Reiner Schurmann Neoplatonic Henology As An Overcoming of Metaphysics
Reiner Schurmann Neoplatonic Henology As An Overcoming of Metaphysics
Reiner Schurmann Neoplatonic Henology As An Overcoming of Metaphysics
REINER SCHRMANN
New School for Social Research
It has often been noted that among the academic disciplines philosophy
is the one that depends most on its own history. This may be so because,
just as we learn to speak from our parents and society, so we learn to
think from our forebears and our culture. Our twentieth century may
furthermore place us in the peculiar position where reflecting upon the
historical situatedness of our reasoned convictions has become a major
element of the philosophical endeavor itself.
Whoever sets out to do philosophy, whether in the Middle Ages or
today, places himself within a lineage. He is situated diachronically. But
he is also situated synchronically, he places himself within a cultural
network of exchanges. This network makes for an interest that is
operative in philosophical works, an interest that turns the philosopher
into the spokesman for his times. One may describe this synchronic link
in psychoanalytical terms and speak of a desire that comes to the fore in
thinking. One may also describe it in structuralist terms and speak of
systemic rules that thinking obeys in every age. One may finally describe
25
26
"
Reading the Henological Tradition Prospectively
.
Several times it has happened: I awake from the slumber of
.
_ the body to return to myself; and leaving behind all things and
becoming self-encentered, I behold the most marvelous
. '
beauty. Then, more than ever, I am assured of community
with the loftiest order. I live the highest life and acquire
identity with the divine. Poised within it by having attained
. that activity, I am raised above all other intelligible beings.
Yet, there comes the moment of descent from intellection to
reasoning, and after that sojourn in the divine, I ask myself
how it happens that I can now be descending and how the soul
ever entered into my body.22
ourselves by doing what everyone else does, that we stop fleeing from
ourselves into distraction and dispersion" and take up our existence as
our own. One may see here a late reminiscence of Plotinus' remark that
he became "self encentered."'2 The difference is, however, that Plotinus
reverts inward from the physical and emotional manifold, whereas the
authentically existent according to Heidegger reverts from our many
ways of covering up death. To accept one's mortality is to become eigen,
to come into one's own by becoming what one already is, namely
"towards death." The self that we retrieve in authenticity is not the
'
individual ("ontic") self that has its history, made of birth, childhood,
'
adolescence, etc.; it is rather a potential, a possibility, and as such, once
again, nothing. Meister Eckhart may have taught something similar
when he urged his auditors to be "rid of allEigenschaJt,"I3 which means
"property" in the sense of a quality, but also in that of ego-attachment.
Eigenschaft is essentially diverse, scattered, whereas the true self is a
void, opposed to all diversion and diversity. Heideggerian authenticity
thus has undeniably Neoplatonic overtones.
. The more directly henological strain appears in Heidegger's writings
after Being and Time. The One is still opposed to literally dissolute
existence: "singleness does not individualize [us] into dispersion."
However, the One is something towards which we are to move:
"Singleness carries the soul to what is unique, it gathers it into the
One."'4 Just as for Parmenides, the One, for Heidegger, is being: it is
, "what is singular as such, what is singular in its numerical unity and what
is singularly and unifyingly one before all number."" Formulations like
this have led some commentators to believe that Heidegger's "being" is
man's "all-powerful partner," "a power towards which one may assume
personal attitudes as towards the Christian God."'6
To the received opinion, henology amounts undoubtedly to negative
theology, and the One is a substance. There are metaphysicians who call
the supreme being "the Good" because God_is that being in which man's
desire for irrevocable possession finds rest. 17There are those who call it
"the Beautiful" because it orders all things into a cosmos, an order that
can be mastered by reason." Still others call it "the Truth," for it is
known by the mind's return upon itself.19 Finally, more mystically
inclined metaphysicians, it seems, call God "the One" because we
cannot really know of him what he is.20 Nevertheless, henological
negations are the most adequate language about God for those who are
the most intimately convinced that he is. Such is the common opinion
about this tradition, which does not agree easily with a retrospective
- eading of it.
30
Whoever wishes to obtain strong answers from the tradition must raise
strong questions about it. The strong question that Heidegger's
deconstruction puts to the history of Western philosophy is the question
of being: How has being been understood in the epochs that our inherited
. doctrines reflect? This question could hardly have arisen prior to the
historicist turn in the last century, in late Modernity. Looking at the
authors from late Antiquity and the late Middle Ages whom I have
mentioned, it is not so certain that they speak of "the One" only to stress
that the supreme being is inconceivably actual, spiritual, changeless,
powerful, causative, eternal; that our discourse about it has to remain
apophatic. Rather, the very understanding of the tasks and possibilities
of thinking and living may be at stake-in other words, our very
understanding of being.
The being question hinges on the retrieval of what Heidegger sometimes
calls the ontological difference. Simply stated, this is the difference
between the process of coming to presence-of entering into our field of
attention-and the thing that is present or that so enters into our horizon.
The first is best expressed by a verb, "presencing," the second by a noun,
"something present." The easiest way to grasp this difference is to look
at ordinary language. There is something remarkable about the
grammatical form that we call a participle. On the one hand, it refers to
some activity, to a predicate, and on the other, to some entity, a subject.
It is called a participle since it "participates" both in the verb and in the
noun. To say "shining," for instance, is to speak both of an activity, the
emittance or reflection of light, and of a substance that performs such
emittance, the surface of the sea or of metal. The verbal participle
designates something that is essentially one and simple: the fact of
' shining. The nominal participle, however, can be plural: there are many
things on earth that shine. The English "being" and the Greek on (or the
archaic eon) thus are equivocal concepts. They designate both "to be,"
esse, and "a being," ens. About this equivocity, Heidegger writes: "On
says 'being' in the sense of to be a being; at the same time it names a being
which is. In the duality of the participial significance of on the distinction
between 'to be' and 'a being' lies concealed."21
Now the henologists have something quite precise to say about being,
namely that it is not what is ultimate. The One is not a being, not
something. This is clearly implied in the first lines of Plotinus' treatise
"On the One": "It is due to the One that all beings are beings."22 Why
can the One not be called something, a being? "The One is in all respects
the first, but mind, as well as the ideas and being are not first."23 We
31
heard that what Meister Eckhart calls "the One" is the mind's identity
with the Godhead. The One, then, is not an entity and is therefore likened
to a desert.24 Beings are below the One quite as God the person is below
the Godhead. The derivative status of being in its nominal sense is a
consequence of its chief quality, intelligibility. All that there is, all that
exists, can be understood. But the One, or the Godhead, is beyond the
reach of intellection. Hence it is not a being. Conversely, being is
secondary since it is of the same order as the hypostasis "mind" or the
personal God. Here the phrase "supreme being" is a contradiction in
terms.
What the method of deconstruction can show about the ancient and
medieval henologists is that the being that is derivative is a noun, but that
the First-the Plotinian "One" or Eckhart's "Godhead"-is best
designated by a verb. Heidegger charges precisely that the "verb"
connotation of the participle "being" has been obscured since Plato by
the identification between the nominal on and the supreme being. The
henologists may have been the only thinkers in our tradition who broke
through that obfuscation. Meister Eckhart's diversified vocabulary of
being testifies to this. Two of the several German words translated as
"being" in his writings refer directly to the ontological difference. The
one, iht, is a noun usually translated as "something"; it designates any
entity whatsoever, including God. The other, wesen, is a verb. It can be
translated as "essentializing" or "unfolding," and it designates the
Godhead as well as the mind's identification with the Godhead. It is from
this latter term that Heidegger developed his own understanding of
Anwesen, presence, as a verb, as "presencing."
The henologists are so important for the retrieve of the being question
because they were the ones who kept making the point that whatever our
mind can represent as "a being" must rank, for that very reason, after
some more radical condition. This condition of all beings is not
representable, since it is not something. Henology thus achieves what
negative theology can never achieve, namely, an understanding of the
difference between non-being and being as the difference between the
verbal and the nominal participle, between "to be" and "a being." The
One differs from Mind, and the Godhead from God, as a process or an
event differs from a thing. Plotinus himself never equates to hen with to
einai. In a later Neoplatonist, however, we read these lines:
The editor of this striking text first attributed it to Porphyry, and later to
the "Anonymous of Turino."2S The One here is not only called "pure
acting" and thereby de-substantialized, but it is also identified with the
verb "to be." Here the ontological difference between the first and the
second hypostasis is clearly expressed as the difference between "to be"
and "a being"; between the indeterminate or pure "is" and the
determinate sum of all beings; between the verbal and the nominal
participle; between wesen and iht.
This de-substantialized notion of the One designates no transcendent
reality-no thing-and in that sense, nothing. The "verbal" understanding
of the One is also irreducible to the later Scholastic notions of ipsum esse
subsistens and actus essendi. Although these notions rehabilitate the
infinitive in the ontological discourse, the verb there serves to express the
principle of intelligibility, which is the Neoplatonic second hypostasis.
As to Meister Eckhart, he takes considerable pains to de-substantialize
his notion of Godhead. His affirmations about the identity between the
"ground" of the mind and the "ground" of God, as we saw, refer always
to an "identity in operation," einheit im gewrke, never to substantial
identity (which would be pantheism). One frequent metaphor for such a
dynamic concept of One is fire:
Acting and becoming are one. God and I are one in this work:
he acts and I become. Fire transforms all things it touches
into its own nature. The wood does not change the fire into
itself, but the fire changes the wood into itself. In.the same
way we are transformed into God so that we may know him
as he is.26
and then another, until the original formation has been restored."28 It is
through this line of thinking that we have to understand the One. Plotinus
calls it the "principle of being," arche ontos.29 As a principle of order, as
the differentiating principle among things, "the First is present without
any coming and, while it is nowhere, there is nothing where it is not."3
This is to say, the One is the factor of coordination in all things without
which all would disintegrate. It is their pure constellation, uniting bricks
into a house, soldiers into an army, cities into an empire. But far from
being the epitome of power, as the modality of phenomenal interaction it
is most inconspicuous.
Here again, the alliance between metaphysical apophatism and onto-
theology obscures the phenomenological discovery contained in henology.
This discovery can now be stated in a paraphrase of the initial quote from
the Enneads: it is due to unification-to their entrance into an order of
interconnectedness-that all beings are beings. In negative theology, on
the contrary, we heard that the One is the supreme being, of which we do
not know what it is, although we know that it is. But if the One as henosis
and as Godhead is a resurgence of the "verb" connotation of the
participle, then we can think, although not know, what it is-we can think
its nature: it is the very movement of nasci, or phyein, of coming-to-
presence, in all that there is. It is the phainesthai, the appearance as
such, in all phenomena. It is their origin in the sense of pure oriri,
showing-forth. These verbs-nasci, phyein, phainesthai, oriri-indicate
how the One is an event. It is the event in which any phenomenon
whatsoever enters into a given constellation or disposition of presence.
The later Heidegger has a word for the One as mere factor of
unification: Ereignis. This is again a word derived from the radical eigen,
"proper" or "own," and has therefore been translated as "event of
appropriation" or "enownment." The point is, however, that appropriating
or owning are no longer understood by the later Heidegger to be human
doings, they refer to man only secondarily. Rather the event of
appropriation, the enownment, designates the link, which is specific to
each era, by which phenomena form an order, a cultural system.
Heidegger calls our twentieth century the atomic age. This is one way of
designating the peculiar mode in which things enter into rapport with one
another today-the way in which they are mutually appropriated or
"enowned." Ereignis is the term for the movement of crystallization by
which things enter into an epochal configuration..
I am not claiming that the medieval henologists understood being, in
the verbal sense, the way Heidegger understands Ereignis. Their lack of
a sense for history should suffice to prevent anyone from such synchretism.
I am suggesting, however, that the medieval henologists were the ones
34
At first sight, these lines hardly sound like an echo of the henological
tradition. In another language, they deal however with the very discovery
made by Plotinus, Meister Eckhart and others, namely, that we keep
moving among figments so long as we do not break through conceptual
prehension and grant all phenomena what Heidegger here calls an open
field. What exactly is at stake?
At stake is a specific form of "breakthrough" (the term, as I said, is
Meister Eckhart's) that is available to us, a dismantling that becomes
possible and necessary at the end of metaphysics. Heidegger describes it
as breaking through the representations that tend to place themselves
between the mere presencing of things and ourselves. This is the counter-
37
historical position. "I have never spoken against technology, "40 he says.
Plotinus and Meister Eckhart had already made it clear that the thinking
that moves among entities (the ideas contained in the hypostatic nous, or
Eckhart's "sum total of the created") does not encounter the thinking
that breaks through to the One. This double thinking, so to speak, is even
the distinctive feature of the henologists since they teach not only a
movement of transcendence from the empirical to the noetic, but a
second such movement from the noetic to the trans-noetic, the One. In its
historicized version, in Heidegger, this duality of thinking remains
equally sharp. He couches it in the Kantian distinction between thinking
and knowing, or he states more flatly: "The sciences do not think."4'
What, then, is the task of thinking if it is to "break through"
representational violence? Heidegger's answer is quite clear: Anything
"that tends to place [itself] between the thing and us must first be
removed."
After what I have said, we already know what it is that tends to place
itself between the simple process of presencing and ourselves: it is the
representation of some ultimate entity whose many shapes in metaphysics,
we heard, today "lose their constructive force and become nothing." The
overcoming of metaphysics therefore cannot be obtained by some
contraction of the will. For Heidegger, there is only one attitude at our
disposal by which technological violence can perhaps be broken. The
name for this attitude is yet another word that he borrows from Meister
Eckhart: Gelassenheit, usually translated as "releasement." Releasement,
he says, "does not belong to the domain of the will."'2 Releasement is the
preparatory play of an economy of presence deprived of ultimate
measure-giving representations. It thus preludes the transgression of an
epochal order of presence stamped by domination and of the violence
that results from this stamping. In the lines on which I am commenting,
Heidegger alludes to releasement when he says: "Such an assault [can]
perhaps be avoided ... if we grant the thing an open field." Granting
things an open field in which they may appear-in which they may
become phenomena-was precisely what the One did according to the
interpretation of it that I have given. It is thus not an overstatement when
Heidegger makes an ancient dictum about Meister Eckhart his own and
calls him "the old master of reading and of living
The potential that the topology-the laying bare of topical strategies in
the history of philosophy-yields for present-day thinking affects the
problem area that may well be the most pressing of all, namely the
problem of how to live in a culture whose prime systemic feature is
domination: not domination of man over man (of which there is perhaps
39
less in today's Western world than in the past), but domination as that
posture to which everyone is called in all he thinks and does.
Heidegger's way of putting contemporary technology into question
goes more surely to the heart of systemic violence than the discussion of
alternatives to standardization and mechanization. He asks, What is the
essence of technology? and he discovers that it is the same as that of
metaphysics, namely the quest for ultimacy. The step that the henologists
took to transgress the metaphysical domination by some ultimate
representation can teach us something for transgressing the technological
domination by global regulation.
NOTES