Duns Scotus. Ordinatio 2 D. 3 P. 1 Qq. 5-6
Duns Scotus. Ordinatio 2 D. 3 P. 1 Qq. 5-6
Duns Scotus. Ordinatio 2 D. 3 P. 1 Qq. 5-6
* Translated from Iohanni Duns Scoti opera omnia tom. VII, studio et cura Commisionis
Scotisticae (ad fidem codicum edita), praeside P. Carolo Balić, Civitatis Vaticana:
Typis Polyglottis Vaticanis 1973, 458–494.
–1–
2 Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6
Hence it seems that matter is outside the account of the quiddity and of
anything that primarily possesses the quiddity. Thus, since [matter] is some-
thing in the realm of beings, it seems to be [either]:
(i ) a part of the individual
(ii ) the individuation of the whole
Whatever is in the individual that is completely incompatible with the ac-
count of the quiddity can be held to be the primary account of individuating.
Accordingly, etc.
[134] [Aristotle] proves in Met. 12.8 [1074a 31–38] that there cannot be
many heavens. He says:
If there were many heavens, as [there are many] men, the principle
regarding any one [of them] would be specifically one but numeri-
cally many. But whatever [items] are numerically many have matter.
However, the primary what-it-was-to-be does not have matter, for
it is an entelechy. Therefore, the prime unmoved mover is one in
account and in number.
The argument, by which the unity of the heavens is inferred from the unity
of the mover—and the unity of the mover [is inferred] not only specifically
but numerically, for the reason that [the mover] does not have matter—
would not be valid unless numerical distinction came about through matter.
Therefore, etc.
[135] De caelo et mundo 1.9 [278a 10–15]:
When I say ‘heaven,’ I mean the form; when I say ‘this heaven,’ I
mean the matter.
[Therefore, singularity is from the matter.]
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6 3
[Man and horse and the things that are in singulars in this way are
not substance taken universally, but a certain whole simultaneously
from this matter and this account.]
Man and horse and whatever is such in singulars are not substance [taken]
universally, i. e. as the form, but a certain whole simultaneously, i. e. as the
composite, from this matter and this account—where by the ‘this’ [Aristo-
tle] does not mean uniform and singular matter, but determinate [matter],
since otherwise he would contradict himself when he adds there “[taken]
universally.” Shortly afterwards [Aristotle] adds:
And Socrates is already [composed] of ultimate matter. . .
and so on.
[138] The same point is also clear from Met. 12.5 [1071a 27–29], where
[Aristotle] wants principles to be the same as what follows from them. He
says:
And [the principles] of those [things] that are in the same species
[are] diverse—not [diverse] in species, but because [they are princi-
ples] that belong to singulars. Your matter and mover and species
are one thing and mine another. Yet they are nevertheless the same
in their universal account.
Hence [Aristotle] grants the distinctness of form in particulars, just as [he
grants the distinctness] of matter [in particulars]. Thus [he grants] the
unity of matter in general, just as [he grants the unity] of form [in general].
Therefore, it is still necessary to ask: by what is matter a this?
[139] Furthermore, as is proved in many passages in Met. 7 while discussing
the parts of the definition: matter belongs to the essence of a composite
substance—e. g. it belongs to man—and a composite is not precisely such
by the essence of the form. Hence just as the composite cannot be of itself
a this (from [Ord. 2 d. 3 p. 1 q. 1 n. 29]), so too neither will matter, which
is a part of [the composite], be of itself a this, since the composite cannot
be common and of the same account in diverse [things], but rather that all
that which belongs to its essence could be of the same account as they are.
[140] Besides, matter is the same in what is generated and in what is
corrupted; hence it has the same singularity in what is generated and in
what is corrupted.
[141] If you were to object that [the matter] does not belong to the same
species in what is generated and in what is corrupted, I argue against in-
determinate quantity as I did before ([Ord. 2 d. 3 p. 1 q. 4 n. 100]): in that
case there will be circular generation, first of fire from water, and second of
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
4 Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6
water from fire. The water that is corrupted in the first [generation] and
the water that is generated [in the second generation] have the same mat-
ter and belong to the same species. Therefore, they are really this water.
Therefore, the first [water] naturally returns as numerically the same—and
this goes against them.
[ Q. 6: Whether material substance is individual through some
beingness per se determining the nature to singularity ]
[142] The resolution of the passages from the Philosopher [in n. 130 and
nn. 132–135] for the opposite position requires the solution of a sixth ques-
tion, namely: What is it through which a material substance is completely
individual? Hence I ask, sixth, whether material substance is individual
through some positive beingness per se determining the nature to singular-
ity.
[143] [First Negative Argument] That it is not: [First], in that case, the
determinant would be related to the [specific] nature as act is [related] to
potency. Hence from the specific nature and that determinant, there would
be really and properly one composite. This result is inadmissible, for the
determinant is either (a) matter; (b) form; or (c) something composed of
[matter and form]. Whichever [of these alternatives] may be granted, the
result is inadmissible. [If (a) were granted], there would be matter in the
composite that differs from the matter that is part of the nature. [If (b) were
granted], there would be a form [in the composite] different from the [form]
that is held to be part of the nature. [If (c) were granted], there would be
a composite different from that which is the composite of the nature.
[144] [Second Negative Argument] In that case, the singular, composed out
of the nature and the per se determinant, would be one per se, and hence
intelligible per se—[which seems to lead to two inadmissible consequences].
[First], this seems contrary to the Philosopher in De an. 2.5 [417b 22–23]
and Met. 7.10 [1035b 33–1036a 8], where he seems to explicitly hold that
understanding is of the universal and sense and sensation is of the singular.
[145] [Second], if [the singular] were intelligible per se, there could be
demonstration and science with regard to it, and so there could be a proper
science of singulars insofar as they are singulars—which the Philosopher
denies in Met. 7.10 [103bkb33–1036a 8].
[146] [Third Negative Argument] If the [singular] were to include the specific
nature and the per se determinant, then it could be defined per se by these
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6 5
two [factors] included per se in its account. Hence there would be one
definition of the individual and another [definition] of the species—at any
rate, [the definition of the individual] would add something beyond the
definition of the species, as the definition of the species adds something
beyond the definition of the genus.
[147] [Positive Argument] For the opposite view: Anything lower-level
includes per se something that is not included in the understanding of the
higher-level. Otherwise, the concept of the lower-level would be just as
common as the concept of the higher-level, and then the per se lower-level
would not be per se lower-level, since it would not be beneath the common
and the higher-level. Therefore, something is included per se in the account
of the individual that is not included in the account of the nature. Now
what is included is a positive beingness, by [Ord. 2 d. 3 p. 1 q. 2 n. 57].
[This positive beingness], along with the nature, produces [something] per
se one, by [Ord. 2 d. 3 p. 1 q. 4 n. 111]. Hence [this positive beingness] per
se determines the nature to singularity, or to the account of the lower-level.
[148] Here [Godfrey of Fontaines] holds that: (G1) the specific nature is
of itself a this; (G2) through quantity the [specific] nature can be common
to many singulars—that is, quantity can be the account whereby many
singulars can fall under the same nature.
[149] Now (G1) [in n. 148] is supported in the following ways. [First], the
most specific species is of itself atomic; therefore, it is indivisible.
[150] This is confirmed by a passage from Porphyry, [Isagoge 2]:
When we have descended from the most generic to the most specific,
Plato commands us to halt.
But if it were possible that there be a further division of the nature, one
would not then halt at the [specific] nature. Therefore, [the specific nature
is of itself a this].
[151] Likewise by Boethius, De divisione [877B]. [Boethius] enumerates all
divisions, not only per se [divisions] but also per accidens [divisions]; yet
he does not mention the division of the species into individuals. Hence the
specific nature is not a this through something else.
[152] [Second], if there were some reality in the individual beyond just the
reality of the specific nature, the species would not express the whole esse
of its individuals—and this is contrary to Porphyry ([Isagoge 2]).
[153] (G2) [in n. 148] is supported [as follows]. Although quantity is not
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
6 Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6
the formal account of the division of something into subjective parts, nev-
ertheless when a quantitative whole is divided into quantitative parts it is
divided per se into [items] that are of the same account. Now the principle
of division into some [items] is the same as the principle of distinction for
the [items] that divide it. Therefore, just as quantity itself is the principle
of the division, so too it is the principle of distinction for the [items] that
divide it. However, the latter are subjective parts of the common nature.
Therefore, quantity is the principle of distinction for such parts.
[154] How (G1) and (G2) can obtain together is clear by an example. Ac-
cording to the Philosopher (Phys. 1.2 [185a 32–185b 5]), substance is of itself
indivisible (speaking of [divisibility] into parts of the same account). Yet
once quantity advenes [on substance], it is partitionable into such parts—or
rather, it then has such parts. Hence in this way the nature of the species
can be of itself a this, and nevertheless it can be this and that by a nature
advening on it extrinsically.
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6 7
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
8 Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6 9
[ Scotus’s View ]
[168] Therefore, to the question [whether material substance is individual
through some positive beingness per se determining the nature to singular-
ity], I answer that it is.
[169] I support this [answer] by the following [two] arguments. [First], just
as unity in general is per se consequent upon beingness in general, so too
any given unity is per se consequent upon some beingness. Therefore, unity
simpliciter—such as the unity of the individual, frequently described above,
i. e. [the unity] with which the division into many subjective parts is incom-
patible and with which not being designated as ‘this’ is incompatible—if it
[actually] exists in beings, as every view assumes, is per se consequent upon
some per se beingness. But [the unity of the individual] is not consequent
upon the per se beingness of the nature, since there is some proper and per
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
10 Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6 11
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
12 Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6 13
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
14 Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6 15
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
16 Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6
[189] From the discussion, the response to the first principal argument [in
n. 143] is clear. When it is inferred [in n. 143] that every individual in which
the nature is contractible is more composite than the nature itself—I state
that ‘composition’ can be understood:
(i ) strictly—as the [composition] of an actual thing and a potential
thing
(ii ) less strictly—as the [composition] of a reality and an actual and
potential reality in the same thing
According to (i ), an individual is not composite with respect to the specific
nature, since it does not add any reality [to the specific nature]—for it adds
neither matter nor form nor composite, as the argument then establishes.
According to (ii ), on the other hand, an [individual] is necessarily composite,
since the reality from which the specific differentia is taken is potential with
respect to the reality from which the individual differentia is taken, as if
they were thing and thing. The specific reality does not of itself have the
wherewithal to include by identity the individual reality. Instead, only some
third [thing] includes by identity both [the specific reality and the individual
reality], [namely the concrete individual composite].
[190] This is the sort of composition that cannot obtain along with the
perfect divine simplicity. In fact, the [divine simplicity] is not only incom-
patible with the composition of a thing and an actual and potential thing
([as in (ii )]), but [it is also incompatible] with [the composition] of an actual
reality and a potential reality ([as in (i )]). Comparing any essential [feature]
to any other in the divine, the essential [feature] is formally infinite. There-
fore, of itself it has the wherewithal to include by identity whatever can
be along with it (as often touched upon in Ord. 1). The extremes are not
precisely perfectly the same, because some third [thing] perfectly includes
them both, [namely the formal infinity of one or the other of the extremes].
But in the case at hand, the specific beingness does not include by identity
the individual beingness, nor conversely. Instead, only some third [thing],
of which both of these are (as it were) per se parts, includes by identity
both of them. Therefore, the most perfect composition, which is that of
thing and thing, is lacking [in the case at hand]. Yet not every [composi-
tion is lacking]. For universally, any given nature that is not of itself a this
but rather determinable to being a this—whether in such a way that it is
determined by another thing (which is impossible in every case), or in such
a way that it is determined by another reality—is not simply-simple.
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6 17
[191] With regard to the second [argument in n. 144], I grant that the
singular is intelligible per se, on its part. However, if [the singular] is not
intelligible per se to some intellect—for instance, to ours—see [Ord. 2 d. 3
p. 2 q. 1 n. 294] regarding this point. At any rate, there is no impossibility
on the [singular’s] part for it to be able to be understood, just as there is no
impossibility on the part of the Sun for seeing and for vision in the night-owl
[in sunlight], but the [impossibility] is on the part of the night-owl’s eye.
[192] With regard to the [remarks] about definition [in n. 146], I state
that if some account could express anything concurrent with the individual
beingness, the account will still not be a perfect definition, since it does
not express the what-it-was-to-be—and, according to the Philosopher in
Top. 1.5 [101b 39]:
The definition completely expresses [the essence].
Therefore, I grant that the singular is not definable by some definition other
than the definition of the species. The [singular] is nevertheless per se
a being, adding some beingness to the specific beingness. However, the
per se beingness that [the singular] adds [to the specific beingness] is not
quidditative beingness.
[193] From these remarks, the reply to the [second inadmissible conse-
quence in n. 145], concerning demonstration and science, is clear. The def-
inition of the subject is the middle [term] in the most powerful sort of
demonstration. However, the singular does not have a proper definition,
but only the definition of the species. Thus there is no proper demonstra-
tion concerning [the singular]. Instead, there is only demonstration that
concerns the species (for [the individual] does not have a proper attribute,
but only the attribute belonging to the species).
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
18 Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6 19
[ Resolution of Question 5 ]
[200] With regard to Question 5 [in n. 219], about matter, the solution
is clear from the arguments [in nn. 194–199] against [Godfrey’s] view. I
grant that matter absolutely, insofar as it is a nature, is not the ratio of
distinction or individuation. For whatever is a nature, be it total or partial,
in any genus whatsoever is not of itself a this. Therefore, one must look into
by what a [nature] is a this.
[201] With regard to the passage from the Philosopher [in n. 130], namely
(Met. 5.6 [1016b 32–33]):
Those [things] are numerically one [whose matter is one]
I reply as follows. I state that [Aristotle] takes ‘matter’ in this passage
for the individual beingness that constitutes [something] in material esse—
but not in formal esse, insofar as the quiddity is called ‘form,’ since that
beingness is not quidditative. This analysis is manifest by what [Aristotle]
adds next ([1016b 33–35]):
[Those things are] specifically [one] whose account is one.
Here ‘account’ is taken for the quiddity, which is called the ‘form’ with
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
20 Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6 21
[of the what-it-is] is not the same [as the what-it-is] when it includes some
beingness outside the ratio of its quiddity. Indeed, in this case the [possessor
of the what-it-is] is not the same as the what-it-is primarily, since the what-
it-is does not belong to it primarily due to the fact that the possessor [of the
what-it-is] includes some beingness outside the ratio of what is the what-it-is
primarily.
[206] Hence, with regard to what the Philosopher proposed [in Met. 7.11
1037a 32–1037b5], I state that in the case of [things] that are not con-
ceived with matter—i. e. not with an individual beingness that contracts
the quiddity—the what-it-is is primarily the same as that to which it be-
longs, since the kind to which it belongs has no account outside the ratio
of what is the what-it-is. On the other hand, in the case of [things] that
are conceived with matter—i. e. with an individual beingness that contracts
the quiddity—the what-it-is is not primarily the same as that to which it
belongs, since what is conceived in this way primarily would not possess the
what-it-is of itself but only through a part, namely through the nature that
is contracted by that individual beingness.
[207] Therefore, one does not get from this passage that the matter that
is one of the parts of the composite is outside the account of the quiddity
per se. Instead, the matter genuinely pertains to the quiddity. The species
(and the possessor of the form in every instance) primarily possesses the
what-it-is and is primarily the same as it. Therefore, it does not follow that
the matter that is one of the parts of the composite is what individuates.
Rather, this only follows for the matter that is the beingness contracting the
quiddity, which I granted [in n. 206]. In [Ord. 2 d. 3 p. 1 q. 7 nn. 238–239] I
will deal with whether the lack of the matter that is one of the parts [of the
composite] entails the lack of this sort of individual beingness, according to
the Philosopher.
[208] With regard to the Philosopher’s remark [in n. 132] that the gener-
ator generates another according to matter ([Met. 7.8 1034a 4–8]), qI state
that the Philosopher’s intent here is that the Ideas are not necessary for
generation. The reason for this is that (i ) the distinction of the generator
from what is generated, as well as (ii ) the assimilation of what is generated
to the generator—both of which are required for univocal generation—can
be had without Ideas. From its form, a particular agent has the wherewithal
to assimilate the patient to itself, and the generator [has the wherewithal
to assimilate] what is generated. From the matter, [the generator] has the
feature that it be distinct from what is generated. [The generator] does not
[have this feature] principally [from the matter], even though it necessarily
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.
22 Duns Scotus: Ordinatio 2 d. 3 p. 1 qq. 5–6
c Peter King 1987, all rights reserved.