Mind Association, Oxford University Press Mind
Mind Association, Oxford University Press Mind
Mind Association, Oxford University Press Mind
Rule-Consequentialism
Author(s): Brad Hooker
Source: Mind, New Series, Vol. 99, No. 393 (Jan., 1990), pp. 67-77
Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of the Mind Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2254891
Accessed: 14-03-2018 18:19 UTC
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms
Mind Association, Oxford University Press are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize,
preserve and extend access to Mind
This content downloaded from 108.61.242.12 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 18:19:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Rule-Consequentialism'
BRAD HOOKER
1 This paper is much better than it would otherwise have been because of written comments on
earlier drafts from Penelope Mackie, Mark Overvold, Peter Vallentyne, Anthony Ellis, Mark Nelson,
and Richard Brandt. I am extremely grateful to these people, and to Alan Fuchs, James Griffin, R. M.
Hare, Roger Crisp, David Dyzenhaus, Cheryl Misak, Eldon Soifer, Howard Robinson, Madison
Powers, and Greg Trianosky for helpful discussions about the ideas in the paper. Remaining defects,
however, are my responsibility.
2 I do not want to make any controversial assumptions about what desires and dispositions human
beings are capable of having. I do not want to enter here into debates about how 'plastic' human nature
has been up to now; nor do we need to take up questions about whether trying to 'improve' human
nature via genetic engineering would be advisable.
3 So rule-consequentialism is a kind of indirect consequentialism. It is a mistake to think that
indirect consequentialism assesses not acts but only the rightness and wrongness of other things such
as motives, standing dispositions, rules, and social practices. Indirect consequentialism does assess acts
as well (see B. Williams, 'A Critique of Utilitarianism', in J. J. C. Smart and B. Williams,
Utilitarianism: For and Against, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, I973, p. I2I).
4 See R. M. Adam's distinction between 'Individualistic motive utilitarianism' and 'Universalistic
motive utilitarianism' ('Motive Utilitarianism', journal of Philosophy, I976, p. 480) and D. Parfit's
distinction between 'Individual Consequentialism' and 'Collective Consequentialism', Reasons and
Persons, Oxford, Clarendon Press, I984, pp. 30-I. There might seem to be something fishy about the
claim that the right act is whatever one would be called for by the desires, dispositions, and rules which
are such that, if every last person had them, the best consequences would result. I shall return to this.
This content downloaded from 108.61.242.12 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 18:19:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
68 Brad Hooker
This content downloaded from 108.61.242.12 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 18:19:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Rule-Consequentialism 69
This content downloaded from 108.61.242.12 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 18:19:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
7o Brad Hooker
12 The rules in question must of course be 'fairly general' because rule-consequentialism collapses
into extensional equivalence with act-consequentialism if the rules are allowed to be infinitely specific.
Brandt mentions this problem ('Indirect Optimific Theories', p. 347). The question of just how
universal the acceptance of the mode code must be is one I return to below.
13 This objection is discussed in many places. Sidgwick acknowledges that utilitarianism 'seems to
require a more comprehensive and unceasing subordination of self-interest to the common good' than
common-sense morality does (Methods of Ethics, p. 87, italics added). See also ibid., pp. 492, 499.
Other discussions of this objection include: K. Baier, The Moral Point of View, Ithaca, Cornell
University Press, I958, pp. 203-4; Scheffler, 'Introduction' to Consequentialism and its Critics,
pp. 3-4; G. Harman, The Nature of Morality, New York, Oxford University Press, I977, p. I57-62;
F. Feldman, Introductory Ethics, Englewood Cliffs, Prentice-Hall, I978, ch. 4; R. Brandt, A Theory of
the Good and the Right, Oxford, Clarendon Press, I979, p. 276; J. Hospers, Human Conduct: Problems
of Ethics, 2nd edn, New York, Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, i982, pp. i62-5; D. Brock, 'Utilitarianism
and Aiding Others', in The Limits of Utlihtarianism, ed. H. Miller and W. Williams, Minneapolis,
University of Minnesota Press, i982; Thomas Carson, 'Utilitarianism and World Poverty', in Miller
and Williams; Parfit, Reasons and Persons, pp. 30-I; and B. Williams, Ethics and the Limits of
Philosophy, Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, i985, p. 77. And consider the following
passage from Railton, a defender of act-consequentialism: [J]ust how demanding or disruptive it [act-
consequentialism] would be for an individual is a function-as it arguably should be-of how bad the
state of the world is, how others typically act, what institutions exist, and how much that individual is
capable of doing. If wealth were more equitably distributed, if political systems were less repressive
and more responsive to the needs of their citizens, and if people were more generally prepared to
accept certain responsibilities, then individuals' everyday lives would not have to be constantly
disrupted for the sake of the good' (p. i6i). So act-consequentialism holds that in the real world, where
wealth is not equitably distributed, where political systems are repressive and unresponsive to the
needs of their citizens, and where most others are not more generally prepared to accept certain
responsibilities, most of your acts will not be morally right unless your everyday life is constantly
disrupted for the sake of the good? And one of the main ways in which act-consequentialism can
become not constantly disruptive is for a much wider group of people to make sacrifices for the sake of
those in need?
This content downloaded from 108.61.242.12 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 18:19:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Rule-Consequentialism 71
14 See P. Singer, Practical Ethics, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, I979, p. I63.
15 Scheffler and T. Nagel usefully set out a number of different ways moral theorists might respond to
a very demanding moral conception (Scheffler, 'Morality's Demands and their Limits', Journal of
Philosophy, I986, pp. 53I-7; Nagel, The View from Nowhere, New York, Oxford University Press,
I986, ch. X; but cf. Griffin, Well-Being, pp. I27-62, I95-206, 246-5I, 302-7; Railton, pp. I69-70
n. 42; and D. Brink, 'Utilitarian Morality and the Personal Point of View', Journal of Philosophy, I986,
pp. 432-8). Particularly important is the following contrast. When confronted with an account of
morality which pictures it as extremely demanding, some of us would respond by rejecting that
account of morality's content. Another response is to accept that account of its content but then limit
morality's rational authority. Though there are other possible responses as well, the idea I am drawing
on in this paper is that any account of the content of morality which makes it constantly and
relentlessly demanding is ultimately mistaken. The purpose of the second half of this note is to
acknowledge that not everyone will find that idea seductive.
16 See Carson, 'Utilitarianism and World Poverty', p. 243.
17 A principle Sidgwick thinks is part of 'common-sense morality' and even, 'broadly speaking,
unquestionable' (Methods, p. 348-9; see also pp. 253, 26I).
This content downloaded from 108.61.242.12 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 18:19:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
72 Brad Hooker
This content downloaded from 108.61.242.12 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 18:19:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Rule-Consequentialism 73
II
right and wrong must be sensitive to a requirement of psychological realism, i.e., act-consequentialism
cannot demand more self-sacrifice than human nature can deliver. I am grateful to James Griffin for
this suggestion, but I do not have room here to explore it here.
22 Brandt, 'Fairness to Indirect Optimific Theories in Ethics', p. 357. See also his Theory of the Good
and the Right, pp. 297-9, and his 'Problems of Contemporary Utilitarianism: Real and Alleged', in
Ethical Theory in the Last Quarter of the Twentieth Century, ed. N. E. Bowie, Indianapolis, Hackett
Publishing Co., I983, pp. 99-I02. I should mention that I will usually follow common practice in
contrasting full and partial compliance. But, since the best versions of rule-consequentialism (including
Brandt's) are concerned with acceptance-utility rather than compliance-utility, this terminology will be
less than perfectly accurate. The distinction between acceptance-utility and compliance-utility is
important because the consequences of everyone's accepting some code (and being motivated
accordingly) may involve more than the consequences of their acts of compliance with that code. (On
this, see Williams, 'Critique of Utilitarianism', pp. I I9-30; Adams, 'Motive Utilitarianism', pp. 467-8I,
p. 470; S. Blackburn, 'Errors and the Phenomenology of Value', in Morality and Objectivity, A Tribute to
f. L. Mackie, ed. T. Honderich, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, I985, p. 2I n. I2.)
23 'Fairness to Indirect Optimific Theories in Ethics', p. 342; see also p. 358.
This content downloaded from 108.61.242.12 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 18:19:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
74 Brad Hooker
24 See the famous discussion in Ross, Right and the Good, pp. 34-5. The claim made in my text
must not be misconstrued as a reply to the following common objection against rule-consequentialism:
given that rule-consequentialism says the point of following moral rules is to optimize, its refusal to
permit us to break the rules when doing so would be optimific makes the theory internally incoherent.
I do not have room here to go into detail about this well-worn objection, which Brandt does take up in
'Fairness to Indirect Optimific Theories' on pp. 353-7, and to which I believe that there are
persuasive indirect consequentialist replies. But I am grateful to Anthony Ellis for pointing out that I
need to distinguish the idea I discuss in the text from this objection.
25 For a recent attempt to deal with fairness by someone sympathetic to utilitarianism, see Griffin,
Well-being, ch. X.
This content downloaded from 108.61.242.12 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 18:19:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Rule-Consequentialism 75
III
26 Actually this is not exactly what Brandt presents. He says that his proposal would lead us to
think that in the example from South Africa in which the agent is being watched by rabid racists 'the
requirement to treat people equally now may be weaker than the prohibition on causing great harm,
but the requirement to do what one can to improve matters will be stronger than simple capitulation to
the rules subscribed to by the majority' ('Indirect Optimific Theories', p. 359). This is confusing
because it suggests that the optimal moral code would include an intrinsic motivation to capitulate to
the rules subscribed to by the majority-which must be a mistake. To be sure, we might accept the idea
that attempts at moral reform may be most successful if they try to build on, rather than completely
overturn, existing rules. (On this idea, see Sidgwick, Methods of Ethics, pp. 467-7I, 473-6, 480-4;
Griffin, Well-being, pp. 206, 302; Brandt, Theory of the Good and the Right, p. 290, and 'Indirect
Optimific Theories', pp. 350, 356-7.) But to accept that attempts at moral reform may be most
successful if they try to build on existing rules is not to accept the idea that people should be motivated
to capitulate to whatever moral rules the majority accepts.
This content downloaded from 108.61.242.12 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 18:19:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
76 Brad Hooker
This content downloaded from 108.61.242.12 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 18:19:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
Rule-Consequentialism 77
Utilitarianism', p. 98. See also J. L. Mackie's remark that in devising a moral code 'we are to take men
as they are and moral laws as they might be' (Ethics: Inventing Right and Wrong, Harmondsworth,
Penguin Books, I977, p. I33).
29 If at all! As Brandt observes in his book, 'What these rules [of obligation] may require is limite
by the strain of self-interest in everyone, and [by] the specific desires and aversions bound to develo
in nearly everyone . . .' (p. 287).
30 As Brandt concedes, 'the optimific indirect theory does run into complications when we try to
work out the details in any realistic way' ('Indirect Optimific Theories', p. 36o).
31 Cf. J. Arthur, 'Equality, Entitlements, and the Distribution of Income', in Applying Ethics, ed. J.
Olen and V. Barry, Belmont, CA, Wadsworth Inc., i989, pp. 362-72.
Brandt's Theory of the Good and the Right contains a powerful and celebrated attack on the idea that
we should judge moral theories by how much they agree with our intuitions (see op. cit., ch. I sect. 3).
But see also N. Daniels, 'Can Cognitive Psychotherapy Reconcile Reason and Desire?', Ethics, i983,
pp. 772-85, esp. pp. 778-8i. My own opinion is that, while we must heed Sidgwick's warning that 'it
cannot be denied that any strong sentiment, however purely subjective, is apt to transform itself into
the semblance of an intuition' (Methods, p. 339) considered judgements might nevertheless play a
legitimate role in the testing of moral theories.
This content downloaded from 108.61.242.12 on Wed, 14 Mar 2018 18:19:57 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms