Owen G. E. L. - Eleatic Questions
Owen G. E. L. - Eleatic Questions
Owen G. E. L. - Eleatic Questions
Author(s): G. E. L. Owen
Source: The Classical Quarterly, Vol. 10, No. 1 (May, 1960), pp. 84-102
Published by: Cambridge University Press on behalf of The Classical Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/637593
Accessed: 14-03-2018 15:54 UTC
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
Cambridge University Press, The Classical Association are collaborating with JSTOR to
digitize, preserve and extend access to The Classical Quarterly
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ELEATIC QUESTIONS
THE following suggestions for the interpretation of Parmenides and M
can be grouped for convenience about one problem. This is the
whether, as Aristotle thought and as most commentators still assu
menides wrote his poem in the broad tradition of Ionian and Italian c
The details of Aristotle's interpretation have been challenged over and
but those who agree with his general assumptions take comfort from
all of the following major arguments. First, the cosmogony which fo
last part of Parmenides' poem is expressly claimed by the goddess
pounds it to have some measure of truth or reliability in its own rig
indeed the very greatest measure possible for such an attempt. Se
earlier arguments of the goddess prepare the ground for such a co
in two ways. For in the first place these arguments themselves st
assumptions derived from earlier cosmologists, and are concerned me
work out the implications of this traditional material. And, in the seco
they end by establishing the existence of a spherical universe: the fr
of the physical world can be secured by logic even if the subsequent
tion of sensible qualities or 'powers' into this world marks some d
logical rigour.
These views seem to me demonstrably false. As long as they are allo
stand they obscure the structure and the originality of Parmenides' a
(B I. 28-32. In the first instance I shall quote fragments from the text of
Diels-Kranz.)
Thus the final couplet follows a sharp denunciation of Pfpoirv 8dea, and
subsequently this denunciation is driven home. When the goddess comes to
the promised account of mortal ideas she calls it by the phrase which Em-
pedocles took as a challenge--Ko'rZov TL6V E TE'7WV r 7Ta7r7qAdv (B 8. 52, cf. Emped.
B 17. 26). And it is certainly this same way of inquiry that she bars to her
hearer in B 6. 4-9, and B 7. 1-5 : the way of mortals who know nothing, who
' Contra those who follow Bernays in 183-4), though this path is the 'wholly un-
identifying this, the second of the false paths intelligible' line of sheer negation (B 2. 5) : a
denounced by the goddess, with the theories preposterous equation that he did not try to
of Heraclitus, and so have to distinguish it make plausible. The second false path is the
from the unheraclitean cosmology expounded error not of Heraclitus but of all men: see the
in the last part of the poem. This thesis led second section of this paper and Verdenius,
Burnet to identify the cosmology with the Parmenides, app. J; Jaeger, Theology of the
first false path (Early Greek Philosophy,4 pp. Early Greek Philosophers, p. ioi ; Kirk,
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ELEATIC QUESTIONS 85
it is given simply bs ob ~oi-q orE 71o fp opoi-cwv yvuoC1q7 rapEAd'u- (B 8. 61), though
these are still the same witless mortals, men at the mercy of the words they use
(B 6. 4-7; B 8. 38-41, 53; B 9). So, on this construing of the lines, no onto-
logical claims have been made and the cosmology need be no more than
a dialectical device.
Nor, again, can any reality be conjured into the world of appearance from
the ambiguous couplet B 8. 53-54. 'Mortals decided to name two forms, of
which it is not right to name one-and there they went astray': whether or
not these words are meant to show that, as Aristotle supposed, one of the forms
which dominate the cosmogony is logically respectable, what is certain and
agreed is that the question cannot be settled from the obscure text. The inter-
pretation of that text itself depends on the answer we give to our general
problem.5 So the saving qualification is still to seek.
Hence the importance of the couplet which ends the passage quoted above
(B I. 31-32); for since Wilamowitz many interpreters have thought that on its
most natural interpretation it expressly promises some sort or degree of reality
to the contents of the cosmology.
The sole authority for the couplet is Simplicius, and he quotes it together
Heraclitus: the Cosmic Fragments, p. 21 I. Toexplanation is given below, pp. 90-92 and p.
take this path is to suppose that to be and not
91, n. 3. Both the points queried by V. are
to be are the same and not the same (B 6. 8-9:
essential to Parmenides' criticism: ordinary
for the negative in rd o'K dEraL cf. B 8. 40,men not only want to keep both elvaL and
where it cannot be explained as oratio OVK ELvaL; in trying to distinguish them they
obliqua). Gregory Vlastos, to whom I amconfuse them. That is why both expressions
indebted for making me reinforce and re-in their ordinary use are empty names (B 8.
consider my argument at some salient points, 38-41).
argues: 'Those who deny any allusion to 1 o80 roAdviEtpov, B 7. 3, for which Calo-
Heraclitus in Parmenides . . . have yet to gero suggests 'l'esperienza della molteplicith
explain why in these lines Parmenides should delle cose' (Studi sull'Eleatismo, p. 32 n. I);
(a) impute to anyone the belief in the identity but if the adjective is rroAv7rrEtpos it is better
of being and not-being (rather than merely taken with the accompanying ac. Perhaps
the belief in not-being, which is bad enoughfrom 7roAvrerpwv, 'widespread'.
. . .) and (b) after saying otf ~ rr TEdAE ~TE Kati 2 Hermes, xxxiv (1899), 204-5.
OVK Lvat 7ra,7TrV vEvdoltaraL here, which
Verdenius, op. cit., pp. 50-51.
would be quite sufficient to make his point, 4 Ibid., citing Odyssey 3. 124-5 and 4. 239
should add maliciously KO~ 7rat-7rv, producing(cf. 266).
the expression -ra'-r'dv KOV -ra7ro'v, which so s Cf. Kirk and Raven, Presocratic Philo-
sophers, p. 281 n. I, and by contrast Vlastos,
strikingly parallels OAa Kat ov'x jAa in Hera-
clitus' (A.J.P. lxxvi [1955], 341 n. I ). TheTrans. Am. Philol. Assn. lxxvii (1946), 74-
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
86 G. E. L. OWEN
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ELEATIC QUESTIONS 87
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
88 G. E. L. OWEN
promises "AA' rpnjr Kal T'a-ra taLOraEac her -ra-a is naturally taken to refer to
the previous line. It means just 'the contents of mortal opinions'.3 There is no
true belief found among such opinions, nevertheless Parmenides shall be told
these things too. And then without a connective the sentence continues: as -ra
be epexegetic, elaborating the -araTa: and ,amv'a, on the natural reading, are
the contents of human opinions. So the sense is: Still, you shall learn (at
second-hand from me) these things too (sc. the content of mortal opinions),
namely (still at second-hand and giving the general content of those opinions)
how the things-that-seem had to have genuine existence (8oKLtow Edvat in the
only possible sense), being indeed the whole of things'4-or, if we read crEp6vra,
'. .. and to pervade everything without exception'.
To be sure, the twist of sense on which I have laid stress-the twist that
forced Kranz to supply 'und zwar'-might also have been avoided by denying
that -rava looks back to the preceding line. We might have held, as Diels and
others have done, that the whole couplet is concerned with the goddess's own
comment on mortal opinions. But if we say this all the old puzzles are restored.
The only people who can say of the 8OKOVTra that and how they 8OKLtLWS exist
are the mortals who believe in them (B, 8. 38), not the goddess.
If this is correct, the choice between rrEp v-ra and rrEpvra depends on a last
of 'Pherecydes', Diog. Laert. I. I22. Hesy-2 Verdenius, Parmenides, p. 49.
3 raira after 8Gdas is of course no obstacle:
chius gives SOKL/tLw SOKEcW, o0opat. Cf. Gow
on Theocritus 30. 25 (apparently misread
cf. e.g. Od. 3. 124-5-
by LSJ. s.v.). 4 rTEp as vel, cf. Denniston, Greek Particles,z
Reinhardt, op. cit., pp. 7-9. PP. 482, 484-
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ELEATIC QUESTIONS 89
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
9o G. E. L. OWEN
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ELEATIC QUESTIONS 91
together with the remaining right road,
answers to the question E07u-Lv o)K orw;
is an unqualified yes. The first wrong p
this is rebutted at the start by the argum
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
92 G. E. L. OWEN
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ELEATIC QUESTIONS 93
or vice versa, o~7Ws " I rdCrt-9 ay 7TEAEvaL XPEcWV ErTrLV o?xt (B 8. I) ; and then the
second alternative is ruled out as unintelligible (B 8. 15-18). So the proof has
allegedly been given that the subject exists rr7ad4rav or cdo'ov, unqualifiedly,
without intermission; and this is exactly the premiss required to prove that it is
indivisible and single. Moreover, the form and placing of the rE'rl'-clause in B
8. 22 show that it takes up a conclusion previously established. For Parmenides'
train of argument in B 8 breaks into four main stages which are clearly dis-
tinguished and correctly ordered in the programme given at the start,' and
each succeeding movement is introduced by an drEl-clause which, in the other
cases at least, shows how the new argument depends on a proposition already
proved. (Thus in the third movement B 8. 27 looks back to B 8. 6-2I and
especially to line 21 ; and in the fourth B 8. 42 looks back to B 8. 26-33 and
especially to lines 26 and 3o-31.2) As we might expect, then, the second stage
of the argument-the proof of unity and continuity in lines 22-25-is no more
an isolated and unargued pronouncement than the other stages. The unity of
the subject is proved, not assumed ab initio.
It is worth noticing that all but the first of these reasons for reading Er'rc
doCotov could be satisfied by an alternative explanation of the lines which would
leave pLoLov predicative. (But the first seems to me inescapable.) Up to this
point the argument has been concerned only with variation in time: the sense
in which it has been shown that the subject adclprav hEAE-rat is just that it has no
temporal boundaries, no ydvEoLS or jAEOpoS. Now this is just the sense that
Melissus later gave to ray nivjot'ov,3 and the words can be construed in the same
way in B 8. 22 without at all affecting the proposed interpretation. The fact
that, on either version, the argument for continuity in lines 22-25 depends on
the prior elimination of temporal starts and stops in lines 6-21 is of the first
importance for understanding that argument, and we shall come back to it in
another context. For the present we have sufficient grounds for dismissing these
attempts to saddle Parmenides' argument with a subject from earlier cos-
mology.
(c) But there is a subject. Some interpreters gave up the quest for a subject.
Hermann Fraenkel suggested that 'the lOcrw is primarily used by Parmenides
as a so-called impersonal, somewhat like "it rains" = "raining takes place" '.4
But this move, soundly antiseptic as it is, is unconvincing because Parmenides
goes on to prove various characteristics of the subject of his Er-wv. To supply
that subject we have to repeat our question: What must it be from the start if it is
to satisfy the demands of the argument ? If it is not assumed to be existent and
indivisible, what is it assumed to be ? And the answer is clear and, I think, of
great interest. The goddess maintains that to the question 'Does it exist?'
See the Additional Note, p. Ioi below. 4 Class. Philol. xli (1946), 169, criticizing
2 On this see the third section of the paper. Verdenius's suggestion that the subject is
3 Melissus B 7 = Simplicius, Phys. 1III. 'All that exists, the total of things'. Cf.
22-23 Diels (cf. I 12. 3-4): Et yap rTEpOLOV6raL Calogero, Studi, p. 18; Kirk and Raven,
dvdyKr 7 gv L oov d volOV at,A a$7ToAAdUtvaOa Presocratic Philosophers, p. 269.
-ro rpoov EOdv, r S' OVK EOv yw'EcOat.
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
94 G. E. L. OWEN
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ELEATIC QUESTIONS 95
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
96 G. E. L. OWEN
TO KEV 7"TavO uV ;KVELcOaL ElS topoV is neither more nor less dynamic than the
earlier TO KEV ElpyOL ptv uvve'XECOaL . .. .C3v ydp eovdr 7TE0Aa ELt: the primary sense
of 7eAdELV, like that of lKVE~LaOat, is one of movement, but the reason why either
verb is preferred to a more static counterpart must, here as elsewhere in the
argument, be one of style and not of content.4 The same holds good of the
later conclusion, ptc's- v Terpagt KVpEL (B 8. 49), even if we read this as though
it were dyKVpEL Trdpaot ('gleichmi1Big begegnet es seinen Grenzen', Kranz); but
probably KV'pE has its weaker, copulative sense. Yet this very phrase engenders
doubts about the parallel I have tried to draw between the arguments. How can
faced squarely the question 'Is thinking of the same at Soph. 248 d-249 a in making the
being a part of being?' Plato implies that Eleatic Stranger say that if reality contains
he had not; for Parmenides constantly life and soul and understanding it cannot be
couples thinking and naming (B 2. 7-8; dKwV77ToV Ea0Tg.
B 8. 17; B 8. 35-36), and in Soph. 244 c-d ' Wege und Formen, pp. 186-97.
Plato argues that Parmenides does not face a 2 Empedocles B 62. 6.
dilemma in the relation of -r6 'v to its name: 3 Studi, p. 27 and n. i.
are there after all two things in existence or 4 The 4AA 0"ea is full of metaphors of
is the name a name of nothing? This is in movement and arrested movement: motion
effect the same problem as whether the on a path comes often (including the puzzling
vdo'pLa is distinct from or identical with -rn B 5), and arrested motion in B 6. 3; B 7. 3;
EodV, and (for what this is worth) Plato im- B 8. 13-15 and 37. Cf. L. Woodbury, Harvard
plies that it had not been faced. He implies Studies in Class. Philol. lxiii (1958), I54-
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ELEATIC QUESTIONS 97
is taken must
quently from carry
the refutation
a temporalofsense.
yE'vEaTL and ,AEOpos
Secondly, that precedes
this application it,pre-
of the and conse-
ceding conclusion is clearly called for. For when it has been argued that the
subject has neither beginning nor end in time it still remains to draw the corol-
laries, that there can be neither a succession of separate entities nor inter-
nal change in any one entity; and these corollaries are drawn in B 8. 22
and 23-24 respectively. Thirdly, the temporal import of the argument at its
first occurrence is proved, not only by its being embedded in a context of
temporal argument that reaches to B 8. 33, but by the fact that when Par-
menides comes to resume the conclusions reached at B 8. 34-41 he mentions
only ideas of temporal change (lines 40-41, where the only exception is
clval TE Kat o0Vt, and these are present because their misuse is taken to be basic
to the other errors). Moreover, that avVXE's can have a temporal sense needs
no arguing,z and that it must have it here is shown again by the couplet which
introduces the refutation of yE'VErs: ov3'' ror' v ov03' ETaL, E'Err VV EUTL
FLoD T(V a, V , aUVEXEs-. rtva ydp yEvvav St>7aEaL a'vTroo; (B 8. 5-6). Thus one
of our difficulties is resolved: Parmenides' reason for repeating the continuity-
argument is that it is applied first in a temporal sense and then in a spatial.
The next section of the argument (B 8. 26-33) remains within this temporal
framework. It begins a'r'p adKVwT7qrov "LEYa AWV V6 ITEIpaLtL ETL6~V E"u-v vap ov
Jdravorov, and thereby shows that in its turn it is applying the conclusions
See the Additional Note, p. ioi below. this passage but the whole treatment of
2 And if avveXcs then also in this context temporal variation is couched in spatial
its opposite, 8taper'dv. (Thus Aristotle, main- metaphor (the impossibility of any different
taining against Parmenides that continuity state of affairs is pictured as being chained to
does not preclude but always entails divisi- one place, B 8. 14-15, 26-27, 30-3 , 37-38) ;
bility, can say that time and any process in and Parmenides wants to keep open the pos-
time is avvEx',s and therefore taLtperos, Phys. sibility of a spatial application of the same
Z 2. 232b23-26 et al.) In this setting of arguments. (Karsten, pointing to the sin-
temporal continuity it is natural to explain gularity of i7- here without an answering
that -r in line 23, which is commonly read adverb and observing that the necessary
as implying an answering 7r in 24, must have contrast is carried by L ... rL ..., emended
not its spatial sense but its wider meaning, so as to excise it; Stein proposed 7r7,
'in this respect' (Empedocles B 26. io); plausibly in view of the source of contamina-
but I doubt if Parmenides wants wholly to tion in B 8. 45 and 48.)
Jose the spatial metaphor in r-S, for not only
H
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
98 G. E. L. OWEN
Similarly, to say that the subject of the argument is o0K d)c 7EAEro70V (B 8.
32) is not to say that it has frontiers, as opposed to stretching ad infinitum. The
sense of it is just that, since we cannot talk of what does not exist, we cannot say
that there is still something lacking which could be supplied by any change.
But this formulation, like Parmenides' own, is ambiguous, and the ambiguity
gives him his transition to the final spatial conclusions in B 8. 42-49. If we
consider the possibility of change in general, there is an obvious temporal sense
to be given to Parmenides' formula: the subject lacks nothing, in the sense that
there is no state of affairs left for it to realize in the future. But movement has
just been distinguished from other forms of change (B 8. 29-30, cf. the resume
See p. 86, n. 5 above. essential qualities of r E'dv' before the less,
O;VJKEV in B 8. 32 means 'because' (as but he has not seen that the OUK c-rEAE'r'T7-ov
generally in Homer: so Fraenkel, Wege und is in fact the conclusion of the opening argu-
Formen, pp. 191-2), not 'therefore' (as von ment and the premiss of the next.
Fritz argues in Class. Philol. xli [1946], 237- S Iliad 18. 501; Odyssey 5. 289.
8). Von Fritz urges that to deduce immo-
4 Aristotle, Phys. F 4. 203b4-15?
bility from finiteness would reverse the s See Ross's note on Phys. r 4. 203ao-15 ;
'natural logical order' and depart from Raven, Pythagoreans and Eleatics, pp. 188-94-
Parmenides' procedure of putting the 'more
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ELEATIC QUESTIONS 99
rrTvZLarov,
in TETEAXTrMEvov
its turn depends d2 rrTdcVTroOEV
on the conclusions (B 8.but42-43).
already established; The Ed'El
even without theshows that this proof
connective it should have seemed absurd to interpret ire-pas here as 'boundary',
a sense flatly incompatible with the whole train of argument in which the word
was first introduced. The epithet rrv'a-arov, so far from compelling that transla-
tion, itself recalls rrelparos . . Tod PEtrw Vzt1 iEpyEc, a phrase used in a context
where any suggestion of literal boundaries was out of the question (B 8. 31).
So the sense is not in doubt: the opening words mean, in effect, 'Moreover,
since it is utterly unchanging'. And the conclusion is drawn that, since there
cannot be movement, there cannot be room for movement. TerEAEalJeLvo
crdvroOEV is the exact spatial counterpart of the temporal o3K a7 TEAEv'?70ov in
B 8. 32; and in case this correspondence should escape any reader Parmenides
reinforces his conclusion and shows its sense by transferring to this spatial
context the very argument for continuity which was earlier, in its temporal
application, associated with the o0K d c7EAEV'27TOV (B 8. 44-48). But before
giving this argument Parmenides introduces his simile: the subject is E'KVKAOU
alap 4JvalyKL5ov yK(cp, PLUU'aad4EV ao raA 7c' v7r, precisely because there is
nothing true of it at one point or in one direction that is not true elsewhere. Its
uniformity is like the perfect balance of a ball about its centre. (It is not of
course a uniformity of radius: that is ruled out by laorraAE.) And the whole
argument concludes: ot ydp Cvro0eV ov (LCo t dpE dEpUwL KCPE (B 8. 49).
Here again is the metaphorical notion of being contained in relpaira; here
again is the equality which is rd laooraAE', spatial indifference. And JP4Ja does
not of course mean 'at an equal distance from the centre': its meaning is
given by the lIKVEa8OatL EL ddo'v of lines 46-47. So the phrase has an exact sense:
to the irElpara of temporal invariance Parmenides has added the dtpca of
invariance in space.
So Parmenides' treatment of space exactly matches his treatment of time;
there is no place in it for boundaries or a spherical universe. And if that is so
there is a rider that deserves to be added. It is sometimes said that Melissus
differed from Parmenides 'in holding that reality was spatially as well as
temporally infinite'.' Both, we are told, agreed that 'reality is eternal'; but it
was Melissus who saw the inconsistency of saying in the same breath that it had
spatial frontiers. Thus it becomes an engaging puzzle why Melissus directs the
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
I00 G. E. L. OWEN
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
ELEATIC QUESTIONS 1ox
cannot have a body; for otherwise it would have
quently, distinguishable parts (odpta), and then
(30 B 9). Here the word to'dpov must evidently b
Eleatic attack on divisibility: the argument a
view of the world, a physical solid is divisible in
identified and distinguished in it, either by fin
them or by characterizing them as having more
say, or heat) than their neighbour; and it is thi
which Parmenides' argument in B 8. 44-48 is
to point out that his subject is not such a soli
space does not involve divisibility or prevent the
That Plato at any rate took this to be Melissus'
of Parmenides in Timaeus 37 e-38 a: what is unc
ADDITIONAL NOTE
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
102 G. E. L. OWEN
reiteration of negative prefixes (adydrwov ... dvAEOpov ... ca-rpE1LES) into writing
4 L' drEAELov and this was corrected to the orthodox Homeric clausula 83'
CdLTaErov (1. 4. 26). With this emendation the programme is complete.
This content downloaded from 151.100.101.138 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 15:54:46 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms