Understanding in Qualitative Research
Understanding in Qualitative Research
Understanding in Qualitative Research
2
www.aeph.in
AEIJMR Vol 5 Issue 05 May 2017 ISSN - 2348 - 6724
Adapted from: Lincoln and Guba, 1985, p. 37; Creswell, 1994, p. 5; Hudson and Ozanne,
1991, p. 508.
3
www.aeph.in
AEIJMR Vol 5 Issue 05 May 2017 ISSN - 2348 - 6724
6
www.aeph.in
AEIJMR Vol 5 Issue 05 May 2017 ISSN - 2348 - 6724
theoretical reasons or on grounds of internal consistency (Miles and Huberman, 1994, p. 6).
The challenge to the researcher, then, is to insure that the interpretation is indeed a valid
interpretation, or, that the understanding is true.
Validity, however, is seen here not in the positivist vein; instead, it is seen in terms of the
trustworthiness of the interpretation. It is a measure of the authenticity (Lincoln and Guba,
1985) of the interpretation. The researcher must strive to maximize credibility (Glaser and
Strauss, 1965) of the research process and the interpretation.
The problem, then, lies in the choice of criteria for evaluating the interpretation.
Qualitative researchers argue that there are special criteria for trustworthiness that the
positivist evaluation criteria of validity, reliability, and generalisabilty do not apply to
interpretive work (Lincoln and Guba, 1985). No social research is accurately portrayed by
positivism, and thus positivism should not serve as the foil against which standards for
qualitative research should be developed (Howe and Eisenhart, 1990, p. 3).
Qualitative researchers, however, have been quick to adopt the validity-reliability-
generalisability framework (for example: Creswell, 1994; Miles and Huberman, 1995) in the
development of their interpretive evaluation criteria (Maxwell, 1992). Hirschman (1986)
outlined four evaluation criteria, termed credibility, transferability, dependability, and
confirmability.
Credibility alludes to whether the interpretation is credible to constructors of the
multiple realities. That is, confidence in the interpretation is buttressed by local
groundedness (Miles and Huberman, 1995, p. 10). Dukes (1984) refers to this as the eureka
factor, where outside readers see the logic in the interpretation of the qualitative researcher
as their own. If the researcher succeeds in seeing the structural invariants of an experience
and in faithfully articulating them (which would require more vivid and jargon-free language
than is currently standard in the human sciences), then the reader should spontaneously
recognize the faithfulness of the description (p. 201).
Transferability is analogous to generalisability, and measures the ability of the
interpretation to transfer to other contexts. Can the knowledge of this particular phenomenon
be extended to or subsumed by another phenomenon? Lincoln and Guba (1985) call this
understanding and management the development of patterns and working hypotheses
from an empathetic understanding, and the use of these hypotheses in pertinent situations.
Dependability is akin to reliability and refers to how the interpretation compares to other
studies of the same phenomenon/context/time and to other similar qualitative research. Have
things been done with care? Does the researcher follow best practice? Is the process
transparent and auditable (Miles and Huberman, 1995)?
And finally, confirmability suggests that the research process and the interpretation itself
are more trustworthy if they can be confirmed by external sources. So, a researcher can use a
team of auditors to review notes, transcription, data entry, interpretation, and other aspects of
the research, to provide confirmation (Dukes, 1984) (See Table 3.).
8
www.aeph.in
AEIJMR Vol 5 Issue 05 May 2017 ISSN - 2348 - 6724
10
www.aeph.in