A Critique of Gell On Art and Agency
A Critique of Gell On Art and Agency
A Critique of Gell On Art and Agency
A Critique of Alfred Gell on "Art and Agency" [Corrected title: A Critique of Alfred Gell on
Art and Agency]
Art and Agency: An Anthropological Theory by Alfred Gell
Review by: Ross Bowden
Oceania, Vol. 74, No. 4 (Jun., 2004), pp. 309-324
Published by: Wiley on behalf of Oceania Publications, University of Sydney
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/40332070 .
Accessed: 01/09/2014 21:29
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Wiley and Oceania Publications, University of Sydney are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to Oceania.
http://www.jstor.org
Ross Bowden
La TrobeUniversity
ABSTRACT
Thisreviewarticleexaminesin detailtheargument in AlfredGell's posthumously
published
bookArtandAgency:an anthropological The reviewis dividedintotwoparts.In the
theory.
firstI summarisethemainargument of each chapterin turnand commenton someof the
author'smorequestionable
assumptions andconclusions. In thesecondI stepbackfromthe
individual andcomment
chapters on threeofthemoregeneralissuesthebookraises.
AGENT-PATIENTRELATIONSHIPS
Two keytermsin theanalysisare 'agent' and 'patient',or 'social agent'and 'recipient'
respectively. Gell presumablytakes the firstpair fromtraditionalgrammarwherethe
'agent' is theperformer of an actionand the 'patient'theperson(or otherentity)which
'suffers'or is thetargetof theaction.An agent,Gell writes,is any'thing'(e.g. an artwork
or a person)'who is seen as initiating
causal sequencesof a particular type,thatis, events
causedbyactsofmindorwillor intention.' (p.16; see also pp.17and 19). Again,'Whenev-
er an eventis believedto happenbecauseof an "intention" lodgedin thepersonor thing
whichinitiatesthecausal sequence,thatis an instanceof 'agency" (p.17). Personsare
alwaystheprimary agentsbutartworks andotherinanimate objectscan be agentsin a sec-
ondaryor indirectsense,foralthoughtheythemselves are notintentional beingstheyfre-
quentlyact as themediumsthrough whichpeople 'manifestand realize' theirintentions
(p.21). As suchtheyare 'extensions'of thepersonswhoseagencytheyexpress- partof
their'distributed' personhood(see especiallyChapter7). Agentand patientare relational
concepts:foreveryagenttheremustbe a patient, andviceversa(p.22).
310
Fig. 1 . Untitled cartoon by Reg Lynch, fromthe Melbourne newspaper The Age,
Money Managers section, 31 Aug. 2002. Reproduced with the artist's permission.
agency in relationto the patientthanthe producerof the prototype,i.e. the artist.But in sit-
uations where a viewer responds to an artworkprimarilybecause of how it depicts some-
thingthenthe artistexercises greateragency than the prototype.As an example, Gell cites
the well known case of Winston Churchill who so disliked the way the painterGraham
Sutherlanddepicted him in a commissioned portraithe refusedto have the paintingin his
house (p.34).
Gell uses complex, scientific-lookingformulaeto express the way in which the differ-
ent termsin an art nexus can exercise greateror lesser agency according to context(e.g.
pp.52-56). In the situationdepicted in the cartoon,for instance,the greateragency of the
prototypein contrastto the artistcould be expressed in the formulareproducedbelow. The
extensions'-A' and '-P' signifythe agent and patientroles respectivelyplayed by different
termsin thisartnexus.
311
312
sightforit means thatthe claims he makes forthe impactof these artworkson theirowners'
tradingpartners- and indeed forart in general in this chapter - is nothingmore than an
hypothesisforwhichno concreteevidence is provided.
In Chapter6, 'The Critiqueof the Index', the focus of the argumentshiftsto non-figu-
rativeor 'abstract' art,somethingwhich Gell equates, astonishinglynaively,with non-rep-
resentationalart.Much non-figurative artis non-representational but in indigenoussocieties
of the kind Gell is consideringthe greatbulk of non-figurative art is representational.This
considerationapart,Gell offersin this chaptera new argumentin relationto what makes
artworkseffectivemediatorsof social agency - and, by implication,valuable aesthetically.
Here he argues that non-figurativemotifsare effectivemediators of agency not because
viewers cannot reconstructhow they were made but because they form visual puzzles
which cannot be deciphered easily or quickly (pp.73ff). Gell does not make the point
explicitlybut he appears to be implyingthatthe more puzzling a design is visually the more
highlyvalued it will be as art.Much of thischapteris devoted to a discussion of mazes and
othercomplex optical forms,all of which Gell amusinglydubs 'mind-traps'(Gell 1998:80).
Visually complex non-figurativeforms,he argues, often also have apotropaic roles. For
instance,in partsof India women place such motifsat the doors of theirhouses to prevent
malign spirits from entering and harming the occupants. They serve as 'demon-traps'
(pp.84-85) because the spiritsstop at the thresholdto tryto decipherthe designs. As inter-
estingas the materialin this chapteris ethnographicallyGell fails totallyto show how it is
relevantto the studyof art more generally.It throwsno light on how people in different
societies conceptualise what Gell and other analysts call 'art' or the criteriathey use to
judge qualityin art.
In Chapter 7, 'The distributedperson', the focus shiftsto representationalart (some-
thingwhich Gell naively equates withfigurativeimagery).Here he advances a thirdtheory
forwhy artworksserve as effectivemediatorsof social agency - and, by implication,why
they are valued aesthetically(e.g. p.97). For Gell, representationalimagery serves as an
effectivemediatorof social agency because the act of representationitselfconferspower
over the entityrepresented(p. 102) - even if this power is only imaginary.It does this by
-
capturingpartof the entityrepresented,notablyits image or simulacrum partof the enti-
ty's 'distributed' self - and 'binds' thatpart of its to
identity the artwork (or otherindex of
agency). By conferring(imaginary)power over the entitydepicted the maker of the repre-
sentationbecomes entitledto benefitsof various kinds fromthe entitydepicted (see espe-
cially pp.lO2ff). Gell devotes the greaterpart of this chapternot to a discussion of what
would normallybe called 'art' but to two institutionswhich he believes operate according
to the same representationallogic. One is idol-worship,an institutionwhich he says, with
commendable candour, he would preferto explain ratherthan rechristenfor reasons of
politicalcorrectness(p.96). The otheris whathe calls 'volt' sorcery.Gell definesidolatryas
physical interactionwith inanimateentities(such as sculptures)which representdivinities
for the purpose of receiving the blessings those supernaturalbeings supposedly confer
(p.135). In partsof South Asia, he reports,the act of makinga representationof a divinity,
in returnforwhich the divinityis obliged to confera blessing on the devotee, mightconsist
of nothingmore thanforminga visual image of it, such as by layingeyes on an idol depict-
ing it. Gell uses the termvolt sorceryforthe practiceof harmingvictimsfroma distanceby
manipulatingrepresentationsof them. The act of representingan intendedvictim 'binds'
partof the target'sdistributedpersonto the index and therebyenables the sorcererto injure
or kill the victim(pp.96ff) - by inflictinginjuriesof thekind the sorcererwould like to see
inflictedon thetargetof the sorceryon thatpartof his or her identityattachedto the index.
AlthoughGell undertakesno analysis of the social role of artin modernWesternsoci-
eties he neverthelessfeels able to assertthatthe culturalvalue placed on representational art
in the West can be explained in the same way as idolatry(or volt sorcery).Indeed, forGell
the value thatmodernWesternersplace on the act of contemplatingartworksin galleries
313
STYLE
At theconclusionof Chapter7 Gell makesan astonishing admissionandone thatis actually
verydamaging forhisargument as a whole.He statesthatthereasonhe hasfocusedup tothis
pointin his bookexclusively
on thetransactional contexts in whichartworks arefound,and
paid no attention
to suchtopicsas themeanings theymight encode,is notbecauseto do so
wouldbe unanthropological, whichis whathe initially argued,butbecausehe has hitherto
focussedon individualartworks,i.e. objectstakenin isolationfromeach otherethnographi-
314
cally. When objects are takenin isolation,he says, the analyst'is always going to emphasize
therelationalcontextat theexpense of artisticor aestheticform,the networkof agent/patient
relations'in the vicinity'of the workof art' (p.153). But if sets of artworksbecome the sub-
ject of analysis,especially sets whose membersare unifiedby a commonstyle,otherinterpre-
tive opportunities open up. One is thatit allows foran investigationof the problematiccon-
cept of style.In the followingchapter,accordingly,Gell turnsto the problemof style.In that
chapterhe also addressesthequestionof whetherthe structural principlesthatunderliea par-
ticularartstyleoperatein otherareas of the same society,and whetherartstylesin thissense
'thematizeand make cognitivelysalient' wider'culturalparameters'(p.157; see also p.216).
Entitled 'Style and culture', Chapter 8 is divided into three parts. In the firstGell
attemptsto define 'style'. In the second he attemptsto illustratehis understandingof this
concept throughan examinationof Marquesan art.In the thirdhe attemptsto show thatthe
principlesthatunderliethe stylisticunityof Marquesan artalso underliethe Marquesan sta-
tus system,and thatin theMarquesas, at least, the artdoes thematize'essential' (p.157) cul-
turalparameters.
Regrettably,none of the ambitious goals that Gell sets himself in this chapter is
achieved. In the firstsection he fails to provide a methodologicallyuseful definitionof
style.The best thathe can do is offerseveral high-levelglosses of the term,such as by say-
ing thatstyleis the 'harmonicprinciple' that 'unites works of art into groups' (p.157). His
failureto providea usefuldefinitionis a consequence of the factthathe ignoresvirtuallyall
of the genuinelyvaluable work on stylethathas been done in recentyears by anthropolo-
gists, art historiansand especially archaeologists (see, for example, the various essays in
Conkey and Hastoff1990). The only theoreticalworkon stylehe does discuss in detail is an
anthropologicallyuninformedessay by thephilosopherWollheim(1979).
Even thoughhe failsto providea methodologicallyusefuldefinitionof styleGell never-
theless attemptsto illustratewhat he understandsby the termin the second section through
an examinationof Marquesan art.The workhe examines is not theentirecorpus of Marque-
san art (which, of course, is still being added to) but the limitedset of motifsillustratedin
Karl von den Steinen'sthree-volumeThe Marquesaners and theirart,publishedin 1925. On
thebasis of theseobjects Gell contendsthatwhatgives Marquesan artits stylisticunityis the
fact thateach distinguishablemotif(a notion he does not define) can be transformed into
every other motif through one or more steps involving, at each stage, what he refers to as
minimalvisual changes. This process is based on what he calls the 'principle of least differ-
ence' (Gell 1998:218). More particularly, Gell arguesthateach motifcan be transformed into
every other through the application of one or more of four 'transformation' rules (p.170);
these,he acknowledges,parallelthosedevised a generationearlierby proponentsof thecom-
ponentialapproachto the studyof kinshipterminologies(e.g. Lounsbury1964).
In markedcontrastto thetransformation rulesdevised by proponentsof thecomponential
to
approach kinshipterminologies, which can at least be applied rigorously, Gell's rulesare so
vaguely formulated that there is no way of applying them consistently or in a testableway;
of how theyallegedlyoperateare therefore
Gell's own illustrations ad hoc and arbitrary.
A B
Fig. 2. 'Plane of
rotation' one Marquesan motif(A) intoanother(B), adapted from
Gell 1998, Fig. 8.7/2,p.172.
315
316
317
318
andnotjustprovisional of thestylistic
interpretations features thatconnectthemembers of
thesetarepossible,forno newobjectsarebeingaddedtotheset.
It is true,of course,thateven in thecase of a deceasedartist, his or herworkis not
finiteor boundedsincehitherto unknownworksby thesame personcould come to light,
and thesepotentially could lead to a re-evaluation of the stylisticlinksthatconnectthe
worksthatwerealreadyknown.Butthisis a relatively minorpoint.For thereis no reason
whyan analystshouldnottaketheworksthatare known,or evena smallsub-setof them,
suchas thoseproducedin whatmightbe consideredtheartist'smaturestyle,and on the
basis of thatboundedset offeran interpretation of theirstylisticinterrelationships in
absoluteterms.This,in fact,is preciselywhatGell himselfdoes in his analysisoftheMar-
quesanartstylein Chapter8. In thatchapterhe bases his analysisof theMarquesanstyle
noton all knownworksbuton thoseillustrated in Steinen'sbook.Furthermore, Gell does
notprefacehis analysisin thatchapterby sayingthatthestylistic relationsbetweenthe
motifs he is considering areinherentlydynamicandunstableandthathis analysistherefore
is provisional;on thecontrary, he offersan analysisof whatconnectsthesemotifsstylisti-
cally in absoluteterms.It is perfectly truethatany interpretation of a bodyof empirical
data,whatever the academic is
discipline, alwaysprovisional in thesensethata better(e.g.
moreconsistent or simpler)interpretation of thesame bodyof datacan alwaysin principle
be advanced;butthisis notwhatGell is arguing.
AN OVERVIEW
Artand Agencyraisesmanyotherissueson whichI could commenton at lengthif space
permitted. butconfusednotionofthe'distributed
One is thefashionable person'whichGell
discussesat lengthin chapters7 and 9. In thisconcludingsection,however,I restrict
my
comments tothreemoregeneralissues.
4 studiesofart
Anthropological9
As alreadynoted,Gell beginshis book witha no-holds-barred denunciationof earlier
anthropological analyses of artwhich focus on what he calls 'aesthetic'
systems andthecul-
tural'meanings'thatartworks supposedly encode.He denouncesthesenotbecausetheyare
illegitimateintellectuallybutbecausetheyareinherently unanthropological. Theyareunan-
thropological because they do not focus on the transactional contexts in which artworks
occur,andin particular on thewayartworks mediatesocialagency.If studiesof symbolism
and 'aesthetics'areto be undertaken at all, Gell considers, theyshouldbe carriedoutbyart
historiansand 'critics'(p.2). Gell partlywithdraws fromthispositionat theendof Chapter
7 butitnevertheless remainsthebasicpositionadoptedthroughout thebook.
No seriousanthropologist woulddenythatartworks typically, evenuniversally, serve
as indexesof socialagency.In theSepikRiversocietyin whichthepresentwriter conduct-
ed fieldwork themembers ofeach clandeliberately andquiteconsciously decoratethecere-
monialbuildingsthey own in slightly different ways from all otherspreciselyforthepur-
of
pose distinguishing themselves as members of a distinctsocial group(see Bowden1992).
Furthermore, thesize of thesebuildingsand thelavishnesswithwhichtheyare decorated
withbarkpaintings andpolychrome sculptures areuniversally interpretedas indexesofthe
size,politicalstrengthanddepthof artistic skillof theclansthatownthem.Entirely legiti-
mately, Gell exploressimilarissuesin Chapter9 in relationto theceremonialarchitecture
of 19thcentury Maori.
But as he does so oftenin thisbook Gell startswitha valid pointand drawsinvalid
conclusionsfromit. In thiscase, he infersfromthefactthatartworks frequently serveas
mediatorsof social agencythatthisis theprimary role of artcross-culturally (see Gell
1998:251) and even the only one that should be of interest to anthropologists.But restrict-
319
Aestheticvalues
A secondmajorproblemwiththebookis thatit providesno coherent accountof aesthetic
values,i.e. thecriteria peopleuse in to
anysociety judgequality in art.
The studyofaesthet-
ic valuesis nota trivialor secondary matter anthropologically,as Gell implies(p.6), butis
centralto thestudyofartcross-culturally, forhowthemembers ofa societyjudgequalityin
artreflects theway theyconceptualise artas a culturalphenomenon, as well as how they
understand artistic Gell
creativity. does not directly addresstheissue of aestheticvaluebut
he does alludeto it.The problem, as alreadynoted,is thatwhathe saysis bothinconsistent
and,at times,astonishingly uninformed. His primary argument, outlinedin Chapter5, is
thatwhatgivesartworks theirvalue aesthetically is theirtechnicalcomplexity - thesame
feature,in his view,thatmakesthemeffective as mediatorsof agency.He also implies,
thoughwithout providing anyevidence,thataestheticvaluesare thesamecross-culturally.
Gell advancedan identicalargument in his well-known1992 articleThe technology of
enchantment ... ', and thatarticleactuallyprovidesthemostmemorablestatement of it.
Therehe recallshow his parentstookhimas an elevenyearold childon his firstvisitto
SalisburyCathedral.He recallsbeingutterly captivatednotby thecathedralitselfbutby a
matchstick modelofitwhichthechurchauthorities hadon displayto advertisetheirrestora-
tionappeal. He reportsthathis strongest impression whencontemplating thismiracleof
model-making was his totalinabilityto understandhow its makerhad constructed it.
Indeed,thismodel,ratherthanthecathedral,epitomisedforhimas a boy 'dexterity in
objectified form'(Gell 1992:47).
320
321
322
ofart
Definition
A thirdmajorshortcoming of Gell's bookis thatit failsto providea coherent definition of
artandhencefailsto specifywhatthebookis ostensibly about.This is a significantfailing
in a workthatpurports to offerbotha theoryof artand a modelof how anthropological
analysesof artshouldproceedcross-culturally. Gell was clearlywell awarethathe had not
adequatelyaddressedtheissue of how 'art' is to be defined,forin theopeningchapterhe
attempts to sidesteptheissuebydismissing itas irrelevant methodologically (Gell 1998:7).
Butthisstrategy, to use thevernacular, is a cop-out.Gell knewit,furthermore, forimmedi-
atelyafterbrushing theissue aside he attempts to justifyhis indifferenceto how 'art' is to
be definedby saying- highlymisleadingly as it happens- thathe will limithis discus-
siontoobjects which no-one would dispute were art,suchas theMona Lisa (p.7).
Gell also attempts to sidesteptheproblemof how to define'art' by sayingthatthis
conceptis onlyfoundin certaintypesof societies,notablythosewith'institutions' suchas
galleries,artschoolsandcritics;anydefinition, consequently, wouldhaveno valuein cross-
culturalresearch(p.12). Gell is correctwhenhe statesthatthemodernWestern conceptof
artis onlyfoundin certaintypesof societies,notablyEuropeansocietiesand theircultural
offshoots (Appiah1995;Kaeppler1989). Butthefactthata conceptis notfounduniversal-
ly does notmeanthatit has no value in cross-cultural research.If he werecorrectexactly
the same could be said of almostall the analyticalcategoriesthatanthropologists use,
including'polities','economies','religion',even 'kinship'and 'family'.Rather,thefact
thattermscloselyparallelling artare notfoundin theformerly nonliteratesocietieswhich
anthropologists havetraditionally studiedshouldprompt theanalystfirstto offeran ethno-
graphically informed accountofhowthetermis usedin thosesocietiesin whichitis found,
and thenofferan explanation forwhyclose equivalentsare notfoundin manyothercul-
tures,even when are
they greatart-producing societiesin Western terms.If Gell had done
thisit wouldhavetakenhimclose to theheartof manyof themajorissuesin thestudyof
artcross-culturally.
AlthoughGell rejectstheneedto define'art' he nevertheless revealsin passingwhat
he believesthecharacteristics of artworks to be. Artworks display'technicalexpertise',
of a
'imagination high order', and 'exploit the intrinsicmechanisms ofvisualcognition with
subtlepsychologicalinsight'(Gell 1998:68). This is certainlybetterthannothing,but
unfortunately thethreefeatures he mentionsare notlimitedto artworks and consequently
do notdistinguish thisclass of objectsfroma wholerangeof otherentities,suchas any
well-designed producton a supermarket shelf,thebesttelevisionadvertisements, and any
number ofcomputer games.
Paradoxically, Gell's failureto offera methodologically usefuldefinition of 'art'reflects
thefactthathisbook,despiteitstitle,is notprimarily aboutartatall.Theprimary focusofthe
bookis indexesofagency, ofwhichartworks areonlyonevariety. Indeed,forGell'spurposes
323
NOTES
1. One oftheanonymous reviewersofthisarticlesuggested
thatcriticismofGell's bookshouldbe temperedby
thefactthatit was publishedposthumously.Butthisis questionable.If Gell had notwantedthemanuscript
or had notwanteditpublishedin theformin whichhe leftit,he wouldhaveinstructed
published, hisexecu-
torsaccordingly.
The factthathe didnot,andthathisexecutors publishedthebookoverhisownnamerather
thanthatofan editor,impliesthatthetextrepresents
Gell's consideredviewson itssubject-matter.
REFERENCES
ANDERSON, RICHARD L. 1989.ArtinSmall-scaleSocieties.EnglewoodCliffs,New Jersey: PrenticeHall.
APPIAH,KWAMEANTHONY.1995.WhyAfrica?Whyart?RA: theRoyalAcademy No. 48,pp.4O-41.
magazine,
BOWDEN, R.D. 1979. Tapu and Mana: RitualAuthority and PoliticalPowerin Traditional Maori Society.The
.JournalnfPacific,Hixtnrv 14:50-61
1984. MaoriCannibalism: An Interoretation.
Oceania 55:81-99.
1992. Art,Architecture and CollectiveRepresentations in A New Guinea Society.In Coote, Jeremyand
Anthony Shelton(Eds),Anthropology and Aesthetics . Oxford:ClarendonPress,pp.67-93.
1999. Whatis WrongwithAn ArtForgery? An Anthropological Perspective.TheJournalofAesthetics and
ArtCriticism 57 (3):333-43.
2002. Whatis 'Authentic' AboriginalArt?PacificArts,Nos 22 and23, pp.1-10.
CONKEY, MARGARETW. andCHRISTINE A. HASTOFF (eds). 1990.The Uses ofStyleinArchaeology. Cam-
bridge:CUP.
GELL, ALFRED. 1992.The Technology of Enchantment and theEnchantment of Technology.In Coote,Jeremy
andAnthony Shelton(Eds). Anthropology and Aesthetics. Oxford:ClarendonPress,pp.40-63.
1998. ArtandAgency:AnAnthropological Theory.Oxford:ClarendonPress.
KAEPPLER, ADRIENNE L. 1989. Artand Aesthetics. In Alan Howardand RobertBorofsky. Developments in
PolynesianEthnology. Honolulu:Univ.ofHawaiiPress,pp.211-240.
LAMBERT,SUSAN. 2001. Printsand Techniaues. London:V&A Publications.
LAYTON, ROBERT. 2003. ArtandAgency:A Reassessment. TheJournaloftheRoyalAnthropological Institute.
(N.S.) 9, 447-464.
LOUNSBURY, F.G. 1964. A FormalAccountof Crow-and Omaha-TypeTerminologies. In Goodenough,W.
(Ed.), Explorationsin CulturalAnthropology . New York:McGrawHill.
OLIVER, DOUGLAS L. 1974.AncientTahitianSociety.3 vols.Honolulu:University PressofHawaii.
OSBORNE, HAROLD. 1978.TheOxfordCompaniontoArt.Oxford:ClarendonPress.
SAHLINS, M. D.1966. Poor Man, Rich Man, Big-man,Chief:PoliticalTypesin Melanesiaand Polynesia.In I.
HogbinandL.R. Hiatt(eds). ReadingsinAustralian and PacificAnthropology. Melbourne:Melbourne
University Press,pp.159-79.
SMITH,BERNARD. 1989.EuropeanVisionand theSouthPacific.(2nded.). Melbourne: OxfordUniversity Press.
THOMAS, NICHOLAS. 1998. Foreword,to Geli, A. Artand Agency:An Anthropological Theory.Oxford:
ClarendonPress,pp.vii-xiii.
WEINER,ANNETTE. 1992.InalienablePossessions:theParadoxofKeeping-while- giving.Berkeley:University
ofCalifornia Press.
WOLLHEIM, RICHARD. 1979. Pictorial
Style:Two Views. In B. Lang (ed.) The Conceptof Style.[Philadel-
phia?]:University ofPennsylvania Press.
324