Islamic Constitutionalism Not Secular. N PDF
Islamic Constitutionalism Not Secular. N PDF
Islamic Constitutionalism Not Secular. N PDF
ISLAMIC CONSTITUTIONALISM:
NOT SECULAR. NOT THEOCRATIC. NOT IMPOSSIBLE.
Asifa Quraishi-Landes
I. INTRODUCTION
1 For further detail, see Bernard Weiss, Interpretation in Islamic Law: The
Theory of Ijtihad, 26 AMER. J. COMP. L. 199 (1978).
2015] ISLAMIC CONSTITUTIONALISM 555
no lawmaking at all. They most certainly did. But the laws they
made were of a very different type than fiqh.7
(“after the age of mihna . . . the ‘ulama (religious scholars or jurists) were able to
establish themselves as the exclusive interpreters and articulators of the divine
law . . . . [T]he inquisition was a concerted effort by the state to control the
juristic class and the method by which Shari’ah law was generated. Ultimately,
however, the inquisition failed and, at least until the modern age, the jurists
retained a near exclusive monopoly over the right to interpret the divine law.”).
7 See Abou El Fadl, supra note 6, at 30–31 (“Only the jurists [were]
qualif[ied] to investigate and interpret the Divine will . . . . However, pursuant to
the powers derived from its role as the enforcer of Divine laws, the State was
granted a broad range of discretion over what were considered matters of public
interest [known as the field of al-siyasah al-Shar’iyyah].”).
8 See Asifa Quraishi, The Separation of Powers in the Tradition of Muslim
Governments, in CONSTITUTIONALISM IN ISLAMIC COUNTRIES: BETWEEN UPHEAVAL
AND CONTINUITY 67 (Tilmann J. Roder & Rainer Grote eds., 2012); Gianluca
Parolin, Religion and the Sources of Law: Shari‘ah in Constitutions, in LAW,
RELIGION, CONSTITUTION; FREEDOM OF RELIGION, EQUAL TREATMENT, AND THE LAW
95–97 (Durham et al. eds., 2013) (describing the difference between fiqh and
siyasa); FRANK VOGEL, ISLAMIC LAW AND LEGAL SYSTEM: STUDIES OF SAUDI ARABIA
31 (2000) (describing fiqh and siyasa as “microcosmic” and “macrocosmic” law).
9 See VOGEL, supra note 8, at 52, 171–73. For an insightful study of some
interaction between fiqh and siyasa in Muslim legal history, see KRISTEN STILT,
ISLAMIC LAW IN ACTION: AUTHORITY, DISCRETION, AND EVERYDAY EXPERIENCES IN
MAMLUK EGYPT (2012), describing the mixed fiqh-siyasa role of the muhtasib.
558 RUTGERS JOURNAL OF LAW & RELIGION [Vol. 16
10 See Mohammad Fadel, The True, the Good, and the Reasonable: The
Theological and Ethical Roots of Public Reason in Islamic Law, 21 CAN. J.L. &
JURIS. 5, 59 (2008) (“this area of the law was entirely independent of theological
expertise, and accordingly, legitimized rule-making for the vindication of public
interests rather than the vindication of express revelatory norms.”); Abou El-
Fadl, supra note 6, at 30–31 (describing Muslim ruler broad range of discretion
over matters of public interest).
11 Sadiq Reza, Torture and Islamic Law, 8 CHI. J. INT’L. L. 21, 27 (2007).
12 For more detail on maslaha, see FELICITAS OPWIS, MASLAHA AND THE
PURPOSE OF THE LAW: ISLAMIC DISCOURSE ON LEGAL CHANGE FROM THE 4TH/10TH TO
8TH/14TH CENTURY 1–8 (2010).
13 Frank Vogel, Islamic Governance in the Gulf: A Framework for Analysis,
Comparison, and Prediction, in THE PERSIAN GULF AT THE MILLENNIUM: ESSAYS IN
POLITICS, ECONOMY, SECURITY, AND RELIGION 259 (Gary G. Sick & Lawrence G.
Potter eds., 1997) (“as understood by [fiqh scholars] the ruler possesses authority
under siyasa doctrine to act freely to pursue the welfare of the [community] as he
understands it . . . .”). Shihab al-Din al-Qarafi, for example, described siyasa as
“that power entrusted to the government to improve society. Exercises of this
power were valid insofar as they were undertaken with the purpose of enhancing
the community’s welfare, and did so improve it in fact.” See Fadel, supra note 10,
at 58 (quoting al-Qarafi’s al-Furuq). See generally OVAMIR ANJUM, POLITICS, LAW,
AND COMMUNITY IN ISLAMIC THOUGHT: THE TAYMIYYAN MOMENT (2012) (comparing
a great number of siyasa shariyya scholars on the topic of Islamic governance,
including their divergent views on the reason for and nature of the siyasa ruler).
2015] ISLAMIC CONSTITUTIONALISM 559
16 It was self-enforced when individual Muslims sought out fatwas for their
personal legal questions. It was enforced by the state if the fiqh was being applied
through the judgment of a qadi.
17 See WAEL B. HALLAQ, AN INTRODUCTION TO ISLAMIC LAW 85–124 (2009).
2015] ISLAMIC CONSTITUTIONALISM 561
government under the rule of law brought the hegemony of statutory legislation
that has largely dominated legal and judicial practice in Muslim societies. The
government and its legislative branch tend to act as the sole repository of
legislative power.”); see also Jackson, supra note 5.
2015] ISLAMIC CONSTITUTIONALISM 563
21 See e.g., Tamir Moustafa, Islamic Law, Women’s Rights, and Popular
Legal Consciousness in Malaysia, 38 LAW & SOC. INQUIRY 168 (2013) (showing,
based on recent polling data, lay Muslim ignorance of core epistemological
commitments in Islamic legal theory, such as its commitment to pluralism and
the centrality of human agency in fiqh lawmaking).
22 For details on this phenomenon in the context of Islamic law and
women’s rights, see Asifa Quraishi, What if Sharia Weren’t the Enemy?
Rethinking International Women’s Rights Advocacy on Islamic Law, 22 COLUM. J.
GENDER & L. 173 (2011).
564 RUTGERS JOURNAL OF LAW & RELIGION [Vol. 16
23 Support for sharia legislation is often fueled by identity politics such that
it has come to symbolize what it is to be a religious Muslim, as against secularism
as an extension of cultural imperialism and the politics of Christians. See Anver
M. Emon, The Limits of Constitutionalism in the Muslim World: History and
Identity in Islamic Law, in CONSTITUTIONAL DESIGN FOR DIVIDED SOCIETIES:
INTEGRATION OR ACCOMMODATION? 258, 259 (Choudhry ed., 2008).
2015] ISLAMIC CONSTITUTIONALISM 567
24 As Mohammad Fadel has said, “Muslims should not ask whether the
human rights standard is the same as that under Islamic law, but only whether
the human rights standard represents a legitimate act of government.”
Mohammad Fadel, The Challenge of Human Rights, SEASONS: SEMIANNUAL
JOURNAL OF ZAYTUNA INST. 59, 69 (2008).
25 See JOHN L. ESPOSITO AND DALIA MOGAHED, WHO SPEAKS FOR ISLAM:
choice is for her fiqh school to also be the law of the land for
everyone. If, however, a parallel fiqh realm were available to her
to enforce her preferred fiqh school, then she would have much
less motivation to pressure the state to enact her personal fiqh
choices over everyone. An officially-recognized fiqh realm could
likewise redirect the attention of Islamist advocacy away from
state law as the only way for fiqh rules to be enforced. By
constitutionally protecting a separate realm of fiqh that is
facilitated—but not controlled—by the siyasa power, the proposed
framework thus offers a way to return fiqh back to its proper
place—not mined as raw material in support of political agendas,
but rather living in its own separate sphere, making a variety of
fiqh options available at the individual request of each Muslim.
An important attribute of the fiqh realm should be legal
diversity. This would honor both the epistemology of Islamic
jurisprudence as well ensuring meaningful choice for those
choosing to use fiqh as their governing law. As described earlier,
all fiqh understandings of sharia are equally valid, making the
world of fiqh law inherently and unavoidably one of doctrinal
diversity. According to Islamic legal theory, individual Muslims
are free to choose whichever fiqh school’s interpretive methodology
best fits them. To borrow modern constitutional terms, the
freedom to choose a fiqh school is a matter of Islamic religious
freedom. Moreover, a sufficiently diverse fiqh realm—with fiqh
rules and scholars from every classically-established school as well
as new and reform fiqh scholarship—will help ensure that those
opting to use this fiqh realm are doing so with full consent.
The importance of choice also means that there should be
freedom to not use the fiqh realm at all. This means that a full and
robust body of state laws (created through democratic
determinations of the public good) should exist parallel to the fiqh
realm, including topic areas covered by fiqh. In this, the
constitutional structure proposed here diverges from classical
Muslim legal pluralism. In pre-modern Muslim systems, siyasa
laws were typically limited to logistical and administrative needs
of society and generally did not overlap with the topics covered by
fiqh. Accordingly, pre-modern Muslims could have their legal
issues decided according to their chosen fiqh school but they could
not choose to follow no fiqh school at all, for there were no siyasa
laws written for the general public on many important legal
570 RUTGERS JOURNAL OF LAW & RELIGION [Vol. 16
35 Using Frank Vogel’s language, there is a very real risk that a consensus-
based sharia check would, “fall into the trap of adopting medieval legal views as
permanent constitutional principles, even when disagreement as to them has
emerged in modern times.” Frank Vogel, Objectives of the Shari’a (on file with
author).
36 The public reaction to Tariq Ramadan’s call for a moratorium on the
death penalty in Muslim countries could be described as an example of this “dead
hand.” His call would almost certainly have served the public good, but yet,
because it contradicted past fiqh consensus about the use of the death penalty, it
was met with great resistance in many Muslim circles. See Tariq Ramadan, An
International Call for Moratorium on Corporal Punishment, Stoning and the
Death Penalty in the Islamic World, (Apr. 5, 2005), available at
http://www.tariqramadan.com/spip.php?article264. Ramadan was severely
criticized by Muslim leaders and academics from around the world who asserted
that he was attempting to ban a God-decreed punishment. See Dina Abdel-
Majeed, Tariq Ramadan’s Call for a Moratorium: Storm in a Teacup, (Apr. 18,
2005), available at http://www.onislam.net/english/shariah/contemporary-issues/
critiques-and-thought/439960-tariq-ramadans-call-for-a-
moratorium.html?Thought=.
576 RUTGERS JOURNAL OF LAW & RELIGION [Vol. 16
awkwardly fit one type of Islamic law (siyasa) into the other type of Islamic law
(fiqh), the purpose-based approach honors the bifurcation of fiqh and siyasa,
separating sharia review from fiqh formalism altogether, but still keeping it
within the boundaries of sharia ideals, writ large.
578 RUTGERS JOURNAL OF LAW & RELIGION [Vol. 16
VI. CONCLUSION