Frede-Stoics and Skepticson Clear and Distinct Impressions
Frede-Stoics and Skepticson Clear and Distinct Impressions
Frede-Stoics and Skepticson Clear and Distinct Impressions
151
152 CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS
be on the way to the kind of knowledge Socrates had searched for in vain.
Now when the Stoics claimed that such knowledge is attainable, they also
thought that they had to construct an epistemology in terms of which they could
show that and how such knowledge is to be gained. On this account nature has
provided us with a firm basis for knowledge by providing us with clear and dis-
tinct impressions, the so-called kataleptic or cognitive impressions, which by
their very nature cannot be false and hence constitute an unfailing guide to the
truths one has to know in order to have the wisdom that guarantees the good life.
Thus the Stoic theory of knowledge is based on a doctrine of clear and distinct
impressions. Given that the skeptics not only were not persuaded that such
knowledge had been attained, but even questioned whether such knowledge was
attainable, they naturally focused their attack on the Stoic theory of knowledge
and in particular on the Stoic doctrine of clear and distinct impressions by means
of which we are supposed to be able to acquire the knowledge in question. As
a result a lively debate ensued which lasted for more than two centuries and
which attracted the best philosophers of the time.
Tradition, though, has developed a view of the Stoic position which makes
it so vulnerable to skeptical attacks that it becomes very difficult to understand
how the Stoics, through centuries, were able to sustain the criticism without hav-
ing to concede defeat. If the Stoics had defended the position that tends to be
ascribed to them, their school should have been deserted in no time. That instead
it was defended by men of the ingenuity of a Chrysippus should encourage us
to take a fresh look at the Stoic position to see whether it might not be more at-
tractive or at least easier to defend than tradition would make us believe.
Impressions
Animals and human beings are constructed in such a way that their survival
and well-being depends essentially on the adequacy of their cognitions. They
have to be able to recognize and to shun what is bad for them, and they have
to be in a position to realize and seek out what is conducive to their preservation
and well-being. For this purpose they are equipped with a sensory apparatus and
a soul which, via the senses, receives impressions of the outside world, and thus
provides them with some kind of awareness of the world around them. There
is a crucial difference, though, between the impressions of rational beings and
the impressions of animals. The impressions of rational beings are called "ratio-
nal impressions" (D.L. VII 51). Rational impressions have a prepositional con-
tent, they are impressions to the effect that something is the case very much in
the sense in which we might say ordinarily, "the impression which one gets, if
one looks at the evidence, is that. . . . " Thus rational impressions are thoughts
CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS 153
(D.L. VII 51; Ps.-Gal. Def. med. XIX 381 K.) which present themselves to the
mind and which the mind either accepts or refuses to accept. To accept or give
assent to a thought or impression is to have the belief that the proposition which
forms the content of the impression is true, to refuse to accept a thought is to
suspend judgment. Thoughts may present themselves to the mind in all sorts of
ways. They may come to mind when one considers the evidence concerning a
question in doubt. But many of them are brought about by the causal agency of
an external object which, through the sense organs, gives rise to an impression
in us. Thus to see something, on this view, is to have a certain kind of thought
generated in a certain way. But thoughts may also be generated in all sorts of
other ways.
Now the Stoics follow Socrates, Plato, and Aristotle in the view that it is a
mark of moral knowledge that one never has a mistaken view in moral matters.
The Stoics even take the stronger view that the wise man will never have any
false beliefs at all (Stob. Ed. II 111, 18 W.), because, for reasons we shall see
later, any false belief might stand in the way of one's acquiring the kind of
knowledge we are after. One way in which nature could construct a mind which
has the ability to avoid any false beliefs whatsoever would be to endow the mind
with the ability unfailingly to sort the true impressions from the false ones. But
such a mind would be superhuman; nothing like the human physiology would
be able to support such a powerful mind. Instead nature provided human beings
with the ability unfailingly to distinguish true impressions of a certain kind—
namely, clear and distinct impressions-from all other impressions whether they
are true or not. In this way human beings are not in a position to know all truths
but only those whose truth is guaranteed by clear and distinct impressions. But
then we do not need to know all truths to lead a good life, and the clear and dis-
tinct impressions we receive in the ordinary course of events provide an ample
basis for what we need to know. If our ability to know is restricted this way,
our ability to avoid false belief is unlimited: all we need to do is not to accept
as true any impression that is not guaranteed to be true by clear and distinct im-
pressions. Thus there will be many true impressions which we nevertheless will
not give assent to, but there will be no false impressions which we accept as true.
All this presupposes that there is a class of impressions which by their very
nature cannot be false and that the mind can discriminate between these and
other impressions. Our main task in the following will be to explain how the
Stoics could make these assumptions. To understand this, we first have to have
a closer look at the Stoic doctrine of rational impressions quite generally.
On the one hand, rational impressions are not mere sensory affections. This
distinguishes them from the impressions of irrational animals. There are several
passages according to which the Stoics distinguish rational impressions from
mere sense-impressions (cf. Cic. Acad. II 21; SE M VII 345). Even the most
primitive rational impression, like the impression that this is white, already in-
154 CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS
volves the representation of the object by means of a concept, in this case the
concept "white." It is in this way that they require a rational mind and manage
to be thoughts and to have a definite prepositional content. Sometimes commen-
tators talk as if we applied concepts to objects on the basis of impressions which
in themselves are preconceptual. But this cannot be the way the Stoics think of
rational impressions. For given an impression which does not yet involve the
conceptualization of the object, we could have any number of beliefs about the
objects on the basis of such an impression. Hence there would not be any one
definite proposition that forms the content of the impression, and assent to the
impression would not constitute a definite belief. It may be objected that impres-
sions are supposed to be passive affections of the mind, whereas the mind's con-
ceptualization of an object would be an active contribution of the mind to the
impression. But it has to be kept in mind that the Stoics characterize an impres-
sion as a passive affection of the mind to contrast it with the act of assent and
not to deny that the mind has any part in the formation of a thought. As we shall
see, the Stoics think that the kind of impression which we have very much de-
pends on whether our mind is in normal working order; and part of what an ob-
ject does, when it gives rise to an impression in a rational mind that is in working
order, is that it makes the mind conceptualize the object in a certain way. In this
sense the rational impression is a passive affection of the mind, though it does
involve the operation of the mind. It will also be objected that impressions only
give rise to concepts and hence cannot themselves already presuppose concepts.
This objection overlooks the developmental character of the Stoic account. Hu-
man beings, according to the Stoics, start out as irrational animals. As such they
have the kind of sense-impressions which animals have. But in the case of human
beings these impressions give rise to concepts of very simple perceptual features
like colors, shapes, tastes, and the like, and thus reason slowly starts to grow.
Once we have these simple concepts, we can have corresponding rational im-
pressions and, what is more important, corresponding cognitive impressions.
These will naturally give rise to more complex concepts, like that of a man or
a tree, which in turn will enable us to have more complex rational and in particu-
lar cognitive impressions (cf. Cic. Acad. II21). Thus these common notions that
arise in us naturally on the basis of more primitive impressions turn out to be
truly anticipations (Cic. nd I 44; prolepseis); for they are needed to form the
impressions that afford us a grasp on things (katalepsis); it is in terms of them
that the mind has a grasp on things. Thus rational impressions and in particular
cognitive impressions do presuppose concepts, but these arise from more primi-
tive impressions that do not presuppose these concepts, and ultimately from
sense-impressions that do not presuppose any concepts whatsoever but that are
not rational either. Given this developmental account, it is easy to see how the
Stoics can claim that concepts only arise from the appropriate impressions and
CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS 155
in terms of general concepts each of which might equally apply to other objects.
But if I see the object and think that it is green, the object may not be represented
by general concepts at all, except for the concept "green," though it will be
represented in such a way that, just on the basis of the impression, we could go
on to represent it in terms of a host of concepts.
From what has been said it should be clear that there is some sense in which
impressions have parts corresponding to the various features that are rep-
resented in the impression—more particularly, a part or parts corresponding to
the features in terms of which the object of the thought or the subject of the
proposition is represented, and a part or parts corresponding to the feature or
features the object is represented as having—that is, a part or parts that corres-
pond to the predicate of the proposition the impression is a thought of. The
Stoics seem to be willing to call such parts of impressions "impressions," too.
For they call general notions "impressions" (SE M VII 246; Plut. Comm. not.
1084F; cf. Cic. Acad. II 21). But this seems to be misleading, since parts of
impressions are not true or false in the way impressions properly speaking are.
Hence it might be better to call such parts of impressions "ideas" and to
distinguish the way ideas have a prepositional content and are true or false from
the way impressions properly speaking are prepositional and true or false. The
Stoics also seem to distinguish between generic, or abstract, and specific, or
concrete, ideas (cf. SE M VII 246). The idea of man in general, for example,
is abstract, whereas the idea of Socrates and the idea of his complection may
be specific, or concrete. The fact that we represent an object in an impression
by means of a general concept is reflected by the fact that the corresponding
part of the impression is an abstract idea. Moreover, we have to assume that
the parts of rational impressions are ordered so that their combination in the
appropriate order amounts to the thought of a proposition, whereas their com-
bination in a different order might amount to the thought of a different proposi-
tion or to no thought at all.
To sum up: impressions are impressions of an object; in the case of rational
impressions this impression consists in a thought concerning the object; such a
thought involves the conceptualization of the object, but it need not be, and in
the case of perception is not, entirely conceptual; nevertheless, the thought is
the thought of a proposition; but it is characterized not only by the proposition
it is a thought of, but also by the way this proposition is thought; the way a
proposition is thought depends on the way the constituents of the proposition are
represented in the thought; this representation does not have to be entirely con-
ceptual—that is, it does not have to consist entirely of abstract ideas—in order
to represent a constituent of a proposition and in order to be constitutive of a
thought; in the case of perception the thought is partly nonconceptual; it
nevertheless is a thought, because it does involve the conceptualization of the
object, and in particular because it minimally involves the kind of conceptualiza-
CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS 157
tion of its object which gives it a prepositional content that is true or false, as
a result of which the thought itself can be said to be true or false.
Cognitive Impressions
How could there be impressions that cannot fail to be true, not for the trivial
reason that they are true or correspond to the facts, but because of some other
feature that is logically independent of their truth? It seems that there could be
such a feature, namely the property of having a certain kind of causal history,
and that the Stoics are relying on this feature.
Impressions have a certain causal history. In the course of this history all
sorts of things can go wrong. The mind, for example, may be defective and
hence produce the wrong impression. In the case of vision the light may be
wrong, the distance too big or too small, the sensory apparatus malfunctioning,
and as a result we may get a false impression. On the other hand, it stands to
reason that nature has constructed things in such a way that under normal condi-
tions the impression we receive is true. If under normal conditions something
appears to be red or appears to be a human being, then it is red or is a human
being. Thus impressions with the right kind of history cannot fail to be true,
though the fact that they have this kind of history is logically independent of their
truth. Let us call such impressions "normal."
There are different kinds of normal impressions. In particular it seems useful
to distinguish two kinds. If, for example, I have the impression that 2 + 2 =
4 because I have a proof for the proposition that 2 + 2 = 4, my impression will
have the right kind of causal history that will guarantee its truth. But it is not
a causal history that links the object of the impression, say the number 4, with
my impression; the impression, though produced in an appropriate, normal way,
is not produced or caused by the object of the impression itself. It is, at least
according to the Stoics, only in cases of perception that the normal impression
is caused by the object itself. Hence it will be useful to treat normal impressions
of this particular kind as a separate class and to call them "perceptual im-
pressions."
That the Stoics think of cognitive impressions as normal is suggested by the
following. Sextus Empiricus (M VII 247) characterized noncognitive impres-
sions quite generally as those one comes to have because of some abnormal con-
dition (pathos). "Abnormal condition" here can hardly refer just to abnormal
states of mind; for even in a normal state of mind one will have noncognitive
impressions—for example, if one is seeing something from too far away. Hence
"abnormal conditions" here has to be understood as referring to a whole set of
normal conditions. And in SE M VII424 we are in fact given such a set of condi-
tions for the case of vision. Five conditions have to be met for a visual impres-
sion to be cognitive: conditions on the sense organ, on the object of vision, on
158 CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS
how the object is placed, on how the impression comes about, and on the state
of mind. And though this is not said explicitly, it is strongly suggested that if
these conditions are met, the impression will be cognitive. Similarly Cicero
(Acad. II19) refers to such a set of sufficient and necessary conditions for cogni-
tive impressions.
Moreover, though this is a matter of considerable controversy, it also seems
that the Stoics think of cognitive impressions as perceptual. Aetius (Plac. IV
8.1) explicitly says that cognitive impressions come about through a sense or-
gan. Cicero talks of cognitive impressions as if they originated in the senses
(Acad. II 83). And the way the Stoics define cognitive impressions (they are sup-
posed to arise from an object) and what they have to say about the clearness and
distinctness of impressions make straightforward sense only for perceptual im-
pressions.
What seems to stand in the way of this assumption is the following. The
Stoics clearly assume that there are nonperceptual cognitions, namely, in those
cases where we have a proof of a theorem (DL VII 52). But it is also the case
that according to the Stoics even nonperceptual cognitions involve impressions.
(SE M VII370). Hence, it seems natural to assume that the impressions involved
in cognitions, whether they are perceptual or not, are cognitive. Moreover, there
are texts which claim that a cognition consists in the assent to a cognitive impres-
sion (SE M VII 151; VIII 397). Hence, if there are nonperceptual cognitions,
there should be nonperceptual cognitive impressions. Finally, cognitive impres-
sions are supposed to be the criterion of truth. Whatever else this may mean,
it must mean that the truth of cognitive impressions is the guarantee of the truth
of whatever impressions the wise man accepts as true. But if we restrict cogni-
tive impressions to perceptual impressions, it is difficult to see how their truth
would suffice as a basis to guarantee the truth of all other impressions the wise
man will accept as true.
To deal with the last point first, we have to take into account that the Stoics
seem to think that all features of objects—that is, of sensible bodies—are per-
ceptible. Thus they think that we can even learn to see that something or some-
body is beautiful, good, or virtuous (Plut. Comm. not. 1062C; Stoic, rep.
1042E-F; Cic. ND II 145), just as we have to learn to see that something is a
man or a horse (Cic. Acad. II 21). If this at first sight seems strange, we have
to remember that according to the Stoics, qualities of bodily objects like virtue
are bodies themselves that form a mixture with the bodies they are the qualities
of and hence cannot fail to affect our perception of the objects, given that our
perception, at least if trained, is extremely discriminatory; a virtuous body must
look quite different from a vicious body to a trained eye. Thus perception, as
the Stoics understand it, provides a much broader basis than we would assume.
And it will also turn out, when we consider the doctrine of the criterion, that
the Stoics do in fact think that all other impressions can be accepted as true to
CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS 159
the extent that their truth is guaranteed by the truth of perceptual impressions.
Thus Cicero (Acad. II 21-22) points out that at some time in our development
we come to have the (nonperceptual) cognition that if something is a man, it is
a mortal rational animal. But when he explains why this cannot but be true, he
does not say that the corresponding impression is cognitive; instead he says that
it cannot be false because it is due to impressions that cannot be false, namely,
cognitive impressions that are perceptual.
Once we realize that all truths available to us are supposed to be certified by
the truth of perceptual impressions, it seems fairly clear that our problem about
the scope of cognitive impressions is not so much a problem concerning Stoic
doctrine but rather a problem concerning terminology. In fact, it is rather simi-
lar, and materially related, to the problem which we have about the scope of
"clear" or "evident" and which it seems best to solve by distinguishing between
self-evident impressions and impressions whose evidence depends on the evi-
dence of other impressions. Similarly, it seems that the Stoics take the view that
only perceptual impressions are cognitive in their own right. Thus other impres-
sions can be called cognitive only to the extent that they have a cognitive content
which depends on the cognitive content of impressions which are cognitive in
their own right. Thus we may distinguish between self-evident impressions
which are cognitive in a narrow sense, and evident impressions which are cogni-
tive in a wider sense. And if we do so, we can say with Sextus Empiricus that a
cognition consists in the assent to a cognitive impression, and we can also say that
any cognition, whether perceptual or not, involves a cognitive impression, and
nevertheless assume that cognitive impressions, strictly speaking, are perceptual.
Perceptual impressions, in addition to being normal and hence true, have cer-
tain other features that are of interest for our purposes. In the case of perceptual
impressions, the impression represents the object the way it does because the ob-
ject is this way—that is, all representational features of the impression are due
to the object and not to some abnormal condition that would cause the mind to
produce an impression different from the one it would produce normally. Thus
a perceptual impression in no way misrepresents its object. But considering the
purpose for which we have been endowed with cognition, it also stands to reason
that nature has constructed things in such a way that under normal conditions
we not only have an impression which does not misrepresent things but have one
which represents them clearly, that is, affords us a clear answer as to what kinds
of objects we are facing. And under normal conditions we do in fact have a clear
view of an object we are confronted with, and we can tell without difficulty what
its visual features are. Let us call such an impression "clear" or "evident."
The term "evident" has been used, misused, and misunderstood in many
ways. To guard against such misunderstanding of the Stoic position some re-
marks may be in order. The adjective "evident" (enarges) can be used in ordi-
nary Greek to qualify a term "A" to refer to something as being obviously an
160 CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS
thought by an evident thought when I see an octagonal tower under normal con-
ditions, and by a nonevident thought, if I just know from a book that the tower
is octagonal. Propositions only secondarily may be called evident, if there
should be any propositions that cannot be thought at all except by evident
thoughts. What makes a thought or an impression evident is that it is already
part of the representation of the subject of the proposition that the predicate
should be true of it and that the representation of the subject is entirely due to
the subject itself. Thus evidence is not what makes an impression or a proposi-
tion true, but an evident impression cannot but have a true proposition for its
content and hence be true itself.
So far it would seem that for the impression that S is P to be evident, the
representation of S already has to represent S as being P. But it seems that under
normal conditions, when we have a clear view of an object, more than one of
its features is clearly represented. And, in fact, Sextus (M VII 248, 250, 251)
talks as if a cognitive impression captured all the characteristics of the object
in precise manner. Cicero, on the other hand, explains that a cognitive impres-
sion does not pick up all the features of an object, but only all those features
which are appropriate for its kind, visual features in the case of vision, auditory
features in the case of hearing, etc. (Acad. I 42). Since even the weaker claim
is extraordinarily strong, it will be safer to follow Cicero. In this case a cognitive
impression will be evident in that it involves a representation of the object which
clearly represents all the features of the object that are appropriate for the kind
of impression it is; and since it represents all the features of the object in ques-
tion, it will also represent the particular feature which it represents it as having,
that is, the feature attributed to it in the proposition.
Cognitive impressions are not only clear, as opposed to obscure (amudros;
cf. Alex. Aphrod. De an. 71.5ff.), they also are distinct (ektupos; cf. DL VII
46), as opposed to confused (sugkechumenos; cf. SE M VII 171). To see what
their distinctness is supposed to consist in, it will be useful to refer to a doctrine
which is never explicitly attributed to the Stoics but which we do find in Hellen-
istic dogmatic medicine and of which we have some reason to believe that it is
in part of Stoic origin. According to this doctrine, the discriminatory power of
the senses far outruns the ability of the mind to conceptualize the object. Thus,
if under normal conditions we see an object clearly, its features are represented
in the impression in such detail that our concepts do not capture them in all their
detail. Hence, though a normal impression, as a rational impression, has a
propositional content, the way it represents the subject of the proposition cannot
be exhausted by any number of propositions (cf. Gal. De he. aff. VIII 86.12ff.,
87.4, 117.6 339.13, 355; Depraesag. ex puls. IX 366.10K; De sanit. tuenda,
CMC V 4.1, p. 185, 16). Now the Stoics assume that the properties of bodies
themselves are particular (Cic. Acad. II 56). Hence they are called "idibmata,"
that is, properties (SE M VII 248). And they seem to be particular not in the
162 CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS
sense that Socrates' wisdom is Socrates' wisdom rather than Plato's wisdom, but
in the sense that they are qualitatively different individuals. After all, on the
Stoic theory, Plato's wisdom and Socrates' wisdom quite literally are two partic-
ular bodies, which, by the law of the identity of indistinguishables which the
Stoics adhere to, should be internally distinct and not just differ in their relational
properties. A property, given its intimate connection and interdependence with
the whole body it is the property of, cannot but take a certain form reflecting
the idiosyncrasy of the object and hence be peculiar to it. Moreover, both Sextus
and Cicero emphasize the artistic precision with which the features of the object
are represented in a cognitive impression down to their last detail (SE M VII
248, 250-251; cf. "subtiliter impressa" in Cic. Acad. II 34). Hence a cognitive
impression of an object will involve a representation of this object which is so
articulate that the only object which will fit this representation is the very object
the impression has its origin in (cf. SE M VII 252). This feature of cognitive
impressions, that they represent their objects in such detail as to fit only them,
is their distinctness. Since the Stoics assume that clear impressions represent all
the relevant features of an object, cognitive impressions will be highly distinct.
Now normal impressions in general and perceptual impressions in particular
have been characterized in such a way that their normality or perceptuality is
a relational feature of these impressions, a feature which these impressions do
not have by themselves, but only in virtue of the fact that they stand in a certain
relation to the world. Hence it would seem that to determine whether an impres-
sion is cognitive or perceptual it will not suffice just to consider the impression
by itself; we also have to consider its relation to the world.
But the Stoics also seem to assume that cognitive impressions by themselves
differ from all other impressions, that there is some internal characteristic that
serves to mark them off from other kinds of impressions and allows the mind
to discriminate between cognitive and noncognitive impressions without having
to consider their relation to the world (Cic. Acad. I 41). Cognitive impressions
are supposed to differ from noncognitive impressions in the way in which horned
serpents differ from all other kinds of snakes, that is, by some internal differen-
tiating mark (SE M VII252). The reason the Stoics postulate such a mark is easy
to see. All the mind has to go by is its thoughts or impressions. If there is not
a privileged set of impressions which we can rely on to be true, we shall be
reduced to considerations of plausibility and coherence, to inferences to the best
available explanation for our impressions, to decide which of them to accept as
true and which to reject as false or to suspend judgment on. But even in the best
of all circumstances such considerations could not fail to occasionally produce
wrong conclusions, and there is nothing to guard us against the possibility that
they generate conclusions which are so much off the mark that they would dis-
rupt our life radically. But the Stoics want to argue that we are entirely responsi-
ble for our life and for that reason nature has put us into the position to avoid
CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS 163
any false beliefs at all. And the only way to do this, it seems, is to provide us
with impressions which cannot but be true and which we can discriminate.
Most of us will be thoroughly disinclined to believe that there is such a
qualitative difference between our impressions. But one has to keep in mind that
its postulation fits in with Stoic physics without any difficulty. Given that accord-
ing to Stoic physics all states of the world and all parts of a state of the world
are closely interdependent, any variation of the conditions under which an im-
pression arises should affect the impression itself. Thus the assumption that nor-
mal impressions have a distinctive character seems not to be ad hoc but to be
required by Stoic physics anyway. Even if this were not so, it would not be much
of a problem for an omniscient nature to ensure that only impressions which
have a normal history have a certain distinctive character which is the effect of
the kind of history they have. Moreover, we have to take into account that it
is part of the Stoic position that we are so corrupted that we tend to give assent
to and to act on cognitive and noncognitive impressions rather indiscriminately.
Hence our awareness of their difference is not just seriously retarded but also
very distorted. And in any case it does not follow from the fact that we have
such difficulties in telling whether an impression is cognitive or not, that there
is no clear difference between them. Finally it has to be kept in mind that Plato
and Aristotle had already made very strong claims regarding the power of the
knowledge they attributed to the wise man; the man of practical wisdom is al-
ways right in practical matters. The Stoics explicitly refer to this Aristotelian
doctrine (Pap. Here. 1020, col. 1 n., SVFII, p. 41, 25), and they just seem to
try to provide a theory that would explain how the wise man might manage to
invariably get things right. If one gives up this conception of the wise man, one
will, of course, not have the motivation the Stoics had to resort to such a strong
assumption. But this conception of wisdom was too firmly embedded to be given
up lightly in the face of epistemological difficulties.
Let us, then, first consider the definition in its shorter version. To follow the
formulation in DL VII46, an impression is cognitive exactly if (i) it comes about
from what is (apo huparchontos) and (ii) it is imprinted and impressed in exact
accordance with what is. Though this is by no means obvious from the formula-
tion of the second clause by itself, Sextus's comments on this clause in M VII
250-251 show that it is supposed to amount to the requirement that the impres-
sion be clear and distinct. And this interpretation is borne out by the characteri-
zation of noncognitive impressions which in DL follows immediately on the def-
inition of cognitive impressions. According to this definition an impression is
noncognitive if "it either is not from what is or, though it is from what is, is not
in exact accordance with what is; one which is not clear nor distinct." Here the
phrase "one which is not clear nor distinct" looks like a gloss on "is not in exact
accordance with what is," that is, the negative counterpart to the second clause
in the definition of cognitive impressions. And if this is correct, the second
clause of the definition of a cognitive impression should amount to the require-
ment that cognitive impressions be clear and distinct.
It is tempting to think that the first clause amounts to the requirement that a
cognitive impression have its origin in a real object rather than some disturbance
or affection of the mind, that the object the impression presents itself as an im-
pression of be a real object rather than a mere figment of the mind. And this
seems to be the way Sextus interprets the clause, as one can see from his com-
ments on the first part of the second clause in M VII 249. Nevertheless the in-
terpretation of the first clause has been the subject of considerable controversy,
which mainly turns around the force of the term "what is" (huparchori). It has
been pointed out that Cicero in this context again and again renders "huparchon"
by "what is true," that is, understands "what is" in the sense of "what is the case"
(cf. Acad. II42, 112), and that the Stoics do use "to huparchori" for a true propo-
sition. Against this it has to be remembered that there is a great number of exam-
ples in which Sextus talks of impressions that have their origin in something or
other, and that in his examples the something or other in question never is a
proposition but always a real or a fictional object.
Nevertheless, there is some reason to think that Cicero's rendering is not a
mere mistranslation or due to misinterpretation, but rests on the correct assump-
tion that the first clause was not meant to amount to the requirement that the im-
pression should have its origin in a real object, but to the stronger requirement
that it be altogether true. That this assumption may be correct is suggested by
M VII 402ff. There Sextus, following Carneades, argues that there are impres-
sions which have their origin in what is not, but which present themselves as
impressions which have their origin in what is just as much as purportedly cogni-
tive impressions do. And as an example of such an impression Sextus adduces
the case of Heracles who in his madness took his own children to be those of
Eurystheus. Heracles here is explicitly said to have an impression that has its
CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS 165
origin in his own children who are standing in front of him, that is, in a real
external object. And nevertheless this impression, too, is supposed to be an ex-
ample of an impression that has its origin in what is not. The reason for this must
be that the impression is false in that it represents Heracles' children as being
Eurystheus's children. In what sense could such an impression be said to have
its origin in what is not? The answer seems to be that the impression does not
as a whole have its origin in what is; part of it—namely, the part that represents
Heracles' children as being Eurystheus's children—is made up by the mind and
is not due to the object. We saw earlier that it is characteristic of perceptual im-
pressions that all their representational features are due to the object. In this
sense, only true impressions, and more particularly impressions that are true not
by accident, have their origin in what is. If we interpret the first clause in this
way, not only do we not have to assume that Cicero has misunderstood the Stoic
definition, it will also be easy to explain why the third clause of the longer ver-
sion of the definition—which runs, "it is such that it could not come about from
what is not"—is standardly interpreted as meaning that a cognitive impression
has to be such that it could not be false (cf. SE M VII 152, 252; Cic. Acad. II
42, 112). But even a confused and obscure impression may be entirely true and
true not by accident but because all of its representational features are due to
the object that has given rise to it. Hence, to single out cognitive impressions,
the second clause is added. So much about the shorter version of the Stoic defini-
tion of cognitive impressions.
Standardly, though, the Stoics define cognitive impressions by adding a third
clause. A cognitive impression is supposed to satisfy the further requirement that
it be "such that an impression of this character could not come about from what
is not" (SE M VII 248, 252; DL VII 50). This, as we noted above, is taken to
imply that an impression of this character could not be false (cf. SE M VII 152,
252). Given the strong reading of "has its origin in what is," it is easy to see
how the clause would have this implication. The main question concerning the
third clause is the identity of the character referred to. Is this a further charac-
teristic of cognitive impressions which is postulated, but not specified by the de-
finition, or is it the property of satisfying the first two conditions, or is it perhaps
just the property of being clear and distinct? The phrase "of this character" (hold)
is ambiguous in this respect.
Given what we said earlier about cognitive impressions, it seems most plausi-
ble to take this to refer to the distinctive inherent feature that cognitive impres-
sions are supposd to have. And this seems to be confirmed by remarks in Sextus
(M VII 252) and in Cicero (Acad. II 77) which suggest that the Stoics think that
any impression which satisfies the first two conditions will in fact also satisfy
the third condition, but that they add the third clause because this implication
is denied by the Academics, though both agree that cognitive impressions, in or-
der to play the role assigned to them by the Stoics, would have to satisfy the
166 CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS
third condition, too. And this dispute about the third clause turns out to be a dis-
pute about whether cognitive impressions have an internal differentiating feature
(cf. SE M VII252). Hence, it would seem that the third clause refers to this dis-
tinctive feature of cognitive impressions, which is postulated, but not specified.
The Criterion
To get a clearer notion of this feature and of the role it is supposed to play
in cognition, it will be useful to briefly consider in which way cognitive impres-
sions are supposed to constitute the criterion or canon of truth. We have already
seen that they are not a criterion of truth in the sense that they put us in a position
to determine the truth of any proposition whatsoever. There are lots of proposi-
tions that cannot be certified by them. Nor are they the criterion of truth in the
sense that whenever the truth of a proposition is in question, we at least consider
the corresponding impression and try to determine by introspection whether it
has the distinctive mark of a cognitive impression. There are several reasons
why this can hardly be the Stoic view of the matter.
First of all, cognitive impressions will directly guarantee only the truth of
their own prepositional content. And if it is true that cognitive impressions are
perceptual, the only propositions whose truth they can guarantee directly are
propositions that attribute a perceptual feature to a particular object. If they
nevertheless are called the criterion of truth, it is because in an indirect way they
also guarantee the truth of all other propositions that are known to be true by
human beings. And they do this in the following way. They give rise to general
ideas, the so-called common notions which the mind forms naturally on the basis
of cognitive impressions and which in turn allow us to have further cognitive
impressions. And since cognitive impressions do represent things as they are,
the common notions based on them will represent things as they are. Thus if the
common notion of a man represents a man as a biped rational animal, the propo-
sition that man is a biped rational animal will be certified not by an impression
that man is a biped rational animal, which is cognitive in its own right, but by
the common notion, and this in turn will be certified by the cognitive impressions
which give rise to it and which it gives rise to, and these will be cognitive in
their own right (cf. Cic. Acad. II 22). And the truth of propositions certified by
cognitive impressions and of propositions certified by common notions in turn
will guarantee the truth of further propositions derived by deductive inference
from the former propositions. It is for this reason that Chrysippus sometimes can
say that perceptions and common notions constitute the criterion (DL VII 54).
Cognitive impressions, then, are the criterion of truth in the sense that their truth
guarantees the truth of whatever can be known by human beings. It is only
through them that we have any knowledge of what is true and what is not true.
Second, we have to remember that there is no such thing as the impression
that corresponds to a given proposition, and, therefore, when the truth of a prop-
CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS 167
sions such that cognitive impressions play their criterial role not through our
awareness of their distinctive feature, but through the causal effects they have
on our minds in virtue of this feature. The word "to discriminate" is ambiguous.
It is used in cases in which one recognizes things to be of different kind and,
in virtue of this awareness of the difference, treats them differently. But there
are also cases in which somebody reacts differently to things of a different kind
not in virtue of an awareness of their difference and perhaps even without know-
ing that there is such a kind of thing which he systematically reacts to in a dis-
tinctive manner; there is a causal link between a feature of the object and the
behavior of the person, but the awareness of the feature on the part of the person
is not an essential part of the causal chain; and nevertheless such a person can
be said to discriminate or to discern the feature. Many forms of discrimination
in the pejorative sense are of this kind. The suggestion, then, is that the distinc-
tive mark of cognitive impressions is a causal feature in that it makes the mind
react in a distinctive way and that it is in this sense that the mind can discriminate
cognitive and noncognitive impressions. It can also learn to tell whether an im-
pression is cognitive or not, but that is a different ability not at issue at this point
in our argument.
What reason do we have to think that this is the Stoic position? The Stoics
assume that cognitive impressions give rise to common notions. Common no-
tions have their privileged status exactly because the mind forms them naturally
on the basis of cognitive impressions. Nobody, so at least the Stoics think, can
help but end up with the notion of a tree and the notion of a human being and
the notion of the color green if he grows up normally in a normal environment.
This formation of common notions is not something we engage in deliberately
according to certain rules and precepts; if we did, we could make mistakes and
end up with the wrong notions. The Stoics clearly assume that the mind sorts
out cognitive impressions to form concepts on the basis of them without our be-
ing aware of this at all; we just find ourselves having certain concepts that we
did not have to start with. Thus the Stoics also must assume that the mind can
discriminate cognitive impressions without our being aware of it.
We also have to find some explanation of the fact that the mind gives assent
to some impressions but not to others. As soon as the mind has acquired all sorts
of beliefs, it is easy to see how it would accept or reject impressions against the
background of the beliefs it already has. But in the beginning, it would seem,
the mind has no more reason to accept than not to accept any given impression.
This problem would be solved if we assume that cognitive impressions cause the
mind to accept them. And there is some evidence, though by no means decisive,
that this is in fact the Stoic position (cf. SE M VII 405, 407; Cic. Acad. II 38;
Plut. Adv. Colot. 1121E, 1122C). This is perfectly compatible with the further
Stoic claim that we are responsible for our acts of assent, for it is explicitly not
part of the Stoic doctrine of responsibility that we are responsible only for those
CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS 169
things which we could have done otherwise. But it clearly cannot be the Stoic
view that we acquire our first beliefs by scanning our impressions and by being
caused to assent to those which we detect to have the distinctive remark of cogni-
tive impressions. It, rather, must be the case that the Stoics assume that the mind
does this without our being aware of it.
Moreover, the Stoics point out (SE M VII 258; Cic. Acad. II 19) that if we
do not have a clear impression we take the appropriate steps to receive an evi-
dent impression, in case the subject is of any importance to us; that is, not having
a clear impression naturally makes us consider the matter further till we have
a clear impression. The suggestion does not seem to be that we recognize that
our impression is confused and obscure and hence decide to get a clearer one,
but, rather, that there is a causal mechanism that sets us going and would natu-
rally make us stop once we had a clear impression. For these reasons, then, it
seems that the differentiating mark of cognitive impressions is a causal feature
rather than a phenomenological character to be detected by introspection.
But this is not to say that we cannot be aware of the fact that an impression
is cognitive or noncognitive, that we cannot learn to tell whether an impression
is clear and distinct or obscure and confused. In fact, the Stoic view seems to
be that this is a matter of practice and that in principle one can get so good at
it that one will never take a noncognitive impression to be cognitive. But to learn
this is not to acquire a mysterious sixth sense which, unlike the other senses,
is not subject to the possibility of abnormal conditions and hence unfailingly
gives us notice of an equally mysterious feature of cognitive impressions. Judg-
ments regarding the evidence of an impression are notoriously as fallible as any
other judgments, and there is no reason to saddle the Stoics with the assumption
that this is not so. But we can get better and better at seeing how variations in
the conditions under which our impressions arise, especially variations in our
mental state and the beliefs we have, do affect our impression.
to test and expose unfounded claims to expertise. And this is precisely what the
skeptics did.
Now there are some crucial features of Socratic dialectic which it is worth-
while to recall if we want to understand the skeptical position. The Socratic
method allows one to test expertise in a subject without being oneself an expert
in this subject—in fact, without committing oneself to or even having any views
on the subject. All one has to do is to show that the person who claims expertise
or makes statements with the air of authority involves himself in contradictions
concerning the very subject he claims to be an expert in or that he is unable to
discard a thesis which is the contradictory of a thesis he has put forth with the
air of expertise. For if he were an expert, he should be able to defend his position
against theses to the contrary, and he certainly should not involve himself in con-
tradictions. Hence such dialectical arguments are not meant to establish the truth
or falsehood of some thesis. All they are meant to show is that the opponent is
no authority on the matters in question.
It is important to keep this in mind, because otherwise one might be misled
into thinking that the skeptics themselves accept either the premises or the con-
clusions of their arguments. Thus one might think that the ancient Academic
skeptic fits the prevailing modern notion of what a skeptic is, in that he believes
that all that is given to us are our impressions and that he tries to convince us
that since this is so, there is no way in which we ever can have certain knowledge
of what the world that gives rise to these impressions really is like. The skeptic
may argue this way, but if he does so, it is just another ad hominem argument
against those who believe that all that is given to us immediately are our impres-
sions. There is no reason why the skeptic himself should feel committed to this
very dogmatic, speculative, unskeptical assumption and the dualism between the
mental and the physical, the subject and the object which tends to go with it.
Thus it is not surprising that in other contexts the skeptic is quite willing to chal-
lenge the dogma of the impression as a given (Gal. De diff. puts. VIII710, 18ff.
K.; Depraenot. XIV 628, 14ff.). He is quite willing to say that some things evi-
dently appear to be the case, as we ordinarily do, but he does not think that this
commits him to the view that there are such entities as impressions, assents, and
evidence. Nor are the skeptics committed to the conclusions of their argu-
ments—for example, the conclusion that there is no knowledge or the conclusion
that nothing can be known, or the conclusion that the wise man will suspend
judgment on all questions. He is not even committed to the view that the conclu-
sions of his arguments follow from their premises. For, as he will emphasize,
he does not subscribe to the canons of logic worked out by his opponents, either
(cf. Cic. Acad. II 91ff.). He is just prepared, for the sake of argument, to meet
whatever standards of logic are met or required by his opponents. For otherwise
his arguments will not have the desired effect on them.
172 CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS
What is the envisaged effect of such arguments? Reporting his experience the
skeptic might say that they tend to leave one with the impression that the Stoics
have not successfully argued their case concerning the nature and the attainabil-
ity of knowledge. They may also tend to leave one with the impression that it
is doubtful whether such a case can be made at all. More generally, it will appear
doubtful whether the case for any revisionist conception of knowledge can be
made; we might just have to accept the fact that all that is available to us is the
kind of everyday knowledge the vulgar have. Even more generally, it may ap-
pear doubtful whether the case for any position can be made. On the other hand,
it would not be desirable, from the skeptic's point of view, if one was left with
the impression that the positions attacked by him are false, or that, even if they
are true, there is no way to definitively establish them as true. This would lead
to a dogmatic pseudoskepticism quite alien to true Academic or Pyrrhonean
skepticism (cf. SE PHI 200, 226, 236; Gal. De subf. emp. 84, 22 D.).
Given the central position of the doctrine of cognitive impressions in Stoic
epistemology, it is not surprising that the skeptics focused their attack on this
doctrine. And here the main point at issue was whether cognitive impressions
differ qualitatively from all other impressions. This, as we saw, is an assumption
so central to the Stoic position that Zeno already added it to his definition of cog-
nitive impressions. The skeptics were quite willing, at least for the sake of argu-
ment, to accept the first part of the definition and to grant that there may be im-
pressions that have their origin in what is and that represent their object faith-
fully and clearly (SE M VII402). But they took issue with the added assumption
that such an impression, just given its internal characteristics, could have no
other origin than the object it faithfully represented, that there could not be an im-
pression exactly like it which was nevertheless false. Already Arcesilaus attacked
the further assumption (Cic. Acad. II77; SE M VII154), Carneades pursued the
same line of attack (SE M VII 164, 402ff.), and it was to remain the main point
of contention throughout the debate (Cic. Acad. II 33, 78; SE M VII 252).
We have only a rather general idea of the form this debate took, since its de-
tails have not been studied with the care they deserve. Apparently, the skeptics
adopted the strategy of arguing for the more general thesis that for any true im-
pression there could be another impression exactly like it which is false (Cic.
Acad. II 40, 41, 42; 44, 84, 90; SE M VII 154, 164, 252, 402, 415, 428), or
at least one which differs so minimally from the true one that we cannot distin-
guish between it and the true one and which, nevertheless, is false (Cic. Acad.
II 40, 85). More particularly, they seem to have argued the matter for the vari-
ous kinds of true impressions, kind by kind (Cic. Acad. II 42). In the case of
cognitive impressions, they did so in at least two ways. To start with, they tried
to show that there are impressions which, as far as their representational features
are concerned, differ in no way, or at least in no discriminable way, from cogni-
tive impressions, though they themselves are not true. But then they also tried
CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS 173
to show that there are impressions which have all the supposed characteristics
of cognitive impressions—which, for example, are vivid or striking, or which
at least could not be distinguished from a cognitive impression by the person
who has the impression at the time he has them, and which nevertheless are false
(SE M VII 408).
Let us first turn to the impressions that are supposed to be exactly like, or
at least indistinguishable from, cognitive impressions in the way in which they
represent their object (cf. Cic. Acad. II 84ff.; SE M VII 408ff.). Suppose that
Socrates is standing in full view in front of one; in this case one may have the
cognitive impression that this is pale or that this is a man or even that this is
Socrates, if one has learned to grasp his Socraticity and has a corresponding idea
of Socrates. Now also suppose that Socrates has a twin brother, whom we do
not know anything about, but who is exactly like Socrates, or who at least looks
exactly like Socrates. In this case, the skeptic rightly claims, the impression one
would have of Socrates' twin brother under identical normal conditions would
be exactly like the cognitive impression one has of Socrates. Hence, he goes on
to argue, it is not the case, as the Stoics claim, that an impression which has
all the characteristics of a cognitive impression can have its origin only in the
object which gives rise to it and that there could not be another impression ex-
actly like it which does not have its origin in this object. Moreover, suppose (i)
that we first see Socrates and have the cognitive impression that this is Socrates
and (ii) that then Socrates disappears and his twin brother takes his place. We
would have an impression exactly like our first impression and on the basis of
it judge again that this is Socrates. But this impression and the corresponding
judgment would be false.
The Stoic answer to this relies on the assumption that no two objects are ex-
actly alike (cf. Cic. Acad. II 85). Thus Socrates and his twin brother will differ
from each other at least minimally. Hence, a cognitive impression of Socrates,
being by definition distinct, could not be exactly like an impression that had its
origin in his twin brother. If the impression one received of Socrates were ex-
actly like the one which one received of his twin brother, both impressions
would be confused and hence not cognitive. But the impressions we receive of
Socrates and his twin brother do not need to be indistinguishable and hence con-
fused. For, the Stoics assume, the two brothers do differ from each other at least
minimally, and by sufficient training we can learn to distinguish perceptually any
two perceptible objects (cf. Cic. Acad. II 20; 56; 57; 86). Thus we can learn
to distinguish Socrates and his twin brother however much they may look alike,
and only if we have learned this can we have the cognitive impression that this
is Socrates. Hence, it cannot happen that we first have a cognitive impression
of Socrates and then a false impression exactly like it that this (Socrates' twin
brother) is Socrates.
The crucial issue here is the metaphysical principle of the internal distinctness
174 CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS
do not have an effect on the internal character of the impressions they produce;
in fact, often it seems obvious enough that an abnormal state of mind systemati-
cally changes the character of our impressions. And, for reasons indicated
above, Stoic physics would seem to require that the internal character of impres-
sions implies a certain state of mind. Second, it needs to be noticed that even
if it were the case that in certain abnormal states a person is not in a position
to tell whether his impressions are cognitive or not, because the noncognitive
ones seem to him to have all the features of cognitive ones, this would not show
that he does not have cognitive and noncognitive impressions which differ from
each other qualitatively and which his mind discriminates accordingly. And cor-
respondingly we do not find the Stoics arguing that even dreamers and madmen
can tell that their dreams and hallucinations are noncognitive, but that even
dreamers and madmen react differently to cognitive and noncognitive impres-
sions (cf. SE M VII247). And this seems true enough, if we consider the matter
in general. The Stoics are, of course, committed to the view that the mind in
each case manages to discriminate between cognitive and noncognitive impres-
sions, but their theory also seems to allow them to explain apparent counterex-
amples. It is exactly a sign of a severely abnormal state of mind, if the mind
treats cognitive and noncognitive impressions almost indiscriminately so that in
particular cases there may seem to be no difference in observable behavior.
Thus, it seems that the skeptics fail to show that cognitive and noncognitive
impressions do not differ from each other qualitatively and that, hence, the mind
cannot discriminate between them on the basis of their inherent difference. They
even fail to show that it is impossible to tell absolutely reliably whether one's
impression is cognitive or not. What they perhaps do show is that we, in our
present state, cannot invariably tell whether an impression is cognitive or not.
But then the Stoics would be the last to deny that.
Conclusion
Academic skepticism is not characterized by a certain philosophical position, by
a set of philosophical views Academics are expected to subscribe to, but by a
certain dialectical practice and the impression the purusit of this dialectical prac-
tice left on them. Now it seems that earlier Academic skeptics like Arcesilaus
and Carneades were left with the impression that they had no reason to accept
philosophical beliefs. Whatever reasons they may have had when they started
out had been neutralized by arguments to the contrary. Later Academic skeptics,
though, starting with Metrodorus and Philo, seem to have had the impression
that however much one argued on both sides of any philosophical or theoretical
question, one still may find in the end that, as a matter of fact, one is still inclined
toward one side of the matter, that there is no reason to think that this is just
due to the fact that one is lacking in dialectical skill or has not considered the
176 CLEAR AND DISTINCT IMPRESSIONS
matter carefully enough, and that there is no reason not to report which view
one feels inclined to, at least as long as one is among one's peers and there is
no danger that one's report is mistaken for an authoritative statement, as it might
be, for example, by young students. As a result many Academic skeptics came
to articulate quite elaborate philosophical beliefs. And given the dominance of
Stoicism and the syncretism of the time, these often hardly differed from the
views of their Stoic rivals. And since the Stoics did not claim knowledge for
their views either, the two positions became more and more difficult to distin-
guish, as soon as one left the field of epistemology. But given that both sides
now tended to have more or less the same beliefs on the basis of the same con-
siderations anyway, the epistemological debate must have started to look some-
what academic and futile, especially since it seemed to have ended in a deadlock.
Galen (De dogm. Plat: et Hipp. 796, 8ff. M) could even claim the following:
the younger Academics say that everything should be judged by means of plausi-
ble, tested, incontrovertible impressions (the Carneadean "criterion"), Chrysip-
pus maintains that matters should be judged by cognitive impressions, and com-
mon sense tells us that it is all a matter of perception and evident thought; but
their disagreement is only verbal: if one considers the matter more closely, Ga-
len says, one will see that they all advocate the same epistemic practice.
Thus it is not surprising that some skeptics thought that the Academy had be-
come unfaithful to its skeptical tradition and that they tried to revive the radical
skepticism of the early Academics, but now under the name of "Pyrrhonism" to
distinguish themselves from their Academic contemporaries. But by this time,
it seems, the Stoics were no longer inclined to engage in a real debate on the
matter and to refine their position accordingly. And thus orthodox Stoicism itself
was soon a matter of the past, whose views only lived on in the more or less
distorted form in which they were assimilated into other systems. And in this
distorted form the Stoics' views on cognitive impressions and their clarity and
distinctness, in fact the whole Stoic epistemology, have exercised, through sur-
viving Greek and Latin authors like Cicero and Sextus Empiricus, an enormous
influence well into modern times.