J2018 - The Subject Is Freedom

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 22

The Subject Is Freedom

Arindam Chakrabarti

Philosophy East and West, Volume 68, Number 1, January 2018, pp. 277-297
(Review)

Published by University of Hawai'i Press


DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/pew.2018.0018

For additional information about this article


https://muse.jhu.edu/article/682210

Access provided by National Taiwan University (12 Apr 2018 08:17 GMT)
FEATURE REVIEW

The Subject Is Freedom

Arindam Chakrabarti
Philosophy Department, University of Hawai‘i
[email protected]

Free Will, Agency, and Selfhood in Indian Philosophy. Edited by Matthew R. Dasti
and Edwin F. Bryant. New York: Oxford University Press, 2014. isbn 978-0-19-
992275-8.

1. Does the Question of “Free-Will” Arise in Indian Philosophy?

As the first comprehensive collection of essays in English on the perennial problem


of free will and agency in Indian philosophies, Free Will, Agency, and Selfhood in
Indian Philosophy, edited by Matthew R. Dasti and Edwin F. Bryant, richly deserves
to be read widely and critically by philosophers, Asianists, and global historians of
ideas. It is an excellent endeavor in comparative philosophy. So, like every exercise
in comparative philosophy, it must face a frustrating double bind. Let me start this
review essay by illustrating this double bind with an anecdote. Many years back, in
a large freshmen’s Introduction to Logic class at Montana State University, as a
­zealous young visiting professor from India, I was asked to give a single lecture on
Indian logic. On the first day, I gave a super-abbreviated accessible account of the
original Nyāya /Buddhist argument-paradigm and the features of a good and bad
­argument introducing a handful of peculiarly Indian technical terms for the subject
of the inference, the target property to be inferred, the reason property, and the
ways of establishing or questioning the universal concomitance between the reason
and the target property. The senior American professor who was co-teaching the
­Elementary Logic course with me commented that this was fascinating but it did not
sound like “Logic” as we understand it in the West. He requested that I reformulate
the basic insights in recognizably Western logical terms and give a second lecture.
When I did that, on another occasion, his comment was “But this logic we already
have in the West, between Aristotle and Frege-Russell; what is so Indian or different
about it?”
This double bind would always plague comparative philosophers as long as they
use English (or any Western language) to make philosophy originally written in San-
skrit, Pali, Tibetan, or Chinese available to a Western or even Asian philosophical
audience (and increasingly now, philosophy teachers and students in Asia speak and
understand nothing but a Western idiom of philosophy). Should you emphasize the
uncommon (“exotic”) issues and techniques that are foreign to Western thinking, you

Philosophy East & West  Volume 68, Number 1 January 2018 277–297 277
© 2018 by University of Hawai‘i Press
would have a hard time convincing your audience that it is really “philosophy” (e.g.,
the discussion at the heart of Mīmāṃsā, concerning the exact meaning of a verb-­
ending in an imperative sentence that enjoins an action-to-be-done to its compre-
hending hearer, which chapter 6 by Elisa Freschi so clearly lays out in the volume
under review). Should you emphasize, instead, the common issues that are also
known to and focused on in Western philosophy, you will either be suspected of
superimposing a Western conceptual scheme on Classical Indian philosophy or,
worse, you will be ignored as presenting a boring old hat. It is simply exhilarating to
see how several essays in the volume under discussion here manage to escape both
horns of this comparativist’s dilemma while discussing one of the most hackneyed
topics of traditional and contemporary Western philosophy: Given that our actions,
including our acts of willing and choosing are events happening according to natural
causal laws, how can they be free?
The problem of free will and agency as it is discussed, even if tangentially, in
Sāṃkhya, Buddhist, Nyāya, Jain, Kashmir Shaiva, Mīmāṃsā, Advaita, Viśiṣṭādvaita,
and Dvaita Vedānta texts is recognizable to be that problem by a Western lens as you
go through this book, and yet the discourse around the problem, surely but unnotice-
ably, changes so radically that not only new solutions but new problem terrains are
created. Effortlessly, comparative philosophy turns creative. For all its Indological and
philological context-setting, the reader takes home from this anthology a fresh set of
insights and puzzlements that are simply philosophical without any prefix: “West-
ern” or “Indian,” “classical” or “modern,” or even “comparative.” Good comparative
philosophy should be just that: good philosophy. With this book, Indian comparative
philosophy gets closer to this bright future of losing the parochial prefix.

2. Were Asian Philosophers Unaware of the Free Will Problem?

The Mahābhārata claims about itself that “whatever is here is elsewhere, and what is
not here is not anywhere in the world.” Some of us working in the confluence be-
tween Indian and Western philosophies would like to believe, analogously, that any
perennial philosophical issue that is discussed elsewhere must have been discussed,
in some form or other, in Indian philosophy as well. If a philosophical problem is
deep and non-phony and arises from the human condition, it must have been dis-
cussed somewhere in the vast diachronic debating arena that is Classical Indian phi­
losophy. Now, no one can deny that whether human beings are free to will and act
as they choose, given the sway of causality over their psychophysical lives, is a deep
and genuine philosophical issue. The same issue has been put poignantly and pow-
erfully by Karl Potter negatively as follows: “as long as a person is at the mercy of
forces external to himself, so long will he be subject to frustration, despair and un-
happiness.”1 How could it be possible that such a fundamental existential problem
escaped the attention of the contemplative and argumentative Indians? Yet, it was
and is thought generally even by eminent scholars of Indian philosophy (such as J. N.
Mohanty and Jay Garfield) that it is a typically Western (perhaps Judeo-Christian)
problem about which Indian philosophers never much bothered to debate or write.

278 Philosophy East & West


If we accept this alleged “lack of concern,” that is, the putative fact that the free
will debate is absent from the list of topics discussed by Indian philosophers, we have
to tweak the other two assumptions. Either we diagnose, in a late Wittgensteinian
way, why the Free Will question is a pseudo-problem, so that our generalization is
well protected: all genuine problems of Western philosophy were discussed by the
Indian philosophers. Or we question the audacious over-generalization itself (that all
real philosophical problems are discussed in Indian philosophy). Just as some very
central philosophical issues — for example, “Does the imperative verb-ending in a
command sentence mean the intention of the speaker or the to-be-done-ness of the
action meant by the verb?” — are not discussed majorly in any nook of Western Phi-
losophy, there are many genuine philosophical issues that escaped the attention
of Indian philosophers. Whether, for example, the same objects exist in different
possible worlds or whether the identity of individuals is bound and confined to the
particular possible world they exist in cannot arise in Indian philosophy because the
model theory for modal logic is not formulated in any textual tradition of Indian phi-
losophy, because of historical cultural contingencies of the social-religious-­linguistic
context in which they thought, taught, and wrote.
The corresponding conundrum with respect to Classical Chinese Philosophy and
its two usual “solutions” has been succinctly reconstructed by Kai Marchal and
Christian Wenzel: “Surprisingly, the problem [of free will] seems to be absent in
­Chinese thought. Did the Chinese miss something or has the West been chasing
an ­illusion?”2 “One and many, free will and determinism, reality and appearance,
mind and body, knowledge and opinion, good and evil — fundamental metaphysi-
cal problems . . . were not interesting or important in shaping the classical Chinese
philosophic tradition,” wrote Roger Ames.3 Even twenty years later, after develop-
ing the ethics of familial and social roles, Ames seems to endorse the second solu-
tion: “the West has been chasing an illusion,” namely that the Free Will problem
is big only for those Western thinkers whose metaphysics is dualistic and ethics
individualistic.
But a third alternative position seems to have been taken by Marchal and
Wenzel. However relationally and non-substantially human personhood may be
­understood in Confucianism and Daoism, Marchal and Wenzel go on to show that,
at different levels, agency and voluntary actions for which persons can be blamed or
praised are theorized and problematized in many distinct ways in the long and varied
Chinese philosophical traditions. So, neither is “the problem of agency and will”
spurious, nor did the Chinese miss it. The third and middle way is to search for a
culturally different sensitivity to the problem of free will in the 2,500-year-old Chi-
nese corpus and find out how perhaps a related but different set of issues around
choice, will, agency, and moral accountability was discussed by Confucius, Men-
cius, Xunzi, Wang Ming, and others. Marchal and Wenzel start by locating in Classi-
cal Chinese four or five words for a faculty to make choices, or ways of making
choices, and factors that influence or even control one’s life, namely: (1) xin 心
(heart, heart-mind), (2) xing 性 (human nature, characteristic tendencies, inborn ca­
pacity), (3) ming 命 (life span, fate, command, allotment, endowment), (4) ziran 自然

Arindam Chakrabarti 279


(so of itself, n
­ ature, spontaneity), and another term, zhi 志, which has often been
translated as “will.”
But a more precise translation is “direction [of the heart-mind].” One does not
have to be an expert in Classical Chinese or Chinese philosophy to notice how the
meanings of these five terms both capture the heart of the question “What makes
humans initiate actions?” and also redefine the problem-space beyond any perceived
conflict between natural events and human volition, or between fate and freedom.
Without any trace or need of a theodicy-type reason to credit human will with free-
dom (so that God is not blamed for human atrocities), Xunzi sounds almost like an
indeterminist when he remarks:

The heart is the lord of the body and the master of one’s spirit and intelligence. It issues
orders, but it takes orders from nothing: it restrains itself, it employs itself; it lets itself go,
it takes itself in hand; it makes itself proceed, it makes itself stop. Thus, the mouth can be
compelled either to be silent or to speak, . . . but the heart cannot be compelled to change
its thoughts.4

But, of course, such a view of human action, its naturalistic causes, and its spon-
taneity is much more subtle than compatibilism or absolute free-will-ism. For in-
stance, both letting go and self-restraining, in this passage, are treated as equally
spontaneous acts of the heart-mind. The goal of this third wave of comparative phi-
losophy should be, as Rosemont and Ames5 and Chakrabarti and Weber6 suggest,
to take uniquely Chinese, uniquely Indian, uniquely Japanese concepts such as the
concept of an exemplary sage, of the heart-mind, of desireless action, of agency of
surrendering agency, of collective ignorance, et cetera, and underscore their absence
in classical and modern Western philosophy.
In his book on a very different problem of evil in Chinese philosophy, Franklin
Perkins quotes an intriguing passage from Zhuangzi about the Promethean spirit of
human beings: “Thus, they (human beings) rebel against the illuminating brightness
of the sun and moon above, scorch the refined essence of the mountains and rivers
below, and overturn the orderly progression of the four seasons in between. . . .
Deep, indeed, is the disorder brought to the world by the love of knowing!”7 While
this is clearly about human choice and freedom, Perkins perceptively comments:
“this is explained not in terms of free will but through a blend of desire and knowl­
edge.”8 Is love of knowing, then, a bad thing, to be curbed? Tracing ecological de-
structiveness to the unbridled human desire for knowledge (haozhi 好知), Perkins
gives a radically new spin to the problem of free will that would be immensely rele-
vant to the contemporary tension between technology-driven science and environ-
mental ethics.9
In Sanskrit also, we have terms like svātantrya that stand for freedom, and terms
like kratu or kṛti that stand for will. And of course, for “freedom from” (bondage,
­ignorance, suffering) Sanskrit has words, by now familiar to the West, such as mokṣa,
mukti, and apavarga. So, philologically we know where to look if we have to search
for discussions of the free will, agency, or freedom issue. But what we shall find when
we search carefully may well be something very different from the Western or mod-

280 Philosophy East & West


ern counterparts. If I am allowed a suggestive play on words, just as a free action
changes the subject (agent), a comparative philosophy of freedom should also change
the subject.
Matthew Dasti and Edwin Bryant, with the help of an august array of first-rate
scholar-thinkers, have neither dismissed the Western formulations of the free will
­issue as unheard-of or marginal in Indian philosophical thinking nor deemed the
­issue itself to be phony or parochial. They have taken the third and middle way of
solving this strategic problem for comparative philosophers. They have shown that it
is not a fact that the apparent conflict between natural causation and conscious hu-
man will was never the focus of attention of the classical Indian philosophers. It often
was. The issue of the self’s agency, threatened on the one hand by God’s omnipo-
tence and omniscience, some mysterious force of “destiny,” and, on the other hand,
by the ubiquitous sway of naturalistic and karmic causality, was very much at the
center of several debates, just like the issue of external-world-realism versus ideal-
ism, realism-about-universals versus nominalism, and conceptualism versus non-­
conceptualism about perception, et cetera — discussed of course, in the distinctive
Indian religious and secular argumentative style. This seems to be the editorial stance.
But not all contributors agree.

3. Garfield’s Dismissal of the Free Will Issue as “The Question Does not Arise”

For example, Jay Garfield, one of the most provocative contributors to this volume,
in his brilliant chapter “Just Another Word for Nothing Left to Lose,” repeatedly as-
serts that the Free Will Problem — “How can human beings be held responsible for
their good and bad actions if they are just cogs in the inexorable causal machine
of nature?” — is an artifact of Augustinian Christianity. With some measure of vehe-
mence, Garfield argues that Western philosophy’s preoccupation with the free will
problem can be traced back to the twin presuppositions of choosy autonomous hu-
man agent-selves and of an omniscient God who eternally knows what each of those
selves will ever choose to do. Since Buddhism rejects both of these presuppositions,
the free will question simply does not arise, at least in Buddhist philosophy. And,
of course, the enlightened Nāgārjunian Buddhist is “free” in the minimal sense that
she is free from all clinging to essences, and she has “nothing left to lose.” It was eye-­
opening for me to try to see, as Garfield writes, that “Everything that the post-­
Augustinian libertarian West buys with the gold coin of the freedom of the will, along
with all of the metaphysical problems it raises, are bought by the Mādhyamika much
more cheaply with the paper currency of mere imputation” (chap. 7, p. 182).
But not all forms of the (“Western”) antinomy we discussed above are derived
from the metaphysical assumption of an agent-self and an omniscient creator God.
How could Garfield write “The will as we (seem to) know it is in fact the legacy of
St. Augustine, and for his struggle to solve the theodicy problem raised by the Fall of
Adam and Eve in Eden” (p. 165), when, as he himself shows that he well knows (on
page 168, he mentions Aristotle’s doctrine of choice as the cause of voluntary action)
that Aristotle devotes five chapters of his Nicomachean Ethics to the question of will,

Arindam Chakrabarti 281


volition, and choice as propellers of rational human actions. To quote, a bit at length,
from what must have been Aristotle’s lecture notes on this:

Both the voluntary and the involuntary having been delimited, we must next discuss
choice; for it is thought to be most closely bound up with virtue and to discriminate char-
acters better than actions do.
Choice, then, seems to be voluntary, but not the same thing as the voluntary; the latter
extends more widely. For both children and the lower animals share in voluntary action,
but not in choice, and acts done on the spur of the moment we describe as voluntary, but
not as chosen. . . . Again, the incontinent man acts with appetite, but not with choice;
while the continent man on the contrary acts with choice, but not with appetite.10

Surely what Aristotle is grappling with here has nothing to do with God, Augustine,
or the biblical story of the Fall of Man, but has everything to do with at least one
version of the problem of choice, agency, and will in contemporary secular Western
moral psychology.
Garfield, who goes back to the historicist-Wittgensteinian diagnosis that the
problem of Free-will-versus-Determinism is a local pseudo-problem of Western
­philosophy, that the Nāgārjunian Buddhist fly never got trapped in that particular
fly bottle, eventually shows how a skeptical Mādhyamika Buddhist response to
the Western/Christian problem of free will advances our understanding  —  and
­dissolution — of the problem itself. Even if there was no philosophical discussion of
the free will versus determinism debate in Indian philosophy, now, thanks to this
volume, there is.
We shall see in a later section of this review that Karin Meyers, in the section of
her chapter 2 on “Karma, Free Will, and Moral Responsibility,” clearly does not quite
take Garfield’s route. Given the central doctrines of dependent origination and no-
self, the problem of free will, she says, is, in so many words “one worth thinking
about from a Buddhist perspective” (p. 46; emphasis hers).

4. The Mahābhārata’s Open-ended Way of Reckoning with the Problem of Free Will

Dasti and Bryant have invited contributions representing almost all schools of Indian
philosophy, but chose not to have any entry on the philosophy of the Mahābhārata
or of the Bhagavad Gītā (which is a small but crucial part of that philosophical epic).
I take this to be a moderately regrettable omission. Everyone who is acquainted with
the Vedic-Puranic literature knows that the Mahābhārata is not merely a long narra-
tive poem about a royal family feud turning into total war; it is treated by the tradition
as a philosophical commentary on the Vedas and Upanishads. The eighteen chapters
of the Bhagavad Gītā, for example, are best read, I submit, as an indirect commentary
on the eighteen verses of the Īśa Upanishad. Let me start and end this otherwise
­congratulatory review with two bookends that are missing from the volume I am
showcasing as pathbreaking. First, very briefly, there is the complex problem-space
regarding freedom, determinism, agency, action, and inaction that is created by the
Mahābhārata and Bhagavad Gītā. Second — and I shall end the review with this — is

282 Philosophy East & West


the stunningly original position argued for by K. C. Bhattacharya regarding the self/
subject not just as free from or free to do something but as freedom itself.
After the great Mahābhārata war (controversially dated between 2,500 to 1,500
b.c.e.), described in the epic poem of a hundred thousand verses, through the stench
of rotting corpses on the battlefield the question “Who or what is responsible for this
genocide?” is raised repeatedly. Fingers are pointed at the warrior-princes’ lust for
power, land, or a beautiful woman; at the virtuous hero Yudhiṣṭhira’s weakness for
gambling; and above all at the conniving agency of Krishna, the “devious” divinity
who could have prevented the carnage but chose not to (though in crucial moments
he claimed to be identical with Cosmic Time and hence had to let the accumulated
karma of all participating parties bring forth inexorably the perilous fruits they were
“morally destined” to produce!).
To promote the virtue of forgiveness, the following parable is told at the start of
the thirteenth book, the Book of Teachings. A venomous snake bites and kills the only
son of the pious woman Gautamī. A hunter catches the snake and brings it to Gau-
tamī for permission to kill it. Gautamī points out that such retribution is pointless
because it will not bring her dead son back. The hunter keeps insisting that she must
see her son’s killer killed. At this point, the snake manages to stick its head out and
argue that the death of the son must have been predestined by Time, kāla, and that
because he did not kill anyone willfully or knowingly, he could not be “blamed” or
“punished.” In his defense of fatalism, the snake says: “You foolish fowler! How is it
my fault? I have no will of my own, and am not independent. Not out of any spite
against the child, but being propelled by Death I’ve bitten this child. Therefore, the
sin, if any, should belong to Death” (MBh XIII.1.29). When the fowler responds that
the snake deserves to be killed even if it has been employed by someone else as an
instrumental cause of the child’s death, the argumentative snake enters into a deeper
discourse on the metaphysics of causation, and claims that as an instrument akin to
a potter’s wheel and its pivotal rod, it is not independent, and thus cannot be an
agent.
It is noteworthy that God does not make any appearance in this story, either as a
killer or as a redeemer. In another narrative, a wise bird tells a human king, “Destiny
(daiva) and human agency work in reciprocal dependence. The noble ones take good
initiatives, while eunuchs worship destiny” (MBh XII.139.78). “From knowledge
­arises craving, craving leads to intentional motivatedness, from motivation ensues
bodily effort, and from effort action results” (MBh XII.206; Poona critical edition
­Ch-199).
The moral dilemmas explored in the Mahābhārata come to their sharpest focus
with the Bhagavad Gītā section of the epic. Warlike, both by temperament and by
caste criterion, Prince Arjuna suddenly develops an aversion to the ensuing carnage
on the eve of the war. He wants to drop out of the battle for he does not want to kill
his kinfolk and respected elders on the other side. He seeks to renounce this grue-
some military life, even if he has to beg for a living. But Arjuna’s charioteer-mentor
Krishna convinces him that wisdom and emancipation consist not in ascetic inactiv-
ity but in the midst of vita activa — a life of engaged but unattached, zealous but

Arindam Chakrabarti 283


non-egoistic, ethical work. Freedom lies in renouncing the fruits of action, not in
renouncing actions. However, Krishna also warns in this connection: “Even wise
men are confounded about what is action versus what is mere omission or inaction”
(BG 4.16). In the eighteenth and final chapter, five causal conditions of any action are
set out: (1) the body (locus), (2) the conscious knower-agent, (3) different sorts of in-
struments, (4) exertion and effort of various kinds, and finally (5) a divine factor or
fate (BG 18.14). At the end we are told: “God dwells in the heart of all living beings,
making them move around with his magical power as if on a motor-driven machine”
(BG 18.61). Thus, the Bhagavad Gītā’s final stance on free will remains elusive.
­Krishna’s final exhortation seems to juxtapose a metaphysics of divine predetermina-
tion with a libertarian appeal to free will, with no attempt at reconciliation: “There-
fore get up, earn fame, defeat your enemies and enjoy the entire kingdom; I have
already killed off those enemies in the future, just be an occasioning agent of victory”
(BG 11.33).11

5. The Western Problem Rehearsed in an Indian Idiom

What exactly is the Western problem of free will such that in spite of such clear en-
gagement with the question of “Who did this wrong? Who is responsible” in the
classical philosophical epic Mahābhārata, very knowledgeable modern chroniclers
of Indian philosophy go on saying that in the Indian classical corpus of philosophy,
the problem of free will versus determinism is not discussed at all? Let us quickly
recast the Western debate in recognizably Indian terms.
No social human beings who care for dharma — the universal moral code for a
good life in any place or time or locale and age-and-community-specific codes of
piety — can live without judging their actions as good or bad, and blaming each ­other
for bad actions and regretting having done wrong. All of that presupposes that they
could have acted differently, that when they did something praise- or blameworthy
they acted freely. Yet, at least five different types of arguments can be given in support
of the exact opposite thesis that human action is never free action.
A. The first is a metaphysical argument. Every human action is an event in time.
Every event in time has a cause (as the Buddha’s central insight “dependent origi­
nation” encapsulates). Whatever has a cause is determined by a strict causal law — 
whether or not we are able in each case to discern what that law is. Whatever is
­determined by a strict causal law is non-free, since given its antecedent events it
could not have happened otherwise. Therefore, every human action is causally de-
termined, which is to say that no human action is free.
B. The second is a logico-semantic argument, whose force is not so easy to feel.
It is beautifully summarized in the following Sanskrit verse from that gold mine of
ethical wisdom called “Pancatantra”: “Yad a-bhāvi na tad bhāvi, yad bhāvi na tad
anyathā / iti cintā-viṣaghno’yam agadah kim na pīyate?” (What is not-to-happen will
not happen, what is going to happen cannot be made otherwise. Why not drink this
potion that kills the poison of anxiety?) (Note that Pañcatantra calls this a lazy man’s
words: “iti keśāncit ālasya vacanam”). So, the argument goes like this: Any action

284 Philosophy East & West


that we appear to be considering now whether to do or not to do is a future event.
Like an event in the past about which it is either determinately true or determinately
false that it happened, an event in the future — independent of our ability to predict
or foresee — is either going to take place or not going to take place, since a future-­
tense sentence is either true or false (now). If it is going to happen — that is, if the
sentence “A woman will become the President of the USA in 2021” is true then no
one, not even the strongest group of misogynist politicians, can do anything to make
that statement false. If it is not going to happen, that is, if that statement is false, then
no one can make it true. Since in neither case does anyone have any freedom to
change the undiscovered truth-value of the future-tense sentence — and a third op-
tion does not exist — no one is free about any future action — which is all that one can
feel free about.
C. The third is a religious argument from (God’s or Buddha’s) omniscience. Had
I been really free in choosing my future course of action then no one — not even God
or Buddha — can know from now what I am going to choose, freely, to do. But God
or the Buddha is omniscient and knows all that was, is, or will be the case. So it is
not true that no one knows what I shall choose to do. Therefore, I am not really free.
Instead of omniscience, the omnipotence of God is also used sometimes to de-
duce that we are merely instruments (as in the passage about human mechanical
dolls in the hands of God in the Bhagavad Gītā passage mentioned above).
D. The fourth is also a religious argument, though it is not theistic. Even atheistic
Hindu, Buddhist, and Jaina philosophers can propose this argument for determinism,
as long as they share religious faith in the ethico-hedonic law of karmic retribution.
It goes as follows: Whatever happens in the bodily or mental life of a human being
is wholly determined by his or her past karma — good and bad actions done in this
or an earlier life that have left their unseen effects behind. Even if no external force
compels me to act the way I actually do, my so called “own” will to act is an un­
chosen effect of my own past actions and their unseen but accumulating effects on
my disposition. If the will itself is an unchosen effect of an inexorable law — then
whatever is propelled by such unchosen unfree will is itself unfree. Hence none of
my actions, even the ones that I feel I have voluntarily done of my own accord, are
free.
E. Finally, the fifth argument is a secular version of the karma-theoretic argument
in terms of psychological determinism. My act of volition — whether it is identified
with a neuro-physical event in the brain or not — is a mental event as much applica-
ble in terms of its antecedents and lawlike connections as any physical event. Just as
a kleptomaniac or a neurotic obsessive-compulsive person does not act freely, I also
undergo psychological states propelled by my own neuroses and external stimuli.
What I happen to think or wish or elect or decide is in principle explicable in terms
of my genetic code and the details of my upbringing and my immediate environ­
mental inputs. Therefore, none of my voluntary actions are genuinely free.
With such a battery of supportive arguments, determinism looks invincible. Yet,
one of the most well-known practical philosophies of India, Patañjali’s philosophy of
Yoga, clearly rejects the strict determinism of the early Ajivika Niyativādin (fatalists).

Arindam Chakrabarti 285


In his recently published book, Daniel Raveh remarks: “In Pātanjala Yoga, ‘freedom’
is an act of will. Yoga is philosophy of action.”12 None of the deterministic arguments
above have gone unchallenged. Take, for example, the very general first argument.
Even if we grant that as an event every human action must have a cause, that cause
need not be another event. The cause of my own action can be my own self — the
very person that I am. In order to be a free action my action need not be uncaused.
As long as it is auto-nomous — caused by my self and not caused by another foreign
agency — it can be free. And the causal chain of events can stop at the self. Since the
self is not an event but a substance, its being itself free from the sway of causal law is
quite consistent with the general law: every event must have a cause.
In response to the religious or theistic argument from God’s foreknowledge, con-
temporary Indian philosophers have defended human freedom rather easily. If you
do not already assume determinism, then there is no reason to admit that, before
I actually decide to raise my left hand next Sunday morning, there is any truth-value,
either true or false, to the forecast: “Arindam will raise his left hand next Sunday
morning.” And if there is no truth-value to it, it does not tarnish or curtail God’s
­omniscience not to know which truth-value it has. So, in brief, God does not know
the exact course of my future free actions because — as yet — there is no course of
action by me to be known. But what about God’s complete, detailed knowledge of
the future? The very coherence of the notion of omnitemporal omniscience has been
questioned by orthodox Vedic exegetes (the Mīmāṃsā philosophers).
Another alternative route one can take to dissolve the tension between God’s
foreknowledge and our genuine freedom is to say that God being timeless, the ques-
tion “Does he know now what I shall do next Sunday” does not arise for him, be-
cause the question is inextricably temporal.
Let us now counter the preceding set of determinist arguments with three very
strong arguments in favor of the opposite view: libertarianism. This is the view that
human actions — at least some of them — are indeed free, and free will is a real fea-
ture of humanity (rather than “sheer nonsense” — as Swami Vivekananda says in one
of his lectures).
A. The first argument is from introspective self-observation. Noticing the work-
ings of our own minds we undeniably observe and feel that while there are some
mental states and acts we simply cannot help, over others we have an obvious con-
trol. If for some reason I am very angry with a friend, the desire to use wounding
words seems to flow uncontrollably from that anger. But when I want to imagine a
nice scenario in my mind’s eye, as it were, I seem to have a good deal of creative
freedom as to which scenario to imagine — a beautiful temple on a hilltop or a beach
with palm trees or a village of thatched cottages in the middle of lush green paddy
fields. This voluntarism about the imagination is championed in Indian poetics and
aesthetics by Abhinavagupta and his Kashmiri followers, who claim that “in the king-
dom of poetry, the poet alone is an unconstrained sovereign”
About the nature of our own mental states, whether it is pain or pleasure that
I am feeling, whether my anger is mild or intense, my own considered introspective

286 Philosophy East & West


evidence seems to be so irreplaceable that if I feel I am free with respect to some
mental acts, then I must actually be free. Therefore some mental acts are free. Indeed,
to use the standard argument from contrast, we would not know what it is to be com-
pelled, constrained, forced to think, feel, or perceive, some of the time, unless at
other times we were genuinely uncompelled, unconstrained, and unforced. If for
some reason the appeal above to direct introspective evidence is disregarded as illu-
sory or misplaced, then the strongest argument for preserving the freedom of human
actions comes from the need for ethical appraisal, which we notice in Elisa Freschi’s
chapter on Mīmāṃsā in the volume under review.
B. If all that human beings do is naturally causally determined, then the entire
range of our moral and social reactive attitudes of resenting, regretting, reprehend-
ing, admiring, rewarding, punishing, and so forth would be as illicit “as blaming a
cow for stealing or an oyster for lying” (to use an expression Swami Vivekananda was
fond of using). But the undeniably unique feature of humans is that only humans can
be legitimately blamed for lying or admired for sacrificing their self-interest for the
benefit of others.
The only way we could ignore this argument for the reality of free will is to insist
that all morality, moral resentment, and morally tinged notions like obligation, right,
stealing, and lying are based on a huge but human error. But, like calling something
an “error,” to call some widespread practice a mistake is itself a strong normative, if
not moral, statement, which comes with recommendations that we should stop judg-
ing people’s actions morally, and that we should adopt the scientific attitude toward
human action, but it makes sense to insist that we should do something only when
we are free to do it!
C. This brings me to the most subtle argument for the ineliminability of human
freedom, the argument from pragmatic self-refutation. Supposing someone gives an
eloquent speech arguing that language does not exist, we would naturally conclude
that such an argument refutes itself insofar as one uses language to show that lan-
guage does not exist. Similarly, imagine someone arguing for the unreality of time,
concluding with the utterance “On the preceding grounds, after you have con­
sidered my reasoning, you must stop believing in the reality of time.” Since the
­recommendation itself assumes the temporal succession or sequence “after consid-
ering my reasoning, do this,” the appeal to the unreality of time is pragmatically self-­
refuting (vadato-vyāghāta). Now, any argument that the determinist gives urging us
to give up the mistaken idea of freedom — insofar as logical arguments are used at
all — comes with a normative force: “If you admit the truth of the premise then you
must acknowledge the truth of the conclusion.” Now this “must” of rational logical
obligation, just like the moral “must,” presupposes that the audience — the listener to
whom the determinist’s parārthānumāṇa is addressed — has the freedom to deny the
conclusion, and hence the ability to accept the conclusion, freely and voluntarily.
Thus, to give any argument sincerely is to appeal to human intellectual freedom,
since there is no logical “should” without a logical “can,” backed up by a logical
“might not.”

Arindam Chakrabarti 287


6. Panini and Bhartṛhari, Showcasing Cardona’s Majestic Chapter

Anyone who says the Sanskrit word for “free” (svatantra) is untheorized in Indian
philosophy must be forgetting that Pān.ini (in the fourth century b.c.e.) defines an
agent or doer (kartā) as “One who is free” (svatantra, self-ruled). Bhartṛhari, the phi-
losopher of grammar, in explaining this idea of auto (sva)-nomous (tantra), in the
fourth–fifth century c.e., lays down six criteria of free agency:

(a) X is an autonomous agent if X started acting before drawing his strength from
other aiding factors, such as the instruments.
(b) X retains his preeminence by subjugating all other contributors to the action.
(c) The operations of all other causal factors are subject to the functioning of X.
(d) If X stops functioning, all the other conditions stop producing effects.
(e) X is irreplaceable or non-substitutable with any surrogate, such that even if
any other particular action-condition (e.g., the locus, instrument, the accusa-
tive) is missing or replaced, X has to be there for this action to be possible.
(f ) X can get the action done, even if indirectly from a distance, through its
­influence over other more directly involved employed agents.

7. The Position of Ancient Sāmkhya

The most ancient, pre-Buddha, Sāmkhya tradition of philosophy defends a dualism


much more radical than the Cartesian dualism of mind and body. In Sāmkhya, there
is no room for conscious will to act because to be conscious is to be inactive and
unchanging, and to be active and dynamic is to be unconscious. “Conscious free
will,” under this metaphysics, would at best be an oxymoron, at worst a logical mis-
take (though a mistake can only be committed by an active conscious cognitive
agent, which does not exist according to Sāmkhya!). After delineating this view as a
form of determinism or a fictionalism concerning free will, Edwin Bryant insightfully
remarks: “the unwelcome corollaries of Sāmkhya’s hard-line position on such issues
[are] acting as a trigger for much subsequent development in Indian philosophy.”
Bryant ends his chapter prefiguring the chapters to come as follows:

Unhappy with the Sāṃkhya position, Nyāya seeks to couple an eternal unchanging ­ātman
as a substance with separable changing qualities such as agency; Buddhism to jettison
notions of any eternal entities in the first place; and Advaita Vedānta of non-eternal ones;
and the theists to conclude that unresolvable philosophical problems of this sort mandate
the existence of an Īśvara who is beyond comprehension. All run into philosophical diffi-
culties of their own. (pp. 38–39)

Far from failing to find any awareness of the Free Will problem, notice how
this brief history of Indian philosophies makes them all go around the normative
voluntarism-versus-naturalistic causation issue. Finding or not finding a philosophi-
cal problem raised or not raised in a certain ancient tradition is just a matter of look-
ing with the appropriate search engine.

288 Philosophy East & West


8. Early Buddhist and Pali Canon Treatment of Human Will and Action

Karin Meyers seems to forget about the word centanā when she writes that early
Buddhists did not have a term equivalent to “free will” or any discrete faculty of the
will. In chapter 2, Meyers gives us a contemporary formulation of the early Buddhist
naturalized theory of karma (actions) done by empty persons who are reduced to
streams of interdependent ephemeral dharma (event-like factors). Her account re-
minds us of Charles Goodman’s syllogistic refutation of Paul Griffiths’ (whose view is
like Rick Repetti’s, which I mention approvingly below) libertarian interpretation of
the Buddhist theory of free will:

This claim puts Griffiths in a difficult position. If the parameters are all determined by
karma, then people’s actions must be caused by the parameters, by something else, or by
nothing. If actions are caused by the parameters, then they are determined. If they are
caused by nothing, they are utterly random, and therefore not free. If they are caused by
something else, this something else must either be the self or something other than the
self. If the something else is not the self, then either determinism or randomness will re-
sult. But the something else can’t be the self, because, according to Buddhists, there is no
self. Therefore, Griffiths’s interpretation is untenable.13

In his recent impressive anthology titled Buddhist Perspectives on Free Will:


Agentless Agency? 14 Rick Repetti (who has reprinted the same essay by Garfield) re-
marks: “Some Buddhist scholars think Buddhism rejects free will, or they deny there
is, was, or should be . . . even any Buddhist inquiry into free will. I disagree.” Al-
though I learned an enormous amount from Meyers’ and Garfield’s essays, on this
issue I tend to agree with Repetti’s disagreement. There are a number of supporting
passages like the following from the Dhammasangani, which support a voluntaristic
anti-determinist interpretation of early Buddhist philosophy of action:

“What on that occasion is volition (cetanā)? The volition, purpose, purposefulness, which
is born of contact with the appropriate element of representative intellection — that is the
volition that there then is.” And Atthasalini: “Volition is that which co-ordinates. . . . [I]ts
function is conation. . . . It makes double effort, double exertion.”15

At one place, the Buddha describes himself thus: “I am one who tells what ac-
tions should be done as well as how to practice inaction” (kiriyāvādī cāhaṃ . . .
akiriyāvādī cā’ti).

9. On the Jaina View of Human Agency

In his learned chapter on Jainism Christopher Key Chapple presents Jaina philosophy
as taking a “thoroughly voluntarist” stance in the free will debate. Each of us poten-
tially omniscient pure souls finds ourselves covered in the unclean cloaks of karma.
But the good news, for the cleansing-oriented Jaina, is that each fettered soul can do
something autonomously to doff these layers of karmic cloaks. Karma binds us in
eight ways, we are told in this lucid exposition of Jainism: as knowledge-covering,

Arindam Chakrabarti 289


intuition-covering, sensation-covering, deluding, life-span-fixing, body-generating,
status-determining, and generally obstructive. But this karma-determinism, without
the help of any transcendent God, can be overcome by prayer of emulation (to the
wise and emancipated exemplars — the Jinas) and practice of detachment. Human
beings, though mired in the causal nexus of their own past deeds, have the freedom
to purify themselves painstakingly with ascetic self-control and bodily and intellec-
tual nonviolence toward their fellow beings and toward nature. Chapple’s chapter
ends with a wonderful sentence about the fork of choice we face between thickening
or thinning the veil of karma: “Karma determines all things, and each soul faces,
moment to moment, the decision to continue in patterns of behavior that densify
karma and hence obscure the soul or to take up the steady path to purification”
(p. 84).

10. Will, Causation, and Agency in Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika Philosophy of Mind

After the Buddhist denial of the self altogether, naturally comes the Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika
tradition of Indian thought where enduring and substantial self plays the most crucial
role. Dasti himself writes an intensively researched essay on this school’s treatment
of agency or doership of voluntary actions. He highlights three major points of the
Nyāya treatment of agency of an individual (unliberated) Ātman:

(1) the categorization of will and agency (sometimes identified with endeavor/


prayatna, which is a mental quality, whereas effort  /ceṣṭā is physical) as a
quality of the self;
(2) moral responsibility, merit and demerit (unseen adṛṣṭa) as non-essential prop-
erties of the self as long as one remains an embodied and knowing person;
(3) dismissing the sharp distinction that the Advaita Vedantic tradition draws
­between knowledge and action, taking knowing itself as an expression of
freedom.

About the last point, I just wanted to alert the readers that Dasti never claims that
Nyāya regards jñāna (cognition) as an action. An awareness is a quality, not an ac-
tion. As Jayanta Bhaṭṭa argues against the Mīmāṃsaka, knowledge is a quality of the
self, whereas by “karma” Nyāya Vaiśeṣika only means physical motion in space,
which a Nyāya Ātman cannot initiate or undergo because it is literally ubiquitous in
size. But when a Nyāya self knowingly does something, it incurs or earns dharma or
adharma and is accountable for each of its conscious voluntary actions.
In the late twentieth century, Karl Potter, an analytic philosopher very much in
the New Nyāya tradition, defended and interpreted the karma doctrine as a response
to the problem of freedom versus determinism, in a series of now-classic essays.16
Since Dasti’s chapter does not include any discussion of Potter’s nuanced Nyāya
solution to the Free Will problem, let me fill in that gap here in this review. Karl
Potter has famously called the karma theory an a priori presupposition of all Indian
metaphysics of morals, and yet he does not think that the individual’s actions are

290 Philosophy East & West


externally determined if they are largely determined by pre-initiated (prārabdha)
­karma.
Potter’s ingenious version of compatibilism deepens the Nyāya notion of “voli-
tion” in terms of trying to do something. Potter begins his analysis defending the
“prior” existence of the transmigrating self (whom God did not create and whose
doing, trying, and trying to try go infinitely back in time). Suppose that I willfully try
to do some action Ah that I have the ability to do — for example draw a human figure.
If I succeed, I end up drawing either a male figure (Am), or a female figure (Af ), or
drawing a tall, lean male figure (Atml). My generally described goal “drawing a
­human figure” leaves room for these distinct alternative results, each of which would
count as succeeding to do Ah — draw a human figure — not because of any slack in
the causal connection between my trying to draw and the actual drawing that I
­accomplish. In comparison to every intended action that is a determinable, the actu-
ally accomplished act is a determinate. From the fact that John wanted to do a spe-
cific action, to infer that there exists one and only one particular action that John
wanted to do is to commit what Potter calls the fallacy of misplaced determinateness.
Since the object of my trying is imagined doing, and an imagined act, however nar-
rowly specified by the intender, is not causally or logically constrained to be deter-
minately this rather than that of one of its many alternative actualizations, our willed
actions remain free. Potter applies this new logical compatibilism to the Nyāya ­theory
where actions are caused strictly by knowledge, desire, and volition (as Dasti’s
­chapter shows us).

11. Mīmāṃsā and Advaita Vedānta: Opposition between Vita Activa and
Vita Contemplativa?

For the classical Indian Mīmāṃsā (Vedic textual interpretation) philosophers, an


agent is someone who is capable of performing what is enjoined by a moral or ritual
injunction such as “Thou shalt speak the truth” or “Desirous of happiness, you must
perform the fire-ritual daily.”
The exhortation goads the appropriate addressee, one who desires happiness
and has other relevant qualifications, not by coercing or unconsciously brainwashing
him to act according to it, but by bringing about his understanding of the prescriptive
sentence as the only means of knowing his duty. The meaning of a mandate is “what
is to be done.” The act or its karmic results are called apūrva, “what was not there
before”; it is other than all that is known as accomplished or happened because it has
to be done.
When we speak of the “karmic” consequences of an action, say an act of stab-
bing or an act of offering clarified butter to a ritual fire, we are not speaking of the
blood spilled or the smoke generated; we are speaking of the invisible demerit (which
will mature into suffering) or merit (which will mature into happiness) earned by the
agent. Such karmic consequences of action do not show up until after a long gap,
sometimes not until the next life. This gap is “explained” in terms of the unseen
­potency of an action done.

Arindam Chakrabarti 291


There is also the Bhāṭṭa Mīmāṃsā view that the heart of the imperative is the
propulsion that makes it happen (bhāvanā), connoted directly by the injunctive verb-­
ending. This urging propulsion again comes in two varieties: at the level of the sen-
tence itself it is the motivating push of the words (the optative verb-ending “should”),
and at the level of the person who is enjoined to carry out the command, it is the
push by the intended competent auditor-agent. What is this perplexing property
called “urge” or “bhāvanā”?17 It is somewhat psychologically characterized in
Prābhākara Mīmāṃsā moral psychology as “cessation of indifference.” Until one
feels the flutter of this propelling force, one stays volitionally indifferent. To “initiate”
is to bring something about that was never there before (a-pūrva). It is the “initial”
flutter of action-propelling “enjoining force” (niyoga) that harnesses our will to the
act. Nothing counts as knowledge in Mīmāṃsā unless it brings to light something
hitherto unknown.
From her chapter on Mīmāṃsā suggestively entitled “Freedom because of
Duty” — which I am tempted to understand in the light of Strawson’s discussion of
Freedom and Resentment — Elisa Freschi gives us at least three fresh pieces of “knowl­
edge” in this Mīmāṃsā sense:

(A) Just because Mīmāṃsā insists on the action-propelling force of the impera-


tive verb-suffix, we must not think of them as determinists. Enjoining an ac-
tion is not causally coercing the commandee into doing it. The commandee
is free to cultivate the appropriate desire for the fruit of action or respect for
the authority of the Veda, et cetera, without which he is not even the i­ ntended
addressee of the conditional or categorical imperative.
(B) To make room for this essential free will of the doer of Vedic duties, K ­ umārila
is ready even to give up the standard Brahminical/Upanishadic claim of im-
mutable eternity of the soul. Since the agent-self is free to change his actions,
the self is said to be neither utterly same/changeless nor entirely ephemeral,
but a continuant capable of transformation.
(C) Past karma may exert an influence on how one chooses to act but does not
fix or force an agent’s course of action. Mīmāṃsā compatibilism lies in a
duly sophisticated analysis of the competent commandee’s command-­
receptive attitude.

First action, then contemplation! In spite of the fact that both Mīmāṃsā and
­(Advaita) Vedānta come under the general rubric of Vedic Exegesis, insofar as the
former gives an account of active ethical life, and the latter of contemplative spiritual
life, their positions on the free will question seem to be diametrically opposed, at
least according to Sthaneshwar Timalsina. If Pūrva (prior) Mīmāṃsā vindicates Vita
Activa, the Advaita stream of Uttara (posterior) Mīmāṃsā, which rejects any rele-
vance or efficacy of work or ritual performance of duties toward final liberation,
promotes pure Vita Contemplativa: the purely intellectual-meditative path of inac-
tion that recommends the self’s total identification with the disinterested-witness
consciousness. The individual self is ontologically identical to the universal im-

292 Philosophy East & West


mutable Absolute for whom the question of any action or will does not arise. The
agentive individuality that is presupposed by the action-prescribing part of Veda is
erroneously superimposed by our shared ignorance, which projects a plural world
of objects on undifferentiated pure subjective consciousness. That is Advaita
­“inactionism.”
Timalsina begins his impressively erudite account of such a “work”-averse
­Advaita Vedānta with a tell-tale epigraph from the Bhagavad Gītā: “Even as it sits
­inside the body, the Ātman neither acts nor gets attached to the fruits of actions,
­because it has no beginning or quality.” What Timalsina does not entirely ignore, but
does deliberately under-emphasize, is that from the empirical/relative/pragmatic/
transactional standpoint Śaṅkara, especially under his interpretation of Brahma Sūtra
2.3.33–42, works out a pretty strong theory of the individual self as autonomous
agent (kartā), because it has to be meant by the scriptural imperatives for specific
actions (śāstrāthavattvāt). Even that purely contemplative self-realization, the path to
which has been recommended by Sureśvara, whose “Proof of Non-Action” serves
as the central text for Timalsina, is enjoined as a duty: “The Self has to be heard, re-
flected and meditated upon.” Most of Timalsina’s chapter is written from the radical
non-dualist transcendental standpoint from which no will or effort is either neces-
sary or possible even for liberating ourselves from the duality-concocting, reality-­
concealing fetters of ignorance. Those fetters never bind the pure quality-less self in
the first place! But even Śaṅkara would concede that no philosophical argumenta-
tion is possible from that transcendental standpoint. For all the fictionalist double-­
level discourse that Timalsina illuminates with the Borges-like stories from the
Yogavāsiṣṭha, as long as there is philosophical discourse, the talking persons have
duties and therefore the freedom to do or not do those duties.

12. The Other Vedāntas

But Advaita is not the only stream of Vedānta. It is Martin Ganeri’s interpretation in
chapter 10, that Rāmānuja (born 1017 c.e.), the Qualified Non-Dualist Vedāntin,
sounds like a moderate libertarian when he writes “each finite self is a real agent that
exercises genuine freedom of will, in opposition to both Advaita Vedānta and Sam-
khya traditions” (p. 233). Rāmānuja’s ethic of surrender to God as the only initiative
human beings are obligated to take makes it our epistemic duty to understand how
God is the complete controller of all our inner and outer actions. Under this un­
limited freedom of God, we have the limited freedom to relinquish our agency to the
imperative of devotion, which is nothing but full recognition of our utter dependence
on God.
The stances of Dualist Vedānta of Mādhva and Gaudīya Vaiśṇava Metaphysics
are naturally similar on the question of the limited freedom of human individuals,
under the sovereign sway of divine will. Only the Supreme Lord is truly independent
and autonomous; the causally operative action-propelling will of the human individ-
ual is under the overall control of the Lord. And using the Brahamsūtra’s common
theodicy, “Madhva takes recourse to the beginninglessness of karma to exempt the

Arindam Chakrabarti 293


Lord from responsibility for the individual’s good or bad deeds” (p. 259). In spite of
their utterly dependent status, in Madhva’s Vedānta the volition (prayatna) of the
spiritual aspirant (we are told) plays an important role in the ultimate liberation of
those who are destined to be liberated. There are some, only in this system of Indian
thought, who will never be liberated; they are creatures of eternal darkness, perenni-
ally in bondage. An interesting modern question that should be asked is: Insofar as
they are humans, are they free to respond to ethical do’s and don’ts? Do the scrip­
tural imperatives even apply to them?
The distilled results of the investigation into the theistic Gaudīya Vaiśṇava tradi-
tion’s treatment of the notion of “a free doer” (from Grammar to Theology) are stated
succinctly in the last chapter by Dasa and Edelman (p. 305) as follows:

(i) When the embodied but conscious self acts under the magic spell of māyā,
it makes the mind-body complex move but under the permissive oversight of
the Lord/God.
(ii) Such embodied agency should be looked upon as the individuals’ inherent
servitude to God, and therefore a mere expression of God’s own power of
consciousness.
(iii) When this self merges back into God in apparent non-duality, agency re-
mains as an unutilized potential quality.
(iv) Agency in the emancipated realm of Vaikuntha is manifested through a per-
fected celestial body.

13. Portrait of the Knower-Doer as a Creative Artist Unbound in Kashmir Shaivism

We go back in a sense to the Panini-Bhartṛhari line of Grammatical thinking, with


added phenomenological depth and ontological commitment to the dynamism of
the Self who not only has the power of knowing, remembering, and separating out,
but also enjoys the exercise of his power of desiring and acting. Kashmir Shaivism
is the utter freedom from the cage of causality.
Building on the ancient grammarians’ semantics of the autonomous agent
­(discussed by George Cardona in chapter 4), the Shaiva non-dualists of Kashmir — 
primarily Utpaladeva and his prolific commentator Abhinavagupta (tenth–eleventh
centuries c.e.) — ascribe three powers to the conscious self: the power of knowledge,
the power of desire, and the power of action. Each self, currently clothed in layers of
past karma, is inherently capable of perfect freedom by rediscovering its identity with
God (Shiva). David Peter Lawrence brings his well-proven expertise on this Trika
school of thought to bear on the unique role that positive creative freedom plays in
the Kashmir Shaiva concept of consciousness and the first person. It is the exercise
of these powers that makes consciousness reflexively self-aware, dynamic, and play-
fully imaginative. Freedom is the very essence of consciousness, which can be aware
of anything it chooses (ruci). Engaging in, as it were, a cosmic sport, consciousness
first contracts itself into limited knowledge, individuated embodiment, temporal
­sequence, and lawlike causal regularity. But it is part of that sport to expand sponta-

294 Philosophy East & West


neously after this contraction, rediscovering its true identity with the absolute non-­
dual divine consciousness. To remember, for instance, is not to be chained to a fixed
past. In one place (IPVV II, p. 4), Abhinavagupta remarks that “the power of remem-
bering is the ultimate freedom” of the self, because to remember is to feel free to
connect back with the synthetic unity of universal consciousness. Not only do I relish
my own freedom in the self-conscious movements of memory and imagination, but
in communicative practice I also rely on your freedom — you being my own other-ed
consciousness.
The basic freedom of a vibrant, dynamic, agentive I-consciousness is the freedom
to add to or subtract from an earlier experience at the time of recollection. It is a
thorough idealist monism where each knower is a creative artist. There is no thinking
without doing and playing. All addressing of others turns out to be self-addressing by
a playfully self-othering consciousness. Abhinavagupta’s analysis of freedom was
used in all subsequent Sanskrit poetics to portray aesthetic imagination as free from
the constraint of natural causal laws (niyati-kṛta-niyama-rahitā). It is a fascinating
lexical fact that the same Sanskrit word vimarśa, which is used in Nyāya to mean
doubt, is used in Kashmir Shaivism to mean that self-conscious, self-articulating as-
pect of consciousness that makes it free. This seems to support my hunch that the “or”
of doubt and the “or” of freedom that it grounds are at bottom connected.

14. K. C. Bhattacharya on Subject as Freedom (Not of the Will)

I promised to end this review essay by speaking about K. C. Bhattacharya’s concept


of freedom, which the volume under review omits because it is part of modern
rather than classical Indian philosophy. Written in his uniquely analytic yet phenom-
enologically meditative style, without any reference to any previous Indian or West-
ern philosopher, K. C. Bhattacharya’s original work The Subject as Freedom (1930)
takes the subject to be an unmeant meaner.18 The subject is that which “intends by
the word I . . . without being referred to by it.” To discover this self, the phenomeno-
logical analyst passes through successive inward stages: bodily, psychological, and
spiritual subjectivity. In each subsequent rung, freedom lies in the feeling that I can
exist independently of the previous level of subjectivity. In bodily subjectivity, I iden-
tify with my active inner felt body through my freedom from all perceived objects
(including my externally perceived body). In psychological subjectivity, as the intro-
spected flow of ideas and feelings, the self is isolable from even this felt body.
Going beyond introspection, at the highest level of spiritual subjectivity, the sub-
ject finds freedom even from this felt need to distinguish itself. Such a subject, like
the Advaita Vedānta Ātman, which is not conscious but consciousness itself, is not an
individual ego or a spiritual substance free from embodiment or feelings; it is free-
dom itself. In other contexts, for example in his profoundly original paper “Reality of
the Future,” and in his commentaries on classical Sāmkhya and Yoga philosophies,
Bhattacharya has discussed the nature of positive freedom to enact something in
the future, and negative freedom in the sense of mukti (liberation). But the above-­
mentioned densely argued concept of the subject, not merely as free but as freedom

Arindam Chakrabarti 295


per se, is still waiting to be critically analyzed as a third dimension of freedom dis-
tinct from freedom from and freedom to. Instead of the feeling “I could have done
otherwise,” this third sense of freedom consists in the feeling “I might not have been
x,” and ultimately in freedom even from that feeling.
One hopes that in the second edition of this “must-read” collection of essays
Dasti and Bryant will include a critical exposition of K. C. Bhattacharya’s notoriously
difficult but scintillatingly original work Subject as Freedom. I chose the title of this
review essay partly to arouse the readers’ appetite for that fascinating notion, devel-
oped in twentieth-century Indian philosophy.
If and when, inspired by this exemplary anthology, contemporary researchers of
Chinese philosophy bring out a similar volume on freedom, free will, and agency in
Chinese philosophy, one hopes they will not confine themselves to ancient and
­medieval texts and sources only but also include samples of the stance by modern
Chinese philosophers on metaphysical and political freedom and the will.

Notes

1    –    Karl Potter, “Pre-existence,” in P. T. Raju and Alburey Castell, eds., East-West


Studies on the Problem of the Self (The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1968), p. 193.
2    –    Kai Marchal and Christian Helmut Wenzel, “Chinese Perspectives on Free
Will,” in The Routledge Companion to Free Will, ed. Kevin Timpe, Meghan
Griffith, and Neil Levy (New York: Routledge, 2017), p. 374.
3    –    Self and Deception: A Cross-Cultural Philosophical Enquiry, ed. Roger T. Ames
and Wimal Dissanayake (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1996),
p. 219.
4    –    Xunzi: The Complete Text, trans. with introd. by Eric L. Hutton (Princeton, NJ,
and Oxford: Princeton University Press, 2014), p. 229.
5    –    Henry Rosemont Jr. and Roger T. Ames, Confucian Role Ethics: A Moral Vision
for the 21st Century? (Gottingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 2016), p. 110.
6    –    Arindam Chakrabarti and Ralph Weber, eds., Comparative Philosophy without
Borders (New York: Bloomsbury Academic, 2016).
7    –    Franklin Perkins, Heaven and Earth Are Not Humane: The Problem of Evil in
Classical Chinese Philosophy (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2014),
p. 108.
8    –    Ibid.
9    –    Ibid.
10    –    Aristotle, The Nichomachean Ethics, trans. David Rose, rev. with introd. and
notes by Lesley Brown (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), pp. 41–42.
11    –    Quotations from the Bhagavad Gītā in this paragraph are taken from Timpe,
Griffith, and Levy, The Routledge Companion to Free Will.

296 Philosophy East & West


12    –    Daniel Raveh, Sūtras, Stories and Yoga Philosophy: Narrative and Transfigura-
tion (New York: Routledge, 2016), p. 80.
13    –    Charles Goodman, “Resentment and Reality: Buddhism on Moral Responsibil-
ity,” American Philosophical Quarterly 39, no. 4 (October 2002).
14    –    Buddhist Perspectives on Free Will: Agentless Agency? ed. Rick Repetti (New
York: Routledge, 2017).
15    –    See the following website for all the texts that show the Buddha, going against
contemporary fatalists and materialist determinists, endorsing human ability to
initiate actions: www.accesstoinsight.org /tipitaka /an/an06/an06.038.niza.html.
16    –    E.g., Karl Potter, “Freedom and Determinism from an Indian Perspective,” Phi-
losophy East and West 17, nos. 1–4 (1967): 113–124.
17    –    See, Allen Ollett, “What is Bhāvanā?” Journal of Indian Philosophy 41, no. 3
( June 2013): 221–262.
18    –    K. C. Bhattacharya, Search for the Absolute in Neo-Vedanta, ed. with introd.
George Bosworth Burch (Honolulu: University of Hawai‘i Press, 1976).

Arindam Chakrabarti 297

You might also like