and
Wales, FESSUD (Financialisation, Economy, Society and Sustainable
Development) Working Paper series no. 52 (2014).
BEA, Measuring the Economy: A Primer on GDP and the National
Income and Product Accounts (Washington, DC: Bureau of Economic
Analysis, US Department of Commerce, 2014):
http://www.bea.gov/national/pdf/nipa_primer.pdf
Beesley, A. and Barker, A., ‘Apple tax deal: How it worked and what the
EU ruling means’, Financial Times, 30 August 2016:
https://www.ft.com/content/cc58c190-6ec3-11e6-a0c9-1365ce54b926
Bentham, J., A Fragment on Government (London: 1776).
Bergh, A. and Henrekson, M., ‘Government size and growth: A survey and
interpretation of the evidence’, Journal of Economic Surveys, 25(5)
(2011), pp. 872–97: http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-6419.2011.00697.x
Bernanke, B. S., ‘The Great Moderation’, remarks at the meetings of the
Eastern Economic Association, Washington, DC, 20 February 2004.
Bessen, J. and Meurer, M. J., The Patent Litigation Explosion, 45 Loy. U.
Chi. L. J. 401 (2013): http://lawecommons.luc.edu/luclj/vol45/iss2/5
Bessen, J. and Meurer, M. J., ‘The direct costs from NPE disputes’,
Cornell Law Review, 99(2) (2015).
Bogle, J. C., The Clash of the Cultures: Investment vs. Speculation
(Hoboken, NJ: John Wiley and Sons, 2012).
Bogle, J. C., ‘The arithmetic of “all-in” investment expenses’, Financial
Analysts Journal, 70(1) (2014).
Borio, C., Drehmann, M. and Tsatsaronis, K., ‘Anchoring countercyclical
capital buffers: The role of credit aggregates’, BIS Working Paper no.
355 (November 2011).
Boss, H. H., Theories of Surplus and Transfer: Parasites and Producers in
Economic Thought (Boston, MA: Unwin Hyman, 1990).
The Boston Consulting Group, Doubling Down on Data, Global Asset
Management (2016):
http://www.agefi.fr/sites/agefi.fr/files/fichiers/2016/07/bcg-doubling-
down-on-data-july-2016_tcm80-2113701.pdf
Bozeman, B., Public Values and Public Interest: Counterbalancing
Economic Individualism (Washington, DC: Georgetown University
Press, 2007).
Brown, G., ‘2007 Financial Statement at the House of Commons’:
http://www.publications.parliament.uk/pa/cm200607/cmhansrd/cm070321/debtext/70
0004.htm
Buchanan, J. M., ‘Public Choice: The origins and development of a
research program’, Champions of Freedom, 31 (2003), pp. 13–32.
Buffett, W. E., ‘Stop coddling the super-rich’, New York Times, 14 August
2011: http://www.nytimes.com/2011/08/15/opinion/stop-coddling-the-
super-rich.html?_r=2&hp
Buiter, W., ‘Housing wealth isn’t wealth’, National Bureau of Economic
Research Working Paper no. 14204, July 2008.
Burns, D., Cowie, L., Earles, J., Folkman, P., Froud, J., Hyde, P., Johal, S.,
Rees Jones, I., Killett, A. and Williams, K., Where Does the Money Go?
Financialised Chains and the Crisis in Residential Care, CRESC Public
Interest Report, March 2015.
Business Week, ‘Blue-ribbon venture capital’, 29 October 1960.
Butler, S., ‘How Philip Green’s family made millions as value of BHS
plummeted’, the Guardian, 25 April 2016:
https://www.theguardian.com/business/2016/apr/25/bhs-philip-green-
family-millions-administration-arcadia
Chien, C. V., ‘Startups and patent trolls’, Stanford Technology Law
Review, 17 (2014), pp. 461–506.
Christophers, B., ‘Making finance productive’, Economy and Society,
40(1) (2011), pp. 112–40.
Christophers, B., Banking Across Boundaries (Chichester: Wiley-
Blackwell, 2013).
Churchill, W., ‘WSC to Sir Otto Niemeyer, 22 February 1925’, Churchill
College, Cambridge, CHAR 18/12A-B.
Clark, J. B., The Distribution of Wealth: A Theory of Wages, Interest and
Profits (New York: Macmillan, 1899).
Cohen, L., Coval, J. and Malloy, C., ‘Do powerful politicians cause
corporate downsizing?’, Journal of Political Economy, 119(6) (2011),
pp. 1015–60: https://doi.org/10.1086/664820
Cohen, W. M., Goto, A., Nagata, A., Nelson, R. R. and Walsh, J. P., ‘R&D
spillovers, patents and the incentives to innovate in Japan and the United
States’, Research Policy, 31(8–9) (2002), pp. 1349–67:
http://doi.org/10.1016/S0048-7333(02)00068-9
Cournède, B. and Denk, O., ‘Finance and economic growth in OECD and
G20 countries’, OECD Economics Department Working Paper no. 1223
(2015).
Coyle, D., GDP: A Brief but Affectionate History (Princeton, NJ:
University Press, 2014).
Crane, E., Ownership of UK Quoted Shares: 2014 (London: Office for
National Statistics, 2015):
https://www.ons.gov.uk/economy/investmentspensionsandtrusts/bulletins/ownershipo
09-02
Crouch, C., ‘Privatised Keynesianism: An unacknowledged policy
regime’, British Journal of Politics and International Relations, 11(3)
(2009), pp. 382–99.
Crouch, C., The Knowledge Corrupters: Hidden Consequences of the
Financial Takeover of Public Life (Cambridge: Polity Press, 2016).
Dahl, R., Charlie and the Chocolate Factory (New York: Knopf, 1964).
David, P., ‘Clio and the economics of QWERTY’, American Economic
Review, 75(2), Papers and Proceedings of the Ninety-Seventh Annual
Meeting of the American Economic Association (May 1985), pp. 332–7.
Davidoff, S., ‘Why I.P.O.s get underpriced’, Dealbook, New York Times,
27 May 2011.
Davies, R., ‘Uber suffers legal setbacks in France and Germany’, the
Guardian, 9 June 2016:
https://www.theguardian.com/technology/2016/jun/09/uber-suffers-
legal-setbacks-in-france-and-germany
Dezember, R., ‘KKR to earn big payout from Walgreen–Alliance Boots
deal’, Wall Street Journal, 1 January 2015.
Dosi, G., ‘Sources, procedures, and microeconomic effects of innovation’,
Journal of Economic Literature, 26 (1988), pp. 1120–71.
Dilulio, J., Bring Back the Bureaucrats: Why More Federal Workers Will
Lead to Better (and Smaller!) Government (West Conshohocken, PA:
Templeton Press, 2014).
The Economist, ‘The third industrial revolution’, 21 April 2012:
http://www.economist.com/node/21553017
The Economist, ‘Time to fix the patents’, 8 August 2015:
http://www.economist.com/news/leaders/21660522-ideas-fuel-
economy-todays-patent-systems-are-rotten-way-rewarding-them-time-
fix
Eichengreen, B., The European Economy since 1945: Coordinated
Capitalism and Beyond (Princeton, NJ: University Press, 2008).
Ellis, K., Michaely, R. and O’Hara, M., ‘When the underwriter is the
market maker: An examination of trading in the IPO aftermarket’,
Journal of Finance, 55(3) (1999), pp. 1039–74.
Elson, D., Macroeconomics and Macroeconomic Policy from a Gender
Perspective, Public Hearing of Study Commission on Globalization of
the World Economy – Challenges and Responses, Deutscher Bundestag,
Berlin, 18 February 2002.
Epstein, G. A., Financialization and the World Economy (Cheltenham and
Northampton, MA: Edward Elgar Publishing, 2005).
Evans, P., Embedded Autonomy: States and Industrial Transformation
(Princeton, NJ: University Press, 1995).
Falck, O., Gollier, C. and Woessmann, L., ‘Arguments for and against
policies to promote national champions’, in Falck, O., Gollier, C. and
Woessmann, L. (eds), Industrial Policy for National Champions
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2011), pp. 3–9.
Fama, E., ‘Efficient capital markets: A review of theory and empirical
work’, Journal of Finance, 25(2) (1970).
Farrell, G., ‘Blankfein defends pay levels for “more productive” Goldman
staff’, Financial Times, 11 November 2009:
http://www.ft.com/intl/cms/s/0/c99bf08e-ce62-11de-a1ea-
00144feabdc0.html
Farrell, M., ‘The Internet of things – Who wins, who loses?’, the
Guardian, 14 August 2015.
Fioramonti, L., Gross Domestic Problem (London: Zed Books, 2013).
Foley, D. K., Adam’s Fallacy: A Guide to Economic Theology
(Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 2006).
Foley, D. K., ‘Rethinking financial capitalism and the “information”
economy’, Review of Radical Political Economics, 45(3) (2013), pp.
257–68: http://doi.org/10.1177/0486613413487154
Forero-Pineda, C., ‘The Impact of stronger intellectual property rights on
science and technology in developing countries’, Research Policy, 36(6)
(2006), pp. 808–24.
Foroohar, R., Makers and Takers (New York: Crown, 2016).
Fortado, L., ‘Hedge funds fees take a trim’, Financial Times, 22 December
2016: https://www.ft.com/content/ab1ce98e-c5da-11e6-9043-
7e34c07b46ef
Freeman, R. E., Harrison, J. S., Wicks, A. C., Parmar, B. L. and de Colle,
S., Stakeholder Theory: The State of the Art (Cambridge: University
Press, 2010).
Friedman, B. M., ‘Crowding out or crowding in? Economic consequences
of financing government deficits’, Brookings Papers on Economic
Activity, 3 (1979), pp. 593–654.
Friedman, M., Capitalism and Freedom (Chicago, Ill.: University Press,
1962).
Furceri, D. and Mourougane, A., ‘Financial crises: Past lessons and policy
implications’, OECD Economics Department Working Papers no. 668
(2009):
http://www.oecd.org/officialdocuments/publicdisplaydocumentpdf/?
doclanguage=en&cote=eco/wkp(2009)9
Gaus, G. F., Value and Justification: The Foundations of Liberal Theory
(New York: Cambridge University Press, 1990).
Gertner, J., The Idea Factory: Bell Labs and the Great Age of American
Innovation (London and New York: Penguin, 2013).
Gimein, M., Dash, E., Munoz, L. and Sung, J., ‘You bought. They SOLD’,
Fortune, 146(4) (2002), pp. 64–8, 72, 74.
Glyn, A., Capitalism Unleashed: Finance, Globalization and Welfare
(Oxford: University Press, 2006).
Gompers, P. A. and Lerner, J., The Venture Capital Cycle (Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press, 2002).
Goodhart, C. A. E., ‘Competition and credit control’, Financial Markets
Group, London School of Economics, Special Paper no. 229 (2014).
Greenspan, A. and Kennedy, J., Estimates of Home Mortgage
Originations, Repayments, and Debt on One-to-Four-Family
Residences, Finance and Economic Discussion Series 2005-41
(Washington, DC: Board of Governors of the Federal Reserve System,
2005).
Haber, S. and Werfel, S. H., ‘Patent trolls as financial intermediaries?
Experimental evidence’, Economics Letters, 149 (2016), pp. 64–6:
http://dx.doi.org/10.2139/ssrn.2552734
Hadas, E., ‘Seeing straight: Why buybacks should be banned’,
Breakingviews, 14 December 2014:
https://www.breakingviews.com/features/why-buybacks-should-be-
banned/
Haywood, W. D., Bill Haywood’s Book: The Autobiography of Big Bill
Haywood (New York: International Publishers, 1929).
Henderson, N. and Schrage, M., ‘The roots of biotechnology: Government
R&D spawns a new industry’, Washington Post, 16 December 1984:
https://www.washingtonpost.com/archive/politics/1984/12/16/government-
r38/cb580e3d-4ce2-4950-bf12-a717b4d3ca36/?
utm_term=.27fd51946872
Herndon, T., Ash, M. and Pollin, R., ‘Does high public debt consistently
stifle economic growth? A critique of Reinhart and Rogoff’, Cambridge
Journal of Economics, 38(2) (2014), pp. 257–79:
http://doi.org/10.1093/cje/bet075
Hill, A., Khoo, S., Fortunak J., Simmons, B. and Ford, N., ‘Minimum
costs for producing Hepatitis C direct-acting antivirals for use in large-
scale treatment access programs in developing countries’, Clinical
Infectious Diseases, 58(7) (2014), pp. 928–36:
https://doi.org/10.1093/cid/ciu012
Hill, C., The Century of Revolution 1603–1714 (London: Nelson, 1980).
Hill, J. M., ‘Alpha as a net zero-sum game: How serious a constraint?’,
Journal of Portfolio Management, 32(4) (2006), pp. 24–32:
https://doi.org/10.3905/jpm.2006.644189
Hill, P., ‘The services of financial intermediaries, or FISIM revisited’,
paper presented to the Joint UNECE/Eurostat/ OECD Meeting on
National Accounts, Geneva, 30 April–3 May 1996:
http://www.oecd.org/dataoecd/13/62/27900661.pdf.
Hilner, B. E. and Smith, T. J., ‘Efficacy does not necessarily translate to
cost effectiveness: A case study in the challenges associated with 21st-
century cancer drug prices’, Journal of Clinical Oncology, 27(13)
(2009).
Hooper, R., ‘Saving the Royal Mail’s universal postal service in the digital
age: An update of the 2008 Independent Review of the UK Postal
Services Sector, September 2010:
https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/31808
1143-saving-royal-mail-universal-postal-service.pdf
Houlder, V., Beesley, A. and Barker, A., ‘Apple’s EU tax dispute
explained’, Financial Times, 30 August 2016:
https://www.ft.com/content/3e0172a0-6e1b-11e6-9ac1-1055824ca907
Hutton, D., Smith, I. R. and Hooper, R., Modernise or Decline: Policies to
Maintain the Universal Postal Service in the United Kingdom,
Independent Review of the UK Postal Services Sector:
https://www.gov.uk/government/uploads/system/uploads/attachment_data/file/22878
‘Fiscal policy as a countercyclical tool’, World Economic Outlook, ch. 5
(Washington, DC: International Monetary Fund, October 2008).
Jacobs, M. and Mazzucato, M. (eds), Rethinking Capitalism: Economics
and Policy for Sustainable and Inclusive Growth (Chichester: Wiley-
Blackwell, 2016).
Jensen, M. J. and Meckling, W. H., ‘Theory of the firm: Managerial
behavior, agency costs and ownership structure’, Journal of Financial
Economics, 3(4) (1976), pp. 305–60.
Jevons, W. S., The Theory of Political Economy, 2nd edn, ed. Collison
Black, R. D. (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1970).
Jorgenson, D. W., ‘A new architecture for the U.S. national accounts’,
Review of Income and Wealth, 55(1) (2009), pp. 1–42.
J. P. Morgan, ‘Bridging the gap between interest rates and investments’,
JPM Corporate Finance Advisory, September 2014.
Kantarjian, H. and Rajkumar, S. V., ‘Why are cancer drugs so expensive in
the United States, and what are the solutions?’, Mayo Clinic
Proceedings, April 2015.
Kasperkevic, J., ‘America’s top CEOs pocket 340 times more than average
workers’, the Guardian, 17 May 2016:
https://www.theguardian.com/us-news/2016/may/17/ceo-pay-ratio-
average-worker-afl-cio
Keller, M. R. and Block, F., ‘Explaining the transformation in the US
innovation system: The impact of a small government program’, Socio-
Economic Review, 11(4) (2013), pp. 629–56:
https://doi.org/10.1093/ser/mws021
Kelly, K., ‘The new socialism: Global collectivist society is coming
online’, Wired magazine, 17 June 2009.
Kendrick, J., ‘The historical development of national-income accounts’,
History of Political Economy, 2(2) (1970), pp. 284–315.
Kennedy, J. F., ‘Moon speech’, Rice Stadium, 12 September 1962:
https://er.jsc.nasa.gov/seh/ricetalk.htm
Kennedy, J. F., ‘Address before the Irish Parliament in Dublin’, 28 June
1963: https://www.jfklibrary.org/Asset-
Viewer/lPAi7jx2s0i7kePPdJnUXA.aspx
Kenney, M. and Patton, D., ‘Reconsidering the Bayh-Dole Act and the
current university invention ownership model’, Research Policy, 38(9)
(2009), pp. 1407–22.
Keynes, J. M., The End of Laissez Faire (London: Hogarth Press, 1926).
Keynes, J. M., The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Money
(London: Macmillan, 1936).
Keynes, J. M., How to Pay for the War (New York: Harcourt, 1940).
Keynes, J. M., ‘Proposals for an International Clearing Union’, in The
Collected Writings of John Maynard Keynes, ed. Moggridge, D., vol.
25: Activities 1940–1944. Shaping the Post-War World. The Clearing
Union (Cambridge: University Press, 1943).
Kirkwood, G. and Pollock, A. M., ‘Patient choice and private provision
decreased public provision and increased inequalities in Scotland: A
case study of elective hip arthroplasty’, Journal of Public Health, 39(3)
(2017), pp. 593–60.
Kliff, S., ‘Meet Serco, the private firm getting $1.2 billion to process your
Obamacare application’, Washington Post, 16 July 2013:
https://www.washingtonpost.com/news/wonk/wp/2013/07/16/meet-
serco-the-private-firm-getting-1-2-billion-to-process-your-obamacare-
application/?utm_term=.33eeeadf4a01
Kokalitcheva, K., ‘Uber now has 40 million monthly riders worldwide’,
Fortune, 20 October 2016: http://fortune.com/2016/10/20/uber-app-
riders/
Krueger, A. O., ‘The political economy of the rent-seeking society’,
American Economic Review, 64(3) (1974), pp. 291–303.
Kuznets, S., National Income: A Summary of Findings (New York:
National Bureau of Economic Research, 1946).
LaMattina, J., ‘Politicians shouldn’t question drug costs but rather their
value. Lessons from Soliris and Sovaldi’, Forbes, 4 August 2014:
https://www.forbes.com/sites/johnlamattina/2014/08/04/politicians-
shouldnt-question-drug-costs-but-rather-their-value-lessons-from-
soliris-and-sovaldi/#5d9664502675
La Roche, J. and Crowe, P., ‘The richest hedge fund managers in the
world’, Business Insider, 2 March 2016.
Lavoie, M., Introduction to Post-Keynesian Economics (Basingstoke:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2009).
Lazonick, W., Sustainable Prosperity in the New Economy? Business
Organization and High-Tech Employment in the United States
(Kalamazoo, MI: W. E. Upjohn Institute for Employment Research,
2009): https://doi.org/10.17848/9781441639851
Lazonick, W., ‘Profits without prosperity’, Harvard Business Review,
September 2014.
Lazonick, W., ‘Innovative enterprise or sweatshop economics? In search
of foundations of economic analysis’, ISIGrowth Working Paper no. 17
(2016).
Lazonick, W. and Tulum, Ö., ‘US biopharmaceutical finance and the
sustainability of the biotech business model’, Research Policy, 40(9)
(2011), pp. 1170–87.
Lazonick, W. and Mazzucato, M., ‘The risk–reward nexus in the
innovation– inequality relationship: Who takes the risks? Who gets the
rewards?’, Industrial and Corporate Change, 22(4) (2013), pp. 1093–
128: https://doi.org/10.1093/icc/dtt019
Lazonick, W., Mazzucato, M. and Tulum, Ö., ‘Apple’s changing business
model: What should the world’s richest company do with its profits?’,
Accounting Forum, 37 (2013), pp. 249–67.
Leigh, D. and Blanchard, O. J., ‘Growth forecast errors and fiscal
multipliers’, Working Paper no. 13/1 (Washington, DC: International
Monetary Fund, 2013).
Leigh, D., Devries, P., Freedman, C., Guajardo, J., Laxton, D. and
Pescatori, A., ‘Will it hurt? Macroeconomic effects of fiscal
consolidation’, IMF World Economic Outlook (2010), pp. 93–124.
Lemley, M. A., ‘Software patents and the return of functional claiming’,
Wisconsin Law Review, 2013(4), pp. 905–64.
Lemley, M. A. and Shapiro, C., ‘Probabilistic patents’, Journal of
Economic Perspectives, 19(2) (2005), pp. 75–98: DOI:
10.1257/0895330054048650.
Lequiller, F. and Blades, D., ‘The general government account’, in
Understanding National Accounts, 2nd edn (Paris?: OECD Publishing,
2014): http://doi.org/10.1787/9789264214637-en
Leslie, S. W., The Cold War and American Science: The Military-
Industrial-Academic Complex at MIT and Stanford (New York:
Columbia University Press, 1993).
Levina, I., ‘A puzzling rise in financial profits and the role of capital gain-
like revenues’, Political Economy Research Institute Working Paper no.
347 (April 2014).
Light, D. W. and Lexchin, J. R., ‘Pharmaceutical research and
development: What do we get for all that money?’, BMJ,
2012;345:e4348: http://dx.doi.org/10.1136/bmj.e4348
MacFarlane, L., Blueprint for a Scottish National Investment Bank
(London: New Economics Foundation, 2016).
Malthus, T. R., An Essay on the Principle of Population, critical edn ed.
James, P. (1798; Cambridge: University Press, 1989).
Marshall, A., Elements of Economics of Industry (London: Macmillan,
1892).
Marshall, A., Principles of Economics (1890; London: Macmillan, 1920).
Marx, K., Theories of Surplus Value (vol. 4 of Capital), Part I (Moscow:
Progress Publishers, 1863).
Marx, K., Capital, vol. 1 (London: Penguin Classics, 2004).
Marx, K., Capital, vol. 3 (London: Penguin Classics, 1992).
Marx, K. and Engels, F., The Communist Manifesto (1848; London:
Penguin Classics, 2010).
Mason, R., ‘G4S fined 100 times since 2010 for breaching prison
contracts’, the Guardian, 15 April 2016:
https://www.theguardian.com/society/2016/apr/15/g4s-fined-100-times-
since-2010-prison-contracts
Mazzoleni, R. and Nelson, R., ‘The benefit and costs of strong patent
protection: A contribution to the current debate’, Research Policy, 27
(1998), pp. 273–84.
Mazzucato, M., The Entrepreneurial State: Debunking Public vs. Private
Sector Myths (London: Anthem Press, 2013).
Mazzucato, M., ‘From market-fixing to market-creating: A new
framework for innovation policy’, special issue of Industry and
Innovation: ‘Innovation policy – Can it make a difference?’, 23(2)
(2016).
Mazzucato, M. and Penna, C., ‘Beyond market failures: The market
creating and shaping roles of state investment banks’, Journal of
Economic Policy Reform, 19(4) (2016), pp. 305–26.
Mazzucato, M. and Shipman, A., ‘Accounting for productive investment
and value creation’, Industrial and Corporate Change, 23(4) (2014), pp.
1059–85: http://doi.org/10.1093/icc/dtt037
Mazzucato, M. and Wray, L. R., ‘Financing the capital development of the
economy: A Keynes-Schumpeter-Minsky Synthesis’, Levy Economics
Institute Working Paper no. 837 (2015).
McLeay, M., Radia, A. and Thomas, L. R., ‘Money creation in the modern
economy’, Bank of England Quarterly Bulletin, 54(1) (2014), pp. 1–14.
Meek, R. L., The Economics of Physiocracy: Essays and Translations
(London: George Allen & Unwin, 1962).
Merler, S. and Hüttl, P., ‘Welcome to the dark side: GDP revision and the
non-observed economy’, Bruegel, 2 March 2015:
http://bruegel.org/2015/03/welcome-to-the-dark-side-gdp-revision-and-
the-non-observed-economy/
Metrick, A. and Yasuda, A., ‘The economics of private equity’, Review of
Financial Studies, 23(6) (2011), pp. 2303–41:
https://doi.org/10.1093/rfs/hhq020
Minsky, H. P., ‘The financial instability hypothesis: An interpretation of
Keynes and an alternative to “standard” theory’, Challenge, 20(1)
(1977), pp. 20–27.
Minsky, H. P., Stabilizing an Unstable Economy (New Haven and London:
Yale University Press, 1986).
Minsky, H. P., ‘Reconstituting the United States’ financial structure’, Levy
Economics Institute Working Paper no. 69 (1992).
Minsky, H. P., ‘The capital development of the economy and the structure
of financial institutions’, Hyman P. Minsky Archive, Paper no. 179
(1992).
Minsky, H. P., ‘Finance and stability: The limits of capitalism’, Levy
Economics Institute Working Paper no. 93 (1993).
Mirowski, P., More Heat than Light: Economics as Social Physics,
Physics as Nature’s Economics (Cambridge: University Press, 1989).
Mirowski, P., ‘Learning the meaning of a dollar: Conservation principles
and the social theory of value in economic theory’, Social Research
57(3) (1990), pp. 689–718.
Mishan, E. J., The Costs of Economic Growth (New York: Praeger, 1967).
Morozov, E., ‘Don’t believe the hype, the “sharing economy” masks a
failing economy’, the Guardian, 28 September 2014:
http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2014/sep/28/sharing-
economy-internet-hype-benefits-overstated-evgeny-morozov
Morozov, E., ‘Silicon Valley likes to promise “digital socialism” – but it is
selling a fairy tale’, the Guardian, 28 February 2015.
Morozov, E., ‘Where Uber and Amazon rule: Welcome to the world of the
platform’, the Guardian, 6 June 2015.
Morozov, E., ‘Cheap cab ride? You must have missed Uber’s true cost’,
the Guardian, 31 January 2016:
http://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2016/jan/31/cheap-cab-
ride-uber-true-cost-google-wealth-taxation
Morozov, E., ‘Data populists must seize our information – for the benefit
of us all’, the Guardian, 4 December 2016:
https://www.theguardian.com/commentisfree/2016/dec/04/data-
populists-must-seize-information-for-benefit-of-all-evgeny-morozov
Moulton, B. R., The System of National Accounts for the New Economy:
What Should Change? (Washington, DC: Bureau of Economic Analysis,
US Department of Commerce, 2003):
http://www.bea.gov/about/pdf/sna_neweconomy_1003.pdf
Moulton, B. R., ‘SNA 2008 in the US national income and product
accounts’ (Eurostat Conference: ‘The Accounts of Society’,
Luxembourg, 12–13 June 2014).
Mukunda, G., ‘The price of Wall Street’s power’, Harvard Business
Review, June 2014.
Mun, T., England’s Treasure by Forraign Trade (1664; London:
Macmillan, 1865).
Newcomer, E., ‘In video, Uber CEO argues with driver over falling fares’,
Bloomberg, 28 February 2017:
https://www.bloomberg.com/news/articles/2017-02-28/in-video-uber-
ceo-argues-with-driver-over-falling-fares
Oltermann, P., ‘Berlin ban on Airbnb short-term rentals upheld by city
court’, the Guardian, 8 June 2016:
https://www.theguardian.com/technology/2016/jun/08/berlin-ban-
airbnb-short-term-rentals-upheld-city-court
ONS (Office for National Statistics), Public Service Productivity
Estimates: Total Public Services, 2012 (2015):
http://www.ons.gov.uk/ons/dcp171766_394117.pdf
Osborne, G., Mansion House speech by the Chancellor of the Exchequer,
10 June 2015: https://www.gov.uk/government/speeches/mansion-
house-2015-speech-by-the-chancellor-of-the-exchequer
Ostrom, E., Governing the Commons: The Evolution of Institutions for
Collective Action (Cambridge: University Press, 1990).
Ostrom, E., Understanding Institutional Diversity (Princeton, NJ:
University Press 2005).
Owen, G., Industrial Policy in Europe Since the Second World War: What
Has Been Learnt? ECIPE Occasional Paper no. 1, 2012 (Brussels: The
European Centre for International Political Economy):
http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/41902/
Oxfam, An Economy for the 1%, Oxfam Briefing Paper, January 2016:
https://www.oxfam.org/sites/www.oxfam.org/files/file_attachments/bp210-
economy-one-percent-tax-havens-180116-en_0.pdf
Oxfam, An Economy for the 99%, Oxfam Briefing Paper, January 2017:
https://www.oxfam.org/sites/www.oxfam.org/files/file_attachments/bp-
economy-for-99-percent-160117-en.pdf
Palin, A., ‘Chart that tells a story – UK share ownership’, Financial Times,
4 September 2015: https://www.ft.com/content/14cda94c-5163-11e5-
b029-b9d50a74fd14
Perez, C., ‘Capitalism, technology and a green global golden age: The role
of history in helping to shape the future’, in Jacobs, M. and Mazzucato,
M. (eds), Rethinking Capitalism: Economics and Policy for Sustainable
and Inclusive Growth (Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2016).
Pessoa, J. P. and Van Reenen, J., ‘The UK productivity and jobs puzzle:
Does the answer lie in labour market flexibility?’, Centre for Economic
Performance, Special Paper no. 31 (2013).
Petty, W., A Treatise of Taxes and Contributions (London: 1662), in
Charles Henry Hull (ed.), The Economic Writings of Sir William Petty, 2
vols (Cambridge: University Press, 1899).
Petty, W., Several Essays in Political Arithmetick (London: 1699), in
Charles Henry Hull (ed.), The Economic Writings of Sir William Petty, 2
vols (Cambridge: University Press, 1899).
Phelps, M. G., Kamarudeen, S., Mills, K. and Wild, R., ‘Total public
service output, inputs and productivity’, Economic and Labour Market
Review, 4(10) (2010), pp. 89–112: http://doi.org/10.1057/elmr.2010.145
Philippon, T., ‘Finance vs Wal-Mart: Why are financial services so
expensive?’, in Blinder, A., Lo, A. and Solow, R. (eds), Rethinking the
Financial Crisis (New York: Russell Sage Foundation, 2012):
http://www.russellsage.org/sites/all/files/Rethinking-
Finance/Philippon_v3.pdf
Pigou, A. C., The Economics of Welfare (London: Macmillan, 1926).
Piketty, T., Capital in the Twenty-First Century (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 2014).
Pisano, G., Science Business: The Promise, the Reality, and the Future of
Biotech (Boston, MA: Harvard Business School Press, 2006).
Polanyi, K., The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic
Origins of Our Time (1944; Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 2001).
Pollitt, C. and Bouckaert, G., Public Management Reform: A Comparative
Analysis (Oxford: University Press, 2004).
Porter, M. E., Competitive Advantage (New York: Free Press, 1985).
Porter, M. E. and Kramer, M. R., ‘Creating shared value’, Harvard
Business Review, 89 (2011), pp. 62–77.
Poterba, J. M., ‘Venture capital and capital gains taxation’, in L. H.
Summers (ed.), Tax Policy and the Economy, Vol. 3 (Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press, 1989), pp. 47–68.
Protess, B. and Corkery, M., ‘Just how much do the top private equity
earners make?’, Dealbook, New York Times, 10 December 2016.
Reich, R. B., The Work of Nations: Preparing Ourselves for the 21st
Century Capitalism (New York: Knopf, 1991).
Reich, R. B., ‘Economist John Maynard Keynes’, TIME magazine, 29
March 1999.
Reich, U. P. and Horz, K., ‘Dividing government product between
intermediate and final uses’, Review of Income and Wealth, 28(3)
(1982), pp. 325–44.
Reinert, E. S., How Rich Countries Got Rich and Why Poor Countries Stay
Poor (London: Constable, 2008).
Reinhart, C. M. and Rogoff, K. S., ‘Growth in a time of debt’, American
Economic Review, 100(2) (2010), pp. 573–8.
Reinhart, C. M. and Rogoff, K. S., ‘Debt, growth and the austerity debate’,
New York Times, 25 April 2013:
http://www.nytimes.com/2013/04/26/opinion/debt-growth-and-the-
austerity-debate.html?_r=0
Reinhart, C. M. and Rogoff, K. S., ‘Reinhart and Rogoff: Responding to
our critics’, New York Times, 25 April 2013:
http://www.nytimes.com/2013/04/26/opinion/reinhart-and-rogoff-
responding-to-our-critics.html
Ricardo, D., The Works and Correspondence of David Ricardo, ed. Sraffa,
P. with the collaboration of Dobb, M. H., vol. 1: On the Principles of
Political Economy and Taxation (Cambridge: University Press, 1951).
Ritter, J., IPO data website, 2012:
http://bear.warrington.ufl.edu/ritter/ipodata.htm.
Ro, S., ‘Chart of the day: Here’s who owns the stock market’, Business
Insider, 13 March 2013: http://www.businessinsider.com/chart-stock-
market-ownership-2013-3?IR=T
Robbins, L., An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic
Science (London: Macmillan, 1932).
Rogers, C., Money, Interest and Capital: A Study in the Foundations of
Monetary Theory (Cambridge: University Press, 1989).
Roncaglia, A., The Wealth of Ideas: A History of Economic Thought
(Cambridge: University Press, 2005).
Roose, K., ‘Silicon Valley’s secessionist movement is growing’, New York
magazine, 21 October 2013:
http://nymag.com/daily/intelligencer/2013/10/silicon-valleys-
secessionists.html
Rubin, I. I., Essays on Marx’s Theory of Value (1928; Detroit, Ill: Black
and Red Press, 1972).
Rubin, I. I., A History of Economic Thought (1929; London: Pluto Press,
1989).
Saez, E., ‘Striking it richer: The evolution of top incomes in the United
States’ (University of California, Berkeley, Department of Economics,
2015).
Samuelson, P., Economics, 3rd edn (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1955).
Sandel, M. J., What Money Can’t Buy: The Moral Limits of Markets
(London and New York: Allen Lane and Farrar, Straus and Giroux,
2013).
Say, J.-B., Traité d’économie politique (Paris: 1803).
Schumpeter, J. A., History of Economic Analysis (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1954).
Sekera, J. A., The Public Economy in Crisis: A Call for a New Public
Economics (Switzerland: Springer International Publishing, 2016).
Simon, H. A., ‘Public administration in today’s world of organizations and
markets’, PS: Political Science and Politics, December 2000.
Smith, A., ed. Skinner, A., The Wealth of Nations (1776; London:
Penguin, 1999)
SNA 1968: A System of National Accounts (New York: United Nations,
1968).
SNA 2008: System of National Accounts 2008 (New York: United
Nations, 2009).
Snowdon, B. and Vane, H., A Macroeconomics Reader (London:
Routledge, 1997).
Steiner, P., ‘Wealth and power: Quesnay’s political economy of the
“agricultural kingdom” ’, Journal of the History of Economic Thought,
24(1) (2002), pp. 91–110.
Stiglitz, J. E., The Price of Inequality: How Today’s Divided Society
Endangers our Future (London: Allen Lane, 2012)
Stiglitz, J. E., ‘Austerity has been an utter disaster for the Eurozone’, the
Guardian, 1 October 2014:
https://www.theguardian.com/business/2014/oct/01/austerity-eurozone-
disaster-joseph-stiglitz
Stiglitz, J. E., Sen, A. and Fitoussi, J.P., Mismeasuring Our Lives: Why
GDP Doesn’t Add Up (New York: The New Press, 2010)
Stiglitz, J. E., Sen, A. and Fitoussi, J.P., Report by the Commission on the
Measurement of Economic Performance and Social Progress (Paris:
Commission on the Measurement of Economic Performance and Social
Progress, 2010).
Stiglitz, J. E. and Weiss, A., ‘Credit rationing in markets with imperfect
information’, American Economic Review, 3(71) (1981), pp. 393–410.
Stone, R., ‘Definition of the national income and related totals’, in
Subcommittee on National Income Statistics, Measurement of National
Income and the Construction of Social Accounts (Geneva: United
Nations, 1947).
Studenski, P., Income of Nations (New York: University Press, 1958).
Stuvel, G., National Accounts Analysis (Basingstoke: Macmillan, 1986).
Sunga, P. S., ‘An Alternative to the current treatment of interest as transfer
in the United Nations and Canadian systems of national accounts’,
Review of Income and Wealth, 30(4) (1984), pp. 385–402:
http://doi.org/10.1111/j.1475-4991.1984.tb00487.x
Swanson, A., ‘Big pharmaceutical companies are spending far more on
marketing than research’, Washington Post, 11 February 2015:
http://www.washingtonpost.com/news/wonkblog/wp/2015/02/11/big-
pharmaceutical-companies-are-spending-far-more-on-marketing-than-
research/
Sweney, M., ‘Netflix and Amazon must guarantee 20% of content is
European’, the Guardian, 25 May 2016:
https://www.theguardian.com/media/2016/may/25/netflix-and-amazon-
must-guarantee-20-of-content-is-european
’t Hoen, E. F. M., The Global Politics of Pharmaceutical Monopoly Power
(Diemen: AMB Publishers, 2009):
https://www.msfaccess.org/sites/default/files/MSF_assets/Access/Docs/ACCESS_bo
Tassey, G., ‘Underinvestment in public good technologies’, Journal of
Technology Transfer, 30(2) (2005), pp. 89–113.
Teece, D. J., ‘Profiting from technological innovation’, Research Policy,
15(6) (1986), pp. 285–305.
Thiel, P. and Masters, B., Zero to One: Notes on Startups, or How to Build
the Future (New York: Crown, 2014).
Tomaskovic-Devey, D. and Lin, K. H., ‘Income dynamics, economic
rents, and the financialization of the U.S. Economy’, American
Sociological Review, 76(4) (2011), pp. 538–559:
http://doi.org/10.1177/0003122411414827
Tullock, G., Seldon, A. and Brady, G. L., Government Failure: A Primer
in Public Choice (Washington, DC: Cato Institute, 2002).
Turner, A., Economics After the Crisis: Objectives and Means
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2012).
Tversky, A. and Kahneman, D., ‘Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative
representation of uncertainty’, Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5(4)
(1992), pp. 297–323: doi:10.1007/BF00122574. ISSN 0895-5646.
Vanoli, A., A History of National Accounting (Washington, DC: IOS
Press, 2005).
Veblen, T., ‘The limitations of marginal utility’, Journal of Political
Economy, 17(9) (1909), pp. 620–36.
Verkuil, P. R., Outsourcing Sovereignty: Why Privatization of Government
Functions Threatens Democracy and What We Can Do about It
(Cambridge: University Press, 2007).
Walker, D. A. and van Daal, J. (eds and trans.), Léon Walras, Elements of
Theoretical Economics: Or the Theory of Social Wealth (Cambridge:
University Press, 2014).
Walras, L., Elements of Theoretical Economics, trans. and ed. by Donald
A. Walker and Jan van Daal (1883; Cambridge: University Press, 2014).
Wolff, E. N., Growth, Accumulation, and Unproductive Activity: An
Analysis of the Postwar U.S. Economy (Cambridge: University Press,
1987).
Wood, R., ‘Fallen Solyndra won bankruptcy battle but faces tax war’,
Forbes, 11 June 2012.
Wray, L. R., Modern Money Theory (Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan,
2012).
Zirkelbach, R., ‘The Five essential truths about prescription drug
spending’, March 2015, available on PhRMA website at
http://catalyst.phrma.org/the-five-essential-truths-about-prescription-
drug-spending
Acknowledgements