The Basic Theory of Capitalism: The Forms and Substance of The Capitalist Economy
The Basic Theory of Capitalism: The Forms and Substance of The Capitalist Economy
The Basic Theory of Capitalism: The Forms and Substance of The Capitalist Economy
In Japanese
CONTEMPORARY CAPITALISM
MARXIAN ECONOMICS TODAY
(and other works)
The Basic Theory of
CapitalisiD
The Forms and Substance of
the Capitalist Economy
Makoto ltoh
Professor of Economics
University of Tokyo
M
MACMILLAN
PRESS
© Makoto Itoh 1988
Published by
THE MACMILLAN PRESS LTD
Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire RG21 2XS
and London
Companies and representatives
throughout the world
1.1 Mercantilism 3
1.2 Physiocracy 6
1.3 The Classical School 11
Its Formation 11
Adam Smith 12
David Ricardo 16
10 On Socialism 347
Notes 376
Bibliography 417
Index 427
Preface
We are living in a peculiar and uncertain age- a fin de siecle. After a
century in which the historical evolution of capitalism increasingly
strengthened the economic role of the state, the capitalist world seems
suddenly to have lost any sense of progress as it experiences the great
depression which began in 1973. There has spread an overall disil-
lusion with views that state policies of either a Keynesian or Monet-
arist sort can prevent or mitigate economic instability and distress.
Indeed, it is asked whether they are not rather aggravating the
disasters. Such serious doubt and disillusion are combined in econ-
omic theory with the damage to the analytical foundation of neo-
classical price theory given by both the so-called capital controversy
and recent Marxian critiques, and thus present a deep crisis for
orthodox marginalist economic theories. This constitutes an import-
ant element of the general crisis and distrust in the conventional
social sciences, within the framework of bourgeois ideology, which
regards the capitalist social order as natural. As a result, an irrational
nationalism and militarism has tended to gain ground, often along-
side a general indifference to substantial socio-economic problems
even among young students.
It is ironic to see that despite all this, in the very process of the
great depression in our age, capitalism seems to be strongly reassert-
ing the workings of its intrinsic and violent law of motion rather than
weakening itself. What has been weakened is rather the social posi-
tion of workers and their trade-union organisations. The economic
position of the 'third world' countries has also generally been
worsened. The actions of capitalist firms to increase the efficiency of
the valorisation process through 'rationalisation' and restructuring
are so much facilitated. 'The social structure of accumulation' of
capitals seems to be under reconstruction in full scale throughout the
capitalist world.
In spite of the actual deep crisis in the capitalist economy, as well
as in bourgeois social thought, the socialist movement is not gaining,
but rather suffering with the weakening social position of workers.
Moreover, added to it, there have been problematic situations in the
existing socialist countries, including international conflicts - even
wars and military invasion- among them. The process of the cultural
revolution in China, the weak social position of workers expressed in
ix
X Preface
MAKOTO ITOH
EDITOR'S NOTE
PAUL BULLOCK
Part I
Economic Schools and
Ideologies
Capitalism is a special social formation where both the selling and
buying of commodities organised by capital dominate human econ-
omic activities. As capitalism began to develop in Western Europe,
from about the sixteenth century, economic theories also began to
evolve as a specific field of social sciences. It was not a mere coinci-
dence nor simply part of a new tendency for modern sciences to grow
separately from a comprehensive system of theology or philosophy.
On the one hand, capitalism broadened and complicated social
relations in production, distribution and consumption. The social
mechanism of economic life, which was now carried on through
commodities, money and capital, not only became more and more
important for society but it was also impossible to fully understand it
merely by daily common sense. On the other hand, economic activi-
ties based on commodity transactions, unlike those in various pre-
capitalist societies, basically tended to be self-operating and became
independent of extra-economic, religious and political forces. Con-
sequently political economy grew as an independent and basic social
science alongside the development of capitalism.
In its process of growth and development, the study of the capital-
ist economy gave rise to various schools. The distinctions among
major schools are apparently linked with the different frameworks of
ideologies. Ideology can roughly be defined here as a more or less
total system of social thought, or 'a co-ordinated set of beliefs and
ideas' which is historically relative and apt to be related with a certain
political position. 1 A new school of economic theory often arises in
order to support a new political perspective, and this school may then
become popular as a logical basis for such an ideology, reflecting the
direction of social change and developing social interests. In most
cases the new social thought and its theoretical expression asserted
their universal objectivity and truth, and criticised the older or the
other as being partial, distorted and one-sided, or totally wrong.
However, the successive changes of dominant schools of economic
theories cannot be regarded simply as a continuous progress toward
1
2 Economic Schools and Ideologies
by, and the basis of, foreign trade, and that foreign trade was the
source of national wealth and treasure. Their argument, especially
Mun's, was so influential in supporting mercantilist policies up until
the middle of the eighteenth century, that according to A. Smith 'the
title of Mun's book, England's Treasure by Foreign Trade [1664],
became a fundamental maxim in the political economy, not of England
only, but of all other commercial countries'. 1
James D. Steuart (1712-80) systematised the mercantilist theories
in An Inquiry into the Principles of Political Economy (1767).
Although it was unduly neglected by A. Smith and generations of his
followers, it was a remarkable and great work in the following sense.
First, it presented a whole range of political economy. It begins from
a systematic description of a commercial society, analyses the func-
tions of money and credit and discusses the role and the appropriate
usage of public debt and taxes. In its description, various forms in a
commodity economy such as prices, costs, profits, money, credit,
interest, demand and supply are more or less organically studied as
principles of a commercial society, in particular from the view of
circulation and trade. Money, for instance, is no longer treated as an
absolute treasure as with bullionism, but observed in various forms
and functions including money of account, the measure of value,
bank money, coins as the means of circulation and the bullion as
universal money. This treatment of money is clearly wider than that
of the classical school where money is regarded only as the conven-
tional means of circulation. Together with his critique of D. Hume's
quantity theory of money where the level of prices is mechanically
determined by a rise or a fall of the quantity of money, Steuart's
monetary theory obviously contributed to part of Marx's later theor-
etical system, although it was not then based upon the labour theory
of value.
Second, in describing a commercial society which is driven by
self-love to pursue trade, Steuart does not believe in the assurance of
equilibrium between demand and supply or between jobs and popu-
lation. Rather, he emphasised a possible crisis of disequilibrium
which is often worsened by foreign trade. Hence he argues for the
necessity of mercantile protectionist policies or even fiscal policy to
restore the balance. In this respect he can be regarded as an import-
ant forerunner ofT. R. Malthus and further J. M. Keynes. Third,
Steuart is conscious of the historical character of a commercial
society in comparison with serfdom or feudal society, on the basis of
his observation of different societies on the Continent during his
seventeen years of refugee life. This point of view, which is mostly
The Birth of the Theoretical System of Capitalism 5
lost in the classical school, anticipates the later historical school and
the Marxist as well.
Fourth, in spite of these remarkable views Steuart's theoretical
framework remained 'the rational expression of the Monetary and
Mercantile systems' ,2 in so far as it thoroughly stresses the central
role of trade and commerce. In particular Steuart believed that profit
upon alienation, being determined by the degree of demand, always
enters into the prices of goods together with real value or prime costs.
In his concept of 'positive profit' which 'results from an augmentation
of labour, industry or ingenuity', 3 Steuart seems to be already taking
off from a mere mercantilist view where profit is always observed as
an increment of real wealth to be obtained in commerce. However,
so far as 'Steuart makes no attempt to explain' how positive profit
arises from such productive activity, 4 he cannot go beyond a theoreti-
cal limitation of mercantilist theory of value and profit.
Such a theoretical limitation reflects the basic character of capital-
ism in the mercantilist period. Capitalist accumulation in this period
had not yet established its own industrial basis in the form of the
modern factory system. The development of woollen manufacture,
which organised a subtle division of labour in factories under capital-
ist management, was an important key industry for the expansion of
global trade. But capitalist manufacture could not defeat small-scale
domestic woollen industry so long as it was based on handwork
technology. As a result the main source of capitalist profit and the
augmentation of social wealth seemed to originate from merchant
activity particularly in a large-scale foreign trade. The expansion and
penetration of the commodity economy carried out by merchant
activity in this period powerfully transformed the European societies
and wove every country into a Euro-centred world market. Through-
out the central and peripheral societies the capitalist expansion of the
commodity economy was not just a peaceful idyllic process. As Marx
made clear, the so-called 'primitive accumulation' which preceded
and prepared industrial capitalist accumulation, was full of violence
and state intervention. 'The exploitation of the agricultural producer,
of the peasant, from the soil, was the basis of the whole process'
(1, p. 876) 5 to create wage-labourers for capitalist production, as was
classically shown in the British enclosure movement. The colonial
system, the slave trade and the system of trade protection also
worked in the great transformation process of society from the feudal
or semi-feudal to the fully capitalist society. It is striking to see how
violent means and state power served as the midwife for the birth of a
seemingly peaceful commercial capitalist society. Unawareness of the
6 Economic Schools and Ideologies
1.2 PHYSIOCRACY
and the sterile class.' The productive class advances the expenditures
for agricultural labour and cultivation, and reproduces national wealth
including the net product to be paid to the class of proprietors. The
class of proprietors contains the sovereign, the owners of land and
the tithe-owners. This class subsists on the revenue or the net product
paid by the productive class. The ·sterile class is composed of all the
citizens who are engaged in works or services other than agriculture.
For instance, in a kingdom of about 30 million population, the
productive class owns 10 milliards (livres) primitive advance, of
which 1 milliard is yearly depreciation (which is confusedly called
interest for the primitive advance) and also expends 2 milliards yearly
advance. Three milliards advance in total brings about 5 milliards
yearly agricultural products including 2 milliards net products. The
productive class owns also 2 milliards (livres) money which is equival-
ent to the net product and pays it to the class of proprietors. Of 5
milliards (livres) agricultural products 1 milliard is to be consumed by
the class of proprietors, 1 milliard (as foods) and another 1 milliard
(as raw material) are to be used by the sterile class, and the remaining
2 milliards is reserved in kind as the yearly advance for the next year's
cultivation. The sterile class does not produce any net products
(surplus-value). It reproduces the same 2 milliards (livres) just as it
consumes both 1 milliard raw material by yearly advance and another
milliard for means of consumption. One-half of its (manufactured)
products is sold to the proprietors and the other half is to the
productive class. Then Quesnay's simplified tableau (Figure 1.1)
shows the total transaction as follows:
While each milliard of products of the productive and the sterile
class moves along the lines in the opposite direction to arrows, 2
milliards (livres) of money flows back directly and indirectly via the
sterile class to the productive class which originally pays that money
to the class of proprietors, and the advanced money of 1 milliard
from each side is also regained for the next year.
Quesnay's table was the first original attempt to observe the total
material relations of social reproduction and clearly preceded Marx's
reproduction schema and Leontieff's later inter-industry relations
table. Quesnay's theoretical analyses of the table and its implications
also provided a remarkable advance in the theory of capitalist pro-
duction. In contrast with the mercantilist theory of profit upon
alienation the source of surplus-value is now found in the sphere of
production. In particular, surplus-value as the net product is seen as
obtainable from capitalist advances, and is the surplus product over
and above the necessaries of life and the means of production used
The Birth of the Theoretical System of Capitalism 9
Revenue
Annual Advances for the Proprietors Advances
of the of the Land, the of the
Productive Class Sovereign, and the Sterile Class
Tithe-owners
5 milliards 5 milliards 5 milliards
Expenditure of {
the annual advances 2 milliards Total ..... . 2 milliards
of which one-half
Total ..... . 5 milliards is held back by this
class for the
following year's
advances.
Its Formation
Adam Smith
An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations (1776)
by A. Smith (1723-90) was epoch-making in formulating a theoretical
system of a capitalist economy as a study of its inner economic
structure. In the first two Parts especially, before the three parts
treating economic history, previous systems of political economy and
public finance, the book describes theoretically the nature and the
construction of a fully capitalist economy. The basic theories of value
The Birth of the Theoretical System of Capitalism 13
theory of value which in fact attributes the surplus value (profit and
rent) to the surplus labour of wage-labourers. This theory is nothing
but an extension of the labour embodied theory.
However, Smith is inclined to see labour as an exchange process
and thereby t~nds to slip off to the other theory of value. So long as
labour is observed just in the exchange process it seems to be the
means of exchange to obtain necessary consumption goods to live on,
no longer from nature, but now from the capitalist. The amount of
labour which a labourer offers to a capitalist in exchange for the
necessary means of consumption must be exactly the same amount of
labour obtainable by these means if these are used as capital to
employ wage-labourers. Thus the equal amounts of labour seem to
be exchanged between a labourer and a capitalist from the viewpoint
of the labour commanded theory of value. If a wage-labourer can get
the same amount of labour as he expends, then the source of surplus
value, i.e. profit and rent, cannot be in his labour. Here appears a
deep division in Smith's dual-labour theories, and further, a switch to
a sort of factor costs theory of value or an adding-up theory of value
in which wages, profit and rent are defined as original independent
sources of exchange values. It is not too hard to recognise here some
residues of the mercantilist and physiocratic views of revenues.
There remained many problems in Smith's complex theories of
value. It may not be much of an exaggeration to say that all the later
studies of value relate in one way or the other to these problems.
Presently let us reconfirm just the discrepancy (with related points)
between the deduction theory of value and the adding-up theory of
value. It is clear that these theories directly contradict each other for
instance in the case of a rise of wages. When wages rise, other
circumstances being equal, according to the deduction theory, the
other components, i.e. profit and rent, must be reduced within the
same amount of value being defined by the embodied labour time in a
commodity. On the contrary, according to the adding-up theory, the
exchange value of a commodity must rise so long as an independent
decline of profit or rent does not happen to cancel the rise of wages.
Interestingly even in the recent debates about inflation the basic
views of these opposite positions have repeatedly appeared. Smith
might not have been very conscious or concerned about the discrep-
ancy in his theories. However, while he conventionally operated and
used different theories, he could not consistently extend the labour
theory of value to more precise studies of the inner relations between
wages, profit and rent. There was plenty of room for such an
16 Economic Schools and Ideologies
David Ricardo
Anti-classical Theories
Utopian Socialism
The birth and the growth of the neo-classical school was another
reaction to the deadlock and dissolution of the classical school. 33 This
school has attempted to formulate universal theories in sharp con-
trast to the historical school, and has become dominant among
Anglo-American academia, and then extended throughout the capi-
talist world in the period after the Second World War. We follow
here the concept of the neo-classical school in its broadest sense,
including Keynesianism. As is well known the mariginal revolution
led by C. Menger (1835-1921), M. E. L. Walras (1834-1910) and
W. S. Jevons (1835-82) initiated the school at the beginning of 1870s.34
The Dissolution of the Classical School 31
(1847, in MECW, vol. 6, pp. 105 ff.), and then briefly formulated
later in the Preface to A Critique of Political Economy (1859). Once
obtained as the general result of the critical review of Hegelian
philosophy along with the investigation of political economy, histori-
cal materialism 'served as a guiding thread' ,4 for Marx's further
studies which were more and more concentrated on the basic econ-
omic theory of capitalism. Its main points can be summarised as
follows. 5
A social superstructure and ideologies like politics, law, religion
and social consciousness do not move independently. They are not
created nor moved by the heavenly Idea or the absolute spirit. They
are formed and conditioned by the economic structure, the real
foundation of each society. The economic social structure mainly
consists of the material productive forces and the relations of produc-
tion, and develops historically through the dialectical motion be-
tween the productive forces and the relations of production. An
epoch of social revolution begins when the relations of production
turn from being the appropriate forms for the forces of production
into fetters on the development of those forces. The changes in the
economic foundation lead sooner or later to the transformation of the
whole immense superstructure; and men become conscious of this
social basic conflict and fight it out in various ideological forms. 'In
broad outline, the asiatic, ancient, feudal, and modern bourgeois
modes of production may be designated as epochs marking progress
in the economic development of society'. The bourgeois mode of
production is the last antagonistic form of the social process of
production. The prehistory of human society ends, therefore, with
this social formation.
In view of this historical materialism, not only Hegel's idealism but
also Feuerbach's spiritual liberation from the medieval Christian
fetter through humanistic materialism is obviously far from being
sufficient. Really total human liberation is realisable only in the true
history, or the history of human society which begins after abolishing
the final class relations of production as developed in a capitalist
society. The driving subject of the dialectic was thus turned from
Hegel's absolute spirit or the Idea via Feuerbach's natural human
being to the productive forces of Marx's new world view. The
productive forces are the degree of development of productivity
based upon technological changes. With the inevitable progress in
the productive forces, the nature of the relations of production,
which represent the social system organising the direct workers under
The Marxian Theory of Capitalism 43
the ruling class in class societies, must change sooner or later. This
view of the dialectic between the forces of production and the
relations of production by Marx also enabled him to overcome the
weaknesses in early socialism, particularly the romantic tendency to
admire past societies. It is now clear that Marx's original reframing of
the basic economic theory of capitalism is guided by his new world
view, i.e. historical materialism.
Soon after creating historical materialism Marx wrote with Engels the
Manifesto of the Communist Party and published it in February 1848
by request of The Communist League. This League had been formed
in June 1847 by linking up the main centres of communist activities in
Paris, London, Brussels and Cologne. This pamphlet has been one of
the most popular and influential among the massive volume of works
by Marx and Engels, and presents prototypes of some of Marx's
theories of capitalism. Those theories were clearly made up at that
time by applying historical materialism more directly than in Marx's
later writings like Capital. There are four sections in the Manifesto of the
Communist Party 11 namely 'Bourgeois and Proletarians', 'Proletarians
48 Economic Schools and Ideologies
I. Capital
(a) Capital in general
(1) Production process of capital
(2) Circulation process of capital
(3) Unity of both processes, or profit and interest of capital
(b) Competition
(c) Credit
(d) Joint-stock capital
II. Landed property
III. Wage labour
IV. State
V. Foreign trade
VI. World market
Figure 3.1
d) Share-Capital ---
c) Credit system - - - - 5) Interest and credit
II. ON LANDED
PROPERTY 6) Ground-Rent
7) Revenues.
Ill. ON WAGE LABOUR
IV. STATE
V. FOREIGN TRADE
VI. WORLD MARKET
73
74 Value, Labour and Capital
does not clarify the logical development of the value-form from the
simple form to the money-form, by stating that 5 beds = 1 house is
directly indistinguishable from 5 beds = a certain amount of money.
Although the form of value equation is in a sense something foreign
to the true nature of things as use-values, it is by no means a mere
tentative 'makeshift' but forms an endogenous logical order for
commodities. Marx does not point to the lack of analysis of the inner
logic of the equation, for Aristotle's attempt, to develop the value-
forms, but just puts emphasis on the lack of the concept of the
substance of value. If only the labour theory of value matters, the
classical school prior to Marx already discovered it.
Nevertheless the labour theory of value in the classical school did
not guarantee a way forward for the study of value-forms. As we
quoted in note 1 of this chapter, Marx was well aware that the task of
clarifying the value-form in this section of Capital had never been
pursued by the classical school. The failure of the classical school to
discover the form of value was due to the mistake of treating capital-
ist production and commodity economy as the eternal natural form of
economy. In this regard the neo-classical and the neo-Ricardian
school also are not immune from the same failure.
As is exemplified in his dialogue with Aristotle, Marx attempts to
confirm the character of the substance of value, as well as the
historical basis that enables us to recognise abstract human labour as
the value substance through his theoretical analysis of the form of
value. As an actual fact in the history of economic theory, Marx's
theory of the forms of value could not have been obtained without
superceding the classical labour theory of value and social repro-
duction. The mercantilist theories of circulation had to remain frag-
mental, and could not lead directly to systematic studies of the forms
of value from a broader and deeper historical view like that of
Marx's. Capital demonstrates a deepening process of 'a critique of
political economy' by developing dialectically the theories of the
forms and the substance of value. Thus Marx's critique of Aristotle in
the theory of the value-form went dialectically to the historical basis
of the abstraction of the substance of value.
A similar dialectical combination of the studies of the forms and
the substance of value is observable in many places other than that of
the dialogue with Aristotle. Although it is educative and interesting
to read them as the formation of theories and critiques, the theory of
the forms of value itself can and must be separated from the critical
investigation into the substance of value, with a view to having a
The Forms of Value- Commodity, Money and Capital 81
not to the linen in the relative form of value. Therefore, the ex-
panded form of value cannot simply be reversible. Marx thus left
unsolved the question of how to overcome the defects in the ex-
panded form of value, and how to pass over to the general form of
value.
It is apparent that all the commodities do express each of their
values in the simple, and then in the expanded relative form of value,
just as the linen does. At first sight the defects in the expanded form
of value of linen do not seem soluble in relation to the similar
expressions of value of other commodities, but sink rather into a
chaos which is composed of an unlimited number of different ex-
pressions of the values of various commodities. 8 In a chaotic series of
parallel expressions of values however, some commodities must be
found among the motley equivalents which are common at least for a
certain number of commodities taking the relative form of value.
Then this commodity, say tea, which is common among the equival-
ents for a certain range of commodities, comes to be required not
only for its special use-value, say to drink, but also for its 'formal
use-value' (I, p. 184), i.e. the direct exhangeability with other com-
modities. Under such circumstances the owners of commodities
generally wish to obtain tea in exchange, and values of commodities
become jointly expressed in terms of tea. The third, general form of
value thus appears:
In the third chapter of the first volume of Capital Marx analyses the
basic forms of the functions of money. In the classical school as well
as in the neo-classical school (before Keynes), money tends to be
treated just as a conventional means of exchange. In contrast, Marx
systematically puts in order the rich forms of the function of money,
namely the measure of value, the means of circulation, and money as
the absolute form of value which further comprises the forms of
hoarding, means of payment and world money. Marx absorbed and
made use of observations of the forms of money by the mercantilists
like James Stuart. At the same time Marx's original analysis of the
commodity form which clarifies the unique position of money in the
world of commodities, enabled him theoretically to distinguish es-
pecially the function of money as the absolute form of value from that
as the means of circulation. The analysis of the means of circulation
itself also became richer than that of the classical school. In the light
of the theory of the value-form, however, there are still some prob-
lems in Marx's theory of money, in particular concerning the measure
of values in the first section of the third chapter.
important premise for the concept of world money, and further, for
the theory of transformation of money into capital as we shall discuss
a little later. Before discussing these topics we have to examine other
functions of money structurally forming each sphere of commodity
circulation or a commodity market.
Figure 4.1
~ '',._.
M--e,
.... ~ ...............
,,
·c,:::::-Mx
~, ~
c, .......
.
··c,··....... Mx
c3
We see here 'how the exchange of commodities breaks through all
the individual and local limitations of the direct exchange of pro-
ducts' (I, p. 207), and develops the broad interrelations between
mutually unknown commodity-owners. The circulation of com-
modities, which pass the network from the lower left-hand side to the
upper-right-hand side in Figure 4.1, is maintained by the current
motion of money which flows from the upper left to the lower right
remaining within the market as currency.
The means of exchange or circulation was the only form of the
function of money for the classical school. Various other functions of
money on the basis of its position as the universal equivalent were
disregarded. Money was then treated just as a conventional means of
exchange between basically harmonious commodities. Say's law orig-
inates in such a view of money. According to the law, the circulation
of commodities necessarily implies an equilibrium between sales and
purchases because every sale is a purchase, and every purchase a
sale. Hence it is assumed that supply always creates its own demand.
As Marx criticises (I, pp. 208--9), such a position is boiled down to a
flat tautology to say that 'the number of actual sales accomplished is
equal to the number of purchases', or it neglects the mutually
independent and antithetical relation between sale and purchase. 'No
one can sell unless someone else purchase. But no one directly needs
to purchase because he has just sold.' A commodity becomes useless
if it cannot be bought by the owner of money. The impossibility of
selling a commodity may cause a similar difficulty for another com-
modity in a chain reaction, breaking the network of circulation of
commodities. Therefore, contrary to Say's law, these forms of sale
and purchase 'imply the possibility of crises, though no more than the
possibility'. (I, p. 209).
The Forms of Value- Commodity, Money and Capital 93
MV = PT, or P = MT
v
In this equation or rather identity P is determined proportionally by
Min so far as other circumstances including V and Tare unaltered.
Against the quantity theory of money Marx argues that the level of
prices is determined not by the quantity of money, but basically by
the substantial values of commodities and the value of gold (the
money material). At the same time he takes into consideration thai
the quantity of money as the means of circulation is adjusted accord-
ing to the needs of commodity circulation by having the convertible
relation with other forms of money. Under the gold standard monet-
ary system of his time the excessive quantity of money over that
necessary for the circulating medium is pushed out into hoards or
deposits, as he illustrates by the evidence that 'one has only to throw
a given quantity of £1 notes into circulation in order to extract the
same number of sovereign from it. This trick is well known to all
bankers'. (I, p. 216). Thus, according to Marx, 'for a given interval of
time during the process of circulation, we have the following equa-
tion: the quantity of money functioning as the circulating medium =
the sum of the prices of the commodities divided by the number of
times coins of the same denomination turn over'. (I, p. 216). Or
symbolically:
- PT
M - v
The equation signifies here that the quantity of money as the means
94 Value, Labour and Capital
circulation. When the state has to depend on issuing paper money for
budgetary needs, the state generally tends to overissue it.
As Marx noticed, if the amount of paper money exceeds the limit
of the amount in gold coins of the same denomination which could
have been in circulation, then the quantity of gold represented by
each sheet of paper money has to diminish. For instance, if the
quantity of paper money becomes twice as much as the limit, 'then in
practice £1 will be the money-name not of 114 of an ounce of gold, but
1/8 of an ounce .... The value previously expressed by the price of
£1 would now be expressed by the price of £2.' (I, p. 225). We see a
simple basic case of inflation here. The quantity theory of money
takes such a case for the general principle of determination of prices,
or at least it cannot distinguish the law of monetary circulation for
gold currency and that for paper money. At a very abstract level the
contemporary inflation is basically understandable from the logic of
motion of prices in the case of overissue of paper money. Hence
there is a certain abstract relevancy in monetarism's desire to restrict
the supply of money in order to calm down inflation. However, in
comparison with simple paper money issued by the state, the incon-
vertible bank notes which now prevail together with various other
sorts of credit-money have far more complex functions and influence
on the level of prices, which must be investigated at the more
concrete level of research. For instance, they are issued not merely to
meet the state budget, and function more widely than the mere
means of circulation. These complexities basically relate to the diffi-
culty of monetarism in defining and effectively controlling the quan-
tity of money in our age.
Although there have been many debates and studies on the 'trans-
formation problem' from values into prices of production in the third
volume of Capital, the problem in Marx's theoretical treatment of the
transformation of money into capital has not yet attracted much
attention among Western theorists. The exceptional to this was
where Marx defined the value of labour-power, as we shall see later.
Among Japanese Marxians, especially in the Uno School, however,
the problem has been discussed no less seriously than the so-called
'transformation problem'. It may be called 'another transformation
problem'. Though the problem here may seem remote and indepen-
dent from the problem in the third volume of Capital, its solution can
serve as a necessary precondition for a proper treatment of the other
problem.
In the theory of the transformation of money into capital, Marx
defines M - C- M' as 'the general formula for capital' and refers to
merchants' capital and interest-bearing capital as a kind of capital.
However, in discussing 'contradictions in the general formula,' he
emphasises the theoretical impossibility for capital to acquire
surplus-value, properly understood, in the sphere of circulation. It is
because commodities are assumed to be bought and sold generally at
their value as the embodied labour time on the basis of the preceding
labour theory of value. As a result, capital cannot arise from circula-
tion, whereas 'it is equally impossible for it to arise apart from
circulation' (1, p. 268). The contradiction can be solved only when the
money-owner can find within the sphere of circulation a special
commodity to be used as a source of value and surplus-value, namely
the commodity labour-power. In this theoretical sequence money can
eventually be transformed into capital only as industrial capital
carrying out the production process by using the commodity labour-
power. Thus, according to Marx's treatment, while commodities and
money can appear along with many precapitalist economic forma-
tions of society, 'it is otherwise with capital. The historical conditions
The Forms of Value - Commodity, Money and Capital 103
condition for all the forms of society from the historically specific
capitalist economy which we are observing? Marx stresses here the
aspect of the production of use-values by capitalism. 'What the
capitalist sets the worker to produce is a particular use-value, a
specific article. The fact that the production of use-values, or goods,
is carried on under the control of a capitalist and on his behalf does
not alter the general character of that production. We shall therefore,
in the first place, have to consider the labour process independently
of any specific social formation.' (I, p. 284).
This corresponds to the definition of use-values Marx gives in his
initial analysis of the two factors of the commodity - that use-values
'constitute the material content of wealth, whatever its social form
may be' (I, p. 126). Also in the subsequent analysis of the dual
character of labour embodied in commodities, Marx stated: 'Labour
as the creator of use-values, as useful labour, is a condition of human
existence which is independent of all forms of society; it is an eternal
natural necessity which mediates the metabolism between man and
nature, and human life itself.' (I, p. 133).
These analyses seem clear and sound. As Marx says, labour as the
creator of use-values must obviously be an universal condition for all
human societies. A problem remains here, however, as we shall see
later, if the other aspect of labour as abstract labour is to be excluded
from such an universal condition. Let us presently follow Marx's
notion of the labour process. Marx inquires as to what is character-
istic to human labour as a process of metabolism with nature.
Labour is, first of all, a process between man and nature, a process
by which man, through his own actions, mediates, regulates and
controls the metabolism between himself and nature. He confronts
the materials of nature as a force of nature. He sets in motion the
natural forces which belongs to his own body, his arms, legs, head
and hands, in order to appropriate the materials of nature in a form
adapted to his own needs. Through this movement he acts upon
external nature and changes it, and in this way he simultaneously
changes his own nature. (I, p. 283).
Abstract Labour
Marx was the first to point out and examine the dual character of
labour; i.e. the concrete useful character and the abstract human
character of labour. However, in the theoretical system of Capital
where the substance of value is presented from the very beginning in
the initial analysis of two factors of the commodity, the dual charac-
ter of labour tends to be observed as being embodied in commodities
and is strictly correlated to value and use-value of commodities. As a
result, Marx does not refer to abstract labour or the dual character of
labour in analysing the labour process. He comes back to the aspect
of abstract labour only when he proceeds to the theory of the
valorisation process of capital in the separate second section of ch. 7
of the first volume of Capital.
There remains here an important problem-whether the abstract
character of labour exists exclusively within commodity-value rela-
tions or is common to all societies as an aspect of human activity in its
metabolic interaction with nature. The problem is fundamental to the
theoretical basis of the labour theory of value and Marxian socialism.
In my opinion Marx's notion of the labour process is still incomplete,
and too narrow in this regard as an analysis of the universal condi-
tions of societies based on labour. It may also be inconsistent with his
observations in other places.
114 Value, Labour and Capital
h1 + t tz + -} = tl (1)1
-}tl + Ttz +-} = tz (2) (5.2)
} t1+ -} tz + 1 =t 3 (3)
Solution of these equations determines first t 1 = } , t2 = 1 from (1)
and (2), and then t3 = 2. If a spindle is produced by 7 hours of current
labour using 9 kg of coal and 3 kg of iron on the same technical basis,
then 16 hours of labour in total is embodied in a spindle. We can
conceive of these technical relations of production as an example
behind Marx's assumption that 20 hours and 4 hours of labour are
120 Value, Labour and Capital
n
l:Plj + li = ti (aij;:::: 0, li > 0, i = 1, 2, ... n) (5.3)
Surplus-labour
of working day, the number of yearly working days, and the average
physical amounts of the necessary means of subsistence of a worker
are given, each including the historical and social factors of their
determination, then the quantities of the necessary and the surplus-
labour-time, as well as their ratio, are determined.
Whatever the ratio between the necessary and surplus-labour-time
may become, it is a universal condition of economic life common to
all social formations that the workers repeatedly obtain their histori-
cally determined necessary means of subsistence together with the
necessary labour-time embodied in them. As a whole, this condition
is also expressed in the universal social necessity of maintaining the
reproduction of labour power itself by consuming the necessary
means of production which are produced by a portion of the expendi-
ture of labour. Let us come back again to the initial problem of this
subsection and examine the quantitative relations intrinsic to the
reciprocally transferred labour-time between industries.
Let us presently assume a set of representative technological
conditions of production with simple labour and a single product for
all the industries. Then the quantity of labour-time embodied in each
unit of production from both past and living labour is determined as
we have seen. In so far as each industry must maintain at least the
current production levels to satisfy the social need for its product, the
means of production and the living labour which are necessary for its
reproduction must be reobtainable in a system of socially divided
labour. The portion of living labour is, however, recharged indirectly
by securing for the workers in each industry the means of subsistence
containing the necessary labour-time, which is less than the total
living labour expended. Consequently the portion of living labour
embodied as surplus-labour in its product need not be fully reob-
tained in the form of products from other labour processes. So long
as the necessary labour time in the form of necessary means of
subsistence is obtained and consumed by the workers, they are able
to expend a larger amount of living labour in the labour process. This
is quite different from the portion of past labour which is transferred
from the means of production, as this portion must be recharged at
least in the same amount in the form of products from other labour
processes.
These conditions form an expanded part of the general economic
norms and can be illustrated by extending the previous numerical
example of spinning. Let us assume a working day of 12 hours com-
posed on average of 6 hours of necessary labour and the same length
126 Value, Labour and Capital
Figure 5.1
~
(_, \ (C+ V+ S)
M-C {Pm(c) ____ p ---- C ' - M'
L(v)
formation and
130 Value, Labour and Capital
(1)
p;' = _ _~ ~·
,:--_ _ =--7""""""'----:---:;-- (5.2)
C; + V; C; I V; +1
Production of Surplus-value
So far as capital pays wages for the value of the commodity labour-
power, it duly gets the command of its use-value as the actual
expenditure of labour-power, and obtains the whole results of la-
bouring activity according to the rules of a commodity economy. As a
whole, labourers have to purchase back from capitalists the means of
subsistence which they have produced in the necessary labour-time,
by repeatedly handing over the money obtained as the value of
142 Value, Labour and Capital
149
150 Value, Labour and Capital
What does 'a social process that goes on behind the backs of the
producers' mean? The process may well be interpreted in this context
as the exchange relations in a market 'behind the backs of the
producers'. At least Marx does not show how complex labour-time is
socially measured as multiplied simple labour-time, apart from the
reduction through commodity value which seems to imply that value
in exchange here determines labour-values rather than the reverse.
From the viewpoint of vulgar economics, which resolves all economic
152 Value, Labour and Capital
+ (6.1)
Since the terms 1ri and a;i are technically determined, there are n + m
+ 1 unknowns (a; and <l>r) in n equations. Let a; be the amount of
unskilled labour contained in one unit of skill of type s. It is in a sense
assumed here, following Hilferding's point of view, that skill in the
skilled-labour-power is producible by a certain amount of abstruct
human labour, and thus accountable by units of unskilled labour.
Then one unit of labour in an average lifetime of this type is equival-
ent to one unit of unskilled labour of the worker concerned plus a·s
units of unskilled labour embodied in his skills. Then
(6.3)
(6.4)
(6.5)
e =
(1 + (}-
S
(1 + ()
S
kO-b·
I IS =
1 - kO-b·
I IS (6.6)
s (1 + ()
s
kO;bis kO;bis
capitalist firm will not directly bear educational costs of skills, since
educated skilled workers may 'escape' to other competitive firms in
order to sell their labour-power dearer. In a competitive capitalist
economy without a public sector, educational costs thus tend to be
borne by families, and thus ironically reduce competitive mobility
independent of families, each of which are connected with certain
different grades of skilled labour. Wages or the form of value of
skilled labour-power on this occasion function as a channel of distri-
buting educational funds deducted from social surplus-labour to the
families of skilled workers. If wages of a certain type of skilled
workers are higher than the costs necessary both to maintain their
families and to replace their ability through their children, then other
children of the families which can afford such educational costs will
come in sooner or later, and vice versa. This is exactly the case, in
fact, consonant with the H-0-R model as we have seen. In such a
case wages as the form of value of skilled labour-power are main-
tained in a market by the inconvertibility of such labour-power just at
the level tendentially being equivalent to the educational costs plus
the ordinary wages for simple labourers, and this enables skilled
workers to obtain more substance of value than simple workers. The
higher wage-costs of technologically necessary skilled workers force
capitalist firms to set much higher prices of production for their
products in a competitive market, so as to enable these firms to
maintain reproduction through price-relations with an average rate of
profit, as substantially shown by the B-G model. So long as the extra
portion of the substance of value obtained by the skilled labourer as
compared to the common simple labourer remains within the quan-
tity of surplus-labour-time in his life, the skilled worker may be
conceptually classified as being exploited, nevertheless he must have
a more or less petit-bourgeois character as well. This is probably what
is implied by the degree of 'the rate of exploitation in common
labour' in the B-G model. It must be noted, however, that even
when a skilled worker is not exploited and is rather exploiting in this
context, he may indirectly add to total surplus-value by increasing the
productivity of other workers in various cases.
In an opposite case where educational costs of skills are entirely
borne by the state or the public entity from taxes on surplus-value,
the substance of value acquired personally by skilled workers through
the form of value of labour-power or wages need not contain any
social funds from surplus-labour, and must theoretically be reduced
to the same level as that of the common simple workers. We assume
166 Value, Labour and Capital
(1 + r) 5p 1 + 1 = 6p1 + Pz (6.7)
(1 + r) 10p2 + 1 = 3p1 + 12pz (6.8)
1 =i-P1 +fpz (6.9)
V =3X (-1) + 5 X 2 = 7
S =5 X (-1) + 2 X 2 = -1
v+s = 6.
Thus, surplus-value appears negative, while the rate of profit is
positive.
Steedman concludes from this analysis that Marx's labour theory of
value is not merely redundant, but also inconsistent, and that it
should be abandoned and replaced by the Sraffian theory of prices.
Anti-Critiques
An Alternative Solution
For instance, the social total annual commodity products are 9000, of
which 6000 are the means of production produced in the department I
and 3000 are the means of consumption produced in department II.
The composition of capital between constant capital (e) and variable
capital (v) is assumed to be 4:1 in both departments, and the rate of
surplus-value (s' = s/v) is assumed equally 100 per cent. It is also
assumed that the turnover of capital is once a year, and the particular
turnover of fixed capital over years is abstracted for the moment.
Then, the value-relations of commodity products from both depart-
ments for the process of simple reproduction must be such as follows:
They will bring about at the end of the second year the commodity
products of I 6600 and II 2400, or 9000 in total, which are beyond
8250, the value of commodity products of the first year, by realising
reproduction on expanded scale.
Expanded reproduction in any form of society must necessarily be
performed through expansion of the production of means of pro-
duction. This general norm of economy appears in the value-relations
of capital, as a condition I (v + s) > ne, instead of the condition 1 (v
+ s) = ne for simple reproduction. The basic condition for expanded
reproduction is thus I (v + s) > ne (11, p. 590). It is because the
products of I in the form of means of production must be greater than
the means of production consumed in both departments, i.e. 1 (e + v
+ s) > Ie + lie, or alternatively the products in II in the form of
consumption goods must be smaller than the social total of variable
capital and surplus-value, i.e. II (e + v + s) < 1 (v + s) +II (v + s).
More precisely the basic condition for a balanced expanded repro-
duction can be summarised into an equation Iv + s(v) + s(k) =lie+
s(e), as shown in the numerical example above.
a1 = C1 + V 1 + S1 = C1 + C2 (6.12)
vl + sl = Cz (6.13)
(6.14)
On the other hand, department II must spend CzX billion pounds for
the purchase of the products of department I, in order to replenish
the means of production used up. Therefore, purchase and sale
mutually performed between the departments can be balanced when
the following equation holds:
(6.15)
(6.16)
a 1 = C1 + St(c) + Cz + Sz(c)
VI + Sl(v) + Sl(k) = Cz + Sz(c) (6.18)
It is obvious that the relation V1 + s 1 > c2 must exist here as a basic
condition for expanded reproduction. Let us suppose here, as in the
previous case of simple reproduction, that the products of depart-
ments I and II are given prices in pounds respectively x times and y
times labour substance. The amount of money to be expended by
department I for the purchase of commodities from department II is
composed of both wages to be paid in the expanded reproduction,
i.e. v 1 y + s 1<vlY• and the portion for capitalist consumption as a
residue of the total price of the products after deducing the expendi-
tures necessary for expanded reproduction, i.e. a1x- (c1x + v1 y +
S1<clx + s 1<vly). The amount must thus be as follows:
(6.20)
(6.22)
195
196 The Motion of Capitals as a Concrete Mechamism
the total sum of labour contained in the commodity over the sum of
labour that is actually paid for' (III, p. 133).
In so far as cost-price and profit are thus treated as the internal
divisions within the substance of commodity value directly measur-
able in terms of labour-time, capitals would acquire surplus-value as
profit just as much as surplus-labour expended in each of their own
process of production. As a result, the yearly rate of profit against the
total advanced capital, which is hereafter simply called 'the rate of
profit' in accord with usual terminology must necessarily vary across
different branches of industry with a different number of workers
employed against the total advanced capital, due to different organic
composition and/or different turnover period of capital. We can
reasonably assume here that the length of the working day as well as
the real wages, and therefore the rate of surplus-value (s; = s;lv;) tend
to be equalised across industries through competition among capitals
and workers. There cannot be any theoretical reason, however, to
expect the equalisation of the organic composition of capital (v/c;) or
of the turnover period of capital across industries having different
technical bases. The industries with lower compositions of capital,
employing more labourers with a given amount of capital, or those
with faster turnover, must obtain a higher rate of profit than other-
wise, so long as the law of value is identified here with the equal
exchange of labour embodied in commodities.
Marx examines these points in chapter 8, 'Different Compositions
of Capital in Different Branches of Production, and the Resulting
Variation in Rates of Profit', in the third volume of Capital, and
summarises the problem further to be clarified as follows:
The incompatibility pointed out here between the law of value, as the
equal exchange of labour, and the law of the equalisation of the rate
of profit across industries with different organic compositions or
turnover times of capital was a crucial problem for the labour theory
of value since the classical school. Marx's solution is presented in the
following chapter 9, 'Formation of a General Rate of Profit (Average
Rate of Profit), and Transformation of Commodity Values into
Prices of Production', starting from Table 7.1, where turnover of
capitals is assumed equally once a year.
Table 7.1
If we treat the 500 as one single capital, with I-V simply forming
different portions of it, - then the average composition of the
capital of 500 would be 500 = 390c + 110v, or in percentages 78c +
22v. Treating the capitals of 100 as each simply a fifth of the total
capital, its composition would be this average one of 78c + 22v: in
the same way the average surplus-value of 22 would accrue to each
of these capitals of 100, the average rate of profit would thus be 22
per cent, and the price of each fifth of the total product produced
by this capital of 500 would be 122. (III, p. 255). Taken together,
commodities are sold at 2 + 7 + 17 = 26 above their value, and 8 +
18 = 26 below their value, so that the divergences of price from
Competition among Capitals 205
A controversy has continued on and off since the end of the nine-
teenth century concerning the two problems discussed above. In the
period after the Second World War particularly until the 1950s, the
focus of discussion among some Western scholars was on the second
problem of how to transform values into prices of production consist-
ently, including the elements of cost-prices. In this first phase of the
Western controversy on the transformation problem, the first prob-
lem was untouched, and all the participants, Marxians and non-
Marxians alike, assumed the labour theory of value or value prices as
a given precondition for the debates. However, in the second phase
of the controversy since 1970s, the scope of the debate has no longer
been confined to the second problem, as the number of participants
and the contents of controversy have largely extended. The growth of
a neo-Ricardian School after the publication of Sraffa's Production of
Commodities by Means of Commodities in 1960, and the following
revival of the Western Marxian School, caused a rekindling of the
controversy on Marx's value theory across the two problems, forming
Competition among Capitals 211
I c1 + v1 + S1 = C1 + C2 + c3
II C2 + V 2 + S2 = V 1 + V 2 + V 3 (7.1)
III C3 + V 3 + s 3 = S1 + S2 + S 3
Marx's definition of prices of production wasP;= (c; + v;) + r(c; + v;),
where the average rate of profit was defined as r = "2.s/'2:.(c; + v;). The
cost-price (c; + v;) was in terms of value, and not yet transformed into
prices of production. So as to clear up this residual incompleteness,
B-S introduce three unknowns, x, y, z, which designate the ratios of
the price of production to the value of the commodity products of
departments I, II, III. For example, the price of production of the
means of production is assumed to be x times of its value when
complete transformation including the elements of cost-prices is
212 The Motion of Capitals as a Concrete Mechanism
I c1x + v 1 y + r(c 1x + v 1 y) = (c 1 + c2 + c3 )x
II CzX + VzY + r(CzX + V2 Y) = (v 1 + V2 + V3)y (7.2)
III c~ + VJY + r(c~ + VJY) = (s 1 + S2 + s 3 )Z
From the first two equations in (7 .3) we can deduce a solution which
is non-negative and consistent with the equations, as follows:
- (/z8t + 8z) + Y(/z8t + 8z) 2 + 4 lf1 - fz)8t8z
a= 2(/t- fz)
225 90 60 375
II 100 120 80 300
III 50 90 60 200
Total 375 300 200 875
Competition among Capitals 213
288 96 96 480
II 128 128 64 320
III 64 96 40 200
Total 480 320 200 1000
Let us. try to make clear the structural logical relation in the dimen-
sionally distinct concepts of value so as to construct a more satisfac-
tory theory of prices of production. In my view we must investigate
the three aspects of value in their relation in order to solve the
confusing transformation problem. It is not sufficient to see how (i)
the substance of values, or the amounts of labour embodied in
commodity products on the basis of given social and technical condi-
tions of production determine (ii) the prices of production as a form
Competition among Capitals 221
Department of Ci Vi sj a~l
production
I 225 90 96 411
II 100 120 64 284
III 50 90 40 180
Totals 375 300 200 875
s; = p; + liz = ~; x p;f~p;, a; = C; + v; + s;
Competition among Capitals 223
total profit against total wages "i:.p/'2:.v;J, or the ratio of total surplus
value against total capital "i:.s/"i:.(c; + v;) in terms of labour-substance
and the rate of profit in terms of prices "i:.p;l"i:.(c;:x + VJI) do not
generally coincide in these tables. It is no longer any wonder, in spite
of all the criticisms against Marxian value theory on this point,
causing continuous perplexity among serious Marxians, since the
total quantities and ratios compared belong to different dimensional
orders and are counted by different units. It must be noted that the
labour-substance of value acquired through prices of production are
not directly proportional to prices (and their components) in Table
7 .5. So long as capitalists in each department continue their produc-
tion they have to reinvest the money obtained by selling their com-
modity products at the prices of production, and must repurchase the
factors of production consumed. The money representing the portion
of prices of constant capital c;x within the cost-prices must be ex-
pended in order to repurchase the means of production which contain
llx of prices in labour-hours, or c; hours of value-substance. The
money obtained as the portion of the price of variable capital V;Y in
the cost-prices must also be expended to repurchase labour-power of
workers, enabling them to get lly of wages in labour-hours as the
substance of value of their necessary means of consumption. The
same number of workers can thus be employed by each department
of production, and they will replenish the labour-substance of vari-
able capital v; as well as that of surplus-value s; through their living
labour again in the next year. Therefore, c; and v; together with their
totals in Table 7.4 reappear in each corresponding items of the same
quantities in Table 7.6, representing the substance of value acquired
through transactions performed this year at prices of production.
Correspondingly, the surplus-labour embodied in the social surplus
products appears as the only portion of the substance of value that
are to be treated socially through the form of profit. Unlike c; and v;,
this portion of the value substance s; need not be reobtained by each
department in the same amount as is produced in that department.
Competition among capitals determines the distribution of the sub-
stance of surplus-value, by equalising the rate of profit across indus-
tries in the form of prices of production. So far as simple repro-
duction and equal composition of capital (or a single product) in
department III are assumed here, the quantity of the substance of
value of the surplus product obtained by the average profit p; result-
ingly coincides with the social distribution of the total substance of
surplus-value in direct proportion with p;, as shown in Table 7 .6. By
224 The Motion of Capitals as a Concrete Mechanism
than the standard condition of production does not exist, and there-
fore where there is no countervailing transfer of the substance of
value within the same sphere. The substance of this type of extra
profit can also be the transfer of surplus-labour extracted in other
industrial spheres just as the substance of some portion of average
profit, as we have already argued in Chapter 5, Section 5.2 concern-
ing the extra surplus-value obtained by capitals with improved
methods of production. In its nature the substance of extra profit
obtained by technologically superior conditions of production con-
tains a role for the socially necessary labour cost of improving and
renewing production methods, a cost which is more or less common
to all forms of society, and also to a socialist society. There is no
doubt, however, that capitalism would never consciously intend to
develop production methods in favour of workers' own well-being or
in ecological harmony with wider nature, as far as it copes with the
labour costs of improving production methods subject to the indivi-
dualistic chrematistic form of extra profit.
Differential Rent
Table 7.7
(i) -The supply of wheat from the worst soil, type A of the four
types, is indispensable to satisfy the social need of wheat under
the given technological conditions of capital.
(ii) -The soil type A represents the natural conditions of reproduc-
tion of wheat which allows the flexibility to adjust the supply to
meet fluctuating demand. In other words, the supply can be
increased or decreased in about the same soil type A when the
social demand for wheat increases or decreases for the moment.
(iii) -In contrast, the better soil types B, C, Dare now restricted and
capitals are unable to expand cultivation on these types of soil.
Otherwise, the conditions (i) and (ii) above could not be as-
sured.
In so far as the soil type A represents for the present the natural
conditions of supply to meet the fluctuating demand for wheat under
these social conditions, the governing market price of production of
wheat is determined by the conditions of production on this type of
soil. Upon the basis of such a determination of the market price of
production the extra profit for capitals invested on the better soil
types B, C, D must necessarily be obtained by selling their products
at the governing market price of production, and it must be trans-
formed into differential rent as shown in Table 7. 7
There seem to be two related problems here in the theory of
differential rent, which have been favoured targets of anti-Marxian
critiques, especially in view of the 'technological average' theory of
market value, along with a one-sidedly technological approach to the
labour theory of value. In the conventional Marxian 'technological
average' theory of market value, it is believed to be the socially
average quantity of labour embodied in commodities produced in an
industrial sphere which determines their market value. The extra
surplus value obtained by capitals with better than average technical
conditions of production is then regarded as a transfer of surplus-
labour from capitals with inferior technical conditions in the same
sphere. The theory of differential rent seems to contradict these
general notions in two points: first in its definition of the market value
or market price of production by the worst 'marginal' productive
conditions of land in use, and second in its notion of extra profit
without a countervailing transfer of surplus-labour from capitals in
the same sphere with inferior productive conditions.
From what we argued in the previous section, the first point can no
longer be a serious problem. The notion of market value or market
Competition among Capitals 241
of market value, 600 sh. in the above instance, could not theoretically
be distinguished from the real substance of value or the
quantity of labour-time actually embodied in wheat. Marx was con-
scious of the point, but he did not thoroughly solve the problem with
his clumsy concept of 'false social value'. The conventional Marxian
'technical average' theory of market value was unable to solve the
problem. Uno's reformulation of the theory of market value, as well
as his thorough distinction between the forms and the substance of
value found the way forward. 32 From the view of the form of market
value in our reformulation, the governing price of production of
wheat which is determined by the production conditions of the soil
type A can no longer be exceptional. The general notion of market
value or market price of production as the gravitational centre of
fluctuating market price, revealing the conditions of production
which can meet social demand elastically, is exactly applicable to the
governing price of wheat. From the view of the substance of value,
however, the difference in the conditions of production based upon
the monopolisable natural conditions of land must be treated separ-
ately. In case of technical conditions of production, the representa-
tive conditions in a sphere of production, which are revealed through
a fluctuating market, must be a standard basis on which to define the
substance of value or the quantity of labour-time embodied in a
commodity product of the sphere. Such representative technical
conditions of production are socially to be confirmed even among
capitals cultivating the same soil type A, as well as on the other soil
types. Apart from such representativeness of technical conditions of
production, we should not just take the natural conditions of the soil
type A for the social standard basis or which to define the substance
of value embodied in the product of the soil, even though the soil
type A would serve here as the regulative condition of land for the
market price of production. Thus, in contrast with the conventional
notion of the value of land-products since Ricardo, the substance, not
the form, of value of the land-products must be determined by the
total or average conditions of land, and not by the worst marginal
condition.
Upon the basis of differential rent I as we have seen, differential
rent II appears when sums of capital are invested successively on the
same piece of land with varying productivity. Each unit of successive
investment must be mutually separable and independent so as to
form extra profit due to the various productivities to be transformed
into differential rent II. For instance, an additional unit of seeds,
244 The Motion of Capitals as a Concrete Mechanism
Table 7.8
Absolute Rent
ment, and they would not yield absolute rent. On the other side, the
possibility of increasing the supply of land-products on the old
leaseholds without paying additional rent for the time being must
limit the claim of landowners to ever larger amounts of absolute rent.
For instance, additional investments on the better soil type B, or C,
or D with a lower productivity in producing wheat at the price of
production of 65 sh. a quarter was made possible in our previous
example by the restriction of landowners of the worst type A land
which raised the governing price up to that level. On the other side,
however, the landowners of the type A land cannot demand more
than 5 sh. an acre as absolute rent by pulling up the governing price
further, in so far as additional investment with such a productivity
can still be expanded on the old leaseholds of better soil types.
Thus, absolute rent is generally subject to the motion of differen-
tial rent both in its qualitative form of appearance and its quantitative
limitation. In this regard, absolute rent is theoretically separable
from monopoly rent, which is not subject to such a general limitation
and is determined 'rather by the demand of the purchasers and their
ability to pay' (III, p. 898) as in the case of some vineyards suitable for
producing special kinds of wine. Monopoly rent as such can be put
outside of the principles of ground rent in a capitalist economy, so as
to be analysed in more concrete levels of research. In principle,
capitals determine by their own motion the form and the limitation of
the concessionary transfers of certain parts of surplus-value to landed
property, as we have seen in the two 'normal' forms (ibid.) of both
differential and absolute rent. The basic logic of competition among
capitals centring around a general rate of profit is not at all distorted
by payment of these forms of ground-rent, but rather carried out
through them.
8 The Mobilisation of
Capitals
Competition among capitals which forms a general rate of profit and
the market prices of production across industrial spheres, through the
process of fluctuating market prices, demonstrates the concretely
developed forms of the law of value as the law of motion of a
capitalist economy. An anarchical capitalist market economy must
incessantly misallocate dead and living labour in various spheres,
bringing about either an excessive or short supply of commodities.
Such misallocation of labour is not generally insolvable. It is usually
repeatedly readjusted in the process of the expansion of capitalist
production, guided by the movement of market prices. A short
supply of commodity products in relation to social demand is indi-
cated when extra profit is obtained by some spheres by selling their
products at market prices higher than the market prices of produc-
tion. Then the expansion of production in such spheres is speeded up
basically by reinvesting the extra in addition to the average profit. An
excessive supply of commodity products would cause the reverse
effects. The shortening of the selling-time of commodity products
reflecting favourable market conditions would usually go along with
the rise in market prices, having similar effects, and the prolongation
of selling-time would have the opposite effects. 1
The general economic rule common to all social formations, which
is to adjust the allocation of labour so as to suit the social system of
needs, on the basis of given technical conditions of production, is
thus carried through by an anarchical market mechanism in the
process of competition among capitals. Capitalism is not one-sidedly
a destructive or unbalancing economic order, but in a peculiar way it
is also an efficient order in that it expands production by readjusting
its own misallocation of labour. Competition among capitals to get
higher individual rates of profit, resultingly equalising the rate of profit
across industries, serves as the basic mechanism for capitals to adjust
the allocation of labour in the process of the expansion of production.
Such a process of competition among capitals along with their
expansion of production cannot be as smooth and efficient as it could
be, if capital remains just individual industrial capitals. Individual
industrial capitals with lower rates of profit, cannot rapidly escape
250
The Mobilisation of Capitals 251
How to Approach It
Commercial Credit
Figure 8.1
Bank Credit
Typical bank credit in the basic theory of the credit system appears
on the basis of commercial credit. It is a capitalistic social organisa-
tion mediating the mutual accommodation of idle capitals on a broader
scale than commercial credit. Banks form capitalist social relations of
debt and credit with many and unspecified industrial and commercial
capitalists. Their debt is basically in the form of issued bank notes
and received deposit. They give credit typically in the form of the
discount of bills of exchange.
Bank notes appear as bank's promissory notes to pay on sight a
quantity of the money commodity, e.g. a quarter-pound of gold
coined as a pound sterling. It can obtain a broader circulation as a
higher grade of credit money beyond the restrictions on bills of
exchange in commercial credit. A capitalist likeD above, who cannot
purchase the necessary commodities by a bill of exchange received,
because of the restrictions of time, amount or creditability, would be
able to go on with the necessary transactions if he could get bank
notes at a bank in exchange for the bill. The bank would thereby
obtain money credit in the form of the bill upon a certain debtor (like
The Mobilisation of Capitals 265
A above) until the due date, but also stand in money debt in the form
of the bank notes issued when it discounted the bill for D. The cash
reserve of a bank to pay its money debt when requested, is formed
not merely by a portion of the banker's own capital, but also by an
inflow of cash as deposits, and payment for the bills of exchange held
by it at their redemption dates. The proportion of a banker's own
capital in the cash reserve can be substantially reduced and may even
become zero when the bank becomes consolidated and is able to
depend sufficiently on its cash inflow through return payments and
deposits for, reserve. Practically, the extension of bank credit relies
on the trend of deposits and return payments. When bank notes
issued by a bank are brought back into the same bank in the form of a
deposit or return payment, it reduces the bank's money debt, espe-
cially as a ratio to its cash reserve so as to facilitate the potential
extension of bank credit. Its effect is similar to a cash inflow which
increases the bank's reserve against its money debt.
So far as bank credit is extendible on the basis of the growth of
capitalist production, banks would receive deposits by accepting and
mobilising various idle-money capitals in the hands of industrial and
commercial capitalists, so that the banks can increase their own bases
of business. Industrial and commercial capitals would also regard it as
convenient to have deposits at banks in order to economise on the
cost of storing, paying and receiving money, as well as the costs of
clearing credit transactions. Banks act in this function as a mod-
ernised form of money-dealing capital (see note 2 of this chapter).
In the case that a bank receives deposits easily and plentifully, it
need not issue bank notes for its business, though it may occasionally
issue some forms of bank cheque or bank draft to make its business
elastic.
When a bank exchanges cash or bank notes for a commercial bill of
exchange upon the request of capitalist, say the raw-cotton grower D,
it does not pay the same amount of cash or bank notes as the nominal
price given on the bill. A certain amount, according to the period
remaining until the redemption date of the bill, is discounted from
the nominal price. The discount is actually a form of interest. For
instance, if the general rate of interest is 8 per cent a year, about £200
would be discounted from the bill of £10 000 on surface with 3
months' time of due, and £9800 of cash or bank notes are given in
exchange with the bill. Suppose the bill is from capitalist D in the
illustration above. The bank which discounts the bill will actually
obtain interest of £200 together with the principal sum of the money
266 The Motion of Capitals as a Concrete Mechanism
credit of £9800, when the return payment of £10 000 is paid from A
on the due date of the bill.
Capitalists who get cash or bank notes in exchange for commercial
bills can accelerate the turnover of their capital, economise their idle
funds, and thus obtain additional profit. 14 They would not mind
sharing out a portion of the available additional profit as interest in
the form of discount on bills. However, the capitalist like D who asks
a bank to discount a commercial bill of exchange is not really a sole
bearer of the discount interest for the bill. The raw-cotton grower D
has already sold his commodity product raw cotton, for the commer-
cial bill with a 3 months' life, at a credit price of £10 000, higher than
the cash price of about £9800. The nominal price of a commercial bill
thus contains a portion of interest from the date of its issue, and its
transfer must always accompany the credit price being more or less
higher than a cash price. Therefore, the discount interest obtained by
a bank for the bill was actually born by the initial debtor capitalist A,
and possibly also by the series of capitalists B, C and D, who
subsequently used and passed the bill before it was discounted by the
bank. Distribution of the costs of interest contained in the nominal
price of the bill, which is finally discounted by the bank, would vary
among the four capitalists concerned, depending on the different
rates of interest contained in the credit prices of each individual
transaction, as well as on the different length of time in which the bill
remains in a hands of each capitalist.
Anyway, interest obtained by banks through the discount and
redemption of the commercial bill is no longer buried in the credit
price of commodities transacted by commercial credit. It now ap-
pears clearly as interest on a money loan taking the form of discount,
and is obviously separated from the transactions of commodities in
the case of bank credit. This must react on commercial credit in
making capitalists more conscious of the interest contained by the
credit prices of commodities, though individual divergence in its rate
would still remain. As banks can extend their basis of loan to earn
interest by gathering more deposits, they pay interest to depositors to
encourage it, and thus further generalise interest or the form of
interest-bearing capital in a capitalist economy. Against loan capital
in the form of interest-bearing capital, industrial and commercial
capitals are contrasted as real capital invested in profit-making enter-
prises.
Although banks have the capitalistic social function of mobilising
idle capitals, they appear in principle as profit-making enterprises
The Mobilisation of Capitals 267
funds with a single central bank and using its bank notes in common.
Thus logically chosen, the central bank retains the common cash
reserve, upon which the flexible rediscounting of bills can take place.
It is just like the basic case where individual industrial capitals
mutually economise their reserve funds by utilising a common local
bank.
The central bank appears thus as the bank for banks especially in
the central money market. The bank notes issued by such a central
bank are used as a common means of settlement, not merely among
the banks in the central money market, but also in commercial
transactions in the commercial centre as 'the coin of wholesale trade'
(III, p. 529). The range of circulation of the central bank notes would
further be extended into commercial and credit transactions with and
within local areas which have close relations with the commercial
centre. However, in so far as a central bank in our basic theory is still
private bank capital with a limited amount of capital investment and
acceptability, the central bank notes would not come unlimitedly
'into general circulation' outside of central commercial and credit
circulation. The central bank and the central money market cannot
form equally close relations with all the local areas. Banks of issue
independent from the central bank would continue to operate mostly
in such areas as relatively alienated from the commercial centre or
having their own special needs for credit expansion, like the agricul-
tural country banks or the Scottish banks of issue coexisting with the
Bank of England in UK in the nineteenth century. 16 Specie payment
is necessary for the settlement of commercial and credit transactions
with such areas. The central bank note as the 'the coin of wholesale
trade' would not be completely substituted for by real coins, particu-
larly in the small amounts of payment for wages and retail trade, as
the bank would regard it unprofitable to issue and handle bank notes
of small face value in view of its basic position as the bank of banks. 17
Therefore the general need for specie and hard coins as the means of
circulation and of payment remain along with the circulation of the
central bank notes. Correspondingly the cash reserve of the central
bank against its liability in the form of both its bank notes issued and
deposits accepted must be in the form of specie or hard coins as the
gold reserve.
The flexible extensibility of bank credit which is generalised by the
money market between banks is thus further increased by the forma-
tion of a central bank as the bank of banks. The relative indepen-
dence of credit expansion in local areas, as well as in individual banks
The Mobilisation of Capitals 273
prospect of a total or marginal profit rate higher than the general rate
of interest in the money market will be encouraged to utilise more
loans to expand their business. On the contrary, real capitals with a
prospect of a total or marginal profit rate lower than the general rate
of interest will be forced to reduce their debt and business. For
instance, the expansion of production in the spheres of production is
accelerated by a margin between a higher rate of profit including
extra profit and the general rate of interest where commodity pro-
ducts are in short supply so elevating their market prices above the
prices of production. As a result a relatively rapid increase in supply
of the commodity products would eventually lower their market
prices so as to decrease and then remove extra profit, and vice versa.
Thus, the money market together with the whole substructure of the
credit system works as a concrete mechanism for 'the equalisation of
the profit rate or the movement of this equalisation, on which the
whole of capitalist production depends' (III, p. 566). This working is
substantially realised in combination with another function of the
credit system in reducing circulation costs and idle circulation capitals
(similar to, but more broadly than, commercial capitals) by acceler-
ating 'the velocity of the metamorphosis of commodities, and with
this the velocity of monetary circulation' (III, p. 567).
In the neo-classical school, the rate of interest and the general rate
of profit are considered equal in equilibrium analyses. This assumes
on the one hand the perfect mobility and convertibility of capital
values between loan capital in the money market and real capital in
industry and commerce, and on the other hand determination of the
rate of profit as well as that of interest in the sphere of the market.
These assumptions and the resulting identity between both rates are
not in the tradition of the classical or the Marxian schools. This must
be regarded as an important watershed, dividing the major theoreti-
cal currents in economics.
In the Marxian school, which critically developed classical econ-
omics, the general rate of profit is determined by the physical con-
ditions of reproduction as we have seen. In contrast, the general rate
of interest is not determinable directly by the physical and technical
conditions, but substantially dependent upon the balance of supply
and demand of loan capital in the money market. The determinants
of both rates are quite separate. Perfect mobility and convertibility
between loanable money capital and real (industrial and commercial)
capital is indeed too abstract and formalistic an assumption to be
actual. Industrial and commercial capitals with more or less fixed
The Mobilisation of Capitals 275
divided by the price of a stock, Ps) and the rate of interest. In other
words, the price of a stock is tendentially determined around the
standard price, being the capitalised amount of dividend per stock, or
the price calculated by dividing the dividend per stock by the rate of
interest (Ps = d/i).
In practice the dividend does not precisely represent the actual
profit earned by a corporation. A part of profit must be subtracted for
the remuneration of directors and managers. Internal reserves and a
disguised form of profit through accelerated depreciation funds, etc.,
are often also subtracted (although stock investors use indices that
compensate for such manoeuvers). Contrariwise, a portion of inter-
nal reserves are sometimes added to the dividend in order to stabilise
the stock price against a decline in actual profit. In addition, transac-
tions of stocks in the capital market always involve anarchic specula-
tion as to prospects of individual companies, the motion of interest,
and business activities in specific spheres and in general. Conse-
quently, the actual stock price commonly deviates above and below
the theoretical standard level of the capitalised dividend from profit
per stock. However, the stock price of a corporation must increase
tendentially as its actual profit per stock rises, reflecting actual profit-
ability, and would generally decline as the rate of interest rises, so as to
fluctuate if widely around the theoretical standard defined above.
Even though the dividend yield (y) thus tends to be equalised with
the rate of interest (i), giving profit the form of interest, it does not
mean that the real rate of profit (p') against a corporation's own
principal capital actually invested, and not against the stock price,
also becomes identical to the interest rate. Competition among
capitals for higher rates of profit on actually invested capital must
effect even giant corporations and consequently works as a means of
equalising the rate of profit in the long run by shifting capitals from
spheres with a profit rate lower than average to other spheres with a
higher profit rate. Marx seems to neglect this when he says: 'Since
profit here simply assumes the form of interest, enterprises that
merely yield an interest are possible, and this is one of the reasons
that hold up the fall in the general rate of profit, since these enter-
prises, where the constant capital stands in such a tremendous ratio
to the variable, do not necessarily go into the equalization of the
general rate of profit.' (III, p. 568). Hilferding criticises Marx's
statement here by saying: 'Marx was thinking of the railway corpora-
tions of his day', . . . . 'it is clear that with the spread of the corpora-
tion its profit, just like that of an individually owned enterprise, must
286 The Motion of Capitals as a Concrete Mechanism
equal yields on their stock prices. The actual inequality of the rates of
profit is thus hidden and buried in the tendential equality of the rates
of dividend yield in the form of joint-stock capital. Similarly, any
regular annual income such as ground-rent or fixed interest on state
bonds is given the fictitious form of money capital as the capitalised
amount of the annual income estimated on the current rate of
interest. In principle this is the way to determine the standard price of
land on the basis of the preceding theory of ground-rent. 29
Capitalism is a specific socio-economic formation grounded on the
commodity form. It systematically embraces into that form all the
elements of economic life under the dominant motion of capital. The
commodity form of labour-power, besides that of the means of
production and consumption, was an essential precondition for the
formation of a thorough commodity economy as capitalism. In the
mechanisms of the motion of capitalism, the commodity form is
further given to money funds in a money market, and finally to
capital itself, which is the central subject of the whole system. The
logical process of the development of the forms of commoditisation
in a capitalist economy then reaches in principle its final and highest
form in joint-stock capital. As Marx suggested in his initial plan,
joint-stock capital must thus be really presented as the most devel-
oped final form of capital. In fact capitalism has not created any
further forms of capital beyond this. For instance, finance capital or
monopoly capital is a concrete organisation of giant joint-stock
corporations each with its national characteristics,30 and multinational
corporations are the more developed organisation of such finance
capital across international spheres of activity. Development of both
of these types of capital does not contain a fundamentally new form,
but are rather related to the more concrete national or international
economic conditions faced, which must be studied along with their
actual historical significance at separate, more concrete levels of
researches founded on the basic principles of capitalism.
In its highest complete form of joint-stock capital, however, capital
cannot effectively make up a completely unified system of reproduc-
tion. The creation of giant joint-stock capitals partially mitigate the
difficulty of accumulation and profitability for themselves, but does
not solve and may indeed deepen the difficulties for other capitals as
well as of the economy as a whole. The movement of capitals in
readjusting the anarchical imbalances between industrial spheres,
through competition among capitals equalising the rate of profit, are
constantly obstructed and retarded by the relative immobility of giant
The Mobilisation of Capitals 289
The relative mass of the industrial reserve army thus increases with
the potential energy of wealth. But the greater this reserve army in
proportion to the active labour-army, the greater is the mass of a
consolidated surplus population, whose misery is in inverse ratio to
the amount of torture it has to undergo in the form of labour. The
more extensive, finally, the pauperized sections of the working
class and the industrial reserve army, the greater is official pauper-
ism. This is the absolute general law of capitalist accumulation. (I,
p. 798).
Either the price of labour keeps on rising, because its rise does
not interfere with the process of accumulation .... Or, the other
alternative, accumulation slackens as a result of the rise in the price
of labour, because the stimulus of gain is blunted. The rate of
Business Cycles and Crises 303
accumulation lessens; but this means that the primary cause of that
lessening vanishes, i.e. the disproportion between capital and
exploitable labour-power. The mechanism of the capitalist produc-
tion process removes the very obstacles it temporarily creates. The
price of labour falls again to a level corresponding with capital's
requirements for self-valorization. (1, p. 770).
Prosperity
market would not have any difficulty in maintaining its cash reserve
by accepting both deposits and return payments sufficiently, while the
demand for rediscounting would remain relatively low.
Therefore, the interest rate in the money market between banks
would also be comparatively low, reflecting a relative abundance of
loanable money capital. It easily facilitates industrial and commercial
capitals expanding their commercial credit at a low rate of interest
and their business activity in general. However, the relative abun-
dance of loanable money capital must not be taken for a basic cause
of the prosperity. The easy money market in this phase expresses
rather, the prosperous expansive accumulation of real capitals with a
relatively stable and satisfactory rate of profit. Though such a rate of
profit and a comparatively low rate of interest appear logically
interrelated in the phase of prosperity, the determinants of both rates
must be conceived separately as we have argued in Chapter 8,
Section 8.2; the former rate is regulated basically by the system of the
technical conditions of production and the level of real wages in
physical terms, whereas the latter rate is determined by the balance
between the demand for and the supply of loanable money capital.
Therefore, it is no surprise to observe a divergence between the
general rate of profit and the comparatively lower rate of interest in
the process of prosperity, despite a traditional tendency in neo-
classicists to identify them. This is not to deny that real capitalists
would usually consider the interest rate as a minimum standard for
their marginal rate of profit for additional investment.
Since the process of capital accumulation with a relatively stable
and satisfactory rate of profit continues in a expensive fashion as a
quantitative boom, it one-sidedly absorbs the labouring population
into the capitalist process of production, if not literally proportionally
to the increase of the total value of capital. So far as the ratio of
capital yearly accumulated, as a dependant function of the rate of
profit, generally surpasses the rate of growth of population in the
phase of prosperity, the relative surplus-population would decrease
further and further, and the labour market would become tightened
sooner or later. Then, towards the end of prosperity wages must rise.
Unlike in case of commodity products, capital cannot increase the
absolute amount of the supply of labour-power even when its price
rises. Because of this inelasticity in the supply of labour-power, the
rise of its price, the nominal wage-rate, in the labour market cannot
be generally counterbalanced by the possible rises of other commod-
ity prices here in our basic principles.
Business Cycles and Crises 307
Anyhow, a rise in the interest rate in the face of the falling rate of
profit must form an important restriction on the motion of capitals
which have so much depended upon an extensive credit system for
their reproduction. The process of a tightening money market be-
comes more clearly decisive when the gold reserve of the central
bank begins to drain away. In the basic theory of capitalism the
central bank must be conceived as a private central bank of issue, and
its bank notes cannot be totally substituted for gold money, particu-
larly in transactions with places well outside of the central trading
area as well as for use in wage payments, as we discussed in Chapter 8,
Section 8.2. As the special fluctuations in commodity prices and the
speculative trades develop with the process of the over-accumulation of
capital, the balance of payments among increasing commercial bills
between various trading areas would be very much distorted. The
necessary amount of specie payment to settle the balance of credit
between various areas would thus increase along with an increase of
cash payment for wages. Capitals and banks have now to hold more
gold money as reserve for payment. Therefore, an inflow of gold to
the central bank through return payments and deposits would be-
come smaller than before, whereas the outflow of gold in the forms of
withdrawals of deposits or conversions of bank notes increases. The
gold reserve of the central bank which is a central indicator of the
money market must then absolutely decrease. 20 Since the central bank
cannot use the other bankers' notes or bills as its reserve for payment, it
must raise its discount rate so as to reduce the absolute amount of
discount and attempt to control the daily quantity of discount business
when such an absolute decrease in the gold reserve occurs. All other
banks then find it difficult to continue their expansion of credit by
relying upon rediscounting commercial bills in the money market or
with the central bank, while carefully securing their cash reserves. A
sharp rise in the interest rate therefore generally appears with a
quantitative restriction on the credit supply.
The speculative stockpile of various commodities, which has been
increased and maintained upon a basis of expandable credit and in
expectation of a rise in prices, must lose its rationale, eroded from
two sides; the slowing down of the total demand in the commodity
market due to a falling rate of profit, and a sharp rise in the rate of
interest in the money market towards the very end of the prosperity.
When the expected rate of rise in the price of a commodity becomes
lower than the increasing rate of interest, it must be seen that to carry
on holding the stockpile on the basis of credit (alone increasing it)
Business Cycles and Crises 313
Crisis
commodity market and the money market. As Marx points out: 'This
explains the phenomenon that crises do not first break out and are
not first apparent in the retail trade, which bears on immediate
consumption, but rather in the sphere of wholesale trade, as well as
banking, which places the money capital of the entire society at the
wholesalers' disposal.' (III, p. 419).
Since speculative overtrading is an appearance of the inner diffi-
culty of excessive capital accumulation, generally involving industrial
capitals as well, the resulting collapse in speculation by wholesalers
cannot be an isolated phenomenon. With the breakdown of large-
scale speculative operations in wholesale trade, the prices of com-
modities which have been elevated to higher levels by such opera-
tions must collapse. The basis of credit relations, which are extended
assuming certain relations of prices, is then destroyed. The difficulty
of finding the necessary amounts of cash for the bills falling due must
spread, causing a series of insolvencies in a chain reaction, as com-
modities cannot be sold at expected prices. The whole credit system
becomes paralysed by the reciprocal collapse of the commodity
market and the money market. While new commercial credit would
hardly be given among industrial and commercial capitalists, banks
would also most severely restrict the issue of credit in the form of
discounting bills, in order to secure their own cash reserves as well as
to avoid the danger of insolvency. The interest rate rises more
sharply, to the highest level of the whole phase of the business cycle,
as the demand for credit in order to obtain money as the necessary
means of payment desperately increases in spite of the severe restric-
tion or the supply of credit. So far as the process of reproduction
through commodity transactions is carried on on the basis of the
credit system, its repetition becomes not merely difficult, but also
meaningless as the process of valorisation of capital. Its repetition
would mostly make a loss by paying such expensive interest rates.
The sale of commodities therefore, even at a sacrifice·, is urged on by
the pressure to clear off past debts among real capitals. A general fall
in commodity prices with the extreme difficulty of selling them
appears in reciprocal relation with the general collapse of credit
transactions.
In sum, the inner difficulty of the over-accumulation of real capital
is expressed contradictorily in an absolute shortage of money capital
in the money market as well as in a correlated absolute excess of
commodity capital in the commodity market. Alongside the recipro-
cal collapses of the money market and the commodity market, 'in
Business Cycles and Crises 315
contrast to the theoretical beliefs of the classical school and the neo-
classical tradition, capitalism cannot be a natural harmonious socio-
economic order which can increase the welfare of workers without
causing any serious disturbance or crisis by itself. As we have seen in
the basic principles of political economy, the logical inevitability of
periodical crisis is thus shown on the basis of Marx's notion of the
'absolute overproduction of capital' in relation to the labouring popu-
lation. Disequilibrium among industrial spheres and the severe res-
triction on the effective demand of workers, both of which have been
much emphasised in the excess commodity theory of crisis, appear as
important moments, if not fundamental causes, of the process as well
as the results of crisis. 22 The excess capital theory of crisis, of a
labour-shortage type, sees the root of the self-contradiction of the
capitalist economy causing periodical crises, not in the superficial
balance between the demand and the supply of commodity products,
but in the very essential precondition of capitalism which is to treat
human labour-power as a commodity. It should also be noted that the
logical inevitability of an acute general crisis is presented by showing
not merely the fundamental difficulty of the over-accumulation of
capital, but also the manner in which through competition and credit
among capitals the difficulty of over-accumulation intensifies result-
ing in the trinity of commercial, credit and industrial crises.
There is a problem as to where and why the vicious circle of
reciprocal contractions between the commodity market, the effective
demand of labour and the reproduction of capitals ends. It seems
difficult to think of the point where the vicious circle looses its
violence, so long as capitals are conceived abstractly as a homoge-
neous entity. Indeed, if real capitals are assumed to be homoge-
neous, the theoretical limit to the destruction of capitals would be
quite hard to define. Where can a fall in commodity prices, the
contraction of effective demand and the wave of bankruptcies
theoretically come to an end? As an answer it might be argued that
there must be some minimum consumer demand by workers to
sustain their lives. However, workers under capitalism cannot create
an effective demand for consumption goods without being employed
at least as part-timers, excepting the very limited amounts of their
savings from the previous prosperous phase. We can see that the limit
to the destruction of capitals must be a priority for the problem to be
solved. Another possible proposal for the problem is to see a decisive
moment in the reversal of the downward vicious circle in the expan-
sion of gold production which must become profitable in the process
Business Cycles and Crises 317
Depression
loose link between demand and supply in the money market prevail
on the credit system during depression. Marx points to the appear-
ance of such a loose credit condition as follows:
As business cycles and crises not only reveal the inner contradiction
in capitalism, but also serve as an actual solution to the contradiction,
they form a concrete mechanism for the law of value to carry itself
through as the law of motion of a capitalist economy. The theoretical
relations between the law of value and the dynamics of business
cycles must be analysed in three co-related aspects; the relations
between first the fluctuation of wages and the value of labour-power,
second the fluctuation of relative prices among commodity products
and their values, and third the fluctuation of the general price level
and the value of the money commodity gold.
First, as Marx formulated, 'taking them as a whole, the general
movements of wages are exclusively regulated by the expansion and
contraction of the industrial reserve army, and this in turn corre-
sponds to the periodic alternations of the industrial cycle' (I, p. 790),
or 'the rate of accumulation is the independent, not the dependent
variable; the rate of wages is the dependent, not the independent
variable' (I, p. 770). However, the latter famous mathematical for-
mulation should not be understood too mechanically. For the move-
ments of the wage-rate, which is basically determined by the process
of capital accumulation and the relative weight of the industrial
reserve army, do react dialectically to the features of accumulation
especially, as we have seen, in the process of causing periodical
326 The Motion of Capitals as a Concrete Mechanism
Prices that fall in the phase of crisis will not fully recover and remain
lower than in the previous period of prosperity, reflecting stagnation
in reproduction and circulation (including circulation no. II). In sum,
commodity prices would rise towards the end of prosperity from their
standard level in mid-prosperity, fall sharply during crisis as a process
of the breaking down of the whole market mechanism, and not fully
recover from the very bottom of the crisis and will remain low or
stagnate during depression before finally being restructured into a
330 The Motion of Capitals as a Concrete Mechanism
possibly be regarded as a part of the logical basis for the long wave of
capital accumulation, which should be properly discussed in a sepa-
rate item.
Although the periodical business cycle is 'of such a nature that the
same circuit must reproduce itself, once the first impulse has been
given' (III, p. 620), it cannot continue to move for ever in the same
circuit like the motion of 'the heavenly bodies' (1, p. 786).
As we noted in the first section of this chapter, capitalism used to
repeat the regular periodical business cycle most typically about
every ten years in the period of liberalism between the 1820s and
1860s. The basic theory of regular business cycles could be abstracted
from the historical experience of Marx's age, assuming a certain
range of size and type of fixed capitals, which were replaceable more
or less concertedly in the leading industries within the period of the
business cycle. It implies that regular business cycles were a historical
phenomenon subject to metamorphoses with the development of
capitalism. A shift in leading sector from the light (especially cotton)
industries to the heavy industries actually induced the metamor-
phoses of business cycles, initiating the stage of imperialism. A full
investigation of the transformation of business cycles, in relation to
the socio-economic structural changes, in the course of the historical
development of capitalism certainly requires upper levels of research
as proposed in the stages theory, or more concrete empirical studies
beyond the basic theory of capitalism. However, let us try in this
section to theorise, at the level of the basic theory the logic of the
metamorphoses of business cycles as far as possible. Then we will
also examine what we can say about long-wave theories and the
nature of long waves, considering the relevance of our basic theory of
capitalism as a frame of reference for more concrete researches. The
historical experiences must also be taken into consideration here, but
they will presently be referred to just as illustrations of the basic
logic.
Through the process of capital accumulation, which develops its inner
contradiction between the relation of production and the growth of
productive power, in regular business cycles, the growth of the pro-
ductive power of capital eventually results in the uneven development
334 The Motion of Capitals as a Concrete Mechanism
for a long upswing, as in the periods between 1897 and 1913, and
more recently between 1945 and 1973.
We have already come to discuss the long waves, which are
generally assumed to last about fifty years each. The greater cycles
including smaller cycles in them are virtually nothing but long waves,
which have become a popular topic again among economists, and not
confined to Marxians, in the process of the current great depression.
It must be noted, however, that long waves have gained actual
significance through the metamorphoses of the business cycle as we
have seen. This is a reason why the long wave theories could only
begin to be explored, initially among Marxians like Parvus and K.
Kautsky, 31 since about the turn of the last century. It would be
dogmatic and improper not to recognise the importance of the
metamorphoses of business cycles and the resulting long waves, by
adhering to the idea of a continuation of regular periodical business
cycles and crises as a way of application of Marx's crisis theory. 32
Also it would be improper to treat long waves as if they were entirely
parallel with, even if not replacing, regular business cycles in the
basic theory of capitalism.
Nevertheless, in attempting to formulate a theory of long waves in
one way or the other, major theorists in this area likeN. D. Kondra-
tieff, J. A. Schumpeter and recently E. Mandel among others are all
apt to believe that long waves have always existed in parallel with
regular periodical business cycles from the very beginning of indus-
trial capitalism. Can we really believe in the existence of a long
down-swing in the quarter-century until 1847 which is comparable
with later great depressions? That was a distinct period when British
capitalism could develop the central cotton industry quite rapidly on
the achievements of the preceding Industrial Revolution. Even
though the effects of a rise in prices due to the discovery of the
Californian gold mines and the defeat of radical social movements,
combined with some aggregate statistical data, may well be referred
to as distinctions between the two quarter-centuries before and after
1847, historically it must be much more important to see that British
capitalism with its central cotton industry was continuously develop-
ing as 'the workshop of the world', promoting a consistent period of
liberalism in these two quarter-centuries. 33 At this stage of liberalism
the inner contradiction of capitalism was clearly revealed in the
repetition of periodical crises in regular business cycles, as Marx
intended to show in the basic theory, and not yet in the great
depression as with the downswing of long waves. Over-generalisation
Business Cycles and Crises 339
343
344 Socialism - an Addendum
Marx's creation of the theory of the forms of value, which was totally
absent in the classical school, was a decisive innovation for the
On Socialism 355
omy for a certain period of time including a severe war period. The
system, however, has become ineffecient in satisfying the varying and
sophisticated needs of members of a society as consumers, there
being a chronic shortage of sophisticated durable consumers' goods,
while the quality of products are often unreliable. The enterprises or
firms tend, bureaucratically, to dislike radical changes in norms, the
sorts of products, or the methods of production, concentrating just
quantitatively to keep up the norms. The system has failed to activate
the workers' own subjective co-operation and efforts in the regular
work places. The second economy, through black or grey markets,
has increased its role in offering and obtaining various goods and
services, thus much obstructing the efficiency of the regular economy.
The cumulative effects of these factors, besides the unfavourable
effects of the economic depression in the external capitalist countries,
are probably the basis of 'the abrasion' of the soviet type of economy
which has become conspicuous since the 1970s. 10
In order to overcome these difficulties in the centralised planned
economy, another function of the price-form as a flexible market
mechanism has repeatedly been proposed as a possible solution.
Although distribution of the basic means of consumption should be
planned and performed outside of market fluctuations in socialism,
the prices of some kinds of consumer goods in short supply, which
must be personally selected outside of the goods given in common
level of subsistence, can flexibly be elevated as in a sort of voting
system where money serves as a more efficient and fairer way of
distribution, in so far as money incomes among members of society
are carefully equalised. The raised prices would stimulate the produc-
tion processes of those goods and the series of means of production
for them, by distributing some portions of increased monetary re-
venue or 'profit' even after increased 'taxes' among the members of
the enterprises in those processes. Also from the view of reducing the
bureaucratic state centralised control, the flexible price-form would
be utilised as an alternative soft economic system to distribute and
transfer various goods and services with the necessary information
about them, among relatively independent communal enterprises
and regions under workers self-control. Just as the forms of a com-
modity economy sprang up outside of the social labour process as the
economic form of the inter-communal and interregional exchange of
goods, indifferent of the particularity of the internal mode of produc-
tion of the societies, the price-form might be utilisable for the time
being in the process of constructing a socialist economy, even after
360 Socialism - an Addendum
order, and lacked the concept of the labour process as such as well as
the theory of the forms of value. Marx poses us a problem in his
theory of the labour process as to what the exclusive characteristic of
human labour is when differentiated from 'the first instinctive forms
of labour which remain on the animal level' (I, p. 284). As Marx
points out, the basis of characteristically human labour is that it has a
conscious purpose and will steering the exertion of the working
organs so as to cause appropriate changes in external materials as a
part of metabolism with nature. This characteristic is shown first of all
in the aspect of concrete useful labour as 'purposeful activity aimed at
the production of use-values' (I, p. 290).
However, as we have argued in Chapter 5, Section 5.1, the human
ability to work in each individual is not destined for each fixed form
of useful labour. On the contrary, it can be expended in various
forms of useful labour according to the differing purposes aimed at,
which can themselves be flexibly altered and widened in scope of
coverage on the grounds of human intellectual ability. In this qualifi-
cation human labour appears not merely as concrete useful labour,
but also simultaneously as abstract human labour being quantita-
tively comparable simply by the physical time of duration. Marx did
not define abstract human labour in his analysis of the labour process,
since he reduced commodity value to the crystallisation of abstract
human labour at the very beginning of Capital, contrasting it with
trans-historical use-values made by concrete useful labour. Rubin
and similar value theorists in the Rubin School have thereupon
deduced that abstract human labour is a result of commensuration
through commodity exchange in a market, or that abstruct human
labour cannot exist apart from a commodity economy. 14 This inter-
pretation is not only inconsistent with Marx's view (for instance
in the section on 'The Fetishism of the Commodity and Its Secret')
that the appropriate distribution of labour-time to various necessary
types of useful labour must be performed commonly in any societies,
but also neglects the theoretical determinableness of the amount of
abstract human labour-time embodied in each product upon the basis
of technological conditions of production processes in a society,
independently of the estimation by the market.
Rejection of the concept of abstract human labour outside of a
commodity economic order would have three possible implications
for socialism. First, reproduction and distribution in a socialist econ-
omy may be conceived just in physical terms, counting various
heterogeneous use-values and useful labour as such, without any
364 Socialism - an Addendum
with incentive wages need not be fixed, but can be flexibly altered in
the process of changes of technologies and preferences of the people.
The social educational and training system should be freely open to
all members of society on equal footing, if with some competition,
and should not function to consolidate a privileged social class or
stratum which has an easier access to higher education on an indivi-
dual family basis. At the same time it should continuously raise the
general human ability to work more freely in wider range of fields,
developing further more the common individual capacity of being
able to perform abstract human labour in various concrete forms.
376
Notes 377
16. The quotation from p. 482 of vol. III. is not literal. The English trans-
lation in the Moscow, and Lawrence & Wishart edition lacks the import-
ant nuance of 'the further' analysis in the German original here.
17. R. Wilbrandt, Karl Marx (Leipzig and Berlin: B. G. Teubner, 4. Aufi.
1920) s. 97. .
18. K. Kuruma ['For Confirmation of Marx's Theory of Crisis' (1930) in his
Studies in the Crisis Theory] (Tokyo: Otsuki-Shoten, 1965).
19. V. S. Vygodski, The Story of a Great Discovery, translated by C. S. V.
Salt (1973) p. 118. An editorial note to the vol. 23 (Das Kapital, vall) of
Marx-Engels Werke (Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1962) s. 844. The editor's
preface to Theories of Surplus Value, part 1, ibid. p. 16. See also A.M.
Kogan, [The Plan of the Critique of Political Economy and 'Capital'],
translated from Russian by Y. Nakano (Tokyo: Otsuki-Shoten, 1979).
20. H. Grossmann, 'Die Anderung des urspriinglishen Aufbauplans des
Marxschen "Kapital" und ihre Ursachen', Archiv fur die Geschichte des
Sozialismus und der Arbeiterbewegung, XIV- 2 (1929) 305 ff.
21. K. Tribe, 'Remarks on the theoretical significance of Marx's Grundisse',
Economy and Society (May 1974) highly appreciates Grossmann's argu-
ment on this point in a survey of the debates on the plan problem in the
appx I, while it does not refer to weaknesses in Grossmann's standpoint.
22. F. Behrens, Zur Methode der politischen Okonomie (Berlin: Akademie-
Verlag, 1952) s. 31-48.
23. R. Rosdolsky, The Making of Marx's 'Capital', translated by P. Burgess
(London: Pluto Press, 1977) p. 54.
24. Ibid. p. 56.
25. M. ltoh, book review: 'The Making of Marx's Capital, Science and
Society, XLII-3 (Fall 1979) p. 362.
26. K. Uno, [The Theory of Crisis], (Tokyo: lwanami-Shoten, 1953.), appx 1.
27. Cf. K. Uno, Principles of Political Economy (Brighton: Harvester Press;
Atlantic Highlands, N.J. Humanities Press, 1980) pp. xxi-xxiii. M. ltoh,
Value and Crisis (London: Pluto Press; New York: Monthly Review
Press, 1980) pp. 39-42.
28. K. Uno's methodology is presented in more detail with favourable
assessments from different angles in T. Sekine, 'Uno-Riron: a Japanese
Contribution to Marxian Political Economy', Journal of Economic
Literature, 13-3 (September 1975); R. Albritton, A Japanese Recon-
struction of Marxist Theory (London: Macmillan, 1986), and M. ltoh,
Value and Crisis, ch. 1.
29. e.g. K. Suzuki ed., [Principles of Political Economy], 2 vols (Tokyo:
University of Tokyo Press, 1960, 1962), H. Iwata, [World Capitalism]
(Tokyo: Mirai-Sha, 1964).
30. E. Bernstein, Die Voraussetzungen des Sozialismus und die Aufgabe der
Sozialdemokratie (Stuttgart: Dietz, 1899).
31. K. Kautsky, Bernstein und das Sozialdemokratische Programm
(Stuttgart: Dietz, 1899).
32. K. Kautsky, Die Agrarfrage (Hannover: J. H. W. Dietz, 1899).
33. V. I. Lenin, 'The Proletarian Revolution and a Renegade Kautsky'
(1918), in vol. 28 of The Collected Works of Lenin, vol. 28, (Moscow:
Foreign Languages Publishing House, 1965).
382 Notes
tion in Capital is probably to be found in the fact that the third section of
the first chapter was formulated and inserted in its place later, from the
second German edition (1872), leaving the contents of the second
chapter unaltered.
Uno avoided the separation of views and the overlapping of the
subject of analysis in these places of Capital, by introducing the role of
possessors of commodities as well as the essential contents of the second
chapter into the theory of value-form. I believe that Uno's revision here
is proper to make the theory of value-form easier and clearcut. The
possessors of commodities, however, must be conceived here not as
human beings in general, but as specifically those regulated by commodi-
ties which they own. Their will and behaviour are not free from com-
modities. Here is a basic distinction between the marginal utility theory
of value which pretends to rest on the general psychological preference
in human beings and the Marxian position.
6. G. Pilling, Marx's Capital (London, Boston and Henley: Routledge &
Kegan Paul, 1980) is one of the recent Western works which emphasises
the importance of Marx's theory of the value-form. Its explanation,
however, that the elementary value-form (20 yards of linen = 1 coat) is
'the exchange of two commodities' (p. 147) as well as its emphasis of
Marx's analyses of the labour-substance through the value-form, does
not seem to sharpen either Marx's originality or his essential points in the
theory of value-form, although it may not be inappropriate as an inter-
pretation of the third section in the opening chapter of Capital. U.
Krause, Money and Abstract Labour, translated by P.Burgess (London:
NLB and Verso, 1982) is another conspicuous work underlining Marx's
theory of the value-form. In ch. 2 of this book, Krause discusses the
value-form without reference to labour just like Japanese Uno School.
However, he also treats the value-form as the exchange relation, unlike
us, and concentrates rather on the quantitative problem to solve the
possible inconsistency in the exchange ratios between commodities with-
out money.
7. Though Marx titles this second value-form 'the total or expanded form of
value', the expansion of the equivalent commodities can not really be so
'total' as to embrace all kinds of commodities from the view of the
possessor(s) of linen in the relative form of value.
8. This situation is formulated by Marx at the beginning of 'Form IV' in the
first chapter of the first edition of Capital (K. Marx, Value: Studies by
Karl Marx, translated and edited by A. Gragstedt, London: New Park
Publication, 1976, pp. 33-4). The 'Form IV' is there placed after the
general form of value in the 'Form III' and the form is further reversed to
turn every commodity into the universal equivalent-form, which is actu-
ally and theoretially impossible in making every commodity directly
exchangeable with others. Therefore, this form is omitted from the
appendix on the form of value to the first edition of Capital and there-
after. Marx's idea contained in the 'Form IV', however, can be utilised in
the transformation from the second to the third value-form of commodi-
ties.
9. Marx later refers to the substitutability of gold (hard) money as the
Notes 385
17. Marx, Grundrisse, op. cit. p. 708. Along with such development, the
burden of domestic labour which has been so much on the shoulders of
women in class societies, especially in capitalism, must be reduced and
shared with men. The extension of communal social life and its facilities
will be helpful for it, and in economic life it will further reduce the
relative role of the portion of private means of consumption and the
labour-time embodied in them. Then, the necessary labour-time embodied
in the necessary means of subsistence essentially comprises two different
portions. The portion to be consumed in a communal form in particular
will be closely related and mutually supplementary to the social function
of surplus-labour, though theoretically those are still distinct.
18. Within these 54 hours, 6 hours of necessary labour-time must be a more
flexible portion than the other even on the basis of fixed conditions of
production, so far as the necessary means of subsistence include histori-
cal and social elements independent of technological conditions of pro-
duction.
19. A contrary procedure is assumed in a traditional Marxian interpretation
of values and prices of production, presented in a historical-logical
sequence, following the development from a precapitalist commodity
economy to a capitalist. Besides the fact that there are certain weaknes-
ses in this type of theory (as we have already examined in Chapter 4,
Section 4.1) it is also inappropriate as an interpretation of the theoretical
system in Capital. This is because the contents of capitalist production
are analysed by means of the theory of value in Capital, and not directly
using the theory of prices of production. Our critique of this type of value
theory from the view of the Uno School however, does not imply a
negation of the relevancy of the law of value in a precapitalist commodity
economy. D. Gleicher, 'A Historical Approach to the Question of
Abstract Labour', op. cit. seems to misunderstand this point. although
its position is quite close to ours.
20. P. Samuelson, 'Wages and Interest: A Modern Discussion of Marxian
Economic Models', American Economic Review, XLVII (Dec 1957) pp.
891-2. 'Understanding the Marxian Notion of Exploitation', Journal of
Economic Literature, 9-2 (June 1972) p. 415. M. Morishima, Marx's
Economics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973) ch. 7.
21. This position is first presented briefly in chapter 2 of M. Itoh, Value and
Crisis (London: Pluto Press; New York: Monthly Review Press, 1980).
Even when standard prices as the form of value are assumed to be in
direct proportion to the labour-substance of commodities, according to
the conventional notion of the law of value in the analyses of the
capitalist process of production prior to the theory of prices of produc-
tion, the possibility and the general scope of deviation of prices from
such a direct proportionality had better be noted. The hypothetical
character of, say, the third position above would be clarified and
theoretically supplemented by noting these points as being examined
below.
22. Cf. Braverman, op. cit. ch. 13, 'The Universal Market', I. Illich, Shadow
Work (London: Marion Boyars, 1981).
23. Although excessive overwork in domestic labour of housewives is
390 Notes
1. P. M. Sweezy ed., Karl Marx and the Close of his System by Eugen
von Bohm-Bawerk and Bohm-Bawerk's Criticism of Marx by Rudolf
Hilferding (New York: A.M. Kelly, 1949) p. 86.
2. E. Bernstein, 'Zur Theorie des Arbeitswerts', Die Neue Zeit, XVIII
(1899-1900) part 1.
3. Sweezy ed., op. cit. pp. 136-46.
4. N. Okishio, 'A Mathematical Note on Marxian Theories', Weltwirt-
schaftliches Archiv, Heft 2 (1963).
5. B. Rowthorn, Capitalism, Conflict & Inflation (London: Lawrence &
Wishart, 1980) ch. 8. In his more recent 'Notes on Skilled Labour'
(rnimeo, 1985) Rowthorn has deepened his theoretical view of this
problem, and basically come closer to my position in this section.
Therefore, my treatment and criticisms of his argument here cannot be
applicable to his recent view, although his previous argument would
remain as a typical case for the technological approach to this issue.
Notes 391
same level of real wages to give the same quantity of wheat per hour of
labour, the nominal wages as the form of labour-power are to be halved
as for the portion of wheat. The substance of value of labour-power
obtainable through its form of value, however, is not reduced so much,
since 'the real production price' would decline from 24 sh. a quarter to
just 20 sh. a quarter (180 sh I 9 qrs.). Thus, the quantitative changes in
this case can be ordered from smaller to larger upon the same level of
real wages; the substance of value of labour-power, nominal wages as the
form of value of labour-power, and the amount of differential rent in its
substance and form.
32. However, Uno did not thoroughly clarify the substantial source of
differential rent, and remained just to quote Marx's notion of 'false social
value' which was paid by society considered as a consumer (Uno,
Principles of Political Economy, op. cit. p. 98, p. 104). He distinguished
extra profit as 'false social value' to be converted into differential rent
from extra surplus-value obtained in the process of improvement in
productive methods, on the ground that the latter, unlike the former,
could be recognised as the cost of innovation common to all societies as a
part of general economic rule. Although this distinction is suggestive and
relevant to a clarification of different social functions and characters of
two sorts of extra profit, it would not establish that either of them has
some special source outside of the total surplus-labour as the substance
of social surplus-value. My position is thus different from Uno's on this
point.
33. Uno also followed Marx here in defining absolute rent within a gap
between the value and the price of production of agricultural product
(ibid. p. 102). It coincides with Uno's treatment of the transformation
problem mostly following Marx. It was contribution of T. Ouchi and
H. Hidaka (in op. cit.) among Uno theorists that initiated the theoretical
critique and solution of the problem here left over since Marx.
100Y lOOY
P=
d p
York and London: Monthly Review Press, 1972), asserted the under-
consumptionist variant of crisis theory as an orthodox Marxian position.
In these classical arguments initiated by Tugan-Baranowsky, Marx's
theory of the reproduction schemes was much utilised in order to show
the difficulties in maintaining the balance between various items in the
schemes, although essentially it was an unsuitable theory for proving the
logical inevitability, and not merely the possibility, of periodical crises,
as we saw in Chapter 6, Section 6.3. More recently, P. Sweezy, The
Theory of Capitalist Development (1942, New York: Monthly Review
Press, 1956), ch. 10, and his other writings follow the orthodox Marxian
position of the under-consumptionist type.
6. N. Okishio, [The Theory of Accumulation] (Tokyo: Chikuma-Shobo,
1976) for instance, presents a sort of sophisticated type of under-
consumptionism in a model of the cumulative process of disequilibrium
between the effective demand of wage-workers and the increasing pro-
ductive power of society. In his model, incessant shortage of effective
demand due to restricted real wages can be balanced more than suf-
ficiently by investment demand so as to cause a rise in commodity prices
or inflation in the phase of prosperity. With this rise in prices, real wages
must fall more and more so that reproduction of labour-power becomes
impossible to maintain. A reversal of such a process of accumulation
through crises is necessary for capitalism to survive as a social system.
Though Okishio sees the operation of the law of value in the reversal of
the cumulative upward and downward process of disequilibrium in turn,
he tends to negate the working of the law of value in readjusting the
disequilibrium between demand and supply with relative stability in the
process of prosperity. It is also difficult for me to agree with his recogni-
tion that real wages must fall in the actual process of prosperity when in
fact expanding employment creates a shortage of labour-power.
7. H. Grossmann, Das Akkumulations und Zusammenbrucksgesetz des
kapitalistischen Systems (Leipzig: Hirschfeld, 1929), assumes an increase
of variable capital of 5 per cent a year and of constant capital of 10 per
cent with a constant rate of surplus-value of 100 per cent in order to show
the breakdown of a capitalist system due to the disappearance of the
portion of surplus-value for consumption by capitalists. E. Preiser, 'Das
Wesen der Marxschen Krisentheorie', in Festschrift fiir Franz Oppen-
heimer - Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft (Frankfurt: Frankfurter Societats-
Druckerei, 1924) assumes a fall in the rate of surplus-value, as in the
labour-power-shortage theory, in his example of the sudden decline of
the rate of profit. M. Dobb, Political Economy and Capitalism (London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1937) ch. 4, and E. Mandel, Late Capitalism,
translated by J. De Bres (London: New Left Books, 1975) combines this
variant of crisis theory with varying circumstances in a multicausal
approach. D. Yaffe, 'The Marxian Theory of Crisis, Capital and the
State', in Bulletin of the Conference of Socialist Economists' (Winter
1972), P. Bullock and D. Yaffe, 'Inflation, the Crisis, and the Postwar
Boom', in Revolutionary Communist, no. 3/4 (Nov 1975) stand purely
upon the law of tendential fall of profit rate as the causal basis for crisis.
A. Shaikh, 'An Introduction to the History of Crisis Theories', in URPE
408 Notes
exchange in London, which used to form the peak of the periodical crises
in England. The same was also true for the crisis in 1873, and in 1890.
And Engels wrote in a note to the third volume of Capital that 'the acute
form of the periodic process with its former ten-year cycle seems to have
given way to a more chronic and drawn-out alternation, affecting the
various industrial countries at different times, between a relatively short
and weak improvement in trade and a relatively long and indecisive
depression' (III, p. 620). Although various factors, such as the expansion
of the means of transportation and communication, the formation of
competing industrial countries, as well as cartels and trusts, or the
growing investment of surplus European capitals in all parts of the world,
are suggested by Engels as the causes of such metamorphoses of business
cycles, a fundamental moment would be in the difficulty of coping with
excessive large-scale fixed capital. In this respect R. Hilferding's treat-
ment of the problem in ch. 20 of Finance Capital is neither sufficient and
thorough. Hilferding stresses there that the formation of cartels in
particular mitigates the acuteness of crises while intensifying the diffi-
culties in the non-cartelised industries.
30. A representative work from this viewpoint is P. A. Baran and P. Sweezy,
Monopoly Capital (New York and London: Monthly Review Press,
1966).
31. Parvus (alias A. Helphand), Die Handelskrisen und die Gewerkschaften
(Mi.inchen: M. Ernst, 1901). K. Kautsky, 'Die Wandlungen der Gold-
produktion und der wechselnde Charakter der Teuerung', in Die Neue
Zeit, supplement to no. 16 (Jan 1913).
32. Russian orthodox studies of the theories and the history of business
cycles and crises have not been entirely immune from such a tendency.
See for instance L. A. Mendelison, [The Theory and History of Econ-
omic Crises], translated into Japanese by K. Iida et al., (Tokyo: Otsuki-
Shoten, 4 vols, 1960-1), and I. A. Trakhatenberg, [The Money Crises],
translated into Japanese by A. Oikawea, (Tokyo: Iwasaki-Gakujitsu, 3
vols, 1967-8). Their prestige was effectively weakened by the historical
experience of the sustained long upswing in the post-Second World War
period.
33. The overall index of prices also seems strikingly stable during this period
in comparison with the preceding or the following periods, though a
slight uprise is discernible in the second quarter-century as a result of the
discovery of Californian gold mines, especially taking into account a
generally rising productivity in other commodity products (cf. B. R.
Mitchell, Abstract of British Historical Statistics (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1962, pp. 471-2).
34. N. D. Kondratieff, 'Die Langen Wellen der Konjunktur', in Archiv fur
Sozialwissenschaften und Sozialpolitik, Bd 56 (1926), 'The Long Waves
in Economic Life', in Review of Economic Statistics, 60 (1935).
35. This coincides with a point among Bob Rowthorn's critical comments on
E. Mandel's Late Capitalism. Bob Rowthorn, Capitalism, Conflict and
Inflation (London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1980) pp. 101-2. In general the
existence of abundant cheap loanable capital is neither a sufficient nor an
indispensable precondition for the upturn, though it can serve as a
412 Notes
10 On Socialism
Monthly Review Press, 1981), and Crisis in the World Economy (New
York: Holmes & Meier. 1981), is that the independendent cause(s) of
the economic difficulties inside Soviet types of societies themselves
cannot properly be underlined.
11. For example, L. von Mises, 'Economic Calculation in the Socialist
Commonwealth7 , (1920, in A. Nove and D. M. Nuti, eds, Socialist
Economics, Harmondsworth, Middx: Peguin Books, 1972), typically
asserts that socialism without market pricing lacks a rational measure-
ment of efficiency and therefore cannot be a rational economy. Von
Mises points to the difficulty of reducing the products of skilled labour to
units of simple labour as an important reason. Hence, we also see in this
example how essential is our search for a sounder labour theory of value
in oder to examine and clarify the basis of the argument for socialism.
12. P. Sraffa, Production of Commodities by Means of Commodities
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1960) ch. II.
13. 0. Lange, 'The Computer and the Market' (1967, in A. Nove and D. M.
Nuti, eds, op. cit.), suggested that 'Mathematical programming assisted
by electronic computers becomes the fundamental instrument of long-
term economic planning, as well as of solving dynamic economic prob-
lems of a more limited scope. Here, the electronic computer does not
replace the market. It fulfils a function the market never was able to
perform.' (pp. 404-5). The more recent development of information
technologies seems to widen the possibility of the more flexible appli-
cation of electronic computers as a means for a multi-terminal system of
adjusting economic relations, and useable not merely for long-term
centralised economic planning. The social decision on how to use and
apply newly growing technological possibilities will become quite import-
ant in this respect being related to the desirable socio-economic order
being realised in socialism.
14. I. I. Rubin, Essays on Marx's Theory of Value (1982, translated by M.
Samrdzija and F. Perlman, Detroit: Black & Red, 1972). See note 7 of
Chapter 5 for the recent representative value theorists in the Rubin
School. The theoretical similarity does not necessarily mean that all
these recent theorists I call the Rubin School have studied and depended
upon Rubin's work to form their views. Since their position can be
deducible rather directly from a part of Marx's conception as well as
from a certain type of attempt logically to formulate the relation between
the form and substance of value.
15. Rubin, ibid. pp. 139 ff.
16. If one adheres to a rigorous measurement of the intensity of labour
across different concrete forms and grades of work, a completely objec-
tive way to define the measurement would not be available. In this
regard we have to admit the basic human ability to work in various forms
as a basis for our conception of human labour equally forming the social
substance of economic life, being indifferent to the concrete forms or the
grades of skill, specially in a really socialist society. This reflection on the
basis of the measurability of abstract human labour under socialism,
basically relies upon our understanding of value theory, but it may
Notes 415
417
418 Bibliography
__ (ed.), Karl Marx and the Close of His System by E. von Bohm-Bawerk
and Bohm-Bawerk's Criticism of Marx by R. Hilferding (New York: M.
Kelley, 1966).
__ Post-Revolutionary Society (New York and London: Monthly Review
Press, 1980).
__ 'Marxian Value Theory and Crisis', in I. Steedman et al., The Value
Controversy (London: Verso and NLB, 1981).
TAKUMI, M. [World Capitalism] (Tokyo: Nihonhyoron-Sha, 1980).
THOMPSON, P. The Nature of Work (London: Macmillan, 1983).
THOMPSON, W. An Inquiry into the Principles of the Distribution of Wealth
most Conducive to Human Happiness (1824) (New York: A.M. Kelley,
1963).
TRAKHATENBERG, I. A. [The Money Crises], translated by A. Oikawa,
3 vols (Tokyo: Iwasaki-Gakujitsu, 1967-8).
TRIBE, K. 'Remarks on the Theoretical Significance of Marx's Grundrisse',
Economy and Society (May 1974).
TROTSKY, L. The Revolution Betrayed, translated by M. Eastman (Lon-
don: Faber & Faber, 1937).
__ 'On the Curve of Capitalist Development', Fourth International (May
1941).
TSURU, S. 'On the Reproduction Scheme', in P. Sweezy, The Theory of
Capitalist Development (1942) (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1956).
TUGAN-BARANOWSKY, M. Les Crises Industrielles en Angleterre,
translated by J. Schapiro (Paris: M. Jiard & E. Brieve, 1913).
UNO, K. [The Theory of Crisis] (Tokyo: Iwanami-Shoten, 1953).
__ ['The Law of Value and Socialism'] (1953), in his ['Capital' and
Socialism] (Tokyo: Iwanami-Shoten, 1958).
__ ['Capital' and Socialism] (Tokyo: lwanami-Shoten, 1958).
__ [The Methodology of Political Economy] (Tokyo: University of Tokyo
Press, 1962).
__ [The Fundamental Problems in a Social Science] (Tokyo: Aoki-Shoten,
1966).
__ 'The Tasks of Crisis Theory', in his [Problems in Marxian Economics]
(Tokyo: lwanami-Shoten, 1969).
__ Principles of Political Economy, translated by T. Sekine (Brighton:
Harvester Press; Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1980).
VEBLEN, T. B. The Theory of Leisure Class (New York: The Macmillan
Co., 1899).
--The Theory of Business Enterprise (New York, 1904).
VYGODSKI, V. S. The Story of a Great Discovery, translated by C. S. V.
Salt (Berlin: Verlag die Wirtschaft, 1973).
WAGNER, A. Lehrbuch der Politischen Okonomie (Leipzig: Winter, 1879).
WALRAS, M. E. L. Elements of Pure Economics (1874), translated by W.
Jaffe (London: Allen & Unwin, 1954).
WEBER, M. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism (1904-5),
translated by T. Parsons (London: George Allen & Unwin, 1930).
__ 'Die "Objektivitiit" Sozialwissenschaftlicher und Sozial Politischer
Erkenntnis', Archiv fur Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik XIX (1904).
WEEKS, J. 'The Process of Accumulation and the "Profit Squeeze" Hypo-
thesis', Science and Society, XLII-3 (Fall 1979).
426 Bibliography
427
428 Index