Henry Chadwick Boethius The Consolations of Music
Henry Chadwick Boethius The Consolations of Music
Henry Chadwick Boethius The Consolations of Music
Boethius
The Consolations of Music, Logic, Theology, and Philosophy
Henry Chadwick
Preface
HILARIAE
FILIAE DILECTISSIMAE
Born fifteen hundred years ago (within a reasonable approximation), Boethius wrote one of the dazzling
masterpieces of European literature. But he has been seldom studied as a whole, and has been seen more through
the eyes of those whom he influenced than in relation to the writers whom he had read and who influenced him.
The purpose of this book is to see the man in the setting of his own turbulent and tormented age, not to trace his
large posterity in thought and literature. Moreover, the latter concern predominates in the collection of studies on
Boethius by various authors, including myself, edited by Dr Margaret Gibson (Blackwell, 1981). Much is also said
of that in the studies of Boethius by Pierre Courcelle (1967). Modern reappraisal of Boethius, especially since the
work of Klingner (1921) and Courcelle (1948), has concentrated on his debt to the late Platonists of Athens and
especially of Alexandria. The present book continues that line, and adds fresh Neoplatonist evidence for the
interpretation of the five tractates on Christian theology. On the other side, I have also found more affinity with
Augustine than has been generally recognized, and therefore conclude with a portrait of Boethius simultaneously
more deeply Neoplatonic and more deeply Augustinian than has been acknowledged. I have also tried to integrate
the various constituent elements in his intellectual achievement. The substructure of the Consolation of Philosophy
is only clear when one has also seen something of his arithmetic, music, and logic, the last being the grand
obsession of his mind. It is then possible to make a fresh attack on the question of his religious allegiance, debated
since the tenth century when Bovo of Corvey asked how the evidently
Contents
Abbreviations ix
Chronological Table x
Introduction xi
I
Romans and Goths 1
1
Culture and the Public Service
6
Symmachus
16
The Neoplatonic Schools
22
Out of the Ivory Tower: John the Deacon
29
The Hard Road to Church Unity: the Acacian and Laurentian Schisms
46
Master of the Offices
56
The Collapse of Toleration
66
Boethius' Sacrifice
II
Liberal Arts in the Collapse of Culture 69
71
Arithmetic
78
Music
84
Boethius' Treatise on Music and its Sources
102
Geometry and Astronomy
III
Logic 108
108
Part of Philosophy or a Tool of all Philosohy?
111
Logic and Rhetoric
120
Porphyry
127
Neoplatonists after Porphyry: Iamblichus, Syrianus, Proclus, Ammonius
131
Boethius' commentaries on the Isagoge
133
Translator of Aristotle
141
The Ten Categories
152
On Interpretation
157
Future Contingents
163
The Monographs on Logic
166
Propositional Logic and the Hypothetical Syllogism
IV
Christian Theology and the Philosophers 174
175
Faith and History; De Fide Catholica
180
The Person of Christ
185
The Scythian Monks
190
Nature and Person
203
Absolute and Relative Goodness
211
God the Trinity
V
Evil, Freedom, and Providence 223
225
The Lady Philosophy
228
From Stoic Moralism to Platonic Transcendence
234
O Qui Perpetua
235
Degrees of Perfection: the Quest for the One
237
Reminiscence: Natural Theology and the Bible
239
The Problem of Evil
242
Providence and Fate
244
Divine Foreknowledge and Free Will
247
The Religion of Boethius
Preservation and Transmission 254
Editions 258
Bibliography 261
Notes 285
Index 307
Abbreviations
Chronological Table
SECULAR RULERS
East Roman emperors Barbarian kings of Italy
Marcian 450-7
Leo I 457-74
Leo II 474 Odovacar 476-93
Zeno (first time) 474-5
Basiliscus 475-6
Zeno (second time) 476-91 Theoderic 493-526
Anastasius I 491-518
Justin I 518-27
Justinian 527-65 Athnalaric 526-34
(Amalasuintha regent 526-35)
BISHOPS
Rome Constantinople Alexandria
Leo I 440-61 Flavian 446-9 Cyril 412-44
Hilarus 461-8 Anatolius 449-58 Dioscorus 444-51 (d. 454)
Gennadius I 458-
Simplicius 468-83 71 Proterius 451-7
Felix III 483-92 Acacius 472-89
Timothy Aelurus (first) 457-60 (Monophysite)
Gelasius I 492-6 Fravitas 489-90
Timothy Salofaciolus (first) 460-75
(Chalcedonian)
Euphemius 490-6
Anastasius II 496-8 (exiled)
Timothy Aelurus (second) 475-7
Symmachus 498- Macedonius II Peter Mongos (first) 477 31 July-4 Sept. 477
514 496-511 (Monophysite)
(Laurentius 498, (exiled)
501-6)
Hormisdas 514-23 Timothy I 511-18
Timothy Salofaciolus (second) 477-82
John I 523-6
John II the John Talaia June-Dec. 482 (Chalcedonian)
Cappadocian 518-
20
Felix IV 526-30 Epiphanius 520-35
Peter Mongos (second) 482-9
Boniface II 530-2 Thereafter a Monophysite succession at
(Dioscorus 22 Alexandria; no Chalcedonian until 537.
Sept.-14 Oct. 530)
PHILOSOPHERS
Ptolemy (Claudius Ptolemaeus) fl. AD 127-48
Nicomachus of Gerasa fl. c.150
Apuleius (Carthage) 123-c.180
Alexander of Aphrodisias (Athens) fl. c.200
Plotinus (Rome) 205-70
Porphyry of Tyre (Rome, Sicily) c.250-c.305
Iamblichus (Syria) c.250-c.325
Marius Victorinus (Rome) c.285-c.370
Syrianus (Athens) d. 437
Hierocles (Alexandria and Constantinople) fl. c.440-70
Proclus (Athens) 412-85
Ammonius son of Hermias (Alexandria) c.436-517 (or 445-526)
Martianus Capella (Carthage) fl. c.470 (?)
Damascius (Athens) fl. c.490-c.537-38
Simplicius (Alexandria, Athens) fl. 515-45 or later
Philoponus (Alexandria), Christian pupil of Ammonius c.490-c.570
Elias fl. c.550-c.600
Introduction
`LAST of the Romans, first of the scholastics': the tag echoes a famous judgement on Boethius by the humanist
Lorenzo Valla in the fifteenth century. Valla saw in Boethius a man whose diction and philosophy were touched by
barbarisms but nevertheless allowed him a claim to be the last classical writer in the Latin tongue. Renaissance
humanism mixed its admiration for Boethius with the expression of occasional misgivings. Did his concept of
education allow a sufficient place to literary values? Granted that he adorned the Consolation of Philosophy with a
series of poems including some of real distinction, yet his prose is another matter; and he makes it clear that for
him philosophy and theology are altogether more serious than the pleasures of the Muses who, in Platonic fashion,
receive discourteous treatment in his pages. Renaissance men could also come to feel constricted by Boethius'
writings on arithmetic, music, and dialectic which dominated the medieval schools. His studies in dialectic had in
fact long been the object of mingled admiration and dislike, as one may see in John of Salisbury's Metalogicon of
1159, itself a classic of the twelfth-century renaissance. It was not, of course, a new thing in the fifteenth century
that literary humanists should feel irritated by rigorous training in dialectic which could end by producing tiresome
young nit-pickers who made the subject seem trivial.
As an educator Boethius consistently believes practice to be far less important than theory. His educational ideal is
intended to produce men of understanding rather than of practical action and technique. The disciplines of moral
philosophy, politics, and economics were held in respect and no doubt counted for much in public and political
life; but the purer mental skills for Boethius, as for the Platonic schools of his time, lie in the natural sciences,
mathematics, and metaphysics. And by the study of the natural sciences Boethius really meant the philosophical
questions discussed in Aristotle's Physics (e.g. the nature of change, causation and necessity, the infinite, the
definition of place and of time, the Prime Mover) or De caelo, on the heavenly bodies, or De generatione et
corrup-
I
Romans and Goths
Symmachus
Symmachus' eminence in Italian society as an arbiter of literary excellence is illustrated by the dedication to him of
three works on Latin rhetoric by Priscian,21 resident at Constantinople, who hoped to attract Symmachus'
patronage on a visit that the senator paid to Byzantium about 500, probably as Theoderic's ambassador to the
Byzantine court. In the West the ambitious, place-hunting Ennodius who, like Boethius, owed his upbringing and
education to rich family friends, also dedicated to Symmachus a short tract written about 511 advising two aspiring
young men, Ambrosius and Beatus, how to get on in society.22 The tract ends with a request in verse to further
Ennodius' own career. In alternating prose and verse Ennodius counsels the youths to love God and their
neighbour, to study modesty, chastity, faith, grammar, and above all rhetoric. So they should follow the eloquence
of the living masters in the present senate. And Ennodius names Faustus Niger (consul 490), his son Avienus (cos.
502) now at Ravenna; Festus (cos. 472) and Symmachus (cos. 485) at Rome; or Probinus (cos. 489) and his son
Cethegus (cos. 504), the brilliant young Boethius (cos. 510), Agapitus (cos. 517) and Probus (cos. 525). Or if they
seek feminine exemplars, there is Barbara the very flower of the Roman spirit, or Stephania (Faustus' sister,
The Hard Road to Church Unity: the Acacian and Laurentian Schisms 44
Since the Council of Chalcedon (451) ecclesiastical dissension had come to have social and political consequences
for
Boethius' Sacrifice
A question that the historian is left asking at the end of the narrative is how far Justinian foresaw the outcome, so
greatly
II
Liberal Arts in the Collapse of Culture
Aristotle observes in the Categories that if something is to be known, it must be knowable; conversely something
can be knowable without anyone actually knowing it, either because it has not yet been discovered (such as the
method for squaring the circle) or because it has sadly been forgotten and then by much effort needs to be
rediscovered. This last observation fascinated Boethius, and his commentary on this passage treats it as a word for
his own times. It is his great fear that amid the general collapse of higher studies in his time, the knowledge
acquired by the philosophers and scientists of classical Greece may simply be obliterated by a failure in
transmission. 1 Books may lie in libraries but, if they are to survive for more than a generation, they need users
who understand and value their contents or they will rapidly suffer from neglect, and the valuable space they
occupy will be applied to other purposes. `It is one thing to have reason, another to use it', he writes. `To abandon
the stretching of one's mind's power is to lose it.' Or, with a sharper point, `Men who have long been idle in using
their minds adopt positions from which they never move, and learn nothing until their old age.'2
The Latin world possessed good guides in grammar and in rhetoric. In the middle of the fourth century Jerome
himself had been among those who sat at the feet of the famous grammarian Donatus whose works have been
preserved. Donatus seemed to Boethius a scholar and teacher fit to be compared with the great Alexandrian scholar
Aristarchus in the Greek world. Moreover, his own contemporary Priscian, who taught a more advanced grammar
than that of Donatus, was busy teaching Latin at Constantinople, dedicating works on style to Boethius' father-in-
law, and composing treatises on Latin grammar which became indispensable in medieval schoolrooms. In rhetoric
there was the incomparable model of Cicero, whose treatises on rhetoric explained the tricks of the
Arithmetic
Nicomachus of Gerasa (Jerash in northern Jordan, a few miles south-east of the Sea of Galilee) lived in the middle
of the second century AD and took Pythagoras as his guide to life. He wrote a tract on the Pythagorean order of
daily living, later used by Porphyry and especially by Iamblichus. 3 In this tract Pythagoras' life and wonder-
working career are held up as an example of moral and personal discipline; for Pythagoras suffered
misunderstanding and attack, descended to the underworld and returned, and called an intimate group of disciples
to observe ritual instructions, to heed his gnomic maxims, and to begin and end each day with special chants and
prayers of self-examination.
Nicomachus' Introduction to Arithmetic achieved the status of being a standard textbook in the Neoplatonic schools
of Athens and Alexandria. The work survives in its original Greek. First printed at Paris, 1538, it was last edited by
Hoche in the Teubner series (1866), and has received an English translation and full commentary by M.L. D'Ooge,
F.E. Robbins and L.C. Karpinski (1926 repr. 1972). It received commentaries, also extant, from Iamblichus in the
fourth century, from Asclepius of Tralles, and from Philoponus in the
Music
The Pythagoreans had a high reputation for their researches in number-theory and music.11 They first discovered
that the relative pitch of musical sounds depends on the lengths of
The group of numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, whose sum is 10, give a perfect triangle (according to the modern
algebraic formula for triangular numbers 1/2n(n+1)).
For Pythagoreanism it is no mere social convention or the fact that we count on our fingers that leads all people to
divide
The figures for the internal intervals are computed first for the diatonic genus by calculating the two descending
whole tones in 9:8 proportion. Nine-eighths of 2304 is 2592, and
From Hypate (A) to Paramese (H) and from Mese (G) to Nete hyperboleon (O) are octaves, Boethius notes. He
carelessly
III
Logic
Porphyry
Aristotle's logic was notorious in antiquity for its difficulty to
Translator of Aristotle 45
Boethius approached both Plato and Aristotle with deep rever-
That is to say, four links are possible: substance (which is of but not in a subject) and accident (in but not of a
subject) can either be universal or be individual and particular.
Porphyry's Question and Answer commentary remarks that Aristotle's division is `chiastic' (78, 36) which suggests
that a diagram could originally have been attached to this text to illustrate the point. The diagram is a regular part
of the school convention. It reappears in Philoponus' commentary on the Categories (28, 25). A development of a
similar diagrammatic scheme was developed to become the Pons Asinorum of the medieval logicians.
With chapter 5 Aristotle reaches the concept of substance: `primary' substance for individuals, `secondary'
substance when referring to the species and genera which contain the individuals. For Aristotle the particular is
prior to the universal. We infer the species man and the genus animal only from our knowledge of those particular
instances that share
On Interpretation
The most extended single work from Boethius' pen is his double exposition of Aristotle's difficult treatise `On
Interpretation', which the early editors of the Peripatetic school placed second in the Organon after the Categories.
Aristotle's study of the logic of the simple proposition and of modal sentences containing the words `necessary' and
`possible' was famous in antiquity and later for causing headaches in its interpreters. The commentaries by Boethius
and Ammonius are the principal ancient survivors of a rich exegetical mine. The commentaries by Stephanus (CAG
XVIII, 3) and Proba (extant only in Syriac) depend on Ammonius and have no independent value. A little light,
however, to illuminate Boethius' relation to his sources can occasionally be derived from the tenth-century
commentary and treatise by the Arab philosopher of Baghdad, Al-Farabi. His work is now translated into English
by F.W. Zimmermann (1981).
About AD 200 Alexander of Aphrodisias felt the impulse to write a commentary on the problematic work in
consequence, he says (Boethius ii, 3), of the bewildering disagreements of the exegetes. Porphyry (Boethius ii, 293,
27) declares that in his
The purpose of the diagram is to illustrate where contradictions lie. A particular negation is contradictory of a
universal affirmation, a universal negative of a particular affirmative.
Concerning the indefinite proposition `A man is (or is not) white', where there is no quantifier, Boethius reports
Alexander's opinion that since it is reducible either to a particular or to a universal, it can carry opposite meanings.
But he then prefers Porphyry's subtle analysis of negative indefinite propositions which include the contrary of the
affirmation which they deny, e.g. `a man is not white' may mean `a man is black' (Boethius ii, 159). Boethius
concludes that the indefinite has the force of the particular (ii, 172 cf. Syll. Cat. i, 802D). He rejects Syrianus'
opinion, which he supported by texts from both Plato and Aristotle, that an indefinite negative has the
Future Contingents
The famous ninth chapter of Aristotle, De interpretatione, provokes from Boethius the observation that it touches
on matters too deep for a textbook of mere logic. Many questions in it converge with the treatment of possibility in
the Prior Analytics. 62
Events of the past or present cannot be reversed and so are `necessary'. There are also constants about the physical
world which are `necessary' because they are always the case, even if we cannot always know about them, as, for
example, whether the number of the stars is even or odd; they must be one or the other, but which we cannot
know. (Boethius confuses `they must be either one or the other' with `whichever they are is subject to necessity'.)
There are other constants such as the rising and setting of the sun, the property of fire to give heat as long as it
burns, the indelible rationality of humanity. Other things are `contingent'; that is, they need not necessarily be as
they are but could be otherwise. `Contingent' Boethius explains as meaning that the likelihood of a thing being one
thing rather than another is equal, and here wants to distinguish it from what is possible but very unusual and from
what is usual but not invariable, e.g. if a man's hair fails to whiten in
But the Stoics correctly regarded a proposition as possible if and only if its negation is non-necessary, and
impossible if and only if its negation is necessary. The scheme is therefore a square of opposition:
IV
Christian Theology and the Philosophers
Five tractates of varying length dealing with questions of theology are transmitted by the manuscripts, often in
association with the Consolation of Philosophy, but in many cases independently. The first three and fifth of these
pieces attempt tersely to disentangle some of the central logical problems besetting the traditional language of the
Latin churches. These tractates attracted great interest from medieval commentators from the ninth century
onwards, culminating in masterful discussions of the first and third from the pen of St. Thomas Aquinas. Although
the third contains nothing specifically Christian, the remainder discuss fundamental questions of Church
Dogmaticsthe Trinity and the Person of Christand can only have been written by a Christian thinker with a special
interest in logical questions. At one time it was customary to contrast the Christian opuscula with the pagan
Consolation, and to propose the hypothesis of two different authors, perhaps of the same name. In the tenth century
Bovo of Corvey considered this possibility, but rightly rejected it on stylistic grounds. In the modern period the
hypothesis was favoured in the eighteenth and especially the nineteenth centuries, going back to Gottfried Arnold's
highly prejudiced `Impartial Church History to the Year 1688' (1700), I, vi, 3, 7. The most elaborate statement
advocating this hypothesis was advanced by Nitzsch in 1860, but has long been seen to rest on radical
misunderstandings. Today it is accepted by all scholars who have given attention to the subject that the careful
Neoplatonic logician who, in the first three and fifth tractates, seeks to unravel logical tangles in the usage of the
Church, is none other than the author of the Consolation and of the commentaries on Aristotle, with which they
manifest numerous parallels in thought and diction. It has come to be acknowledged, and will be made clear
beyond a peradventure in the present chapter, that the tractates, other than the fourth,
V
Evil, Freedom, and Providence
Since the Renaissance, and especially since the scientific revolution of the seventeenth century altered our
understanding of the nature and structure of our environment, Boethius has come to seem a rather lonely and
forgotten foreigner in a world grown strange. Yet something of that isolation belongs to him even during his
lifetime, and never more so than in the near dereliction of the imprisonment during which he wrote the Consolation
of Philosophy. 1 By common consent this remains one of the high masterpieces of European literature, translated
since early mediaeval times into many languages; a work whose English translators alone include King Alfred,
Geoffrey Chaucer, and Queen Elizabeth I; a dominant force (with Thomas Aquinas) in the making of Dante's mind.
The Consolation is the work of a refined humanist scholar with a richly stocked memory, delighting in lyrical
poetry and elegant prose, fascinated by logical problems almost to the point of obsession. In Theoderic's prison at
Pavia he knew that his time was limited (iv, 6, 5), but he evidently had more than sufficient leisure to produce
polished composition and a sophisticated structure. The work has a Virgilian quality in being almost a mosaic of
subtle literary allusions. Joachim Gruber's commentary (1978) marks a signal advance in the identification of his
literary echoes, but also makes it clear that he is not transcribing sources. This is not a man composing with a
library of books open before him, but a very well-read mind which can recall a phrase from here or from there at
will. His Latin is densely packed with concentrated argument; and the argument is carried on from the prose
sections into the poems which he inserts, he says (iv, 6, 57), with the intention of lightening the reader's task with a
difficult subject. The poems normally have subtle links with the prose sections that precede or follow them.
The method of mixing prose and verse had been practised by
O Qui Perpetua
In the 38 hexameters of O qui perpetua Boethius fashioned an exquisite poem of petition to the Creator. It is a
nodal point in the work as a whole, and Boethius knew it. An acute observation in the recent commentary by
Joachim Gruber (1978) has noted that the various metres of the poems in the Consolation are grouped in an
ordered and symmetrical structure round O qui perpetua which occupies a central position. This shows, in passing,
that there is no good reason to embrace speculations that something is likely to have been lost at the end of the last
book.
Boethius' ecstatic hymn is reminiscent of the Neoplatonic hymns on cosmic theology characteristic of Synesius and
Proclus. The ideas of the hymn are derived both from Plato and from Proclus' commentary. This was established by
Klingner (1921). The Creator, himself at rest, is cause of motion to everything (Proclus, In Tim. i, 396, 24 f., a
theme going back to Aristotle's Metaphysics). Boethius will repeat this in prose at iii, 12, 37. God is moved to
create by his own goodness (Tim. 29e), not by any external cause. In creating he realized a heavenly pattern,
forming the cosmos in beauty and perfection (30b). Taking a theme also expounded in his Institutio musica (i, 2)
Boethius says that God binds the world's elements together on mathematical principles, `by numbers' (Tim. 31c
`analogia', or proportion). Thus he keeps the equilibrium of cold and hot, dry and wet (31bc). So also he binds the
worldsoul in its harmonious parts (per consona membra) and gives it a threefold structure (35ab; 37a), set in the
middle of the cosmos (36e) to move all things (as Plato's Laws 896e, Phaedrus 245c). Proclus (In Tim. ii, 197, 16)
says that the Creator `divides the Soul among the various parts, fits together the diverse elements and makes them
consonant with one another'.
This divided Soul is split into two, each part to move in a circle (Tim. 36bc) so as to return upon itselfa theme very
Editions
The most accessible edition of the collected writings of Boethius is in J.P. Migne's Patrologia Latina 63-4 (1847
and later reprints). Unfortunately it is not a good edition, but for a substantial proportion of the principal works
better editions now exist. For the Consolatio Migne reprinted the 1679 edition of Petrus Callyus; for the opuscula
sacra Vallinus' good edition (Leiden, 1656, 1671) which first printed De fide catholica, with a note to express
unhesitating confidence in its authenticity on ground of style and content; for the remainder the text of Henricus
Loritus Glareanus (Basel, 1546 and 1570), who had in turn reproduced the Dialectica from the edition of Julianus
Martianus Rota (Venice, 1546) a Venetian humanist who also edited some Aristotle and Galen. In addition Migne
reprinted two pieces, De rhetorica cognatione and Locorum rhetoricorum distinctio, which had been edited by
Cardinal Angelo Mai (Class. Auct. iii, 315) as hitherto unpublished works by Boethius; but they are excerpts from
De differentiis topicis. The treatise De definitionibus was shown by H. Usener (Anecdoton Holderi, 1877) to belong
to Marius Victorinus. The tract De unitate et uno is a twelfth-century piece by Dominic Gonzalez (Gundissalinus).
De disciplina scholarium, recently re-edited by O. Weijers (Leiden, 1976), is by an admirer of Boethius in early
thirteenth-century Paris or Oxford.
Except for Vallinus, who published a good text of Consolatio and Opuscula with excellent notes, the sixteenth-
and seventeenth-century editors of Boethius did not do their work well. In many places, especially in the
Dialectica, an improved text can be obtained by consulting the princeps of the Opera omnia (Venice, 1492).
Although there is as yet no census of manuscripts available, it is certain that Boethius has a rich diversity of
manuscript traditions for all his writings. The Consolatio alone is preserved in about 400 manuscripts; the number
for the translations of Aristotle and for the opuscula sacra is not greatly inferior to this figure. The Consolatio was
first critically edited by R. Peiper for the Teubner library (1871) from fourteen manuscripts. The work now has two
good modern editions: that in the Vienna corpus (CSEL 67, 1934) by Wilhelm Weinberger on the basis of work by
G. Schepss and A. Engelbrecht; and that in the Latin Corpus Christianorum 94 (1957) by Ludwig Bieler. Bieler's
edition adds new manuscript material and, where he differs from Weinberger, in some cases improves the text.
Bibliography
ABERG, N. Die Goten und Langobarden in Italien. Uppsala, 1929.
ABRAMOWSKI, L. `Trinitarische und christologische Hypostasenformeln', Theologie und Philosophie 54, 1979,
38-49.
ACKRILL, J.L. Aristotle's Categories and De interpretatione. Oxford, 1963.
ADAMO, L. `Boezio e Mario Vittorino traduttori e interpreti dell' Isagoge di Porfirio', Rivista critica di storia
della filosofia 22, 1967, 141-64.
ALFONSI, L. `De quibusdam locis quos ex antiquis poetis Boethius et Maximianus repetisse videntur', Aevum 16,
1942, 86-92.
`Problemi filosofici della Consolatio boeziana', Rivista di filosofia neoscolastica 35, 1943, 323-8.
`Studi boeziani', Aevum 19, 1945, 142-57; 25, 1951, 132-66; 210-29.
`Romanità e barbarie nell' Apologia di Boezio', Studi Romani 1, 1953, 605-16.
ALTANER, B. Kleine patristische Schriften = Texte und Untersuchungen 83. Berlin, 1967.
AMANN, E. Articles on Hormisdas: DTC 7, 1 (1927), 171-5; Scythes (Moines), DTC 14, 2 (1941) 1746-53;
Théopaschite (controverse), DTC 15, 1 (1946), 505-12.
AMERIO, R. `Probabile fonte della nozione boeziana di eternità', Filosofia 1, 1950, 365-72.
ANASTASI, R. `Sul processo di Boezio', Miscellanea di studi di letteratura cristiana antica 1, 1947, 21-39.
`Boezio e Massimiano', ibid. 2, 1948, 1-20.
`La fortuna di Boezio', ibid. 3, 1951, 93-110.
ANDERSON, J.F. St. Augustine and Being, a metaphysical essay. The Hague, 1965.
ANDRE BARBERA, C. `Arithmetic and geometric divisions of the Tetracord', Journal of Music Theory 21, 1977,
294-323.
ANNAS, J. Aristotle's Metaphysics books M and N. Oxford, 1976.
ARCARI, P.M. Idee e sentimenti politici dell'alto medioevo. Milan, 1968.
ARMSTRONG, A.H. St. Augustine and Christian Platonism. Villanova University, 1967.
AUERBACH, E. Literatursprache und Publikum in der lateinischen Spätantike und im Mittelalter. Bern, 1958.
(Eng. tr. by R. Manheim, London, 1965.)
Notes
Chapter I
Pages 1-3
1. Ennodius, Paraenesis didascalica, ed. Vogel (MGH) p. 314, 40 f.; ed. Hartel (CSEL 6), p. 409, 8. His name
Severinus may point to a family connection with the consul of this name (for 461, see PLRE ii, p. 1001) whose
attendance at an imperial banquet in Arles is described by Sidonius Apollinaris (ep. i, 11, 10-16). A connection
with Severinus the apostle of Noricum, who died about 482, is unlikely.
2. Procopius, BG i, 1, 5-8.
3. Cassiodorus, Variae ii, 24.
4. A.H.M. Jones, `The Constitutional Position of Odoacer and Theoderic,' Journal of Roman Studies 52 (1962),
126-30.
5. Avell. 114, 1 (CSEL 35 p. 508) = Hormisdas, ep. 14, p. 768 Thiel.
6. Boethius, In Cat. iii, PL 64, 264A.
7. Avitus, C. Eutych. i, p. 16, 1 Peiper (MGH) = PL 59, 203B1. Cf. ibid. ii, p. 22, 14 = PL 59, 210 C10, where
Anastasius is `rex orientis'.
8. CSEL 35, p. 509, 20 = Hormisdas, ep. 14, 2 p. 769 Thiel. So also Jordanes, Getica 29, 146 and 49, 257. The
usage goes back to the division by Theodosius I in 395 (Epitome de Caesaribus 48, 19-20), but the source may
reflect later custom. During the Acacian schism Pope Felix III tells the emperor Zeno `hoc expedit ut si utraque
Roma pro mutuo pignore nuncupatur, fiat utriusque [utraque Thiel] una fides illa Romanorum . . .' (ep. 15, 3 p. 272
Thiel; critical edn. in Schwartz, Publizistische Sammlungen zum Acacianischen Schisma, Abh. Bayer. Akad. NF
10, 1934, p. 84). This anticipates Gelasius' declaration to Anastasius `sicut Romanus natus Romanum principem
amo' (ep. 12, 1 p. 350; Schwartz, p. 19), remarkable in view of Gelasius' African origin; and the bitter
remonstrance of Symmachus to the same emperor (ep. 10, 14 p. 707; Schwartz, p. 157) `nec viventes in iure
Romano lacerare conveniat Romanis', both being rejoinders to imperial demands that Rome and the West conform
to the orthodoxy recognized by the East Roman emperor. In 520, the schism being two years ended, Epiphanius
patriarch of Constantinople turned the argument back on Hormisdas with suggestions unwelcome to Rome: `dum
una utraque sit ecclesia, procul dubio et bona, quae per vigilantiam eveniunt, communis exinde laudis gloria
utrisque patriarchalibus sedibus rimatur,' carrying the implication of sister patriarchates. Hormisdas, ep. 130, 2 p.
949.
9. Utilis at this date may mean good, brave, worthy, honest (Löfstedt, Late Latin p. 102), but here means rich as the
contrast with miser shows; so J.C. Rolfe in the Loeb translation, supported by J.N. Adams, The Text and Language
of a Vulgar Latin Chronicle (Bulletin of
Chapter II
1. In Cat. ii, 230C.
2. In Porph. * Isag. II (CSEL 48, 294, 11 = PL 64, 137C); Perih. ii, 79 Meiser (= PL 64, 433C); Intr. ad syll. cat.
762C.
3. H. Jäger, Die Quellen des Porphyrios in seiner Pythagoras-Biographie (Diss. Zürich, 1919).
4. Iamblichus' commentary is edited by H. Pistelli (Teubner, 1894); Asclepius' commentary by L. Tarán,
Transactions of the American Philosophial Society n.s. 59/4 (1969); Philoponus' work by Hoche (Progr. Wesel,
1864/5; Berlin, 1867), now a very rare book.
5. Marinus, V. Procli 28; Suda, s.v. Proklos (3).
6. Edited by C. Jan, Musici Scriptores Graeci (Teubner, 1895).
7. Some manuscripts of the Institutio Arithmetica have the subscription `legi opusculum meum', i.e. the archetype
had been revised by Boethius himself. See G. Schepss in Blättern f.d. Bayer. Gymnasialwesen 24 (1888), 28. Some
early mss. give the title `incoeptio arithmetica'.
8. On the tradition of Philolaus' fragments see Burkert, Lore and Science in Ancient Pythagoreanism (1972), pp.
238-77, on this fragment, pp. 250 f. which is fuller in Stobaeus i, 21, 7a. Proclus alludes to its doctrine of the world
as a harmony of opposites (In Tim. i, 176, 27 Diehl). Similarly Macrobius, In Som. Scip. i, 14, 19 (of the soul).
Theon of Smyrna writes (p. 12, 10 Hiller) `The Pythagoreans, whom Plato often follows, say that music is the
harmony of opposites and the unity of multiplicity and the concord of dissidents, not only concerning rhythms and
melody but of everything absolutely.'
9. PL. 64, 162. See H. Thesleff, The Pythagorean Texts of the Hellenistic Period (Åbo, 1965) p. 22. On these
Archytas apocrypha cf. Burkert, op. cit., p. 222.
10. Philolaos is cited by Nicomachus for this view, Boethius drops the allusion. The distinction between the three
types of mean is incisively set out by Proclus, In Tim. ii, 171, 21 ff.
11. See W. Burkert, Lore and Science in ancient Pythagoreanism; B.L. van der Waerden, `Die Harmonielehre der
Pythagoreer', Hermes 78 (1943), 163-99.
12. Som. i, 36-37; Q. Gen. iii, 3 (cf. Plato, Phaedrus 259c).
13. In de Caelo, 469, 18-20 Heiberg.
14. Hexaemeron iii, 3, PG 29, 57C.
15. Hexaemeron ii, 2, 7, CSEL 32/1 p. 45. Ambrose combines Cicero, Philo and Basil. There has been some
disagreement about Ambrose's sources in this passage. P. Courcelle (Rev. ét. latines 34, 1956, 232-9) proposed
Basil, Cicero, and Macrobius, but did not convince M. Fuhrmann (Philologus 107, 1963, 301-8) who prefers the
hypothesis of Origen's lost commentary on Genesis. This hypothesis may be supported from
Chapter III
1. The contrary is asserted, on a wafer-thin basis, by G. Pfligersdorffer in Wiener Studien 66 (1953), p. 152.
Chapter IV
1. Horace, Carm. iii, 30; Verg. G. i, 42; A. viii, 67. I owe these two observations to Dr. A.M. Crabbe.
2. A long list of Augustinian echoes is given by E.K. Rand, `Der dem Boethius zugeschriebene Traktat de fide
catholica', Jb. f. class. Philologie, suppl. 26 (1901), 421-4.
3. Augustine does not deny that envy was an important element in the devil's motivation (Enarr. in Ps. 58, 5, etc.).
4. Cf. Aug. City of God xv, 8 for Adam's survival after Abel's death; but Augustine makes nothing of Adam's
remorse on contemplating the fearful consequences of his sin.
5. Cf. Aug. Sermo 67, 7 `simul Christus et in coelo et in terra'.
6. PL 59, 406AB.
7. E.K. Rand, Founders of the Middle Ages (Harvard, 1928), pp. 156-7. Like H.F. Stewart who at first rejected the
authenticity of De fide catholica (with the dangerous sentence `a single reading of it is sufficient to convince one
that this is no work of Boethius', Boethius, an Essay, 1891, p. 139), Rand came soon to abandon his earlier view
that De fide catholica is spurious (Jb. f. class. Philologie, suppl. 26 (1901), pp. 401-61). In 1918 the first edition of
Stewart and Rand's Loeb edition of the Tractates and Consolation (p. 52) made the change of mind of both
scholars explicit. De fide catholica is accepted as genuine by M. Cappuyns in his important article `Boèce' in
Dictionnaire d'Histoire et de Géographie Ecclésiastique ix (1937), 371-2. Though most scholars concur, it was not
accepted by P. Courcelle, Les lettres grecques en Occident (2nd ed. Paris, 1948), p. 301; nor by Helen M. Barrett,
Boethius, some aspects of his times and work (Cambridge, 1940), pp. 148-50; nor by the best German study of the
Opuscula, Viktor Schurr, Die Trinitätslehre des Boethius im Lichte der `skythischen Kontroversen' (Forschungen
zur christlichen Literaturund Dogmengeschichte, XVIII, 1, Paderborn 1935), pp. 8-9. Against this weight of
opinion L. Obertello first argued that the tract is either by Boethius or by John the deacon: Severino Boezio (1974) i
pp. 252-85. He has now come to think it certainly Boethius' work; see the notes to his translation of Gli Opuscoli
Teologici (Milan: Rusconi, 1979). I have independently concluded from the diction that De fide catholica is
certainly from his
Chapter V
1. The monographs of Klingner (1921), Courcelle (1967), and Gruber (1978) have amassed much essential
material for interpreting the Consolation of Philosophy, on which I have constantly tried to draw in this chapter.
Gruber's detailed, sentence-by-sentence exegesis has been particularly valuable, and his book makes it superfluous
to provide this chapter with full annotation.
2. Proclus, In Tim. i, 167, 22, interprets it to mean intellectual wisdom. Celsus (in Origen, Contra Celsum vi, 42)
shows that there is a long history to the Platonic exegesis of the peplos of Athene.
3. I have discussed this in Medium Aevum (1980). Professor J.A.W. Bennett calls my attention to Thomas Browne's
Christian Morals i, 22 `There is a natural standing court within us, examining and acquitting, and condemning at
the Tribunal of our selves, wherein iniquities have their natural Thetas, and no nocent is absolved by the verdict of
himself.'
4. Michael Lapidge, `A Stoic metaphor in Late Latin poetry: the binding of the cosmos', Latomus 39 (1980), 817-
37.
Index
A
Abelard 195
Acacius of Constantinople 30, 44, 182;
schism 12, 29-45, 57
Acephali 185
Achilles bp of Spoleto 32
Adam 177-8, 201-2
Ado of Vienne 54
Adrastus 121
Agapetus, Pope 40, 65
Agapitus (cos. 517) 6, 60
Agapitus, patricius 60, 62
Agnellus of Ravenna 4, 290
Agorius 114
Akoimetae 184
Alan of Lille 252
Alaric 11
Albinus, Platonist 164
Albinus on artes 84, 104, 113
Albinus, senator 48-9, 55, 58, 62
Alcuin 107, 136, 251-2
Alexander of Aphrodisias 16, 81, 105, 109 f., 126, 129, 133-4, 139, 205;
future contingents 246;
Categories 145-6, 193;
Interpretation 152;
fate 159, 162;
providence 161;
Theophrastus 171
Alexandria 17-20, 121; see 30
Amalafrida 53
Amalasuintha 4, 51, 62, 66
Amantius 43-4
Ambrose of Milan 6, 215;
music of spheres 80, 292-3
Ambrose and Beatus 6
Amiri, Al- 125
Ammianus 83
Ammonius, philosopher 19-20, 105-6, 111 ff., 125 ff., 139 f., 191, 197, 208, 220, 244;
astrolabe 102;
Categories 147 ff.;
Interpretation 153 ff.;
hypothetical syllogism 167-9;
question of Boethius' debt 20, 108-9, 146, 154
Anastasius II, Pope 30-1, 38-40, 42, 183
Anastasius, emperor 2, 30-46, 60, 185, 291 n. 67
Andromachus 12-14, 249
Andronicus of Rhodes 121, 126, 143, 151, 164
angels 177, 242
Anonymus Valesianus 3, 50, 52, 61;
verdict on Theoderic 63
Anselm 112; 235-6
Anselm of Havelberg 140
Anthemius, W. emperor 20
Anthimus, physician 288
Antiphon, Advent 237
Apollo 14, 159
Apion 66
Apuleius 21, 70, 113, 156, 166, 232
Aquinas 17, 175, 195, 203, 223
Archimedes 82, 103, 105, 149
Archytas 77-8, 87, 89-90, 99, 127, 143 f.
Areobindus 46
Arianism 3, 57-9, 62, 177, 200, 213, 216
Arigern 49
Aristarchus 69
Aristides, Aelius 61
Aristides Quintilianus 22, 83-4
Aristotle 16-21, 69, 73, 108-73;
brevity 112;
on goodness 208;
nonbeing 207;
man 122, 227;
honour 231;
nobility 233;
chance 244;
music of spheres 79;
numbers 81;
music 83, 86;
geometry 104-5;
the one 227;
hierarchy of sciences 109 f.;
Latin translations 133-40;
Metaphysics 150, 244;
Ethics 214;
Protrepticus 233;
on Philosophy 235 f.;
on the Soul 153;
`heresy' 121;
on coming to be and on passing away 150, 199;
Physics 139, 150, 191 f., 244
Aristoxenus of Tarentum 87-101
Arnold, G. 174
Asclepius of Tralles 71
Aspasius 121, 126, 155
Asterius 5, 7
astronomy 102-7, 110;
zodiac 82
asylum 32, 51, 289 n. 54
Athalaric 52, 62-3, 66
Athens 17-20
Augustine 117, 121, 131, 175 ff., 187, 191 ff., 197, 199 ff., 211 ff.;
God 215, 237-7, hub 242;
God's
B
Barbara 6
Bark, W. 180
Basil, accuser 51
Basil, senator 49
Basil, prefect 57
Basil bp of Caesarea 80
bedbugs 228
Belisarius 255
Bellermann, F. 96
Bhutto, Z.A. 226
Bible 178, 237 f.
Boethius:
birth 1;
death 54-5, 66-9, 225 f.;
wife 6;
ancestry 5;
education 19;
consul 24;
sons' consulate 45-7, 229;
master of the offices 46 ff.;
poet 23;
solamen of philosophy 168;
Consolation 1, 54, 128-9, 140, 162-3, 173-4, 209, 220 ff., 222 ff;
Bible allusions 238;
quadrivium 73 ff.;
panegyric on Theoderic 46;
plan to translate Plato 135, 140;
prolix 120;
critics 120
Boniface II, Pope 65
Bovo 247
Brandt, S. 135
Brescia diptych 5
Burgundians 23, 52
Burgundio of Pisa 139
C
Calcidius 21, 70, 81, 191, 203, 242, 246
calendar of 354 12, 16, 35-6
Calvenzano 55
Capella, Martianus XII, 15, 21f., 24, 70, 84, 92, 102, 113, 116, 121, 169, 224, 232, 235
Cassiodorus 117;
master of the offices 54;
Anecdoton Holderi 7, 23, 46, 175, 225;
chronicle 41, 51f.;
Institutiones 70, 102, 115-16; 118, 139, 168-9, 254-5;
consul 41
Castor and Pollux 13 f.
Cato 7, 243
Censorinus 84
Cethegus 6
Chalcedon 25, 29-45
Chaldaean Oracles 204, 235, 243, 248
chance 119, 158, 244, 250
Charlemagne 60
chromatic genus 93-4
Cicero 5, 24, 68, 105, 148, 241;
wrong on chance 119;
Tusculans 228;
pro Cluentio 229;
pro Archia 231;
ep. ad Brutum 230;
Divination 241, 250;
Topics 113, 168 f.;
Timaeus 141
Clovis 2, 23
coemptio 24, 41
comet 50
Constantine Porphyrogenitus 60
consulate 4-5, 24
contingent 157 ff.
Corinth 60-1
coronation 60, 67
Courcelle, P. 20, 140, 153, 303
Cresconius of Todi 39
Cunigast 47
Cyprian, referendarius 48, 51
Cyril of Alexandria 18, 183, 185
Cyril of Scythopolis 189
D
Damascius 18-20, 157
Damasus, Pope 10-11, 287 n. 24
Dante 40, 223
deification 211, 236
determinism 157-63; 245f.
Devil 178
Diodorus Cronus 159
dialectic 108 ff.
Dionysius Areopagita 221
Dionysius Exiguus 186, 212 f.
Dioscorus bp of Alexandria 44, 184
Dioscorus, deacon 28, 37, 188;
antipope 65
division 164
Donatus, grammarian 69, 116
Dorotheus of Thessalonica 182
dream poems 225
E
Easter 31-3, 36
Ecclesius bp of Ravenna 60
Elias 92, 112, 145
enharmonic genus 83, 93-4
Ennodius:
on Boethius 1, 23;
Theoderic
F
Faber Stapulensis 136
Facundus 189
fallacy 156
Farabi, Al- 126, 128, 152
fate 49-50, 228 ff., 242 ff., 250
Faustus bp of Riez 186, 188, 201
Faustus Albus 9, 12, 41
Faustus Niger 6, 9-10, 40-1, 188
Felix III, Pope 11, 30, 285 n. 8
Felix IV, Pope 64-5
Ferrandus 189, 199
Festus 6, 38, 41
Filioque 176, 219
Filocalus 10, 12, 35-6
Flavian 256
form and matter 214-5
fortune 119, 229
Franks 2, 288 n. 42;
see Clovis
Fulgentius 9, 15, 40, 188, 201, 217
future contingents 157-63, 245f.
G
Gaius 119
Galen 112, 167, 228
Galla 9, 15, 40, 287 n. 26
Gaudentius on music 84
Gaudentius, accuser 51
Gelasius 12-14, 41-2, 45, 183-4, 190, 198, 249, 285-6
Gellius, Aulus 75, 193, 203
geometry 70, 73, 77, 102-7, 110, 132, 208, 210, 214
Gerbert of Aurillac 76, 102-3, 255
Gilbert of Poitiers 203
Glareanus 138
God 210, 236 ff.;
universal belief 156, 207;
Augustine on 215, 235-7, 242;
the One 215 f., 227, 236;
no accidents 216-17
Goths 1-68;
prefer harsh modes 92
grammar 116;
see also Donatus, Priscian
Gregory the Great 9, 11 f., 33, 40, 49 f., 62 f., 190
Gregory of Tours 64
Gruber, J. 23, 234
H
Hadot, P. 135, 207
Hebdomads 203
Helpis 66
Henoticon 30 ff., 65, 182
Hermannus Contractus 98
Herminus 126
Herold 181
Hierocles 17-18, 107, 125, 211, 224, 229, 241, 244, 247
Hilary of Poitiers 219, 287 n. 26
Hilderic 52-3
Hippocrates 112, 203
Hippolytus 82
Historia Augusta 8
Hobbes 11
Horace 176
Hormisdas 25, 28, 41-5, 53, 57-8, 60, 181 f.; 187 ff.;
formula 44 f.
horoscopes 50, 107
Hypatia 18
Hypatius 43
I
Iamblichus 19, 157, 246, 253;
future contingents 163;
authority 134;
God and time 163, 246;
Life of Pythagoras 71;
Nicomachus 17, 71 f., 90;
Protrepticus 233;
Categories 16, 78, 129, 142-5.
imaginationes 131, 214, 220
imperfection 210, 236
implication 172
Importunus, senator 60
induction 151
infinite 125;
no infinite regress 210
Isidore of Seville 114
J
James of Venice 140
K
Klingner, F. 234
know thyself 227
L
Laurentius 9-10, 26, 31-41
law, Roman 35, 119, 286 n. 13
Leo I, Pope 11-12;
Tome 26, 30 ff., 192, 200
Leo XIII, Pope 68
Leontius, monk 186
lethargy 227-8
Lewis, C.S. 251
Liber Pontificalis 9-10, 39-40, 48, 60-2, 291 n. 69
liturgy 251;
baptismal 27;
Paternoster 202
Lombards 66
love 232, 244
Lucan 232, 243
Lucian 224
Lupercalia 12-14, 249
Lupus bp of Troyes 107
Lydian mode 92, 95-6
M
Macedonius 182
Macrobius 7-8, 14, 21, 70, 90, 102, 107, 114, 132-3, 231;
music of spheres 80-2
Macrobius Plotinus Eudoxius 7
magic 49-50, 227, 289 n. 47
Manichees 11, 57, 177
Marcellinus Comes 8, 37, 60
Marcellus, Tullius 114
Marinus 121, 204
Marius of Aventicum 55
Martial 225
Martianus, see Capella
martyrs 227, 230, 249, 287 n. 30
Mary 178, 188;
Theotókos 179
mathematics 70 ff.
matter 191, 199, 229
Maxentius 186 ff., 211
Maximian 254 f.
Menippos 224
Merobaudes 117
Minio-Paluello, L. 113 f., 129, 132, 135 ff.
modal logic 157 ff.
modes 83, 91-3, 96-9
Monophysites 25, 29-45, 50, 58, 180 ff.
Montfaucon, B. de 256
More, T. 253
Muses 86, 117, 226, 238, 250
Music:
Boethius' introduction 78 ff.;
therapy 92;
ratios 78-9;
spheres 79-81;
in Consolation 101
Mutianus 84
N
names 239;
names of names 123
Napoleon 3
nature 191 ff.
necessity 157, 162, 245
Nephalius 185
Nestorius 26, 30, 44, 178, 180-202
Nicomachus XII, 17, 21, 70-101, 120
Nitzsch, F. 174
nothing 190 ff., 244
Numenius 110
O
Obertello, L. 168
Odovacar 1-5, 12, 47
Olybrius 46
Olympiodorus 121, 141, 295 n. 48
Opilio 51, 189
oracles 159
Origen:
comets 50;
slow medication 228;
silence 231;
freedom 162
Orpheus 240
Ostia temple 13
Ovid 225
P
Palladio 84
papacy 9-12;
Laurentian schism 29 ff.;
divine right 31, 65;
free of error 40;
jurisdiction 43-5;
above synods 34-5, 41.
See Leo, Anastasius II, Gelasius, Symmachus, Hormisdas, John, Rome.
Q
quadrivium 70-107
Quintilian 70, 92
R
Rand, E.K. 176, 302 n. 7
Ravenna:
Arian churches 59, 290;
S. Vitale 60;
S. Apollinare Nuovo 59;
synagogues 58;
Theoderic's palace 4;
mausoleum 62;
sarcophagus with Boethius and Symmachus 290 n. 56;
Pope John I's funeral 61;
corruption at court 32, 47
Reginbert 175
relation 149, 196, 218
relativism 155-6, 220
Remigius 203
Renatus 27, 168, 189, 255-6
rhetoric 112 ff.
Richard of S. Victor 195
Ricimer 59
Rijk, L.M. de 165, 300 n. 50
Rome 10-14;
`royal city' 35;
Sacred city 8;
S. Peter's 3, 31-2, 35, 57, 64;
S
Sabinus bp of Canosa 60
scholasticism XIV
Scythian monks 29, 185 ff., 211 f.
seafight 158
sede vacante 33
Sedulius 286 n. 17
Senarius 27
Seneca 227-8, 230, 244
Severinus of Cologne 54, 59
Severinus of Noricum 40; 285 n. 1
Severus bp of Antioch 25, 27, 182, 189-90, 257, 260
Severus, Acilius 224
Severus, Messius Phoebus 20
Sextus Empiricus 164, 166
Sextus the Pythagorean 149
Shiel, J. 129-31, 153
Sidonius Apollinaris 107, 224, 285 n. 1
Sigeric 52
Sigibuld 65
Sigismund 52
Simplician bp of Milan 16, 70
Simplicius, Pope 30, 57
Simplicius, philospher 19-20, 78-9, 102, 111, 125, 127, 206;
uses lamblichus 144, 235, 244;
on Epictetus 199;
Physics 139, 146;
De caelo 139-40;
Categories 143-5, 148, 216, 220
sorcery, see magic
soul, immortal 230, 247;
mathematical 111;
musical 86;
wings 240;
returns to itself 131, 221, 227, 237;
inferior to mind 151
speculatio 131
spheres, revolving 242;
music 79-81
stars 22, 50, 162;
zodiac 82;
horoscopes 107;
fate 242;
Boethius' astronomy 102-7, 227
Stephania 6
Stephanus 152
Stoicism 108-73, 151, 228-33
Sylvester II, Pope: see Gerbert
Symmachus, Pope 9, 26, 31-45, 48, 57, 181
Symmachus, Q. Aurelius (fourth-cent. senator) 5, 9, 14-15
Symmachus, Q. Aurelius Memmius (Boethius' father-in-law) 5-10, 12, 16, 23, 40-1, 56, 69, 103, 116, 168, 181,
213, 226, 229;
executed 56, 67;
haunts Theoderic 63;
drops him into hell 63
Synesius 234
Syrianus 17, 111, 121, 125, 128, 139, 153-4, 156-7, 191, 197, 203
T
Talleyrand 3
Taylor, T. 243
Teles 229
Themistius 78, 114, 120, 127-8, 140
Theodora 55
Theoderic 24, status 2, 30, 42-3;
medallion 3-4;
at S. Peter's 3;
care for Romanitas 4;
for law 119;
civilitas 35;
toleration 56 ff.;
dynastic marriages 52;
restores cities 12;
golden age 63, 66;
death 62;
mausoleum 62;
Arianism 3, 27, 34, 52 ff., 63, 179;
tyranny 227 ff., 240, 248
Theodorus, senator 60
Theodorus, scribe 27, 256
Theologoumena Arithmeticae 72, 142
Theophrastus 126, 166-7, 171; 301 nn. 61, 72
Thrasamund 52-3; 287 n. 26
theta 1, 225
Thierry of Chartres 203
Tiberianus 235
Ticinum, see Pavia
time 163, 177, 217-8, 242 ff.
Timothy Aelurus 44
Totila 63, 66
transmigration 240
Trifolius 188
Trigguilla 47
Trishagion 185 ff.
U
Ulfila 2
Ulpian 119
universals 124, 130, 133, 147-8, 215
Usener, H. 7, 157, 241
V
Valla, L. XI
Vallinus 175
Vandals 21, 32, 52-3, 56
variables 164
Varro XII, 21, 203, 224
Vergil 5, 23, 176, 235, 243, 245;
Aeneid allegorised 15
Verona 48, 53;
Euclid 103-4
via media 182-3
Victorinus, Marius 16, 21, 70, 115-18, 134-5, 158, 168-70, 209, 216
Victorius of Aquitaine 31, 36
Vigilius, Pope 195
Vitalian 43, 186
Vitruvius XII, 84
W
Webster, R. 255
wisdom:
Solomon 237;
sapientia through scientia 131
X
Xystus III, Pope:
alleged adultery 36
Z
Zacharias:
Ammonius 19;
Church History 303 n. 9
Zeno, emperor 9, 30, 285;
see Henoticon