Gunn, Richard Wilding, Adrian. A - Note - On - Habermas
Gunn, Richard Wilding, Adrian. A - Note - On - Habermas
Gunn, Richard Wilding, Adrian. A - Note - On - Habermas
Our discussion focuses on Habermas. What exactly happened in the early 1970s? At
what stage in Habermas's development did the Frankfurt School lose its way? If these
questions are raised, a specific text is brought into prominence: Habermas's
'Wahrheitstheorien' (or 'Theories of Truth') published in 1973.2 Our view is not that
the 'Wahrheitstheorien' is the point where things go wrong in the Frankfurt School's
development. On the contrary, we regard the text as a signal and far-reaching
achievement. Things go wrong when, as is the case, Habermas breaks with the
'Wahrheitstheorien' and its radical claims.
1 Richard Gunn and Adrian Wilding 'Is the Frankfurt School Still Relevant?' Heathwood Institute and Press 19 April
2014.
2 J. Habermas 'Wahrheitstheorien' in H. Fahrenbach, ed., Wirklichkeit und Reflexion (Neske: Pfullingen 1973) pp. 211-
65. See, for discussion, T. McCarthy The Critical Theory of Jrgen Habermas (Cambridge: Polity Press 1984) pp.
299-310.
objective or scientific ring? This first-off impression arises, perhaps, because the
notion of correspondence focuses on theory's relation to its object: is this object
accurately mirrored? The notion of consensus, by contrast, relates theory to the
subjects by whom truth-claims are made.3 Be this as it may, we think that the first
impression of consensus theory as subjectivist and of correspondence theory as
objectivist is mistaken. One of the weaknesses with a correspondence theory is that,
despite its objectivist appearance, subjectivism lurks within it. If truth just is an
accurate mirroring of reality, as correspondence theory asserts, how can we be certain
other than by an appeal to subjective feelings that such a mirroring takes place?
Whereas a correspondence theory of truth rests its final appeal upon subjective
certainty, consensus theory operates differently. In what we have termed the
attractive versions of consensus theory, the emphasis falls on reasons which must
be given in and through discussion if a claim is to count as true. Rather than
grounding truth on subjective sensation, reasons whether they turn on empirical
evidence or hermeneutical sensitivity or conceptual rigour are given their due.
How does all of this relate to Habermas's 'Wahrheitstheorien'? Our reply is that the
Habermas of 1973 addresses the issues just raised. The claims of a correspondence
theory of truth are raised only to be dismissed: 'Sense-certainty or [appeals to] the
objectivity of experience are not appropriate models of truth'.4 The claims of
consensus theory are put in correspondence theory's place: 'The consensus theory of
truth has the merit of distinguishing between intersubjective validity-claims and
merely subjective feelings of certainty'.5 The form of 'consensus' which Habermas
defends is one where an 'ideal speech situation' obtains.6 An ideal speech situation is,
amongst other things, one where 'there is a symmetrical distribution of the chances
for all participants in the discourse to choose speech acts and carry them out'.7 In
short, it is one where as in consensus theory's attractive version an argument
may be followed where it leads. In a situation where all participants may employ all
forms of speech act, discussion may be open-ended and unrestricted. In such a
situation, claims which understand themselves as truthful may be made.
In the present short paper, we do not carry discussions of truth-theory further. Our
aim is to illustrate the far-reaching nature of Habermas's 1973 argument, and this (we
submit) we have done. A point, which concerns the history of ideas, calls for
comment, however. Whether intentionally or unintentionally, Habermas's
'Wahrheitstheorien' echoes themes in Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit. Hegel's
Phenomenology (1806) starts from a critique of subjective certainty and, at the end of
a lengthy discussion, refers to non-alienated interaction (or mutual recognition). In
1973, Habermas criticises the subjective certainty of correspondence theory as a
prelude to discussion of an ideal speech situation. Hegel's Phenomenology sees
Let us trace the change from an earlier to a later Habermas in greater detail. In an
Appendix to his Knowledge and Human Interests, Habermas refers to a 'non-
authoritarian and universally practised dialogue' from which 'our idea[s] of true
consensus are always implicitly derived'. The passage continues: 'To this extent the
truth of statements is based on anticipating the realization of the good life'.10 The
Appendix dates from the mid-1960s, and the just-quoted passage points forward to
the perspectives of the 'Wahrheitstheorien'. We may take it as a base-line from which,
in his post-1973 writings, Habermas subsequently departs.
By the 1980s, this departure had become a feature of Habermas's writings. A text
published in 1982 makes the departure explicit: from an 'ethic of discourse' he tells
us, retracting his earlier position standards for 'something like an ideal form of life'
cannot be inferred.11 Stating the point differently: an image of universally practised
dialogue cannot do duty as an image of emancipated life. Or in the words of an
8 G.W.F. Hegel Phenomenology of Spirit (Oxford: Clarendon Press 1977) pp. 3-4.
9 In a recent collection of his essays, Habermas has criticised the 'Wahrheitstheorien' as 'somewhat speculative' and
hasty: see J. Habermas Rationalitts- und Sprachtheorie: Philosophische Texte Band 2 (Frankfurt am Main:
Suhrkamp 2009) p. 24.
10 J. Habermas Knowledge and Human Interests (London: Heinemann 1972) p. 314.
11 J. Habermas 'A Reply to my Critics' in J.B. Thompson and D. Held, eds., Habermas: Critical Debates (London:
Macmillan Press 1982) p. 261.
interview given by Habermas in 1979: 'One should not imagine the ideal speech
situation as a utopian model for an emancipated society'.12 Such formulations prise
the notion of emancipation away from what (referring to Hegel) we have termed
mutual recognition. In effect, they undo or seek to undo the work of the
'Wahrheitstheorien'. If the 'Wahrheitstheorien' reminds radical theory of its mutually
recognitive focus, the just-quoted formulations direct theory towards less challenging
goals.
Which goals? The 1982 text that we have cited warns that 'mediations' between life
and discourse are not to be ignored.13 The mediations which Habermas has in mind
are, we suggest, social institutions. The passage from 1982 refers to Albrecht
Wellmer, who argues that an emancipated society is one where a 'new
institutionalization of freedom' takes place.14 For Habermas, this means that social
institutions such as a legal system (distinct from morality) and the state must exist in
a modern society even a modern society where, allegedly, emancipation has
occurred. Differentiation between institutions is, for the later Habermas, the hallmark
of modernity; if emancipation is pictured as a de-institutionalisation of society, then
(so he considers) a regression to pre-modern superstition is entailed. Habermas's turn
to institutionalist thinking is, we submit, one with deep implications historical,
political and philosophical. We comment briefly on each.
(iii) The philosophical implications of Habermas's turn concern truth. Above, we have
drawn attention to Habermas's 1973 endorsement of consensus theory. Here, we note
that, as the focal point of his theory shifts from universal dialogue to institutions, his
endorsement of a consensus view of truth is withdrawn. In a world where institutions
channel interaction, unrestricted and open-ended discussion the form of discussion
which underpinned attractive consensus theory is no longer plausible. If
emancipation is no longer seen in terms of mutual recognition, consensus theory's
plausibility is undermined. To these remarks, we must add that a Wellmer-inspired
turn to institutions is not the only reason for Habermas's breach with consensus
theory. Besides the social reasons just referred to, he responds to a conceptual worry:
surely truth truth qua truth involves a surplus over and above warrented or
agreed-upon belief? And does consensus theory focus on warrented belief alone,
leaving truth qua truth out of account? In the present connection, we do not take up
the question of truth's alleged surplus. (In passing, we note that we regard the
notion of such a surplus as misconceived. Worries about truth's alleged surplus
are worries about whether theory accurately mirrors its object. The notion of a
surplus makes sense only if, tacitly, a correspondence view of truth has been
assumed or reintroduced.) For Habermas, anxieties regarding truth's surplus over
warrented belief play a large part in his turning against consensus theory.18 We do not,
here, seek to reduce philosophical to social issues. Nor do we comment on the two-
part or 'Janus-faced' conception of truth which the later Habermas defends.19 We note,
however, that, once mutual recognition has been cast aside, objections to consensus
theory are apt to appear more pressing. If the only world which seems possible is a
world of institutions, truth is apt to be pictured in correspondence (as distinct from
consensus) terms.
Standing back, now, from Habermas's development we offer some observations. One
is that critics and commentators are mistaken when they take up stances for or
17 Hegel Phenomenology p. 300. For a discussion of 'spiritual masses' (or social institutions), see R. Gunn and A.
Wilding 'Revolutionary or Less-than-Revolutionary Recognition?' Heathwood Institute and Press
(www.heathwoodpress.com) 24 July 2013.
18 On issues underlying Habermas's move away from consensus theory, see J. Habermas Truth and justification
(Cambridge, Ma.: MIT Press 2005) pp. 37-8, 249-53. For examples of the extensive literature associated with, and
commenting upon, this change of view, see C. Lafont 'Truth, Knowledge and Reality' Sorites Issue 1 (April 1995);
A. Wellmer 'Truth, Contingency and Modernity' Modern Philology Vol. 90, Supplement (May 1993); B. Fultner 'The
Redemption of Truth: Idealization, Acceptability and Fallibilism in Habermas's Theory of Meaning' Internationaql
Journal of Philosophical Studies Vol. 4, No. 2 (1996); A. Seeman 'Lifeworld, Discourse and Realism: On Jrgen
Habermas's Theory of Truth' Philosophy and Social Criticism Vol. 30 (2004).
19 On the later Habermas's 'Janus-faced' conception of truth, see Truth and Justification pp. 241, 253.
against Habermas. Habermas as a unitary theorist is a myth. There are, as we have
argued, two fundamentally opposed Habermases: an earlier Habermas, whose
greatest work is the 'Wahrheitstheorien' of 1973, and a later Habermas whose work
takes an institutionalist turn. Both the earlier and the later Habermas are, of course,
complex figures; neither may be endorsed (and neither may be deplored) outright.
This said, the earlier Habermas carries critical theory forward; from his writings, the
revolutionary left may learn. By contrast, the later Habermas is a disappointment.
Lines of thought which follow in the later Habermas's footsteps are liable to lead in a
non-revolutionary in a word, a conformist direction.
Second, we may refine an earlier judgement. In our 'Is the Frankfurt School Still
Relevant?', we contrasted Frankfurt School writings between the 1920s and 1970s
with Frankfurt School writings of the Habermasian and Honnethian period. On the
basis of the above discussion, we alter our position slightly: the division between a
radical and a non-radical Frankfurt School falls, not between pre-Habermasian
and Habermasian thinking, but within Habermas. The division is that between the
earlier and the later Habermas. Stated differently, the period during which
Frankfurt School theory retains a revolutionary edge is exactly a half century. The
half century is that between 1923 (when the Institut fr Sozialforschung was founded)
and 1973 (when Habermas's 'Wahrheitstheorien' was published).20 In the years
subsequent to 1973, the sky began to darken.
Thirdly, and finally, we offer a thought about the future. Revolutionary events
associated with the Occupy movement have foregrounded issues of participatory
democracy. Whatever may be the long-term outcome of such events, the resources of
horizontal political organisation remain to be tapped. If nothing else, hierarchy and
the institutionalisation of power are viewed with the gravest suspicion. Is it possible
that, in the period of struggle launched by Occupy, Habermas's 1973 arguments find a
fresh significance? Is it possible that, for a generation of Occupy-influenced readers,
Habermas could count as the author of the 'Wahrheitstheorien' rather than the
institutionalist author of more recent years? If not merely Habermas but the Frankfurt
School as a whole is to be judged accurately, thoughts such as those we have voiced
must be debated.
20 For a survey of the Frankfurt School in its earlier decades, see M. Jay The Dialectical Imagination (London:
Heinemann 1973).