Maurizio Lazzarato-Signs and Machines - Capitalism and The Production of Subjectivity-The MIT Press (2014)
Maurizio Lazzarato-Signs and Machines - Capitalism and The Production of Subjectivity-The MIT Press (2014)
Maurizio Lazzarato-Signs and Machines - Capitalism and The Production of Subjectivity-The MIT Press (2014)
<e>
SIGNS AND MACHINES
CAPITALISM AND THE PRODUC TION OF SUBJE C TIVITY
Maurizio Lazzarato
<B>
SEMIOTEXT(E) FOREIGN AGENTS SERIES
Published by Semiotext(e)
Cover art by Elad Lassry, Girl (Green/Red), 201 1 . C-print, painted frame,
14.5 x 1 1 .5 x 1 .5 inches.
Courtesy of David Kordansky Gallery, Los Angeles, CA.
ISBN: 978-1-58435-130-6
Distributed by The MIT Press, Cambridge, Mass. and London, England
Introduction 7
3. Mixed Semiotics 95
Notes 251
lntroduction1
7
psychologically decimated, with "no material assets-no raw materials,
no reserve capital." What explains the economic miracle? "They
rebuilt a prodigious 'capital of subjectivity' (capital in the form of
knowledge, collective intelligence, the will to survive, etc.). Indeed,
they invented a new type of subjectivity out of the devastation itsel
The Japanese, in particular, recovered aspects of their archaic sub
jectivity, converting them into the most 'advanced' forms of social
and material production. [ . . . ]The latter represents a kind of indus
trial complex for the production of subjectivity, one enabling a
multiplicity of creative processes to emerge, certain of which are,
however, highly alienating."2
Capitalism "launches (subjective) models the way the automobile
industry launches a new line of cars."3 Indeed, the central project of
capitalist politics consists in the articulation of economic, techno
logical, and social flows with the production of subjectivity in such a
way that political economy is identical with "subjective economy."
Guattari's working hypothesis must be revived and applied to current
circumstances; and we must start by acknowledging that neoliberalism
has failed to articulate the relation between these two economies.
Guattari further observes capitalism's capacity to foresee and
resolve systemic crises through apparatuses and safeguards that it
came to master following the Great Depression. Today; the weakness
of capitalism lies in the production of subjectivity. As a conse
quence, systemic crisis and the crisis in . the production of
subjectivity are strictly interlinked. It is impossible to separate
economic, political, and social processes from the processes of
subjectivation occurring within them.
With neoliberal deterritorialization, no new production of
subjectivity takes place. On the other hand, neoliberalism has
destroyed previous social relations and their forms of subjectivation
Introduction I 9
dazzling subjectivations (cognitive workers, "manipulators of
sy mbols," creative self-starters and luminaries). The crisis has
brought debt and its modes of subjection to the fore in the figure of
the indebted man. Now that the promises of wealth for all through
hard work, credit, and finance have proved empty, the class struggle
has turned to the protection of creditors and owners of "securities."
In the present crisis, in order for the power of private property to
assert itself, the articulation of "production" and the "production
of subjectivity" relies on debt and the indebted man.
Obviously, we are talking about a negative subjection, the most
obvious indication that flows of knowledge, action, and mobility,
although continually solicited, lead only to repressive and regressive
subjectivation. The indebted man, at once guilty and responsible for
his lot, must take on himself the economic, social, and political
failures of the neoliberal power bloc, exactly those failures externalized
by the State and business onto society.
It is no longer a matter of innovation, creativity, knowledge,
or culture but of the "flight" of owners of capital whose "exodus"
consists in their plundering the welfare state while refusing to pay
taxes. In this way, the univocity of the concept of production (both
economic and subjective) allows us to see that the financial crisis is
not only about economics, it is also a crisis of neoliberal govern
mentality whose drive to turn every individual into an owner, a
business, and a shareholder has miserably run aground with the
collapse of the American real-estate market.
Japan is emblematic of the impossibility of resolving the crisis
afflicting the country since the 1990s without a new model of
subjectivity. Like every other country in the world, Japan is now
post-Fordist, y et more than any other country it has had the greatest
difficulty replacing the Fordist "capital of subjectivity" (full
Introduction I 1 1
simply has nothing to do with the other. Instead, they assert the
need to conceive a radical separation between "economics" and
"subjectivity," thereby developing an economistic conception of
the economy and an utterly "political" or "idealist" conception of
subjectivity.
Despite the rise of public and private apparatuses for the pro
duction, adaptation, and control of subjectivity, apparatuses whose
authoritarianism has only intensified during the crisis, we must insist
with Guattari that subjectivity still has no ground or means for
subjectivation. "This is a major crisis. A crisis of what? In my opinion,
it is a major crisis because the problem that's at the tip of everyone's
tongue is the following: Shit, we've got to at least have a religion, an
idea! [ ... ] we can't leave everything up in the air like this!"4
But what does the concept of the production of subjectivity
entail? What is meant by subjectivation and, in particular, political
subjectivation?
In capitalism, the production of subjectivity works in two ways
through what Deleuze and Guattari call apparatuses [dispositiftj of
social subjection and machinic enslavement.
Social subjection equips us with a subjectivity, assigning us an
identity, a sex, a body, a profession, a nationality, and so on. In
response to the needs of the social division of labor, it in this way
manufactures individuated subjects, their consciousness, representa
tions, and behavior.
But the production of the individuated subject is coupled with
a completely different process and a completely different hold on
subjectivity that proceeds through desubjectivation. Machinic
enslavement dismantles the individuated subject, consciousness,
and representations, acting on both the pre-individual and supra
individual levels.
lntroduciion I 13
the production of subjectivity occurs. We will trace a cartography of
the modalities of subjection and enslavement, those with which we
will have to break in order to begin a process of subjectivation inde
pendent and autonomous of capitalism's hold on subjectivity, its
modalities of production and forms of life.
It is therefore essential to understand that the subjectivity and
subjectivations capitalism produces are meant for the "machine."
Not primarily for the "technical machine" but for the "social
machine," for the "megamachine," as Lewis Mumford calls it, which
includes the technical machine as one of its products.
What are the conditions for a political and existential rupture at
a time when the production ofsubjectivity constitutes the most fun
damental of capitalist concerns? What are the instruments specific
to the production of subjectivity such that its industrial and serial
production by the State and the corporation might be thwarted? What
model and what modalities of organization must be constructed for
a subjectivation process that joins micro- and macropolitics?
In the 1980s, Michel Foucault and Guattari each followed
different paths to arrive at the conclusion that the production of
subjectivity and the constitution of the "relation to the self" were
the sole contemporary political questions capable of pointing the
way out of the impasse in which we still continue to founder.
Each in their own way they revealed a new dimension irreducible
to power and knowledge relations. As the power of self-positioning
and existential affirmation (Guattari), the "relation to the self"
(Foucault) derives-in its double sense of originating in and
drawing off - from these relations. The subjective is not, however,
dependent on them. For Foucault, taking the "care of the self" as
one's starting point does not mean pursuing the ideal splendor of a
"beautiful life" but rather inquiring into the overlap of "an aesthetics
Introduction I 1 5
In his way, Guattari not only remained faithful to Marx but to
Lenin as well. Of course, the methods for the production of subjec
tivity that came out of Leninism (the party, the conception of the
working class as vanguard, the "professional revolutionary," etc.) are
no longer relevant to current class compositions. What Guattari
retains from the Leninist experiment is the methodology: the need
to break with "social-democracy," to construct tools for political
innovation extending to the organizational modalities of subjectivity.
Just as the production of subjectivity cannot be separated from
"economics," it cannot be separated from "politics." How must we
conceive of political subjectivation? All political subjectivation
entails a mutation and a reconversion of subjectivity that affects
existence. It cannot only be political in the sense that both Ranciere
and Badiou give the term.
Subjective mutation is not primarily discursive; it does not
primarily have to do with knowledge, information, or culture since it
affects the nucleus of non-discursivity; non-knowledge, and non
acculturation lying at the heart of subjectivity. Subjective mutation is
fundamentally an existential affirmation and apprehension of
the self, others, and the world. And it is on the basis of this non
discursive, existential, and affective crystallization that new languages,
new discourses, new knowledge, and a new politics can proliferate.
We will first examine this question from a specific perspective:
the paradoxical relationship that the discursive-that is, what is
actualized in language but also within the spatiotemporal coordinates
of knowledge, culture, institutions, and the economy-maintains
with the non-discursive, as the focal point of self-production, self
positioning, and existential affirmation.
The same critical theories that neglect the machinic specificity
of capitalism also fail to problematize the relationship between the
Introduction I 1 7
Further, they enact "a radical divorce" (Guattari) between
pragmatic linguistics and existential pragmatics, between the
semiotic logic that produces meaning and the pragmatics that
produces existence and political rupture.
In the act of enunciation (in the same way as in every act of
creation), a power of self-positioning, self-production, and a capacity
to secrete one's own referent emerges, a power which has little to do
with Saussurean "speech," the Lacanian "signifier," or the perfor
matives and speech acts of analytic philosophy.
A force of self-affectation, self-affirmation, and self-positioning
doubles power and knowledge rela,_tions, defying the powers and
knowledge in place. It provides the conditions for rupture as well as
for processes of political subjectivation-indeed, for processes of
subjectivation tout court. The rules governing the production of the
self are those "optional" and processual ones invented by constructing
"sensible territories" and by a singularization of subjectivity (Guattari),
by creating the alterity of "an other life" and "an other world"
(Foucault). Hence the recourse, not to cognitive, linguistic, and
informational methods and paradigms, but to political, ethical
aesthetic approaches and paradigms-the "aesthetic paradigm" of
Guattari and the "aesthetics of existence" of Foucault.
Only as a mutation of subjectivity, as the crystallization of a new
existence (Guattari), gains consistency can one attempt a new
relationship to economic, linguistic, technical, social, and commu
nicational flows.
To produce a new discourse, new knowledge, a new politics,
one must traverse an unnamable point, a point of absolute non
narrative, non-culture, and non-knowledge. Thus the (tautological)
absurdity of conceiving production as the production of knowledge
by way of knowledge. Theories of cognitive and cultural capitalism
Introduction I 1 9
causes and conditions behind by creating new possibilities. It
derives and, paradoxically, does not derive from history.
Viewed through the lens of post-May '68 struggles rather than as
a historical reconstruction, the "Leninist rupture" is characterized by
the coexistence of different orders: the order of causes and the order
of desire (the existential, non-discursive dimension), the order of
"preconscious investments'' governed by causes and aims and the order
of "unconscious revolutionary investments" which have as their cause
a rupture in causality, the condition for opening new possibilitiess.
Such an opening, "prepared by the subterranean work of causes,
aims, and interests," only becomes r through something of another
order, by "a desire without aim or cause."10
Revolutionary possibility can always be identified by the impos
sibility it makes real, and by the fact that a process erupts secreting
other systems of reference at the very place where the world was
once closed. As in all creation (whether artistic, scientific, or social),
the suspension of the ordinary course of things first of all affects
subjectivity and its forms of expression by creating the conditions
for new subjectivation. This process must be problematized. 11
Although the forms of Leninist organization are today neither
possible nor desirable, the "break with causality," the turn from
the expected course of things, the impossible that becomes real,
the organization and metamorphosis of subjectivity-these
remain the burning questions of all revolutionary movements.
And even though one can and must assign the objective factors
[. . . ] within causal series that made such a rupture possible, the
Bolshevik group [ ...] becomes aware of the immediate possi
bility of a proletarian revolution that would not follow the
anticipated causal order of the relations of forces. 12
Introduction I 21
conceiving and practicing politics (micropolitics: young workers,
minorities, the women's movement, etc.). Today, with the party
gone and unions completely integrated into capitalist logic,
macropolitical action and its forms of organization, based on an
irreducible multiplicity of subjectivation processes, are at the heart
of our urgent underlying question: "What is to be done?"
23
production of wealth (and production, period) operates at the
intersection of two heterogeneous power apparatuses-social
subjection and machinic enslavement. What is called economy is
the assemblage of this dual investment of subjectivity such that,
as Guattari puts it, "one must enter the field of subjective economy
and stop concentrating only on political economy," which was
incapable of realizing the full ramifications of its discoveries.
By assigning us an individual subjectivity, an identity, sex,
profession, nationality, and so forth, social subjection produces
and distributes places and roles within and for the social division of
labor. Through language it creates a signifying and representational
web from which no one escapes. Social subjection produces an
"individuated subject" whose paradigmatic form in neoliberalism
has been that of "human capital" and the "entrepreneur of the sel"
The last avatar of individualism, which has made the person the
center and source of action, emerged with the financial crisis during
which the injunction to become "human capital" has been trans
formed into the negative and regressive figure of the indebted man.
The individual is still guilty and responsible for his fate except that
today he is fated to debt.
Foucault describes the mode of governmentality of "subjects"
who must think of and produce themselves as actors in their own
assignations such that domination issues from the subjects them
selves (self-exploitation, self-domination). The user's, worker's,
and consumer's actions and the divisions man/woman, parent/
child, teacher/student, and so on, are invested with knowledge,
practices, and norms---whether sociological, psychological, managerial,
or disciplinary-which solicit, encourage, and motivate the pro
duction of individuals consequently alienated within the social and
gendered division of labor.
In machinic enslavement lie the novelty, the secret, and the power
specific to capitalism, which exploits the molecular, pre-personal,
and supra-personal activities of subjectivity. The enormous produc
tivity and potentiality of science, and of the capitalist economy, have
to do with the nature of these machinic assemblages. Indeed,
capitalist machinic enslavement is a "resurrection'' of what Lewis
Mumford calls the "myth of the machine," the archaic mega
machine-the Egypt of the pyramids. For Deleuze and Guattari,
the latter marks the first emergence of enslavement, in which
" human beings themselves are constituent pieces of a machine they
compose among themselves and with other things (animals, tools)
under the control and direction of a higher unity."9
The archaic megamachine is not primarily technological but
social since it is composed of "a multitude of uniform, specialized,
interchangeable" parts "rigorously marshaled together and coordi
nated in a process centrally organized and centrally directed"10
and of very simple technical machines: the ramp and the lever (the
wheel, pulley, and screw had not yet been invented). Mumford's
megamachine is, along with Simondon's technical objects and the
celibate machines of the avant-gardes (Duchamp), one of the
theories Deleuze and Guattari appropriate in their own thought.
One finds in Mumford's work many of the elements that deter
mine the complex conditions for their concept of the machine:
human flows whose "mechanization" long preceded the mecha
nization of human tools; the machinic phylum of the " 'simple
machines' of classical mechanics" (the result of previous inventions
and practices); sign flows ( "translating speech into graphic record
not merely made it possible to transmit impulses and messages
55
crisis in the production of subjectivity, which can hardly be
explained by technical, economic, or political processes.
Subjectivity, subjectivation, processes of subjectivation, and
subjection are all concepts that consistently appear in critical thought
since the 1 960s (Foucault, Ranciere, etc.), covering different and
often contradictory ideas. In this regard Felix Guattari, who went
further in the conceptual problematization and cartography of the
features and modalities of the production of subjectivity, points to
several pitfalls it is best to avoid.
First of all, the structuralist impasse, which reduces subjec
tivity to the mere result of ..signifying operations: "What the
structuralists say isn't true; it isn't the facts of language or even
communication that generate subjectivity. At a certain level, it is
collectively manufactured in the same way as energy, electricity,
or aluminum."2
The production of subjectivity puts into play something very
different from linguistic performance: ethological, fantasmic
dimensions, economic, aesthetic, and physical semiotic systems,
existential territories, and incorporeal universes, all of which are
irreducible to a semiology of language. The concept of the substance
of expression must be pluralized in order to bring to the fore the
extralinguistic, non-human, biological, technological, aesthetic, and
machinic substances of expression.
The second pitfall comes from phenomenology and psycho
analysis, whose concepts reduce "the facts of subjectivity to
drives, affects, intra-subjective apparatuses and relations," which
Guattari also defines as "intersubjective drivel."3 Technical
(digital, communicational, media) and social machines modu
late and format subjectivity by acting not only within memory
and sense but also within the unconscious. This non-human,
The child not only learns to speak a native language; he also learns
the codes for walking down the street, a certain kind of complex
relationship to machines, electricity, etc. [ . . . ] and these different
codes have to be made part of the social codes of power. This
aspect of general exchange among semiotics is essential to the
capitalist economy. [ . . . ] The initiation to capital above all entails
this semiotic initiation to various codes of translatability and to
the corresponding invariant systems.22
taking power. 30
jaguar") are no longer found only among the mad, children, artists,
and poets ("I is an other") . The linguistic signifying machine
operates and imposes "exclusive disjunctions" (you are a man, you
are a woman, etc.) which prevent becomings, heterogeneous
processes of subjectivation; it recognizes only identities defined by
these significations (man, chd, animal, etc.) and by specialized
functions (worker, boss, student, etc.). The structure of the modern
signification machine opposes inclusive-disjunctive syntheses, con
centrating all subjectivity and expressivity in man by reducing the
other (nature, things, the cosmos) to an object.
The subjectivity of capitalist societies is not only an autonomous
and independent subjectivity confined to the individual, it is also a
subjectivity fragmented into compartmentalized and "interiorized
faculties" (Reason, Understanding, Sense, etc.) each in opposition to
the other according to the dualisms of the sensible and the intelligible,
the real and the imaginary, thought and extension.
In primitive societies "an individual's psychism was not orga
nized into interiorized faculties but was connected to a range of
expressive and practical registers in direct contact with social life and
the outside world."35
The individuated subject of capitalist societies is endowed with
an "individuated body," with a "naked body," a "shameful body,"
which must be made part of domestic and social economies. The
naked body, the shameful body dosed in on itself like language,
autonomous and independent, detached from the multiplicity of
3. Asignifying Semiotics
M ixed Semiotics
95
1. The Trader's Machinic Subjectivity
Mixed Semiotics I 97
him, making him act and decide without necessarily accessing
consciousness. What type of subjectivity and what semiotics are
mobilized by these sites of proto-subjectivation determined by
diagrams, computers, and so on? Foremost, as with primitive
peoples, the insane, and children, the subjectivity is transitivist,
transindividual, and the semiotics symbolic.
In order to account for the subjective behavior involved in asset
pricing, convention theory and cognitive capitalist theory presup
pose agents' mimetic behavior. The intersubjectivity, language,
and communication of the mimetic relationship are supposed to
supplant the methodological individualism of homo economicus,
founded on rationality and sovereignty. Unfortunately, mimetic
behavior is irreducible to linguistic, cognitive, or communicational
intersubjectivity.
Without in the least partaking of the philosophical theory that
underpins the notion of financial behavior as mimetic behavior, we
must emphasize that for its creator, Rene Girard, mimetic emula
tion is above all the emulation of desire. One does not imitate ways
of being, one does not imitate ideas or the "cognitive basis" of the
"other"; one imitates desire. If mimesis implies the emulation of
desire, its constitution and dissemination/circulation cannot,
however, be explained by communication, language, or cognition,
because affects undermine precisely the communicational, informa
tional, linguistic, and cognitive models.
"Mimetic rationality'' is not linguistic-cognitive-far from it.
For affect suspends the speaker/hearer enunciative dichotomy.
'Meet sticks to subjectivity," but as much to the enunciator's
subjectivity as to that of his addressee. Spinoza, Guattari suggests,
perfectly understood this transitivist feature of affect: " ('from the
fact of conceiving a thing like ourselves to be affected with any
lvlixed Semiotics I 99
a rational subject who controls information and his choices, homo
economicus is a mere terminal of asignifying, symbolic, and signi
fying semiotics and of non-linguistic constituents which for the
most part escape his awareness. We are not only well beyond the
individualism and rationality of homo economicus, we have moved
beyond "cognitive capitalism."
In this context, signifying semiologies, discourses, cognitive
activities, fulfill a specific function: controlling the deterritorialization
and desubjectivation the diagrammatic semiotics and symbolic
semiologies define. The individual subject, his sovereignty and
rational behavior, ruined by the real workings of the stock market,
must literally be reconstructed, refabricated, by signifying semiolo
gies, communication, and cognition. The discourse of economists,
media, experts, and judges3 create the belief that it is indeed the
individual subject who acts and who thus must be compensated as
a result. Through the semiotics of signification, stories, information,
and commentary are produced which construct and legitimate the
function and the role of these "individuated subjects" (traders) in
public opinion.
Signifying semiologies cannot be reduced to "ideology."4 Narra
tives and discourses that speak of homo economicus, the freedom of
the entrepreneur, the self-regulating power of the markets, and so
on, have no superstructural function, since it is sign machines that
produce a specific and fundamental commodity: the individuated
subject. The "ideological force" of signifying semiologies does not
lie in the fact that it prevents us from thinking or in mere manipu
lation (although it can do both as well), but rather in its ability to
effect a mutation in subjectivity. The refrains of neoliberalism (be an
asset, be a self-starter, get rich, etc.) are there to ensure this happens.
The latter do not hide a reality from us; instead, they endow us with
In the last years of his life, Guattari often drew on Daniel Stern's book
The Interpersonal World of the Infant5 in order to map a cartography
of the semiotic, affective, and existential components that contribute
to the production of subjectivity. In Stern's work, preverbal subjec
tivity, expressed through asignifying symbolic semiotics, is described
in its problematic relationship to the linguistic "social machine."
According to Guattari, linguistic theory and analytic philosophy
systematically ignore or gloss over this pre-individual subjectivity,
which is at the root of all modes of subjectivation.
Stern's book undermines the unity of the subject by enumerating
the multiplicity of "selves," semiotics, relations, and affects, espe
cially preverbal ones, constituting him. The approach proves
particularly enlightening when trying to apprehend the existential
and self-referential dimension at the heart of Guattari's theory of
subjectivity. Far from passing solely through language, cognition, or
cornmullication, the relation to the selfpresupposes a self-positioning
that is existential, pathic, and affective prior to being linguistic or
cognitive. Subjective mutation is not primarily discursive, because it
Mixed Semiotics I 1 01
is situated at the focal point of (existential) non-discursivity at the
core of subjectivity. It is starting from this existential dimension that
there is an emergence, a processualicy, a taking on of consistency, of
subjectivity. Only from this asignifying, unnamable, and incommu
nicable core can there be signification, language, and narrative. The
point has important political implications since this same pre
individual subjectivity is brought to bear by capitalist machinic
enslavements to exploit affects, rhythms, movements, durations,
intensities, and asignifying semiotics.
the ultimate reservoir that can be dipped into for all creative
Mixed Semiotics I 1 03
experience."8 All learning and all creative acts depend on this sense
of emergent self "This domain of experience remains active during
the formative period of each of the subsequent domains of sense of
self" as well as during later learning and creative processes.
We have access to these modes of semiotization in childhood,
through psychosis, drug use, and certain altered states of consciousness,
but also through artistic creation, falling in love, political passions,
existential crises, and, even discursively, through philosophy.9
2. The Sense ofa "Core Self," the Sense ofa ''Subjective Self," and Sym
bolic Semiotics
The sense of a "core self' (the self as opposed to the other and the self
with the other) constitutes the experience of self and other as "entities"
with "a physical presence, action, affect, and continuity." The sense of
core self depends on "numerous interpersonal capacities."10 This is still
not a cognitive construction (for it occurs outside consciousness) but
rather an integration of experience and a "memory without words"
which provide the bases for all the more complex senses of self
According to Stern, the period spanning two to six months is
perhaps the most exclusively and intensely social period of the
infant's life (the social smile, vocalizations directed at others, the
mutual gaze, etc.) . 1 1
The sense of a subjective self occurs when the infant discovers
that he has a "mind" and that others do too, that experiences, con
tent, affects, and emotions are shareable (or not shareable) and can
be communicated without words because language is yet unavailable.
Self and other are no longer only core entities with a certain physical
presence, action, affect, and continuity; they are entities with
"internal and subjective states."
The fourth sense of self, the sense of a verbal self, has to do with the
junction and disjunction, the complementarity and gap, between the
verbal and nonverbal parts of subjectivity, between asignifying
symbolic semiotics and signifying semiologies. This is because the
emergence of language is the source of a cleavage between experience
as it is "lived" and as it is "represented."
If linguistic significations make our experiences with others
more easily shareable, they can also make certain parts of these same
Mixed Semiotics I 1 05
experiences inaccessible to others as well as to ourselves. The non
verbal and "global" part of experience and that part of experience
converted into words can very well coexist, the verbal part harmo
niously enriching and expanding lived (affective) experience. But
the latter may also be fractured, rendered poorly by language,
consequently forcing experience underground (repression). The
adult's words, "Oh, look at the yellow sunlight," specify, separate,
and fracture the amodal experience of the sunray the infant has.
"The paradox that language can evoke experience that transcends
words is perhaps the highest tribute to the power of language. But
those are words in poetic use; The words in our daily lives more
often do the opposite and either fracture amodal global experience
or send it underground."15 The three preverbal senses of self are
not steps in the formation of the verbal sel They remain inde
pendent centers of semiotic and subjective "production" and
continue to function in parallel with their own "autonomy'' and
their own semiotics.
According to Guattari, the way in which linguistics and psy
choanalysis conceive of the relationship between verbal and
nonverbal semiotics raises the same political problem. The theories
are informed by a model founded on the opposition between a raw
world of desire, drives, instinct, animality, and spontaneity, on the
one hand, and, on the other, a universe of social order, the symbolic,
law, and prohibition expressed by language and signifying semiotics.
The semiotic-linguistic model is in reality a political model. In the
same way as a supposedly undifferentiated economy of desire neces
sitates signifying, symbolic semiotics, the law, and taboos to provide
its structure, in the process of political subjectivation we need the
political party and its "democratic centralism" in order to structure
and discipline the spontaneity of subjectivities.
lvlixed Semiotics I 1 07
The point is not to devalue language and signifying semiotics, but
rather, as opposed to what linguistics and analytic philosophy do, to
place ourselves between the discursive and the non-discursive in order
to make enunciation and subjectivation "grow from the middle."
asignifying semiotics);
-the gestures and movements of the human body, etc. (symbolic
semiologies);
-the duration, movements, breaks in space and time, gaps,
sequences, etc., that make up asignifying "intensities."18
The cinema, whose effects derive above all from its use of asignifying
symbolic semiotics ("linkages, internal movements of visual
images, colors, sounds, rhythms, gestures, speech, etc."19), repre
sented for a brief moment the possibility of moving beyond
signifying semiologies, of bypassing personological individuations,
and opening up possibilities that were not already inscribed in
dominant subjectivations.
Film images cannot be directly encoded, marked out, and
framed by the syntagmatic and paradigmatic axes that ensure the
relative stability and invariance of meanings as in language.
With cinema, it becomes possible to rediscover the features of
pre-signifying semiotics in a post-signifying world. The cinema
does not put two components of expression (signifier/signified) into
play, but rather, as in primitive societies, "n": the images, sounds,
and words spoken and written (texts), movements, positions, colors,
rhythms, and so on. Depending on the component that prevails,
there are different modalities of reading and seeing a film. "It can be
seen through its colors or rhythms, through its images, through the
chain of affects it creates, and there is absolutely no univocal,
Mixed Semiotics I 1 09
necessary, or unmotivated relationship between a signifying chain
and the contents signified."20
As in primitive societies, images (symbolic semiotics) and
intensities, movements, intervals, temporalities, and velocities
(asignifying semiotics) reintroduce ambiguity, uncertainty, and
instability into denotation and signification. Expression once again
becomes polyvocal, multidimensional, and multireferential. "The
semiotic components of film glide by each other without ever
fixing or stabilizing themselves in a deep syntax of latent contents
or in transformational systems that would lead, superficially, to
manifest contents."21
The same impossibility of formalizing filmic language is analyzed
by Pasolini. For the Italian poet, the cinema as well as an important
part of human reality and of things themselves are expressed through
systems of signs, in other words, by nonverbal (images or "im-signs")
and non-human "languages." Images from memory and dream all
have the features of film sequences, they are "almost prehuman events,
or on the border of what is human. In any case, they are pregram
matical and even premorphological (dreams take place on the level of
the unconscious, as do mnemonic processes) ."22
The cinema is at once "fundamentally oneiric" and a "hypnotic
monstrum." The "irrational" elements of the language of film, "bar
barous, irregular, aggressive, visionary," cannot be eliminated; thus
the difficulty in establishing an "institutional film language."23
Indeed, these features, which Pasolini terms "irrational," make up
the modalities of expression of affects, intensities, velocities, etc.,
whose functioning depends on a logic other than that of the indi
viduated subject's rationality.
The cinema is thus capable, if for only an instant, of making us
"orphans: single, amnesiac, unconscious, and eternal," and removing
Mixed Semiotics I 1 1 1
The commercial cinema is "undeniably familialist, Oedipian,
and reactionary. [ . . . ] Its 'mission' is to adapt people to the models
required by mass consumption."25 If it is incapable of establishing
as invariable and stable significations as language, it can still pro
duce models of subjectivity that have the force of examples, the
obviousness of physical presence. Cinema acts on the depths of
subjectivity because it provides subjectivity with identities and
models of behavior by exploiting asignifying and symbolic semiotics.
In this way, it functions like "group psychoanalysis," normalizing
intensities, hierarchizing semiotics, and confining them within the
individuated subject.
Commercial cinema's effect on the unconscious is even more
powerful than that of psychoanalysis, since its unconscious, "popu
lated by cowboys and Indians, cops and robbers" (in other words, a
non-Oedipal consciousness, an unconscious equal to the world
around us), and the range of semiotic mechanisms it mobilizes
"directly connect with the spectator's processes of semiotization."26
The effect produced by commercial cinema and in turn by tele
vision has nothing to do with ideology, for it does not involve
reflexive consciousness and representation.
"All its irrational, elementary, oneiric, and barbaric elements
were forced below the level of consciousness; that is, they were
exploited as subconscious instruments of shock and persuasion''27
by the cultural industry and industry in general.
Consciousness-raising is not a sufficient response because
images affect us and organize themselves in direct relation with the
three "selves" preceding the linguistic self Asignifying, symbolic
semiotics do not act on consciousness but rather directly on "the
continuous variation and force of existing and potential action."
Mixed Semiotics I 1 1 3
enumerates a great variety and intensive use of asignifying semiotics
irreducible to speech. Up and down the hierarchy, asignifying
symbolic semiotics operate with signifying semiotics, but the rela
tive weight of one with respect to the other changes according to the
hierarchical level in which they function.
The board of directors does "political work when it sets the
organization's goals and strategies by providing the necessary
resources" ("capital, operating budget, and their allocation'') .31 The
board's "orders" are transmitted along the hierarchy, mobilizing the
most varied asignifying transactions. Speech would be insuffi
cient to organize the production "process" and powerless to
command and activate subjectivities.
"CEOs" give preliminary form to the generic objectives handed
down from the board of directors "in the form of 'development
plans,' 'ethical commitments,' 'quality policies,' 'cost-saving mea
sures,' 'authorization' 'management control,' 'digitalization,'
'marketing strategies,' 'IT systems,' 'advertising campaigns."'32
"Budget constraints" are also transformed into asignifying organi
zational elements: "budgets," "HR policies," "investment plans."
Under the CEOs, the work of "manager experts," to whom
upper management has entrusted the work of turning out instruc
tions and ensuring they are followed, "consists primarily in
transforming the abstract demands for 'total quality,' 'comfort,'
'attractiveness,' 'versatility,' or 'ethics' into 'specific organizational
requirements."' The translation of CEOs' choices is non-discursive.
Employees are not summoned the way Menenius Agrippa did the
plebeians in an attempt to convince them with his rhetorical arsenal
to put an end to their insubordination (Ranciere treats the episode as
a model of the egalitarian function special to language). In the capi
talist organization of work this is not how orders are transmitted.
Mixed Semiotics I 1 1 5
already had it in the 1 960s, private enterprise and marketing are the
ones responsible.
Mixed Semiotics I 1 1 7
over disciplinary and discursive control even as it employs them
both.39
Even "self-control," which measures the "subjective" investment
of the employee's "I"-one form of social subjection-is "main
tained by managerial tools (rankings, performance summaries,
etc.)." Within the service industry a large part of the employee's
work consists in rating, ranking, classifying ("We have to follow
procedures, jot down, draw up the indicators, validate, track [ . . ].
.
Mixed Semiotics / 1 1 9
The sociology (and the psychology) of work is imprisoned,
along with the rest of sociology, in anthropomorphic thought whose
"actors" are the "I" of the employee and the intersubjectivity of the
"collective" of workers. Deleuze and Guattari's anti-sociology frees
us from the political limits imposed by the reduction of labor orga
nization to the personology of social subjection.
Although the Marxist and Marxian theory of value has directly
or indirectly inspired the "progressive" part of sociology and indus
trial psychology, it in no way helps to escape this anthropomorphic
paradigm, for by distinguishing "living labor" from "dead labor," it
assigns all creativity and prouctivity to the former and relegates to
the latter a mere reproductive function. The distinction between
living labor and dead labor is appropriate only from the point of
view of social subjection. From the point of view of machinic
enslavement the sites of productivity, the vectors of enunciation, the
"for itself" (pour soi] and "for the other" (pour lautre], are not exclu
sively human. Machines, objects, procedures, diagrams, maps, and
so on, are not waiting for the "biblical" spirit of living labor to
restore life, mobility, and creativity to them. From the point ofview
of machinic enslavement, asignifying semiotics, objects, diagrams,
programs, and so on, contribute to production, creativity, innova
tion, in the same way as "people" do. Like machines, humans are
hybrids of "dead" and "living labor."
Machinic enslavement (or processes) precedes the subject and
the object and surpasses the personological distinctions of social
subjection. The latter, between living and dead, subject and
object, are the result of the reterritorialization process centered on
"man" and "labor." Sociology and industrial psychology operate a
humanist reterritorialization, a "humanization'' of work, which has
nothing progressive about it; indeed, it is identical to the social
Mixed Semiotics I 1 21
conceive a reterritorialization that leads to something other than
"work=value." We must seize the opponunity of desubjectivation
opened by machinic enslavement so as not to fall back on the
mythical-conceptual narratives of producers, workers, and employees.
This is one of our most urgent tasks if we are to invent new political
subj ectivations.
Mixed Semiotics I 1 23
significations. To take hold, to act on subjectivity, to determine
where and when to act, another type of process is needed, a molecular
process of subjectivity carried out through machinic enslavements
that circumvent representation, consciousness and signification.
Enslavement mobilizes both more and less than the person and the
individuated subject insofar as it intervenes at infra-personal and
supra-personal levels.
The two modes combine and complement one another: signifying
semiotics effectuate a molar processing of subjectivity that targets,
solicits, and interpellates consciousness, representation, and the
individuated subject, whereas asignifying semiotics effectuate a
molecular processing of the same subjectivity, mobilizing partial
subjectivities, states of non-reflexive consciousness, perceptual
systems, and so on. We should again emphasize that the destitution of
the subject and his semiologies through capitalist deterritorialization
"still does not invalidate human semiotics." The recourse to
"human" semiotics has a well-defined goal: to control and modulate
the processes of deterritorialization and reterritorialization realized
and assured by the asignifying semiotics of technico-sciemifi.c systems,
economics, and the collective resources of the State, destroying
previous existential territories, their values, and their way of life.
An example of the non-reactionary use of signifying semiotics is
that of the workers' movement. In the nineteenth century, the latter
was able to invent a revolutionary reterritorialization that, rather
than simply defending those whom capital was destroying, went
beyond capitalist deterritorialization: proletarian internationalism,
mutualization, and transnational class solidarity went beyond man
in the singular.
The ambiguities, uncertainties, and upheavals which periods of
great change, like ours, have experienced can be in part explained by
Mixed Semiotics / 1 25
This language of production and consumption-and not the lan
guage of man-appears as implacably deterministic. It only wants
to communicate functionally; it doesn't want to perorate or exalt
or convince-advertising slogans see to all that.
-Pier Paolo Pasolini, Heretical Empiricism
Pasolini is surely one of the first authors to have grasped the nature
and functioning of the sign systems of "neo-capitalism." The way in
which he frees himself from the limits oflinguistics and semiotics as
those fields developed over the nineteenth and twentieth centuries
intersects, at many points, witli the work of Guattari.
The "general semiology" he looks to elaborate recognizes the
continuity between nature and culture modernity had broken by
concentrating all subjectivity on the subject and by depriving the
object of all capacity for expression. Drawing on his experience in
film, he created, following Peirce's example, a new semiology
starting from the question of the image. By refusing to view the
latter as a production of the brain or the result of our system of
perception, he is able to overcome the dualisms of the image and
things, of consciousness and the object. The shot ofJerry Malaga's
hair and Umberto Eco's "real" eyes are part of the same continuum
of images that constitute a world that is, consequently, a cinema
in itself, a cinema in nature, a metacinema. As in the first chapter
of Bergson's Matter and Memory, the eye is in things themselves;
things are luminous by themselves with no consciousness illumi
nating them.
By situating the eye in things, cinema undermines the anthro
pomorphic conception of expression and action. Things express
themselves by themselves, constitute focal points of subjectivation;
they have a power of expression, a "luminosity," a capacity for
Mixed Semiotics I 1 27
Nonverbal discourse is "endowed with a persuasive power which
nothing verbal possesses."53 We can forget what we have been
taught through words but we can never forget what we have learned
through things.
The first image from Pasolini's life is a white curtain, and this
image spoke to him "objectively" and communicated the world of
his bourgeois childhood to him, the universe in which he was
living. We also find a curtain, although "red," in Guattari, which
also speaks, communicates, and expresses something.
Mixed Semiotics I 1 29
bypasses representation and the cognitive dimensions of subjectivity
to affect existence itsel
"It is above all in lived experience, in the existential, that we find
conformity to the model, and thus in the body and behavior as
well."60 The semiotic efficiency of nonverbal discourse is formidable
because it affects existential functions (Guattari) through domesti
cating effects: "What has to be educated, shaped, is the flesh itself,
the flesh as mold of the spirit."
These models of conduct and subjectivation are imposed
through a "physical language," a "language of behavior," which,
because nonverbal, "is no longer rhetorical in the humanist sense,
but pragmatic in the American sense."61
Neo-capitalism asserts the primacy of languages of clarity, pre
cision, functionality, and instrumental and pragmatic efficiency by
vacating them of the expressive dimension of humanist languages.
During a historical period in which verbal language has become
completely conventional and empty, subjected to the translatability,
the centralization, and the imposed equivalency of languages of
infrastructure, "this physical and gestural language is of decisive
importance."62
Neo-capitalism always acts and expresses itself through "mixed
semiotics," albeit by reversing the semiotic hierarchies in which
languages of superstructure (school, law, university, etc.) were
once dominant.
Mixed Semioiics I 1 31
models and the socioeconomic disparity produce the frustration,
violence, guilt, and aggressiveness that Pasolini identifies above all in
the behavior and presence of young people's bodies.
Before neo-capitalism incorporated and subordinated society in
its totality, the poor experienced a "segregation and marginality''
that allowed them to conserve, reproduce, and reinvent their culture
and forms of expression. The lurnpenproletariat of the 1 950s were
"blacks" in all but name, over whom the bourgeoisie limited its con
trol to police repression without bothering to "evangelize" them, in
other words, without bothering to impose cultural models or models
of subjectivation. From this point of view, fascism was still a part of
the world of the first capitalism, or more specifically; it stood at the
intersection, at the threshold, of the old and the new capitalism.
The languages of production and consumption represent a more
considerable internal revolution of fascist dictatorship.
lv1ixed Semiotics / 1 33
"the demands-let us say the liberal and progressive demands--of
liberty and, by making them its own, changed their nature and
made them worthless."68
The normalization, standardization, the leveling of ways of life
and behavior are no longer exclusively the result of discipline and
confinement (of which the Roman "borgate" were a paradoxical
example), but rather the work of the "most subtle, cunning, and com
plex'' technologies of power to which semiotics surely belong. The
latter express and institute consumer society's "mass hedonism," an
apparently more tolerant and liberal power that is in reality, according
to Pasolini, more intolerant and more destructive than fascism.
Mixed Semiotics I 1 35
The "characteristic feature of peasant civilizations is not their
finding nature 'natural,"'73 but rather "animated," subjectivated,
sacred. Where capitalism seeks to desacralize things and people, to
make them objects in order to measure, exchange, and capitalize
them, Pasolini looks instead to "resacralize them as much as possible."
Against the capitalist process that requires us to perceive only the
"inanimate, mechanical". appearance of things, against the "objective
and scientific" conception of reality, Pasolini opposes the "subjec
tive" consistency of the same reality.74
Some of this "religion" ended up in his "semiotics," for, as with
Guattari, there is no break, fissure, or abyss between sign and reality,
between content and expression, culture and nature. Pasolini's
animism is a kind of expressionism since the sign is immanent to
the real. In his polemic with Umberto Eco, Pasolini asserted that his
semiotics does not naturalize cultural codes but "transforms nature
into cultural phenomena: it transforms all life into speech."75
Nature as culture is expressive nature; it speaks to itself because
there is a "continuum without any solution of continuity" between
a person who says "oak tree" and the oak tree itsel The latter is not
the referent of the sign "oak tree," but a sign itself, an iconic sign,
just as the living person is not the referent of the sign "person," but
a "living-iconic" sign itsel A person and an oak tree are the "im
signs" of reality which cinema merely reproduces.
Subjectivated nature, animated culture, is a "Vedic-Spinozan'' God,
says Pasolini, which speaks with itsel Everything that exists, whether
plant or rock, expresses, sings, the glory of this immanent "God."76
Even if man were to lose his "imperialist" claim to be endowed
with what all other existents lack-the power of enunciation and
expression-"the nonverbal is nothing other than another ver
baliry" such that the signs of verbal languages do no more than
Mixed Semiotics I 1 37
classical humanist ideals" and of being lost in what Pasolini calls the
"pragma'' of languages of infrastructure. Along with other audiovi
sual techniques, cinema seems to be the language of this pragma; it
seems to function in complete harmony with capitalist deterrito
rialization. But cinema can also represent a chance for salvation,
a possibility for a change of course, precisely because it expresses this
pragma-"and it expresses it from the inside; by producing itself, by
taking it as its starting point, by reproducing it."77 The cinema
machine is completely inside the real. But what makes it an apparatus
for subjection and enslavement can also be turned into new processes
for subjectivation provided that one recognize the nature of
machinic assemblages, that one abandon the anthropological and
humanist perspective that imbues so much of critical thought.
The immanent power of im-signs prefigures the formidable
political power of audiovisual machines like television. Signs do not
exist in the world of superstructures but make up operative semiotics,
power signs, which act on both the real and on subjectivity.
Action-images can also sing the glory of the "Lord," like the
little birds in The Hawks and the Sparrows, in other words, they can
sing the emergence of a new political subjectivity or sing the glory
of capital, that is, vulgarity, arrogance, and the impotentized power
of the machinic image like Berlusconi's, whose rise Pasolini had
anticipated with surprising lucidity.
1 39
whose rise is directly proportional to the intensity of the conflict,
intermittent workers have asked themselves, on the one hand, what
special experience and what legitimacy the experts have that allow
them to develop and build knowledge with regard to their practices.
On the other hand, they have questioned what the experts "can do,"
in other words, the ways in which the experts participate in decision
making and in the socioeconomic choices that bear on labor,
employment, and unemployment conditions.
The second set of questions the motto raises reflect on the Coor
dination's own practices: ''"What do we know?" and "What can we
do?" In other words: What is the value and import of our experiences
and our words in the production and distribution of knowledge
about us? Why are our words and knowledge limited and niive and
thus disqualified while "specialist" knowledge represents "objectivity"
and "universality"? What power do we have as a group, a collective,
an association, to play a part in the decisions that concern us? Why
is our speech institutionally termed "non-political"?
In short, the motto "We are the experts!" puts into question the
composition and legitimacy of the assemblage that "knows" and the
composition and legitimacy of the assemblage that "decides." The
issue can be put like this: "Why don't we have the right to partici
pate in the collective arrangement that problematizes and explores
the possibilities our work, employment, and unemployment repre
sent? And who has the right and the legitimacy to make decisions
about our lives?"
The mobilization of intermittent workers seems to follow the
two paths typical of "minority" struggles which question both the
procedures of the production of democracy and the procedures of
the production of knowledge. The fight against cultural-labor
market reforms constitutes a critique of the knowledge produced by
Problemati.zation
intermittent work."12 The assertion neglects the fact that over the
last thirty years insecurity has also spread to all sectors of the economy.
In any case, his remarks are disproven by the reality of those working
in the job market's cultural sector who are not covered by intermittent
workers' unemployment insurance. I 3
I n professions whose .?.ctivities d o not provide the rights of
intermittent employment the same (but worse) phenomena of
underemployment and insecurity have also emerged. Without a
compensation regime like that of intermittent workers', individuals
either have recourse to basic welfare benefits or must take on several
jobs in order to survive. To turn Menger's viewpoint on its head, we
might say that if inequality is more acute in these sectors of the
cultural job market (and in every sector where discontinuous
employment exists), it is precisely because of the absence of a com
pensation regime that accounts for the discontinuity of employment
and the forms of work and training in a flexible economy. Poverty,
underemployment, and enormous disparities in income are not a
function of the intermittent regime but of the flexible organization
of the culture industry and the way its job market functions.
What is happening here is what has already happen:ed in other
parts of the economy over the last thirty years: a policy of full
employment (creating "real," stable, full-time jobs) that neglects the
actual conditions of production and divides and fragments the job
market by creating a growing disparity among incomes. It serves
only to further differentiate, to further multiply, inequalities and thus
I know very well that people in favelas couldn't care less about
psychoanalysis, Freud, or Lacan. But the abstract machines of
subjectivation produced by psychoanalysis through the media,
magazines, films, and so on, are certainly also present in what
takes place in the favelas.
-Felix Guattari, Molecular Revolution in Brazil
"
has to say. Try as one might, the entire interpretive and subjectivation
machine "exists to suppress the conditions of real expression."25
The more you express yourself; the more you speak, the more you
become part of the interactivity of the communication machine,
the more you give up what it is you have to say because the com
municational apparatuses cut you off from your own collective
assemblages of enunciation and connect you to other collective
assemblages (television) which individualize you as a split subject, as
a double subject-both the cause and effect of utterances.
Psychoanalysis experiments with techniques for controlling and
producing subjectivity. By concentrating on the enunciation rather
than utterances, these techniques then migrate to other domains,
especially the media, management, the individual monitoring of the
unemployed and welfare recipients, and so on: "While, to achieve
their ends, religions act by direct suggestion, by the imprint of
standardized representations and statements, at least to begin with
psychoanalysis gives free reign to a certain individual expression
[ . . . ] . While religion, dare I say it, straitjackets subjectivity in the
open air, psychoanalysis gets rid of some of the ballast of statements
in order to concentrate its efforts on remodeling enunciation. [ . ] . .
1 69
In order to account for the political function of language, both
the theories of certain feminists in the United States and post
operaist theories in Europe draw on analytic philosophy - and
especially on performatives in such a way that understanding
linguistic agency seems to me very difficult. Since the mid-1 990s
we have seen a return in force of analytic philosophy and Saussurean
linguistics at a time when few would have expected it given the post
structuralist critiques of the 1 960s and 70s and the political
critiques of the semiotics of power.
The first and foremost criterion for the finalization of the utterance
is the possibility of responding to it or, more precisely and broadly,
of assuming a responsive attitude toward it (for example, executing
an order) . This criterion is met by a short everyday question, for
example, "What time is it?" (one may respond to it), an everyday
request that one may or may not fulfill, a scientific statement with
which one may agree or disagree (partially or completely), or a
novel, which can be evaluated as a whole. 16
5. Discursive Strategies
(1) the phonic side of the word, the musical constituent proper; (2)
the referential meaning of the word (with all its nuances and varia
tions); (3) the constituent of verbal connections (all the relations
and interrelations that are purely verbal); (4) the intonational (on
the psychological plane-the emotional-volitional) constituent of
the word, the axiological directedness of the word that expresses the
diversity of the speaker's axiological relations-ethico-political and
more specifically social values (pre-individual voices and post
personal social voices); (5) the feeling of verbal activeness, the
feeling of the active generation of signifying sound (included here
are all motor elements-articulation, gesture, facial expressions,
etc.-and the whole inner direcredness of my personality).32
With Bakhtin, we can push our critique still further. In reality, what
precedes the subject is not language, grammar, and their rules, but
what Bakhtin calls "speech genres." We can only learn language by
way of "chains of concrete utterances" whose use, in differentiated
verbal spheres, develops relatively stable types. We learn to speak, we
"become a subject" not through grammar and syntax, but through
immersion in these genres of which the first are those of colloquial
discourse.
Speech genres operate at the intersection oflanguage "structure"
(what is reproducible) and then each time singular enunciation
(what is non-reproducible). Through these language enters life and
life enters language.
straints and conventions have fallen away, one can take a special
unofficial, volitional approach to reality. [ . . ] Intimate speech is
.
The speaker does not find himself thrown into one space-time "satu
rated" with power one can escape solely through the dialectic
pirouettes of the work of the negative. Instead, he exists in a multi
plicity ofpower relatiom, in a great variety of space-time blocs in which
the voices and harmonics of standardized speech genres as well as
those of the "intimate and familiar" genres resound, in which rela
tionships among them and with utterances are conducive to creativity.
The development of space-time blocs of one or the other kind does
not depend on language (Saussure), grammar {Wittgenstein), or
performatives (Butler and Zizek), but on the micro- and macro
politics of language (the centrifugal and centripetal forces-of
which linguistics and structuralism are obviously a part-that shape
language) and on micro- and macro-politics tout court.
We have already said that the role of these others, for whom my
thought becomes actual thought for the first time (and thus also
rush headlong into it, even if they know that rationally it doesn't
hold water.
replace organizations.
201
Representative democracy has progressively transformed into a
mechanism of the State; political parties and trade unions have
become, through a process spanning the entire twentieth century, an
integral part of State institutions. The crisis affecting the West since
2007 has subsequently transformed political democracy and social
democracy. The former is completely subordinate to the logic of
neoliberalism to the extent that Marx's remark, which has too often
been ridiculed, that "the State is but a committee for managing the
common affairs of the bourgeoisie," has again become relevant. One
needs only change "bourgeoisie" to "creditors" and you have the func
tion of political representation in a nutshell. Even a weak political
democracy like ours is still too democratic for neoliberal politicians.
Social democracy, on the other hand, does no more than represent
and defend the social strata of full-time employees, and in particular
retirees, without, however, really managing to succeed.
The protests that have exploded more or less everywhere on
the planet reveal that within representative democracy "there are
no possible alternatives." In this regard, Guattari opens more than
one avenue for reflection, uniting a critique of representative poli
tics and a critique of the representational functions of language.
Signifying semiotics (language, writing) claim to "represent" all
other supposedly pre-signifying modes of expression (corporeal,
gestural, iconic) as well as asignifying ones (money, scientific
equations, etc.). The latter supposedly lack something only lan
guage can provide in the same way that citizens and the social
lack something that only political representation can provide.
In reality, linguistic "representation," just like political represen
tation, constitutes a seizure ofpower, overcoding, hierarchizing, and
subordinating other semiotics and other modes of expression. The
two forms of "representation" in the systems of signs and political
subjectivation. 26
"When the orchid 'chooses' the wasp in order to, in a way, co-opt
p
it into its re roduction process, the wasp becomes a part of the
The choice and the act both depend on machinism and on a certain
kind of consistency of assemblages. Guattari often cites Lenin's
example in order to account for the relationship between existential
(revolutionary) affirmation and the consistency of collective, social,
and political assemblages. The act is causa sui et non ex nihilo
because in a singular situation there are thresholds, "actance
crystals" (a certain political situation, a certain stage in the organi
zation of the party, a certain phase of subjectivation of the working
class, etc.), which, while they are not the cause of the act, deter
mine the consistency of "optional matter" [matiere a option]. In
schizoanalysis there is no determinism because the act occurs only
when there is a surplus value of possibilities, when there is a "possi
bility of playing a completely new tune, when there are relative
fields of potential creativity established."34 Potentialities and possibles
that must be created.
but in one case you have semiotic productions and in the other
subjective productions.46
225
every-and especially political-enunciation. At the core of this
new and original point of view bearing on non-representative
"democracy," one finds the relationship between the existential and
enunciation, between self-affirmation and political speech.
1. Two Equalities
2. "Truth-Telling" (Parrhesia}
The issue is not integrating people who, for the most part, are
from animality that the human being assened and manifested its
The Cynics dramatize not only the difference between equality and
inequality but also the practices of the "true life" and its institutions
by exhibiting a shameless life, a scandalous life, a life that manifests
itself as a "challenge and exercise in the practice of animality."
- September 20 1 0
251
I. Production and the Production of Subjectivity
2. The "user" is only one of the forms of implication, activation, and exploitation of
subjectivity in the service-relationship maintained by business or the Welfare State.
Hence the limirations of all theories that make "use" the cornerstone of politics (see,
for example, the otherwise remarkable work of Michel de Certeau).
3. Michel Foucault, Disdpline and Pzmish, trans. Alan Sheridan (New York: Vintage,
1995), 202. Foucault seems to forget this conception ofpower as a machine or diagram
when he rums to his analysis of the "relation to the self," "conduces," and the "govern
ment of men," when he moves .from disciplinary societies to societies of control.
10. Lewis Mumford, The Myth of the Machine: Technics and Human Development
(New York: Harcourt, Brace, and World, 1967), 196.
1 1 . Ibid., 195, 192.
12. Ibid., 196, 197.
13. Ibid., 199.
14. Ibid., 201.
15. Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, op. cit., 458. Transla
tion modified.
16. Obviously, the claim "we have never been modern" (Bruno Latour) is no more
than a catchphrase, since the modern individuated "subject" and "roan'' are absolutely
17. For Badiou and Ranciere, the production ofsubjectivity poses no difficulty at all
since, whether we are talking about Greek society, 1948, the New Deal, or today,
subjectivity is always the same. Thus the complete lack of analysis of the processes
of subjectivation capitalism entails, the formalism of the definitions of power rda
tions, and the return of a politics emptied of politics.
19. Theories that make "language primacy" the key co how semiotics operate in our
societies risk missing how capitalism actually works. Capital functions &om a mul
tiplicity of semiotics and not only signifying and linguistic semiotics, as the theories
of "cognitive" or "cultural" capitalism claim.
20. Felix Guattari, Les Annees d'hiver: 1980-1985 {Paris: Les Prairies Ordinaites,
2009), 294.
2 1 . When one is no longer able to measure labor in time, as is the case in most areas
today, "automatic" and "objective" evaluators are replaced by the subjective and
continuous (in schools for students and teachers, in hospitals and public health
systems for services and "workers," etc.). Note, for example, the confilcr that erupted
in France at universities and hospitals when new methods of evaluation were intro
duced, methods part and parcel of neoliberal techniques of government.
22. Friedrich Nietzsche, Twilight ofthe Idols, in The Anti-Christ, &ce Homo, Twilight of
the Idols, tranS. Judith Norman (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2005), 169.
23. Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, op. cit., 492.
24. With. regard to sociology's anthropomorphism, see Emile Durkheim, for whom
the "vital forces ofsociety" recall Marx's "live labor," whereas "things," among which,
apart &om "material objects," "must be included the products of previous social
activity-the law and the customs that have been established, and literary and artistic
monuments" play the role of "fixed capital." Objects and products "are the matter
Notes I 253
to which the vital forces are applied, but they do not themselves release any vital
forces. Thus the specifically human environment remains as the active factor." The
Rules ofSociological Method, trans. W. D. Halls (New York: The Free Press, 1982),
136. In the work of his rival, Gabriel Tarde, can be found the conditions for a non
anthropocentric sociology.
25. In the industrial production of a large corporation like Fiat, the human labor
force accounts for only 7.5% of general costs. Guattari points out that the impact
of a completely automatized business would affect society on the whole rather than
workers alone.
26. "The real control of machinic time, from the enslavement of human organs to
the productive assemblages, cannot be effectively measured based on a general
equivalent. We can measure a time of presence, a time of alienation, a period of
incarceration in a factory or prison; we cannot measure the consequences on an indi
vidual. We can quantify the apparent labor of a physicist in a laboratory, not the
productive value he creates." Felix Guattari, La Revol11tion moleettlaire (Paris: Union
generale d'editions, 1977), 74.
27. "I would argue that the differential relationship between capital flows and labor
flows generates a surplus value that it would be accurate to call human, since the
latter is produced through human labor; the differential relationship between
financing flows and revenue flows is productive of a surplus value that should
specifically be called financial surplus value; and, finally, the third relationship
between market flows and innovation (or knowledge) flows generates a properly
machinic surplus value." Gilles Deleuze, Seminar of February 2, 1972,
http://www.le-terrier.net/ deleuze/anci-oedipel OOOplateaux/0722-02-72.hrm. In
any case, innovation/ knowledge as such never produces value. "The market flow,
which includes innovation and through which innovation turns a profit, is of a
completely different kind and of a completely different, non-commensurate power
[ . . ] : it is not the same form of money that pays for innovation and, furthermore,
.
28. Whereas the theory of value in the first book of Marx's Capital is an additive
theory (the arithmetical sum of individual labor), and whereas surplus value is still
conceived as "human surplus value," in the Grnndrisse and Results ofthe Immediate
Process of Production, Marx describes machinic enslavement without, however,
developing a theory of "machinic" value. Guattari points out that the Marxian
30. Ibid.
3 1 . Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari, A Thousand Plateaus, op. cit., 492, 469.
34. "The notions o f a capitalist enterprise and a paid job have become inseparable
from the entirety ofthe 'social fabric,' which is itselfproduced and reproduced under
the control of capital." Ibid., 90.
35. That desire equals possibility implies a new and revolutionary definition of
desire. Desire only emerges when, following the rupture of previous equilibriums,
relations appear that had otherwise been impossible. Desire is always identifiable
through the impossibility it opens and the new possibilities it creates. It is the fact
that a process arises which secretes other systems of reference from a world that was
once closed. To clearly register the rupture with the classical conception of desire,
Guattari emphasizes its artificial "nature." Artificial, deterritorialized, and machinic
desire means that it is not a "natural" or "spontaneous" force. Desire is not the
equivalent of what Freud calls "drive" or of what Spinoza calls conarus (striving):
"Desire is never an undifferentiated instinctual energy, but itself results from a highly
developed, engineered setup rich in interactions." Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guat
tari, A Thousand Plateaus, op. cit., 215. "There are no internal drives in desire, only
assemblages." Ibid. 229. Desire is not a matter of fantasy, dream, or representation,
but rather of production. To desire always means to construct an assemblage; to
Notes / 255
desire always means to act in and for a collective or multiplicity. Desire is not a mat- .
ter of individuals and does not result from the simple interaction of individual drives
or conarus (intersubjectivity). It does not come from within the subject, it always
emanates from the outside, from an encounter, a coupling, an assemblage. The
classical conception of desire is abstract, because it identifies a desiring subject and
an object supposed to be desired, whereas one never desires someone or something
bur always a person or a thing within a whole constituted ofa multiplicity ofobjects,
relations, machines, people, signs, etc. It is the assemblage and not the individuated
subject that makes someone or something desirable. One never desires only a
person or a thing but also the worlds and possibilities one senses in them. To desire
means to construct an a.Ssemblage that unfolds the possibilities and worlds that a
thing or person contains. "We always make love with worlds." Gilles Deleuze and
Felix Guattari, Anti-Oedip11s, op. cir., 294. Desire is first of all collective though "col
lective" is not with the same as intersubjectivity. A collective assemblage is indeed "a
basis of relations and [ . . ] a means of assigning agents a place and a function; but
.
these agents are nor persons, any more.than these relations are inrersubjective." Ibid.,
47. Persons and things "intervene only as points of connection, of disjunction, of
conjunction of Hows and elements of this multiplicity." Ibid., 349.
1. "We (teachers, shrinks, social workers, journalists, etc.) are workers in an ultra
modern industry, an industry that provides the subjective raw material necessary for
all other industries and social activity." Felix Guattari in Jean Oury, Felix Guattari,
and Frani;:ois Tosquelles, Pratiques de l'instittttionnel et politique (Vigneux, France:
Mattice editions, 1985), 5 1 .
2 . Felix Guarrari, Les Annees d'hiver: 1980-1985 (Paris: Les Prairies ordinaires,
2009), 128.
6. "It is a question of rediscovering in the laws that govern that other scene (ein
andere Scha11platz), which Freud, on the subject of dreams, designates as being that
of the unconscious, the effects that are discovered at the level of the chain of mate
rially unstable elements that constitutes language: effects determined by the double
play of combination and substitution in the signifier." Jacques Lacan, Ecrits, trans.
Alan Sheridan (London: Routledge, 1989), 218.
9. Pier Paolo Pasolini, Heretical Empiricism, trans. Ben Lawton and Louise K.
Barnett (Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press, 1988), 63.
1 1 . Ibid., 15.
13. Hannah Arendt, The Human Condition (Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press, 1998), 23 1 .
14. Ibid., 4.
15. Ibid., 7.
16. Felix Guattari, Schizoanalytic Cartographies, trans. Andrew Gaffey (New York:
Bloomsbury, 2013), 2.
17. Felix Guattari, The Machinic Unconscious, op. cit., 43, 199. Translation modified.
1 8. The linguistic tum in philosophy and the social sciences, which concentrate on
human language {and, with Wittgenstein, the study of ordinary language, which
really changes nothing), completely neglecrs the specifically capitalist force of
asignifying semiotics, those expressed through the "languages of infrasrrucrures"
(economics, science, technique, aesthetics, etc.). The relationship between language
and forms of life, between ethics and enunciation, goes completely unnoticed.
19. Felix Guarrari, Moleett!ar Revolution, crans. Rosemary Sheed (New York: Pen
guin, 1984), 164-165.
26. Ibid., 63. Guattari quotes Alain Rey, "Langage et temporalites," Langages, vol. 8,
no. 32 (December 1 97.3): 58.
27. Gilles Deleuze, Felix Guarrari, A Thousand Plateaus, crans. Brian Massumi (Min
neapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1987), 76.
Notes I 257
28. The subjectivity produced by consciousness "cannot be assigned purely and
simply to the order of representation." Felix Guattari, Molecular Revolution, op. cit.,
126. It manifests "man's specific capacity for deterritorialization that enables him
to produce signs for no purpose: not negative signs, but signs to play about with
for fun, for art." Ibid., 127. The autonomy and arbitrariness of the play of signifi
cations have "contradictory consequences: [they open] possibilities for creativity,
but [ . . . ] also [produce] a subject cut off from all direct access to reality, a subject
imprisoned in a signifying ghetto." Ibid., 92.
29. Felix Guattari, The Anti-Oedipus Papers, trans. Kelina Goeman (Los Angeles:
Semiotext(e), 2006), 258.
30. Felix Guattari, Molecular Revolution, op. cit., 1 69-170. Translation modified.
33. Felix Guarrari, Molecular Revolution, op. cit., 93. Guattari quotes Benveniste's
Problemes de linguistique generale II CP:iru: Gallimard, 1974), 68.
34. "Personological: an adjective qualifying moral relations within the subjective
order. The emphasis on the role of persons, identities, and identifications characterizes
the theoretical concepts of psychoanalysis. The latter's Oedipus brings persons,
typified persons, into play: it reduces intensities, projects the molecular level of
investments onto a 'personological theater.'" Felix Guattari, Les Annies d'hiver:
1980-1985, op. cit., 295.
35. Felix Guattati, Chaosmo_sis, trans. Paul Bains and Julian Pefanis (Bloomington,
Indiana: Indiana University Press, 1995), 98-99.
36. Felix Guattari and Suely Rolnik, Micropolitiques (Paris: Les Empecheurs de
penser en rond, 2007), 401 .
38. Pier Paolo Pasolini, Heretical Empiricism, op. cit., 58n. Translation modified.
39. His engagement with Deleuze's thought begins with the concept of the
"machine," which Guattari elaborated in the 1960s. Most philosophers who, like
Badiou, fail to recognize Guattari's original contribution to his and Deleuze's work
together miss the hugely important political shift in the concept of the machine.
40. Felix Guattari, "Balance Sheet-Progtam for Desiring Machines," trans. Robert
Hurley, Anti-Oedip1lf, Semiotext(e), vol. 2, no. 3 (1977): 1 17-1 18.
41. Felix Guattari and Olivier Zahm, "Entretien avec Olivier Zahm;' Chimeres 23
(Summer 1994): SO.
42. Felix Guattari, Chaosmosis, op. cit., 39, 40. "It is said that machines do not repro
duce themselves, or that they only reproduce themselves through the intermediary of
43. "We are misled by considering any complicated machine as a single thing, in truth
it is a city or society, each member of which was bred truly after its kind. We see a
machine as a whole, we call it by a name and individualize it; we look at our own
limbs, and know that the combination forms an individual which springs from a
single center of reproductive action." Ibid., 285.
44. Ibid., 286.
45. "Labor is not fuse and foremost concerned with objects, it aims at the dynamics
that animate objects. Labor is a relation of forces: the action of forces meant to orient
other forces. It is not directly concerned with possession but with becoming. [ . . . ] In
work, there is not on one side the subject and on the other the object. To work, one's
senses must adapt to the play of forces animating the object. [. . .] In work, a pre
reflexive relationship with objects is manifest, which 'precedes consciousness' and
'undermines a clear separation between subject and object."' Philippe Davezies,
"Entre psychique et social, quelle place pour l'activice?" La sante mentale en actes
(Toulouse: ERES, 2005), 123.
46. Felix Guattari, Chaosmosis, op. cit., 36.
49. Money obviously has other functions that become clear through the interaction
with other semiotic systems: at the "symbolic" level, money functions as an imagi
nary subjection of the individual. His purchasing power "manipulates him nor only
according to codes of social srarus" but also according to perceptual and sexual
codes. The monetary economy "interacts constantly with the signifying encodings
of language, especially through legal and regulatory systems." Felix Guattari, La
Rivoltttion mo!iC11!aire (Fontenay-sous-Bois, France: Recherches, 1977), 295.
50. What one calls purchasing power is in fu.ct a non-power. Only the actions of the
dominated can transform these impotentized signs into signs ofpower by making them
function in a process ofsubjectivation independent of the economic law ofpurchasing
power. In the self-.valorization process of the dominated, they represent nothing other
than t!i.e independent self-positioning of their own production and reproduction.
5 1 . Felix Guattari, Schimanarync Cartographies, trans. Andrew Gaffey (New York:
Bloomsbury, 2013), 168.
52. Felix Guattari, MoleC11!ar Revolution, op. cir., 76. Translation modified.
Notes / 259
53. "On one paper surface we combine very different sources that are blended
through the intermediary of a homogeneous graphical language," i.e., the diagram.
Bruno Latour, Pandora's Hope: Essays on the Reality ofScience Studies (Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999), 66. Latour very hastily concludes that "we
have never been modern." Such is true only in terms of machinic enslavement. As
for social subjection, we have indeed been modern and even hyper-modern.
Capitalist deterritorialization continually reterritorializes itself on "man" and on the
"individualism" of the subject, the individual, homo economicus, etc., which, sys
tematically fulling, fulls back on the "collectivism" of nationalism, racism, fascism,
Nazism, machinism, class exploitation, etc. By neglecting the connection between
enslavement and subjection, Latour takes major political risks, for he is incapable of
accounting for the dramatic endpoint toward which capitalism systematically tends.
To say that "we have never been modern" is the symmetrically opposite error of
56. "When you write a function 'x function of. . . ' it looks sratic, but these are signs
=
that function in order to grasp a series ofprocesses that are of the order ofreal time and
movement, that try to account for it." Felix Guattari, Chimeres 23 (Summer 1 994): 43.
57. Felix Guattari, Schizoanalytic Cartographies, op. cit., 22. Translation modified.
58. Radio broadcasting does not furnish "the orientation, limits, and structure of
the space" of enunciation but only the relations among sound intensities. The
radio "uses sound fragments less as sensory qualities relating to an object than as an
unlimited series of modes and passive and active forces of affect." "'Sound carries
elementary forces (intensities, pitch, intervals, rhythm, and tempo) that have a more
direct impact on people than the meanings of words-that is the foundation of
radiophonic art."' Serge Cardinal, "La radio, modulateur de !'audible," Chimeres 53
(2004): 5 1-52. Cardinal cites Rudolf Arnheim, Radio: An Art of Sound (Salem,
Massachusetts: Ayer Company Publishers, 1986), 28-29. Speech along with televi
sion and computers are always being "machined."
59. Greek political orators would deliver a "speech meant to last a very brief period
of time, in a space never to exceed that in which the human voice could be heard,"
before a limited number of people "momentarily removed from all other prevailing
influences," a speech written by the orator in the same spirit. "The newspaper is
meant for a much larger, although dispersed, audience, made up ofindividuals who,
while they read their article, remain subject to all kinds of distraction, hearing the
buzz of conversations around them, among friends or in a cafe, ideas contrary to
those of the author." Readers, like radio listeners, never see the writer/speaker, nor
his gestures, bodily movements, or facial expressions, and, unlike the radio, they do
3. Mixed Semiotics
1. The "accident" that hit Wall Street in May 2010 (the sudden 10% drop in share
prices which in just a few seconds made billions of dollars go up in smoke-in 14
seconds stocks changed hands 27,000 times} originated in computer and data com
munications machines. The transformation of operators from protagonists into
spectators was due to the technological and strucrural revolution of the American
stock market. The invention of ever more powerful computers has changed the way
in which investors interact with the marker. Today; more than 90% of orders made
on the New York Stock Exchange are automated. The largest part of transactions on
Wall Street are made automatically without human intervention, for the speed with
which people can calculate and act is much too slow relative to the mass of informa
tion and speed with which it circulates. "Since stock market transactions have been
completely taken over by computers, speculators' ultimate weapon is speed. IBtrarapid
buying and selling softwares, based on ever more complex algorithms on ever more
powerful computers are now critical tools. A cur-throat arms race is caking place
among traders [. . .] . The lead time {the delay between the issue of an order and its
execution) is around a millisecond, and che profits subsequently made amount to
billions of dollars every year. Supercomputers scan dozens of exchanges in order to
detect market trends, then place orders ac the speed oflighc, leaving the much slower
traditional investor in the dusc. They can also detect the ceiling price a buyer sets (the
price above which he won't buy a stock). As soon as ic is reached, the compucers buy
up all the available stocks before the real-life buyer has the time to act, selling them
ac a higher price, and generally at the highest price possible-that is, at one cent
below the ceiling [. . .] . In response to the demand for maximum speed, small systems
for automated cransacrions have emerged. They operate with the help of a few dozen
employees set up in inexpensive offices fur from Wall Street. Certain of these systems
have become formidable competition for the traditional scock market. In July 2009,
the No/ York Srock Exchange accounted for only 28% of marker transactions in the
Uniced States and the NASDAQ just 21 %. Two companies thac most people don't
know about, che BATS Exchange in Kansas Ciry, Missouri, and Direct Edge in
Jersey Cicy, New Jersey; are competing co become the third largest American
exchange, accounting fur 10% to 12% of the market depending how one measures."
Yves Eudes, "Les 'Geeks' a Ia conquece de Wall Street'' Le Monde, September 2, 2009.
Notes / 261
2. Felix Guattari, "Ricornellos and Existential Affeccs," trans. Juliana Schiesari and
Georges Van Den Abbeele, The G11attari Reader, ed. Gary Genosko (Cambridge:
Blackwell Publishers, 1 996), 158.
3. Recall, for example, the trial ofJerome Kerviel, the Sociece Generale trader, who
was judged the "sole" guilty party in the loss of five billion dollars.
5. Daniel N. Stem, The lnteipersonal World ofthe Infant fJ...ondon: Karnac Books, 1998).
6. Ibid., p. 71.
7. Ibid., 54.
8. Ibid., 67-68.
9. "The "sense of an emergent self' is also what the philosophers of difference (Berg
son, William James, Tarde) have examined since the lace nineteenth century. "Pure
experience" is the name James gives to "the immediate Hux of life which furnishes
the material of our later reflection with its conceptual categories" and its division
into subject and object, self and ocher, spatioremporal figures, etc. James further
remarks chat it is "new born babes, or men in semi-coma from sleep, drugs, ill
nesses" chat experience or offer the experience of chis emergent self and its
organizing processes. "A Pluralistic Universe," Williams fames: Writing.r 1902-1910
(New York: Library of America, 1987), 782.
14. Felix Guattari, Chaosmosis, trans. Paul Bains and Julian Pefanis (Bloomington,
Indiana: Indiana University Press, 1995), 67.
17. Felix Guattari, Molecular Revolution in Brazil, trans. Karel Clapshow and Brian
Holmes (Los Angeles: Serniot=(e) , 2007), 316.
18. Felix Guattari, Chaosophy, trans. David L. Sweet, Jarred Becker, and Taylor
Adkins (Los Angeles: Serniotext(e), 2009), 243.
22. Pier Paolo Pasolini, Hermetic Empiricism, rrans. Ben Lawton and Louise K Bar
nett (Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana University Press, 1 988), 1 69.
28. Felix Guattari, Les Annees d'hiver: 1980-1985 (Paris: Les Prairies ordinaires,
2009), 129.
29. Marie-Anne Dujarier, L'idialdzt travail (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 2006).
33. Ibid., 1 1 5.
Notes / 263
34. The Althusserian interpellation constitutive of the subject who is addressed by
power ("Hey, you there!") would be totally ineffecrual without the work of asignifying
semiotics.
36. Ibid.
39. "There no longer exists a single official voice but multitudes of functional mea
surements deployed for the sake of the hierarchy, each independent of the other."
Ibid., 212.
44. "Soon the processes themselves will be the major factor in evaluating work.
It may even be that, more than work, the evaluation of processes will become
the priority." Ibid., 1 64.
45. Ibid., 6.
46. As Marx remarks, in a quote Benjamin includes in his vicious critique of social
democracy's exaltation of work, "'the man who possesses no other property than his
labor power' must of necessity become 'the slave of other men who have made them
selves the owners."' Walter Benjamin, "Theses on the Philosophy of History,"
Illuminations, trans. Harry Zohn (New York: Harcourt Brace, 1968), 259.
47. Christophe Dejours, "La critique du travail entre vulnerabilite et domination,"
in Travail et sante, (Toulouse: Eres, 2010).
48. As the former president Nicolas Sarkozy put it in a speech in 2007, "I am
proposing the following choice to the majority party: social policy, work, educa
tion policy, work, economic policy, work, fiscal policy, work, business policy,
work, immigration policy, work, monetary policy, work, budgetary policy, work."
"I am asking you to make work your policy."
66. Pier Paolo Pasolini, Entretims avec Jean Dujlot (Paris: Editions Gutenberg,
2007), 182.
67. Pier Paolo Pasolini, Ecrits corsaires, op. cit., 147.
68. Ibid.,145.
69. Sergei Eisenstein wrote remarkable texts on the animism in Walt Disney's
cartoons. See Eisenstein on Disney, ed. Jay Leyda (London: Methuen, 1988).
70. One should recall chat in E. P. Thompson's The Making ofthe English Working Class
these same "oral" cultures play a central role, something Marxists all too easily forget.
Notes / 265
7 1 . Pier Paolo Pasolini, Hcrits corsaires, op. cit., 1 1 0.
72. In the early twentieth century, it was 60 to 65% peasantry; in 2000, nly 1 .8%.
73. Pier Paolo Pasolini, Entretiens avec jean Dzifl.ot, op. cit., 105.
74. Ibid., 36.
3. Michel de Certeau, Cult11re in the Plural, trans. Tom Conley {Minneapolis: Uni
versity of Minnesota Press, 1997), 1 1 1.
5. Starting in the 1980s, consumption, mass communications, and mass culture have
been part of an integrating and co-opting process of "singularity" such that the
problem is now the following: How can one integrate singularities, differences,
minorities, in the standardizing and leveling system of capitalist valuation and accu
mulation? "Corporate leaders are trying to create conditions for at least some
singularization to be possible in the vectors of production. This means that in these
stratified structures an attempt is being made to create sufficient margins to allow for
these processes, as long as the system capable of co-opting them remains absolute." Felix
Guattari, Molemlar Revolution in Brazil, trans. Karel Clapshow and Brian Holmes (Los
Angeles: Semiotext(e), 2007), 70. We are confronted with a multiplicity of choices,
options, and possibilities that account for "specific" issues in order to circumscribe,
block, and reincorporate certain problematics. This is why Guattari prefers to speak of
"processes of singularization'' rather than "singularity": "The whole problem comes
8. Gilles Deleuze, Two Regimes ofMadness, trans. Ames Hodges and Mike Taormina
(Los Angeles: Semiotext(e), 2006), 143.
9. Ibid., 15.
10. Pierre Michel Menger, Les lntermittents dtt spectacle: sociologie d'ime exception
(Paris: Editions de l'EHESS, 2005).
1 2. Ibid., 59.
13. In 2005, a study by the Ministry of Culture showed that half of the artists
afftliated with the Maison des Artistes (an "association responsible for managing the
social security regime of artists in the visual and graphic arts") declared malting less
than 8,290 euros annually. If we look at one of the criteria for poverty (monetary
poverty) indicated by INSEE (National Institute of Statistics and Economic Studies),
we see that half of these artists declare income below the poverty line. We find
among the artists affiliated with the Maison des Artistes the same structure, in more
acute form, that we have observed for the job market of intermittents. In line with
a "widespread characteristic among arts professionals," income appears very concen
trated: half of the artists share a little more than 10% of allocated revenues;
conversely, 10% of artists enjoying the highest incomes share around 45% of total
allocated revenues." Looking at the same study, in which the Ministry of Culture
examines the changes in income of "creators" affiliated with AGESSA (the "associa
tion responsible for managing the social security regime ofartists") in the three years
1993, 2000, and 2005, we see "a significant increase, in every category, in the num
ber of artists whose incomes are below the threshold for membership." 30% of
photographers, 28% of software designers, and 30% of playwrights do not meet the
threshold for membership. Departement des Etudes, de la Prospective et des Sta
tistiques (DEPS), "Peintres, graphistes, sculpteurs . . . Jes artistes auteurs affilies a la
Maison des artistes en 2005," Culture Chiffres, activit!, emploi, travail (2007-6),
www2.culture.gouv.fr/deps. We should also note that the Maison des Artistes does
not ortly bring together artists in the fine arts but also a whole series of new profes
sions, which attests, in its way, to the changes in the figure of the artist and creator:
painters, graphic designers, sculptors, illustrators, cartoonists, textile designers,
engravers, ceramists, stained-glass artists, decorative painters, interior designers, etc.
Notes I 267
14. Menger, who boasts of his studying the field for thirty years, nonetheless sys
tematically and blithely confuses work and employment. Throughout his analysis
and recommendations, he limits himself exclusively to employment without ever
15. CERC, "La securite de l'emploi face aux defis des transformations economiques"
Ooh security and the challenges of economic change) (Paris: La Documentation
franaise, 2005), http://www.ladocumentationfrancaise.fr/var/storage/rapports
publics/054000141/0000.pd.
18. Michel de Cerceau, The Practice ofEveryday Life, trans. Steven Rendell (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1984), 185-186.
20. "The social sciences consistently claim for themselves the unearthly power of
reestablishing meaning they fearlessly assert is hidden and that it is precisely their
mission to uncover. Psychologists, who are on the front lines in this, manage to silence
no one: to accomplish that objective would require armies of policemen, judges, and
social workers. They make do with changing the origin of speech, attributing it to irra
tional fears that must be explained, not in view of making a decision about those fears
but of accepting them." Michel Callon, Pierre Lascumes, and Yannick Barthe, Agir dans
un monde incertain. Essai sur la dbnocratie technique (Patis: Seuil, 2001), 158.
21. Gilles Deleuze, "Five Propositions on Psychoanalysis," trans. Alexander Hickox,
Desert Islands and Other Texts (Los Angeles: Semiotext(e), 2004), 275-276. Transla
tion modified.
22. Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari, Kafka: Toward a Minor Literature (Min
neapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1 986), 83. Translation modified.
24. Reality shows use these same techniques but on another scale (in the mass audi
tions that take place throughout the country and in front of a public who follows
25. Gilles Deleuze, Desert Islands and Other Texts, trans. Michael Taormina (Los
Angeles: Semiotext(e), 2004), 274.
26. Felix Guattari, Schraoanalytic Cartographies, trans. Andrew Gaffey (New York:
Bloomsbury, 2013), 43-44.
28. But these dynamics are far from unilateral. "The public is no longer there, it is no
longer circulating in these images or caught in their traps; it is elsewhere, in the
background, assuming the position of an amused, interested, or bored receiver. [ . . . ]
For the purpose of obtaining an inkling ofwhat the receivers of serialized messages
may be, what they think, or what they desire, polls begin to multiply. Market
research of this kind only yields answers by respondents who 'play' with the ques
tions; from the polls are extracted only fragments of the theatricalizacion in which it
is playing a role; the polls no longer affect the people who slip away and disappear
into unknown realms behind the 'reactions' of a 'public' that is now and again called
upon to walk onto the stage of a national commed.ia dell'arte." Ibid., 136-137.
29. The complicity between the social sciences and media also occurs at a less direct,
less immediate, level than what we have described with regard to intermittent
workers. The social sciences have invented a whole series of techniques which the
media have appropriated and reconfigured. They have experimented with "methods
of posing the 'right' questions allowing them to obtain the 'right' answers in opinion
polls, through their phrasing of questionnaires, or in ethnographic studies of native
populations. W'hat is awe-inspiring in the social sciences is that they are sufficiently
diverse and varied ro be able to both stop people from speaking and make them
speak." Michel Callon, Pierre Lascumes, and Yannick Barthe, Agir dans ttn monde
incertain. Essai sur la dimocratie technique, op. cit., 158.
30. Michel Foucault, The Birth ofBiopolitics, trans. Graham Burchell (New York:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2008), 67.
31 Ibid., 64.
1 . The word "scum" translates the French racaille, which former French President
Nicolas Sarkozy, while still interior minister, used to describeyouth from impoverished
Parisian suburbs during the riots that erupted there and elsewhere in France in 2005
following the death of two suburban teenagers. Recorded live, the insult was well
covered by French media and a cause of much controversy. Translator's note.
Notes / 269
2. Paolo Virno, Q;1ando ii verbo sifa carne: linguaggio e natura umana (Torino: Bol
lati Boringhieri, 2003).
3. Christian Marazzi, Capital and Language, trans. Gregory Conti (Los Angeles:
Serniotext(e), 2008.
4. Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri, Multitude (New York: The Penguin Press, 2004).
5. See J. L. Austin, How to Do Things with W'Ords- (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1976).
6. Fran<;ois Recanati, Meaning and Force (New York: Cambridge University Press,
1987), 9.
7. "Thus the utterance 'I speak to you' is not a performative, although irs enuncia
tion emails that one speak." Oswald Ducrot, "De Saussure a la philosophie du
langage" (introduction to the French edition of John Searle's Speech Acts), Les actes
de langage (Paris: Hermann, 1972), 12.
8. Michel Foucault, The Government of Self and Others, trans. Graham Burchell
(New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2010), 6 1 .
9. Ibid., 63, 62.
1 1 . Ibid., 68.
13. "The subject of linguistics is only the material, only the means of speech commu
nication, and not speech communication irself, not utterances in their essence and not
the relationships among them (dialogic), not the forms of speech communication, and
not speech genres. Linguistics studies only the relationships among elemenrs within
the language system, not the relationships among utterances and not the relations of
utterances to reality and to the speaker, nor between the utterances and past and
future utterances." Mikhail Balthtin, Balthtin, Speech Genres and Other Late Essays,
trans. Vern W. McGee (Austin, Texas: University of Texas Press, 1986), 1 18.
15. "Instead of obliterating the possibility of response, paralyzing the addressee with
fear, the threat may well be countered by a different kind of performative act [. . . ] ."
Judith Butler, Excitable Speech: A Politics ofthe Peiformative (New York: Routledge,
1997), 12.
16. Mikhail Balthtin, Speech Genres and Other Late Essays, op. cit., 76.
17. Ibid.
18. Oswald Ducrot's definition of the performative's force is in reality the force
of every enunciation, every speech act, once the latter is understood as a dialogic
19. "In reality, practical intercourse is constantly generating, although slowly and
in a narrow sphere. The interrelationships between speakers are always changing,
even if che degree of change is hardly noticeable. In che process of chis generation,
che content being generated also generates. Practical interchange carries che nature
of an event, and che most insignificant philological exchange participates in chis
incessant generation of the event." Mikhail Bakhtin, Pavel Medvedev, The Formal
Method in Literary Scholarship, uans. Alben J. Wehrle (Cambridge: Harvard Uni
versity Press, 1985), 95.
20. For there co be a power relationship (and not simply violence), it is necessary
chat "'the ocher' (the one over whom power is exercised) be thoroughly recognized
and maintained to the very end as a person who acts; and chat, faced wich a rela
tionship of power, a whole field of responses, reactions, results, and possible
inventions may open up." Michel Foucault, "The Subject and Power," in Huben
Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow, Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics (Chicago: The
University of Chicago Press, 1983), 220.
21. "This is first of all because discourse is a weapon of power, conuol, subjection,
qualification, and disqualification. Bartle discourse and not reflective discourse [. . .] .
Discourse-the mere fact o f speaking, o f employing words, o f using the words of
ochers (even if it means turning chem around), words chat ochers underscand and
accept (and possibly turn around chemselves)-chis very fact is a force. Discourse is,
wich respect to che relation of forces, not only a surface of inscription but itself
operates effects." Michel Foucault, Dits et ecrits, vol. 3 (Paris: Gallimard, 1994), 124.
22. Bakhtin, Speech Genres and Other Late Essays, op. cit., 95-96. Dialogism can be
understood quite well in che terms Foucault uses to describe action: "[T]he way in
which a partner in a cenain game acts with regard to what he chinks should be che
action of che ochers and what he considers che others chink to be his own; it is the
way in which one seeks to have the advantage over others." Michel Foucault, "The
Subject and Power," op. cit., 224. "Games" in Foucault are of a whole different kind
than chose we find in Wittgenstein.
25. Voloshinov quoted in Tzvecan Todorov, Mikhail Bakhtin: The Dialogical Principle,
trans. Wlad Godzich (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984), 46.
Notes / 271
26. Voloshinov, op. cit. 104.
27. Ibid.
29. For Ranciere the 2005 riots were nor political because the "youth" fulled co insti
tute a space for incerlocution.
30. "[A] certain performative force results from the rehearsal of the conventional
formulae in non-conventional ways. [. . .] [A] formula can break with its originary
concexc, assuming meanings and functions for which it was never intended." Judith
Butler, F.xcitable Speech, op. cir., 147. Derrida identifies the "force" of the perfor
mative with a scruccural feature of the sign, every sign being obliged co break with
the context in which it is used in order co conserve its "icerabiliry." Here, the social
conventions do nor constitute the "force" of the performative, as in Austin, bur
rather the scruccural status of the sign-mk.
3 1 . The speech ace also requires a repetition bur an oncological one which muse be
distinguished from linguistic repetition. Thus the function of repetition in Guaccari's
existential pragmatics.
32. Mikhail Bakhcin, Art and Answerability, trans. Vadim Liapunov (Austin, Texas:
Universiry ofTexas Press, 1 990), 308-309. See Guaccari's commentary in Chaosmosis,
trans. Paul Bains and Julian Pefanis (Bloomington, Indiana: Indiana Universiry
Press, 1995), 15-18.
34. Mikhail Bakhtin, Speech Genres and Other Late Essays, op. cit., 159.
36. Ibid., 9 1 .
40. Mikhail Bakhtin, Speech Genres and Other Late Essays, op. cit., 120.
41. Ibid. As early as 1928 Bakhtin, using the same arguments, criticized the static model
of communication. "This scheme is radically incorrect. In real fact, the relationship
between A and R is constantly changing and generating, and itselfchanges in the com
municative process. And there is no ready-made communication X. It is generated in
the process of intercourse between A and R Furthermore, X is not transmitted from
one to the other, bur is constructed between them as a kind of ideological bridge, is
built in the process of their interaction." The FormalMethod in Literary Scholarship, op.
cit., 1 52. Since the performacive's rediscovery by critical thought, in particular in the
US, a current of "performative studies" has developed which identifies performative
and performance whereas their dynamics are diametrically opposed.
42. "Therefore, the single utterance, with all its individuality and creativity, can in
no way be regarded as a completelyfree combination of forms of language, as is sup
posed, for example, by Saussure (and by many other linguists after him), who
juxtaposed the utterance (la parole), as a purely individual act." Mikhail Bakhtin,
Speech Genres, op. cit., 8 1 . There is nor only a combinatory of language but also one
of speech genres, of ways of speaking.
43. Ibid., 77. "There are a great many everyday and special genres (i.e., military and
industrial commands and orders) in which expression, as a rule, is effected by one
sentence of the appropriate type. [ . . .] Bur for the moment we need only note that
this type of sentence knits together very stably with its generic expression, and also
that it absorbs individual expression especially easily. Such sentences have contributed
much to reinfordng the illusion that the sentence is by natttre expressive" (my empha
sis). Ibid., 89-90. The force and expressivity of the speech act never derives from
syntactic, grammatical, etc., forms, as Benvenisre believes, bur only from the dia
logic and evaluative relationships that support them. Command or expressivity are
not given via the abstract forms of language but through the "dialogic harmonics,"
through the voices that traverse utterances and that alone can express the "beautiful,
the just, and the true."
46. Judith Butler, Excitable Speech, op. cit., 28. In these "critical" or even "revolutionary"
readings.of the relationship between language and power, one can still hear the "speech
genres" of the priest! Radical and originary servitude to "the Law" and to "Language"
[La Langue] (to castration, repression, to lack, in La.can's original fully-realized version)
replaces dependence on original sin. The repression of desire is the modem iteration
of the old faulr before the divinity. Now it is no longer humanity's sin against the
Notes / 273
divine order, but an "individual" sin against the patriarchal order a:nd the law of capi
talism. This Hegel-Lacanian rerurn smacks of the sacristy!
47. Jacques Lacan, Ecrits, trans. Bruce Fink (New York: W. W. Norton, 2006), 148.
Foucault always conceived power as a "relationship of power" (whether in the form of
war, battle, or government) in which acting differently is always possible. A way out of
power's grip is never sought in the magical Hegel-Lacanian exchange of master and
slave (if servitude to power is a necessary condition for emancipation, there is no other
solution but the dialectid), but rather in the ontology of the "relation to the sel''
48. Neoteny in Lacan, just as in all the other more or less reactionary social sciences,
manifests an originary "lack," a constitutive absence, an "incompleteness," and man's
"delay in development," which the signifier, language, and culrure cover over and
sublimate. Ibid., 152.
49. Mikhail Bakhtin. The Dialngic Imagination, trans. Caryl Emerson and Michael
Holquist (Austin, Texas: University ofTexas Press, 198 1), 293.
52. Ibid. "The question arises as to whether science can deal with such absolutely
unrepeatable individualities as utterances, or whether they extend beyond the
bounds of generalizing scientific cognition. And the answer is, of course, it can."
Mikhail Bakhtin, Speech Genres, op. cit., 108.
53. "It is much easier to study the given in what is created (for example, language,
ready-made and general elements of world view, reflected phenomena of reality, and
so forth) than to study what is created. Frequently the whole of scientific analysis
amounts to a disclosure of everything that has been given, already at hand and
ready-made before the work has existed (that which is found by the artist and not
created by him)." Ibid., 120.
1 . Felix Guattari, "A propos des Machines," Chimeres 19 (Spring 1993): 94.
2. Felix Guattari, Soft S11bversions, trans. Chet Wiener and Emily Wittman (Los
Angeles: Semiotext(e) , 2009), 299. Translation modified.
3. Felix Guattari and Olivier Zahm, "Entretien avec Olivier Zahm," Chimeres 23
(Summer 1994): 58. Nearly all of this chapter's quotations are taken from the
5. Badiou would do well to read more attentively what Deleuze wrote with the "non
philosopher" Guaccari after Logic ofSense and especially what Guattari wrote alone.
Ic would prevent him from asserting falsehoods of the cype: "Deleuze's formula is
irrevocable: 'The event, that is to say sense.' From the beginning of his book, he
fashions what to my mind is a chimerical entity, an inconsistent portmanteau-word:
the 'sense-event.' Incidentally; this brings him far closer than he would have wished
co the linguistic turn and the great lineage of contemporary sophistry. To argue that
the event belongs ro the register of sense tips it over entirely onto the side of lan
guage." Alain Badiou, Logics of Worlds, trans. Alberro Toscano (New York:
Continuum, 2009), 386. Not only did Guattari steer Deleuze away from psycho
analysis but from scrucruralism as well. Foucault's lase lecrures equally put the lie to
Badiou's criticisms, according to which Foucault is implausibly supposed to have
systematized a "linguistic anthropology." Ibid., 35.
9. Felix Guattari, Chaosmosis, trans. Paul Bains and Julian Pefanis (Bloomingron,
Indiana: Indiana University Press, 1 995), 127-128.
10. Felix Guaccari, "Substicuer l'econciation a I'expression," Seminar ofApril 25, 1984.
14. Felix Guattari, "Singularite et complexice," op. cit. Content and sense become
double: a semantic content and a pragmatic content, a semiotic sense and an exis
tential sense.
16. "So it is chat for decades, a constellation of existential ritomellos [re&ains] gave
access to a 'Lenin-language' engaging specific procedures which could just as well be of
a rhetorical and lexical order as of a phonological, prosodic, facial, or other order. The
threshold crossing-or initiation-that legitimates a relation offull existential belonging
co a group-subject depends upon a certain concatenation and becoming-consistent of
Notes / 275
these components, which are thereby ritomellized." Felix Guattari, "Riroumellos and
Existential Affects," trans. Juliana Schiesari and Georges Van Den Abbeele, The
Guattari Reader, ed. Gary Genosko (Cambridge: Blackwell Publishers, 1996), 165.
24. Ibid.
25. "Freud refers to various ancient myths in these connexions, and claims that his
researches have now explained how it came about that anybody should think or pro
pound a myth of that sore. Whereas in fact Freud has done something different. He has
not given a scientific explanation ofthe ancient myth. What he has done is to propound
a new myth." Ludwig Wittgenstein, Lectures and Conversations on Aesthetics, Psychology,
and&ligiotts Belief, ed. Cyril Barrett (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1967), 5 1 .
26. Felix Guanaci, Chaosmosis, op. cit., 65.
27. Felix Guattari, "Machine abscraite et champ non-discursif," op. cit.
29. "Things happen outside of representations, things that aren't the product of
chance but rather are highly differentiated, involving the entire economy of subse
quent choices. And the first of these things [ . . . ] is the fact of acting itsel Indeed, you
have the refrain of representation, right, I'm going to go now." And then, a
moment later, you're leaving but you have no representation whatsoever [ . . .]. The
'I'm going' somewhere got disconnected from the system of representation. And yet,
it has to do with representation; these aren't the reflexes of a decerebrated frog. [ . . . ]
Between representation and the act, a whole range of relationships are possible!" Ibid.
30. When "It's working" during a revolution, a struggle, a social change, etc., one is
not primarily dealing with "consciousness raising" but with an assemblage of dis
cursive and non-discursive elements which function and circulate in a diagrammatic
register; one is dealing with a revolutionary "war machine."
35. 'other category must be thought up, because there is no link, because there
is no discursivity, because existential territories are blocked in a non-discursive
agglomeration, a non-discursive constellation." Ibid.
37. Ibid.
39. Ibid.
40. This relationship between the discursive and the non-discursive is always
contradictory and "inevitably contradictory. You cannot seek the ethico-aesthetic
completion of an affect. In saying this, I think of Deligny: we can see that his idea
of completion is, I mean, at bottom, for him, at the level of the smallest gesrure;
there is no room for words. At the same time, Deligny has a kind of enunciative
elegance, a written elegance. The ethical dimension is obvious too. Of course,
Deligny still developed formidable myths. His whole life, he wrote novels, even a
kind of mythology, at a certain point, of the unrepentant delinquent, at another
point, of the autistic child, because there was no other way." Ibid.
4 1 . The politics of the event they propose is a weak and stunted one since, in
reality, there is not one articulation between the existential and the discursive to
examine, bur three: before, during, and after the event of a struggle, a change, a
revolution. The relationship between subjectivation and economic, social, instiru
tional, and linguistic flows must be posed in a radically different way before, during,
and afrer political ruprure. This I attempted to show in my book Expirimentatiom
politiqttes (Paris: Editions Amsterdam, 2009),
42. Enzo Rullani, "La produzione di valore a mezzo di conoscenza. Il manuale che
non c'e," Sociologia del lavoro 1 1 5 (2009). One only has to think of the "cognitive
experience" of the soccer fan mentioned in Rullani's text to see that the experience
he has in mind has little to do with the cognitive.
43. Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari, Anti-Oedipus, crans. Roberr Hurley, Mark Seem,
and Helen R Lane (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983), 235-236.
44. "Here Andre Gorz's double porrrait ofthe 'scientific and technical worker' cakes on
its fullmeaning. Although he has mastered a flow of knowledge, information, and
training, he is so absorbed in capital that the reflux of organiz.ed, axiomatized stupidity
coincides with him, so that, when he goes home in the evening, he rediscovers his little
desiring-machines by tinkering with a television set-0 despair. Of course the scientist
as such has no revolutionary potential; he is the first integrated agent of integration, a
refuge for bad conscience, and the forced destroyer of his own creativity." Ibid., 236.
Notes / 277
45. Cited by Guattari in Schizoanalytic Cartographies, op. cit., 274n. Mikhail
Bakhtin, "The Problem of Content, Material, and Form in Verbal An," Art and
Answerability, op. cit., 278.
2. Michel Foucault, Ethics, crans. Robert Hurley (New York: The New Press, 1997), 81.
3. Michel Foucault, The Courage ofthe Tmth, trans. Graham Burchell (New York:
Palgrave Macmillan, 201 1), 9.
5. Ibid., 184.
6. Jacques Ranciere, On the Shores ofPolitics, trans. Liz Heron (New York: Verso,
1995), 65. "The egalitarian logic implied by the ace of speaking and the inegalitarian
logic inherent in the social bond," ibid., 8 1
9. Ibid., 50.
1 1 . Michel Foucault, The Government ofSelfand Others, op. cit., 62, 63.
_
12. Ibid., 68.
14. Ibid., 1 1.
15. William James, The Will to Believe, in William fames: Writing,r 1878-1899, ed.
Gerald E. Myers (New York: Library of America, 1992), 458.
16. Michel Foucault, The Courage ofthe Tmth, op. cit., 46.
32. Michel Foucault, The Courage ofthe Truth, op. cit., 67.
Notes / 279
SIGNS AND
Maurizio Lazzarato
MACHINES Translated by Joshua David Jordan
"It is never an individual who thinks, never an individual who creates. An individual
who thinks and creates does so within a network of institutions (schools, theaters,
museums, libraries, etc.), technologies (books, electronic networks, computers,
etc.), and sources of public and private financing; an individual immersed in
traditions of thought and aesthetic practices-engulfed in a circulation of signs,
ideas, and tasks-that force him or her to think and create."
Moving beyond the dualism of signifier and signified, Signs and Machines shows
how signs act as "sign-operators" that enter directly into material flows and into
the functioning of machines. Money, the stock market, price differentials, algo
rithms, and scientific equations and formulas constitute semiotic "motors" that
make capitalism's social and technical machines run, bypassing representation
and consciousness to produce social subjections and semiotic enslavements.
Lazzarato contrasts Deleuze and Guattari's complex semiotics with the political
theories of Jacques Ranciere, Antonio Negri and Michael Hardt, Paolo Virno, and
Judith Butler, for whom language and the public space it opens still play a fun
damental role. Lazzarato asks: What are the conditions necessary for political
and existential rupture at a time when the production of subjectivity represents
the primary and perhaps most important work of capitalism? What are the
specific tools required to undo the industrial mass production of subjectivity
undertaken by business and the state? What types of organization must we
construct for a process of subjectivation that would allow us to escape the hold
of social subjection and machinic enslavement? In addressing these questions,
Signs and Machines takes on a task that is more urgent today than ever.