Cambridge Studies in International Relations 113 Vincent Pouliot International Security in Practice The Politics of NATO Russia Diplomacy Cambridge University Press 2010
Cambridge Studies in International Relations 113 Vincent Pouliot International Security in Practice The Politics of NATO Russia Diplomacy Cambridge University Press 2010
Cambridge Studies in International Relations 113 Vincent Pouliot International Security in Practice The Politics of NATO Russia Diplomacy Cambridge University Press 2010
How do once bitter enemies move beyond entrenched rivalry at the dip-
lomatic level? In one of the fi rst attempts to apply practice theory to
the study of International Relations, Vincent Pouliot builds on Pierre
Bourdieu’s sociology to devise a theory of practice of security communi-
ties and applies it to post-Cold War security relations between NATO
and Russia. Based on dozens of interviews and a thorough analysis of
recent history, Pouliot demonstrates that diplomacy has become a nor-
mal, though not a self-evident, practice between the two former enemies.
He argues that this limited pacification is due to the intense symbolic
power struggles that have plagued the relationship ever since NATO
began its process of enlargement at the geographical and functional lev-
els. So long as Russia and NATO do not cast each other in the roles that
they actually play together, security community development is bound to
remain limited.
editors
Christian Reus-Smit
Nicholas J. Wheeler
editorial board
James Der Derian, Martha Finnemore, Lene Hansen, Robert Keohane,
Rachel Kerr, Colin McInnes, Jan Aart Scholte, Peter Vale,
Kees Van Der Pijl, Jutta Weldes, Jennifer Welsh, William Wohlforth
V i nc e n t P ou l io t
c amb ri dge unive rs it y p re s s
Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore,
São Paulo, Delhi, Dubai, Tokyo
Cambridge University Press
The Edinburgh Building, Cambridge C B 2 8RU , UK
Published in the United States of America by Cambridge University Press, New York
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9780521122030
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library
Bibliography 251
Index 275
ix
Figures and tables
x
Preface
xi
xii Preface
xiv
Abbreviations xv
1
2 International Security in Practice
1
This section draws on Pouliot (2007).
2 3
Deutsch et al. (1957, 5). Adler and Barnett (1998, 30 and 34).
4 5 6
See Pouliot (2006). Wendt (1999, 229). Deutsch et al. (1957, 5).
4 International Security in Practice
7 8
Deutsch et al. (1957, 5). Adler and Barnett (1998, 39).
9
Adler and Barnett (1998, 55–6).
10
Pouliot (2007) expands on each of these indicators.
11
In 1994, Bill Clinton and Boris Yeltsin pledged to re-target all their nuclear
forces away from each other’s territories. As two Russian experts confi rm,
“deliberate conventional or nuclear war between Russia and the European
Union or the NATO states is unthinkable”; Arbatov and Dvorkin (2006, 32).
On more recent developments in nuclear relations, see Pouliot (n.d.).
Introduction 5
12
See, e.g., PIPA (2002); Zimmerman (2002); White, Light and McAllister
(2005); Allison (2006); Colton (2008); and the EU’s yearly Eurobarometer.
13
Hopf (2002); Neumann (1999).
14 15
Pouliot (2006). Wenger (1998); Adler (2005).
6 International Security in Practice
Most theories of social action focus on what agents think about at the
expense of what they think from. In IR, rational choice theorists pri-
marily emphasize representations and reflexive knowledge in explain-
ing political action. In the rationalist equation (desire + belief = action),
ideas factor in an individual calculation informed by intentionality.
Agents deliberately reflect on the most efficient means to achieve their
ends. For their part, several constructivists theorize that norms and col-
lective identities reflexively inform action. Intersubjective representa-
tions of reality, morality or individuality determine socially embedded
cognition and action. In a related fashion, Habermasian constructiv-
ists concentrate on collective deliberation and truth-seeking as a form
of communicative action. Overall, the three logics of social action
that have the most currency in contemporary IR theory – the logics
of consequences, appropriateness and arguing1 – suffer from a similar
bias toward representational knowledge. Conscious representations
are emphasized to the detriment of background knowledge – the inar-
ticulate know-how from which reflexive and intentional deliberation
becomes possible.
In and of itself, this focus on representational knowledge is not nec-
essarily a problem: the logics of consequences, appropriateness and
arguing cover a wide array of social action, as recent studies about
socialization in Europe have demonstrated. 2 The problem rests with
the many practices that neither rational choice nor rule-based and
communicative action theories can explain properly. Take the case of
diplomacy, perhaps the most fundamental practice in international
politics. For most IR theorists, diplomacy is primarily about strate-
gic action, instrumental rationality and cost-benefit calculations. Yet
this scholarly understanding is at odds with that of practitioners,
1 2
March and Olsen (1998); Risse (2000). See Checkel (2005).
11
12 International Security in Practice
3 4
Watson (1991, 52). Nicolson (1963, 43); Satow (1979, 3).
5
Neumann (2002; 2005a; 2007).
6
Practices are patterned social activities that embody shared meanings; see
Adler and Pouliot (n.d.). As Barry Barnes notes, contrary to habits, practices
can be done correctly or incorrectly (Barnes 2001).
7
Taylor (1993, 45).
A theory of practice of security communities 13
8
Schatzki, Knorr Cetina and Von Savigny (2001).
9 10 11
Schatzki (2005, 177). Neumann (2002). Hopf (2002).
12 13 14
Adler (2005). Williams (2007). Mitzen (2006).
15
Though inspired by Bourdieu’s “logic of practice,” the notion of
practicality is meant to specifically theorize the non-representational basis
of practices. In Bourdieu’s more ambitious framework, the logic of practice
covers both representational and non-representational action (see
Bourdieu 1990a).
14 International Security in Practice
16 17
Toulmin (2001, 2). De Certeau (1990, 177–9).
A theory of practice of security communities 15
and sixteenth centuries, however, maps began to evolve into the geo-
graphical representations from above that still exist today. Of course,
this epistemic transformation took place over centuries. For a while,
maps conveyed both practical and representational knowledge: in pre-
modern maps, for instance, “ships drawn on the sea convey the mari-
time expedition that made representations of the coast possible.”18
But progressively the god-like posture of modern science, which looks
at the world from above, triumphed over practical knowledge. As
“totalizing representations,” contemporary maps do not convey the
practical operations that made them possible. The entire modern sci-
entific enterprise can be interpreted as a similar movement away from
practical knowledge and toward formal and abstract representations
of the world.
The representational bias in modern thinking is reinforced by the
logic of scientific practice and its institutional environment. In try-
ing to see the world from a detached perspective, social scientists
put themselves “in a state of social weightlessness.”19 Looking at the
world from above and usually backward in time implies that one
is not directly involved in social action and does not feel the same
proximity and urgency as agents do. In contrast to practitioners,
who act in and on the world, social scientists spend careers and lives
thinking about ideas, deliberating about theories and representing
knowledge. As a result, they are enticed “to construe the world as a
spectacle, as a set of significations to be interpreted rather than as
concrete problems to be solved practically.”20 The epistemological
consequences of such a contemplative eye are tremendous: what sci-
entists see from their ivory tower is often miles away from the practi-
cal logics enacted on the ground. For instance, what may appear to
be the result of rational calculus in (academic) hindsight may just as
well have derived from practical hunches under time pressure. This
“ethnocentrism of the scientist”21 leads to substituting the practical
relation to the world for the observer’s (theoretical) relation to prac-
tice – or, to use Bourdieu’s formula, “to take the model of reality for
the reality of the model.”22
18
De Certeau (1990, 178).
19
Bourdieu (2003, 28). This and further translations from French are mine.
20 21
Wacquant (1992 , 39). Bourdieu and Wacquant (1992 , 69).
22
Bourdieu (1987, 62). See also Bourdieu (1990b); and Pouliot (2008) for an
epistemological discussion in IR.
16 International Security in Practice
The analyst can choose which problem he wishes to study, whereas the
statesman’s problems are imposed on him. The analyst can allot whatever
time is necessary to come to a clear conclusion; the overwhelming chal-
lenge to the statesman is the pressure of time … The analyst has available
to him all the facts … The statesman must act on assessments that cannot
be proved at the time that he is making them. 23
23
Kissinger (1994, 27).
24
Kissinger (1973, 2 and 326). There is no doubt that, in so arguing, Kissinger
is also positioning himself as the holder of better knowledge than his fellow
IR scholars. Beyond its analytical value, the distinction between the art and
the science of politics is obviously part of a larger symbolic struggle over
authoritative knowledge in the field of IR. As will become clear in
Chapter 3, I believe that both practical and theoretical knowledge are
necessary and mutually enlightening.
25
Schelling (1980).
26
Because it argues that the cost-benefit model “is a legitimate approximation
of real processes,” empiricist rational choice is the primary target here
(Tsebelis 1990, 38). However, instrumentalist rational choice, premised on
the notion that models need not be realistic so long as they explain social
outcomes accurately, also falls victim to the representational bias in that
it overlooks the process of practice (which is modeled regardless of what
happens at the level of action) to focus on its outcome (as congruent with
A theory of practice of security communities 17
distinct modes of social action.31 On the one hand, the logic of appro-
priateness deals with rules that are so profoundly internalized that
they become taken for granted. On the other hand, the logic of appro-
priateness is a reflexive process whereby agents need to figure out
what behavior is appropriate to a situation.32 Ole Jacob Sending calls
these two possible interpretations “motivationally internalist” vs.
“motivationally externalist,”33 a distinction that hinges on whether
agents reflect before putting a norm into practice. I argue that a vast
majority of constructivist works fall in the latter camp, according to
which norm-based actions stem from a process of reflexive cognition
based either on instrumental calculations, reasoned persuasion or the
psychology of compliance. Even those few constructivists who theo-
rize appropriate action as non-reflexive assimilate it to the output of a
structural logic of social action or to a habit resulting from a process
of reflexive internalization. Problematically, nowhere in these inter-
pretations is there room for properly theorizing the logic of practical-
ity (see Table 2.1).
Three main strands of constructivist research construe appropri-
ateness as a motivationally externalist logic of social action.34 A fi rst
possibility is to introduce “thin” instrumental rationality in the con-
text of a community or a norm-rich environment. Margaret Keck
and Kathryn Sikkink’s “boomerang model” is one of the best-known
frameworks of this genre: state elites’ compliance with transna-
tional norms fi rst comes through strategic calculations under nor-
mative pressure; only at a later stage do preferences change.35 Frank
Schimmelfennig’s notion of rhetorical action – “the strategic use of
norm-based arguments”36 – follows a similar logic of limited strategic
31
Risse (2000, 6).
32
March and Olsen lean toward this second interpretation when they write that
in order to enact appropriate behavior, actors pose questions such as “Who
am I?” or “What kind of situation is this?” (March and Olsen 1989, 23).
33
Sending (2002).
34
Arguably, a fourth externalist strand is rule-based constructivism, which also
seems to presume a reflexive dimension to rule-following. As Nicholas Onuf
writes: “As agents begin to realize that they should act as they always have,
and not just because they always have acted that way, the convention gains
strength as a rule” (Onuf 1998, 67; emphasis added). By contrast, I suggest
below that rules become doxa, and thence gain strength, precisely when they
are forgotten as rules.
35 36
Keck and Sikkink (1998). Schimmelfennig (2001, 62).
A theory of practice of security communities 19
37
Risse (2000, 7). Note that Thomas Risse tends to emphasize the
representational dimension of Habermas’s social theory (i.e. collective truth-
seeking) at the expense of what the Frankfurt theorist calls Lebenswelt or
lifeworld.
38 39
Checkel (2001). Shannon (2000, 300). See also Johnston (2001).
20 International Security in Practice
40
Sending (2002 , 445).
41
Sending (2002 , 451). As Sending continues: “It is thus a central feature of
structuration theory, which is a key building block of constructivist theory,
that the actor is always in a position to evaluate, reflect upon and choose
regarding what rules to follow and how to act” (Sending 2002 , 458). On a
closer look, however, there is nothing in Anthony Giddens’s defi nition that
restricts agency to choice: “Agency concerns events of which the individual is
the perpetrator” (Giddens 1984, 9).
42
Patrick Jackson locates agency in:
the double failure of social structures to cohere on their own. First,
particular constellations of processes are never inevitable, but represent
ongoing accomplishments of practice. The “fit” of particular legitimating
practices with one another has less to do with intrinsic properties of the
practices themselves, and more to do with active processes of tying practices
together to form relatively coherent wholes. Second, cultural resources
for action are always ambiguous, and do not simply present themselves
as clearly defi ned templates for action. Instead, cultural resources provide
opportunities, but actualising those opportunities demands practical,
political and discursive work to “lock down” the meaning of the resource
and derive implications from it. (Jackson 2004, 286).
A theory of practice of security communities 21
43 44
Checkel (2005, 804). Wendt (1999, 310–11).
45
Hopf (2002 , 12). See also Weldes (1999) on the social construction of
“commonsense.”
46
See Hopf (n.d).
22 International Security in Practice
Practice turns
Still a recent development in IR, the practice turn has also been pro-
moted in a number of other disciplines. The philosophical interest in
practical knowledge dates back at least to Aristotle who, in his discus-
sion of practical reasoning (that is, reasoning oriented toward action),
highlighted the importance of topoi or the “seat of argument.”49 These
commonplaces are tacit in nature: one discusses or acts with them but
not about them. According to Gilbert Ryle, however, this Aristotelian
insight was later overshadowed by his disciples’ fascination with rep-
resentational knowledge. With René Descartes, centuries later, the
representational bias entrenched itself within Western philosophical
47 48
Hopf (2002 , 11 fn. 44). E.g. Ashley (1987); Neumann (2002).
49
In IR, see Kratochwil (1989).
A theory of practice of security communities 23
50 51
Ryle (1984). Toulmin (2001, 168).
52
Wittgenstein (1958). Among other philosophers who argued in a similar
direction, the American pragmatists (e.g. John Dewey, Charles Peirce) as well
as Martin Heidegger and Maurice Merleau-Ponty are particularly prominent.
53 54
Taylor (1993, 50). Ryle (1984, 15–16, 29).
55 56
Ryle (1984, 30). Polanyi (1983, 19).
24 International Security in Practice
57 58 59
Polanyi (1983, 10). Polanyi (1983, 17). Searle (1998, 108).
60 61
Kahneman (2002 , 449). Kahneman (2002 , 451).
62 63
Stanovich and West (2000). Epstein (1994, 710).
A theory of practice of security communities 25
1. Holistic 1. Analytic
2. What feels good 2. What is sensible
3. Associative 3. Logical
4. Behavior mediated by hunches 4. Behavior mediated by conscious
from past experiences; automatic appraisal of events; controlled
5. Encodes reality in concrete 5. Encodes reality in abstract
images, metaphors, and narratives symbols, words, and numbers
6. More rapid processing: oriented 6. Slower processing: oriented
toward immediate action toward delayed action
7. Slower to change: changes with 7. Changes more rapidly: changes
repetitive or intense experience with speed of thought
8. Context-specific processing 8. Cross-context processing
9. Experienced passively and 9. Experienced actively and
preconsciously; tacit thought consciously; explicit thought
processes processes
10. Self-evidently valid 10. Requires justification via logic
and evidence
Note: Adapted from Epstein (1994, 711); and Stanovich and West (2000, 659).
64 65
Epstein (1994, 710). Reber (1993, 5).
26 International Security in Practice
66 67
Reber (1993, 13). D’Andrade (1995, 144).
68
Zerubavel (1997, 16). 69 Garfi nkel (1967); Giddens (1984).
70
Schatzki, Knorr Cetina and Von Savigny (2001).
71
Barnes (2001, 19).
72
Bigo (1996); Gheciu (2005); Huysmans (2002); Villumsen (2008); Williams
(2007).
73
Ashley (1987); Guzzini (2000).
74
Adler-Nissen (2008); Kauppi (2005); Pop (2007); Madsen (2007).
75
Dezalay and Garth (2002); Fourcade (2006); Leander (2001). For wider
discussions of Bourdieu in IR, see Mérand and Pouliot (2008) and Jackson,
Peter (2008).
A theory of practice of security communities 27
Practical knowledge
An interesting starting point to understand the logic of practical-
ity is James Scott’s Seeing Like a State, a rare study, in political sci-
ence, that takes practical knowledge seriously. To explain the failure
of certain states’ grand schemes for social engineering, Scott argues
that state projects of societal legibility and simplification usually fail
because they ignore what the Greeks used to call mètis, “a rudimen-
tary kind of knowledge that can be acquired only by practice and that
all but defies being communicated in written or oral form apart from
actual practice.”77 This practical knowledge is absolutely necessary
for the implementation of any policy because it is on it, and not on
bureaucratic models, that people’s everyday lives thrive. Contrary to
the abstract schemes produced by technocrats and social scientists,
mètis presents three main characteristics. First, it is local and situated.
76 77
De Certeau (1990, xxxv). Scott (1998, 315).
28 International Security in Practice
78 79
Scott (1998, 329). Hopf (2002 , 12).
80
Wittgenstein (1958, § 217).
A theory of practice of security communities 29
81
Searle (1998, 100–2).
30 International Security in Practice
By watching the moves made by others and by noticing which of his own
moves were conceded and which were rejected, he could pick up the art of
playing correctly while still quite unable to propound the regulations in
terms of which “correct” and “incorrect” are defi ned … We learn how by
practice, schooled indeed by criticism and example, but often quite unaided
by any lessons in the theory.83
82 83
Reber (1993, 25). Ryle (1984, 41).
84
Ashley (1987); George (1993).
A theory of practice of security communities 31
85 86
Berridge (2004, 6). De Certeau (1990, 110).
87 88
Bourdieu (2000, 261). Bourdieu (2003, 231).
89
Bourdieu (2000, 285).
32 International Security in Practice
90 91
Bourdieu (2000, 308). Taylor (1993, 50).
92 93
Williams (2007, 28–31). Bourdieu (1990a, 73).
94
One example of a non-reflexive practice that nevertheless goes through
the brain is verb conjugation. When one conjugates a verb in one’s mother
tongue, one usually applies grammatical rules without thinking: practical
mastery is based on background knowledge derived from experience.
This is starkly different from conjugating verbs in a foreign language, an
action that cannot be undertaken without reference to formal and explicit
representations such as conjugation tables.
95
Jackson and Nexon (1999).
A theory of practice of security communities 33
96
Quoted in Marti (1996, 67).
97 98
Fiske et al. (1998, 915). Bourdieu (2000, 301).
34 International Security in Practice
economic capital in the form of money, yet in the academic field that
will only take one so far. It is rather the accumulation of a specific
form of cultural capital, notably publications and professional titles,
that can move the agent toward the top of this unique configurational
hierarchy. In Bourdieu’s words, “capital is accumulated labour”: “It
is what makes the games of society … something other than sim-
ple games of chance offering at every moment the possibility of a
miracle.”99 Since positions in the field are defi ned by the distribu-
tion of capital, the concept paves the way to relational and positional
analysis.
Second, fields are defi ned by the stakes at hand, that is, the issues
around which agents converge. Fields are relatively autonomous
because they are characterized by certain struggles that have been
socially and historically constituted. All participants agree on what
it is they are seeking – political authority, artistic prestige, economic
profit, academic reputation and so on. Thus the field is a kind of social
game, with the specificity that it is a game “in itself” and not “for
itself”: “one does not embark on the game by a conscious act, one
is born into the game, with the game.”100 In addition to this innate
investment in the game, which Bourdieu calls illusio, agents also
struggle over the value and forms of capital, leading both to evolve
over time and space. Hence the third characteristic of fields is that
they are structured by taken-for-granted rules. This doxa is com-
prised of “all that is accepted as obvious, in particular the classify-
ing schemes which determine what deserves attention and what does
not.”101 Positions in the field are determined by the possession of cer-
tain resources whose value is defi ned by doxa. Generally, dominant
players have a vested interest in preserving the doxic rules of the game
(including the conversion rate between forms of capital) by turning
them into social things – institutions, norms, procedures, etc. In this
endeavor, symbolic capital – those resources that allow one to change
or maintain the rules of the game and to endow these rules with a
doxic aura of naturalness and legitimacy – becomes a “meta-capital,”
because it potentially presides over the defi nition of other capital con-
version rates.102
99 100
Bourdieu (1986, 241). Bourdieu (1990a, 67).
101 102
Bourdieu (1980, 83). Bourdieu and Wacquant (1992 , 114).
A theory of practice of security communities 35
From the interplay between habitus and field results practical sense,
“a socially constituted ‘sense of the game.’ ”103 As the intersection of
embodied dispositions and structured positions, practical sense makes
certain practices appear reasonable and axiomatic, that is, in tune
with commonsense. Of course, agents are not all equally endowed
with this social skill. In order to have a feel for the game, agents need
to have embodied specific dispositions (habitus) in the past and face a
social context (field) that triggers them. It is through the actualization
of the past in the present that agents know what is to be done in the
future, often without conscious reflection or reference to explicit and
codified knowledge. In this sense, practical sense is fundamentally
dialectic – a synthesis between the social stuff within people and that
within social contexts.104 Thanks to practical sense, agents do what
they could instead of what they should. Practice is “the done thing …
because one cannot do otherwise.”105 Contrary to normative com-
pliance in the logic of appropriateness, practical sense unthinkingly
aims at the commonsensical, given a peculiar set of dispositions and
positions.
The practical sense is inarticulate not only because it feeds on the
unreflexive dispositions of habitus, but also because it hinges on what
I call positional agency. Positional agency refers to those practices that
derive from their performers’ location in a field’s hierarchical struc-
ture. To paraphrase the famous dictum, where you sit is what you do.
Generally speaking, people go on with their lives using the tools and
resources that are ready at hand and enact practices based on their
resource endowments and the opportunity constraints they face. Put
differently, they think from the resources in their possession (i.e. their
position in the field). In the same way that players are taken by their
game, agents are “invested” by the field, including its capital value
delineations. As such, they make use of what is available around them
to get their way. In practice, social action often derives from the mate-
rials that are immediately available in the social configuration; means
regularly matter more than ends. The practical sense is an inarticulate
feel for the game at both dispositional and positional levels.
The notion of practical sense offers a promising way to tease out the
mutually constitutive dynamics between agency and structure. Social
103
Bourdieu and Wacquant (1992 , 120–1).
104 105
Bourdieu (1981, 305–8). Bourdieu (1990a, 18).
36 International Security in Practice
action derived from the feel for the game follows neither a structural
nor an individualistic logic, but a relational dialectic of “the internali-
zation of exteriority and the externalization of interiority.”106 Habitus
is embodied at the subjective level but it is comprised of intersubjective
dispositions. The field is a bundle of structured relations within which
agents are variously positioned. Put together, habitus and field trigger
practice in a non-representational way, as an intuition that more or
less fits a social pattern. Given a social configuration and agents’ tra-
jectories, action X follows somewhat unreflexively from situation Y.
Suspended in between structure and agency, practical sense is a “pre-
reflective, infraconscious mastery that agents acquire of their social
world by way of durable immersion within it.”107 This view is akin to
what Erving Goffman calls the “sense of one’s place” – the seemingly
natural feeling people usually have about how to behave in a given
social situation. It is the practical sense and not interests, norms or
truth-seeking that allows people to thoughtlessly comport themselves
in tune with commonsense.108 In Bourdieu’s sociology, then, social
action is neither structural nor agentic, but relational.
By implication, the logic of practicality is ontologically prior to the
other three logics of social action mentioned above. To put it simply,
it is thanks to their practical sense that agents feel whether a given
social context calls for instrumental rationality, norm compliance or
communicative action. The intersection of a particular set of embod-
ied dispositions (constituted by a historical trajectory of subjectiv-
ized intersubjectivity) and a specific field of positions (comprised of
power relations, objects of struggle and taken-for-granted rules) is the
engine of social action – be it rational, rule-based, communicative or
habitual. For instance, while it may make sense to be instrumentally
rational when planning investments in the economic field, it is quite
nonsensical (and socially reprehensible) to constantly calculate means
and ends with family and friends. In certain social contexts, but not
others, instrumental rationality is the “arational” way to go thanks
to the logic of practicality. Practicality is ontologically prior to instru-
mental rationality because the latter is not a priori inscribed in human
106 107
Bourdieu (2000, 256). Wacquant (1992 , 19).
108
Goffman (1959). As I explain below, however, the practical sense is not
infallible as dispositions can be out of touch with positions (what Bourdieu
calls the “Don Quixote effect” or hysteresis).
A theory of practice of security communities 37
109 110
Bourdieu (2003, 201). Bourdieu (1990a, 11).
38 International Security in Practice
For instance, Adler notes that “the capacity for rational thought and
behavior is above all a background capacity.”111 The same could be
said of normative compliance and communicative action. Contrary to
practicality, these three logics of social action share a similar focus
on representations: instrumental rationality is premised on calculated
interests; appropriateness derives from normative judgment; and com-
municative action is informed by explicit notions of truth and deliber-
ation. In practice, however, the four logics are necessarily interwoven
because any reflexive action stems from the practical sense. When
contemporary statespeople are involved in a deterrence situation, for
instance, their practical sense may lead them to calculate the costs
and benefits of their policy options. In the field of military strategy,
comparing means and ends is inscribed in agents’ dispositions as well
as in the rules of the game. When the same statespeople face close
allies in a disagreement about core values, their practical sense may
guide them to abide by shared norms. Within NATO, for instance,
cold calculations do not always make sense in view of the embodied
shared identity and history of the community. When, fi nally, these
statespeople seek to reach an agreement on new international norms
of intervention, they may feel from their practical sense that reasoned
dialogue is the way to reach a compromise. In sum, which logic of
reflexive social action is to apply typically depends on an unreflexive
practical mastery of the world. Such is also the case with interstate
peace.
111 112
Adler (2002 , 103). Deutsch et al. (1957, 32).
A theory of practice of security communities 39
113 114
Adler and Barnett (1998, 38). E.g. Neumann (2005a); Hopf (2002).
115 116
E.g. Mattern (2005). Kitchen (2009, 100).
117 118
Kitchen (2009, 97). Wenger (1998, 151).
40 International Security in Practice
Self-evident diplomacy
How does peace exist in and through practice? The fi rst conceptual
challenge is to identify the constitutive practice of security com-
munities. I defi ne a constitutive practice as a social action endowed
with intersubjective meanings that are shared by a given community
and that cement its practitioners.120 In the IR literature, Adler sug-
gests that “peace is the practice of a security community.”121 But this
119 120
Adler and Barnett (1998, 46). See Wenger (1998).
121
Adler (2005, 17). In a more recent article, Adler suggests that security
communities “spread by the co-evolution of background knowledge and
subjectivities of self-restraint” (Adler 2008, 197). See also the Norbert Elias-
inspired notion of “habitus of restraint” in Bjola and Kornprobst (2007).
A theory of practice of security communities 41
122
Bull (1995, 156). Limited to the current international order, this historically
contingent observation does not rule out that peace may be constituted
by different practices in political orders other than the current interstate
system, nor is it a normative stance in favor of the international status quo.
My focus on state-to-state peace certainly does not exhaust diplomacy in
twenty-fi rst-century global politics.
123
Watson (1991, 11). In this book I do not thickly describe the diplomatic
practice and its evolution over time because my main focus is not on the
practice per se but on the political processes that make it self-evident in
certain contexts and not in others. For rich accounts of the diplomatic
practice, see Cross (2006); Der Derian (1987); Hamilton and Langhorne
(1995); Jönsson and Hall (2005); Neumann (2005a; 2007); Sharp and
Wiseman (2007); and Watson (1991).
124
Wendt (1998).
42 International Security in Practice
War community:
Diplomacy in parallel Non-war
with organized community:
violence Insecurity Normalized diplomacy
community:
Diplomacy under the Security
shadow of organized community:
violence Self-evident diplomacy
131
Wenger (1998, 4).
132
Foucault (1980, 119). In IR, see Barnett and Duvall (2005); and Guzzini
(2005).
133
Barnett and Adler (1998, 424).
46 International Security in Practice
134
Mattern (2001; 2005); Williams (2001); and Pouliot and Lachmann (2004).
135 136
Bourdieu (2003, 332–3). Bourdieu (2003, 256–7).
137 138
Jackson (2006a). See Swidler (2001, 87).
A theory of practice of security communities 47
139
Bourdieu (1990a, 73).
140
Quoted in Lynch (1997, 339).
141
Bourdieu (1990a, 68); see Bourdieu (2001a).
48 International Security in Practice
142
Bourdieu and Wacquant (1992 , 168).
143
Bourdieu (1990a, 62). For an intriguing modelization of hysteresis in
economics, see Katzner (1999).
144
In international politics, Williams uses a trivial yet telling example of
hysteresis when General Alexander Lebed from Russia visited President
Clinton in the 1990s, a meeting that prompted negative reactions inside the
White House. As Williams comments:
What was “shocking” was that Lebed clearly did not appear to be the
“kind of man” that he was supposed to be, that in significant ways it
appeared he did not “belong.” That he didn’t know where to stand, and
could not “look you in the eye,” reflects a series of judgements emerging
out of the habitus of the American official and the field of accepted practice
in which it operates. This is then directly and evaluatively applied in an
appreciation of Lebed’s personal and political stature via an evaluation of
his own bodily hexis. (Williams 2007, 30).
A theory of practice of security communities 49
from history: since dispositions are durable, they spark all sorts of
hysteresis effects (of lag, gap, discrepancy).”145 When the subjectiv-
ized imprint of habitus is not homologous to intersubjective rules of
the game and positions in the field, this disconnection weakens social
order and domination patterns and opens the door to social change.
In Bourdieu’s theory, therefore, domination rests not only with the
possession of valuable resources (capital) as mediated by the rules of
the game. While power is a social distance defi ned along structural and
relational properties, it also hinges on the ways that these are reflected
within agents’ bodies. In other words, a power relation is necessar-
ily “sobjective” – both objectified and subjective (see Chapter 3). As
Bourdieu contends, conceiving power in symbolic terms “does remind
us that social science is not a social physics; that the acts of cognition
that are implied in misrecognition and recognition are part of social
reality and that the socially constituted subjectivity that produces
them belongs to objective reality.”146 One cannot understand domina-
tion patterns unless one inquires into the embodied dispositions of the
players involved, both dominant and dominated. First, while capital
accumulation defi nes the objectified structure of the field in positional
terms, the very defi nition and value of capital is the object of constant
struggle among agents. The issue, thus, is not only what power agents
have but also what power is in practice.147 Second, domination can
only work if it is (mis)recognized as such in and through social rela-
tions. For this to happen, there must be a homology between history-
made bodies (habitus) and history-made things (field). As Bourdieu
sums up: “One only preaches to the converted.”148
Interestingly, this dispositional view generates a different under-
standing of social causality than usual. For instance, Ryle recalls that it
is not correct to say that the glass broke because a stone hit it. Instead,
we should say that the glass broke when the stone hit it because it is
breakable. In other words, we cannot say that one specific event has
had a determinant effect on behaviors in and of itself; instead, it is
dispositions that, being susceptible to such a determinant effect, give
the event its historical efficacy.149 In terms of social practice, Searle
145
Bourdieu (1990a, 135).
146
Bourdieu (1990a 122); see also (Bourdieu 1989).
147
I owe this formulation to Stefano Guzzini.
148 149
Bourdieu (2001a, 186). Quoted in Bourdieu (2003, 214).
50 International Security in Practice
similarly notes that “we should not say that the experienced baseball
player runs to fi rst base because he wants to follow the rules of base-
ball, but we should say that because the rules require that he run to
fi rst base, he acquires a set of background habits, skills, dispositions
that are such that when he hits the ball, he runs to fi rst base.”150 It is
habitus that makes social patterns possible, not free-floating struc-
tures. In order to capture this crucial dimension of social life, one
must recover the logic of practicality.
All in all, applying Bourdieu to security communities leads to two
key theoretical innovations upon which this book’s case study builds.
First, it defi nes self-evident diplomacy as the constitutive practice
of security community. When a practice is so fully part of everyday
routine that it is commonsensically enacted, it forms the background
knowledge against which all social interaction takes place. When this
embodiment takes place among states’ officials, diplomacy becomes
the shared background against which they interact. They think from
diplomacy not about its opportunity. As a result, peaceful change can
be dependably expected; the orchestra can play without a conductor.
Second, the doxic nature of diplomacy inside security communities
is part of patterns of domination that rest on matching dispositions
and positions. Wielding power in and through practice endows diplo-
macy with a doxic aura of self-evidence and naturalness. Under such a
political pattern, the practicality or self-evidence of diplomacy makes
the social fact of international peace possible.
Conclusion
The logic of practicality is meant to be an epistemic bridge between
practical and theoretical relations to the world. In fact, the very
notion is an oxymoron: practice is logical to the point that being logi-
cal ceases to be practical, as Bourdieu quips.151 This raises thorny
issues at the methodological level.
150
Searle (1995, 144). As Searle further notes, a dispositional conceptualization
of causality and power is in fact akin to Charles Darwin’s evolution theory,
which basically turned conventional wisdom on its head. Instead of: “The
fish has the shape that it does in order to survive in water,” Darwin
professed: “The fish that have that shape (thanks to their genes in reaction
to environment) are more likely to survive than fish that do not.”
151
Bourdieu (1987, 97–8).
A theory of practice of security communities 51
152
Rubin and Rubin (1995, 20).
153
Turner (1994, 19–24) after French sociologist Marcel Mauss.
3 A “sobjective” methodology for
the study of practicality
1 2
Bourdieu (1990a, 25). Adler (2002 ,109).
3 4
Checkel (2004, 239). Finnemore and Sikkink (2001, 392).
52
A “sobjective” methodology 53
5 6
Fierke (2004, 36). See Hall (2003).
54 International Security in Practice
7
Guzzini (2000; 2005); see Adler (2002).
8
Hacking (1982; reprinted in Hacking 2002a, 159–77).
9
Hacking (2002a, 162).
A “sobjective” methodology 55
10 11
Hacking (2002b, 3). Hacking (2002b, 4).
12 13
Hacking (2002a, 189). Hacking (2002a, 190).
14
Hacking (2002a, 181).
56 International Security in Practice
15 16
Hacking (2002a, 190). Katzenstein, Keohane and Krasner (1998).
17
Pouliot (2004). Postfoundationalism is a metatheoretical commitment to
the notion that, in the absence of ontological foundations of knowledge, the
best way forward for social science is to build on the social facts that are
already reified by agents. Thanks to Daniel Nexon who suggested the term
“postfoundationalism.”
18
Fierke (2005, 7).
A “sobjective” methodology 57
19 20
Jackson, Patrick (2008, 133). Guzzini (2005, 499).
21
I thank David Welch for this language.
22
Kratochwil (2000, 91).
58 International Security in Practice
23 24
Zehfuss (2002). Hacking (1999, 6).
25
Social facts are “those facts that are produced by virtue of all the relevant
actors agreeing that they exist” (Ruggie 1998, 12). The concept is Émile
Durkheim’s and the classic example used by Searle is money (Searle 1995).
26 27
Adler (2005). Pouliot (2004).
A “sobjective” methodology 59
Methodological implications
Three main methodological implications follow from characterizing
the constructivist style of reasoning as postfoundationalist social sci-
ence. First, induction is the primary mode of knowing because social
facts constitute the essence of constructivism. Research must begin
with what it is that social agents, as opposed to analysts, believe to
be real. Second, interpretation constitutes the central methodologi-
cal task, as constructivism takes knowledge very seriously. To use
Clifford Geertz’s famous words, it is fi rst and foremost a science “in
search of meaning.”28 Third, the constructivist style of reasoning is
inherently historical for it “sees the world as a project under con-
struction, as becoming rather than being.”29 The mutual constitution
of knowledge and reality therefore necessitates a process-centered
approach.
An inductive methodology
Inductive analysis – a research strategy that moves from the local to
the general – is the necessary starting point for any constructivist
inquiry, as theorization destroys meanings as they exist for social
agents. Deductive theorizing, for instance, deliberately imposes scien-
tific categories upon practical ones. Yet constructivism’s foundations
of knowledge rest not on a set of a priori assumptions but on agents’
taken-for-granted realities. In order to recover such meanings, the
analyst must avoid superseding them with theoretical constructs. In
addition, since the construction of social reality hinges on the social
construction of knowledge, analysts also need to refrain, within the
realms of possibility, from imposing their own taken-for-granted
world onto their object of study. In sociology, Barney Glaser and
Anselm Strauss famously dubbed this inductive enterprise “grounded
theory”:30
28 29
Geertz (1973, 5). Adler (2005, 11).
30
Glaser and Strauss (1967, 226).
60 International Security in Practice
31 32
Heider (1988). Bourdieu (1987, 97–8).
A “sobjective” methodology 61
An interpretive methodology
According to Adler, constructivism rests on “an epistemology in
which interpretation is an intrinsic part of the social sciences.”33
Constructivism’s interpretive methodology seeks to comprehend
meanings in order to explain social life. Decades ago, Geertz convinc-
ingly exposed why interpretation must be part of any social scientific
inquiry: a twitch is not a wink, a difference that hinges on intersub-
jective meanings and nothing else.34 Because of this interest in under-
standing meaningful realities, constructivists just “cannot escape
the interpretivist moment.”35 In contrast to other styles of reason-
ing, however, in constructivism this interpretivist moment is double.
Interpretation means not only drawing inferences from data, as even
diehard positivists do, but also recognizing (and taking advantage of)
the fact that “an important part of the subject matter of social sci-
ence is itself an interpretation – the self-interpretation of the human
beings under study.”36 A constructivist social science therefore devel-
ops meanings about meanings.
How do these double hermeneutics transform the meanings that
are being interpreted? Building on Hans-Georg Gadamer’s under-
standing of interpretation as a “fusion of horizons” or a meaningful
dialogue with an “Other,” Paul Ricoeur famously describes the proc-
ess of interpretation as the “objectification” of meanings.37 A central
claim of Ricoeur’s interpretivism is that meanings need to be objec-
tified in order to be not only understood but also explained. Building
on speech act theory, he argues that moving from discourse to text
transforms meanings in four objectifying ways. First, discourse loses
its perlocutionary effect (what one does by saying) and to some extent
its illocution too (what one does in saying). What remains is the locu-
tionary dimension of discourse inscribed in the text (the act of saying).
Second, contrary to discourse, in a text “the author’s intention and
the meaning of the text cease to coincide.”38 Intentionality loses its
salience in favor of intertextuality. Third, a text is free from “osten-
sive references,” that is, the immediate references drawn from the
33 34
Adler (2005, 12). Geertz (1973, 6).
35
Price and Reus-Smit (1998, 271).
36
Neufeld (1993, 43–4). On the “double hermeneutics,” see also Giddens
(1984) and Jackson (2006b).
37 38
Ricoeur (1977). Ricoeur (1977, 320).
62 International Security in Practice
A historical methodology
An inductive and interpretive methodology amounts to something
similar to Geertz’s “thick description,” which consists of “sorting
39 40
Ricoeur (1977, 328 ff.). Ricoeur (1977, 322).
A “sobjective” methodology 63
41 42 43
Geertz (1973, 9). Adler (2002 , 102). Pierson (2004, 157).
44 45
Bourdieu (2003, 262). Polkinghorne (1988, 170).
46
Ruggie (1998, 32). See Finnemore (2003) for an application.
64 International Security in Practice
The real question [is how] ought one to deploy [experience-near and
experience-distant concepts] so as to produce an interpretation of the way
a people lives which is neither imprisoned within their mental horizons, an
ethnography of witchcraft as written by a witch, nor systematically deaf to
the distinctive tonalities of their existence, an ethnography of witchcraft as
written by a geometer.48
47 48
Geertz (1987, 135). Geertz (1987, 135).
66 International Security in Practice
49 50 51
Hopf (2002 , 25). Hopf (2002 , 23). Neumann (2008a).
52
Adler (2008, 202); see also Adler (1997).
53
Neumann (2002; 2005a; 2007).
A “sobjective” methodology 67
54 55 56
Garfi nkel (1967). Vaughn (2008, 70). Barnett (2002).
57 58
Gusterson (1993, 63–4). Schatz (2009a, 5).
59 60
Quoted in Gusterson (2008, 93). Schatz (2009b, 307).
68 International Security in Practice
61 62
Kvale (1996, 1). Rubin and Rubin (1995, 5).
63
Rubin and Rubin (1995, 8 and 21).
A “sobjective” methodology 69
assumptions and overcome the “Mauss problem” (see Chapter 2). For
instance, Gusterson fi nds that his interviews “generated articulations
not only of fiercely public ideologies, but also of the private, the whis-
pered, the half crystallized on the edge of consciousness.”64 There
exist several techniques to devise an interview questionnaire so as
to indirectly target and recover inarticulate knowledge. For instance,
one could submit hypothetical scenarios to interviewees and ask how
they would react were they to be put in such a situation (see Chapter
4). Another useful trick pioneered by Garfi nkel is to ask questions that
specifically seek to unsettle taken-for-granted knowledge. His classic
example is the routine question: “How do you feel?” When asked
what that question means, subjects in an ethnomethodological exper-
iment appeared at serious loss: the meaning is so taken for granted
that being interrogated about it is puzzling and even destabilizing.65
Certain questions are simply out of place in terms of practical mean-
ings. Should the interviewee appear disturbed, then chances are that
some form of inarticulate knowledge is at work.
Second, ask interviewees to recount other practitioners’ practices.
As I argued in Chapter 2 , asking interviewees to describe their daily
lives always runs the risk of imposing a scholastic logic on prac-
tices. As Bourdieu notes, “as soon as he reflects on his practice,
adopting a quasi-theoretical posture, the agent loses any chance
of expressing the truth of his practice, and especially the truth of
the practical relation to the practice.”66 Just as chefs do not explain
their recipes the same way they cook them, interviews put social
agents in the reflexive yet problematic position of observing their
own practices. This is obviously not the best way to recover the
inarticulate. The corrective that I propose consists of asking inter-
viewees to retell the practices of others – that is, the activities that
they regularly observe on the part of their fellow practitioners. In
this way, the interviewee becomes a kind of participant observer
of everyday interactions. What I have in mind here is not so dis-
tant from what has been called “hearsay ethnography,”67 a method
which consists of asking insiders to recount the practices and inter-
actions that they can observe in their everyday lives (from which
outsiders are excluded).
64 65
Gusterson (2008, 106). Garfi nkel (1967, 42–3).
66 67
Bourdieu (1990a, 91). Watkins and Swidler (2006).
70 International Security in Practice
68 69
Gusterson (2008, 98). Bourdieu et al. (1993).
70 71
Wacquant (1995). Dezalay and Garth (2002 , 9).
A “sobjective” methodology 71
72 73 74
Vaughn (2008, 71). Jackson (2006b, 273). Doty (1996).
75
Many thanks to Iver Neumann and Halvard Leira for sharing their thoughts
on the matter.
72 International Security in Practice
76 77
Milliken (1999). Duffy, Frederking and Tucker (1998).
A “sobjective” methodology 73
78
Milliken (1999, 235).
79
Kornprobst, Pouliot, Shah and Zaiotti (2008).
80 81
Crawford (2002). Hansen (2006, 73–92).
82 83
Mattern (2005). Fierke (1998).
74 International Security in Practice
84 85
Buzan, Wæver and de Wilde (1998). Leander (2008).
86
Williams (2007); Neumann (2002).
A “sobjective” methodology 75
87 88
Hafner-Burton and Montgomery (2006). Nexon (2009).
89 90
Jackson (2006a). On historical methods, see Trachtenberg (2006).
76 International Security in Practice
91 92 93
Cederman (1997). Bartelson (1995, 7). Ringmar (1996, 28).
94 95 96
Neumann (1999). George and Bennett (2005, 6). Checkel (2008).
A “sobjective” methodology 77
97
Searle (1995, 28).
78 International Security in Practice
98
Rudolph (2004). 99 Ricoeur (1977, 330).
100
Wendt (2006, 215).
80 International Security in Practice
upon reasoning along the legalistic style into which lawyers and judges
are socialized. Objectivity and validity are not the primordial proper-
ties of certain facts or theories: they are socially devised criteria upon
which practice communities of social scientists happen to agree.101
Positivists also link validity to the issue of falsification. In Karl
Popper’s famous argument, a theoretical statement is valid insofar as
it can be shown to be wrong. The assertion “all swans are white,” for
instance, can be falsified by the discovery of a black swan. But this
stylized model idealizes the practice of academic research. In the IR
discipline, very few theories (if any) have been discarded in the face
of discrepant evidence. This is due to what Willard Quine dubbed the
under-determination of theory by facts: “Since theory is involved in
deciding what the facts are, there is room for choice when deciding
whether the theory at stake is consistent with them.”102 Whether one
deals with discourses or with coefficients, interpretation and infer-
ence are irreducibly part of social science, rendering Popperian falsifi-
cation impossible. Nonetheless, many constructivists still believe that
a scientific explanation can be shown to be wrong (in relative terms)
in the course of academic debate and reinterpretation. The Rashomon
effect notwithstanding, constructivist studies are to an extent replica-
ble, insofar as the data that is used for research (interview transcripts,
policy documents, official speeches, etc.) can and should be made
available for reinterpretation by others. Therefore, it is academic com-
petition, not dialogue with Nature, that helps refi ne our knowledge
about the world: “The fact that scientific producers have as their only
clients their most rigorous and vigorous competitors – and hence those
most inclined and able to lend to their critique their full strength – is
the one Archimedean point upon which scientifically to see reason in
scientific reason, to rescue scientific reason from relativistic reduction
without having to call in a founding miracle.”103 Informed critical
debate is the foundation of scientific knowledge and refi nement.
Another traditional way to assess validity is generalizability: can the
findings travel from one case to another? From a constructivist perspec-
tive, the time is ripe to abandon the old dream of discovering nomoth-
etic laws in social sciences: human beings are reflexive and intentional
101
For variants of this pragmatist understanding of validity claims in IR, see
among others Kratochwil (2007) and Haas and Haas (2002).
102 103
Hollis and Smith (1990, 55). Bourdieu (2001b, 108).
A “sobjective” methodology 81
104 105
Price and Reus-Smit (1998, 275). Geertz (1973, 25).
82 International Security in Practice
106
Lakatos (1970).
A “sobjective” methodology 83
107
In the post-Cold War history of NATO–Russia relations, this period
corresponds to a fairly difficult one, in the wake of the American
intervention in Iraq. The year 2006 was certainly not as tense as during
the Kosovo or Georgia crises, but it remained a rough patch at the
political level.
A “sobjective” methodology 85
NATO point of view, I also met with a few international civil serv-
ants from the EU (on EU–Russia relations) and the State Department
(on US–Russia cooperation in disarmament). Admittedly, this sample
does not add up to the exhaustive political sociology of the field of
security that Didier Bigo recommends;108 I will leave it to others to
study in more depth the practices of “security professionals,” to ana-
lyze their genealogy and to map the overall field of international secu-
rity. In the more limited framework of this book, my use of Bourdieu
is meant not to inventory the field but to fi nd in it what explains the
evolution of NATO–Russia diplomacy. And although my sample is
not exhaustive, it is representative in terms of including a variety of
countries and organizations.
In order to get as exhaustive a picture as possible, I employed a
second method based on what ethnographers call the saturation
point – basically, the moment when additional interviews do not yield
significantly new insights compared to what was learned in previous
meetings. After a number of interviews, I would usually conclude that
I had grasped an important chunk of the shared background knowl-
edge I was looking for. Of course, as will become clear in Chapter 4,
in doing interviews I was not looking for big-T truth but for practical
logics. My objective was to reconstruct NATO–Russia dealings as
they exist from the practitioners’ point of view – not from some god’s-
eye perspective. This raises different kinds of validity issues than in
positivism. Generally speaking, I tried to probe discrepant views
across my interviews but did not discount any as simply false. In what
follows I do emphasize those story lines that I heard more often than
others, but I also note more heterodox views. In fact, at times I would
even hear different versions from inside the same building, just walk-
ing from one door to the next. Such, indeed, is the messiness and
fluidity of intersubjectivity in social and political life.
Given that my focus in this study is on background knowledge,
however, it is clear that my interviews served to record shared
assumptions more than idiosyncratic opinions. What follows
is not a study of partisan politics and I did not interview politi-
cians from opposing factions in order to understand ideological
debates. As interesting as this approach might have been, in this
book I attempt to study the unsaid and the tacit – the groundswell
108
Bigo (2000).
86 International Security in Practice
109
Wendt (1999, 197); see also Wendt (2004).
110 111
Leander (2008, 21). Quoted in Vaughn (2008, 73).
A “sobjective” methodology 87
112
In his study of the European Court of Human Rights, for example, Mikael
Rask Madsen notes that due to their “collective habitus,” Cold-War
jurists “were generally inclined to deploy an approach consisting of both
a diplomatic understanding of European human rights with a more or less
self-sustainable and conceptual Professorenrecht” (Madsen 2007, 149).
113 114
Bourdieu (1994, 9). Bourdieu (2001a).
88 International Security in Practice
115
Kauppi (2005, 26). This process is akin to what Jackson calls “personation,”
“the social process by which someone is empowered to speak on behalf
of (or ‘in the name of’) an entity, thereby making that entity an actor”
(Jackson 2004, 286–7).
116 117 118
Neumann (2004). Pouliot (2004). Asmus (2002).
A “sobjective” methodology 89
119 120
Eckstein (1975). See George and Bennett (2005).
90 International Security in Practice
121
Goffman (1959).
122
In Hansen’s framework, my discourse analysis conforms to model 1
(analytical focus: official discourse; object of analysis: official texts and
direct and secondary intertextual links) (Hansen 2006, 64).
A “sobjective” methodology 91
95
96 International Security in Practice
1
US State Department Chief for Russian affairs quoted in US Department of
State (2006).
100 International Security in Practice
“I’m quite sure that none of their planning involves defending against
a NATO attack.” As one German official pointed out, since the early
1990s the Alliance’s forces have been converted into deployable bri-
gades (for peacekeeping purposes, mainly) that would be of limited
use in case of a Russian conventional attack. This practice suggests
that the Russian threat had receded from military planning. One
State Department official observed a similar move on the Russian
side: “Look at their military forces. If they thought the United States
was a military threat, they wouldn’t be focusing their military forces
on how to win the Chechen war … From our perspective, the rela-
tionship is demilitarized.” Throughout my interviews in Brussels,
I was struck by how widespread this assurance was, as well as by
the fact that it reached the highest echelons of the NATO hierarchy.
For instance, several national delegates ruled out any sort of mili-
tary planning targeted against Russia, as did a top general from the
NATO military committee. Most strikingly, a senior member of the
Secretary-General’s office went as far as to say that “Russia nowadays
looks to the West rather the same way that the United States looks to
Mexico or Canada. There are some issues, like soft lumber trade, but
it’s basically a very predictable environment.”
Some Atlantic policymakers could still associate a number of
potential threats with Russia, but none was of a military nature.
In Washington, a senior policymaker could imagine Russia turning
into a threat in any of three ways: by “using energy as a political
weapon”; by giving rise to “instability and chaos should the gov-
ernment implode”; and through acts of mischief – “Russia’s newly
found assertiveness and post-imperial angst means it can cause a lot
of problems as we try to solve things in the international commu-
nity.” He concluded: “Notice that military aggression or confl ict is
not one of the threats. I think Russians would be shocked if they
could see inside our minds and NATO planning and realize how
little we think about Russia.” A member of the French delegation to
NATO similarly affi rmed that the only threat he could see coming
from Moscow was the implosion of the state. According to a senior
official at NATO’s Moscow bureau, talk of military confrontation
was nothing but “hogwash.” On the Atlantic side, it seems as though
the possibility of a military confrontation with Russia was simply not
part of the possibilities entertained on a daily basis by 2006 security
practitioners.
The logic of practicality at the NRC 101
No, never; never threats of force. No, never even contemplated … I think
that the pattern has now been set with Russia – that you deal with each
other through negotiation. You deal with each other through bringing
the Russians into a system of rules and regulations and laws … That’s
the way you deal with it and so, force, that’s pretty well out of the
question.
104 International Security in Practice
If you want a really good idea of how in my view the world has changed
for the better, it is that my predecessors would’ve spent one way or another
somewhere in the seventy percent of their time thinking about Russia.
I spend less than five percent of my time thinking about Russia. That’s
sixty-five percent different – it’s representative of energy put to providing
security goods in a more proactive way, in a more beneficial way and not
in a senseless way … I do not spend my time by and large worrying about
a Russian threat.
A latent mistrust
Despite this sea change, interview data and practice analysis also
reveal that a non-negligible level of latent mistrust of mutual intentions
remained in Russian–Atlantic relations in 2006. For instance, one
German colonel believed that through its participation in Operation
Active Endeavour (see below), Russia primarily “wants to gain intel-
ligence” on NATO. Another Alliance official concurred: “Let’s face
it: it gives them a great insight into how we do business, a great intel-
ligence gathering. They now have NATO secret communications on
their ships, they see our standard operating procedures, they have our
doctrine … That’s good stuff if you’re Russia!”3 This mistrust was
undoubtedly reciprocal: for instance, one American officer confided
2
Lo (2002 , 154).
3
Another NATO official would recognize the situation but without taking
offence: “[The Russians] use NATO simply to know what’s happening. So
they’re here, they’re everywhere. They are represented with a lot of diplomats.
They try to proliferate meetings. They meet with a lot of people. So what?
This is basically information and intelligence gathering that they’re doing
here. Which is fi ne.”
The logic of practicality at the NRC 105
that “in private, many Russian officials ask about hidden motives
behind NATO’s willingness to cooperate.” Trust, which stems from
practical sense, formed a thin intersubjective basis for interaction at
the 2006 NRC.
According to interview data, there seemed to be four main sources
of mistrust at the NRC. First (and not limited to this case), it is an
inherent part of the military habitus to plan for the worst contin-
gencies.4 Generally speaking, the military officers I interviewed were
more careful than civilians in their assessment of the possibility of
force in Russian–Atlantic relations. Entertaining worst-case scenar-
ios, after all, is a habit that comes with their job. As a result, they
were less prone to forget about the possibility of military confronta-
tion. A British military officer, now a speechwriter at NATO head-
quarters, put the matter in perspective:
I think one has to differentiate between what is a threat and what is a risk.
If you say a threat is more immediate, a threat is a combination of capa-
bility and intent. Now I would argue that at the moment, Russia still has
the capability but not the intent. That is not to say that changes within the
Russian Federation, in the future years, might not change this and that the
intent would be there as well. But I reckon we would get enough indica-
tors of that to be able to reorient ourselves as necessary … If the threat is
capability and intent, we are not there at the moment. I would say we are at
a risk, which is where the capability exists, but the intent – there’s always
the potential for it to be re-instantiated, to reappear. But I do not think it
will happen and I hope it won’t happen, but as long as there’s the possibility
there, one has to protect.
4
See, e.g., the debate on military planning during the Cold War in Heuser
(1991); and Cox (1992).
106 International Security in Practice
relations more easily than civil servants. Military officers dislike the
ups and downs of politics and they consequently adopt a much more
down-to-earth attitude. For instance, one American NATO officer
turned my question about the possibility of violence on its head in an
attempt to temper his mistrust: “On the possibility of Cold War-like
confrontation, one needs to be cautious. But what really is unthink-
able is the fact that Russia is now at NATO headquarters!”
A second source of Russian–Atlantic latent mistrust is, quite obvi-
ously, the decades of Cold War confrontation. To be sure, lasting rivalry
cannot but leave traces in habitus. These marks appeared especially
pronounced among Eastern European security practitioners: “we still
struggle with the question of whether Russia and the Soviet Union
are two different terms or not.” But remnants of confrontation were
also widespread in other NATO countries: “Old habits die hard,”
as one State Department practitioner readily conceded. One of his
colleagues was equally realistic: “I was brought up during the Cold
War so I’m still skeptical of the Russians. Russia wants to influence
NATO, and the NRC makes mischief making easier. Russia looks for
opportunities to exploit differences among allies.” Significantly, on
the Alliance’s side, this fear that Moscow could “exploit cracks” was
in line with what was probably the most pervasive concern in Brussels
during the Cold War. According to Ira Straus, in the post-Cold War
era this fear for Alliance consensus has been the foremost stumbling
block in creating a new NATO–Russia relationship.5 My interview
data suggest that this point is well taken.
Reciprocally, the Russians also inherited deeply ingrained disposi-
tions of mistrust towards NATO. A middle-aged professor from one
of Moscow’s most prestigious schools told me, as if stating the obvi-
ous: “Of course NATO’s main duty is to plan war against Russia.
This is a well-known fact.” Another security official depicted Cold
War stereotypes in Russia “like the dead holding the living.” To be
sure, Russia’s history of invasions from its western borders has left
an important imprint on strategic thinking. On both sides, accusa-
tions of “outdated, Cold War-like thinking” abound – a practice that
is clearly part of symbolic power struggles (see Chapters 5 and 6).
During his tenure as American permanent representative to NATO,
Nicholas Burns regretted that “[o]ne abiding legacy of the Cold
5
Straus (2003, 234).
The logic of practicality at the NRC 107
6
Quoted in US Department of State (2004).
108 International Security in Practice
force to solve international confl icts and that Russia could eventually
become the next target. In the words of a very moderate Russian
expert:
7
All-Russian Center for the Study of Public Opinion (VTsIOM) poll quoted
in NATO (2006, 2). See also White (2006, 144–6); and White, Korosteleva
and Allison (2006).
The logic of practicality at the NRC 109
8
Quoted in Shegedin and Zygar (2006).
The logic of practicality at the NRC 111
top NATO military officer put it. Against that inertia, older European
members “have to have [the new members] mature and go beyond
that. This will play a very important part in the future” of Russian–
Atlantic relations.
Because the new members’ suspicions are often echoed by the US, in
2006 NATO’s policy toward Russia boiled down to the lowest com-
mon denominator. As one senior NATO official summarized, “the
span of policies toward Russia has enlarged. There was a time where
the ease to reach a consensus was better. [But now] we don’t really
have an active Russian policy. We do things with Russia, we cooper-
ate, but in terms of steering a course, it is very difficult because the
span has widened so much. [It was] absolutely easier in the 1990s.”
On that basis, it seems appropriate to conclude that the entry into
NATO of former Soviet satellites has put a strong brake on the post-
Cold War Russian–Atlantic pacification process. So much so, said
one senior NATO official, that “[i]t’s hard to characterize NATO’s
approach to the Russians on a continuum because the change in mem-
bership has changed the character of the Alliance.”
Several practitioners reported that there were “two factions inside
NATO” as far as its Russia policy was concerned: on one side
were countries such as Germany, France, Italy, Spain, Norway and
Belgium, which exhibited a higher level of trust toward Russia; and
on the other side clustered the US, the United Kingdom, Poland and
the Baltic countries, which remained more mistrustful of Moscow.
According to a Russian delegate who had been posted to Brussels
for more than a decade, the new NATO members “simply do what
‘Master’ says,” while countries from Old Europe are “more reason-
able.” I too could ascertain a division in my interviews, although I
observed a particularly high level of variance among American and
British practitioners. Generally speaking, however, London and
Washington took a more cautious stance toward Moscow than other
Western European capitals. All in all, in 2006 everything took place
as if relations with Russia divided NATO member states a lot more
than they cemented them.
the relationship has become much more stable and pragmatic. If I take a
fi fteen-year window, that was obviously a period of dramatic highs and
lows. We got to know each other to an extent where we managed to rein
that in a little bit and keep expectations real, maintain a level of transpar-
ency to ensure that nobody gets surprised by what the other side does.
You have these honeymoon periods where you ask, “how are you going to
do this together?” I’d actually – let’s be honest: after about six months you
decide you’ve done as much as you can in that particular field and you sit
back and twiddle your thumbs. And say “what else can we do?” You hit
another sort of flat period where nothing is happening – then something
else will happen and you’ll say, “oh, we can do that together,” and you
go off again on another of your honeymoon periods where everything is
hunky-dory and you’re working closely together.
9
One interesting exception, however, was a State Department official
who responded: “You always have to imagine such ruptures, because in
diplomacy when there is a big crisis the response is often a rupture of
relations. Look at Pyongyang, or Tehran: our embassies disappeared when
114 International Security in Practice
things get too hostile. So yes it’s possible, for instance if Russia takes military
action against Georgia or something like that.” The events of summer 2008
obviously proved him right.
10
Fritch (2007, 2).
The logic of practicality at the NRC 115
11
NATO (2004a).
116 International Security in Practice
Does it mean that having that forum with them is going to sway their
mind on certain issues? Any country is going to say, “No, we have our
national interests and we’re going to stick with them.” But the chances are
you’re going to see it coming. You can work to get around it and talk to
them about it but at the end of the day … you’re not going to sway them
from that.
12
NATO (2007, 6).
The logic of practicality at the NRC 119
An elusive momentum
As considerable as it may look from my interview data, the normali-
zation of disputes at the NRC was considerably thwarted in 2006 by
the fact that it remained partly hostage to the larger political relation-
ship between Moscow and the West. The momentum described by a
handful of practitioners appeared quite elusive to many others. As a
NATO military officer posted in Moscow described the NRC diplo-
macy: “It’s not a process that’s self-propelling, with its own momen-
tum. We really have to be creative … you always need new impetus.”
Relatedly, certain practitioners expressed skepticism as to the capacity
of the NRC to work in the absence of political will. While in 2006 the
NRC still benefited from the “highest support” of key governments,
it remained to be seen how much momentum the NRC practitioners’
could keep going, and for how long, should political will falter. One
imaginative interviewee in Washington elaborated: “I don’t think one
ever assumes that institutions and mechanisms can weather any and
all storms … You try to build the building to withstand the force of
the vast majority of storms, but the exception may blow it down.”
With the benefit of hindsight, the Georgia War turned out to be such
an exception, at least temporarily (see Chapter 6). A NATO diplomat
in Moscow also perceived the two upcoming presidential elections in
the US and Russia in 2008 as “clouding” the relationship. Change in
political leadership, especially in the main countries represented at
the NRC, mattered a lot from the practitioners’ point of view. One
NATO official recalled, for instance, that “you will see a particular
country that is particularly pro-Russia one day after a set of elections
and particularly anti the next – Germany being one.” The reverse
could now be said of the Obama administration as compared to the
Bush years.
In addition, practitioners pointed out two other factors that exog-
enously determined the quality of the NRC relationship. The fi rst
was NATO’s own process of transformation, which had been unfold-
ing for a decade and a half and whose endpoint remained far from
clear even to its own civil servants. When asked where they thought
the NATO–Russia relationship would be in twenty years, several
Alliance officials answered that the main difficulty was that “it’s dif-
ficult to say what NATO will be in ten or twenty years.” Because of
its ever-changing mission, “NATO can’t do that much [with Moscow]
120 International Security in Practice
13 14
Shevtsov (1997, 4). Kipp et al. (2000, 56–9).
124 International Security in Practice
15 16
Allison (2006, 111–12). Kujat (2002 , 1).
The logic of practicality at the NRC 125
17
In the weeks following this exercise, Moscow requested help from the
British navy in the rescue of one of its submarine crew near the Kamchatka
peninsula. This success was often hailed by NATO officers as a concrete
NRC deliverable from which Russia benefited.
126 International Security in Practice
of Russian military officers taught for the very fi rst time. The fi rst
academic year of a military-based defense reform course for active-
duty military officers serving at the Russian Ministry of Defense
also came to a successful conclusion in 2006. The course, approved
by the NRC in 2004, had been developed jointly by NATO and a
top-tier Moscow academic institute. During the same year, Mobile
Education Training Teams took part in more than forty events,
including another fi rst: Russian military teaching at the NATO school
in Oberammergau. The NRC’s many working groups of experts also
developed half a dozen detailed glossaries on matters of special opera-
tions forces (2006), peacekeeping (2006), combating terrorism (2006),
defense reform (2005), or nuclear terminology (2004).
The NRC provided a physical locus of face-to-face, daily interac-
tion among Russian and Atlantic security practitioners. In addition
to its mission to the Alliance’s headquarters, in 2004 Moscow also
opened a liaison branch office in Mons as well as a small team within
the Partnership Coordination Cell at SHAPE. As a senior NATO pol-
icymaker put it: “We now have a structural forum … where they meet
all the time on all issues and talk … You start to cycle through offi-
cials who know you, you don’t have such an ignorance of NATO and
suspicion because they know how it works.” The ongoing presence
of Russian officials in Brussels, as well as their almost daily meet-
ings with NATO counterparts, accounted for an important dimen-
sion of the NRC institutionalization. For instance, I was genuinely
astonished to hear a Russian official express the view that “Russia sits
around the table like any other country. It is a member of the family.”
He added that “there is this glue” at the NRC. Interpersonal bonds
seem to work both ways. A British delegate admitted that in prepara-
tion for NRC meetings she would approach her Russian counterparts
the same way she does her French or American ones. A French official
told me a similar story, insisting that he calls his Russian colleagues
in preparation for a meeting, asks for support or draws limits as he
would for inter-Allied negotiations.
Institutionalization at NATO headquarters found its echo in
Russia, though on a much smaller scale. The NRC was represented
in Moscow through an Information Office and a Military Liaison
hosted by the Belgian embassy. A “hotline” was also established in
late 2003 between NATO headquarters and the Russian Defense
Minister. On the civil side, NATO launched a website in Russian in
128 International Security in Practice
When I started in the middle of the 1990s, I couldn’t have imagined that
so soon, in seven to eight years – a very short historical period – NATO–
Russia relations would be characterized by the Russian embassy as the
most successful of all the directions of Russian foreign policy. With NATO
we cooperate. Of course it’s not sufficient, I would like to see more on
The logic of practicality at the NRC 129
The net result was, to use the words of another observer in Moscow,
the emergence of a zdravyi smysl (здравый смысл) or a “common
sense” that the current NATO–Russia relationship had become safe
from mutual violence. This was obviously a sea change from the
Cold War.
For NATO practitioners, engaging the Russian army aimed to
debunk certain enduring myths about the Alliance so as to foster a
workmanlike atmosphere: “We made some progress in the Russian
military,” said one NATO official. “They are much more friendly to
us and much more constructive than they were, I don’t know, ten
years ago … You can’t compare [Russia’s Chief of General Staff Yuri]
Baluyevsky with his predecessors, for instance – he’s much better.
Also the guys here at the Russian mission are different from the previ-
ous staff. They’re ready to cooperate.” According to one American
policymaker, the NRC contributed to changing Russia’s perception
of the Alliance: “They’ve been too much around,” he said. Judging
from high-level declarations on Russia’s side, there seemed to be some
truth to these assessments: Defense Minister Sergei Ivanov declared,
for instance, that “the NATO–Russia cooperation has outgrown the
‘adolescence’ age,” hailing practical achievements on theatre missile
defense and others.18 Although these sanguine statements were often
balanced by harsh criticisms of the Alliance, they represented a signif-
icant departure from those made by the otherwise more pro-Western
Kremlin in the 1990s.
Also striking was the fact that discussions at the NRC created what
a French delegate called a “variable geometry” of political coalitions,
with Russia sometimes siding with certain allies and sometimes with
others depending on the issue: “You come to a point at the NRC
where we have lively discussions not only twenty-six plus one, but
also among allies,” confi rmed an official from the German Delegation
to the Alliance. This constituted a very important departure from
the politics of the PJC, in which the NATO members’ positions were
“pre-cooked” in a prior NAC meeting. These Allied positions were
18
Ivanov (2004).
130 International Security in Practice
19
According to one State Department official, “in theory the NRC works at
twenty-seven and not twenty-six plus one. But in practice, Russia is not part
of NATO. There exists allied solidarity. We can’t let Russia too much in.”
20
Pouliot (2003).
The logic of practicality at the NRC 131
noting for instance that “we will never get them to agree that you
cannot solve terrorism in purely military terms.” For a British official,
deep differences in threat perceptions largely explained contempo-
rary Russian–Atlantic distrust: “The Russians see the war on terror-
ism and the American defi nition as an excuse for American power
to intervene where major oil reserves are.” Equally, many Atlantic
practitioners remained suspicious of “anti-terrorist operations” in
Chechnya. Although in 2006 NATO and Russia were doing a lot of
stuff together, more often than not their respective practices belonged
to contrasting organizational cultures.
21
On bureaucratic culture, see Barnett and Finnemore (2004).
22
Of course, any Western characterization of Russian practitioners reveals as
much, if not more, about the NATO lambda habitus. It is in this spirit that
I record mutual perceptions of daily interactions.
23
See also Williams (2005, 46).
The logic of practicality at the NRC 135
NATO officials get the impression that the Russians don’t give it their
best energy. They’re very rigid in meetings and negotiations. We get the
feeling that we’re dealing with an ancient mindset. It is probably instruc-
tions directly from Moscow, where certain people want certain messages
through. But it does not belong to the dialogue we’ve been having over the
last few years. They sometimes come out of the blue with some confronta-
tional language.
As one Russian expert summed up: “if Putin orders, they will do it!”
This obviously left little room for informal compromises and exchanges
at the NRC. For instance, one senior military officer complained that
during NRC meetings, the Russians strictly present national positions
but refuse to exchange ideas in a casual way. Informal discussions
are kept to a minimum. As one British officer illustrated: “Relations
are always cordial. We smile and drink vodka … But the relationship
fi nishes right after the meeting.”
Top-down control of NATO–Russia interaction was portrayed as a
serious brake on practical cooperation on the ground. Even a Russian
professor admitted that “[w]e have a very Byzantine organization.
Routines are not possible! All decisions are taken in the Kremlin and
then sent to the administrative level. [Bureaucrats] cannot push initia-
tives, only follow guidelines.” As a result NATO was unable to reach
a large number of Russian civil servants and militaries, especially
at the lower echelons. As a senior officer posted in Moscow said,
136 International Security in Practice
24
This interviewee added: “We get the impression that people who have taken
courses at [a] NATO school or some Western institutes have not succeeded in
their military as we expected.”
The logic of practicality at the NRC 137
been dealing with the Russians for decades believed that “the only
language the Russians understand is that of strength. Respect comes
with strength.” For a NATO official posted in Moscow, another trait
of the Russian culture was especially striking: “This is a country of
opposites, which never gives in suppleness … It doesn’t support the
middle – it’s all or nothing. This is a socio-cultural trait but it affects
external policies. Russian reactions are generated through this: always
very strong reactions, in favor or not.” Lionel Ponsard supplies a tell-
ing example, which also touches on the importance of language in
diplomatic interaction:
25
Ponsard (2007, 155).
26
Williams (2005, 47 fn. 18). Major General Peter Williams was the fi rst head
of the NATO Military Liaison Mission in Moscow from 2002 to 2005.
138 International Security in Practice
getting informal with NATO officials means you’re burnt within the
Russian administration. We’ve tracked officers with whom we’ve
been in touch: they’re burnt. The Cold War is not over.” A number
of NATO officials were not comfortable in addressing this sensitive
topic but they could not deny that they too had had that impression.
Oksana Antonenko cites the example of General Shevtsov, who led
the Russian contingent in the Balkans and was widely hailed for his
success in cooperating with NATO’s SACEUR. Upon his return to
Russia, he was met with very little cooperation at the Ministry of
Defense and was ultimately moved to the Interior Ministry. 27
Finally, Atlantic practitioners also apprehended a culture of secrecy
inside the Russian bureaucratic apparatus. A particularly telling
example is Operation Active Endeavour, which gave Russians “a great
insight into how we do business, a great intelligence gathering. They
now have NATO secret communications on their ships, they see our
standard operating procedures, they see our doctrines.” Yet this open-
ness was not reciprocated, according to a senior NATO officer: “They
have a big access. Now the flip side is we get access to theirs too. It
hasn’t been the case yet.” This view was echoed by a NATO military
commander, who estimated that “we don’t get back from Russia the
openness we give. NATO is more forward.” Another example was that
Russian practitioners at the Brussels headquarters had access to the
entire organization’s directory, whereas NATO officials in Moscow
do not benefit from similar conditions. In a similar vein, a British
officer from the Ministry of Defence described the Russian reaction
when given a tour of the building in London: “They’re amazed. This
doesn’t happen in Moscow.”
But Russian practitioners were not outdone when it came to criti-
cizing the other party’s organizational culture. The general feeling in
Moscow was that NATO bureaucratic practices betrayed an insuper-
able hubris – a conviction that the Alliance is right and that Russia can
only nod to it (see Chapters 5 and 6). A Russian official dispatched to
NATO headquarters put it bluntly: “NATO puts a lot of pressure on
Russia and puts her on the defensive. The United States keeps lecturing
Russia. This is not welcome. It looks like diktats for losing the Cold
War. But Russia didn’t lose the Cold War: it was an internal choice.
27
Antonenko (2007, 94).
The logic of practicality at the NRC 139
The West’s main fault is that, for its own good, it has imposed a choice on
Russia: either the West or the East … I don’t think the West is being sincere
in forcing this choice … The West likes to think of itself as the keeper of
values and as a ruler. It wants everybody to act like it, like a steamroller …
Yeltsin thought of himself as a pupil, but the government and the citizens
felt insulted to be treated as such … The West wants to be a tutor: why? …
What the West mainly lacks is the willingness to understand. It knows how
to impose its own values but it doesn’t want to understand that they are
different in Western and Eastern Europe.
On many issues it works the same. They begin by saying they want to do
this and that with us. We respond that such programs already exist in
the larger framework of the Euro-Atlantic partnership. They answer that
they don’t want to do it with the Georgians and everyone. They want an
exclusive relationship with us, so we need to come up with a new docu-
ment. We tell them we already have established this document and we offer
it to Russia so that they can apply it. They reply that they’re not NATO
applicants and that they want a joint program of equals. They come from
the Warsaw Pact where they were the kings. They don’t want to work with
NATO concepts, they want to add something Russian. But we say no.
They are progressively getting to it and mindsets are evolving. They need
time: one does not catch fl ies with vinegar.
140 International Security in Practice
This quotation reveals that, well founded or not, Atlantic and Russian
complaints about one another’s ways of “doing stuff” are not absolute
but relational: they emerge from a deeper struggle over who gets to
defi ne the rules of the game at the NRC.
28 29
Gheciu (2005, 13). Gheciu (2005, 16).
The logic of practicality at the NRC 141
30 31
Neumann (2005b, 13). Primakov (2006, 2).
142 International Security in Practice
On the Atlantic side, the end of the Cold War sparked a widespread
belief that the time had come for the West and its institutions to export
their values to the rest of the world. NATO’s success in socializing
Eastern Europe bolstered this self-understanding as the role model
of democracy, freedom and civilization. This evolution fostered a
preexisting Western disposition towards universalism and bolstered
organizations such as NATO in their role of teacher. In my inter-
views, I was struck by the extent to which many Atlantic practitioners
would equate (unconsciously, for the most part) the peculiar policies
advocated by NATO with the consensus forged in the “international
community.” As the embodiment of the international community, the
Alliance should mold Russia to become a part of it, believed one sen-
ior official from State Department: “The long-term objective has to
be Russia’s integration into the Euro-Atlantic community, the inter-
national community, on all levels, based on shared values; joining the
international club of democratic, market-oriented countries. There
is no competing model for organizing political and economic life in
the international community aside from liberal democracy, rule of
law and market economics.” The background assumption in these
statements, which has consistently informed the Alliance’s political
discourse since the end of the Cold War, holds that NATO is bound
to be the teacher. It is not Brussels that has to make compromises, but
Moscow.
With Russia qua Great Power and NATO qua international com-
munity, there are two masters but no apprentices at the NRC. The
Atlantic superiority complex is variously demonstrated in practition-
ers’ understanding of Russian–Atlantic relations. For instance, one
NATO official told me that “Russia still hasn’t fully grasped the situa-
tion the world and Russia are in.” Another policymaker in Washington
regretted that “Russia has gone pre-Cold War in its mindset, in a kind
of survival of the fittest.” He continued with a particularly telling
analogy picturing Russia as
this huge, seventeen year old male football player. He’s big and strong and
no adult would presume to force him to do anything … The problem for
everyone around him is that you want him to be a good neighbor and a
productive member of society. You wanna talk him through all this anger
and aggression and resentment. But everything you do and say, he just
turns against you … You have to wait for him to grow.
The logic of practicality at the NRC 143
32
At some point during the interview, this representative grabbed
my recorder, shut it down, and lamented grudgingly: “Some say here at
NATO that Germany is Russia’s ‘little friend’: this simply isn’t true.”
This preoccupation with not appearing too pliant with the Russians
in front of NATO allies was shared by all the German officials and officers
I met.
144 International Security in Practice
From this perspective, he added, the NRC “puts limits on how inde-
pendent its actions can be because it has to go through these multi-
lateral frameworks. We want to make those stronger to get Russia
totally embedded.” One Alliance official posted in Moscow was just
as blunt: “It may be true we impose some stuff, but we do it with
their consent. Otherwise, nothing gets done.” As one German official
who negotiated with the Russians on behalf of NATO throughout the
1990s recognized, “from their point of view, they have lots of reasons
to complain and to say: ‘Well, you do listen to us, but you don’t take
into account our argument.’ That’s what you continuously hear from
them.’” Commenting on Russia’s influence over NATO, he admitted
that it has “[v]ery little, so objectively they have a point. There is very
little that we’ve done in the past to accommodate Russian concerns.”
In their relationship with NATO counterparts, however, the
Russians did not suffer from any kind of reciprocal inferiority com-
plex. In 2006, the dominant narrative of Great Power in Moscow
meant that the partnership should be among “equals.” As a result,
NATO’s self-attributed role as a teacher was not recognized by the
Russians – in fact, it was rather despised. Since the end of the Cold
War, NATO has tried hard to impose its views and steer Russia’s
course, with some success during the 1990s. But these attempts also
fed a backlash, as resentment steadily built up in Moscow. As one
expert observed: “The strong attitude in Moscow is that Russia was
humiliated in the 1990s many times.” For a Russian diplomat in
Brussels, the main policy that the Alliance imposed despite Russia’s
opposition was NATO enlargement (see Chapters 5 and 6): “Russia’s
opinions were not taken into account. Here, actions mean more than
The logic of practicality at the NRC 145
33
Quoted in Ministry of Foreign Affairs of the Russian Federation (2007a).
146 International Security in Practice
become members it’s much easier because we have our standards and we
say, “if you want to become members of NATO you have to do this, this,
and this” and they don’t have a choice. They have a choice but the other
choice is not really an option for them. But there is no leverage basically on
Russia. [All that NATO can use is] well, logic, pure logic. We try to con-
vince them that the way we are doing it is much more effective, much more
efficient, actually affordable, etc. It’s pure logic I think.
The Russians said they wanted to develop new joint procedures for peace-
keeping. The United States and other allies said: “Enough! We draw dif-
ferent lessons and we can do this without these new procedures but by
associating with you when there is a need.” There was reluctance so the
The logic of practicality at the NRC 147
debate stopped. We don’t talk about this anymore. The issue is not dead
but it’s on ice. That’s the problem with Russia: everything that was easy to
do, we’ve done. We’ve eaten all the meat on the bone, and now that we’re
at the bone we feel we’ve eaten enough.
This chapter and Chapter 6 look back into history and seek to explain
the main fi nding of Chapter 4 – that in 2006, NRC practitioners
embodied diplomacy as a normal though not a self-evident practice in
solving Russian–Atlantic disputes. Recovering the practical logics of
NRC diplomacy raises the question: what made this practical sense
possible in the fi rst place? Since all socially constructed meanings
emerge from past social struggles, one must add a diachronic dimen-
sion to the analysis and set meanings in motion (see Chapter 3). To
do so, I analyze the historical evolution of NATO–Russia interactions
with regards to the double enlargement – a vexing and persistent bone
of contention in the post-Cold War era.
In order to shed light on practices, I combine field analysis with the
interpretive study of habitus. In terms of the former, I locate Russia
and NATO inside the field of international security and describe
the evolving rules of the game in the post-Cold War era, in particu-
lar the changes in the conversion rates between forms of capital.
For the sake of clarity, and in accordance with the recent evolution
of the field’s doxa, I reduce the range of capital in this field to only
two types of resources. First, material-institutional capital refers
to military forces, money and material riches (industrial capac-
ity, demographics, etc.), as well as networks of allies, friends and
other institutional ties. This form of capital was the main currency
of Cold War realpolitik and balancing. Second, cultural-symbolic
capital designates artifacts, narratives and symbols that defi ne
the meaning of the world (what is real, true, etc.) and legitimize it
(what is right, good, etc.). These resources are the staple of the post-
Cold War, democratic peace era. Below I explain this doxic shift in
more detail; the important point, at this stage, is that mapping the
148
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 149
1
Williams and Neumann (2000, 372).
150 International Security in Practice
2
Gheciu (2005, 4–9).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 151
3 4
Gheciu (2005, 9). Williams (2007).
5
Adler (1998); Flynn and Farrell (1999); Ghebali (1996).
152 International Security in Practice
6 7 8
Adler (2008). Council of the EU (2003, 10). Gheciu (2005, 5).
9
Villumsen defi nes doxic battles as “basic struggles determining what is valued
in the field and what is considered worthless” and based on the mobilization
of capital (Villumsen 2008, 81).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 153
10 11
Williams (2007, 41). Williams (2007, 40–1).
154 International Security in Practice
12
I am indebted to Michael Williams for helping me formulate this argument.
13 14 15
Williams (2007, 40). Wörner (1991, 8). NATO (1990).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 155
16
Asmus, Kugler and Larrabee (1993, 31).
156 International Security in Practice
While some Russian officials expressed concern that the Oslo summit
could reinforce NATO’s position of strength in European security,
these fears concerned the Alliance per se, not the internal mode of
pursuing security that the organization had come to profess. Clearly,
the new Russian elites who came to power in 1992 arrived at the
Kremlin strongly disposed to support the new rules of the interna-
tional security game.
These proto-liberal dispositions were largely inherited from
Gorbachev’s “New Thinking.” Heavily inspired by the CSCE process,
the New Thinking was premised on the notion that security ought to
be mutual or common.17 According to the doctrine of cooperative
security, the existence of the security dilemma means that security
cannot be pursued unilaterally. In addition, resorting to force was
deemed neither legitimate nor effective as a means of solving interna-
tional disputes. These principles were in line with the internal mode
of pursuing security by repudiating force and encouraging domestic
reforms. Several actions taken by Moscow in the late 1980s, includ-
ing asymmetric and unilateral reductions in nuclear and conventional
forces, as well as the surrender of the Soviet glacis in Eastern Europe,
were obvious manifestations of these ideas. This is not to say that
Gorbachev was an idealist politician who weakly surrendered to the
West: there is no doubt that the New Thinking was an attempt to
renew communism at a time of severe domestic and international
crisis and give Moscow a higher moral ground vis-à-vis the West.18
Breaking with the Cold War logic, Gorbachev and his team began
pursuing security by other means – eventually losing control over the
new dynamic they had unleashed.
After the implosion of the USSR in December 1991, the new ruling
elites in Moscow essentially followed the precepts of New Thinking
and the internal mode of pursuing security. In an article published dur-
ing the summer of 1992, Foreign Minister Andrei Kozyrev explained
how the notion of human rights had become the backbone of Russia’s
foreign policy:
17
Checkel (1997); Evangelista (2002); Lévesque (1995); Thomas (2001).
18
Welch Larson and Shevchenko (2003).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 157
will combine our efforts with those taken by all states which recognize
that respect for human rights and fundamental freedoms is an essential
component of peace, justice and well being. This principle has become one
of the mainstays of the foreign policy of the Russian Federation … The
supremacy of human rights is indeed the basis on which states should seek
to discover a common language, a sort of “humanitarian Esperanto.”19
19
Kozyrev (1992 , 289). Note that my discourse analysis does not presume that
speakers necessarily believe what they say; there is no way to probe what is
between people’s ears. However, the very performance of this discourse in
public speaks volumes about the Russian elites’ “sense of their place” in the
early 1990s.
20
Kozyrev (1992 , 290). 21 English (2000).
158 International Security in Practice
22 23
Sergei Blagovolin quoted in Guk (1992). Kozyrev (1993, 3).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 159
the essential forum for consultation among the Allies. While this
should have logically tempered Moscow’s enthusiasm, for a time the
enlargement of NATO’s functions to peacekeeping and partnership
was still considered by the new Russian elite as fitting the security-
from-the-inside-out approach. For instance, the inclusive and coop-
erative spirit of the NACC was in line with the CSCE’s cooperative
security approach and seemed to suit Russian interests quite well. In
October 1993, when the Americans fi rst floated the idea of the PfP
with the Russians, the initial reaction was still quite favorable. Yeltsin
was reported to approve the outreach initiative toward the post-
communist world insofar as it included Russia. Everything took place
as though the Russian apprentice would nod in response to whatever
the Atlantic master said or did.
NATO’s domination over Russia was also obvious in Moscow’s
early actions with respect to the civil war in Yugoslavia, as the Alliance
did not lose much time in putting its new peacekeeping function into
practice. The Bosnian civil war provided Brussels with its fi rst test
case of the collective security doctrine. NATO became involved in
the conflict very gradually. During the summer of 1992, presidential
candidate Bill Clinton was the fi rst to mention the possibility of Allied
air strikes against Bosnian Serbs in combination with the lifting of
UN sanctions against the Bosnian government (the “lift and strike”
strategy). European allies, however, were not convinced and favored
the UN-sponsored Vance–Owen plan, which fi nally faltered in mid-
1993. NATO then undertook two operations intended to support UN
Security Council resolutions on the deployment of the UN Protection
Force (UNPROFOR) in Bosnia. After the bombing of Sarajevo’s mar-
ket in February 1994, the UN Secretary-General asked the Security
Council to mandate NATO air strikes on Bosnian Serb positions.
Starting in April, Alliance forces led by the Americans intensified
their bombing of Bosnian Serb forces until the Srebrenica massacre,
during the summer of 1995, which led to Operation Deliberate Force
and a total of about 3,500 sorties. The Dayton Accord was finally
concluded later that fall under strong American leadership.
The most striking aspect in NATO–Russia dealings over the
Alliance’s involvement in the Bosnian civil war is the explicit sup-
port that the Russian government offered in the beginning. Until
February 1994, Russia shared “the predominant Western interpre-
tation of events in Bosnia: that Serb expansionism and aggressive
160 International Security in Practice
24 25
Headley (2003, 211). UN Security Council (1993).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 161
26
Talbott (2002 , 123). Equally telling is the conclusion drawn by James
Goldgeier and Michael McFaul on the basis of dozens of interviews with
American officials: “On Bosnia, most officials in the U.S. government just
did not want to have to worry about the Russian angle” (Goldgeier and
McFaul 2003, 199).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 163
27 28
Talbott (2002 , 170). Talbott (2002 , 186).
164 International Security in Practice
29 30
Stankevich (1992 , 5). Schimmelfennig (2003, 244).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 165
Alliance “would not be in confl ict with the process of European inte-
gration, including the interests of Russia.”31 In the next few days,
the Russian Foreign Ministry tempered the president’s declaration,
adding that expanding NATO would be counterproductive while
acknowledging the sovereign right of every state to choose means of
ensuring its security. In an obvious act of retraction, in September
Yeltsin wrote a letter to the main Western capitals warning against a
mechanical expansion of the North Atlantic bloc and instead propos-
ing that NATO and Moscow jointly guarantee the security of Eastern
European countries. The Russian president also argued that enlarge-
ment would be illegal in view of the terms of German unification
and that relations between Russia and NATO should always be “a
few degrees warmer” than those between Brussels and ex-Soviet sat-
ellites.32 Yet the damage was apparently done: Yeltsin’s declaration
in Warsaw had opened a window of opportunity for the proponents
of enlargement. For instance, Secretary-General Wörner, who had
been a timid supporter until then, began to endorse the policy more
openly.
Russian diplomats tried hard to back-pedal and state Moscow’s
strong opposition to the Alliance’s expansion as clearly as possible.
In November 1993, the Federal Security Service released an impor-
tant report on NATO enlargement. Written under Primakov’s lead-
ership, it epitomized the dominant thinking in ruling circles at the
time. First, the report noted that “many of Russia’s apprehensions
associated with NATO’s entry into the countries of Central and
Eastern Europe would be removed or eased if there were guaran-
tees of priority development for the process of changing the alli-
ance’s functions.” In the report’s analysis, not only were such
guarantees never given, the Alliance’s threats of force with regards
to the Bosnian civil war only compounded Russian concerns about
NATO’s functional evolution. Second, the report regretted the
“fi xed nature of stereotypes of bloc thinking, which is especially
characteristic of a number of representatives of the military leader-
ship in the Western countries.” Third, while acknowledging that
it would be “incorrect to proceed from [the premise] that NATO’s
geographic expansion would serve to create a staging ground for
infl icting a strike on Russia,” the report emphasized the “objective
31 32
Quoted in Parkhomenko (1993). Quoted in Asmus (2002 , 47).
166 International Security in Practice
33 34
Quoted in Poleshchuk (1993). Quoted in Yusin (1993).
35 36
NATO (1994a) (emphasis added). Quoted in Talbott (2002 , 115).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 167
37
NATO (1994b). 38 NATO (1994c).
39 40
Goldgeier and McFaul (2003, 184). Kozyrev (1995, 9).
168 International Security in Practice
Europe, even before it has managed to shrug off the legacy of the Cold
War, is risking encumbering itself with a cold peace … NATO was created
in Cold War times. Today, it is trying to fi nd its place in Europe, not with-
out difficulty. It is important that this search not create new divisions, but
promote European unity. We believe that the plans of expanding NATO
are contrary to this logic. Why sow the seeds of distrust? After all, we are
no longer adversaries, we are partners. Some explanations that we hear
imply that this is “expansion of stability,” just in case developments in
Russia go the undesirable way. If this is the reason why some want to move
the NATO area of responsibility closer to the Russian borders, let me say
this: it is too early to give up on democracy in Russia!41
For the fi rst time, the Russian frustration with the Alliance’s activi-
ties was stated at the highest level. On the plane to Washington from
Budapest, the Clinton team tried “to figure out if [Yeltsin’s speech]
was a long-term change or a brief interruption in what had been very
close and friendly relations between Washington and Moscow.”42
With the benefit of hindsight, December 1994 constitutes the cru-
cial point when Russian–Atlantic relations became a lot more uneasy.
Only days after the OSCE summit, Russian troops began invading
Chechnya.
41
Quoted in Goldgeier and McFaul (2003, 191).
42
Interview with Burns quoted in Goldgeier and McFaul (2003, 192).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 169
43
Gorbachev (1994).
170 International Security in Practice
not and should not be excluded from the common efforts to regulate the
confl ict in the Balkans, a region where Russia has longtime interests and
influence. Ultimately the advantages of partnership were illustrated when
Russia and the West coordinated their efforts to persuade the warring
parties to make peace. But the initial lack of consultation and coordina-
tion meant that fi rst both sides had to run the risk of returning to the old
benefactor–client relationship that had played such a pernicious role in the
regional confl icts of the Cold War era.44
For the Russians, the fact that NATO took it upon itself to decide on
the use of force in Bosnia went against the grain of the new rules of
the international security game based on inclusive partnership.
In late August 1995, when NATO’s Operation Deliberate Force
began, Russian officials similarly decried their exclusion from prior
consultations. Yeltsin denounced the Alliance for breaking with the
cooperative security discourse it was simultaneously preaching: “In
proclaiming its ‘peacekeeping mission,’ the North Atlantic alliance
has essentially taken upon itself the role of both judge and jury.”45
For the Russians, NATO was guilty of duplicity: while claiming to
include Russia in diplomatic talks through the Contact Group, it
was simultaneously making unilateral decisions to use force without
Russia’s participation. As a result, many in Moscow came to construe
NATO’s functional enlargement not in terms of the internal mode of
pursuing security, but as a shrewd strategy intended to strengthen the
Alliance’s profile in the post-Cold War era. Even the father of New
Thinking protested “a desire to expand de facto NATO’s sphere of
operation far beyond its historical borders. All this has very little in
common with humanitarian ideals of restoring peace in Bosnia.”46
Doubts about NATO’s promise of an inclusive security order began to
emerge – to be compounded by NATO’s decision to enlarge.
Despite all the Alliance talk to the contrary, the December 1994
decision to enlarge seemed to Moscow to breach the three basic
CSCE principles that had been so fundamental after the end of the
Cold War – that security is indivisible, mutual, and cooperative. It
looked as though the NATO-professed rules of the post-Cold War
international security game were scorned by the Alliance itself, whose
actions, as Moscow understood them, smacked more of realpolitik
44 45
Kozyrev (1994a, 66). Quoted in Rossiiskiye Vesti (1995).
46
Gorbachev (1994).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 171
47
Volker Rühe quoted in Yost (1998, 139).
172 International Security in Practice
and others.”48 Instead, mutual security implies that one country’s secu-
rity cannot be enhanced at the expense of others’. For the Russians,
NATO’s unilateral decision to enlarge plainly contravened this prin-
ciple. As Primakov explained: “we don’t need to be convinced that
NATO is not preparing to attack us. We do not intend to attack the
United States, either. But let us suppose, purely hypothetically, that
we were to conclude a military alliance with Mexico, Venezuela and
Cuba. Surely that would elicit a negative reaction from the United
States.”49 At issue were not intentions but the fact that increasing one
side’s forces necessarily has consequences for the other. If security is
mutual, according to Russian officials, then the Alliance cannot be
strengthened without affecting the security of its neighbors.
Despite all NATO claims to the contrary, for Moscow expansion
retained an insuperable anti-Russian flavor. In fact, many officials in
Washington did not hide their suspicions about the new Russia under
Yeltsin. In a 1995 op-ed, Strobe Talbott wrote that “among the con-
tingencies for which NATO must be prepared is that Russia will aban-
don democracy and return to the threatening patterns of international
behavior that have sometimes characterized its history.”50 Turning
NATO into the central security pillar of the new architecture appeared
to be an efficient means of blocking any return to Russia’s past impe-
rialism. This rationale also informed the strong Republican support
for enlargement in the US: Senator Richard Lugar, for instance, “was
convinced that the West had to lock in the gains of the end of the
Cold War before they were frittered away.”51 In a similar vein, the
main reason why post-communist countries were so eagerly begging
for admission was indubitably their fear of Russia. Fully aware of this,
the Russians tried to convince Atlantic officials that in this context
expansion amounted to setting in motion a self-fulfilling prophecy.
Finally, in Russian eyes NATO expansion contradicted the very
principle of cooperative security by which international order could
be achieved only through negotiated settlement. Russian officials
felt that the decision to enlarge was imposed on them and that the
policy failed to take their country’s legitimate security interests
into account. Most strikingly, the 1995 “Study on Enlargement”
appeared “deliberately provocative in offering almost no concessions
48 49
Quoted in Black (1997). Quoted in Kondrashov (1996).
50
Talbott (1995, 6). 51 Asmus (2002 , 32).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 173
52 53
Dannreuther (1999 –2000, 152). Ponsard (2007, 91).
54 55
Primakov (2004, 135). Talbott (2002 , 99).
56 57
Migranyan (1994). Kozyrev (1994b).
174 International Security in Practice
58 59
Quoted in Rossiiskaya Gazeta (1996). Kozyrev (1995, 13).
60 61
MccGwire (1998, 34–5). Kupchan (1994).
62 63
New York Times (1994). NATO (1995).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 175
with the lower position occupied by the country inside the Alliance-
dominated field of international security. While in 1992–4, Yeltsin,
Kozyrev and other members of the Russian government had incor-
porated the new rules of the international security game, acting and
thinking from Russia’s weakened status, later the situation began to
change in part as a result of NATO’s practices of double enlargement.
Despite its verbal promotion of the internal mode of pursuing secu-
rity, in reality NATO appeared to follow a different logic, especially
because of the exclusionary consequences of the double enlargement
for Russia. As a result, the Russian proto-liberal habitus that had ren-
dered possible the Alliance’s domination in the immediate aftermath
of the Cold War gradually gave way to deeply embodied Great Power
dispositions.
The Russian Great Power habitus was never too far from the sur-
face, even during the 1992–4 honeymoon. For more than forty years,
Moscow had been the center of a huge empire and enjoyed a privileged
dialogue with its superpower counterpart in Washington. Such an
enduring position of domination in the international security field left
deeply ingrained dispositions among Russian policymakers. Despite
New Thinking policies and post-communist Russia’s early embrace of
the NATO order, the Great Power habitus has deeper historical roots
than any other in the Russian political soil. Nonetheless, for about a
decade, from Gorbachev to Kozyrev, Great Power dispositions were
remarkably muted inside the Kremlin. This raises the important ques-
tion: what explains the fact that in the mid-1990s the dispositional
balance in Moscow was tipped in favor of the Great Power habitus?
I argue that NATO’s practices with regard to the double enlargement
played an important role in this change.
This is not to say that the Alliance bears sole responsibility for the
resurgence of Great Power attitudes in Russia; several other factors
contributed to this evolution. First, as I just explained, for historical
reasons Russian soil is uniquely fertile for this habitus of grandeur.64
Second, NATO is only one among many international interlocutors
64
An eminent group of scholars identifies a number of other “historical
patterns marking the long haul of Russian foreign policy,” including “the
powerful but often perverse impact of absolutism, the impulse and burden
of shapeless borders, the effect of perennial economic backwardness, the
consequences of empire in lieu of more modern national forms, and the allied
and ultimately most poignant influence, Russia’s permanent and sometimes
agonizing quest for identity” (Legvold 2007, 20).
176 International Security in Practice
65
For Bourdieu-inspired explanations of NATO’s transformation in the post-
Cold War era, see Gheciu (2005); Villumsen (2008); and Williams (2007).
66 67
Neumann (2008b). McDonald (2007, 163).
178 International Security in Practice
68 69
Kozyrev (1994b). Lo (2002 , 5 and 7).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 179
clearly: “Despite the current difficulties, Russia has been and remains
a Great Power, and its policy toward the outside world should cor-
respond to that status.”70 He also insisted on the need for equitable
partnership with the West and reasserted that there was no victor in
the Cold War, as overcoming it had been a joint victory. Starting with
Primakov, Russian foreign policymakers appealed to the historical
notion of derzhava, which Andrei Tsygankov translates as “the holder
of international equilibrium of power.”71 Accordingly, the main con-
stitutive elements of the Russian narrative of Great Power are calls
for equality, multipolarity, spheres of interest and balance of power.
Geopolitical thinking also plays a prominent role in this habitus.72
The gist of my argument consists of linking the revival of Great
Power dispositions in Russia to NATO’s practices with regard to the
double enlargement. I want to substantiate this correlation with four
interrelated arguments. First, NATO’s double enlargement led to an
unprecedented foreign policy consensus in post-communist Russia
around 1995. In the immediate aftermath of the Cold War, there was
a lot of debate on Russia’s new identity. Starting in 1994, however,
these different foreign policy opinions gave way to a broad-based
agreement based on the notion of derzhava. Thereafter, the Russian
elite struck a position that repudiated much of the New Thinking of
the early 1990s and instead integrated several items from the age-old
Russian habitus of Great Power. An insider to these debates, Dmitri
Trenin confi rms that “the turning point came in 1994 with the deci-
sion in principle by NATO to admit new members. Most groups
within the Russian elite, otherwise deeply divided on the issues of
policy, were suddenly united in portraying this decision as essentially
anti-Russian.”73 Crucially, the consensus around the notion of Great
Power emerged after NATO’s official launch of the process of geo-
graphical enlargement.
Second, NATO’s practices regarding its double enlargement played
a significant role in disempowering those elites that had been disposed
to follow Western leadership and recognize its cultural-symbolic
superiority. Epitomized by Primakov’s nomination as Foreign Minister,
the institutional empowerment of the Great Power habitus that took
place in the mid-1990s was accompanied neither by any significant
70 71
Quoted in Moskovskiye Novosti (1996). Tsygankov (2004, 93).
72 73
Tsygankov (2003). Trenin (2000, 13–14).
180 International Security in Practice
74 75
Zimmerman (2002 , 93). Zimmerman (2002 , 206).
76 77
Blacker (1998, 179). Goldgeier and McFaul (2003, 355–6).
78
Quoted in Talbott (2002 , 76).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 181
All in all, the double enlargement left the Russians under the impres-
sion that playing by the new rules of the international security game
was bound to make Russia’s position weaker while NATO’s grew
stronger.
Fourth, from the Russian point of view NATO’s practices of func-
tional and geographical enlargement were reminiscent of the Cold
War game. Progressively, many Russian elites came to feel that
NATO’s discourse of democracy and cooperative security was in fact
a cover-up for collecting its geopolitical trophies. In other words, the
Alliance seemed to use a double language, advocating idealpolitik in
words but implementing realpolitik in deeds. In reaction, ingrained
realpolitik dispositions took precedence over the thinner habitus
that had flourished from Gorbachev to Kozyrev. The double enlarge-
ment policy, in other words, triggered Great Power dispositions at
the expense of those that had informed Russia’s foreign policy in
1992–4. As Vladimir Baranovsky remarks: “The predominant feel-
ing is that even if Russia could not retain its position in Europe, it
certainly did not deserve to be forced out ruthlessly and treated as a
defeated country.”80 Under such circumstances, Great Power disposi-
tions appeared better adapted to playing the game of international
security with NATO member states. When one adds to these proc-
esses the practical imperatives of positional agency, by which Russian
79 80
Kozyrev (1995, 8). Baranovsky (2000, 449).
182 International Security in Practice
81 82
Trenin (2005, 282). Rodin (1994).
83 84
Quoted in Nezavisimaya Gazeta (1994). Quoted in Schmidt (1994).
184 International Security in Practice
85
Talbott (2002 , 218).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 185
86
Quoted in Goldgeier and McFaul (2003, 203).
186 International Security in Practice
87
Quoted in Rossiiskaya Gazeta (1997).
88 89
Quoted in Goldgeier and McFaul (2003, 205). Migranyan (1997).
90
It is worth noting that this unresolved issue of armament ceilings for new
members still haunts Russian–Atlantic relations, and it helps explain
Moscow’s moratorium on the implementation of the treaty on Conventional
Forces in Europe (CFE); see Chapter 6.
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 187
of view, Russia was attempting to punch well above its weight with
its extensive and legally binding demands. Moscow was in no posi-
tion to dictate any provision and should have been happy that NATO
opened a diplomatic negotiation with it in the fi rst place. The Atlantic
compromises granted to the Russians were mostly symbolic in nature
and they did not restrict the Alliance’s freedom whatsoever. From the
Russian perspective, as a Great Power what mattered most was to
be treated as NATO’s equal. This imperative at times appeared even
more important than obtaining genuine concessions from Brussels.
Particularly striking is the emphasis that Russian elites consistently
put on the need to save face. For instance, Primakov regularly had to
defend himself against accusations of watering down Russia’s position
in the hope of achieving an agreement with NATO. More than any-
thing else, for Moscow the Founding Act was meant to get Russia’s
Great Power status publicly recognized.
In addition, Russia’s practices illustrate quite well positional agency
in international diplomacy. Where you sit is what you do: given that
post-communist Russia had very little cultural-symbolic capital – the
resources that had become the prime currency in the internal mode
of pursuing security – it was structurally inclined to resort to the
means at hand, which were mostly military. In the new rules imposed
by NATO, however, military capital had been considerably devalued
and even deemed passé. As a junior player in terms of democracy
and human rights, Moscow could only have a losing hand in this
security-from-the-inside-out game. However, despite all its problems
in the 1990s, given its thousands of nuclear weapons the Russian
army retained a strength superior to almost any non-Western coun-
try in the world. It was thus the country’s position in the field (low
cultural-symbolic capital, fairly high military resources), in addition
to resurging Great Power dispositions, that drove Russia’s response to
the double enlargement, which often appeared ill-adapted from the
standpoint of the dominant players. By the new doxa, reliance on out-
moded and even illegitimate military resources in the international
security field was deemed awkward if not altogether disingenuous by
the Alliance. As a result, Russia’s positional agency appeared all the
more hysteretic to those players whose habitus and resources were
better aligned with the field’s structure.
The Founding Act negotiations gave birth to a number of quixotic
practices on Russia’s part. Because of hysteresis, the Russians had
188 International Security in Practice
91
Rodionov (1996).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 189
92 93
Quoted in Kassianova (2001, 830). Quoted in Kassianova (2001, 832).
190 International Security in Practice
94
Paul (2005).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 191
95 96
NATO (1997). Quoted in New York Times (1997).
192 International Security in Practice
also at the structural location from which they do so, suggests that
with its very limited resources, Russia was in no position to play the
Great Power game in NATO’s eyes. Likewise, NATO’s practices of
double enlargement, largely the result of the organization’s unchecked
domination of the field of international security, were bound to arouse
the Russian habitus. Self-evident diplomacy gave way to strong hyster-
esis effects, with two masters but no apprentice in the relationship.
In using the language of critical juncture, I want to emphasize the
path-dependent nature of social and political relations, whose future
depends on their past because history develops like a branching tree.
Because of positive, reinforcing feedback loops, early steps tend to
lock into a certain trajectory and eliminate alternatives that were
originally open. Arguably, the end of the Cold War was one of those
rare historical instances when the world found itself at an intersection
where several paths were available. As Kissinger writes: “When an
international order fi rst comes into being, many choices may be open
to it. But each choice constricts the universe of remaining options.
Because complexity inhibits flexibility, early choices are especially
crucial.”97
The evidence presented in this chapter suggests that, for a short
time between 1992 and 1994, everything took place as if Russia was
going to integrate into the new NATO world order. At that point,
“[t]he ideas of Russian messianism and the pursuit of an independ-
ent role in line with its Great Power heritage were either understated
or even denied.”98 Many paths were therefore possible, including the
one toward a security community. Things abruptly changed in 1994
when NATO took two initiatives that set its relations with Russia
on the bumpy track that continues to this day. For the Russians, the
double enlargement amounted to NATO reneging, in practice, on its
own discourse of inclusive, mutual and cooperative security. Because
the move was reminiscent more of realpolitik than of the professed
internal mode of pursuing security, Russian Great Power disposi-
tions gradually resurfaced. With rising hysteresis and symbolic power
struggles, the policy amounted to signing the nascent security com-
munity’s death warrant.
Using a Bourdieu-inspired theoretical framework gives an important
edge in matters of critical junctures and early steps because it supplies
97 98
Kissinger (1994, 26–7). Ponsard (2007, 62).
NATO, Russia and the double enlargement, 1992–1997 193
not only a structural mechanism for path dependence (the field) but
also an agent-level process: as a historical distillate of embodied dis-
positions, habitus explains self-reinforcing practices. The historical
constitution of habitus, in effect, is characterized by a “relative irre-
versibility”: “all the external stimuli and conditioning experiences are,
at every moment, perceived through categories already constructed by
prior experiences. From that follows an inevitable priority of origi-
nary experiences and consequently a relative closure of the system of
dispositions that constitute habitus.”99 The practical sense, as a result,
builds on past experiences to feel what is to be done. The dispositions
comprised in the habitus, constituted by subjective and intersubjec-
tive past experiences, in part constitute future practices. As a result,
the path taken at certain historical junctures may make other paths
more or less likely in the future. Such has been the case in post-Cold
War Russian–Atlantic relations: partly because of the resiliency of
Russia’s Great Power habitus, which was reactivated by NATO’s dou-
ble enlargement, today’s symbolic power politics are in great measure
the fallout from the early steps of 1992–7.
99
Bourdieu and Wacquant (1992 , 133).
6 The fallout: NATO and Russia from
Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008
194
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 195
1
Quoted in Gornostayev and Katin (1998).
2 3
Quoted in Mukhin (1998). Quoted in Sysoyev (1998).
4
Talbott (2002 , 300).
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 197
NATO members of the UNSC (while China abstained) to call for the
international monitoring of an immediate ceasefi re and to threaten
“to consider further action and additional measures to maintain or
restore peace and stability in the region.”5 In an official comment
on that vote, the Russian representative to the UN Security Council
declared: “there are no provisions in [Resolution 1199] that would
directly or indirectly sanction the automatic use of force.”6 A few days
later, however, NATO representatives argued during a PJC meeting
that the resolution had described the situation in Kosovo as a threat to
regional peace and stability, thus opening the way to military action
based on Chapter VII of the UN Charter. In a strong rebuff, Foreign
Minister Igor Ivanov declared that Moscow would exercise its veto,
while Defense Minister Igor Sergeyev warned that a NATO opera-
tion in Kosovo would signal the start of a new cold war. Sergeyev
also threatened to break relations with NATO and freeze the proc-
ess of START II ratification. Unshaken, NATO issued a new ulti-
matum to Belgrade in mid-October, prompting Moscow to recall its
ambassador once again. Vladimir Lukin, then chairman of the state
Duma’s International Affairs Committee, went as far as to float the
idea that Russia might offer military support to Yugoslavia in case
of an Alliance military operation. With the Alliance systematically
dismissing Russia’s objections, political discourse in Moscow reached
new levels of nervousness.
Looking for ways to regain the initiative, Russian diplomats sup-
ported an agreement between Serbia’s President Slobodan Milošević
and the Contact Group on establishing the OSCE Kosovo Verification
Mission. This mission proved a double-edged sword, however, when,
in mid-January 1999, the discovery of the Račak massacre confi rmed
Atlantic suspicions of Belgrade. Nonetheless, Moscow pushed the
Contact Group to organize a conference in Rambouillet in mid-
February. Given hysteresis, however, diplomatic accommodation
appeared out of reach. According to one Russian insider: “all Western
attempts to establish within the Contact Group a common under-
standing of the concrete parameters of the agreement met with a kind
of slack resistance on the part of Russia.”7 Given its weak position,
obstruction seemed the only way for Moscow to exert some kind of
5 6
UN Security Council (1998a). UN Security Council (1998b, 11).
7
Levitin (2000, 136).
198 International Security in Practice
8
Quoted in Rossiiskaya Gazeta (1999).
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 199
9
Norris (2005, 144).
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 201
10
Talbott (2002 , 333).
202 International Security in Practice
that the West has fi nally started to realize that it can’t treat Russia like
some lackey. We’re partners, not lackeys.”11 Recall that the Pristina
move happened simultaneously with the extremely tense negotia-
tions on KFOR between Talbott and his team of American generals
and Sergeyev, Ivashov and Chief of General Staff Anatoly Kvashnin.
Under these circumstances, the operation was meant to create a fait
accompli on the ground and offer better leverage to Moscow in its
negotiation with the Alliance. The Russians were pleading for “equal
rights” in the operation like those enjoyed by NATO members, and
for a veto over military operations. In a pattern that continues to
this day, Russian diplomats stubbornly refused to concede any more
to a NATO that would not consider granting Moscow any decision-
making capability. As a result of a very weak position and a habitus
attuned to the external mode of pursuing security, the Russians used
the only resources they had left – the military.
However, with the G8 summit upcoming in Cologne and the need
to get the associated cultural-symbolic recognition, the Russians
needed to reach an agreement with the Alliance. Although NATO’s
domination of Moscow may have been declining, it had certainly not
disappeared by 1999. Russia’s desire for Western recognition was still
strong, particularly on the part of the country’s president. In a phone
call to Clinton, Yeltsin fi nally agreed that Russian troops would
serve under the Bosnia model in Kosovo (with minor modifications).
During a meeting between William Cohen (US Secretary of Defense),
Madeleine Albright, Igor Sergeyev and Igor Ivanov in Helsinki a few
days later, an agreement was reached to the effect that Russian troops
would be scattered across four sectors and would share control of
Pristina airport with NATO. Once again, despite weeks of unprec-
edented outcry, diplomatic brinkmanship and dangerous military
moves, Moscow eventually had to largely cave in to NATO and accept
a formula that gave it, in one insider’s words, “only a paper-thin guise
of military independence.”12 All was now in place for Yeltsin joining
the G8 summit in Cologne in a celebration intended to symbolically
demonstrate the importance of Russia in the world. Days after order-
ing a military stunt that could have degenerated into full-scale con-
frontation, Yeltsin hugged his “friends” from NATO more vigorously
than ever.
11 12
Quoted in Charodeyev (1999). Norris (2005, 290).
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 203
13 14
Hopf (2002 , 218). Morozov (2002 , 411).
204 International Security in Practice
15 16
Gorbachev (1999). Tsygankov (2001, 142).
17
Baranovsky (2003, 279).
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 205
18
Quoted in Norris (2005, 308).
19 20
Quoted in Goldgeier and McFaul (2003, 251). Pushkov (1999).
206 International Security in Practice
21
Quoted in Evangelista (2002 , 2).
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 207
22
Quoted in Morozov (2002 , 412).
208 International Security in Practice
23
Baranovsky (2000, 454–5).
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 209
24
Daalder and Lindsay (2005, 12–14).
210 International Security in Practice
to defeat the terrorist enemy. While it is true that the Alliance plays
only a supportive role in the US-led “war on terrorism,” its focus
has nonetheless switched significantly in the wake of September 11,
2001. 25 Issues that were central during the 1990s, such as peacekeep-
ing in the Balkans, gave way to a new security agenda centered on
terrorism and forceful democratization. This reorientation did not go
entirely smoothly, however, as conflicting interpretations of the ter-
rorist attacks emerged on each side of the Atlantic. Many continental
European countries did not agree with the militarized response to the
terrorist threat put forward by Washington: instead of preemption,
deterrence and retribution, they preferred a softer approach based
on regulations, legal and judicial means, and cooperation between
the police and civil authorities. Despite this disagreement, however,
in relative terms European and American security cultures remained
closer to each other than to those of any other parts of the world.
Moreover, even when confronted by a profound rift on the defense
issue, NATO diplomats never stopped thinking from diplomacy in
solving their disputes.26 In the end, though, an Alliance inhabited by
struggles over its own internal rules of the game certainly reveals a
lower capacity to impose doxa in the field of international security.
On their side, the Russians came to embrace the post-September 11
rules of the game in the international security field imposed by the US,
and to a lesser extent, by NATO. As Baranovsky noted: “Gradually,
the fight against terrorism will become the priority task for states …
One can expect that the political and psychological barriers against
using force will be lowered. Force will probably appear ‘less unac-
ceptable’ than before.”27 This vision, widespread among Russian
elites, happened to fit quite nicely with the American reaction to
September 11, 2001. This homology between the new field’s doxa and
the ingrained Russian habitus constituted an unprecedented develop-
ment. From the mid-1990s on, fast-amplifying hysteresis effects had
erupted from the growing misalignment between the security-from-
the-inside-out doxa and the Russian Great Power dispositions. In the
year following Yeltsin’s retirement, the new president Putin contin-
ued to characterize Russia as a Great Power28 and publicly voiced
his irritation with NATO – an “organization [that] often ignores the
25 26
De Nevers (2007). Pouliot (2006).
27 28
Baranovsky (2002 , 14–15). Tsygankov (2005).
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 211
One of the reasons why Russia’s visibility was so low during the 1990s
was that the security agenda was to a high degree dominated by develop-
ments in sectors where Russia was peripheral. The “soft security” debate
presupposed a way of framing questions to do with power, and particularly
with appositeness of “soft power,” that did not easily fit in with traditional
Russian ways of framing these questions … The Afghan campaign, on the
other hand, meant that conventional warfare was back at the centre of the
security agenda … Russia has simply harvested what has come its way.30
29 30
Quoted in President of Russia (2001). Neumann (2005b, 18–19).
212 International Security in Practice
31 32
See Pouliot (2003). Quoted in Ambrosio (2005, 140).
33
NATO (2001a).
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 213
34
NATO (2001c).
214 International Security in Practice
from Washington, with the support of Turkey, the Netherlands and the
three new member states. Czech president Vaclav Havel, for instance,
criticized the initiative as a “bureaucratic exercise” and warned
that it could make the Alliance “just as spineless as the UN or the
[OSCE].”35 In a replay of the 1996–7 negotiations over the Founding
Act, the main bone of contention was NATO’s enlargement to the
Baltic states.36 In the end, at the May 2002 Rome summit, Russia and
NATO adopted a declaration stating their “determination to build
together a lasting and inclusive peace in the Euro-Atlantic area on the
principles of democracy and cooperative security and the principle
that the security of all states in the Euro-Atlantic community is indi-
visible … [The NRC] will operate on the principle of consensus.”37
The British Foreign Minister went as far as to declare: “This is the last
rites, the funeral of the cold war … Fifteen years ago, Russia was the
enemy, now Russia becomes our friend and ally.”38 Despite this opti-
mistic language, however, the issue of enlargement had been brushed
under the carpet while Russia’s institutional association with NATO
had been considerably diluted.
In terms of the NRC structure, the most important change from the
original proposal was the addition of a retrieval or safeguard mecha-
nism allowing participants to withdraw any issue from discussion. In
practice, such a mechanism meant that Russia’s inclusion in the settle-
ment of a given security issue remained conditional on the goodwill of
all NRC member states. Vilnius could then withdraw from the NRC
agenda any discussion of NATO forces in Lithuania, for instance.
This obviously poses serious limits on Russia being associated with
NATO on contentious issues. Strikingly, Russian officials appeared
quite happy with the results of the Rome summit nonetheless. For
instance, Foreign Minister Igor Ivanov insisted the new Council was
“not a consultative body, it’s an executive body [in which] NATO and
Russia must stand side by side.”39 But Danish Foreign Minister Per
Stig Moeller held a different view: “the text of the agreement with
Moscow includes a provision stating that all of the 19 NATO member
35
Quoted in Yusin (2001).
36
At the time, rumors that the Alliance would invite seven new members for
admission (including the Baltic states) at its upcoming summit in Prague had
already started to circulate.
37 38
NATO (2002). Jack Straw quoted in Traynor (2002).
39
Quoted in Traynor (2002).
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 215
40 41
Quoted in Smirnov (2002). Quoted in Ambrosio (2005, 136).
216 International Security in Practice
Our goal is to erase the false lines that have divided Europe for too long …
The question of “when” may be still up for debate within NATO. The ques-
tion of “whether” should not be. As we plan to enlarge NATO, no nation
should be used as a pawn in the agendas of others. We will not trade away
the fate of free European peoples. No more Munichs, no more Yaltas.42
42
Quoted in the New York Times (2001).
43
Quoted in Kramer (2002 , 748).
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 217
44 45
NATO (2004b, emphasis added). Daalder and Goldgeier (2006).
218 International Security in Practice
Alliance remained one of the most hotly debated among its mem-
bers. Nonetheless, since the Istanbul summit there exists a consen-
sus that as transatlantic as the organization may be in membership,
the issues it has to address now play themselves out on a global
scale. In reality, NATO has already gone global, as the ISAF illus-
trates. This evolution was certainly not to Moscow’s liking, where
“a significant segment of the Russian policy-making elite appears
to have concluded that there has been a direct correlation (and for
many, a causal relationship) between NATO enlargement and the
retreat of Russian influence.”46
In addition to continuing its double enlargement, NATO under-
took a number of policies that further alienated Russia. When selling
its new round of enlargement to the Russians, the Alliance essen-
tially used a similar line as during the 1990s: “Enlargement is not –
as outdated perceptions have it – a zero-sum game where NATO
wins and Russia loses … We are aiming at including, not excluding
Russia.”47 But this language was rejected as duplicitous by Moscow
when, in early 2004, NATO began patrolling the Baltic states’
airspace and policing the border with Russia. Even before these
states formally entered the Alliance in late March 2004, Brussels
had dispatched six F-16 fighters from Denmark, Belgium and the
Netherlands. Moscow responded in kind by sending airplanes on
similar reconnaissance missions along its borders with the Baltic
states. This operation confi rmed doubts about the alleged win-win,
inclusive nature of NATO’s expansion in Russia. Recall that in the
aftermath of September 11, 2001 the Alliance subtly turned down
offers from the Russian side for a deeper rapprochement. In March
2000, Putin had already surprised the world by responding “Why
not?” to a British Broadcasting Corporation (BBC) journalist who
was inquiring into the possibility of Russia one day entering NATO.
At the time, the NATO Secretary-General had replied that Russian
membership was not on the agenda. In late September 2001, Putin
was reported as calling on NATO to admit his country, an offer
that was received very coldly. In November, Putin reiterated to
Washington his desire to go “as far as the North Atlantic Alliance
itself is ready to go and as far as it will be able, of course, to take
46 47
Braun (2008, 1). NATO (2001b).
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 219
into account the legitimate interests of Russia.”48 The offer again fell
on deaf ears on the Atlantic side.49
Several other practices on the part of certain NATO member
states contributed to resurging hysteresis in the following months.
Obviously, the American invasion of Iraq was a case in point. The
main problem for the Russians was the infringement of the principle
of state sovereignty, which the Russians had come to interpret as the
best safeguard against interference in the wake of the Kosovo crisis.
In addition, in early 2002 the Pentagon’s Nuclear Posture Review was
leaked in the American media, counting Russia as one of seven states
on which nuclear weapons could or should be targeted. During spring
2002, the Bush administration announced that the Transcaucasus
and Central Asia had become areas of interest for the Alliance, while
showing little inclination to remove its newly acquired facilities in
Central Asia and Georgia. Finally, starting in early 2003, persistent
rumors that the Pentagon was working on plans to deploy American
forces in Bulgaria and Romania – in contravention of NATO’s 1997
unilateral pledges – further alarmed the Russians.
The more cooperative tide post-September 11 definitely turned in
the aftermath of the “color revolutions” in the post-Soviet space: the
Rose Revolution in Georgia, in November 2003; the Orange
Revolution in Ukraine, in December 2004; and the Yellow or Purple
or Tulip Revolution in Kyrgyzstan, in October 2005. From the outset,
Moscow suspected some shady involvement on the part of Western
countries, particularly in fi nancing opposition parties and in organ-
izing demonstrations. Many high-level politicians denounced the
meddling of the US and other Allied countries on behalf of democra-
tization in the CIS area. Where the West applauded democratic revo-
lutions, Moscow condemned the “continuation of the West’s strategic
line of staging a political takeover of the post-Soviet space.”50 To be
48
Ministry of Foreign Affairs of the Russian Federation (2001).
49
Another telling example is NATO’s repeated refusal to establish ties with
the Collective Security Treaty Organization (CSTO). Under Russia’s
initiative, this was proposed several times at NRC meetings and in high-level
communications from 2004 through December 2006. Cooperation in drug
trafficking and the establishment of a “security belt” around Afghanistan
were proposed, among other things. The Alliance did not answer for a year,
before declining the offer.
50
Pushkov (2004).
220 International Security in Practice
to advocate after September 11, 2001. From the Russian point of view,
integrating seven more post-communist states in the Alliance meant
not the consolidation of the democratic community, but the drawing
of new divisions to Russia’s exclusion. Similarly, the globalization of
NATO’s security mandate did not appear to yield more security for
Moscow: given the Kosovo precedent, it rather seemed to undermine
Russia’s capacity to control its own fate and exert influence in world
politics. In enlarging its security mandate as well as its membership,
then, the Alliance played a game with Russia that smacked of real-
politik instead of democracy promotion. As soon as the diplomatic
momentum that immediately followed September 11, 2001 dissipated,
deeply ingrained Great Power dispositions resurfaced among Russian
elites. In a replay of the late twentieth century, the role of junior part-
ner gave way to power balancing.
This time, however, Russia’s insubordination went one step further
with the public rejection of the democratization and human rights
agenda advocated by Allied member states. Nothing better illustrates
this change than mounting Russian criticisms of the OSCE over the
last few years. In July 2004, CIS countries, under Russia’s strong lead-
ership, distributed a statement to the OSCE’s Permanent Council in
Vienna to the effect that the organization was “often failing to observe
such fundamental Helsinki principles as noninterference in internal
affairs and respect for the sovereignty of states.”51 For the first time
in the post-Cold War era, a group of states led by Moscow mounted
an objection opposing the very principles of the OSCE. By that time,
Russia had become “a poster child of resistance to the democratic and
human rights agenda.”52 Clearly, the pattern of domination that had
given NATO so much authority over Moscow had changed; recent
diplomatic interaction, including over Georgia, prove just that.
51 52
Quoted in Lukyanov (2004). MacFarlane (2008, 41).
222 International Security in Practice
53
Quoted in Ministry of Foreign Affairs of the Russian Federation (2007b).
54
NATO (2008a, para. 23).
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 223
55
Quoted in Myers (2008).
56 57
Lavrov quoted in Solovyov and Sidorov (2006). NATO (2008b).
224 International Security in Practice
to save face, Russia also halted cooperation with NATO indefi nitely.
Despite a ceasefi re brokered by French president Nicolas Sarkozy on
August 12, the Russian military remained deep into Georgian terri-
tory for several weeks in order to create “buffer zones.” At the end
of the month, the new president Dmitri Medvedev formally recog-
nized the new political entities, putting them under the “protection”
of about 7,600 Russian soldiers.
The Georgia War gave way to very strong rhetoric on both the
Russian and NATO sides. The new Russian president tried to
downplay the importance of Western criticisms and retaliatory ges-
tures: “We do not need illusions of partnership. When we are being
surrounded by bases on all sides, and a growing number of states
are being drawn into the North Atlantic bloc and we are being told,
‘Don’t worry, everything is all right,’ naturally we do not like it. If they
essentially wreck this [NRC] cooperation, it is nothing horrible for
us. We are prepared to accept any decision, including the termination
of relations.”58 The American Secretary of State, Condoleezza Rice,
responded by putting Moscow on a “one-way path to self-imposed
isolation and international irrelevance.”59 Tensions mounted particu-
larly high when Georgia officially called on NATO to offer military
assistance during the confl ict. In the end, American planes and ships
supplied aid to Georgia, combined with substantial fi nancial assist-
ance from the US, the EU and the IMF. One senior American offi-
cial was quoted as saying: “Well, maybe we’re learning to shut up
now.”60
Finally, another Russian–Atlantic row that illustrates particularly
well how NATO’s double enlargement has contributed to jeopardize
even the strongest acquis of the end of the Cold War regards the CFE
treaty, which was signed in late 1990 by NATO and Warsaw Pact
countries and sets limits on armaments systems on the European con-
tinent with solid verification and information exchange mechanisms.
At Russia’s request, an adapted version was agreed upon in 1999 in
order to allow more flexibility in Moscow’s deployments, notably
in the Caucasus. In the 1999 OSCE Istanbul Final Act, Russia also
agreed to withdraw its military from bases in Georgia and Moldova.
In the ensuing weeks, NATO countries conditioned the ratification of
58
Dmitri Medvedev quoted in Levy (2008).
59 60
Quoted in BBC (2008). Quoted in Cooper (2008).
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 225
61
Quoted in Sysoyev (2004).
226 International Security in Practice
62 63
Quoted in Izvestia (2004). President of Russia (2007).
64
Quoted in President of Russia (2008).
NATO and Russia from Kosovo to Georgia, 1998–2008 227
65
See Pouliot (2007).
228 International Security in Practice
historical roots of the Great Power habitus and the troubles of domes-
tic transition certainly played a role, this and the previous chapter
demonstrated that the NATO policy of double enlargement was pro-
foundly self-defeating and shortsighted as far as pacification with
Russia was concerned. Of course, keeping alive the “most successful
military alliance in history” or “welcoming back to the European
family” countries that had been brutally occupied for decades cannot
be said to be wrong in intent. Nor can Alliance officials be completely
blamed for being prudent with their former enemies in Moscow, who
remained particularly difficult partners and failed to change their
expectations after the implosion of the USSR. Instead, NATO’s fault
rests with its failure to realize that Russia would not, and in fact
could not, understand the double enlargement in the same way as
Westerners. As much as expansion made sense from the NATO point
of view, it made no sense to Moscow: exclusionary and delusionary,
the policy fitted better with the old realpolitik of Cold War contain-
ment than with the new rules of security-from-the-inside-out pro-
fessed by the Alliance.
Worse, NATO officials also failed to come to terms with the fact
that by contributing to the strengthening of Great Power dispositions
in the Kremlin, they were undermining their own dominant posi-
tion at the symbolic level. There seemed to be a naïve but widespread
conviction that whatever policies NATO could impose, ultimately
Moscow officials would always back down without hard feelings. The
pervasive feeling that the Alliance was right and that Russia would
come to realize it precluded compromise and genuine diplomacy, to
Russia’s growing alienation. Everything took place as if the Alliance
was systematically justified in imposing its decisions on its former
Russian enemy. Things happened quite differently, though, as resent-
ment steadily and cumulatively built up in Moscow. The seeds of
today’s aggravating problems were planted back in 1994; since then
they have continued to grow, as habitus is a durable matrix of action.
NATO’s own practices, in many ways, played a key role in consoli-
dating Great Power dispositions among Russian officials, who were
unable to adjust to the new structure of the post-Cold War field of
international security.
At the end of the day, the main brake on security community devel-
opment was not individual but relational. The unremitting bickering
over the terms of interaction that has been plaguing NATO–Russia
230 International Security in Practice
relations for the last fifteen years feeds on the growing mismatch
between Russia’s ingrained dispositions and the country’s position in
the field as defi ned by the dominant Atlantic players. NATO officials
consistently behave as if all their policies are inherently right while
the Russians keep asking for a status that the dominant player feels
is out of place. As a result, there are two masters but no appren-
tice in NATO–Russia diplomacy, a symbolic stalemate that consid-
erably undermines security community development in and through
practice.
The tragedy of hysteresis is that there are no absolute grounds from
which to assess who is right and who is wrong in a symbolic power
struggle. From the dominant perspective, it is obviously the domi-
nated players who need to take note of the tough reality and adjust
their practices accordingly. Yet Don Quixote happens to live in a dif-
ferent world, where the imposed order of things makes no sense com-
pared to tilting at windmills. There is no obvious way to reconcile
hysteretic practices and move beyond symbolic stalemate. Argument
and persuasion will probably not do the trick, as players are position-
ally opposed in a struggle that can produce no winners: the dominant
are unable to impose the rules of the game on the dominated, who
in turn are combating a structure which they cannot defeat. And the
struggle goes on and on.
7 Conclusion
231
232 International Security in Practice
1 2
See Pouliot (2006). CNN (2003).
234 International Security in Practice
3
On overlapping regional mechanisms of security governance in NATO–Russia
relations, see Adler and Grieve (2009); and Pouliot (n.d.).
4
Wiberg quoted in Wæver (1998, 72).
Conclusion 235
Effect on
Sources of (mis)match security
Degree of between positions and community
Dates (mis)match dispositions development
this day, as Russia and NATO do not cast each other in the roles that
they actually play together, each side perceives the other as trying to
punch above its weight. This obviously makes for difficult and tense
diplomacy and it makes the possibility of the development of a secu-
rity community in and through practice seem remote.
A key thread of this book is that in order to understand security
community development and its false starts, it is more productive to
start with practice than with collective identity. Rather than con-
ceiving we-ness as the driver of practice (that is, as a representation
that precedes action), I proposed to construe collective identity as the
result of practice. Collective identification is embedded in practice, as
Adler aptly argues about self-restraint in the spread of security com-
munities: “their engagement in a common practice makes them share
an identity and feel they are a ‘we.’ ”5 As this book’s case study has
demonstrated, for interstate pacification to thrive we-ness must not
only be represented but also enacted in and through practice. This is
certainly one of the key contributions that practice theory can make
to social and IR theories. There are several others, which I will dis-
cuss below. Meanwhile, I want to return to my case study one last
time in order to derive a couple of policy recommendations about the
politics of NATO–Russia diplomacy today.
5
Adler (2008, 201); see Wenger (1998).
238 International Security in Practice
habitus will not change in the short or medium term; the challenge is
to craft sound policy based on that social reality.
In order to genuinely pacify its relationship with Russia, NATO
must alter its course. My point is not that the Alliance should give in
to the many whims of Moscow’s Great Power habitus. As symbolic
interactionism indicates, treating somebody as if she were an X gen-
erally reinforces, in and through practice, the X identity.6 Caving in
to Moscow’s self-understanding as a Great Power could potentially
amount to reinforcing this narrative. The problem rather stems from
the fact that over the last twenty years the Alliance has adopted a
very ambivalent, and in fact incoherent, policy on the matter. As I
have demonstrated above, at specific points in time NATO has shown
some willingness to grant the symbolic pomp of equality to Russia in
order to obtain its cooperation. But when the time came to also rec-
ognize the power and influence that generally comes with that status,
the Alliance proved immovable. In the end, this disjointed approach
created enormous frustrations for the Russians, reinforcing their
quest for Great Power status while making the objective more and
more inaccessible.
Of course, sooner or later Russian practitioners will have to face
the fact of their country’s decline in the new rules of the international
security game – something they have consistently proved incapable
of doing hitherto. French and British diplomats, whose countries
went through a similar pattern of decline in the twentieth century,
can tell what a difficult process that is. Time will tell whether the
Russians can successfully go through this experience in the twenty-
fi rst century. At the moment, the only certainty that we can have is
that the Great Power habitus will not disappear in the near future.
From the NATO point of view, Russia will continue to be a particu-
larly vexing partner, one of the few that openly contests the order of
international security. As the Georgia War manifestly showed, the
Alliance’s influence over Moscow has become very limited. Based on
this observation, what can be done to gradually rein in hysteresis in
NATO–Russia diplomacy?
I infer from my theory of practice of security communities two
related policy recommendations. First, if NATO wants Russia to
play by the rules of the security-from-the-inside-out game, it should
6
See Wendt (1999).
Conclusion 239
its place. NATO member states would thus have a clear advantage in
multiplying interactions with Russia in those forums where its quest
for status cannot be expressed as strongly as in the realm of nuclear
warheads and geostrategy. This logic works for the Russians as well.
Again, the field of international trade is one in which Western diplo-
mats have recently had to learn the hard way that the “international
community” is not always coterminous with the Quad (made up of
Canada, the EU, Japan and the US). The latter’s incapability to move
the Doha Round forward, in part because of Indian and Chinese res-
ervations, could be the eye-opener required for the West to fi nally
lose the illusion of being the center of the world. The NATO–Russia
relationship would probably benefit from more interactions in multi-
lateral forums where each side’s posturing would be constrained as
much as possible.
As far as NATO– Russia diplomacy per se is concerned, I doubt
that either side would be ready for Moscow’s formal integration in the
Alliance for the time being. The clash of habitus is simply too strong
as things currently stand. That said, I believe that the Alliance should
state openly and unambiguously that it is ready to examine Russia’s
candidacy in due time. While this strategy entails some risks – for
instance, legitimating a troublesome player – it would engage Russia
as a potential member of the club, something that has cruelly been
lacking in the post-Cold War era. This, again, would likely improve
the chances of Moscow being seduced into playing NATO’s game
of security-from-the-inside-out (although probably inelegantly for a
time). The main tradeoff for opening the Alliance’s door to Moscow’s
membership is the potential weakening of the “transatlantic consen-
sus”; but the risk is well worth taking in the currently deteriorating
situation. Preserving the transatlantic consensus at all costs would be
profoundly misguided: in the post-Cold War era, leaving Russia on
the margins of Alliance diplomacy turned out to be a self-reinforcing
dynamic. The transatlantic consensus is useless, and in fact harmful,
if it leads the Alliance to exclude certain states outright and precludes
it from meaningfully engaging with its former enemies. Furthermore,
the risk is all the more worthy of taking because NATO has histori-
cally been a coalition of former enemies.7 A security community com-
prised of France, Germany, Italy, the United Kingdom and the US
7
Baker (2002).
Conclusion 241
8
Tilly (1985).
242 International Security in Practice
9 10
See Adler and Pouliot (n.d.). Elster (1989, 28).
11
Williams (2007, 36). Again, the best explanation for the origins of “focal
points,” for instance, is the logic of practicality – a socially inherited,
context-dependent and intuitive feel that inclines agents toward common
practices.
Conclusion 243
12
Bourdieu (1981, 307–8).
13
Welch (2005, 46).
14
On this point, see Hopf (2002 , 290). I agree with Hopf that identities, and
more especially habitus, are shaped fi rst and foremost at the domestic level
where a number of mimesis mechanisms are in place. As he also notes,
some of these dispositions, for instance the Great Power habitus, are then
challenged or reinforced in and through relations at the systemic level.
244 International Security in Practice
15 16
Waltz (1979, 81). Kauppi (2005, 29).
Conclusion 245
diplomacy was due not to military superiority, which it did not have,
but to its unparalleled competence in ornamental diplomacy premised
on cultural mores and practices.17 The yardstick of power varies over
time and space because the players that occupy any given field defi ne
and struggle over its meaning. The concept of capital, together with
the recovery of the practical point of view, reminds us that resources
have to be recognized as such in order to establish the basis of a power
relation. Not only do players employ capital to get the upper hand in
the field, they also struggle over the meaning and value of resources.
There are a few realists who recognize the importance of “pres-
tige” or “status competition” in international politics; yet ultimately
they too reduce these symbolic power struggles to a material basis.18
Alternatively, Barry O’Neill puts the pursuit of honor, face and pres-
tige at the center of his theory but fi nally concludes that “they are
fought over for the benefits they yield”19 – presumably material. Again,
I do not quibble that material resources have often been highly prized
in human societies, including in international politics; but this is an
empirical observation that cannot be theoretically assumed away.
To reify a contingent observation into a timeless assumption actu-
ally reveals more about the theorist’s own habitus than anything else.
Moreover, the premise that material power is always preponderant
is unwarranted in an increasingly institutionalized world where sur-
vival is only very rarely at stake. As we enter the twenty-fi rst century,
belonging to the club of liberal democracies is often more powerful
a resource than owning a large army. From a Bourdieu-inspired per-
spective, the yardsticks that structure positions in a field are socially
constructed, culturally specific and historically contingent. Structure
too has a practical logic; and its causal efficacy rests with practice.
(4) A similar point applies to the English School, whose greatest
insight probably consists of showing the weight of history on interna-
tional practices. Practices evolve over time through patterns of repro-
duction and contestation, as is the case with diplomacy, for instance. 20
But while the English School is very apt in showing how institutions
17
Reus-Smit (1997, 63–86).
18
Gilpin (1981, 28–31); Wohlforth (2009, 55). The relational competitiveness
for status is generally inspired from Weber’s path-breaking works on
status groups; more recently it has found solid empirical backing in social
identity theory. In IR, see e.g. Mercer (1995); and Lebow (2008).
19 20
O’Neill (1999, 244). Watson (1991).
246 International Security in Practice
every historical action brings together two states of history: objectified his-
tory, i.e. the history which has accumulated over the passage of time in
things, machines, buildings, monuments, books, theories, customs, law,
etc.; and embodied history, in the form of habitus … The relationship to the
social world is not the mechanical causality that is often assumed between
a “milieu” and a consciousness, but rather a sort of ontological complicity.
When the same history inhabits both habitus and habitat, both dispositions
and position, the king and his court, the employer and his fi rm, the bishop
and his see, history in a sense communicates with itself, is reflected in its
own image … The doxic relation to the native world, a quasi-ontological
commitment flowing from practical experience, is a relationship of belong-
ing and owning in which a body, appropriated by history, absolutely and
immediately appropriates things inhabited by the same history.21
21 22
Bourdieu (1981, 305–6). Mearsheimer (2001, xi).
23
Barnett and Duvall (2005).
Conclusion 247
24 25
Carr (1958, 52–3). Jackson and Nexon (2004, 340).
26
Wendt (1999, 141). Wendt does allow for other structures (e.g. material,
interest) but his “primary focus is on a subset of social structure, socially
shared knowledge or ‘culture.’ ”
248 International Security in Practice
27
Sterling-Folker (2002 , 76). 28 Bourdieu (2003, 190).
29 30
Bourdieu (1989, 16). Nexon (2009, 14).
Conclusion 249
31
Neumann (1996, 166).
Bibliography
251
252 Bibliography
Cooper, Helene (2008), “In Georgia Clash, a Lesson on U.S. Need for
Russia,” New York Times, August 9.
Council of the EU (2003), “A Secure Europe in a Better World,” European
Security Strategy, December 12.
Cox, Michael (1992), “Western Intelligence, the Soviet Threat and
NSC-68: A Reply to Beatrice Heuser,” Review of International
Studies 18(1): 75 –86.
Crawford, Neta C. (2002), Argument and Change in World Politics:
Ethics, Decolonization, and Humanitarian Intervention. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Cross, Mai’a K. Davis (2006), The European Diplomatic Corps: Diplomats
and International Cooperation from Westphalia to Maastricht. New
York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Daalder, Ivo and James Goldgeier (2006), “Global NATO,” Foreign Affairs
85(5): 105 –13.
Daalder, Ivo H. and James M. Lindsay (2005 [2003]), American Unbound:
The Bush Revolution in Foreign Policy, 2nd edition. Hoboken, NJ:
John Wiley and Sons.
D’Andrade, Roy (1995), The Development of Cognitive Anthropology.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Dannreuther, Roland (1999 –2000), “Escaping the Enlargement Trap in
NATO–Russian Relations,” Survival 41(4): 145 –64.
De Certeau, Michel (1990 [1980]), L’invention du quotidien 1. Arts de faire
(The Invention of the Everyday: Ways of Doing). Paris: Gallimard.
De Nevers, Renée (2007), “NATO’s International Security Role in the
Terrorist Era,” International Security 31(4): 34 –66.
Der Derian, James (1987), On Diplomacy: A Genealogy of Western
Estrangement. Oxford: Blackwell.
Deutsch, Karl W., Sidney A. Burrell, Robert A. Kann, Maurice Lee Jr.,
Martin Lichterman, Raymond E. Lindgren, Francis L. Loewenheim
and Richard W. Van Wagenen (1957), Political Community and the
North Atlantic Area: International Organization in the Light of
Historical Experience. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Dezalay, Yves and Bryant Garth (2002), The Internationalization of
Palace Wars: Lawyers, Economists, and the Contest to Transform
Latin American States. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Doty, Roxanne Lynn (1996), Imperial Encounters: The Politics of
Representation in North–South Relations. Minneapolis: University
of Minnesota Press.
Duffy, Gavan, Brian K. Frederking and Seth A. Tucker (1998), “Language
Games: Dialogical Analysis of INF Negotiations,” International
Studies Quarterly 42(2): 271–94.
256 Bibliography
Heuser, Beatrice (1991), “NSC 68 and the Soviet Threat: A New Perspective
on Western Threat Perception and Policy Making,” Review of
International Studies 17(1): 17–40.
Hollis, Martin and Steve Smith (1990), Explaining and Understanding
International Relations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hopf, Ted (2002) Social Construction of International Politics: Identities
and Foreign Policies, Moscow, 1955 and 1999. Ithaca, NY: Cornell
University Press.
(n.d.), “The Logic of Habit in International Relations,” mimeo, May
2008.
Huysmans, Jef (2002), “Shape-shifting NATO: Humanitarian Action
and the Kosovo Refugee Crisis,” Review of International Studies
28(3): 599 –618.
Ivanov, Sergey B. (2004), “International Security in the Context of the
Russia–NATO Relationship,” Munich, February 7 (www.securitycon-
ference.de/konferenzen/rede.php?menu_2005=&menu_konferenz ,
accessed July 27, 2007).
Izvestia (2004), “Yury Baluyevsky, First Deputy Chief of the Russian
General Staff: ‘NATO Expansion Will Strike a Fatal Blow to the
Treaty on Conventional Armed Forces in Europe,” Izvestia, March 3,
translated in Current Digest of the Post-Soviet Press 56(9).
Jackson, Patrick Thaddeus (2004), “Hegel’s House, or ‘People Are States
Too,’” Review of International Studies 30(2): 281–7.
(2006a), Civilizing the Enemy: German Reconstruction and the
Invention of the West. Ann Arbor, MI: University of Michigan
Press.
(2006b), “Making Sense of Making Sense: Configurational Analysis and
the Double Hermeneutic,” in Dvora Yanow and Peregrine Schwartz-
Shea, eds., Interpretation and Method: Empirical Research Methods
and the Interpretive Turn, 264–80. New York: M. E. Sharpe.
(2008), “Foregrounding Ontology: Dualism, Monism, and IR Theory,”
Review of International Studies 34(1): 129 –53.
Jackson, Patrick Thaddeus and Daniel H. Nexon (1999), “Relations before
States: Substance, Process and the Study of World Politics,” European
Journal of International Relations 5(3): 291–332.
(2004), “Constructivist Realism or Realist-Constructivism?”
International Studies Review 6(2): 337–41.
Jackson, Peter (2008), “Pierre Bourdieu, the ‘Cultural Turn’ and the
Practice of International History,” Review of International Studies
34(1): 155 –81.
Johnston, Alastair Iain (2001), “Treating International Institutions as Social
Environments,” International Studies Quarterly 45(4): 487–515.
260 Bibliography
(2001), “Bush’s Vision: ‘We Will Not Trade Away the Fate of Free
European Peoples,” New York Times, June 16.
Nexon, Daniel H. (2009), The Struggle for Power in Early Modern Europe:
Religious Conflict, Dynastic Empires and International Change.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Nezavisimaya Gazeta (1994), “Yeltsin on Partnership in NATO,”
Nezavisimaya Gazeta, April 7, translated in Current Digest of the
Post-Soviet Press 46(14).
Nicolson, Harold (1963 [1939]), Diplomacy, 3rd edition. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Norris, John (2005), Collision Course: NATO, Russia, and Kosovo.
Westport, CN: Praeger.
O’Neill, Barry (1999), Honor, Symbols, and War. Ann Arbor, MI:
University of Michigan Press.
Onuf, Nicholas (1998), “Constructivism: A User’s Manual,” in Vendulka
Kubalkova, Nicholas Onuf and Paul Kowert, eds., International
Relations in a Constructed World, 58–98. Armonk, NY:
M. E. Sharpe.
Parkhomenko, Sergei (1993), “Russia Gives Poland Leave to Join NATO,”
Sevodnya, August 27, translated in Current Digest of the Post-Soviet
Press 45(34).
Paul, T. V. (2005), “Soft Balancing in the Age of U.S. Primacy,” Inter-
national Security 30(1): 46 –71.
Pierson, Paul (2004), Politics in Time: History, Institutions, and Social
Analysis. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
PIPA (2002), Worldview 2002: American and European Public Opinion
and Foreign Policy, The Chicago Council on Foreign Relations,
(www.ccfr.org/globalviews2004/sub/pdf/2002_Comparative.pdf ,
accessed January 24, 2004).
Polanyi, Michael (1983), The Tacit Dimension. Gloucester, MA: Peter
Smith.
Poleshchuk, Andrei (1993), “Is an Expansion of NATO Justified?”
Nezavisimaya Gazeta, November 26, translated in Current Digest of
the Post-Soviet Press 45(47).
Polkinghorne, Donald E. (1988), Narrative Knowing and the Human
Sciences. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.
Ponsard, Lionel (2007), Russia, NATO and Cooperative Security: Bridging
the Gap. New York: Routledge.
Pop, Liliana (2007), “Time and Crisis: Framing Success and Failure in
Romania’s Post-communist Transformations,” Review of Inter-
national Studies 33(3): 395 –413.
Bibliography 267
(2006), “Russia and the U.S. in Need of Trust and Cooperation,” Russia
in Global Affairs, February 8 (eng.globalaffairs.ru/number/14/1005.
html, accessed April 5, 2006).
Pushkov, Aleksei (1999), “The Chernomyrdin Syndrome,” Nezavisimaya
Gazeta, June 11, translated in Current Digest of the Post-Soviet Press
51(23).
(2004), “The Aim Is Not to Divide Ukraine, But to Break It Away from
Russia,” Trud, December 1, translated in Current Digest of the Post-
Soviet Press 56(48).
Reber, Arthur S. (1993), Implicit Learning and Tacit Knowledge: An
Essay on the Cognitive Unconscious. New York: Oxford University
Press.
Reus-Smit, Christian (1997), The Moral Purpose of the State: Culture,
Social Identity, and Institutional Rationality in International
Relations. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Ricoeur, Paul (1977 [1973]), “The Model of the Text: Meaningful Action
Considered as a Text,” in Fred R. Dallmayr and Thomas A. McCarthy,
eds., Understanding and Social Inquiry, 316–34. Notre Dame, IN:
University of Notre Dame Press.
Ringmar, Erik (1996), Identity, Interest and Action: A Cultural
Explanation of Sweden’s Intervention in the Thirty Years War.
New York: Cambridge University Press.
Risse, Thomas (2000), “‘Let’s Argue!’: Communicative Action in World
Politics,” International Organization 54(1): 1–39.
Rodin, Ivan (1994), “NATO’s Program Is Not Entirely to the Liking of the
State Duma,” Nezavisimaya Gazeta, March 18, translated in Current
Digest of the Post-Soviet Press 46(11).
Rodionov, Igor (1996), “What Sort of Defense Does Russia Need?”
Nezavisimoye Voyennoye Obozreniye, November 28, translated in
Current Digest of the Post-Soviet Press 48(50).
Rossiiskaya Gazeta (1996), “Let’s Leave Nuclear Ambitions to the History
Books,” Rossiiskaya Gazeta, September 26, translated in Current
Digest of the Post-Soviet Press 48(39).
(1997), “Cooperation Instead of Confrontation,” Rossiiskaya Gazeta,
March 18, translated in Current Digest of the Post-Soviet Press
49(11).
(1999), “NATO Seeks to Enter 21st Century Wearing the Uniform of
World Policeman,” Rossiiskaya Gazeta, March 26, translated in
Current Digest of the Post-Soviet Press 51(12).
Rossiiskiye Vesti (1995), “Abandon Reflexive Resort to Force in Favor of
Considered Approach,” Rossiiskiye Vesti, September 8, translated in
Current Digest of the Post-Soviet Press 47(36).
Bibliography 269
Adler, Emanuel 5, 13, 40, 61, 66, 237 Dayton Accord 159
Adler, Emanuel and Michael Barnett 3, Implementation Force (IFOR) 123
4, 5, 38, 39, 45 Operation Deliberate Force 159,
Afghanistan war 114, 124, 130, 209, 163, 170
211, 213, 217 Sarajevo market bombing 159, 161
basing rights in Central Asia 124, Srebrenica massacre 159, 163
213, 219 Stabilization Force (SFOR) 123, 124
International Security Assistance UN Protection Force (UNPROFOR)
Force (ISAF) 217, 218 159, 162, 163
agent–structure relationship 20, 32–3; Vance–Owen plan 159, 160
see also practicality, logic of Bourdieu, Pierre 1, 2, 5, 15, 26, 27, 31,
Ahtisaari, Martti 200 32, 34, 36, 46, 47, 48, 49, 50, 52,
Albania 196, 222 60, 69, 70, 74, 85, 86, 87, 140,
Albright, Madeleine 185, 186, 199, 192, 232, 243, 244, 246, 247, 248
202 Bulgaria 107, 188, 189, 201, 219, 225
Anti-Ballistic Missile (ABM) treaty Bush, George W. 119, 213, 216, 219,
215, 216 223
appropriateness, logic of 17–22; Bush Doctrine 209
see also social action, logics of; Bush, George H. W. 163
practicality, logic of
Arbatov, Alexei 212 Canada 84, 100, 213
arguing, logic of 11, 19, 73; capital 33–4, 245
see also social action, logics of; cultural–symbolic 148–53, 161, 182,
practicality, logic of 187, 202, 239
Aspin, Les 164 material–institutional 105, 148,
151, 153, 160–1, 182, 187, 188,
background knowledge see practical 202, 206, 209, 211, 222, 228;
knowledge; habitus see also field
ballistic missile defense 4, 89, 101, Chechnya 100, 108, 131, 168, 176,
114, 125, 129 177, 189, 206, 211, 225
Baltic states 84, 107, 109, 110–11, Chernomyrdin, Viktor 199, 200
164, 188, 207, 214, 218, 225 Chirac, Jacques 233
Baluyevsky, Yuri 129, 226 Christopher, Warren 173, 185
Baranovsky, Vladimir 181, 204, 210 Clark, Wesley 201
Belarus 102, 109, 114, 188, 190, 198, Clinton, Bill 159, 162, 164, 166, 167,
199, 207 168, 171, 174, 188, 191, 202
Belgium 111, 127, 218, 223 cognition 11, 19, 21, 24–6, 28, 49,
Bosnian civil war 174, 122, 159–60, 243, 248, 249
161, 165, 169, 216, 227 Cohen, William 202
275
276 Index
Cold War see NATO–Russia relations 173, 174, 181, 182, 191, 192,
and the Cold War 214; see also mode of pursuing
collective defense see NATO and security, internal
collective defense Cooperative Threat Reduction
collective identification 3, 38, 237; program 121–2
see also security community corporate agency 86–8
collective security 158, 159, 161, 195, critical junctures see path dependence
220; see also NATO enlargement Croatia 162, 222
functional Czechoslovakia/Czech Republic
Collective Security Treaty 101, 140, 163, 195, 214, 225;
Organization (CSTO) 219, 220 see also Visegrad states
color revolutions 89, 102, 219;
see also Ukraine; Orange democratic peace see modes of
Revolution; Georgia; Rose pursuing security, internal
Revolution Denmark 188, 218
commonsense see doxa Deutsch, Karl W. 3, 4, 5, 38, 39
Commonwealth of Independent States diplomacy 11–12, 41
(CIS) 89, 188, 219, 220, 221 as normal practice 42, 232
community of practice 5, 13, 39–40, as self-evident practice 1, 40–4, 50,
45, 80, 82 95
Conference on Security and as skill 12, 16, 30–1, 66
Cooperation in Europe (CSCE) embodiment of 42–3, 50, 95–6, 98,
98, 151, 154, 155, 157, 159, 170, 99, 105, 107, 109, 110, 112, 122
173 direction of fit 29–30
Budapest summit (1994) 167 dispositions see habitus
Helsinki principles 221, 226 domination see doxa
Paris Charter 151 doxa 30, 34, 36, 72, 148, 152, 187,
see also Organization for Security 232
and Cooperation in Europe and misrecognition 47–8, 49
(OSCE) and symbolic power 34, 45, 46–7,
consequences, logic of 21, 242; 49, 245, 246–7
see also rational choice see also field
theory; social action, logics of; Durkheim, Émile 60
practicality, logic of
constructivism 11, 18, 242 Elster, Jon 242
and methodology 52, 54, 78–82; English School 245–6, 249
see also Sobjectivism ethnomethodology see Garfinkel,
and practice theory 247–9 Harold
as style of reasoning 54–9 Euro-Atlantic Partnership Council
postfoundationalist 56–9, 77 (EAPC) 155
representational bias in 17–22, 39 European Union (EU) 44, 85, 121, 224
Contact Group 162, 163, 170, 197, European Neighbourhood Policy
199; see also Bosnian civil war; 152
Kosovo crisis European Security Strategy (2003)
contextualization see interpretation 152
Conventional Forces in Europe (CFE),
treaty on 89, 184, 186, 188, 189, field 1, 33, 158
224–6, 227 as social game 34; see also doxa
cooperative security 156, 159, 160, as structure of position 33, 36, 49,
167, 168, 169, 170, 171, 172, 91, 149, 247; see also capital
Index 277
North Atlantic Council (NAC) 84, practicality, logic of 6, 13–38, 27, 50,
129, 143, 155, 164, 167, 66, 97, 120, 140, 231, 249
196, 223 and logic of appropriateness 35, 37
Norway 111, 188, 207 and logic of consequence 36–7
Nunn–Lugar program see Cooperative and logic of habit 21–2, 43–4
Threat Reduction ontological priority of 36, 40
see also social action, logics of
Obama, Barack 119 practice 12
objectification see interpretation; constitutive 40, 41;
historicization see also community of practice
ontological security 13 study of 51, 62, 66–72, 74–5,
Organization for Security and 83, 85–6, 95, 102, 104;
Cooperation in Europe (OSCE) see also induction; interpretation
115, 151, 152, 158, 167, 168, practice theory 13, 23, 27, 45, 241–50
189, 197, 214, 221 practice turn 5, 13, 21, 22
Istanbul Summit 152, 224 Primakov, Yevgeny 141, 165, 166, 172,
173, 174, 176, 178, 179, 184,
Partnership for Peace (PfP) 155, 159, 185, 186, 187, 188, 190, 196,
164, 166, 169, 183, 184, 189, 198, 199, 200, 212
198; see also NATO enlargement, Putin, Vladimir 135, 206, 210, 213,
functional 215, 216, 218, 225, 226
path dependence 63, 75, 161, 192–3,
228, 245–6 rational choice theory 11, 16–17, 56,
peace see security community 242, 248, 249
Permanent Joint Council (PJC) 97, realism 244–5, 246, 249
129, 185, 191, 196, 197, 198, realpolitik see modes of pursuing
212, 213; see also NATO–Russia security, external
Council reflexive knowledge
Perry, William 163 see representational knowledge
phenomenology see induction representational bias 13, 14–22, 26,
Poland 84, 101, 109–10, 163, 45, 52
164, 188, 195, 207, 214, 225; epistemological roots of 14–15, 51
see also Visegrad states representational knowledge 11, 14,
Polanyi, Michael 23, 24, 47 28–30
Popper, Karl 80 Rice, Condoleezza 224
positions see field Ricoeur, Paul 61, 62, 79
positional agency 35, 153, 181, 187, Robertson, Lord 213
206, 211, 228, 239, 244, 248; Rodionov, Igor 171
see also field; practical sense Rogozin, Dimitri 212
positivism 53, 58, 79, 80, 81, 85 Romania 107, 140, 188, 189, 201,
postfoundationalism see constructivism 219, 225
power see doxa and symbolic power Rühe, Volker 164, 166, 196
practical knowledge 1, 11, 12, 21, 22, Russia
23–4, 27–31, 51, 66, 68–70, 95, bureaucracy 84, 101–2, 117, 128,
102 132, 133, 134–8, 139–40, 157,
practical sense 35, 68, 105, 113, 122, 165
193, 194, 233 domestic transition in 119, 120,
and agency and structure 35–6, 134, 176, 189, 228, 229
37 Duma 183, 189, 198
see also practicality, logic of elite change in 105, 176, 179, 228
Index 281