Draft
Draft
The principle of compositionality (henceforth C0) states that “the meaning of a complex
expression is a function of the meanings of its constituents and the way they are
combined.”[1] Seemingly trivial or self-evident at first glance, the principle lies at the
heart of semantics-syntax interface. More than just a working hypothesis or background
assumption, C0 acts almost as methodological principle in fields like the cognitive
sciences or the philosophy of language.
Given the vast territory C0 controls, this essay would begin by demarcating a small
portion that would be of relevance to us (in accordance with Szabó’s proposals1). After a
brief discussion of definitional challenges and common misinterpretations, we would test
the arguments made in its favour (mainly generativity) and also review the obstacles it
currently faces. Finally, a summary is presented linking the implications of its adoption on
semantic theory and Universal Grammar at large.
1 Zoltán Gendler Szabó, The Case for Compositionality: in The Oxford Handbook of Compositionality
(2012) See also, https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2017/entries/compositionality (Szabó, 2017)
2“if the syntax is sufficiently unconstrained and the meanings sufficiently rich, there seems no doubt that
natural languages can be described compositionally. Challenges to the principle generally involve either
explicit or implicit arguments to the effect that it conflicts with other well-motivated constraints on syntax
and/or on the mapping from syntax to meaning” (ibid p.65)
Another issue the author raises is about determination of meaning. That is if C0 suggests
that there exists only a unique way of mapping meaning to utterances. Szabó provides the
examples of two identical languages that differ only in the meaning of a single sentence S
(that in fact has the same surface structure). His hint seems to be at the possible plurality
of intensional systems even with extensional equivalence3. A strong determinist reading
of C0 would be incompatible with such an occurrence. [4]
Through [2], [3], [4] Szabó seems to support a strong, individualistic, rule-by-rule reading
of the principle of compositionality (henceforth Cs):
Multiple readings can be made (singular vs several ambassadors) despite the presence of
identical components and ordering. Yet, one sees how varying narrow interpretations of
[1] including C0 would survive such challenges by positing hidden logical forms,
transformations, or different lexical entries.
Therefore, the principle still remains extremely vague. One can tackle events like deixis
or indexicals by claiming that context-dependent variables are encoded within the
lexicon. Conversational implicatures can also be dealt with as they retain the same
locutionary force and only perlocutionary effects change i.e. the meaning remains intact
but speaker’s intelligence lets him deduce our intentions (sarcasm, request etc.) Even
idioms can be accommodated as long as an independent characterising criteria can be
figured out.
3 Two functions f(x) and f’(x) might have similar extensions {2,4,6,8,10} except for one input (say 0). A
strong reading of C0 necessitates direct correspondance between syntax and semantics and hence rules
out such a possibility: it predicts a unique universal function for sentences with similarly ordered
constituents.
Extra pointers to discuss:
––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––
Why compositionality?
Jeroen Groenendijk & Martin Stokhof∗
––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––
https://adele.princeton.edu/wp-content/uploads/sites/
277/2015/01/13Compositionality-Handbook.pdf
FOR ROUTLEDGE SEMANTICS HANDBOOK, NICK RIEMER (ED.) Compositionality Adele
E. Goldberg
––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––––