1 1 Fassin
1 1 Fassin
1 1 Fassin
RI/LIH
Didier Fassin
3XEOLVKHGE\8QLYHUVLW\RI3HQQV\OYDQLD3UHVV
DOI: 10.1353/hum.2010.0000
What is the human? One way to confront this question has been, since antiquity, to
distinguish the human from the animal, or rather to ask how humans are not just
animals. It is well known that Aristotle’s answer was to affirm that ‘‘man is by nature
a political animal’’ and that speech—or language—yields him this exclusive quality by
giving him ‘‘a sense of good and evil, of just and unjust.’’1 During the twentieth
century, this question about the human has been reformulated, in a philosophical
lineage from Walter Benjamin to Hannah Arendt to Giorgio Agamben, into a
question about ‘‘life,’’ sometimes even rephrased in terms of ‘‘biopolitics’’—or more
precisely, as I have argued, of ‘‘politics of life.’’2 The distinction between man and
animal has thus become a difference between physical or biological life, which man
has in common with the rest of the animal kingdom, and social or political, life, which
renders him unique.
Born from the experience of two world wars and two totalitarianisms, this reading
of the human condition recently took a tragic turn and a radical form which became
central in the analysis of the situation of the refugees and the displaced, the poor and
the dominated, with the camp presented as the biopolitical figure par excellence. In
light of what can be considered as Jacques Derrida’s legacy, but also of my fieldwork
in townships and former homelands in South Africa, I will discuss here this vision of
the politics of life which has exerted an increasing influence in the humanities and
social sciences during the last decade, and I will propose an alternative reading.
‘‘Long before the experience of survival that I am presently facing, I wrote that
survival is an original concept which constitutes the very structure of what we call
existence. We are, structurally speaking, survivors, marked by this structure of the
trace, of the testament. That said, I would not endorse the view according to which
survival is more on the side of death and the past than of life and the future. No,
deconstruction is always on the side of the affirmation of life.’’3 A few weeks before
his death, Jacques Derrida gave his last interview in which he developed at length his
conception of life as survival. Suffering from a terminal disease, he confided: ‘‘Since
certain health problems are becoming more pressing, the question of survival and
reprieve, which has always haunted me, literally, every moment of my life, in a
concrete and tireless way, takes on a different color today.’’ In reference to a sentence
he had used in one of his books (‘‘I would finally like to know how to live’’) he
81
commented with a penetrating irony: ‘‘No, I never learned to live. Definitely not!
Learning to live should mean learning to die. I never learned to accept death. I remain
impervious to being educated in the wisdom of knowing how to die.’’
However, beyond the emergency of this ‘‘shrinking time of reprieve’’ (which he
rejected with humor, saying, ‘‘we are not here for a health bulletin’’), it is the more
general problem of survival on which the philosopher wanted to meditate: ‘‘I have
always been interested in the question of survival, the meaning of which does not add
to life and death. It is originary: life is survival.’’ In fact, both dimensions were for
him intimately related, the personal experience repeating the existential experience,
the circumstantial ordeal making the structural reality more evident and more painful.
How else to understand that on the verge of death, thinking about survival could
become so insistent in this interview, until the final profession of faith? ‘‘Everything I
say about survival as a complication of the opposition between life and death proceeds
from an unconditional affirmation of life. Survival is life beyond life, life more than
life, and the discourse I undertake is not about death. On the contrary, it is the
affirmation of a living being who prefers life and therefore survival to death, because
survival is not simply what remains; it is the most intense life possible.’’
I want to show that Derrida’s conception of life as survival, in its polysemy and
even its ambiguity, may offer an alternative to conceptions of life which, from
Benjamin to Agamben, and in a quite different perspective, from Lamarck to Can-
guilhem, have presented a seductive dualistic framework for the humanities and social
sciences. Both visions are inherited from Aristotle. On the one hand, life is presented
as biopolitical fact: ‘‘Behind the long strife-ridden process that leads to the recognition
of rights and formal liberties stands the body of the sacred man with his double
sovereign, his life that cannot be sacrificed yet may be killed,’’ affirms Giorgio
Agamben in Homo Sacer, where he develops his theory of ‘‘bare life.’’4 From the
‘‘politicization of life’’ in totalitarian systems to the ‘‘isolation of the sacred life’’ in
contemporary democracies, he therefore establishes a continuum of the power over
life. On the other hand, life is conceived as a biological phenomenon: ‘‘any datum of
experience possible to trace as a history comprised between its birth and its death is
living, is the object of biological knowledge,’’ writes Georges Canguilhem for the entry
‘‘Life’’ in the Encyclopedia Universalis.5 He presents life successively as ‘‘animation,’’
‘‘mechanism,’’ ‘‘organization,’’ and ‘‘information,’’ in a chronological review of
biological theories extending from ancient conceptions to contemporary
genetics—and everyone knows that the genome is often said to be the ‘‘code of life.’’
In other words, these two readings present life as what can be put to death (for
Agamben), and as what is comprised from birth to death (for Canguilhem). The social
sciences have largely drawn from these two repertoires: the former has been used to
comprehend the government of populations and human beings; the latter has nour-
ished the sociology and anthropology of sciences and techniques. However different
they may be, these two models rest on the same premises. Both treat life as a physical
phenomenon, whether it is ‘‘bare life’’ or ‘‘biological life’’ (both philosophers insisting
that it is the dimension shared with the entire animal kingdom). And both assume
that life can be separated, for scientific or political reasons, from life as an existential
phenomenon, whether it is called ‘‘qualified life’’ or ‘‘lived experience’’ (by Agamben
Genealogy
‘‘To survive, in the usual sense of the word, is to continue to live, but also to live after
death,’’ Derrida explains in his last interview, adding: ‘‘Speaking of translation,
Benjamin underlines the distinction between überleben, to live after death, as a book
Mere life
In his essay ‘‘The Task of the Translator,’’ Benjamin proposes this surprising
parallel: ‘‘Just as the manifestations of life are intimately connected with the
phenomenon of life without being of importance to it, a translation issues from the
original—not so much from its life than from its afterlife.’’7 There is therefore a life
of the original and a survival through its ‘‘translation,’’ but also through its
‘‘glory’’—and more generally a life that escapes materiality, a life that is ‘‘not limited
to organic corporeality.’’ This intuition allows him to shift from literary work to a
more general reflection on life: ‘‘In the final analysis, the range of life must be deter-
mined by history rather than by nature. The philosopher’s task consists in compre-
hending all of natural life through the more encompassing life of history.’’ What is
true for the work of art is also true for the human being. The full recognition of his
life lies in this history where nature is inscribed. Biography prevails over biology, and
history over nature.
Two years earlier, however, Benjamin had published another article, titled
‘‘Critique of Violence,’’ which ended with a discussion of life in reference to revolu-
tionary violence: ‘‘The proposition that existence stands higher than just existence is
false and ignominious, if existence means nothing more than mere life.’’8 He later
expands on this distinction: ‘‘Man cannot, at any price, be said to coincide with the
mere life in him, no more than any other of his conditions and qualities, not even
with the uniqueness of his bodily person.’’ In other words, ‘‘however sacred man is,’’
it cannot be a consequence of his ‘‘bodily life,’’ as implied in the ‘‘dogma of the
sacredness of life.’’ This is why, for Benjamin, not all violence should be condemned:
if ‘‘lawmaking violence,’’ which is ‘‘executive,’’ and ‘‘law-preserving violence,’’ which
‘‘serves it,’’ are ‘‘pernicious,’’ he writes, then by contrast, violence exerted over other
men for a superior good may be necessary, since it is respectful of life, not as ‘‘mere
life’’ but as ‘‘that life that is identically present in earthly life, death, and afterlife.’’
There is something in life that is not reducible to its physical dimension but includes
and exceeds it.
The formulation of the concept of ‘‘mere life,’’ as contrasted with ‘‘just life,’’ and
the critique of ‘‘the sanctity of life,’’ as opposed to the ‘‘sacredness of man,’’ have
given birth to numerous comments and to a philosophical descent that has nourished
a tragic perspective in the humanities and social sciences. We should take its measure
and consider its consequences. First, it establishes a distinction in the sacredness of
the human between the uniqueness of the bodily person and the continuity of his or
her life beyond this material dimension. Second, it institutes a hierarchy between the
Life itself
An admirer of Benjamin whose work she prefaced, Hannah Arendt positioned the
question of life at the center of her interpretation of the French Revolution: ‘‘Behind
the appearances was a reality, and this reality was biological and not historical, though
it appeared now perhaps for the first time in history.’’ This biological theory of revolu-
tionary movements, which is explicitly a critique of Marxism, is more complex than
it seems. On the one hand, Arendt conceives of it as the production of a social body:
‘‘The biological imagery underlies and pervades the organic and social theories of
history, which all have in common that they see a multitude—the factual plurality of
a nation or a people or society—in the image of a supernatural body driven by one
superhuman, irresistible, general will.’’ On the other hand, Arendt sees the physical
force as the ultimate justification of revolutionary violence: ‘‘It was under the rule of
this necessity that the multitude rushed to the assistance of the French Revolution,
inspired it, drove it onward, and eventually sent it to its doom, for this was the
multitude of the poor.’’ There is therefore implicitly a dual dimension in this theory
of life as the source of the revolution. It is organicist (the unified multitude) and
materialist (the pressing necessity) at once: ‘‘This raging force may well nigh appear
irresistible because it lives from and is nourished by the necessity of biological life
itself.’’ Associating both dimensions, Marx ‘‘strengthened more than anybody else the
politically most pernicious doctrine of the modern age, namely that life is the highest
good, and that the life process of society is the very center of human endeavor.’’ Also
a critic of the sacralization of life, Arendt however dissociates herself from Benjamin
by her rejection of Marxist theory from which he drew his theory of history. Indeed,
between the two, the Leninist project has turned into the Stalinist totalitarianism, the
crimes of which are increasingly acknowledged.9
The analysis of the human condition that Hannah Arendt presented two years
earlier adopts a less dramatic position. ‘‘Vita activa,’’ distinguished from ‘‘vita contem-
plativa,’’ comprises three components: labor, work, and action. Even as the philos-
opher attempts to grasp ‘‘the ever-recurrent cyclical movement of nature,’’ she
immediately adds: ‘‘The birth and death of human beings are not simple natural
occurrences, but are related to a world into which single individuals, unique, unex-
changeable, and unrepeatable entities, appear and from which they depart.’’ Nietz-
sche’s eternal recurrence of mankind is only possible under this condition: the survival
of humanity occurs through the birth and death of human beings, who are unique, in
other words, irreducible to their natural existence. The two dimensions are indisso-
ciable. On the one hand, life, ‘‘limited by a beginning and an end, follows a strictly
linear movement whose very motion nevertheless is driven by the motor of biological
life which man shares with other living things and which forever retains the cyclical
movement of nature.’’ On the other hand, life, ‘‘specifically human, is itself full of
Bare life
Relying on the same philosophical corpus, Giorgio Agamben follows a quite
distinct path in his inquiry on homo sacer. This ‘‘figure of the archaic Roman law in
which the character of sacredness is tied for the first time to a human life as such’’
signifies that certain criminals may be considered as human beings whose ritual killing
is forbidden but whose possible murder is covered by impunity. This paradox of the
homo sacer becomes the point of departure of a profound reflection on ‘‘sovereign
power and bare life,’’ with a parallel drawn between the king’s body and the refugee’s
condition. According to Agamben, these extreme cases—the power of the former and
the vulnerability of the latter—are inscribed in the long history of the politicization
of physical life and of a sovereignty founded on exception. Following Arendt’s propo-
sition, Agamben radicalizes the Aristotelian distinction. On the one hand, he accen-
tuates differences and hardens significations: he contrasts zoē, ‘‘the simple fact of living
common to all living beings,’’ which is ‘‘excluded from the polis in the strict sense and
remains confined to the sphere of the oikos,’’ with bios, ‘‘the way of living proper to
an individual or a group,’’ which is also a ‘‘qualified life, a particular way of life.’’
Between the two, no possible path is envisaged. On the other hand, he underscores,
almost contradictorily, the confusion: ‘‘politics appears as the truly fundamental
structure of Western metaphysics insofar as it occupies the threshold on which the
relation between the living being and the logos is realized’’; consequently, ‘‘in the
politicization of bare life, the humanity of living man is decided.’’ Thus the Western
world is marked, from its very origin, by the inscription of biological life in the heart
of political life. This aporia of separation and confusion of bios and zoē would
therefore be the ultimate truth of our modernity: ‘‘The decisive fact is that, together
with the process by which the exception everywhere becomes the rule, the realm of
bare life gradually begins to coincide with the political realm, and exclusion and
inclusion, outside and inside, bios and zoē, right and fact, enter in a zone of irreducible
indistinction.’’ Homo sacer, long ago confined to the margins of society, is thus
presented as the central figure of our world.11
Continuing this first exploration of the relation between life and politics, Agamben
offers a second inquiry dealing with the state of exception, which he conceives as ‘‘the
Biographies
‘‘We are all survivors on reprieve (and from a geopolitical point of view, the emphasis
is mostly, in a more unequal world than ever, on the billions of living beings—human
or not—who are denied not only the basic ‘human rights’ which go back two hundred
years ago and are increasingly expanded, but also the right to a life worth living).’’
This aside is quite noteworthy in Jacques Derrida’s last interview, which is otherwise
essentially personal. Nevertheless, it is not surprising given his commitments to
Conclusion
Survival, in the sense Jacques Derrida attributed to the concept in his last interview,
not only shifts lines that are too often hardened between biological and political lives:
it opens an ethical space for reflection and action. Critical thinking in the past decade
has often taken biopolitics and the politics of life as its objects. It has thus unveiled
the way in which individuals and groups, even entire nations, have been treated by
powers, the market, or the state, during the colonial period as well as in the contem-
porary era.
However, through indiscriminate extension, this powerful instrument has lost
some of its analytical sharpness and heuristic potentiality. On the one hand, the binary
reduction of life to the opposition between nature and history, bare life and qualified
life, when systematically applied from philosophical inquiry in sociological or anthro-
pological study, erases much of the complexity and richness of life in society as it is in
fact observed. On the other hand, the normative prejudices which underlie the evalu-
ation of the forms of life and of the politics of life, when generalized to an undifferen-
tiated collection of social facts, end up by depriving social agents of legitimacy, voice,
and action. The risk is therefore both scholarly and political. It calls for ethical atten-
tion.
In fact, the genealogy of this intellectual lineage reminds us that the main founders
of these theories expressed tensions and hesitations in their work, which was often
more complex, if even sometimes more obscure, than in its reduced and translated
form in the humanities and social sciences today. And also biographies, here limited
to fragments from South African lives that I have described and analyzed in more
detail elsewhere, suggest the necessity of complicating the dualistic models that oppose
biological and political lives. Certainly, powers like the market and the state do act
sometimes as if human beings could be reduced to ‘‘mere life,’’ but democratic forces,
including from within the structure of power, tend to produce alternative strategies
that escape this reduction. And people themselves, even under conditions of domi-
NOTES
* This text began as a paper titled ‘‘Survivre’’ I wrote for the posthumous homage paid to
Jacques Derrida on December 11, 2004, at the Ecole des hautes études en sciences sociales in Paris.
It extends its initial honorific intention to engage a reflection around his last thoughts. I am
grateful to Linda Garat for her thorough copy-editing of the manuscript.
1. Aristotle, Politics, trans. Benjamin Jowett (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1908), I, 1253a, 28–29.
2. The concept of biopolitics appears in Michel Foucault’s work in the mid-1970s, most
notably in the last chapter of The History of Sexuality, vol. 1, An Introduction, trans. Robert Hurley
(New York: Pantheon, 1978). I have shown that biopolitics as he conceived it had little to do with
politics of life, in ‘‘La biopolitique n’est pas une politique de la vie,’’ Sociologie et Sociétés 38, no. 2
(2003): 35–48.
3. The interview was published in Le Monde, August 19, 2004, under the title ‘‘Je suis en
guerre contre moi-même’’ (‘‘I Am at War with Myself ’’). It was translated in English by Robert
Knafo and appeared as Jacques Derrida: The Last Interview (New York: Studio Visit, 2004). The
excerpts I cite are, however, my own—more literal—translation from the original text.
4. It is well known that the statement of ‘‘an inner solidarity between democracy and totalitar-
ianism’’ has been quite controversial in Agamben, Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life,
trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1998), 10.
5. It is remarkable that the only entry for ‘‘life’’ in the Encyclopedia universalis (Paris: Editions
Encyclopedia Universalis, 1990) concerns the sole dimension of the living from the perspective of
biological sciences, just as it is noticeable that the French Dictionnaire d’éthique et de philosophie
morale, ed. Monique Canto-Sperber (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1996), has no entry
for the word ‘‘life,’’ as if there was no ethical or moral dimension to the concept of life.
6. According to Canguilhem, it is necessary to differentiate ‘‘the present and past participles
of the verb to live,’’ in other words, between ‘‘the living and the lived’’ (le vivant et le vécu). For
Agamben, referring to Plato’s and Aristotle’s supposed distinction, bios is opposed to zoē as the
‘‘qualified life’’ to the ‘‘bare life.’’
7. Walter Benjamin, ‘‘The Task of the Translator,’’ in Illuminations, trans. Harry Zohn (New
York: Harcourt, Brace and World, 1968), 71.
8. Benjamin, ‘‘Critique of Violence,’’ in Reflections: Essays, Aphorisms, Autobiographical
Writing, trans. Edmund Jephcott (New York: Harcourt, Brace, 1978), 299–300.
9. Hannah Arendt, On Revolution, rev. ed. (New York: Viking Press, 1965), 53–54, 108. As is
well known, Arendt wrote the introduction to the English edition of Benjamin’s Illuminations.