J2018 - The Subject Is Freedom
J2018 - The Subject Is Freedom
J2018 - The Subject Is Freedom
Arindam Chakrabarti
Philosophy East and West, Volume 68, Number 1, January 2018, pp. 277-297
(Review)
Access provided by National Taiwan University (12 Apr 2018 08:17 GMT)
FEATURE REVIEW
Arindam Chakrabarti
Philosophy Department, University of Hawai‘i
[email protected]
Free Will, Agency, and Selfhood in Indian Philosophy. Edited by Matthew R. Dasti
and Edwin F. Bryant. New York: Oxford University Press, 2014. isbn 978-0-19-
992275-8.
Philosophy East & West Volume 68, Number 1 January 2018 277–297 277
© 2018 by University of Hawai‘i Press
would have a hard time convincing your audience that it is really “philosophy” (e.g.,
the discussion at the heart of Mīmāṃsā, concerning the exact meaning of a verb-
ending in an imperative sentence that enjoins an action-to-be-done to its compre-
hending hearer, which chapter 6 by Elisa Freschi so clearly lays out in the volume
under review). Should you emphasize, instead, the common issues that are also
known to and focused on in Western philosophy, you will either be suspected of
superimposing a Western conceptual scheme on Classical Indian philosophy or,
worse, you will be ignored as presenting a boring old hat. It is simply exhilarating to
see how several essays in the volume under discussion here manage to escape both
horns of this comparativist’s dilemma while discussing one of the most hackneyed
topics of traditional and contemporary Western philosophy: Given that our actions,
including our acts of willing and choosing are events happening according to natural
causal laws, how can they be free?
The problem of free will and agency as it is discussed, even if tangentially, in
Sāṃkhya, Buddhist, Nyāya, Jain, Kashmir Shaiva, Mīmāṃsā, Advaita, Viśiṣṭādvaita,
and Dvaita Vedānta texts is recognizable to be that problem by a Western lens as you
go through this book, and yet the discourse around the problem, surely but unnotice-
ably, changes so radically that not only new solutions but new problem terrains are
created. Effortlessly, comparative philosophy turns creative. For all its Indological and
philological context-setting, the reader takes home from this anthology a fresh set of
insights and puzzlements that are simply philosophical without any prefix: “West-
ern” or “Indian,” “classical” or “modern,” or even “comparative.” Good comparative
philosophy should be just that: good philosophy. With this book, Indian comparative
philosophy gets closer to this bright future of losing the parochial prefix.
The Mahābhārata claims about itself that “whatever is here is elsewhere, and what is
not here is not anywhere in the world.” Some of us working in the confluence be-
tween Indian and Western philosophies would like to believe, analogously, that any
perennial philosophical issue that is discussed elsewhere must have been discussed,
in some form or other, in Indian philosophy as well. If a philosophical problem is
deep and non-phony and arises from the human condition, it must have been dis-
cussed somewhere in the vast diachronic debating arena that is Classical Indian phi
losophy. Now, no one can deny that whether human beings are free to will and act
as they choose, given the sway of causality over their psychophysical lives, is a deep
and genuine philosophical issue. The same issue has been put poignantly and pow-
erfully by Karl Potter negatively as follows: “as long as a person is at the mercy of
forces external to himself, so long will he be subject to frustration, despair and un-
happiness.”1 How could it be possible that such a fundamental existential problem
escaped the attention of the contemplative and argumentative Indians? Yet, it was
and is thought generally even by eminent scholars of Indian philosophy (such as J. N.
Mohanty and Jay Garfield) that it is a typically Western (perhaps Judeo-Christian)
problem about which Indian philosophers never much bothered to debate or write.
The heart is the lord of the body and the master of one’s spirit and intelligence. It issues
orders, but it takes orders from nothing: it restrains itself, it employs itself; it lets itself go,
it takes itself in hand; it makes itself proceed, it makes itself stop. Thus, the mouth can be
compelled either to be silent or to speak, . . . but the heart cannot be compelled to change
its thoughts.4
But, of course, such a view of human action, its naturalistic causes, and its spon-
taneity is much more subtle than compatibilism or absolute free-will-ism. For in-
stance, both letting go and self-restraining, in this passage, are treated as equally
spontaneous acts of the heart-mind. The goal of this third wave of comparative phi-
losophy should be, as Rosemont and Ames5 and Chakrabarti and Weber6 suggest,
to take uniquely Chinese, uniquely Indian, uniquely Japanese concepts such as the
concept of an exemplary sage, of the heart-mind, of desireless action, of agency of
surrendering agency, of collective ignorance, et cetera, and underscore their absence
in classical and modern Western philosophy.
In his book on a very different problem of evil in Chinese philosophy, Franklin
Perkins quotes an intriguing passage from Zhuangzi about the Promethean spirit of
human beings: “Thus, they (human beings) rebel against the illuminating brightness
of the sun and moon above, scorch the refined essence of the mountains and rivers
below, and overturn the orderly progression of the four seasons in between. . . .
Deep, indeed, is the disorder brought to the world by the love of knowing!”7 While
this is clearly about human choice and freedom, Perkins perceptively comments:
“this is explained not in terms of free will but through a blend of desire and knowl
edge.”8 Is love of knowing, then, a bad thing, to be curbed? Tracing ecological de-
structiveness to the unbridled human desire for knowledge (haozhi 好知), Perkins
gives a radically new spin to the problem of free will that would be immensely rele-
vant to the contemporary tension between technology-driven science and environ-
mental ethics.9
In Sanskrit also, we have terms like svātantrya that stand for freedom, and terms
like kratu or kṛti that stand for will. And of course, for “freedom from” (bondage,
ignorance, suffering) Sanskrit has words, by now familiar to the West, such as mokṣa,
mukti, and apavarga. So, philologically we know where to look if we have to search
for discussions of the free will, agency, or freedom issue. But what we shall find when
we search carefully may well be something very different from the Western or mod-
3. Garfield’s Dismissal of the Free Will Issue as “The Question Does not Arise”
For example, Jay Garfield, one of the most provocative contributors to this volume,
in his brilliant chapter “Just Another Word for Nothing Left to Lose,” repeatedly as-
serts that the Free Will Problem — “How can human beings be held responsible for
their good and bad actions if they are just cogs in the inexorable causal machine
of nature?” — is an artifact of Augustinian Christianity. With some measure of vehe-
mence, Garfield argues that Western philosophy’s preoccupation with the free will
problem can be traced back to the twin presuppositions of choosy autonomous hu-
man agent-selves and of an omniscient God who eternally knows what each of those
selves will ever choose to do. Since Buddhism rejects both of these presuppositions,
the free will question simply does not arise, at least in Buddhist philosophy. And,
of course, the enlightened Nāgārjunian Buddhist is “free” in the minimal sense that
she is free from all clinging to essences, and she has “nothing left to lose.” It was eye-
opening for me to try to see, as Garfield writes, that “Everything that the post-
Augustinian libertarian West buys with the gold coin of the freedom of the will, along
with all of the metaphysical problems it raises, are bought by the Mādhyamika much
more cheaply with the paper currency of mere imputation” (chap. 7, p. 182).
But not all forms of the (“Western”) antinomy we discussed above are derived
from the metaphysical assumption of an agent-self and an omniscient creator God.
How could Garfield write “The will as we (seem to) know it is in fact the legacy of
St. Augustine, and for his struggle to solve the theodicy problem raised by the Fall of
Adam and Eve in Eden” (p. 165), when, as he himself shows that he well knows (on
page 168, he mentions Aristotle’s doctrine of choice as the cause of voluntary action)
that Aristotle devotes five chapters of his Nicomachean Ethics to the question of will,
Both the voluntary and the involuntary having been delimited, we must next discuss
choice; for it is thought to be most closely bound up with virtue and to discriminate char-
acters better than actions do.
Choice, then, seems to be voluntary, but not the same thing as the voluntary; the latter
extends more widely. For both children and the lower animals share in voluntary action,
but not in choice, and acts done on the spur of the moment we describe as voluntary, but
not as chosen. . . . Again, the incontinent man acts with appetite, but not with choice;
while the continent man on the contrary acts with choice, but not with appetite.10
Surely what Aristotle is grappling with here has nothing to do with God, Augustine,
or the biblical story of the Fall of Man, but has everything to do with at least one
version of the problem of choice, agency, and will in contemporary secular Western
moral psychology.
Garfield, who goes back to the historicist-Wittgensteinian diagnosis that the
problem of Free-will-versus-Determinism is a local pseudo-problem of Western
philosophy, that the Nāgārjunian Buddhist fly never got trapped in that particular
fly bottle, eventually shows how a skeptical Mādhyamika Buddhist response to
the Western/Christian problem of free will advances our understanding — and
dissolution — of the problem itself. Even if there was no philosophical discussion of
the free will versus determinism debate in Indian philosophy, now, thanks to this
volume, there is.
We shall see in a later section of this review that Karin Meyers, in the section of
her chapter 2 on “Karma, Free Will, and Moral Responsibility,” clearly does not quite
take Garfield’s route. Given the central doctrines of dependent origination and no-
self, the problem of free will, she says, is, in so many words “one worth thinking
about from a Buddhist perspective” (p. 46; emphasis hers).
4. The Mahābhārata’s Open-ended Way of Reckoning with the Problem of Free Will
Dasti and Bryant have invited contributions representing almost all schools of Indian
philosophy, but chose not to have any entry on the philosophy of the Mahābhārata
or of the Bhagavad Gītā (which is a small but crucial part of that philosophical epic).
I take this to be a moderately regrettable omission. Everyone who is acquainted with
the Vedic-Puranic literature knows that the Mahābhārata is not merely a long narra-
tive poem about a royal family feud turning into total war; it is treated by the tradition
as a philosophical commentary on the Vedas and Upanishads. The eighteen chapters
of the Bhagavad Gītā, for example, are best read, I submit, as an indirect commentary
on the eighteen verses of the Īśa Upanishad. Let me start and end this otherwise
congratulatory review with two bookends that are missing from the volume I am
showcasing as pathbreaking. First, very briefly, there is the complex problem-space
regarding freedom, determinism, agency, action, and inaction that is created by the
Mahābhārata and Bhagavad Gītā. Second — and I shall end the review with this — is
What exactly is the Western problem of free will such that in spite of such clear en-
gagement with the question of “Who did this wrong? Who is responsible” in the
classical philosophical epic Mahābhārata, very knowledgeable modern chroniclers
of Indian philosophy go on saying that in the Indian classical corpus of philosophy,
the problem of free will versus determinism is not discussed at all? Let us quickly
recast the Western debate in recognizably Indian terms.
No social human beings who care for dharma — the universal moral code for a
good life in any place or time or locale and age-and-community-specific codes of
piety — can live without judging their actions as good or bad, and blaming each other
for bad actions and regretting having done wrong. All of that presupposes that they
could have acted differently, that when they did something praise- or blameworthy
they acted freely. Yet, at least five different types of arguments can be given in support
of the exact opposite thesis that human action is never free action.
A. The first is a metaphysical argument. Every human action is an event in time.
Every event in time has a cause (as the Buddha’s central insight “dependent origi
nation” encapsulates). Whatever has a cause is determined by a strict causal law —
whether or not we are able in each case to discern what that law is. Whatever is
determined by a strict causal law is non-free, since given its antecedent events it
could not have happened otherwise. Therefore, every human action is causally de-
termined, which is to say that no human action is free.
B. The second is a logico-semantic argument, whose force is not so easy to feel.
It is beautifully summarized in the following Sanskrit verse from that gold mine of
ethical wisdom called “Pancatantra”: “Yad a-bhāvi na tad bhāvi, yad bhāvi na tad
anyathā / iti cintā-viṣaghno’yam agadah kim na pīyate?” (What is not-to-happen will
not happen, what is going to happen cannot be made otherwise. Why not drink this
potion that kills the poison of anxiety?) (Note that Pañcatantra calls this a lazy man’s
words: “iti keśāncit ālasya vacanam”). So, the argument goes like this: Any action
Anyone who says the Sanskrit word for “free” (svatantra) is untheorized in Indian
philosophy must be forgetting that Pān.ini (in the fourth century b.c.e.) defines an
agent or doer (kartā) as “One who is free” (svatantra, self-ruled). Bhartṛhari, the phi-
losopher of grammar, in explaining this idea of auto (sva)-nomous (tantra), in the
fourth–fifth century c.e., lays down six criteria of free agency:
(a) X is an autonomous agent if X started acting before drawing his strength from
other aiding factors, such as the instruments.
(b) X retains his preeminence by subjugating all other contributors to the action.
(c) The operations of all other causal factors are subject to the functioning of X.
(d) If X stops functioning, all the other conditions stop producing effects.
(e) X is irreplaceable or non-substitutable with any surrogate, such that even if
any other particular action-condition (e.g., the locus, instrument, the accusa-
tive) is missing or replaced, X has to be there for this action to be possible.
(f ) X can get the action done, even if indirectly from a distance, through its
influence over other more directly involved employed agents.
Unhappy with the Sāṃkhya position, Nyāya seeks to couple an eternal unchanging ātman
as a substance with separable changing qualities such as agency; Buddhism to jettison
notions of any eternal entities in the first place; and Advaita Vedānta of non-eternal ones;
and the theists to conclude that unresolvable philosophical problems of this sort mandate
the existence of an Īśvara who is beyond comprehension. All run into philosophical diffi-
culties of their own. (pp. 38–39)
Far from failing to find any awareness of the Free Will problem, notice how
this brief history of Indian philosophies makes them all go around the normative
voluntarism-versus-naturalistic causation issue. Finding or not finding a philosophi-
cal problem raised or not raised in a certain ancient tradition is just a matter of look-
ing with the appropriate search engine.
Karin Meyers seems to forget about the word centanā when she writes that early
Buddhists did not have a term equivalent to “free will” or any discrete faculty of the
will. In chapter 2, Meyers gives us a contemporary formulation of the early Buddhist
naturalized theory of karma (actions) done by empty persons who are reduced to
streams of interdependent ephemeral dharma (event-like factors). Her account re-
minds us of Charles Goodman’s syllogistic refutation of Paul Griffiths’ (whose view is
like Rick Repetti’s, which I mention approvingly below) libertarian interpretation of
the Buddhist theory of free will:
This claim puts Griffiths in a difficult position. If the parameters are all determined by
karma, then people’s actions must be caused by the parameters, by something else, or by
nothing. If actions are caused by the parameters, then they are determined. If they are
caused by nothing, they are utterly random, and therefore not free. If they are caused by
something else, this something else must either be the self or something other than the
self. If the something else is not the self, then either determinism or randomness will re-
sult. But the something else can’t be the self, because, according to Buddhists, there is no
self. Therefore, Griffiths’s interpretation is untenable.13
“What on that occasion is volition (cetanā)? The volition, purpose, purposefulness, which
is born of contact with the appropriate element of representative intellection — that is the
volition that there then is.” And Atthasalini: “Volition is that which co-ordinates. . . . [I]ts
function is conation. . . . It makes double effort, double exertion.”15
At one place, the Buddha describes himself thus: “I am one who tells what ac-
tions should be done as well as how to practice inaction” (kiriyāvādī cāhaṃ . . .
akiriyāvādī cā’ti).
In his learned chapter on Jainism Christopher Key Chapple presents Jaina philosophy
as taking a “thoroughly voluntarist” stance in the free will debate. Each of us poten-
tially omniscient pure souls finds ourselves covered in the unclean cloaks of karma.
But the good news, for the cleansing-oriented Jaina, is that each fettered soul can do
something autonomously to doff these layers of karmic cloaks. Karma binds us in
eight ways, we are told in this lucid exposition of Jainism: as knowledge-covering,
After the Buddhist denial of the self altogether, naturally comes the Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika
tradition of Indian thought where enduring and substantial self plays the most crucial
role. Dasti himself writes an intensively researched essay on this school’s treatment
of agency or doership of voluntary actions. He highlights three major points of the
Nyāya treatment of agency of an individual (unliberated) Ātman:
About the last point, I just wanted to alert the readers that Dasti never claims that
Nyāya regards jñāna (cognition) as an action. An awareness is a quality, not an ac-
tion. As Jayanta Bhaṭṭa argues against the Mīmāṃsaka, knowledge is a quality of the
self, whereas by “karma” Nyāya Vaiśeṣika only means physical motion in space,
which a Nyāya Ātman cannot initiate or undergo because it is literally ubiquitous in
size. But when a Nyāya self knowingly does something, it incurs or earns dharma or
adharma and is accountable for each of its conscious voluntary actions.
In the late twentieth century, Karl Potter, an analytic philosopher very much in
the New Nyāya tradition, defended and interpreted the karma doctrine as a response
to the problem of freedom versus determinism, in a series of now-classic essays.16
Since Dasti’s chapter does not include any discussion of Potter’s nuanced Nyāya
solution to the Free Will problem, let me fill in that gap here in this review. Karl
Potter has famously called the karma theory an a priori presupposition of all Indian
metaphysics of morals, and yet he does not think that the individual’s actions are
11. Mīmāṃsā and Advaita Vedānta: Opposition between Vita Activa and
Vita Contemplativa?
First action, then contemplation! In spite of the fact that both Mīmāṃsā and
(Advaita) Vedānta come under the general rubric of Vedic Exegesis, insofar as the
former gives an account of active ethical life, and the latter of contemplative spiritual
life, their positions on the free will question seem to be diametrically opposed, at
least according to Sthaneshwar Timalsina. If Pūrva (prior) Mīmāṃsā vindicates Vita
Activa, the Advaita stream of Uttara (posterior) Mīmāṃsā, which rejects any rele-
vance or efficacy of work or ritual performance of duties toward final liberation,
promotes pure Vita Contemplativa: the purely intellectual-meditative path of inac-
tion that recommends the self’s total identification with the disinterested-witness
consciousness. The individual self is ontologically identical to the universal im-
But Advaita is not the only stream of Vedānta. It is Martin Ganeri’s interpretation in
chapter 10, that Rāmānuja (born 1017 c.e.), the Qualified Non-Dualist Vedāntin,
sounds like a moderate libertarian when he writes “each finite self is a real agent that
exercises genuine freedom of will, in opposition to both Advaita Vedānta and Sam-
khya traditions” (p. 233). Rāmānuja’s ethic of surrender to God as the only initiative
human beings are obligated to take makes it our epistemic duty to understand how
God is the complete controller of all our inner and outer actions. Under this un
limited freedom of God, we have the limited freedom to relinquish our agency to the
imperative of devotion, which is nothing but full recognition of our utter dependence
on God.
The stances of Dualist Vedānta of Mādhva and Gaudīya Vaiśṇava Metaphysics
are naturally similar on the question of the limited freedom of human individuals,
under the sovereign sway of divine will. Only the Supreme Lord is truly independent
and autonomous; the causally operative action-propelling will of the human individ-
ual is under the overall control of the Lord. And using the Brahamsūtra’s common
theodicy, “Madhva takes recourse to the beginninglessness of karma to exempt the
(i) When the embodied but conscious self acts under the magic spell of māyā,
it makes the mind-body complex move but under the permissive oversight of
the Lord/God.
(ii) Such embodied agency should be looked upon as the individuals’ inherent
servitude to God, and therefore a mere expression of God’s own power of
consciousness.
(iii) When this self merges back into God in apparent non-duality, agency re-
mains as an unutilized potential quality.
(iv) Agency in the emancipated realm of Vaikuntha is manifested through a per-
fected celestial body.
Notes